Alternative voting – why it is not desirable XXX XXX Political Science HA-POL_PSPT.XC_E12 November 1st 2012 Word count: 2187 STU count: 13.647 November 1st 2012 Political Science HA-POL_PSPT.LA_E12 Alternative voting – why it is not desirable What is a desirable electoral system? How does it secure a strong link between the electorate and the government, legitimacy and proportionality? Today it seems that there are mainly two kinds of systems in function. On the one hand majoritarian systems, which includes, amongst others, First Past The Post(FPTP) and Alternative Vote- (AV) systems where the winner takes all, and on the other hand proportional systems in which both the winning and the losing parties, so to speak, are represented according to their share of the votes. Both systems are considered to have their advantages and disadvantages in terms of securing a link between local constituencies their MPs and in the end the government, legitimate winners, and proportional representation – locally and/or nationally. With Britain as the case this paper will examine the pros and cons of three different systems, FPTP, AV and PR and argue why Britain should not go for the AV-system, but instead work towards a PR-system or stick with its current FPTP-system. This will be done by an analysis of the FPTP- and the AV-systems on the basis of relevant theories and concepts. This will be combined with an analysis of the potential advantages of shifting from a majoritarian to a proportional system. In order to establish which system is desirable we need to have an idea about what constitutes a good electoral system. Electoral systems are in place because democratic legislatures are considered desirable. Therefore the systems are ought to convey the ideas and principles of democracy. Accounting for them is a paper in itself and won’t be covered in detail here, but Dahl’s notion about the second milestone of development of democracy, representation, is relevant to include (Mair 2011, pp. 9094). He argues that the adoption of PR-systems over majoritarian systems was an important step in the democratisation process in that it secured greater participation and equality in access to parliament. Furthermore it should be mentioned that this paper will accept Lijphardts overall conclusion, that consensus democracies are preferable over majoritarian democracies as there does not seem to be a trade-off between having a proportional representation in parliament and the effectiveness or quality of the policy outcome. (Lijphardt 1999, pp. 301-305). 3 November 1st 2012 Political Science HA-POL_PSPT.LA_E12 We get an idea of other important qualities of electoral systems from the writings of Kreppel and Gallagher. They can overall largely be derived to be systems that deliver an effective parliament and government whom voters feel represented by and in connection with and therefore accept as legitimate leaders. (Kreppel 2011, pp. 125129) and (Gallagher 2011, pp. 182-188). It is worth noting here that Kreppel stresses the importance of representation of critical groups and consideration for minority groups’ interests as a significant criterion for legitimacy. Logically majoritarian systems tend not to encourage such aspects. This broad definition only serve as a raw sketch of what is perceived as desirable, and it is not easily translatable into real life, as the weighing of representation and legitimacy/decisive outcome and linkage is subjective. In order to secure that most parts of a disparate electorate is represented according to its share of the population there must be multimember constituencies with proportional representation. That on the other hand according to Duverger’s, Sartori’s Rae/Riker’s and Cox’s laws and theories (Caramani 2011, pp. 249-250) produces fractionalised parliaments with multiple parties which inherently encourages hung parliaments, and thereby, at least in theory, less legislative efficiency, albeit the degree of inefficiency is debatable (Maer 2010, pp. 25-26) and (Lijphardt 1999 301305). On the other hand majoritarian systems tend to produce two-party systems, provided that parties are nationalized and receive somewhat homogenous support nationwide. In such systems there will naturally be a winning side, which more easily will be able to rule uncontested and decisively due to its majority in parliament. But it also produces a losing side, which might make up 49,9% of the voters, and whose influence will be very limited. What remains is that in order to secure that a larger part of the whole electorate is represented; also in the individual constituencies and not just in parliament, a PR-system is required. That said all electoral systems are majoritarian in the sense that they serve to establish a decisive and leading majority in parliament, PR-systems and majoritarian systems alike. The majoritarian systems establish this at the earliest possible stage, at the individual constituencies whereas PR-systems seem to establish a majority, and thereby the potential exclusion of parts of the electorate only at the very last stage - in 4 November 1st 2012 Political Science HA-POL_PSPT.LA_E12 parliament. There is arguably a difference in how well represented voters will feel if they are excluded already in the earliest stage of the political system compared to the last due to the subsidiary principle that implies that decisions should be made as close to those they affect as possible (Loughlin 2011, pp. 202-203). Denying up to half of the electorate a local representative will hardly serve to enforce joint ownership of the decisions, and thereby legitimacy decreases. Another important aspect according to Lijphardt is that it is important that everyone affected by a decision have had a meaningful possibility of influencing it and to participate in its creation (Lijphardt 1999, pp. 30-33). Again, excluding up to 49,9% of the electorate already at constituency level seems to work against this notion. Has diversity within the British electorate increased substantially since the formation of the electoral- and party system? If we are to believe Lijphardt, then no. He argues that Britain has a rather homogenous cleavage-constellation based on the left/rightcleavage. This is backed by Bartolini and Mair who argue that party system-volatility in western electorates has not increased significantly from 1885-1985 (Caramani 2011, pp. 243-244). But one cannot help but questioning this claim due to the rise of the Liberal Democrats (LD) in Britain, or for instance the 1973 landslide election in Denmark and countless other examples of changes to party structures. Furthermore the analysis is based on data that does not cover the last 25 years of European history. Also there seems to be consensus amongst sociologist that especially class voting in capitalist democracies has decreased over the course of the last 50 years (Manza 1995, pp. 141-147). In addition it is also granted that especially voters’ identification with specific parties decreases (Caramani 2011, pp. 243-244). Therefore it seems legitimate to question whether Batolini, Mair and Lijphardt are completely correct. If we assume that the electorate has become less homogenous one must ask what can be one to improve representation, proportionality and legitimacy. Is FPTP in keeping with the times or is it time for reform? Some claim an AV-system is the answer, but it is highly doubtful that it would solve any of the substantial problems people seem to have with FPTP. First lets have a look at how AV would improve representation compared to FPTP. According to The Alternative Vote Briefing Paper the effect would be very little and almost limited to psychological aspects such as voters’ 5 November 1st 2012 Political Science HA-POL_PSPT.LA_E12 perception of having increased choice between parties even though it is highly unlikely that the introduction of an AV-system would increase any party but Labour, Conservatives or Liberal Democrats representation in parliament (Renwick 2011, p 2). The biggest impact would be on LD’s number of seats in parliament, which according to simulations would increase significantly. (Renwick 2011, pp. 13-14). In other words the actual outcome of elections would be almost identical to that of FPTP-elections, only with a stronger LD. This is echoed by the independent think tank Policy Exchange (Mcllveen 2010, p. 2). So voters might feel freer to vote as they please without having to worry about voting tactically or “wasting” their votes, but in reality their votes would most likely end up benefitting the same party as it would have under FPTP as tactical voting now has been systematised in that voters can cast a first priority vote on a party without hope of gaining a majority, and still be sure to support their second priority with greater chance of gaining a majority. In the end it is exactly the same outcome. Therefore AV will not benefit minority parties substantially (Renwick 2011, pp. 14-15). AV would not help secure a more proportional representation in parliament compared to the parties’ actual percentage of received votes. Interestingly AV seems to actually enforce disproportionality and may even increase the bias towards centre-left parties (Renwick 2011, pp 13-14) and (Mcllveen 2010, pp. 7-11). Again disproportionality is the logical outcome of a majoritarian system. The correlation of the total vote share nationally and the number of seats in parliament is not strong as it is decided entirely on constituency level. The only way to avoid disproportionality would be to ensure that all constituencies have almost the same number of voters, often referred to as district magnitude in the literature, or by introducing a PR-system. What AV actually would do would be to make it possible for parties to form alliances and encourage their voters to vote in certain ways, so that e.g. Labour and LD could make sure to benefit from whoever gets the least number of votes’ second priority votes, and thereby knock out a Conservative candidate even if he/she received a greater vote share than the two others respectively. One can argue that this is both less and more proportional. It really comes down to whether one perceives 1. and 2. priority votes as equal. Again it must be concluded that the most effective way of securing greater proportionality is to introduce a PR-system. 6 November 1st 2012 Political Science HA-POL_PSPT.LA_E12 This leads us to whether AV would produce more or less legitimate winners. AV is often held forward because it decreases the likelihood of winning with less than 50% of the votes, but it is still possible though as voters are not required to fill out more than one priority. Again AV does not seem to offer a definite solution to this problem. On the other hand PR would make the entire problem obsolete, as there in terms of representation would be no disproportionality and no one would be able to govern without at least not having a majority against him or her. As mentioned AV entails another somewhat debatable phenomena being that voters’ lower priority votes would count just as much as other voters’ 1. priority votes. It can be argued that this is unfair as it sort of goes against the notion of one person, one vote, at least in the sense that voters can cast a vote on several candidates. It might only count once, but voters can still affect the result with a lower priority vote, which must mean less to them than the 1. priority vote of another voter. Whether this is a problem in terms of legitimacy is subjective, but as it is argued it is questionable whether a candidate elected on 50,1% after 3. preference votes is more legitimate than a candidate elected on 49,9% solely on 1. preferences (Mclveen 2010, p. 2). Overall when it can be argued that AV would change very little compared to FPTP. AV would to some extend increase voters’ choice among parties, or at least make them think so, but as it has been shown the effect might very well be limited to theory. Also AV will potentially exaggerate landslide elections and perhaps even bias the electoral system in favour of centre-left parties, which can hardly be desirable, as neutrality must be considered crucial. These are important points to remember when deciding whether AV is a good idea or not. But perhaps it is even more important to remember what AV would not improve, or at least not substantially. It is highly unlikely that AV would eliminate safe seats (only reduce them slightly), end tactical voting (tactical voting would be systematised under AV) or improve MPs linkage to their voters (Renwick 2011, p. 2). On the other hand there is a system which would improve, if not cure, most of the problems there seem to be with majoritarian systems, and that a proportional electoral system which is in use in most of continental Europe. PR would greatly improve representation, as it would allow more voters to have their candidates elected into parliament and at the same time voters would be much more 7 November 1st 2012 Political Science HA-POL_PSPT.LA_E12 proportionally represented. It would be neutral in the sense that there are no peculiar systemic features build into the system that would facilitate disproportionate or nonmonotonic outcomes. It would effectively eliminate tactical voting. Voters could vote for any candidate and be sure to support him/her and have a much higher chance of having this candidate elected. Therefore it must be concluded that introducing AV is not desirable from a democratic or rational point of view. If the British people wish to improve basic democratic elements such as representation, proportionality and legitimacy, they will be far better of with aiming for a more ambitious reform. A reform that would introduce real proportionality and not just theoretical improvements. If moderation is preferred over improved proportionality and representation, then Britain should stick with its current FPTP system and perhaps even out the magnitude of the constituencies in order to secure greater proportionality. 8 November 1st 2012 Political Science HA-POL_PSPT.LA_E12 Bibliography Caramani, Daniel (2011), Comparative Politics 2nd edition. Oxford University Press Mair, Peter (2011), Democracies, pp. 84-101 in D. Caramani, Comparative Politics 2nd edition 2011 Oxford University Press Kreppel, Armie, Legislatures, pp. 121-140 in D. Caramani, Comparative Politics 2nd edition 2011 Oxford University Press Gallagher, Michael (2011), Elections and Referendums, pp. 182-197 in D. Caramani, Comparative Politics 2nd edition 2011 Oxford University Press Loughlin, John (2011), Federal and local government institutions, pp. 198-215 in D. Caramani, Comparative Politics 2nd edition 2011 Oxford University Press Caramani, Daniele (2011), Party Systems, pp. 237-258 in D. Caramani, Comparative Politics 2nd edition 2011 Oxford University Press Lijphardt, Arendt (1999), Patterns of Democracy. Yale University Press Renwick, Alan (2011), The Alternative Vote A briefing Paper. Political Studies Association Mcllveen, Robert (2010), The Alternative Vote – the system no-one wants. Policy Exchange Policyexchange.org (accessed 31/10 2012) Manza, Jeff, Hout, Michael, and Brooks, Clem (1995), Class Voting in Capitalis Democracies Since World War II. Annual Reviews Anualreviews.org (accessed 31/10 2012) Maer, Lucinda (2010), Hung Parliaments. House of Commons Library Parliament.uk (accessed 30/10 2012 9