Joanna Odrowąż-Sypniewska Published in: Sprache und Welt. Language and Word. Pre-proceedings of the 32nd International Wittgenstein Symposium, Kirchberg am Wechsel 2009. Rigidity and Essentialism Abstract According to the semantic conception of rigidity a given kind term is a rigid designator iff it designates the same kind in all possible worlds. According to the metaphysical conception a kind term is a rigid applier iff it is such that if it applies to an object in any possible world, then it applies to that object in every possible world. Both conceptions face serious difficulties. It is widely assumed that natural kind terms should be rigid, while other kind terms should come out as non-rigid. The main problem for the metaphysical conception is that according to the current biological conceptions of species membership in a species is not essential to its members. Hence, biological kind terms are not rigid appliers. In his recent paper Devitt tries to resurrect biological essentialism. I argue that while Devitt’s argument is very persuasive, it does not succeed. 1. Introduction The notion of rigidity has been introduced and defined for singular terms by Kripke. In Naming and Necessity Kripke also suggests that this notion applies to some general terms – namely to natural kind terms. He does not however state precisely how general term’s rigidity should be understood. Scott Soames has argued that extending the notion of rigidity from names to natural kind predicates is one of the two important pieces of “the unfinished semantic agenda that has been left to us by Saul’s Kripke Naming and Necessity” (Soames 2002, 3). In Naming and Necessity we can find two criteria of rigidity. According to the first, “N” is a rigid designator if in every possible world it designates the same object. According to the second, “N” is a rigid designator if “N might not have been N” is false (this is so called “Kripke’s intuitive test”). For singular terms both criteria give the same result. Any singular term which is rigid according to the first criterion, will be rigid according to the second, and vice versa. However, in the case of general terms those criteria come apart. The first criterion leads to the semantic conception of rigidity, whereas the second – to the metaphysical conception. Let us look at the semantic conception first. 2. Semantic conception of rigidity 1 It seems that the simplest way of extending the notion of singular term’s rigidity to general terms is to claim that a general term is rigid if it has the same extension in all possible worlds. However, such an interpretation is a non-starter since according to this definition barely any general terms are rigid. For instance, since the number of elephants in different possible worlds varies, the term “elephant” is not rigid on this account. The same applies to the majority of natural kind terms. The only rigid general terms would be some mathematical terms and terms which are necessarily empty. Another way of extending the first criterion to general terms is to argue that a given kind term is a rigid designator if it designates the same kind (property, category, etc.) in all possible worlds. The main problem for this conception is that all kind terms come out as rigid designators and rigidity is trivialized. Terms such as “honeybee”, “the species typically farmed for honey”, “bachelor”, “the kind most commonly broached in discussions about analyticity” are all rigid since they refer to the same kind (HONEYBEE, THE SPECIES TYPICALLY FARMED FOR HONEY, BACHELOR, THE KIND MOST COMMONLY BROACHED IN DISCUSSIONS ABOUT ANALYTICITY respectively) in all possible worlds. In order to avoid that consequence one may distinguish between different uses of kind terms (cf. LaPorte 2006). Terms “bachelor” and “honeybee” have only rigid uses, whereas expressions “the species typically farmed for honey” and “the kind most commonly broached in discussions about analyticity” have rigid as well as non-rigid uses. “Honeybee” in all of its uses refers to the kind HONEYBEE, whereas “the species typically farmed for honey” on some uses refers to the kind THE SPECIES TYPICALLY FARMED FOR HONEY and on some to the kind HONEYBEE. So, one may argue that general terms are rigid if in all their uses they designate the same kind in all possible worlds. The problem with this solution is that rigid will be the non-natural kind term “bachelor” as well as the natural kind term “honeybee”. On the other hand terms such as “bald happy human” will also be rigid, for they have only rigid uses: “bald happy human kind” in each possible world refers to the BALD-HAPPY-HUMAN kind (cf. LaPorte 2000). It constitutes a problem since rigidity is supposed to be a feature that distinguishes natural-kind from non-natural kind terms. Moreover, on the semantic conception each complex term used descriptively has a rigid use. That is why S.P. Schwartz accused LaPorte of “confusing rigidity with consistency of meaning” (Schwartz 2002, 272). LaPorte argues that although it would be “a confusion to say that an expression is rigid just because it keeps the same meaning from world to world”, his view “does not fall into this confusion” (LaPorte 2006, 329). “The species typically farmed for honey” has rigid as well as non-rigid uses, so it is not rigid, although it keeps the same meaning in all worlds. However, it seems to me that on LaPorte’s account any complex term 2 has a rigid use “just because it keeps the same meaning from world to world” and this is dangerously close to confusing rigidity with constancy of meaning. In addition such a view has a bizarre consequence. Any complex term which does not refer to any natural kind will be rigid. For instance, the term ‘bald-happy-human kind’ is rigid, because BALD-HAPPY-HUMAN kind is the only kind for it to refer to. The term “large carnivorous quadrupedal feline, tawny yellow in color with blackish transverse stripes and white belly” (cf. Kripke 1980) is rigid, if there is no kind which fits that description and it is not rigid if there is a kind that does fit it. So the more gerrymandered the kind the bigger the chance of it being rigid. Such a consequence is extremely counterintuitive. 3. Metaphysical conception of rigidity According to the metaphysical conception a kind term is a rigid applier iff it is such that if it applies to an object in any possible world, then it applies to that object in every possible world (in which the object exists) (Devitt 2005, 146).1 On this view “bachelor” will not be rigid because someone who is a bachelor in the actual world need not be a bachelor in a nearby world. However, it has been argued that rigidity so-understood does not mark out the class of natural kind terms either, because biological kind terms will come out as non rigid. According to most contemporary conceptions of species membership in a species is not essential to its members. Recently LaPorte (2004) and Okasha (2002) have argued that on none of the viable conceptions of species intrinsic properties are decisive as far as species-membership is concerned. The essence of biological natural kinds is relational (on interbreeding and ecological conceptions) or both relational and historical (on the phylogenetic conception). Since relational properties are rarely essential to objects that have them, it is argued that belonging to a particular species is not essential to its members. Therefore a member of a given species in our world may belong to another species in another possible world. So – if relational species theories are correct – on the metaphysical conception of rigidity none of biological kind terms will come out as rigid and rigidity so understood will become useless as a mean of distinguishing natural form non-natural kind terms. However, in his recent paper Devitt tries to resurrect biological essentialism and argues that essentialism is consistent with current biology (Devitt 2008). According to Intrinsic An alternative formulation says that “a predicate P is essentialist iff for all worlds w and any object o, if P applies to o in respect to w, then P applies to o in all worlds in which o exists”. (Soames 2002, 251). On both formulations it is evident that rigidity is akin to essentiality. 1 3 Biological Essentialism (henceforth IBE) Linnaean taxa have essences that are, at least partly, intrinsic underlying properties. Devitt distinguishes three problems: the taxon problem, the category problem and the conspecificity problem, and claims that while relational species concepts give answers to the category problem, it is IBE that provides an answer to the taxon problem. The taxon problem (T) is a problem of what is it to be a member of any group that happens to be species. (i.e. “What makes an x an F?”). The category problem (C) is a problem of what is it for a group to be a species (i.e. “What makes Fs a species?”). And finally the conspecificity problem (CS) concerns the question “In virtue of what xs are in the same species?” Devitt argues that relational species concepts do not answer (T), for none of the conceptions appealing to relational essences of species gives any account of species identity. They say how the notion of “tiger” is to be understood (e.g. on the phylogenetic conception it is a lineage of a certain sort), but they do not say in what being a tiger consist. According to Devitt the only conception well fitted to answer (T) is IBE. Moreover, IBE can be wedded to relational species concepts so that they together are able to answer all the problems. Devitt says that a relational nonintrinsic answer to (CS) would imply a relational nonintrinsic answer to (T) but – contrary to what might seem – a relational answer to (C) given by relational species concepts does not imply a relational nonintrinsic answer to (CS). Relational species concepts, such as e.g. Biological Species Concept (BSC), do not say in virtue of what organisms belong to the same species. According to BSC a given organism is conspecific with organisms with which it can interbreed, but – as Devitt points out – this is not to say that organisms are conspecific in virtue of interbreeding. This is why BSC can be wedded to IBE. IBE coupled with BSC would claim that because the members share the intrinsic properties necessary to make them conspecific, in the given environment they interbreed and hence have the property that makes them a species according to BSC (cf. Devitt, 2008, 365-6). Hence, while BSC provides an answer to the category problem, IBE answers the taxon problem and IBE and BSC together answer the conspecificity problem. Since the answer to the last two problems is (at least partly) intrinsic, the claim that belonging to a species is essential to its members can be rescued and biological kind terms may be regarded as rigid. There is a couple of problems with this solution.2 Firstly, even if it seems plausible for BSC, it is much more problematic for other relational species concepts. If we wanted to combine IBE with the ecological conception, we would be forced to defend a rather controversial claim that it is in virtue of sharing the intrinsic properties necessary to make the organisms conspecific, 2 A separate problem is the worry that IBE postulates intrinsic essences not recognized by biology, but I will not address this worry here. See e.g. Okasha 2002. 4 that they occupy the same ecological niche. In case of the phylogenetic conception, Devitt writes that “an organism is a member of a certain species F in virtue of having a certain intrinsic property and being part of a particular genealogical nexus” (Devitt, 2008, 368). Such an answer implies that both intrinsic features and genealogical history are needed for conspecificity, and this seems inconsistent with current biological theories. Secondly, although distinguishing (T), (C) and (CS) is indeed very important, the weight that Devitt attaches to (T) is much greater than the weight attached to it by relational species theorists. For such theorists an answer to (T) is a sort of by-product of the answer provided to (C) and (CS), whereas for Devitt (T) is of primary importance. BSC answers the category problem (C) by saying that a group of Fs is a species if they interbreed. Of course those organisms that interbreed have certain underlying intrinsic properties that are worthy of investigation. If we find out that there are intrinsic properties that are shared by all and only the members of F (although according to current biology this is unlikely) then we may say that those intrinsic properties are characteristic of the members of F and together they constitute the (partial) answer to the taxon problem (T). However, such intrinsic properties are only of secondary importance. If the organisms in question will cease to interbreed they will cease to be a species, notwithstanding the fact that they will continue to share the intrinsic properties. Similarly, if the organisms start to interbreed with other organisms that have different intrinsic properties, the species F will expand and its intrinsic characteristics will change. Hence, saying that it is intrinsic properties that make the xs the Fs is misleading. If Fs constitute a species, then since membership in a species depends on relational properties and such properties are not essential to members of the species, membership in F is not an essential feature of its members. They may retain all their intrinsic properties but change membership and cease being the Fs. It seems to me therefore that while Devitt’s argument is very persuasive, it does not resurrect essentialism and does not help interpret “rigidity” in such a way that it distinguishes natural from non-natural kind terms. 4. Conclusion Both conceptions of rigidity – the semantic one and the metaphysical one – face serious difficulties. Neither fulfils Kripkean postulate that nearly all natural kind terms are rigid and most of the others are non-rigid. The prospects of resurrecting biological essentialism, which is needed to make the rigid application view viable, are dim. Hence, I agree with Soames 5 when he says that “it might be advisable to reserve the terminology of rigidity exclusively for singular terms” (Soames 2002, 263). Literature Devitt, Michael 2005, “Rigid Application”, Philosophical Studies 125, 139-165. Devitt, Michael 2008, “Resurrecting Biological Essentialism”, Philosophy of Science 75, 344382. Kripke, Saul 1980, Naming and Necessity, Oxford: Basil Blackwell. LaPorte, Joseph 2000, “Rigidity and Kind”, Philosophical Studies 97, 293-316. LaPorte, Joseph 2004, Natural Kinds and Conceptual Change, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. LaPorte, Joseph 2006, “Rigid Designators for Properties,” Philosophical Studies 130, pp. 32136. Okasha, Samir 2002, “Darwinian Metaphysics: Species and The Question of Essentialism”, Synthese 131, 191-213. Schwartz, S.P. 2002, “Kinds, General Terms and Rigidity: A Reply to LaPorte”, Philosophical Studies 109, 265-277. Soames, Scott 2002, Beyond Rigidity: The Unfinished Semantic Agenda of Naming and necessity, New York: Oxford University Press. 6