Back to Realism Applied to Home Page Pavlovian Journal of Biological Science, 18, No. 3, July-Sept 1983, pp. 126-135 Pavlovian_extinction83.doc Pavlovian Extinction, Phobias, and the Limits of the Cognitive Paradigm JOHN J. FUREDY, * DIANE M. RILEY, * AND MATS FREDRIKSON** *University of Toronto, Toronto, Canada, and **Karolinska Institute, Stockholm, Sweden Abstract—The slow or total lack of decrease in some autonomic responses during extinction in aversive conditioning and concomitant verbalizations of fear have remained a problem for learning theories and psychophysiology. Removal of the aversive stimulus should result in a rapid decrement in responding, as it does in cognitive and somatic systems. In laboratory analogues of phobia and clinical neurosis, however, such decreases do not occur in some autonomic responses and reported fear. In this article three areas of research are presented in which dissociations occur between cognitive and autonomic responses: 1) relational learning, 2) phobia, and 3) incubation. The data indicate that there are some important distinctions to be made concerning the properties of different psychological and physiological systems. These distinctions pertain to the differences between cognitive and noncognitive systems, between the two branches of the ANS, and between acquisition and extinction processes. These distinctions lead to a number of hypotheses concerning dissociations between response systems and have important implications for the understanding and treatment of neurosis. ALTHOUGH THE TERMS "S-R behaviorism" and "cognitive" are often ambiguously used by psychological theorists, it is quite obvious that a socalled shift in "paradigm" (e.g., Segal and Lachman 1972) has taken place in psychology during the last 15 years. The shift in the cognitive direction is evident from the almost universal acceptance of the (often implicit) assumption that propositional1 information is all important in determining all behavior. The "information-processing" view has gained ascendancy in such areas as human learning and memory. Moreover, even in behavioristic areas of animal learning such as Skinnerian operant conditioning, propositional information-processing models are frequently employed. Again, and somewhat ironically, in the study of the orienting reflex (OR), recent workers in the area (e.g., Ohman 1979, Siddle and Spinks 1979) explicitly advocate and employ cognitive informationprocessing models. Finally, the term "cognitive" has acquired positive valence to a degree that many areas of psychology are now designated with this term as a qualifier. This designation has occurred not only in such relatively neutral areas as developmental and social psychology. Even a formerly strictly behavioristic area like behavior therapy is now frequently referred to by its exponents as cognitive behavior therapy.2 In Pavlovian conditioning itself, the influence of the cognitive shift may be less apparent if only because few theorists have employed the qualifier "cognitive" to describe Pavlovian conditioning. However, the way in which most workers currently view Pavlovian conditioning is in fact an approach that can be described as a thoroughgoing cognitive one. In Pavlovian conditioning, the beginnings of this cognitive shift may be traced to two chapters in an influential symposium on the work of leading North American Pavlovian conditioners (Prokasy 1965). In one chapter, Kamin (1965), employing evidence from the conditioned emotional response (CER) preparation, argued persuasively against the importance of the CS-US interval, considered critical in such standard texts on learning as that by Kimble (1961). In another chapter, Prokasy (1965) put COGNITIVE PARADIGM forward a view of conditioning that emphasized the importance not of the CS-US interval, but of the CS-US contingency. Then, in what was probably the most influential paper on Pavlovian conditioning of the decade, Rescorla (1967) put forward this contingency3 account as applying to all forms of Pavlovian conditioning: The subsequent Rescorla-Wagner model (e.g., Rescorla and Wagner 1972) has come to dominate current conditioning theory, at least as regards the fundamental assumption of the model. That fundamental assumption of propositional accounts is that conditioning is simply a form of SS learning of the contingency relationships between the CS and the US. Thus what is learned, on this view, is a sign-significate relationship between the CS and the US. These cognitive contingency relationships are different from such noncognitive S-R contiguity relationships (i.e., S-R learning) to which application of the terms true or false would constitute a category mistake, i.e., would make no sense. It is for this reason that Tolman's cognitive maps (which stated sign-significate relationships) were propositional and cognitive, in contrast to Hull and Spence's fractional anticipatory goal responses (which, through such mechanisms as stimulus generalization, were related to, or elicited by, the environmental stimuli). On this purely Tolmanian, cognitive-contingency view of Pavlovian conditioning, then, all performance measures of conditioning taken such as salivation, eyelid, galvanic skin response (GSR), heart-rate (HR), conditioned emotional response (CER), and poison avoidance, are viewed simply as manifestations of, or as being completely governed by, the cognitive CS-US contingency learning process. There is, however, a considerable body of evidence against the cognitive-contingency view, evidence that places severe empirical "limits" (Furedy 1973) on the cognitive paradigm. The present paper is concerned with Pavlovian conditioning where the dependent variables reflect autonomic functions such as the GSR and the peripheral vasomotor response. The main reason for this focus is that such measures are not only autonomically mediated, but are mainly under the control of the sympathetic branch of the autonomic nervous system (ANS). This branch, in turn, is particularly relevant to the paper's concern with phobias, because the fully blown phobic reaction has a considerable sympathetic component in it. In this analysis we shall first present a brief review of the evidence on the limits of the cognitive paradigm's application to human Pavlovian conditioning. We shall then discuss some fundamental distinctions that are suggested by that 127 evidence. Finally, we shall present some testable hypotheses that are derivable from our analysis. Evidence From Human Pavlovian Autonomic Conditioning for Limits of the Cognitive Approach This evidence consists of instances of dissociations between cognitive and autonomic systems or processes. Dissociative evidence of this sort is relevant because it is contrary to the prevailing cognitive paradigm that the cognitive controls the autonomic, or that "human classical conditioning is mediated by an expectancy of, and preparation for the UCS" (Dawson 1973). The dissociative evidence to be presented will be drawn first from Pavlovian autonomic acquisition and then from extinction. Acquisition This evidence comes from previously published papers reporting experiments performed in the Toronto laboratory. The strategy adopted in these experiments was to measure not only the autonomic processes in question, but also the cognitive process of the learning of the CS-US contingency—the process of relational learning (c.f., e.g. Furedy and Schiffmann 1971, Furedy, Arabian, Thiels, and George 1982). The most precise form of relational learning measure that has been used is that of a within-experimental, continuously recorded index of subjective contingency (SC), first detailed in Furedy (1973). Subjects provide this SC index by continuously moving a dial to indicate their moment to moment changes in belief about the occurrence of the US. Figure 1, taken from the results of Schiffmann and Furedy (1977), depicts data based on the SC measure. Positive and negative ordinate values reflect, respectively, contingency beliefs that the US is and is not likely to occur; zero values indicate neutrality of belief about US occurrence. The abscissa depicts trials and seconds (0-10) following onset of the CS. Hence the SC values following CS onset (see especially sees 4 and 5, where the CS-produced SC performance appears to reach full development) represent subjective CS-US contingency beliefs, whereas the SC values at CS onset (i.e., sec 0) represent subjective intertrial-interval (or background stimuli) contingency beliefs. The Positive-CS (pCS) Group received excitatory conditioning trials with the CS being always followed by the US at a 5-sec CS-US interval. The Random-CS (rCS) Group was one where the relation between CS and US was random, this 128 FUREDY, RILEY AND FREDRIKSON FIG. 1. Mean SC at 1-sec intervals from CS onset to 10 sec after CS onset for the pCS, rCS, and nCS groups during preliminary and three blocks of conditioning trials. (The vertical interrupted line marks the point of US onset in the pCS group.) CS being the neutral, "truly random" CS stated by Rescorla (1967) to be the only proper control for Pavlovian conditioning. For the Negative-CS (nCS) Group, the CS was negatively correlated with US occurrence, this CS being inhibitory or "explicitly unpaired" in terms of the contingency model (Rescorla 1967). The SC results depicted in Figure 1 appear to reflect quite accurately the predictions of the cognitive-contingency account (e.g., Rescorla 1967). Especially by the last block of trials (11-15), the pCS, rCS and nCS are perceived, respectively, as excitatory, neutral, and inhibitory. Moreover, the background to the pCS and nCS, as represented by the 0-sec SC values, appears to FIG. 2. Mean GSR (conductance change) to the CS of the pCS, rCS, and nCS groups. become, over trials, inhibitory and excitatory, respectively. Finally, the SC measure appears to reflect the time of US occurrence quite accurately, since in the pCS condition the SC value changes dramatically from positive to negative immediately following the 5th sec following CS onset. However, the aspect relevant to dissociation between the cognitive and the autonomic is that in Figure 1 the SC dependent variable, especially by trials 11-15, shows clear sensitivity to negative contingency as represented by the contrast between SC performance to the nCS and rCS controls. In contrast, the autonomically mediated GSR dependent variable results depicted in Figure 2 did not discriminate between the nCS and rCS. However, as with the SC, evidence for conditioning was obtained, since the GSR discriminated between pCS and the two control stimuli (rCS and nCS). The dissociation between the cognitively mediated, propositional SC dependent variable and such autonomically mediated (and at least partly sympathetically influenced) dependent variables as the GSR and the vasomotor response, has been replicated in a number of Pavlovian conditioning studies run under a wide variety of conditions (Furedy 1971 and 1974, Furedy and Schiffmann 1971 and 1973, Schiffmann and Furedy 1972). Accordingly, the dissociative evidence of Figures 1 and 2 detailed here may be said to be fully representative of the human autonomic Pavlovian conditioning evidence, because, to our knowledge, no evidence for autonomic sensitivity to negative contingencies exists. While the dissociative evidence presented thus far is contrary to the notion that the cognitive completely controls the autonomic, and while the two sorts of processes are different also in terms of applicability of the true/false category, this is not to say that they are completely independent of one another. There is ample evidence to suggest that autonomic conditioning cannot occur without the subjects being aware of the CS-US contingency (e.g., Fuhrer and Baer 1965), which is interpretable as showing that relational learning is necessary for autonomic conditioning. However, even if this interpretation is accepted, the dissociative evidence referred to here shows that the cognitive process, while it may be necessary, is certainly not sufficient to produce autonomic conditioning (c.f. also the necessity-gate hypothesis of Dawson and Furedy 1976). Another source of dissociative evidence comes from examining the correlation between the cognitive (SC) and autonomic (GSR) dependent variables, since if the cognitive fully controlled the autonomic, then high positive correlations should COGNITIVE PARADIGM be observed between the two sorts of dependent variables. Table 1 shows the actual observed correlation between SC and GSR for the Schiffmann-Furedy (1977) experiment. These cognitive-autonomic correlations were computed both within subjects (i.e., trial-by-trial) and between subjects (i.e., overall) for each of the three groups. The fairest summary of the table is that there is essentially no relationship between the SC and GSR measures, with two out of six coefficients reaching significance, but with one of these being negative rather than positive. Moreover, as in the case of the dissociative evidence presented in Figures 1 and 2, so too the lack of high positive cognitive-autonomic correlations shown in Table 1 has been extensively duplicated in other experiments. In a number of studies run under a variety of conditions, the pattern of correlations has consistently failed to show the high positive values demanded by the cognitive-control position (c.f., Furedy and Schiffman 1971, 1973, and 1974, Schiffman and Furedy 1972). Extinction The genesis and maintenance of phobias have challenged students of learning in several ways. Whereas fear is a normal response to some real or imagined threat, phobias are characterized as far more intense fears accompanied by autonomic arousal leading to the avoidance of the situations eliciting it. Both phobics and nonphobics intellectually identify the situations provoking such horror as rather harmless. Thus, the intellectual and emotional evaluations of a stimuli are at variance, presenting a challenge, especially for cognitive theorists. Other phobic idiosyncracies in search of theoretical explanations are the facts that phobias 1) are easily acquired, 2) show extreme resistance to extinction and 3) resist cognitive manipulations (Marks 1969, Fredrikson 1980). In addition, when confronted with their feared object, phobics exhibit a different physiological response pattern than that seen in nonphobics viewing neutral stimuli (e.g., Fredrikson 1981). With respect to phobias, extinction laboratory evidence offers more dramatic illustrations of the limits of the cognitive paradigm than are afforded by the acquisition evidence reviewed above. This is so because in acquisition there is at least a degree of parallelness between cognitive and autonomic processes, inasmuch as both increase as a function of CS-US association. Conversely, we would expect that when the extinction procedure was put into effect, i.e., the removal of the CS-US association, there would be a parallel decrease in both processes. However, this is neither the case as regards autonomically mediated responses 129 TABLE 1. Cognitive-Autonomic Correlations Trial -by-Trial Standard Mean Deviation Overall pCS Group (N = 30) rCS Group (N = 30) nCS (N = 30) .06 .28 .33* .06 .28 .19 -.lit .22 -.08 * P < .05. **P < .01. seen in phobias nor under certain laboratory conditions using the GSR and the vasomotor response. The main source of the relevant dissociative extinction evidence is from experiments conducted in the Uppsala laboratory by Ohman and his associates. These studies have shown that it is possible to mimic the responding of phobics in nonfearful subjects using aversive classical conditioning of autonomic responses to phobogenic stimuli (e.g., Fredrikson and Ohman 1979). In these studies normal subjects were presented with a shock US paired either with a phobogenic (slides of spiders and snakes) or nonphobic CS (slides of flowers and mushrooms). Conditional GSRs to phobogenic as compared to nonphobic stimuli are acquired in a single trial, show minimal extinction, and resist cognitive manipulations once they are acquired. Also, conditioning to phobogenic CSs interact with individual factors such as skin conductance lability, but not with sex of the subjects (see review by 0hman, Fredrikson and Hugdahl 1978). Thus, to explain phobias both situational and individual variables have to be invoked. Figure 3 gives an example from Fredrikson and Ohman (1979) showing that attenuation of the GSR was significantly less to phobogenic CSs than to nonphobic CSs when the US was withheld during an extinction phase. Nor did extinction occur for the phobogenic CSs in the vasomotor response. Although awareness of the CS-US contingency in acquisition and extinction was not formally assessed in these studies, there is little doubt that the (normal, college student) subjects were aware of the extinction CS-US contingency; yet their autonomic responses failed to parallel either this cognitive awareness or the extinction operations. 130 FUREDY, RILEY AND FREDRIKSON FIG. 3. Mean probability of GSR (SCR) to CS+ and CS- during habituation, acquisition and extinction for groups conditioned to fear-relevant and fear-irrelevant stimuli. An even more convincing demonstration of the same sort of cognitive-autonomic dissociation is the case where the normal subjects are actually instructed about the extinction contingency, and report that they do in fact believe the instructions. Still, as shown in Figure 4, based on the results of Hugdahl and Ohman (1977), the au- FIG. 4. Mean GSR (SCR) to CS+ and CS- during acquisition and extinction for groups conditioned to fear-relevant and fear-irrelevant stimuli and being either instructed or noninstructed about extinction. tonomically mediated GSR extinguished slower, in the case of the phobogenic CSs. It is these sorts of results that led Ohman, who favors the cognitive paradigm, to say that "there is a body of experimental data, however, which poses problems for the present [cognitive] approach" (Ohman 1979). Finally, there is an autonomic phenomenon in extinction which is even more dramatic: incubation. This occurs whenever the response actually increases as a function of extinction. It is important to recognize that this phenomenon is hardly robust (c./., e.g., Gray 1975), but the fact that it occurs even sometimes is of interest. Figure 5, based on data reported by Champion and Jones (1962), provides an example of incubation, especially in the group labeled TS-S. This group received shock USs paired with tone CSs during acquisition, and then the USs and CSs were unpaired during extinction. As is clear from the graph, responding increased during this extinction phase. Again, no formal measures of subjective contingency were taken, but it is almost certain that the (normal) subjects of this experiment were aware that the shock was no longer paired with the tone; yet their GSR to the tone not only failed to decrease, but actually increased, during extinction. Distinctions Suggested by the Evidence One distinction that arises from the above evidence is that between cognitive and noncognitive systems. A cognitive system such as the higher CNS is sensitive to prepositional information concerning CS/US contingency relationships. It reacts relatively rapidly and accurately to changes in sign-significate relationships, but this mode of operation is not representative of all systems in the organism. In particular, such noncognitive systems as the ANS are relatively insensitive to CS/US contingencies. Discrimination along the negativecontingency dimension (e.g., between a zerocontingency and negative-contingency sign stimulus) is poor, and contingency variations especially in a negative direction (as in the case of extinction following acquisition) are not readily processed. It bears emphasis that such noncognitive systems are no less real or important than cognitive systems in the total functioning of the organism (c.f., Rachman 1981). Attribution of such inferior status to noncognitive systems follows only if one accepts a model of functioning that is solely cognitive in the sense that all systems in the organism are viewed as being controlled by the cognitive information-processing system. On this model of functioning, an ANS COGNITIVE PARADIGM reaction like the GSR is viewed, like all other reactions, as an index of the central cognitive system, but the evidence reviewed above indicated that this model of functioning is false. Indeed, when the aspect of interest is that of the phobic reaction, which is powerfully influenced by ANS factors, the relative importance of noncognitively functioning systems becomes even more apparent. And just as in the laboratory, extinction of ANS-influenced dependent measures (like the GSR) is not guaranteed by the subject's being aware of the propositional information about the new extinction contingencies, so in the case of the treatment of phobic reactions it is not surprising that these reactions are not readily extinguishable by purely rational (i.e., propositional, cognitive) means. Rather, phobias are irrational, since phobics intellectually recognize the harmlessness of their phobic objects, whereas they emotionally experience them as threatening. A second distinction is that between the speed of inhibition of the two branches of the ANS, branches which do appear to involve different neurotransmitters. In particular, the sympathetic branch, which is implicated in the phobic reaction, is slower to inhibit than the parasympathetic system. Differences in terms of innervation might account for differences between GSR and HR in phobic conditioning in the Uppsala laboratory experiments reviewed above (Fredrikson and 0hman 1979). SNS activation also might be relevant for explaining why the GSRs to potentially phobic CSs were not extinguishable as compared to responses to the nonphobic CSs. The third and final distinction is that between the learning processes involved in acquisition and extinction. It is true that, in procedural terms, both may be seen as a way of manipulating CS/ US contingencies. On this procedural, physical view, acquisition provides positive contingencies whereas extinction provides negative ones. Alternatively, on a pairings version of this view, the CS and US are paired and unpaired, respectively, in acquisition and extinction. However, the way in which different systems in an organism react to the two procedures may obey different laws. In particular, a noncognitive system like the ANS may not react in an appropriately opposite way to acquisition and extinction procedures. This would be expected on the view that the ANS is not sensitive to contingencies but only to contiguities between stimuli. The contingency/contiguity distinction is not empirically important in the case of positive correlations between CS and US, i.e., a pCS. In that (acquisition) procedure, the system can register either the contingency or the contiguity, both producing an excitation to the pCS. Thus, in 131 FIG. 5. Mean % GSR to CS during extinction for groups for which tone (T) and shock (S) were paired during acquisition. In extinction, groups either received shocks (S) unpaired with tones, or no shocks (NS). Figure 2, the GSR discrimination between the pCS and the control CSs could be interpreted either as sensitive to contigency or to contiguity. The interpretation in terms of mere contiguityregistering only the presence but not the absence of a stimulus is supported by the failure of the GSR to discriminate between the two control stimuli, rCS and nCS. This failure contrasts sharply with the apparent contingency-sensitivity of a cognitive measure like that of SC (c.f., Figure 1), which suggests that the cognitive higher CNS system operates in terms of sign-signilicate contingency relationships rather than those of mere contiguity. The slowness of SNS-controlled reactions to dissipate means that responses like the GSR which reflect this branch of the ANS will be retarded in extinction on two counts (a) the failure of the system to register (negative) contingencies, and (b) the presence of undissipated sympathetic activity elicited by the previous CS. On the other hand, PNS-dominated reactions like the HR CR (c.f., e.g., Obrist 1981) will be retarded in extinction only on the former of the two counts. In that connection, it is important to note that there is independent evidence that the HR CR does not register the contingency difference reflected be- FUREDY, RILEY AND FREDRIKSON 132 tween variations in US probability using "truly random" and "explicitly unpaired" controls (Szalai and Furedy 1978; Westregren and Furedy 1978). Some Testable Hypotheses Deducible From the Analysis We present four hypotheses that are both obvious and testable. Intertrial Interval (ITI) Duration in Extinction The ITI during extinction is the interval between the offset of one CS and the onset of the next. A purely cognitive paradigm would not predict effects of varying the ITI over small ranges, i.e., 10-60 sees. However, the present analysis would predict that especially with potentially phobic CSs of the sort used in the Uppsala experiments, extinction would be more readily obtained in such ANS responses as the GSR with longer ITIs. The rationale for this hypothesis lies in the above mentioned notion that the SNS is relatively slow to inhibit. The effect of lengthening the ITI should be to allow SNS activity to be dissipated by the time the next CS is presented, so that there is no longer a contiguity connection set up between the next CS and the remains of the previous SNS reaction. Some support for this notion was given by Fredrikson (1981), who observed extinction of GSR conditioned to phobogenic CSs when acquisition and extinction phases were separated by some days. From these considerations it also follows that the influence of the ITI manipulation on the extinction of ANS-controlled responses should be greatest when the CSs have a predominant SNS effect. It also follows that any ANS-controlled responses which are dominantly PNS controlled like the heart-rate CR (c.f., Obrist 1981) should be uninfluenced by the ITI manipulation, as, of course, should be such cognitive measures as the SC. It should be noted that experiments testing this hypothesis should increase the ITI in extinction; acquisition ITI should be run at a relatively short standard duration, so as to ensure that any differences are due to the extinction rather than any acquisition manipulation. CS Duration in Extinction Increasing the CS duration in extinction should promote extinction especially with potentially phobic CSs for the reasons given above. This prediction is consistent with results summarized by Leitenberg (1976) indicating that prolonged exposure to a phobic cue reduces fear and au- tonomic responding in phobics. In the case of this second hypothesis, however, it appears that a cognitive view would yield a prediction in the opposite direction. Specifically, increasing CS duration is likely to retard the registration of the new (negative) extinction contingency. Moreover, this expectation can be removed from the level of speculation by actually observing that propositional contingency registration by employing the SC measure. This hypothesis, then, predicts that increasing CS duration will enhance extinction in SNS-dominated dependent variables, have negligible effects on PNS-dominated dependent variables, and retard extinction in cognitive dependent variables measuring relational learning. The CS-US Interval With the advent of the cognitive paradigm, this variable which formerly has been considered critical for conditioning (e.g., Kimble 1961) is now viewed by most as unimportant. The reasons for this shift cannot lie purely in the evidence, because in Pavlovian preparations like the eyelid and nictitating membrane, CS-US or inter stimulus intervals (ISIs) of longer that 2 sec produce little or no conditioning at all. Nevertheless, there are evidential considerations for the de-emphasis of the CS-US interval. These include the work of Kamin (1965), who showed that varying the I SI from about 1 sec to about 2 min had little or no effect on the CER form of Pavlovian conditioning, and the work of Garcia and his associates (e.g., Garcia and Koelling, 1966) which showed that appreciable conditioning was obtainable in the poison avoidance preparation with ISIs of as long as several hours. It is evident that the cognitive paradigm assigns little importance to the CS-US interval, since the dominant cognitive, contingency Rescorla-Wagner mathematical model (1972) of Pavlovian conditioning has no parameter that reflects the duration of the ISI. Accordingly, as in the case of the ITI, the cognitive view's prediction for the effect of varying the ISI in conditioning is a null prediction. In contrast, the present view's position concerning ANS-controlled dependent variables, where the process is a noncognitive and response-learning one, is that shorter ISIs will produce superior conditioning. Specifically, with a dependent variable like the GSR, the hypothesis is that a Visec ISI will produce superior conditioning than an 8-sec ISI (the latter ISI being commonly used by the Uppsala laboratory and others). This hypothesis is asserted for all forms of Pavlovian autonomic conditioning, but for the purpose of the present paper, the most relevant experimental context for testing the hypothesis is COGNITIVE PARADIGM a second-order conditioning model originally used by Hare and Blevings (1975) in which phobic and nonphobic subjects have a neutral CS-tone preceding a phobic "unconditional" slide. As compared to nonphobics the phobic group showed greater SCRs and HR acceleration during the 11secCS. Thus, such a model should use patients with specific animal phobias such as snake phobia, and slides of snakes to elicit a genuine phobic reaction evidenced by large magnitude GRS and HRacceleration. The critical point is that what is conditioned is more likely to be a genuine phobic reaction (Hare and Blevings 1975) than in the phobogenic CS model used in the Uppsala experiments . Conditioning of such dependent variables as HR and the GSR in phobics, then, should be superior with a V2-sec ISI relative to an 8-sec ISI. On the other hand, a cognitive dependent variable like the SC measure discussed in the first section should be unaffected by the ISI. Short-Interval "Backward" US-CS Conditioning As in the case of the second hypothesis, this sort of US-CS arrangement can be used to derive predictions that both assert differences, but in opposite directions depending on whether the present analysis or the cognitive paradigm is adopted. The proposed preparation for testing this hypothesis is again the second-order conditioning model previously described. The two conditions would be a "backward" CS (bCS), whose onset would follow US onset by .7 sec, and an explicitly unpaired or negatively correlated CS (nCS) which would have a period of at least 30 sec between it and the next US. As detailed in Furedy et al. (1982, Exp. III), an S-R, response-learning position such as that of Jones's (1962) contiguity-reinforcement theory views this sort of short-interval bCS arrangement as not really backward in terms of S-R contiguity, because a long-latency UR like the GSR follows bCS onset even though US onset precedes bCS onset. Hence, on this S-R view, conditioning is expected with the bCS, though not with the nCS where there is no CS-UR contiguity. Hence the S-R prediction is that the bCS will elicit greater autonomic responding than the nCS (bCS > nCS). On the other hand, as also detailed elsewhere (Furedy et al., 1982, Exp. III), according to the cognitive, contingency Rescorla-Wagner (1972) model, the bCS is more inhibitory than the nCS as regards the CS-US contingencies, so that the cognitive paradigm would predict a bCS < nCS result. This differential pattern of outcomes were in fact obtained for the GSR and SC dependent variables in normal subjects with tone and loud noise as the CS and 133 US, respectively (Furedy et al., 1982, Exp. III; Furedy and Thiels 1981). However, testing the hypothesis with a second-order conditioning model using phobics would be of greater relevance to the question of the sort of mechanisms that may underlie the acquisition of phobias. Summary and Conclusions This paper began with a general overview of the limits of the cognitive paradigm as applied to Pavlovian conditioning. Evidence was reviewed in more detail concerning instances of cognitiveautonomic dissociations, and it was suggested that the dissociations occurring in extinction were more dramatic than those occurring in acquisition. The relevance of this analysis to phobias lies in both the striking nature of the extinction evidence, and the fact that the full blown phobic reaction involves a significant autonomic, sympathetic component. It was then suggested that this evidence indicates the importance of at least three distinctions: cognitive vs. noncognitive systems, the two branches of the ANS, and acquisition vs. extinction processes in Pavlovian conditioning. Finally, four hypotheses were specified which appear to be readily testable in laboratory conditioning experiments. The most important feature of this analysis, in our view, is its emphasis on a multiprocess approach. This contrasts with the uniprocess approach of the currently dominant cognitive paradigm, or, for that matter, of the earlier dominant behavioristic, S-R paradigm. All uniprocess models, in our view, are unrealistic because they ignore the brute fact that the organism's behavior is determined by the complex interaction of qualitatively different systems. If we hope to arrive at an adequate understanding of Pavlovian conditioning, as well as an adequate method of controlling phobias, we need to consider both cognitive SS and noncognitive S-R processes with equal openess and rigor. The purpose of the present analysis is to facilitate this mode of approaching the problems. References Armstrong, D. M. Belief, Truth and Knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973. Champion, R. A., and Jones, J. E. Drive level (D) and extinction in classical aversive conditioning. The Journal of General Psychology, 1962, 67, 61-37. Dawson, M. E. Can classical conditioning occur without contingency learning? A review and evaluation of the evidence. Psychophysiology, 1973, 10, 82-86. Dawson, M. E., and Furedy, J. J. The role of awareness in human differential autonomic classical conditioning: the necessary gate hypothesis. Psychophysiology, 1976, 13, 50-53. 134 FUREDY, RILEY AND FREDRIKSON Fredrikson, M. Conditioning, phobias, and psychophysiological measures. Acta Universitatis Up-saliensias, Abstract of Uppsala Dissertations from the Faculty of Social Sciences No. 19, 1980. Fredrikson, M. Orienting and defensive reaction to phobic and conditioned fear stimuli in phobics and normals. Psychophysiology, 1981, 18, 456-465. Fredrikson, M., and (Ohman, A. Cardiovascular and electrodermal responses conditioned to fear-relevant stimuli. Psychophysiology, 1979, 16, 1-7. Fuhrer, M. J., and Baer, P. E. Differential classical conditioning: Verbalisation of stimulus contingencies. Science, 1965, 150, 1479-1481. Furedy, J. J. Explicitly unpaired and truly random CScontrols in human classical differential autonomic conditioning. Psychophysiology, 1971, 8, 497-503. Furedy, J. J. Some limits of the cognitive control of conditioned autonomic behavior. Psychophysiology, 1973, 10, 108-111. Furedy, J. J. Experimental assessments of the importance of controlling for contingency factors in human classical differential electrodermal and plethysmographic conditioning. Psychophysiology, 1974, 11, 308-314. Furedy, J. J. Cognition is bodily: But cognition is what? Review of P. J. McGuigan's Cognitive Psychophysiology. Contemporary Psychology, 1980, 25, 10-11. Furedy, J. J., and Schiffman, K. Test of the propriety of the traditional discriminative control procedure in Pavlovian electrodermal and plethysmographic conditioning. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 1971, 91, 161-164. Furedy, J. J., and Schiffman, K. Concurrent measurement of autonomic and cognitive processes in a test of the traditional discriminative control procedure for Pavlovian electrodermal conditioning. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 1973, 10, 210-217. Furedy, J. J., and Schiffmann, K. Interrelationships between human classical differential electrodermal conditioning, orienting reaction, responsivity, and awareness of stimulus contingencies. Psychophysiology, 1974, 11, 58-67. Furedy, J. J., and Thiels, E. Short interval backward autonomic conditioning revisited: Dissociations between autonomic and cognitive performance. Paper presented at the meeting of the Psychophysiology Society, London, December, 1981. Furedy, J. J., Arabian, J. M., Thiels, E., and George, L. Direct and continuous measurement of relational learning in human Pavlovian conditioning. Pavlovian Journal of Biological Science, 1982, 17, 69-79. Garcia, J., and Koelling, R. Relation of cue to consequence in avoidance learning. Psychonomic Science, 1966, 4, 123-124. Gray, J. A. Elements of a Two-process Theory of Learning. London: Academic Press, 1975. Hare, R. D., and Blevings, G. Conditioned orienting and defensive responses. Psychophysiology, 1975, 12, 289297. Hugdahl, K., and (Ohman, A. Effects of instruction on acquisition and extinction of electrodermal responses to potentially phobic stimuli. Journal of Ex- perimental Psychology: Human Learning and Memory, 1977, 3, 608-618. Jones, J. E. Contiguity and reinforcement in relation to CSUCS intervals in classical aversive conditioning. Psychological Review, 1962, 69, 176-186. Kamin, L. J. Temporal and intensity characteristics of the conditioned stimulus. In W. F. Prokasy (Ed.), Classical Conditioning: A Symposium. New York: AppletonCentury-Crofts, 1965. Kimble, G. A. Hilgard and Marquis' Conditioning and Learning. 2nd Ed. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts, 1961. Lacey, A. R. A Dictionary of Philosophy. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1976. Leitenberg, H. Behavioral approaches to treatment of neuroses. In H. Leitenberg (Ed.), Handbook of Behavior Therapy and Behavior Modification. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1976. Mackintosh, N. J. Stimulus selection: learning to ignore stimuli that predict no change in reinforcement. In R. A. Hinde, and J. T. Stevenson-Hinde (Eds.), Constraints on Learning. London: Academic Press, 1973. Marks, I. M. Fears and Phobias. London: Heineman, 1969. Obrist, P. A. Cardiovascular Psychophysiology: A Perspective. New York: Plenum Press, 1981. Ohman, A. The orienting response, attention and learning: an information-processing perspective. In H. D. Kimmel, E. H. van Olst, and J. F. Orlebeke (Eds.), The Orienting Reflex in Humans. New Jersey: Lawrence Erlbaum, 1979. Ohman, A., Fredrikson, M., and Hugdahl, K. Towards an experimental model for simple phobic reactions. Behavioural Analysis and Modification, 1978, 2, 97-114. Prokasy, W. F. Classical eyelid conditioning: experimenter operations, task demands, and response shaping. In W. F. Prokasy (Ed.), Classical Conditioning. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts, 1965. Rachman, S. The primacy of affect: Some theoretical implications. Behaviour Research & Therapy, 1981, 19, 279-290. Rescorla, R. A. Pavlovian conditioning and its proper control procedures. PsychologicaI Review, 1967, 74, 71-80. Rescoda, R. A., and Wagner, A. R. A theory of Pavlovian conditioning: variations in the effectiveness of reinforcement and non-reinforcement. In A. H. Black, and W. F. Prokasy (Eds.), Classical Conditioning H. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts, 1972. Riley, D. M., and Furedy, J. J. Reply to Mulholland. In L. White, and B. Tursky (Eds.), Clinical Biofeed-back: Efficacy and Mechanisms. New York: Guilford Press, 1982. Ritchie, B. H. Concerning an incurable vagueness in psychological theories. In B. B. Wolman, and E. Nagle (Eds.), Scientific psychology: Principles and approaches. New York: Basic Books, 1965 Schiffmann, K., and Furedy, J. J. Failures of contingency and cognitive factors to affect long-interval COGNITIVE PARADIGM differential Pavlovian autonomic conditioning. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 1972, 96, 215-218. Schiffmann, K., and Furedy, J. J. The effect of CS-US contingency variation on GSR and on subjective CS-US relational awareness. Memory and Cognition, 1977, 5, 273-277. Segal, E, M., and Lachman, R. Complex behavior or higher mental process: is there a paradigm shift? American Psychologist, 1972, 27. 46-55. Siddle, D. A. T., and Spinks, I. A. The orienting response and information processing: some theoretical and empirical problems. In H. D. Kimmel, E. H. van Olst, and J. F. Orlebeke (Eds.), The Orienting Reflex in Humans. Hillsdale, New York: Lawrence Erlbaum, 1979. Szalai, J. P., and Furedy, J. J. Is the effective tilt US onset merely coy and elusive or should we welcome back backward conditioning-—Pavlov's prodigal son? Psychophysiology, 1978,15, 272 (Abstract). Westregren, B., and Furedy, J. J. Importance of the instructed eye-movement component of the complex imaginational CS in Pavlovian conditioning of cardiac function with negative tilt as US. Psychophysiology, 1978, 15, 266 (Abstract). Footnotes 1 "Propositional" refers to any information or expression that is statable in the form of a proposition to which the true/false category can be sensibly applied. So the expression, "X is Y", is propositional, and the subject (X) and predicate (Y) terms are related by the copula ("is"). It is only such copular relations that are propositional. Other relations, like that between a stimulus and the response it (regularly) elicits, are not propositional. So, to use examples occurring later in the text, Tolman's cognitive maps in which signs are related to significates are propositional, because it makes sense to speak of these sign-significate relations as either true (when the map is right) or false (when the map is wrong). In contrast, the Hull-Spence rg-sg hypothetical mechanism, designed to perform the same explanatory function as that performed by the Tolmanian cognitive map, does not express a propositional relationship, because the true/false category cannot sensibly be applied to it. Note also that both sorts of hypothetical mechanisms can be thought of as information inasmuch as they can both change behavior, but only the (cognitive) Tolmanian one is propositional. In this paper the terms "propositional" and "'cognitive" will be used interchangeably. Although, as a result of the recent so-called paradigm shift to cognitive psychology (see, e.g., Segal and Lachman 1972), this usage is not common in current psychological writings, where "'cognitive" has a much broader meaning and "propositional" is hardly used, we consider our usage to be more appropriate both because it stems historically from the Hull-Tolman debates and because it is consistent with traditional epistemological usage (e.g., Armstrong 1973, Lacey 1976). In addition, we wish to restrict the term "cognitive" to propositional processes in order to avoid the universality of extension, and 135 hence "incurable vagueness" (Ritchie 1965), that the term "cognitive" has come to acquire (c.f., also Furedy 1980, Riley and Furedy 1982). 2 It is interesting to reflect that from the forties to the early sixties, employing the term cognitive to qualify an area in this way would, at least in North America, have been a sure way of denigrating the area in question. A major tenet of S-R behaviorism was that any talk of cognitive processes was fundamentally incompatible with the aim of psychology as a science, and with what also happens to be the explicitly stated aim of this Journal's Society: the objective study of behavior. 3 Although the Rescorla-Wagner model is frequently referred to as a contiguity account of Pavlovian condi tioning, it is, strictly speaking, a contingency model. The Rescorla-Wagner model is characterized by them selves and other theorists (e.g., Gray 1975, Mackintosh 1973) as a contiguity model because it is said to avoid explicit reference to expectancies and mentalism, and presents the Pavlovian condition process as one of gradual incrementation as opposed to "insight." The RescorlaWagner model is, in fact, a contingency ac count because it requires that the organism process propositional information about the relationships between events rather than simply requiring that the organism react to events. That is, it is a model based on the learning of S-S relationships, a process requiring representation. The Rescorla-Wagner organism learns that the CS is a sign of the USIa proposition, and therefore a contingency relationship. A contiguity, or S-R account, on the other hand, can only be based upon the learning of responses to stimuli, a process requiring no representation or processing of propositions. Thus, despite a popular characterization as a contiguity model, the RescorlaWagner model is a contigency account. It differs from a model explicitly labeled "contingency," such as that of Mackintosh, only in the precision of the propositions learned by the organism. For example, as reviewed by Gray (1975), Mackintosh (1973) performed an experiment that appears to refute the Rescorla-Wagner position. In that experiment rats showed greater inhibition in a transfer (to excitatory conditioning) test to a CS that had been random with respect to the US than to a CS that had simply been presented alone. According to the Rescorla-Wagner model, the conditional probability value of both CSs is equal. We agree with Gray (1975) that this constitutes a refutation of the Rescorla-Wagner position, but not because it is a contiguity position but rather because the contingencies it specifies do not make as precise distinctions between known sign-significate relationship propositions as are, in fact, made by the organism. Specifically, with the random CS the organism learns the proposition that "This sign is a signal of the US being completely unpredictable" (1), whereas with the CS-alone the proposition learned is that "This sign is not a signal for anything" (2). Now during the test (excitatory conditioning) stage, both groups learn the proposition that "This sign is a signal for the US" (3). To the extent that propositions (1) and (2) are distinguishable to the organism, the degree of contradiction between (1) and (3) is greater than between (2) and (3). Hence, the results emerge that are contrary to the over-simplistic RescorlaWagner model, which, how ever, is still a propositional, representational, sign- significate, contingency model.