The Evolution of Altruism

advertisement
December 1997
The Evolution of Altruism
By ERIC STRONG
Few theories in the history of science have revolutionized an entire field as Darwin’s theory of
evolution by natural selection has done for biology. Natural selection is the process by which an
environment affects the genetic composition of a population over many generations. First,
genetic mutations within the individuals of a population arise through errors in DNA replication.
Some fraction of these mutations will lead to measurable differences in the traits comprising the
affected individual. Those traits that increase their host’s reproductive success will ensure their
greater representation in successive generations, thus slowly eliminating those traits that are less
able to aid in an individual’s ability to reproduce. As generations pass, this process can
significantly alter the relative proportion of traits within a population, causing the population to
become more adapted for a particular environment. Despite the overwhelming success Darwin’s
theory has had in explaining a wide variety of natural phenomena, great debate continues over
the theory’s application in explaining the evolution of an aspect of animal behavior known as
altruism.
Altruism is the deliberate sacrifice of a portion of an individual’s reproductive capacity in order
to increase that of another. This reproductive capacity is more often described as an individual’s
genetic fitness, and is precisely defined as the contribution an individual makes to the gene pool
of succeeding generations relative to the contributions of other individuals within a population.
Thus, an altruist is defined as an individual who decreases his own genetic fitness to increase the
fitness of another. The concept of altruism is best understood through example: an African wild
dog voluntarily “babysitting” the pups of a pack, while the pack’s hunters search for food ; a bird
giving an alarm call to warn others of an approaching hawk, and thus drawing attention to itself
in the process ; a man jumping into a swimming pool to save a drowning stranger. While these
acts obviously require different levels of sacrifice on the part of the altruist, on average we can
expect all of them to decrease his number of expected offspring.
This is where the paradox of altruism arises. If, by definition, altruism reduces an individual’s
fitness, we should expect Darwin’s natural selection to select against the altruistic trait and
eventually reduce its representation within a population to zero. Even if a population existed that
contained only altruists from the beginning, it would be vulnerable to subversion from within,
whereby a single, mutant selfish individual could exploit the altruistic tendencies of his
neighbors and eventually drive the altruistic trait to extinction.
Although the problem of altruism was largely ignored by early evolutionary theory, over the past
several decades it has risen to become a central issue in the debate over the level at which natural
selection operates - whether that be the level of the gene, individual, kin group, or even an entire
population. Numerous theories have been proposed to explain this phenomenon, several of
which are discussed bellow.
Group Selection
The first mechanism by which altruism can evolve does so under the process of group selection
(see note)
. The following model of E.O. Wilson’s is a good example. Consider a population of N
individuals. Within this population, their exists two types of individuals: an altruistic type (A)
and a selfish type (S) who exist in proportions p and (1-p) respectively. Due to the altruistic
nature of A-type individuals, each member of the population will experience an increase in
offspring equal to the product of a value b (a measure of relative offspring gain) and the
proportion of the population’s “total available altruism” that the member will benefit from. For
S-types, this value will equal b* [Np / (N-1)], while for A-types it will equal b* [Np-1 / (N-1)],
the difference reflecting the fact that altruists cannot benefit from their own altruism. If we then
assign values to c (A-types’ decrease in offspring due to their altruism) and X (the number of
offspring each individual can expect in the absence of altruism), we can then express the average
offspring expected, W, of each type in the presence of altruistic behavior.
Since b and c are always positive, and N is always greater than 1, we can immediately see that
selfish individuals will always have more offspring within a given population than altruistic
individuals. A specific numerical example is shown below using a hypothetical population of
100 individuals in which half are altruistic and half are selfish. N’ is equal to the total number of
individuals in the next generation and p’ is the proportion of A-type individuals in the next
generation.
In this example, we can see how the total percentage of altruistic individuals will decrease after
one generation from 50% to 48%. Iterating this same mathematical procedure over many
generations, we can see how the percentage of altruistic individuals within this population will
soon become very small. If the population is near its carrying capacity and is at steady state, this
example suggests that the altruistic trait within this population will disappear altogether. This is
merely a mathematical model to describe the apparent paradox discussed above - how can
altruism possibly evolve if nature always selects against it?
This paradox can be resolved with a slight modification of our model. In this case, we have two
independent groups of equal size, differing only in their relative proportions of altruistic and
selfish individuals. This example is shown here, using the same values for X, b, and c.
Although the proportion of altruistic individuals declines in each group when taken separately, if
both groups are examined together, their overall proportion actually increases. This
counterintuitive result arises from the condition that the group with the greater number of
altruists is also the most productive. Thus, as long as a population contains multiple groups with
differing proportions of altruistic and selfish individuals, and the groups occasionally mixed for
reproductive purposes, the total proportion of altruists could increase indefinitely. Despite this
model which demonstrates how an altruistic trait could increase its representation if already
established, group selection theories fail to address the issue of how such a trait could arise in the
first place. For this, we must turn our attention to another mode of selection.
Kin Selection
One of the great problems of Darwin’s theory of evolution was its apparent inability to explain
the development of sterile worker castes among the social insects. How could such a caste
evolve if its members could leave no offspring to propagate the sterile worker traits? This
problem was overcome by invoking a special category of natural selection known as kin
selection. The basic premise of kin selection is as follows: An individual can maximize the
representation of his genes in succeeding generations by either increasing his own personal
genetic fitness or by increasing the fitness of his relatives, as relatives are likely to share a great
number of his genes. To fully understand kin selection, it is first necessary to introduce the terms
relatedness and inclusive fitness. The degree of relatedness between two individuals is simply
the fraction of genes they are likely to share due to common ancestry. For example, the
relatedness between a parent and child is ½ since a child will inherit half of his genes from each
parent. The relatedness between two siblings is also ½, between a grandparent and grandchild is
¼, and between first cousins is 1/8. Inclusive fitness is then defined as “the sum of an
individual’s own fitness plus the sum of all the effects it causes to the related parts of the
fitnesses of all its relatives” (Wilson, 1980). Thus, although a sterile insect may have a zero
personal fitness, its inclusive fitness can actually be quite high if it devotes its life to providing
for its relatives.
One can then use the ideas of relatedness and inclusive fitness to determine when altruism
between kin might arise in nature. For example, suppose you are a blackbird who suddenly
notices the approach of a hawk. If you give off a warning call to your neighbors, even if the call
alerts the hawk of your location and you eventually perish, your waning could save a reasonable
number of close relatives in the surrounding area. Therefore, the gene (or set of genes) encoding
for the alarm call trait could still be successful under the pressures of natural selection since your
inclusive fitness would be greater than that of individuals who do not warn relatives of
approaching predators. But what exactly is meant by a “reasonable” number of close relatives?
W.D. Hamilton solved for this mathematically, deriving what is now known as Hamilton’s rule.
Hamilton’s rule states that in order for altruism to occur between two individuals, the condition
k>(1/r) must be met when k is the ratio of the relative’s gain in fitness to the altruist’s loss of
fitness, and r is the degree of relatedness. In the case of two brothers, one brother will give his
life for the other, if that sacrifice will more than double the representation of the other’s genes in
the next generation (since r=½). This rule can also be applied to situations involving more than
two individuals such that an individual will also give his life to
save the lives of two of his brothers, four of his grandchildren
(r=¼), or eight of his first cousins (r=1/8). These are extreme
cases where the altruist’s personal fitness is reduced to zero (by
death), but Hamilton’s rule still holds true for more subtle cases
of altruism.
To better understand, let’s take a look at the following example.
You are a rabbit searching for food in the woods when you
come upon 9 carrots. Let’s suppose that you can only eat 4
carrots, and that each carrot consumed gives the consumer an
arbitrary payoff of 2 units. If you keep the discovery secret and
consume the carrots alone, your total payoff will be 4*2=8
units. However, if in the vicinity are your brother and your
brother’s friend (no relation to you) and you call them over to
share in your discovery, now the carrots will be split evenly
among all three. Now the total inclusive payoff to your genes
will be (3*2)(1) + (3*2)(½) + (3*2)(0) = 9 units. Despite your apparent loss of one carrot, and a
non-relative’s gain of 3 carrots, in this particular case, it will still benefit your genes to give the
food call and share your find.
One might be tempted to ask, how is it that a rabbit can either determine the complex kin
relationships between other neighboring rabbits, or perform the necessary mathematical
calculations to determine whether it should or should not behave altruistically in a given
situation? The obvious answer is that it can’t. Genes are not clairvoyant and cannot necessarily
detect copies of themselves in other individuals. However, they can be programmed to act
favorably to other individuals who are more likely to contain copies of those same genes. There
are multiple ways by which this can be accomplished. The first is known as the “green beard
effect” as coined by Richard Dawkins. If a gene arose in a population that both gave individuals
a conspicuous physical trait (such as a green beard) and a tendency to act favorably to others
with that same trait, mutual altruism between green bearded individuals could evolve. In this
particular case, one can see that it is not necessary for individuals to determine whether their
identical genes are due to common descent or simply coincidental random mutation, as such a
distinction would be a waste of time from the altruistic gene’s point of view. Although the green
beard effect is a theoretical possibility, even Dawkins admits it is somewhat unlikely that a
single gene will produce both a very distinguishable trait (such as a green beard) and altruistic
tendencies.
Another way by which individuals are more likely to act altruistically to others who were
genetically similar is by associating familiarity with kinship. Mothers can certainly know the
exact relationships to their children, but siblings can infer the relationships amongst themselves
also, since individuals who are raised together are more likely to be kin than non-kin. Related to
this method of kin recognition is one dependent on similar location between individuals. For
instance, if you are a member of a population that does not move around much, it is likely that
many of your neighbors are also kin. Thus, a gene encoding for altruism could act not
necessarily on kin, but rather more indiscriminately on any of your close neighbors. This kind of
mechanism can be used to explain altruism within troops of monkeys and pods of whales, since
any two members in these groups are likely to be highly related.
Although these approximate forms of kin recognition are likely to be the prime forces in kin
selection, it should not be ignored that studies have shown that in certain cases closer relatives
are sometimes treated preferentially over non-relatives, independent of other environmental
factors such as proximity. An explanation of this phenomenon is not yet clear.
Reciprocal Altruism
Although kin selection provides a powerful explanation of altruism in much of the natural world,
there are occasions (particularly in higher mammals) where this form of selection fails to explain
altruism occurring between two unrelated individuals. To understand these situations, Robert
Trivers has introduced the idea of reciprocal altruism. Reciprocal altruism is the process by
which one individual will commit an altruistic act towards another in exchange for the second
individual returning the altruistic favor at some later time. The end result of this exchange leaves
both with an increased personal fitness.
Let’s suppose a man is drowning, and an unrelated woman from nearby jumps in to rescue him.
If not helped, the man has a ½ chance of drowning, as opposed to the woman who has a 1/20
chance of drowning if she attempts to save him. One might be inclined to conclude that she will
never attempt a rescue, since the immediate effect would be a decrease in both her personal
fitness and her inclusive fitness (since the man is not a relative). However, if at some later point
in time the woman is drowning, and the man is nearby, he might be inclined to rescue her in
return for her original help at the same personal risk (1/20) that the woman experienced when
she saved him. We can now see that both people have exchanged a ½ chance of death for a 1/20
chance. Thus, a population full of altruistic individuals who enter into a series of reciprocal
exchanges will increase their total genetic fitness as compared to competing population devoid of
such altruism.
A problem with this idea arises however, when one asks why does the man in our above example
bother to reciprocate? If his life has already been saved, what reason does he heave afterwards to
continue to risk it unnecessarily? In human societies, this answer is simple - the cheater will be
punished by both the individual he failed to reciprocate with and also be the greater society. The
cheater will experience a greater decrease in fitness due to cheating than he would by
reciprocating, and natural selection will select against him. However, in most species, the level
of recognition and memory required for this type of selection is not possible, and this is the main
reason reciprocal altruism is relatively infrequent in the natural world as compared to altruism
due to kin selection.
Alarm Calling
Perhaps the most discussed example of altruistic behavior in animals is that dealing with alarm
calls. As a predator approaches an area occupied by more than one individual of a prey species,
the individual who first detects the predator may give an alarm call to alert its neighbors,
drawing attention to itself in the process. As drawing attention to oneself in this situation is
obviously disadvantageous, an explanation for this phenomenon has been actively sought. P.W.
Sherman hypothesizes that any given alarm call may have one (or a combination of several) of
the following six functions:
1.
The alarm call may cause the caller’s neighbors to either aggregate or act nervously, thus
actually drawing attention away from the caller.
2.
The call may discourage prey from a pursuit by alerting it that it has been spotted and has lost the
element of surprise.
3.
Alarm calling might reduce the probability of later attacks by the same predator, if a predator is
more likely to hunt a particular species of prey that has given it success previously.
4.
An individual might give an alarm call if those benefited are likely to return the favor in a form a
reciprocal altruism.
5.
Alarm calling might evolve if prey populations consisted of multiple groups with differing
proportions of individual with alarm calling tendencies as a result of group selection. (Similar to
the previously discussed example.)
6.
Although a caller jeopardizes its own life in the face of immediate danger, if its neighbors consist
of relatives, the call may aid in their escape, thus increasing the caller’s inclusive fitness.
We can immediately conclude that theoretical functions 1, 2, and 3 would not classify as altruism
because the caller would also benefits from the action. Although function 4 may sound
reasonable, Trivers raises several objections to this possibility. First, it is difficult to see how a
group of individuals would identify and discriminate against a single non-reciprocating
“cheater”. Second, no evidence has been found to support the idea that animals in the wild
refrain from sounding alarm calls because their neighbors fail to reciprocate. Function 5 is nearly
identical to the mathematical model of group selection discussed above. This leaves function 6 to
examine more in depth.
Sherman has shown kin selection to be a powerful force in the evolution of altruism in Belding’s
ground squirrels. After studying a population of approximately 1100 individual squirrels over
3000 hours of observation, Sherman found that female squirrels who were currently in their
reproductive years were both more likely to give an alarm call than would be predicted by
chance alone, and more likely to give an alarm call than a control group of non-reproductive
females. Although no significant disagreement was found between reproductive and nonreproductive males, Sherman argues that this is merely the result of both the matrilineal kin
structure of Belding’s ground squirrels and the observation that the female is the more parental
sex in this species.
Food Sharing
As best put by E.O. Wilson, “Other than suicide, no behavior is clearly more altruistic than the
surrender of food.” Yet this form of altruistic behavior occurs frequently in a wide variety of
animal species. Both gibbons and chimpanzees have been observed to offer food to others after
solicitation, and African wild dogs are known to carry fresh meat back to the “babysitter” of their
cubs after a successful hunt. One of the most well documented studies of food sharing however
was done by Gerald Wilkinson on the vampire bat. Vampire bats feed on blood, and although a
single bat will not always be successful in finding prey on any given night, if it does, its payoff
will be big, and often bats will suck up a surplus of blood. Upon the bats’ return to the group, it
is often seen that the successful hunters will regurgitate blood for the consumption of their less
fortunate neighbors. While this sharing of food is often between relatives (usually a mother and
child), there are numerous occasions when the two individuals involved in the exchange are not
related. Wilkinson hypothesized that such generosity could be the result of reciprocal altruism if
the following three conditions were met:
1.
Contact between members of a group of bats must be long enough to ensure many such
exchanges
2.
The gain of receiving aid must be greater than the cost of donating.
3.
Altruistic donors must be able to recognize those bats that had previously failed to reciprocate,
and refuse to feed them.
The first and second conditions were shown to be true from simple observation of
wild bat populations. Wilkinson demonstrated that the third condition was also met.
He selectively removed certain bats from the population and starved them. When the
bats returned, the population was significantly more likely to feed these bats (who had
likely shared food with them in the past) than they were with a control group of starved bats who
were introduced to the population despite no previous contact with them. One can therefore
conclude that food sharing in vampire bats is at least partly the result of reciprocal altruism.
Altruism in Humans
It is only logical that one might now be inclined to take these theories of altruism and apply them
to our own species, especially considering that man is the most altruistic animal of all. Altruism
pervades every aspect of our society, whether in the form of food sharing, helping the sick, gift
giving, or even the sharing of knowledge through education. The use of money may even be seen
as the prime example of reciprocal altruism in modern man, as money itself has no intrinsic
value other than the assurance that another person will trade valuable goods for it at some point
in the future.
It is easy to see how altruism in man could have evolved through kin selection. Bands of early
hunter- gatherers during prehistory were almost certainly composed mainly of close kin. Also,
through language and an increased mental capacity, early man had a much greater ability than
other primates at not only recognizing kin, but also at distinguishing between subtle differences
in degrees of relatedness. As evidence of the operation of altruism by kin selection, J. Rushton
has showed that humans are more likely to favor not only those they definitely recognize as kin,
but also those with whom they share genetic traits. Through a series of extensive studies, he
demonstrated that on average there was greater genetic similarity between friends then between
strangers, and he also made the remarkable discovery that sexually interacting couples were
more likely to share similar blood markers than would be expected by chance alone. The idea
that human behavior between two individuals may be governed by genetic similarity is profound,
and its implications stretch far beyond a discussion of altruism.
Although there is no doubt that kin selection plays an important role in the formation of altruism
in human societies, reciprocal altruism is generally more prominent. Our species easily fits the
conditions for the rise of reciprocal altruism: long lasting relationships, an increased memory to
distinguish reciprocators from non-reciprocators, and a method of punishing non-reciprocators. It
has been hypothesized that some of man’s more complex emotions may have evolved to improve
upon the system of reciprocal altruism. Gratitude and sympathy may increase one’s chances of
receiving altruism by implying an increased chance of reciprocation, while guilt serves to
discourage the non-reciprocator and causes him to demonstrate that he does not plan to refuse
reciprocation in the future. On top of the development of emotions, Trivers even suggests that in
a complicated form of coevolution, the combined selective pressures of finding subtler ways of
cheating one’s neighbors and increasing one’s ability to detect such subtle cheaters may have
contributed to the expansion of man’s mental capacities and led to his current state of high
intellectual ability.
Conclusion
Altruism is one of the great mysteries of social behavior in animals, as it appears to contradict
our understanding of natural selection. Even one hundred years after the birth of Darwinism,
scientists are still continuing to debate the causes and effects of altruistic behavior. Whether the
mathematical models of group selection, the instinctive qualities of kin selection, or the trusting
attributes of reciprocal altruism, are the prime explanations of the development of this behavior
is still largely unknown. In the end, it will probably be found that it is the combination of all
three possibilities that plays a significant role in the natural world.
*Note: I have chosen to use the controversial and often misunderstood term “group selection”
here for simplicity to refer to any process of selection which operates at a level above that of the
kin group. A more precise term to describe the following hypothetical mechanism of evolution of
altruism would be interdemic selection, which is also sometimes referred to as interpopulation
selection. For further clarification of this distinction, see J. Maynard Smith’s 1975 paper “Group
Selection” in the Quarterly Review of Biology and E.O. Wilson’s textbook, Sociobiology.
References:
Begon, M, Harper, JL, Townsend, CR. Ecology. 1996.
Barlow, C. From Gaia to Selfish Genes. 1997.
Dawkins, R. The Selfish Gene. 1989.
Hamilton, WD. “The genetic evolution of social behavior (I&II)”. Journal of Theoretical Biology. 1964, 7:1-52.
Maynard Smith, J. “The theory of games and the evolution of animal conflict”. Journal of Theoretical Biology.
1974. 47:209-221.
Maynard Smith, J. “Group Selection”. The Quarterly Review of Biology. 1975. 51:277-283.
Rushton, JP. “Genetic similarity, human altruism, and group selection”. Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 1989.
12:503-518.
Sherman, PW. “Nepotism and the Evolution of Alarm Calls”. Science. 1977. 197:1246-1253.
Simon, HA. “A mechanism for social selection and successful altruism”. Science. 1990. 250:1665-1668.
Trivers, RL. “The evolution of reciprocal altruism”. The Quarterly Review of Biology. 1971. 46:35-55.
Wilkinson, GS. “Reciprocal food sharing in the vampire bat”. Nature. 1984. 308:181-184.
Wilson, DS. “Levels of Selection: An alternative to individualism in biology and the human sciences.” Social
Networks. 1989. 11:257-272.
Wilson, EO. Sociobiology. 1980.
Download