Investigating the State-Democracy Nexus: A New Research Agenda1 David Delfs Erbo Andersen Ph.D. student, Aarhus University, dandersen@ps.au.dk Paper to be presented at the DPSA annual meeting, October 24, 2013 Abstract Despite recent decades’ increasing interest in the state’s effect on democratic stability, the causal relationship between state and democracy is still mired in uncertainty due to conceptual disagreement and a tendency to assume away the mechanisms connecting the state with democratic stability. I carry out a conceptual analysis of this literature’s key concept of “stateness” and identify the usefulness of disaggregating this concept into the three different attributes of monopoly on violence, administrative effectiveness, and citizenship agreement which likely affect democratic stability in very different ways. This conceptual and theoretical tripartition forms the basis for a new research agenda. I outline how my Ph.D. dissertation aims at sparking this agenda by conducting empirical analyses of the effects of the three attributes on democratic stability across time and space. 1 This paper is based on Andersen, Møller, and Skaaning (forthcoming) and Andersen et al. (forthcoming). 1 Why do some democracies break down while others survive? As of today, modernization theory seems to give the most guidance to answering this question in terms of compelling theoretical arguments and robust empirical analyses (see, e.g., Lipset 1994; Gasiorowski and Power 1998; Przeworski et al. 2000; Svolik 2008; Boix 2011; Haggard and Kaufman 2012: 512). However, to survive democracies not only need socioeconomic development that forges strong and democratically oriented citizens. Democracies also need a source of authority, the most generalized version of such being the state, that is both able to enforce the democratic rights and accepted to do so by its citizens. In fact, states today are increasingly able and willing to promote the political freedom and welfare of their citizens by means of their own power apparatus (Mann 2004: 31, 2008). That a strong state is necessary for a democratic political order to endure has been a prevalent argument among political theorists (Holmes 1995: 18-21) but among more empirically oriented scholars of comparative politics, the relationship between state and democracy either largely remains a postulate (e.g., Huntington 1968: 9; Rustow 1970: 350; Dahl 1989: 47; Fukuyama 2005) or is studied in very fixed spatial and temporal contexts (see, e.g., Hadenius 2001; Rose and Shin 2001; Bratton and Chang 2006; Kraxberger 2007; Dukalskis 2008; Tansey 2011; Møller and Skaaning 2011; Kuthy 2011). Moreover, the empirical analyses of the state-democracy relationship are characterized by tremendous conceptual and theoretical disagreement on what aspects of the state are important for democracy. Tellingly, in his review of the democratization literature, Munck (2011: 38) reached the conclusion that “(w)hile the role of the state is thus increasingly addressed in research on democracy, more theoretical and empirical research is needed to develop this relatively new line of inquiry”. In sum, we thus have some strong theoretical reasons for finding the state to be vital for democratic stability but we do not know whether this holds in the real world and what it actually is about the state that stabilizes democracy. 2 In this paper, I aim to set a new research agenda for the study of the causal relationship between state and democracy. More specifically, I take a step further back than what is usually done in the literature by reconceptualizing what we mean by the state in light of how it relates to political regimes such as democracies (Goertz 2006: 14-16; Saylor 2013: 362-364). This is to lay the groundwork for the empirical analyses which will form the main content of my Ph.D. dissertation. Narrowing down the agenda A research agenda about the causal state-democracy relationship is of course a huge endeavor. First, both democracy and state are “essentially contested concepts” (cf. Collier and Levitsky 1997; Hansen 1998). This means that a complete investigation of the relationships between all significant contemporary types, denotations, and connotations of the state and democracy greatly risk becoming unfocused and unfruitful for any advancement of our understanding of the statedemocracy relationship. Second, the relationship is spurred with endogeneity in that democratic characteristics such as elections and improved civil and political liberties tend to strengthen the legitimacy and in turn capacity of the state (cf. Bratton and Chang 2006; Lindberg 2006; Mazzuca and Munck 2013). Which of the two variables, state and democracy, is explanatory is thus more a matter of the researcher’s choice of focus in his specific project as it is a matter of empirical relevance. In this dissertation, I focus my attention on a specific branch of research on the statedemocracy relationship, namely that centered on the concept of “stateness”. Starting with Linz and Stepan’s (1996: 17) notion, which built on Rustow (1970: 350), that stateness is a necessary condition for democratic transition and consolidation, this literature focuses on how particular aspects of the state are important stabilizers of new democracies across time and space. This 3 literature has been the greatest contributor to the state-democracy relationship in terms of numbers of articles and empirical investigations. After a slow start, the concept of stateness has become hugely influential in the comparative politics literature, including in analyses of democratic transition and stability. However, just as with the state-democracy literature in general, there is no agreed-upon definition of stateness in general or in analyses of its relationship with democracy. Approaching the state-democracy relationship from the side of the stateness literature therefore seems to give the most focused and contributing analyses. That is, my dissertation will investigate whether and how different aspects of stateness stabilize democracy. This first of all entails the possibility of providing conceptual and theoretical order to the study of the effect of stateness and the state more generally on democratic stability. Second, my empirical analyses may provide some stronger grounds on which to evaluate and possibly correct some of the assumptions underlying the widely held belief that “without a state, no modern democracy is possible” (cf. Linz and Stepan 1996: 17). Moreover, they may shed light on the validity of the gradually old idea in the development assistance community of advancing state-building as a natural precondition to and active stabilizer of democracy (cf. Repnik and Mohs 1992; Fukuyama 2004; see also the rather preliminary analyses in Kaufmann, Kraay, and Mastruzzi 2009). I stress that endogeneity is perfectly possible logically and expresses how, in a condition of modernization, “all good things tend to go together”. Besides, one may control for endogeneity in each analysis. The definitions of state and democracy to be employed in effect also narrow down the scope of the research agenda. Throughout the dissertation, I employ a procedural and minimalist understanding of democracy as “that institutional arrangement for arriving at political decisions in which individuals acquire the power to decide by means of a competitive struggle for the people’s vote” (Schumpeter, 2010: 241) – with the precision that “people” requires a certain level of suffrage (cf. Dahl 1989: 225-232). This definition exactly enables a focus on the regimes which have taken the most basic 4 step away from authoritarianism but are still struggling with stabilizing and consolidating the primacy of democratic elections. Democratic stability is then understood dichotomously as the survival or continuous existence of the democratic regime. Conversely, democratic breakdown occurs when the regime de facto withdraws its competitive or participatory edge. It is on the explanatory side, regarding the state, that there is the greatest conceptual work to be done however. I here thus first provide a conceptual analysis of stateness and argue for distinguishing between three different aspects of stateness: state monopoly on the use of violence, administrative effectiveness of the state, and agreement on who are the citizens of the state. Second, and as a virtue of this disaggregation of stateness, I clarify how each of these three aspects may be related to democratic stability. This enables an answer to the research question of my dissertation of whether and how stateness is related to democratic stability. I therefore also suggest how these relationships may be studied empirically which form a proposed outline for my dissertation. I end by providing an outline of a specific study in my dissertation. Mapping definitions of stateness Around 1750, the term “state” had clearly come to denote the modern concept of the state as denoting the political community (Hansen 1998: 108-112). It was this modern, European version of the state which Weber (1964: 1043) famously defined as the entity successfully claiming a legitimate monopoly on violence within a specified territory. This definition includes modern institutions such as the military, a police force, a bureaucracy, and courts. In other words, Weber had the modern, territorial state in mind. The Weberian definition provided something remarkably similar for the concept of the state to what Dahl was later to do for democracy (polyarchy) within comparative politics: a definition which scholars at least have to use as a frame of reference for their own definitions. Indeed, a large number of scholars has simply retained the Weberian 5 definition, albeit with some important elaborations which they argue were underspecified by Weber (e.g., Skocpol 1985: 7-8; Rueschemeyer and Evans 1985: 46-47; Gill 2003: 2-7; O’Donnell 2010: 51-53). For instance, Herbst (2000) and Brenner et al. (2003) criticize Weber’s definition for treating the territory as a given, Migdal (1988) and Holsti (1995: 331-332) demand more focus on the interaction between state and society, and Rotberg (2003: 2-5) primarily associates the state with the ability to provide public goods. They all, however, take their starting point in a Weberian conception of the state. Despite there being a Weberian consensus on the meaning of the state, confusion was fed back into the literature when the concept of “stateness” was introduced by Nettl (1968). The point of departure for this literature is that stateness measures the degree to which a modern state exists. Indeed, the function of stateness as a variable was – and still is – to bring the state into comparative political analysis by being able to measure state strength (Nettl 1968: 579). The reason that this has caused confusion is that scholars mean very different things when they refer to stateness. To illustrate, Evans (1997: 62) defines stateness as “the institutional centrality of the state” in terms of the “extent to which private power can … be checked by public authority”, that is, he construes stateness solely as a matter of capacity. Elkins and Sides (2008: 2) instead argue that “Understanding stateness therefore entails attention to the attitudes and identities of citizens, in particular their attachment to the state”, that is, they perceive stateness solely to be a matter of legitimacy or cultural acceptance. Finally, Bratton and Chang (2006: 1060) define stateness much more broadly as “the bone structure of the body politic or the set of administrative institutions that claim a legitimate command over a bounded territory” potentially including many diverse forms of capacity and legitimacy. 6 I have carried out a more general review of the way stateness has entered comparative politics,2 the results of which are presented in Table 1. Table 1: Attributes of stateness included in extant definitions Monopoly on violence Administrative effectiveness Citizenship agreement Nettl (1968) + + Tilly (1975a) + + Bayley (1975) + Linz and Stepan (1996) + Evans (1997) + + Fukuyama (2004) + + UNDP (2004) + + + Bratton and Chang (2006) + + + + Lindberg (2006) + Kraxberger (2007) + + + Tansey (2008) + Elkins and Sides (2008) + Carbone and Memoli + + + + + + Lemay-Hébert (2009) + + + Migdal (2009) + (2008) Kostovicova and BojicicDzelilovic (2009) Møller and Skaaning + + (+) + Sojo (2011) + + + Ilyin et al. (2012) + + BTI (2012) + (2011) + Kurtz and Schrank (2012) + The mapping shows that all extant definitions of stateness include one or more of three defining attributes that I have termed “monopoly on violence”, “administrative effectiveness”, and “citizenship agreement”. Conveniently, each of the three attributes is defined in relatively similar In practical terms, I searched for “stateness” in ProQuest, JStor, and Google Scholar and selected the hits that, within the comparative politics literature, provided some discussion of the conceptualization of stateness. 2 7 ways by most scholars. Monopoly on violence is the “ability to … force people to comply with the state’s laws” (Fukuyama 2004: 6); citizenship agreement is the absence of “profound differences about the territorial boundaries of the political community’s state and profound differences as to who has the right of citizenship in that state” (Linz and Stepan 1996: 17); and administrative effectiveness is “the ability of states to plan and execute policies” (Fukuyama 2004: 7).3 These definitions should be understood against the background of some more general distinctions. First, whereas democracy concerns access to power, the common denominator for all three attributes of stateness is that they concern the exercise of power (Mazzucca 2010). However, it is also important to note that stateness refers to the internal dimensions of the state as opposed to the external (juridical) dimensions of the state. In other words, the overarching concept of stateness does not concern the formal recognition by other states of a state’s sovereignty as a person of international law, which is normally captured by the concept of “statehood” (Jackson and Rosberg 1982; Clapham 1998). Investigating the effects of statehood (and through that the effects of shifting international sovereignty regimes) on democratic stability is therefore not a purpose of this dissertation. To this end, I acknowledge Holsti’s (1995: 330) insight that today the security problems of states of developing countries are mostly internal. Second, the stateness attributes concern the power of state institutions and organizations which is in and of itself value-neutral. I thus abstain from Marx-inspired definitions of the state as the blunt instrument of the capitalist 3 There is a proviso to this. Some accounts have been challenging to categorize. One group of definitions uses other terms or connotations that I however believe can be subsumed under the heading of the three attributes. For instance, I take Elkins and Sides’ (2008: 2) stateness-element of ‘attachment to the state’ as implying citizenship agreement. Similarly, I interpret Nettl’s (1968: 579-580) definition of stateness as “saliency of the state” and his focus on the central administration as a sectoral, specific, and technical matter in countries with high degree of stateness as indications of monopoly on violence and administrative effectiveness. A second group includes an attribute at one place while neglecting it at another indicating uncertainty about whether or not to include it in the stateness definition. For instance, Linz and Stepan (1996: 16-17) begin by defining stateness as citizenship agreement in a state holding a monopoly of violence, but in the theoretical framework and later empirical analyses, they treat citizenship agreement as the most interesting aspect regarding democratic consolidation (Linz and Stepan 1996: 20-24). In such cases, I include attributes that are present in the definition so as not to mistake the relevant scholars’ definition with their empirical focus. 8 ruling class (Giddens 1980: 884). Besides, Marxist state definitions are rarely used in democratization studies and are less relevant in rural or less developed countries (cf. Jessop 2002). Bearing these distinctions in mind, two different approaches to defining stateness can be identified in Table 1. Stateness is either conceived of as a matter of capacity, that is, a set of coercive or administrative functions that must be carried out with a certain degree of effectiveness, or as a matter of legitimacy, that is, an integrated whole – a body politics – perceived as legitimate by its demos. The first approach is represented by Nettl’s (1968) original definition, it pervades influential analyses such as Tilly (1975a) and Evans (1997: 62, 83), and it has recently been resuscitated by Fukuyama (2004). Here, stateness is a product of a monopoly on violence and/or administrative effectiveness. The other approach was inaugurated by Linz and Stepan (1996: 16, 20-24), who break with the traditional perspective in two ways. First, they sever the link between stateness and the attribute of administrative effectiveness. Second, they introduce citizenship agreement as a hitherto neglected attribute of stateness. More specifically, Linz and Stepan define stateness as a product of monopoly on violence and citizenship agreement – but with most emphasis on the latter attribute. However, the most striking aspect of Table 1 is surely the massive heterogeneity in terms of combining the three attributes. None of the three attributes are present in all the definitions of the mapping. Of the 21 definitions reviewed, administrative effectiveness is included in 13, whereas monopoly on violence and citizenship agreement are included in 17 and 14, respectively. Citizenship agreement has been included in most definitions since Linz and Stepan’s (1996) intervention and today seems to be perceived as the core attribute of the concept of stateness, reflected in a growing number of analyses of democratic transition or stabilization focusing on minority inclusion, border settlement, and the legitimating and integrative potential of the state (e.g., Daskalovski 2004; Lindberg 2006; Kraxberger 2007; Dukalskis 2009; Lemay-Hébert 2009; 9 Sojo 2011; Møller and Skaaning 2011; Ilyin et al. 2012). On the other hand, some scholars (e.g., Evans 1997; Fukuyama 2004; Kurtz and Schrank 2012) still adhere to Nettl’s (1968) older conception. More generally, no less than six of the nine logically possible combinations of the defining attributes are represented in Table 1. Stateness is thus a term with many meanings. Disentangling the stateness attributes Most scholars would probably expect the three stateness attributes of monopoly on violence, administrative effectiveness, and citizenship agreement to be empirically associated with each other: Coercive and administrative powers are closely related phenomena (Mann 2003), states capable of maintaining a monopoly on violence also tend to have no or only politically insignificant citizenship disputes (Rokkan 1975: 578-579), and administratively effective states tend to foster trust between the citizens and legitimate the state’s presence and jurisdiction (Gilley 2006; Rothstein 2011). Nonetheless, the three properties of stateness capture aspects that are fundamentally different in nature and their empirical co-variation is likely to be anything but perfect. The two most closely connected attributes are monopoly on violence and administrative effectiveness, both of which have to do with capacity. In a very direct sense, they concern to what extent and by what means states can exercise power across their territories. Specifically, states are rarely administratively effective in their exercise of power without a monopoly on violence. But as attributes of the state, monopoly on violence and administrative effectiveness also differ in important ways: whereas monopoly on violence only concerns the sovereignty of the state through the means of effective military and police forces, administrative effectiveness concerns a qualitatively different type of capacity, namely, the power to regulate, organize, and extract through the means of an effective bureaucracy (Dryzek and Dunleavy 2009: 2, 10 5). Even if the difference between the two attributes is not perfectly captured by Mann’s (2003: 115) seminal distinction between despotic and infrastructural power, we can at least say that there is a wide gap between controlling society through basically violent means and controlling it through peaceful compliance with general rules. Even more important is the distinction between monopoly on violence and administrative effectiveness on the one hand and citizenship agreement on the other hand. Whereas monopoly on violence and administrative effectiveness are solely attributes of the state, citizenship agreement is an attribute of both state and society in that it concerns the acceptance of different population groups of being members of the same state. In effect, it concerns the popular legitimacy of the state. The citizens’ attitudes towards the state are related to the exercise of state power in the sense that no country can have citizenship agreement without there being some central state authority to which the population refers. But citizenship agreement can surely be present without a genuine monopoly on violence. States might be weak in coercive capacity and thus prone to (or at least vulnerable in the face of) violent rebellions but still survive because of an entrenched citizenship agreement which makes the incentives to rebel few and weak (Mann 2003). Much of Western Europe exemplifies a development where the state has gradually withdrawn from more despotic to more subtle forms of coercion and control as civil society groups have come to terms with each other and the state while also building their own capacities (Mann 2003). Moreover, many states are characterized by robust levels of citizenship agreement even though the state apparatus lacks resources and is pervaded by patrimonialism. This was the case in Southern Italy (Putnam 1993) and Brazil (Evans 1995). More generally, states continuously interact with their populations with the aim of expanding or defending their authority, and the sequencing of state capacity and citizenship agreement is therefore not straightforward (Tilly 1975a; Mann 1986; Giddens 1987; Gurr, Jaggers, and Moore 1990: 102; Gill 2003). 11 Next, numerous states have been characterized by monopoly on violence or administrative effectiveness but also by citizenship disputes (Mann 1986: Ch. 3). Many states have been able to endure in spite of intense disagreements about how borders are drawn and which populations should be included within these borders because of the state’s sheer coercive force and the systematic use of state repression. Prominent examples of this are Spain and the Soviet Union (Rokkan 1975; Fukuyama 2012; Acemoglu and Robinson 2012). Or one might take East Germany during the Cold War, where the state penetrated society but at the same time severed the citizens from fraternal West Germany, thereby undercutting its own legitimacy. In present-day Belgium, administrative effectiveness also co-exists with significant citizenship disagreement (Oberschall 2011). The connection between state repression, state effectiveness, and citizenship agreement thus cannot be established a priori (Gilley 2006; Davenport 2007). The co-variation between monopoly on violence and citizenship agreement is arguably different from the co-variation between administrative effectiveness and citizenship agreement. Whereas many states with monopoly on violence have citizenship disputes, fewer states boast administrative effectiveness in the face of such disputes. This is at least partly because of the legitimizing consequences of administrative effectiveness. Perhaps this is most vividly illustrated by East Asia where regimes have achieved legitimacy through economic performance and, contrariwise, by Sub-Saharan African states suffering from illegitimacy because of dire economic performance (Evans 1995; Englebert 2000). Furthermore, the increase in administrative effectiveness was one of the developments paving the way for the strongly integrative and legitimate national states of Western Europe (Tilly 1975a; Mann 1986: Chs. 13-14). While it is evident that citizenship agreement does not follow logically from monopoly on violence or administrative effectiveness, citizenship agreement needs to be further separated from the concepts of historical state legitimacy and national identity. First, citizenship 12 agreement rightly regards the state’s legitimacy but is not necessarily an agreement about any precolonial culture, institutional framework, or conservative celebration of the past (cf. Englebert 2000). On the contrary, it can be established on the basis of old cultural communities and completely new principles of solidarity and inclusion (Durkheim 2000: 138). Second, citizenship agreement does not necessarily equal a strong national identity just as state does not equal nation (Tilly 1975a; Mann 1986). There are broadly speaking two ways of building citizenship agreement: “state-nation building” and “nation-state building” (cf. Stepan, Linz, and Yadav 2011). This somehow is at odds with Holsti’s (1995) distinction between “historic-civic” and “natural” state legitimacy but the idea is basically the same. A state-nation is multicultural and sometimes even has significant multinational components but nonetheless still manages to engender strong identification and loyalty from its citizens. It is crafted by normative integration as appropriate amounts of rights to minorities allow the formation of a more general political community (Elkins and Sides 2008: 718; Stepan, Linz, and Yadav 2011: 4). In this sense, state-nations are exemplified by the Roman Empire and many other empires (Gill 2003: 49-52), by modern-day federations such as Germany and USA, the republic of France, and by what has been termed consociational states such as India, Switzerland, and Belgium (Lijphart 1969; Stepan, Linz, and Yadav 2011). Citizenship agreement can also be obtained through nation-state building. A nationstate privileges one socio-cultural group over others. In effect, this means matching the political boundaries of the state with the cultural boundaries of the nation (Gellner 2006). Even though many contemporary scholars see the process of nation-state building and the consequential nationalism as impediments to citizenship agreement today (Habermas 1996: 133; Stepan, Linz, and Yadav 2011: 2-11), the nation-state has historically been the most successful source of citizenship agreement. The medieval European process of state formation through national conflicts was unique in many respects and did not create pure nation-states but – provided that certain conditions are in place – it 13 still bears testimony to the possibility of creating citizenship agreement by means of nation-state building (Tilly 1975b: 601-602). There are of course numerous ways in which the citizens of a state show their allegiance to the state. State legitimacy may thus rise through performance or because people are given the right to political co-determination (cf. Scharpf 1998). However, these forms of legitimacy are only indirectly connected with the state as they are manipulated by the economy in general and political regimes. In contrast, citizenship agreement directly concerns a kind of legitimacy that it constitutive of the state, namely the integration of various population groups (cf. Holsti 1995; Linz and Stepan 1996; Mazzuca and Munck forthcoming). I therefore stick to citizenship agreement as the source of state legitimacy. Theoretical disaggregation Based on the conceptual analysis, the advantages of disaggregating stateness into the three attributes of monopoly on violence, administrative effectiveness, and citizenship agreement should be evident. The three attributes of stateness are both different conceptually and they are unlikely to cluster perfectly empirically. Such conceptual ambiguity is not necessarily problematical. Quite the contrary, an equivocal term such as stateness might actually facilitate our understanding of the state-democracy nexus by allowing scholars to elucidate it from different angles. In other words, the main weakness of the literature included into Table 1 is not the conceptual disagreement per se. However, it becomes problematic when the definitions bundle together distinct aspects pertaining to the state which are likely to have different effects on regime change or regime stabilization and/or to follow from different causes (cf. Munck 1996; Goertz 2006: 242-243; Mazzuca 2010: 336; Coppedge and Gerring et al. 2011: 251). This is a general trait of the stateness literature and is neatly illustrated by Bratton and Chang (2006) analysis of the state- 14 democracy relationship in Sub-Saharan Africa. First, they underline that – at the core – the state is nothing more than a coercive institution. But they still include citizenship agreement and administrative effectiveness in the definition of stateness (Bratton and Chang 2006: 1066-1069). Second, they examine the disaggregated effects of the stateness components on democracy, concluding that stateness is a necessary condition for democracy: “democratization requires a set of state structures that enforce law and order, respect human rights, respond to popular demands, govern by constitutional means, and control official corruption” (Bratton and Chang 2006: 10761077). However, this conclusion neither sheds light on the interrelationships between the constitutive attributes of stateness, nor on their relationship with democracy. Moreover, variables such as “respect for human rights”, “response to popular demands”, and “government by constitutional means” are treated as indicators of stateness, thereby producing near-tautological relationships with democracy. Taken together, a highly aggregated stateness concept hampers the theoretical treatment of the causal relationship between stateness and democracy and rules out empirical analyses of these relationships. I therefore argue that it is pertinent to proceed in a disaggregated way, that is, by systematically interrogating the state-regime nexus with respect to each of the three attributes of monopoly on violence, administrative effectiveness, and citizenship agreement. Disaggregation makes it possible to first theorize and second investigate the independent causal effect of each of these components. For instance, both monopoly on violence and administrative effectiveness have been identified as relevant in explaining democratic stability (Skocpol 1979; Bermeo 1997: 19; Fukuyama 2005), yet only by separating the two can we investigate whether they do in fact have uniform effects. Note in this connection that much evidence points to a less stabilizing effect of strongly coercive state power than of meritocratic bureaucracies capable of 15 delivering balanced economic development (Gasiorowski and Power 1998; Davenport 2007; Rothstein 2011). Turning to an equally telling example, Linz and Stepan’s (1996: Ch. 21) analysis of democratic consolidation in Southern Europe, South America, and Post-Communist Europe conflates citizenship agreement with state capacity. They are therefore unable to investigate the independent effects of monopoly on violence, administrative effectiveness, and citizenship agreement. The same can be said of Migdal’s (2009: 164-165) analytical framework for studying the state in Sub-Saharan Africa and of the analyses of Linz and Stepan’s proselytes such as Dukalski (2009: 948).4 This is problematic considering that, throughout modern democratic history, democratic consolidation has not so much been hindered by societal conflicts as by popular uprisings against resource-deprived and unskilled administrations (Bunce 2000: 713-714) – something that can only be appreciated by distinguishing between the different attributes of stateness. Bearing in mind the disaggregated understanding of stateness and the recent explanatory difficulties pertaining to the state-democracy relationship, my dissertation aims at examining three causal relationships which are significantly different but are all fundamental expressions of the state-democracy relationship. That is, I examine whether and how a state monopoly on violence, administrative effectiveness, and citizenship agreement, respectively, affect democratic stability. In the next sections, I account for how we should expect these three attributes to relate to the chances of maintaining democracy. Specifically, I argue that administrative effectiveness is expectedly the most stabilizing factor of stateness because it uniquely embeds performance legitimacy in the democratic regime. 4 The non-tenable conflation of the state capacities and citizenship agreement also pertains to the literature on democratic breakdowns in the interwar years. Here, explanations either conflate citizenship disputes and lack of monopoly on violence (e.g., Aarebrot and Berglund 1995), assume citizenship disputes and resulting revolts to lead to destruction of state monopoly on violence (e.g., Kopstein and Wittenberg 2010: 30), or treat societal state opposition as a given while focusing one-sidedly on state capacities as explanation (e.g., Bermeo 2003). 16 Monopoly on violence and democratic stability A monopoly on violence means that the state security forces, which enforce internal state sovereignty, are united in protecting public order. A causal coupling of a state monopoly on violence with democratic stability then rests on the insight that whereas democratic transitions occur when the common people free themselves from the sovereignty of the existing elites, the then installed democracy can only endure if the now liberated people are also controlled by some central authority of which the state is the only potentially effective one (Dahl 1989: 47). The underlying reason is rather simple: Since the ideal typical man desires power, democratic regimes would erupt in civil war or coups if no common authority could provide some control. Democratic instability, or breakdown, either results from a democratically elected government that withdraws the popular right to be able to elect representatives for a national legislative apparatus or from mass or elite driven groups that carry out a coup d’état. Such circumstances often come about in a setting of public disorder (Loewenstein 1937; Tilly 2007: 19). For democracy to function, the state security forces (i.e. the military and police) must safeguard against violations of political and civil rights so as to ensure holding of peaceful elections (Giddens 1987: 202; Dahl 1989: 47). The mechanism connecting monopoly on violence and democratic stability thus revolves around security forces which enforce containment of anti-systemic forces on the ground-level. Some of the clearest examples of this are found in Interwar Europe. For instance, the interwar trajectories of democratic Czechoslovakia, Belgium, and Finland go to show that democracies can overcome strong anti-systemic threats if the state is capable of enforcing the democratic institutional rules (Bermeo 1997: 19-20; Capoccia 2005). Even in the post-Cold War era, a strong police and security apparatus remains vital for guaranteeing stable electoral processes in new democracies (Carothers 2007: 13; Fukuyama 2004: 8; Tilly 2007: 16-18). 17 Of course, the state’s coercive apparatus also matters in-between elections but its importance depends on the social distribution of power. The ability to carry out a general enforcement of the law throughout the state’s territory is crucial to avoid the breakdown of civic order – especially in new democracies where ethnic or class-based conflicts may develop into violent opposition against the existing regime or even civil war (Fearon and Laitin 2003; Tilly and Tarrow 2007; Englehart 2009). For instance, the Kenyan state lost control in the aftermath of the bloody 2007-election. This seriously jeopardized the regime by making the risk of a military coup d’état loom (Kagwanja and Southall 2009). Though Kenya ultimately avoided such a scenario, military dictatorships piggybacking on state disintegration and political chaos have been common phenomena in post-colonial Sub-Saharan Africa (Kposowa and Jenkins 1993). Similarly, many regime breakdowns in Latin America from the 1960s through the 1980s were directly caused by the inability of internally factionalized military forces to come together to protect the regime (Loveman 1999). As these examples illustrate, democracies need coercive capacity to be able to weather short-term political and social tempests. However, in the longer term, reliance on security forces to maintain order in the face of recurrent challenges chips away at the legitimacy of the democratic regime, especially where extrajudicial means are regularly employed.5 That is, democratic institutions increase the costs of repression because governments are expected to be accountable to their citizens in a much more direct sense than in autocracies where state repression is often used to stabilize the regime (Davenport 2007: 10-14). Coercive capacity as such is regime neutral in that it favors both democratic and autocratic stability (Skocpol 1979: 29; Holmes 1995) but over time, it is 5 Gasiorowski and Power (1998: 756, 760) have even shown that – in the context of developing countries – military personnel/cap. goes from contributing to democratic consolidation to destabilizing democracies 12 years after the inauguration of the new regime. 18 expectedly a weak stabilizer of democracies. We should thus not expect that a monopoly on violence is the main factor responsible for the claimed stabilizing effect of stateness on democracy. Citizenship agreement and democratic stability I now turn to the arguably stronger stabilizing factor of citizenship agreement. First of all, it should be mentioned that the proposed relationship has often been the opposite: democracy forges integration of culturally and politically different groups. Indeed, this was one of the bearing rationales of the Wilsonian agreement at Versailles in 1919 and the creation of a European Union after the end of WWII (Anderson 1999). Conversely, some have argued that the great problem underlying the weak governance of post-colonial African states has had more to do with authoritarianism than with arbitrarily formed borderlines themselves (Ake 1996: 4-5). Yet possibly strong feedback mechanisms do not undermine the existence of a strong relationship between citizenship agreement and democratic stability in the first place. Studies of citizenship disputes and its detrimental impact on democratic stability have been increasing since Linz and Stepan’s intervention. Recently, Elkins and Sides (2008: 1) have deepened the understanding of this relationship by noting that no democratic election and bargaining can be accomplished without public support for the nation-state whose political arrangements the regime is regulating. With certainty, population groups, which fundamentally do not want to be part of the same political community, will disrespect arrangements meant to install one common government to rule them all. Installing citizenship agreement decreases the need for coercive force in order to provide public order. This is a very strong claim that first, however, needs to be disentangled into a convincing causal mechanism. The decisive link between citizenship agreement and democratic stability is establishment of a basic solidarity between the individuals of the state that serves to safeguard 19 against extremists monopolizing political power. With citizenship agreement and thus a basic solidarity or even strong social trust, people generally accept mutual dependency, and that political problems can only be solved in communion (Giddens 1987: 204; Easterly and Levine 1997). In other words, elections and the general political process of compromise function more easily when all participants feel part of a ‘community of fate’ because they then respect each other’s political liberties (Linz and Stepan 1996: 33-37; Gerschewski 2013: 20). Moreover, as all politicians will have a fair chance of gaining political success without structural barriers such as cultural or ethnic group membership, their incentive to defect the government or monopolize political power from an oppositional position decreases (Easterly and Levine 1997). Finally, as mentioned, peaceful relations between societal groups and their relations with the state as a regulating authority are so fundamental that they are likely to underpin the recognition of the state as sovereign and the successiveness of implementation of policies. Accordingly, citizenship agreement may stabilize democracy indirectly through strengthening of monopoly on violence and administrative effectiveness. Many post-communist regimes are excellent examples of the problems of citizenship disputes for democratic stability. The most clear-cut one is Czechoslovakia which almost approximating a natural experiment tried to make democracy work but eventually had to split in two. Whereas the culturally homogenous Czech Republic rather quickly consolidated its democracy, Slovakia with its substantial Hungarian minority suffered from political conflict, deadlocks, and extremist movements (Linz and Stepan 1996: 328-33). Although any form of citizenship agreement stabilizes democracies, the stabilization effect of the different forms likely varies. As politicians in new democracies struggle with integration of conflicting population groups into the political system, they ask themselves what type of state furthers peaceful and just integration (cf. Stepan, Linz, and Yadav 2011). As presented 20 earlier, citizenship agreement may arise in many different types of settings which likely have different effects on democratic stability. For the sake of simplicity, I have distinguished between a nation-state and a state-nation although there are many forms of political integration of culturally different groups. Admitting the stability of democracy in ethnically homogenous countries such as the Scandinavian ones means that there is no good theoretical reason to believe already established nation-states to be less stable than established state-nations such as Switzerland. However, there is good reason to believe that in states still struggling with legitimizing themselves through integration of their citizenry, a strategy of nation-state building, that is, forced cultural unification or outright cultural/ethnic exclusion, leads to regime illegitimacy and destabilization (Linz and Stepan 1996: 25; Wimmer 2013: 33). By contrast, state-nations facilitate respect for cultural differences and ease compromises across cultural groups. This in turn hinders political power monopolization and thus democratic reversal (Lijphart 1969: 211-215; Stepan, Linz, and Yadav 2011: 10). On the outset, citizenship agreement is thus a very strong stabilizer of democracy. However, I believe that stating the relationship in such a deterministic way is an exaggeration. In fact, some democracies such as Indonesia since the fall of Suharto in 1998 (Bertrand 2004) have survived years of citizenship disputes or outright civil war-like conditions admittedly with democratic quality left in vain but with the basic democratic feature of a competitive and relatively free and fair election kept intact. Particularly the Belgian case (cf. Oberschall 2011) illustrates that antagonistic groups can peacefully speak together and negotiate democratic, political arrangements if for instance an institutionalized and competitive party system manage the balance of including and expelling extremist forces into the mainstream political system (Mainwaring and Scully 1995; Kopstein and Wittenberg 2010). Even though citizenship agreement expectedly contributes strongly to democratic stability and is in any way positive for democracy’s functionality, it can be substituted for by inclusive elite-level institutions. 21 Administrative effectiveness and democratic stability Administrative effectiveness is arguably the most important factor underlying the stabilizing effect of stateness on democracy. It contrasts with a monopoly on violence in that it actually embeds the regime in performance legitimacy and it contrasts with citizenship agreement in being irreplaceable in the creation of this legitimacy. Just as with citizenship agreement, there are arguably feedback mechanisms from democracy to administrative effectiveness. The installation of democracy tends to legitimize the existence of a centralized bureaucracy with regulative authority, the common people will likely assist more willingly in public goods provisions, and a democratic regime tends to recruit a broader pool of people to fill political and administrative seats, which, ceteris paribus, increase the quality of bureaucracy (Dryzek and Dunleavy 2009: 140-149). The sequencing of good governance, a broadening of the concept of administrative effectiveness, and democracy is still unsettled and should probably be conceived as simultaneously established conditions the absence of each is negative for the other just as the presence of each is positive for the other (Santiso 2001: 6; Bratton and Chang 2006). Here, I however only focus on one side of the equation, namely that centered on the effect of administrative effectiveness. The reason why an effective bureaucracy stabilizes democracy involves how any political regime must satisfy its citizens’ economic needs in order to be legitimate. There are to some extent trade-offs between a democratic regime resting on the legitimacy of protracted public and elite negotiations and effective government (see, e.g., the literature on governance in the EU, cf. Scharpf 1998). Compared to autocracies however, democracies remain to have the advantage that they create (indeed rest on) vertical accountability established through the electoral channel (Bäck and Hadenius 2008). Yet cross-regional surveys have shown that in new (as well as old) democracies, the most important form of legitimacy, and thus source of stability, is not related to 22 democracy as principle but to performance, that is, the ability of the state to deliver public goods such as economic development and redistribution (e.g., Gilley 2006; Chu et al. 2008). In new and poor democracies, lack of performance legitimacy may lead to democratic breakdown by spurring class-based conflicts or by radicalizing ethnic or secessionist groups (Lichbach 1982; Fjelde and de Soysa 2009). When the government disposes of an effective bureaucracy, it tends to increase the faith in the democratic regime because bureaucrats do not exploit public offices and people recognize and count on its ability to contribute to social and economic betterment (Linz and Stepan 1978: 41; Suleiman 1999; Rothstein 2011: 95; Fukuyama 2013: 5-6). This is underscored by the fact that economic growth has been shown to contribute to regime stability (Przeworski and Limongi 1997) and that meritocratic bureaucracies have been shown to forge economic growth (Evans and Rauch 1999). Additionally, as another component of performance legitimacy, an effective bureaucracy is also important for securing that the democratic institutions, such as free and fair elections, function effectively and peacefully (Elklit and Reynolds 2002: 92). The mechanism connecting administrative effectiveness with democratic stability therefore involves three processes: first, that bureaucrats implement (and perhaps even innovate) policies that secure equitable economic growth (and/or secure peaceful, regulated, and accountable elections); second, that the majority of the citizens evaluate this as a positive trait of the regime; and third, that these citizens mobilize against anti-systemic forces to protect their economic (and/or democratic) interests. Just as coercive capacity, administrative capacity as such is regime neutral. That administrative effectiveness stabilizes autocracies is vividly illustrated by contrasting the neopatrimonial, poor, and instable regimes of post-colonial Africa (Bratton and Van de Walle 1994) with Southeast Asia where countries such as China (Nathan 2003), Malaysia (Case 1993), and Singapore (Slater 2010) for long periods of time have used their infrastructural power to create 23 basic popular acceptance of dictatorial rule, not least through industrialization and impressive growth rates. However, administrative effectiveness is arguably a stronger stabilizing factor in democracies than brute force because, in contrast to states with pure coercive force, administratively effective states “engender and maintain the belief that existing political institutions are the most appropriate or proper ones for the society” (Lipset 1959: 86). To illustrate the different effects of monopoly on violence and administrative effectiveness, take post-World War II Colombia. Here, guerilla groups undermining state sovereignty have not in themselves been the greatest challenge to democracy (Acemoglu, Robinson, and Santos 2013). The big democratic problem in Colombia, as in most other Latin American countries, is old patterns of corrupt, patrimonial bureaucratic rule which have been largely responsible for a poor record of economic performance in general and of wealth distribution in particular (O’Donnell 1988; Mainwaring and Scully 2010: 368). Also, administrative effectiveness is arguably a stronger stabilizing factor than citizenship agreement for democracy. Both performance legitimacy and intergroup solidarity are important sources of democratic stability. However, in contrast to citizenship agreement which may be substituted by an institutionalized party system in creating the minimum of intergroup solidarity at the elite level, there is no substitution for administrative effectiveness in creating performance legitimacy. Even with innovative businesses and citizens with a strong work ethic, a central, coordinating apparatus is needed to create and sustain economic development (Evans 1995). Similarly, high levels of development assistance or vast natural assets for the state apparatus could be used for economic growth creation but these resources are often used for private purposes or are inefficiently administered precisely because of corrupt politicians and bureaucrats (Sandbrook 1986; Cammack 2007). Administrative effectiveness holds the advantages of being an irreplaceable cause of the performance legitimacy so important for democratic stability. 24 In sum, I expect all three versions of stateness to stabilize democracy. However, such a claim is highly imprecise. A monopoly on violence in and of itself does not entail any kind of legitimacy, neither of the state nor the regime, which means that it will only stabilize democracy in the short run and is in any case a risky strategy for a democratic government. Citizenship agreement creates the solidarity between population groups and the state legitimacy that may erase the need for coercive force in the first place thus stabilizing democracy in the longer term. However, citizenship disputes and stable democratic rule prevail in many countries because of substitutive inclusion by the party system. On the contrary, administrative effectiveness provides the regime with long-term legitimacy while being the only real factor capable of doing so. Therefore, I expect administrative effectiveness to be primarily responsible factor for the stabilizing effect of stateness on democratic stability. Figure 1 presents these propositions in a simple model that I examine in the dissertation. Figure 1: Relationships between stateness and democratic stability Capacity Administrative Effectiveness Legitimacy Stateness Monopoly on Violence + + Democratic Stability + Citizenship Agreement 25 Studying the state-democracy relationship empirically I have made a strong call for conceptual and theoretical disaggregation of the state-democracy relationship. I now finally set up a framework for empirical analysis of it within the scope of my Ph.D. dissertation. To be able to answer the overarching research question of whether and how the state is related to democratic stability, I argue that comparisons across time and space are necessary to avoid getting biased snap-shots of the empirical patterns that we are analysing. The main purpose of comparing is that it allows us to control (Sartori 1991). This point holds regardless of whether I do cross-temporal or cross-spatial comparisons and regardless of whether small-N or large-N comparisons are marshalled. Only by including periods and contexts in which our core variables show significant variation can we get an adequate grasp of relevant relationships and boost external validity. I also argue that within-case analysis of a few, but carefully chosen cases, is needed in order to bolster the internal validity of the relationships. It follows from this that an exhaustive treatment of the state-democracy relationship would require systematic comparisons of the association between the three attributes of stateness and democratic development in the entire period in which modern democracy has been in existence. Due to current data limitations, especially with regard to measuring the state (cf. Van de Walle 2005; Hendrix 2010; Saylor 2013), it is of course unrealistic to conduct an analysis of such an ambitious scope in any one paper or even in a dissertation. However, I believe that the research question may be answered by identifying more confined historical periods and regions of particular interest. Specifically, I will be interested in cases of democratic survival and breakdown in periods of different international contexts. The most basic and common scope condition for all countries is perhaps the international system. If I only analyze, say, the late Interwar period, I might derive misleading conclusions about democratic stability for the simple reason that domestic relationships were affected by the diffusional forces of Hitler’s Germany and the systemic clash between 26 democracies and autocracies. Regime dynamics are indeed very different in today’s post-Cold War world (Schedler 1998; Boix 2011). Whereas some analyses may be carried out with statistical tools, some, i.e. small-N studies, cannot. It is worth pointing out that in small-N studies the logic of control can be pursued in different ways. One may use more “classical” comparative-historical approaches in the form of focused comparisons of a few cases (cf. Mahoney and Rueschemeyer 2003; Capoccia and Ziblatt 2010) or process tracing in one very specific case to further examine the mechanisms assumed to be drive the relationships in the larger-N analyses (cf. George and Bennett 2005: Ch. 10). Furthermore, small-N and large-N studies often enrich each other. Studying the processes and specific mechanisms which connect various aspects of stateness and political regime developments may both benefit from and contribute to cross-case knowledge of the state-democracy relationship. Finally, apart from the above methodological considerations, I need a comprehensive framework that explains democratic stability to appreciate the causal role of the state. It is not only interesting to examine the size of the effect of the stateness attributes but also what conditions their effect and how they interact with other variables in stabilizing democracy. The most important competing and complementary explanations to a state-centred one are: level of socioeconomic development (cf. Przeworski et al. 2000), economic crisis (cf. Svolik 2008), dense civil society (cf. Putnam 1993; Ertman 1998), and an institutionalized party system (cf. Mainwaring and Scully 1995; Ertman 1998). I aim to elaborate on the relationship between stateness and these other factors in the relevant papers. Suggestive outline of the dissertation 27 I plan to make an article-based dissertation. Table 2 outlines the articles that I currently suggest to undertake. This outline is open-ended and I will continuously revise it due to new insights or inspirations from writing the articles. The first article6 introduces to the field of research, that is, the state-democracy relationship, with which the dissertation deals. Since the main weaknesses of this literature are conceptual and theoretical, I have conducted a conceptual analysis of the sort presented in this paper. This is the basis for the rest of the dissertation, including the theoretical propositions to be made. I also here suggest all the empirical analyses to have explicit comparative purposes. However, a general trait is that indicators of state strength (and stateness in particular) are generally weakly comparable and do not extend very far back in time. This basic data problem affects the methods of the particular articles. Even though I aim to design my analyses so as to be able to make valid inferences for all newly democratized countries across time and space, the dissertation thus mostly makes use of small-N and medium-N methods and has a stronger qualitative edge. A somewhat chronological order of the dissertation will hopefully work as a reader’s guide to understanding of the analytical points. Therefore, I start the empirical part of the dissertation by investigating the conditions for democratic survival and breakdown in the interwar years, focusing on the Great Depression in particular. The interwar period is well-suited for conducting such an analysis that may form the basis of further empirical analyses. First, the interwar period represents the first and hitherto most dramatic reverse wave of democratization in modern times (Huntington 1991: 14). Much can be learned from such a global and intense process in terms of the basic prerequisites of democracy. It constitutes the historical foundation upon which prospects of democracy today can be evaluated (Capoccia and Ziblatt 2010: 932). Second, the interwar period, and especially the Great Depression, not only witnessed several democratic breakdowns but also a 6 This article has been the base of this paper, is currently in review, and to be published in Democratization September 2014. 28 significant number of survivals. This raises the comparative potential of studying the trajectory of the democracies that were or came to being immediately after WWI when they were confronted with the devastating economic crisis of the Great Depression. Third, the period approximates a natural experiment as it is clearly demarcated by two world wars which set it apart from earlier and later developments. While the economic crisis of the 1930s constituted a scope condition that every democracy had to deal with and thus can be held as a constant (Bermeo 1997; Ertman 1998: 476-477), WWI and the peace settlement at Versailles was the stimuli that set some but not all countries off on state- and nation-building paths that would destabilize democracy (Aarebrot and Berglund 1995; Aldcroft 2006: Ch. 3). In my master’s thesis, which I wrote on this particular subject, I studied the conditions 7 for democratic survival for all democracies in 1919 globally throughout the whole interwar period using crisp-set QCA and found that democratic survival could only be obtained by a combination of a monopoly on violence, administrative effectiveness, a dense civil society, and an institutionalized party system. In the dissertation’s Article 2, I narrow down my focus to studying only the so-called “swing states” during the Great Depression. I elaborate on this in the last section of this paper. The third article will constitute the most comprehensive study of the state-democracy relationship in the dissertation. In an analysis of democratic transitions and reversals from 19802000, Haggard and Kaufman (2012) reject various suggestive explanations pointing to redistributional conflicts. They conclude by hypothesizing some alternative causal paths: “there might be other economic and institutional factors that condition the capacity of low-income groups to engage in collective action” (Haggard and Kaufman 2012: 496). With the use of Causal Process Observations (cf. Haggard and Kaufman 2012; for a similar approach, see also Ross 2008), I aim to examine the causal processes leading to democratic breakdown inferring to all democratic 7 I examined the validity of all three stateness attributes, dense civil society, and an institutionalized party system. Economic crisis could largely be held at constant but was integrated in small within-case studies of the cases as a potential confounder. Other confounders (analyzed as antecedent conditions) were: the existence of a diversified economy and ethnic polarization. 29 breakdown cases from 1946 till today. Dichotomous coding of democracies and autocracies in this period is available from Boix, Miller, and Rosato (2012) (data from 1800-2007), Cheibub, Gandhi, and Vreeland (2009) (1946-2008), and Geddes, Wright, and Frantz (2013) (1946-2010). The purpose is double: to understand the causes of breakdown and to investigate specifically the causal role of the state, that is, the three stateness attributes, which could very likely give substance to Haggard and Kaufman’s hypotheses. Therefore, I specifically test some causal mechanisms which we should expect to connect each of the three stateness attributes with democratic breakdown. I compare the findings with the causes of democratic breakdown in the interwar period (Article 2) and thus reuse the theoretical framework by focusing on the confounding or conditioning effect of civil society, the party system, economic development and crisis as well as shifting international contexts. Causal Process Observations includes two stages: (1) within-case analysis and coding of cases on specific variables of the process leading to the breakdown and (2) aggregation across the population of cases. Instead of assessing mean effects of the explanatory variables, the final analytical stage is thus to investigate whether the path to democratic breakdown conforms to the causal process stipulated in the theoretical model (Haggard and Kaufman 2012: 498-499). The reasons for using Causal Process Observations are both pragmatic and idealistic. Pragmatically, data limitations on the stateness variables are severe when going further back than 2003 (cf. BTI 2012). Even though rough proxies are available, it is much easier, precise, and thus more fruitful to make use of case-specific knowledge when coding. Idealistically, the severe shortcomings of the literature concern finding robust causal mechanisms that make us believe in the validity of the claim that a strong state is necessary for democratic stability. Scholars have found significant correlations but no robust mechanisms across time and space. 30 The fourth article8 delves into the two attributes of stateness that regard capacity, namely monopoly on violence and administrative effectiveness. Specifically, it investigates whether the state is indeed as two-edged sword as proposed by political theorists, that is, it investigates the regime-neutrality of these two capacities as well as the alleged stronger stabilizing effect of administrative effectiveness in democracies. To determine whether a country has experienced autocratic or democratic breakdowns, Geddes, Wright, and Frantz’s (2013) Autocratic Regimes Dataset is employed. Although the indicators of state capacity are proxies and could be misleading, the findings suggest that, after controlling for level of GDP/capita, a monopoly on violence (measured as military expenditure/cap.) is only a strong stabilizer in autocracies whereas administrative effectiveness (measured using ICRG’s Bureaucratic Quality indicator) is only a strong stabilizer in democracies. This casts doubt on both state capacities being completely regimeneutral. Articles 5 and 6 delve into the effect of citizenship agreement. According to Wimmer (2013: 33), the end of ethnic exclusion, as a form of citizenship disagreement, should greatly increase the chances of democratization. However, it is not given that democratic governments will prevent renewed ethnic exclusion. Elaborating on this insight, this means that formerly ethnic exclusionary countries which have recently embarked on a path toward democracy are in great risk of reverting back to state repression and autocracy due to grievances among the excluded population and the protective measures employed in effect by the incumbents (Gurr 2000: Ch. 3). Article 5 thus analyzes whether and how regimes with former exclusion of majority ethnic groups can become democratic and sustain the democratic rule. Ethnic exclusion may be measured using data from Cederman, Wimmer, and Min (2010) and the existence of a state-nation while democratic may be measured by rough proxies such as the number and cultural width of parties represented in 8 This article has been the base of this paper, is currently in review, and to be published in Democratization September 2014. 31 parliament. We choose a few cases which have managed to stabilize democracy for within-case analysis of how this has come about with specific interest in the role of citizenship agreement. Accordingly, this study enables assessment of the detrimental effects of a weak nation-state but also enables investigation of possible ways out of citizenship disputes and democratic instability, for instance by employing state-nation building. Article 6 focuses on the contemporary debate spurred by Stepan, Linz, and Yadav (2011) the take-off of which is that the functionality and success of democracies may be attributed directly to their success as state-nation builders and that the creation of Swiss-like state-nations can travel to any context because they can be crafted by specific policies and designs (Stepan, Linz, and Yadav 2011: 8). However, the Swiss and Indian state- and nation-building trajectories are so unique that it is perhaps dangerous to prescribe these as models to follow everywhere. For instance, the problems of democratic instability in West African states such as Liberia, Sierra Leone, and the Ivory Coast, where ethnic tensions have been huge since decolonization, may be very different in terms of weak state coercive capacity, bureaucratic performance, or party system institutional deficiencies (e.g., Bratton and Van de Walle 1994). Although the idea of forging identification with a common state across different cultural groups seems compelling in its many basic effects on politics, concrete challenges may differ. I thus aim to compare the context specific to Switzerland at the time of its state-nation building with the context of present West African states which experience democratic instability amidst struggling with violent societal conflicts and low state legitimacy. A concluding chapter of the dissertation will put the pieces together, evaluate the current state-democracy literature as well as the specific one on stateness, and suggest areas for future research. 32 Table 2: A suggestive outline of the Ph.D. dissertation Article Working title Description Author(s) 1 (in The State-Democracy Nexus: Conceptual Introduction to the study of the state-democracy relationship; conceptual analysis of David Andersen, Jørgen Møller, and review) Distinctions, Theoretical Perspectives, and “stateness”; analytical/explanatory disadvantages of aggregation of stateness concept; Svend-Erik Skaaning Comparative Approaches suggestions for a comparative approach 2 (in Stateness and Democratic Stability during the Comparative-historical analysis of the conditions for democratic survival and breakdown progress; Great Depression among “swing-states” during the Great Depression; the interaction between stateness, civil master David Andersen society, and the party system thesis) 3 States in Processes of Democratic Use of Causal Process Observations to analyze democratic breakdowns during the second Destabilization: The Reverse Waves reverse wave and in the Post-Cold War period; comparison with interwar cases of Compared democratic breakdown; the interaction between stateness (including the two forms of David Andersen citizenship agreement), economic crisis and development level, civil society, and the party system; control via the design for effect of the international context; case illustrations 4 (in State Capacity and Political Regime Stability: Large-N, statistical analysis of the role of state capacity in securing autocratic as well as David Andersen, Jørgen Møller, review) A Two-edged Sword? democratic stability; the independent effects of the two state capacities and evaluation of Svend-Erik Skaaning, and Lasse their regime neutrality Lykke Rørbæk Prospects of Democratization and Democratic Analysis of former ethnically exclusivist countries’ transition paths and of their David Andersen and Lasse Lykke Stability with an Exclusivist Past consolidation paths depending on the types of citizenship agreement; possibly large-N, Rørbæk 5 statistical analysis comparing regime stability in non-exclusionary and exclusionary countries; coupling with a few in-depth case studies 6 Types of Citizenship Agreement and Investigating whether ethnic diversity is the problem behind democratic instability in West Democratic Stability: From Continental Africa and whether the state-nation model of Continental Europe can travel to ethnically Europe to West Africa? diverse West African democracies; comparison of historical cases (Continental Europe) and present cases (West Africa) of democratization amidst state- and nation-building 33 David Andersen Outline of Article 2 Despite recent upheavals of studies of interwar democratic stability, no general, that is, comparatively valid, explanation for why some of the world’s democracies broke down while some others survived has been established. In this paper, I take as my point of departure the latest comprehensive efforts in this regard by Ertman (1998), Bermeo (2003), Capoccia (2005), Capoccia and Ziblatt (2010), Weyland (2010), and Boix (2011). Specifically, I part with Capoccia and Ziblatt’s thesis that in the so-called “swing states” democratic survival was, at the end of the day, completely determined by actors’ contingent choices. Instead, I continue the line of thought of classical comparative-historical scholars such as Tilly (1975a), Rokkan (1975), and Ertman (1997) whose broad analyses of European political development highlight the essential importance of structural factors in explaining the systematic variation across Europe, where Northwestern democracies survived and Eastern, Southern, and Central European democracies broke down (cf. Møller 2013). To this geographical pattern, one might add that the democracies of former British colonies (USA, Canada, New Zealand, and Australia) survived while democracies of former Spanish colonies broke down (Rueschemeyer, Stephens, and Stephens 1992). However, I also take into account the impact of WWI and the Versailles Treaty’s principles of new states and selfdetermination of national minorities (cf. Rothschild 1974; Aldcroft 2006). In the most recent contribution to the debate on interwar democratic stability, Capoccia and Ziblatt present the view that historical research should regain strength in democratization studies. Among other cases, they, inspired by Linz and Stepan’s (1978) study, base this on observations of processes of democratic stabilization in interwar Europe which they claim was caused by three factors. First, more than class-cleavages democratic (in)stability was a result of the handling of ethnic or religious cleavages. Second, ideas mattered. Diffusion of ideas through networks of mutual learning between independent actors accounts for the geographical clustering of 34 democratic survival and breakdown, respectively. Third, the party system and the individual parties had profoundly stronger effects than hitherto assumed. Parties and their interaction developed the ideas and policies that were significantly different between democratic survivors and casualties. The governments of the democratic survivors produced policies to combat anti-systemic forces while the governments of the casualties passively led extremists capture the political process and eventually political power (Capoccia and Ziblatt 2010: 946-949). I disagree with each of these interpretations of the interwar democratic trajectories in the following sense. First, as is rightly noted by Kopstein and Wittenberg (2010), ethnic tensions within the new states forged at Versailles in 1919 have largely been ignored since analyses have focused on class-cleavages and interactions in effect largely ignoring the trajectories of Eastern Europe and states of former empires. However, as this insight reveals, the challenges of national minority inclusion are better conceived of as structural factors rather than phenomena that could be manipulated by actors. Second, ideas were diffused by networks acting across borders. Weyland (2010) rightly notes how diffusion plays a significant part in accounting the geographical clustering of cases. However, as he also notes, the ways in which and the degree to which ideas could travel from country to country vary with the national context. For instance, fascist ideas were in some places successfully replicated, in other places blockaded (see also, Mann 2004: 43). Just as the national context must take the international one largely as a given, so are international ideational trends formed by the national discourse. I here focus on the national context. Third, the argument that ideas were forged in the minds of party politicians acting on a tabula rasa seems unconvincing. As the geographical pattern implies, such a contingent argument is weak in explaining the systematic variation of ideas across countries. The question thus remains why governments and “bording parties” in the survivor cases held genuinely more democratic attitudes than governments 35 in the casualty cases. Where did the democratic ideas of French politicians as opposed to the weakly democratic attitudes of Germany’s Hindenburg stem from? In the paper, I investigate the causes of the differing records of democratic breakdown and survival among six cases: Czechoslovakia, Finland, France, Germany, Spain, and Uruguay. These were all “swing states” because they experienced considerable anti-systemic pressure from within or outside the political system against the democratic government. On comparison, they contrast with “safe-home” democracies such as the Scandinavian ones, United Kingdom, Netherlands, Switzerland, and the Neo-Europes and the “doomed” democracies of Southeastern and Eastern Europe (cf. Mann 2004: 38-40; Capoccia 2005: 7).9 To simplify the analysis, I limit my analysis to the period under the Great Depression starting in 1929 and continuing through to WWII. First, this makes for controlling for the influence of the structure of the international system which gradually became less democratic during the 1920s and decisively turned anti-democratic in 1933 with Hitler’s takeover in Germany. This pressured all democracies alike during the Great Depression (Boix 2011: 823). While I acknowledge the relevance of the economic crisis as a trigger cause of anti-systemic movements, it has been shown that crisis-level and level of socioeconomic development (that is, the existence of a strong middle class) are insufficient in explaining democratic stability (Bermeo 1997; Ertman 1998). Rather, what mattered was whether and how the state apparatus and the political system as such reacted to the crisis and the degree to which antisystemic forces could rise and gain significance in the first place (Bermeo 1997: 19-20; de Bromhead, Eichengreen, and O’Rourke 2012). To put substance to the geographical pattern of democratic breakdown and survival, which is important in reaching a satisfying explanation (Møller 2013: 701), my working hypothesis 9 Other possible swing states such as Belgium, Italy, and the Latin American democracies of Argentina and Chile could be explored. Italy however experienced its breakdown many years before the Great Depression (in 1922) while Belgium was comparatively a somewhat weak version of a swing state that could rather belong to the Northwestern family (cf. Mann 2004: 41; Capoccia 2005: 14). Similar lines as in Uruguay could be drawn when assessing the breakdown causes in Argentina and Chile but, for the sake of focus, at most I only use these as “shadow cases” for comparison. 36 is that a conjunction of factors separate the survivors from the casualties. The democratic survivors either had or developed gradually through the 1920s a dense civil society and an institutionalized party system as well as administrative effectiveness and a monopoly on violence. These factors were each necessary but only in conjunction sufficient for democratic survival to result from the societal conflicts of the Great Depression. Democracies needed not only a genuine democratic attitudinal edge and determination among their elites and populations, they also basic state capacity and authority to enforce the anti-systemic laws of the elites and fight the economic crisis by administrative means. Germany suffered from a weakly institutionalized and polarized party system and a disunited state security apparatus (Ertman 1998: 502-503; Bermeo 2003: 35-41) which produced the deeply incapable and passive leadership of Hindenburg, von Papen, and von Schleicher that invited Hitler to power by constitutional and democratic means. By comparison, Spain’s democracy ended in civil war in 1936 because the democratic trend was not that prevalent among Spain’s military, conservatives, and middle-classes (Mann 2004: Ch. 9) and because the administration led the economic crisis slip out of hand only worsening the ideological conflict between communists and fascists (Lapuente and Rothstein 2010). Finally, Terra’s initiative to install a softly authoritarian regime in Uruguay in 1933 to make the political system more effective and reinstall public order came about because of an institutionalized yet malfunctioning party system and a patrimonial, corrupt administration whose origins can be traced back to the Spanish conquerors (Lindahl 1962: 185; González 1991: 7, 35). I set up a comprehensive historical analysis of each swing state focusing on the origins and development of the four factors identified. While doing this, I maintain a comparative focus on the basis of the logic of comparative control. Even though the aim is to develop a general 37 explanation, I also am aware of contingent effects, which contribute to explaining for instance the survivals of Czechoslovakian and Finnish democracy. 38 References Aarebrot, Frank, and Sten Berglund. “Statehood, Secularization, Cooptation: Explaining Democratic Survival in Inter-War Europe: Stein Rokkan’s Conceptual Map Revisited.” Historical Social Research 20, no. 2 (1995): 210-225. Acemoglu, Daron, and James A. Robinson. Why Nations Fail. New York, NY: Crown Business, 2012. Acemoglu, Daron, James A. Robinson, and Rafael J. Santos. “The Monopoly of Violence: Evidence from Colombia.” Journal of the European Economic Association 11, S1 (2013): 5-44. Ake, Claude. Democracy and Development in Africa. Washington D.C.: The Brookings Institution, 1996. Aldcroft, Derek E. Europe’s Third World: The European Periphery in the Interwar Years. Bodmin, Great Britain: MPG Books. Andersen, David, Jørgen Møller, and Svend-Erik Skaaning. ”The State-Democracy Nexus: Conceptual Distinctions, Theoretical Perspectives, and Comparative Approaches.” Democratization, forthcoming. Andersen, David, Jørgen Møller, Svend-Erik Skaaning, and Lasse Lykke Rørbæk. ”State Capacity and Political Regime Stability: A Two-edged Sword?” Democratization, forthcoming. Anderson, Jeffrey J. Regional Integration and Democracy: Expanding on the European Experience. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield Publishers, 1999. Bäck, Hanna, and Axel Hadenius. “Democracy and State Capacity: Exploring a J-Shaped Relationship.” Governance 21, no. 1 (2008): 1-24. Bayley, David H. “The Police and Political Development in Europe.” In: The Formation of National States in Western Europe, edited by Charles Tilly. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1975. Bermeo, Nancy. “Getting Mad or Going Mad? Citizens, Scarcity, and the Breakdown of Democracy in Interwar Europe.” CSD Working Papers, 1997. Bermeo, Nancy. Ordinary People in Extraordinary Times: The Citizenry and the Breakdown of Democracy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2003. 39 Bertrand, Jacques. “Democratization and Religious and Nationalist Conflict in Post-Suharto Indonesia.” In: Democratization and Identity: Regimes and Ethnicity in East and Southeast Asia, edited by Susan J. Henders, and Susan J. Plymouth. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books, 2004. Boix, Carles. “Democracy, Development, and the International System.” American Political Science Review 105, no. 4 (2011): 809-828. Boix, Carles, Michael K. Miller, and Sebastian Rosato. “A Complete Dataset of Political Regimes, 1800-2007.” Comparative Political Studies, S (2012): 1-32. Bratton, Michael, and Nicolas Van De Walle. “Neopatrimonial Regimes and Political Transitions in Africa.” World Politics 46, no. 4 (1994): 453-489. Bratton, Michael, and Eric C. C. Chang. “State Building and Democratization in Sub-Saharan Africa: Forwards, Backwards, or Together?” Comparative Political Studies 39, no. 9 (2006): 10591083. Brenner, Neil, Bob Jessop, Martin Jones, and Gordon MacLeod. State/Space – A Reader. Oxford, UK: Blackwell Publishing, 2003. BTI. Methodology. Berlin: Bertelsmann Stiftung, 2012. Bunce, Valerie. “Comparative Democratization: Big and Bounded Generalizations.” Comparative Political Studies 33, no. 6-7 (2000): 703-734. Cammack, Diana. “The Logic of African Neopatrimonialism: What Role for Donors?” Development Policy Review 25, no. 5 (2007): 599-614. Capoccia, Giovanni. Defending Democracy. Baltimore, MD: The John Hopkins University Press, 2005. Capoccia, Giovanni, and Daniel Ziblatt. “The Historical Turn in Democratization Studies: A New Research Agenda for Europe and Beyond.” Comparative Political Studies 43, no. 8-9 (2010): 931968. Carbone, Giovanni, and Vincenzo Memoli. “Does democratization foster state consolidation? A panel analysis of the ‘backward hypothesis’.” Working paper of the research project ‘The economic, social and political consequences of democratic reforms. A quantitative and qualitative analysis’, 2008. Carothers, Thomas. “The “Sequencing” Fallacy.” Journal of Democracy 18, no. 1 (2007): 12-27. 40 Case, William. “Semi-Democracy in Malaysia: Withstanding the Pressures for Regime Change.” Pacific Affairs 66, no. 2 (1993): 183-205. Cederman, Lars, Andreas Wimmer, and Brian Min. “Why Do Ethnic Groups Rebel?: New Data and Analysis.” World Politics 62, no. 1 (2010): 87-119. Cheibub, José Antonio, Jennifer Gandhi, and James Raymond Vreeland. “Democracy and Dictatorship Revisited.” Public Choice 143, no. 1-2 (2009): 67-101. Chu, Yun-han, Michael Bratton, Marta Lagos, and Sandeep Shastri. “Public Opinion and Democratic Legitimacy.” Journal of Democracy 19, no. 2 (2008): 74-87. Clapham, Christopher. “Degrees of Statehood.” Review of International Studies 24, no. 2 (1998): 143–57. Collier, David, and Steven Levitsky. “Democracy with Adjectives: Conceptual Innovation in Comparative Research.” World Politics 49, no. 3 (1997): 430-451. Coppedge, Michael, and John Gerring, with David Altman, Michael Bernhard, Steven Fish, Allen Hicken, Matthew Kroenig, Staffan L. Lindberg, Kelly McCann, Pamela Paxton, Holly A. Semetko, Svend-Erik Skaaning, Jeffrey Staton, and Jan Teorell. “Conceptualizing and Measuring Democracy: A New Approach.” Perspectives on Politics 9, no. 2, (2011): 247-267. Dahl, Robert A. Democracy and its Critics. USA: Yale University, 1989. Daskalovski, Zhidas. “Democratic consolidation and the ‘stateness’ problem: The case of Macedonia.” Ethnopolitics: Formerly Global Review of Ethnopolitics 3, no. 2: 2004: 52-66. Davenport, Christian. ”State Repression and Political Order.” Annual Review of Political Science 10, no. 1 (2007): 1-23. de Bromhead, Alan, Barry Eichengreen, and Kevin O’Rourke. “Right Wing Political Extremism in the Great Depression.” Updated version of working paper presented at the conference on “The Ethics of Economics” October 5 2011, 2012. Dryzek, John S., and Patrick Dunleavy. Theories of the Democratic State. Great Britain: Palgrave MacMillan, 2009. Dukalskis, Alexander. “Stateness problems or regime unification? Explaining obstacles to democratization in Burma/Myanmar.” Democratization 16, no. 5 (2009): 945-968. Durkheim, Émile. Om den sociale arbejdsdeling. Copenhagen: Hans Reitzels Forlag, 2000. 41 Easterly, William and Levine, Ross. “Africa’s Growth Tragedy: Policies and Ethnic Divisions.” The Quarterly Journal of Economics 112, no. 4 (1997): 1203-1250. Elkins, Zachary, and John Sides. Seeking Stateness. Unpublished, 2008. Elklit, Jørgen, and Andrew Reynolds. “The Impact of Election Administration on the Legitimacy of Emerging Democracies: A New Comparative Politics Research Agenda.” Commonwealth & Comparative Politics 40, no. 2 (2002): 86-119. Englebert, Pierre. State Legitimacy and Development in Africa. Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner Publishers, 2000. Englehart, Neil J. “State Capacity, State Failure, and Human Rights.” Journal of Peace Research 46, no. 2 (2009): 163-180. Ertman, Thomas. Birth of the Leviathan: Building States and Regimes in Medieval and Early Modern Europe. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press, 1997. Ertman, Thomas. “Democracy and Dictatorship in Interwar Western Europe Revisited.” World Politics 50, no. 3 (1998): 474-505. Evans, Peter B. Embedded Autonomy: States & Industrial Transformation. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1995. Evans, Peter B. “The Eclipse of the State? Reflections on Stateness in an Era of Globalization.” World Politics 50, no. 1 (1997): 62-87. Evans, Peter B., and James E. Rauch. “Bureaucracy and growth: A cross-national analysis of the effect of “Weberian” state structures on economic growth”. American Sociological Review 64, no. 5 (1999): 748-765. Fearon, James D., and David D. Laitin. “Ethnicity, Insurgency, and Civil War.” American Political Science Review 97, no. 1 (2003): 75-90. Fjelde, Hanne, and Indra De Soysa. ”Coercion, Co-optation, or Cooperation?: State Capacity and the Risk of Civil War, 1961-2004.” Conflict Management and Peace Science 26, no. 1 (2009): 5-25. Fukuyama, Francis. State-Building – Governance and World Order in the Twenty-First Century. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 2004. Fukuyama, Francis. ““Stateness” First.” Journal of Democracy 16, no. 1 (2005): 84-88. 42 Fukuyama, Francis. The Origins of Political Order. London: Profile books ltd, 2012. Fukuyama, Francis. “Democracy and the Quality of the State.” Journal of Democracy 24, no. 4 (2013): 5-16. Gasiorowski, Mark J., and Timothy J. Power. “The Structural Determinants of Democratic Consolidation: Evidence from the Third World.” Comparative Political Studies 31, no. 6 (1998): 740-771. Geddes, Barbara, Joseph Wright, and Erica Frantz. “New Data on Autocratic Breakdown and Regime Transitions.” 2013. http://www.dictators.la.psu.edu/ Gellner, Ernest. Nations and Nationalism. John Wiley & Sons, Ltd., 2006. George, Alexander L., and Andrew Bennett. Case Studies and Theory Development in the Social Sciences. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2005. Gerschewski, Johannes. “The three pillars of stability: legitimation, repression, and co-optation in autocratic regimes.” Democratization 20, no. 1 (2013): 13-38. Giddens, Anthony. “Classes, Capitalism, and the State.” Theory and Society 9 (1980): 877-890. Giddens, Anthony. The Nation-State and Violence. Berkeley and Los Angeles, CA: University of California Press, 1987. Gill, Graeme. The Nature and Development of the Modern State. New York, NY: Palgrave MacMillan, 2003. Gilley, Bruce. “The Determinants of State Legitimacy: Results for 72 Countries.” International Political Science Review 27, no. 1 (2006): 47-71. Goertz, Gary. Social Science Concepts – A User’s Guide. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2006. González, Luis E. Political Structures and Democracy in Uruguay. Indiana: Helen Kellogg Institute, 1991. Gurr, Ted. People Versus States: Minorities at Risk in the New Century. US Institute of Peace Press, 2000. 43 Gurr, Ted Robert, Keith Jaggers, and Will H. Moore. “The transformation of the western state: The growth of democracy, autocracy, and state power since 1800.” Studies in Comparative International Development 25, no. 1 (1990): 73-108. Habermas, Jürgen. “The European nation state. Its achievements and its limitations. On the past and future of sovereignty and citizenship.” Ratio Juris 9, no. 2 (1996): 125-137. Hadenius, Axel. Institutions and Democratic Citizenship. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 2001. Haggard, Stephan, and Robert R. Kaufman. “Inequality and Regime Change: Democratic Transitions and the Stability of Democratic Rule.” American Political Science Review 106, no. 3 (2012): 495-516. Hansen, Mogens Herman. “Polis and City-State: An Ancient Concept and its Modern Equivalent.” In Acts of the Copenhagen Polis Centre Vol. 5. Copenhagen: Munksgaard, 1998. Hendrix, Cullen. “Measuring state capacity: Theoretical and empirical implications for the study of civil conflict.” Journal of Peace Research 47, no. 3 (2010): 273-285. Herbst, Jeffrey. States and Power in Africa. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2000. Holmes, Stephen. Passions and Constraint: On the Theory of Liberal Democracy. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1995. Holsti, K.J. “War, Peace, and the State of the State.” International Political Science Review 16, no. 4 (1995): 319-339. Huntington, Samuel P. Political Order in Changing Societies. USA: Yale University Press, 1968. Huntington, Samuel P. The Third Wave: Democratization in the Late Twentieth Century. Oklahoma: University of Oklahoma Press, 1991. Ilyin, Mikhail, Tatiana Khavenson, Elena Meleshkina, Denis Stukal, and Elena Zharikova. “Factors of Post-Socialist Stateness.” Working Paper 3, Political Science. National Research University Higher School of Economics, 2012. Jackson, Robert H., and Carl G. Rosberg. “Why Africa’s Weak States Persist: The Empirical and the Juridical in Statehood.” World Politics 35, no. 1 (1982): 1-24. Jessop, Bob. The Future of the Capitalist State. Oxford, UK: Blackwell Publishing, 2002. 44 Kaufmann, Daniel; Kraay, Aart and Mastruzzi, Massimo. “Governance Matters VIII: Aggregate and Individual Governance Indicators 1996-2008.” Policy Research Working Paper 4978, World Bank, 2009. Kopstein, Jeffrey S., and Jason Wittenberg. “Beyond Dictatorship and Democracy: Rethinking National Minority Inclusion and Regime Type in interwar Eastern Europe.” Comparative Political Studies 43, no. 8-9 (2010): 1089-1118. Kostovicova, Denisa, and Vesna Bojicic-Dzelilovic. Persistent State Weakness in the Global Age. Great Britain: Ashgate Publishing Group, 2009. Kposowa, Augustine J., and J. Craig Jenkins. “The structural sources of military coups in postcolonial Africa.” American Journal of Sociology 99, no. 1 (1999): 126-163. Kraxberger, Brennan M. “Failed States: Temporary Obstacles to Democratic Diffusion or Fundamental Holes in the World Political Map?” Third World Quarterly 28, no. 6 (2007): 10551071. Kurtz, Marcus J., and Andrew Schrank. “Capturing State Strength: Experimental and Econometric Approaches.” Revista de ciencia política 32, no. 3 (2012): 613-621. Kuthy, Daniel W. The Effect of State Capacity on Democratic Transition and the Survival of New Democracies. Dissertation, Department of Political Science, Georgia State University, 2011. Lapuente, Victor, and Bo Rothstein. “Civil War Spain versus Swedish Harmony: The Quality of Government Factor.” QoG Working Paper Series 10, (2010). Lemay-Hébert, Nicolas. Statebuilding without Nation-building? “Legitimacy, State Failure and the Limits of the Institutionalist Approach.” Journal of Intervention and Statebuilding 3, no. 1 (2009): 21-45. Lichbach, Mark Irving. Governability in Interwar Europe: A Formal Model of Authority and Performance. Quality and Quantity 16, no. 3 (1982): 197-216. Lijphart, Arend. “Consociational Democracy.” World Politics 21, no. 2 (1969): 207-225. Lindahl, Göran G. Uruguay’s New Path: A Study in Politics during the First Colegiado. Stockholm: Library and Institute of Ibero-American Studies, 1962. Lindberg, Staffan I. Democracy and Elections in Africa. Baltimore, MD: The John Hopkins University Press, 2006. 45 Linz, Juan J., and Alfred Stepan. The Breakdown of Democratic Regimes: Crisis, Breakdown, and Reequilibration. Maltimore, MD: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1978. Linz, Juan J., and Alfred Stepan. Problems of Democratic Transition and Consolidation - Southern Europe, South America and Post-Communist Europe. Baltimore, MD: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1996. Lipset, Seymour Martin. “Some Social Requisites of Democracy: Economic Development and Political Legitimacy.” American Political Science Review 53, no. 1 (1959): 69-105. Lipset, Seymour Martin. “The Social Requisites of Democracy Revisited: 1993 Presidential Adress.” American Sociological Review 59, no. 1 (1994): 1-22. Loewenstein, Karl. “Militant Democracy and Fundamental Rights, II.” American Political Science Review 31, no. 4 (1937): 638-658. Loveman, Brian. For la Patria: Politics and the Armed Forces in Latin America. Wilmington, DE: Scholarly Resources Inc., 1999. Mahoney, James, and Dietrich Rueschemeyer. Comparative Historical Analysis in the Social Sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003. Mainwaring, Scott, and Scully, Timothy R. Building Democratic Institutions: Party Systems in Latin America. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1995. Mainwaring, Scott, and Timothy Scully. Democratic Governance in Latin America. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 2010. Mann, Michael. The Sources of Social Power, Volume 1: A History of Power from the Beginning to AD 1760. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986. Mann, Michael. Fascists. West Nyack, NY: Cambridge University Press. Mann, Michael. “The Autonomous Power of the State: Its Origins, Mechanisms and Results.” In: State/Space: A Reader, edited by Neil Brenner, Bob Jessop, Martin Jones, and Gordon MacLeod. Malden: Wiley-Blackwell, 2003. Mazzuca, Sebastián L. “Access to Power Versus Exercise of Power: Reconceptualizing the Quality of Democracy in Latin America.” Studies in Comparative International Development 45, no. 3 (2010): 334-357. 46 Mazzuca, Sebastián L., and Gerardo Munck. “State or Democracy First? Alternative Perspectives on the State-Democracy Nexus.” Paper prepared for Annual Meeting of the American Political Science Association, August 29-September 1, 2013. Migdal, Joel. Strong Societies and Weak States. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1988. Migdal, Joel. “Researching the State.” In: Comparative Politics: Rationality, Culture, and Structure, edited by Mark Irving Lichbach and Alan S. Zuckerman. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009. Munck, Gerardo. “Disaggregating Political Regime: Conceptual Issues in the Study of Democratization.” Working Paper #228, August, 1996. Munck, Gerardo. “Democratic theory after Transitions to from Autocratic Rule.” Perspectives on Politics 9, no. 2 (2011): 333-343. Møller, Jørgen. “When one might not see the wood for the trees: the ‘historical turn’ in democratization studies, critical junctures, and cross-case comparisons.” Democratization 20, no. 4 (2013): 693-715. Møller, Jørgen, and Svend-Erik Skaaning. Requisites of Democracy – Conceptualization, measurement, and explanation. Abingdon: Routledge, 2011. Nathan, Andrew J. “Authoritarian Resilience.” Journal of Democracy 14, no. 1 (2003): 6-17. Nettl, J. P. “The State as a Conceptual Variable.” World Politics 20, no. 4 (1968): 559-592. Oberschall, Anthony. “The Two-State Solution: Wrong Goal or Wrong Leaders?” Ethnopolitics: Formerly Global Review of Ethnopolitics 10, no. 3-4 (2011): 457-459. O’Donnell, Guillermo. Bureaucratic Authoritarianism: Argentina, 1966-1973, in Comparative Perspective. Berkeley and Los Angeles, CA: University of California Press, 1988. O’Donnell, Guillermo. Democracy, Agents, and the State: Theory with Comparative Intent. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 2010. Przeworski, Adam, and Fernando Limongi. “Modernization: Theories and Facts.” World Politics 49, no. 2 (1997): 155-183. Przeworski, Adam, Michael E. Alvarez, José Antonio Cheibub, and Fernando Limongi. Democracy and Development: Political Institutions and Well-Being in the World, 1950-1990. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000. 47 Putnam, Robert D. Making Democracy Work: Civic Traditions in Modern Italy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1993. Repnik, Hans Peter, and Ralf-Matthias Mohs. “”Good Governance”, Democracy and Development Paradigms.” Intereconomics January/February (1992): 28-33. Rokkan, Stein. “Dimensions of State Formation and Nation-Building: A Possible Paradigm for Research on Variations within Europe.” In: The Formation of National States in Western Europe, edited by Charles Tilly. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1975. Rose, Richard, and Doh Chull Shin. “Democratization Backwards: The Problem of Third-Wave Democracies.” British Journal of Political Science 31, no. 2 (2001): 331-354. Ross, Michael. “Mineral Wealth, Conflict, and Equitable Development.” In: Institutional Pathways to Equity: Addressing Inequality Traps, edited by Anthony J. Bebbington, Anis A. Dani, Arjan de Haan, and Michael Walton. The World Bank, 2008. Rotberg, Robert I. When States Fail. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2003. Rothstein, Bo. The Quality of Government. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2011. Rothschild, Joseph. East Central Europe between the Two World Wars. Washington D.C.: University of Washington Press, 1974. Rueschemeyer, Dietrich, and Peter B. Evans. “The State and Economic Transformation: Toward an Analysis of the Conditions Underlying Effective Intervention.” In Bringing the State Back In, edited by Peter B. Evans, Dietrich Rueschemeyer, and Theda Skocpol. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985. Rueschemeyer, Dietrich Evelyne Huber Stephens, and John D. Stephens. Capitalist Development and Democracy. University of Chicago Press, 1992. Rustow, Dankwart. “Transitions to Democracy: Toward a Dynamic Model.” Comparative Politics 2, no. 3 (1970): 337-363. Sandbrook, Richard. “The State and Economic Stagnation in Tropical Africa.” World Development 14, no. 3 (1986): 319-332. Santiso, Carlos. “Good Governance and Aid Effectiveness: The World Bank and Conditionality.” The Georgetown Public Policy Review 7, no. 1 (2001): 1-22. 48 Sartori, Giovanni. “Comparing and Miscomparing.” Journal of Theoretical Politics 3, no. 3 (1991): 243-257. Saylor, Ryan. “Concepts, Measures, and Measuring Well: An Alternative Outlook.” Sociological Methods & Research 42, no. 3 (2013): 354-391. Scharpf, Fritz W. “Interdependence and democratic legitimation.” MPlfG Working Paper 98, no. 2, Max Planck Institute for the Study of Societies, 1998. Schedler, Andreas. What is Democratic Consolidation? Journal of Democracy 9, no. 2 (1998): 91107. Schumpeter, Joseph A. Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy. Abingdon: Routledge, 2010. Skocpol, Theda. States and Social Revolutions: A Comparative Analysis of France, Russia and China. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979. Skocpol, Theda. “Bringing the State Back In: Strategies of Analysis in Current Research.” In Bringing the State Back In, edited by Peter B. Evans, Dietrich Rueschemeyer, and Theda Skocpol. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985. Slater, Dan. Ordering Power: Contentious Politics and Authoritarian Leviathans in Southeast Asia. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press, 2010. Slater, Dan, and Daniel Ziblatt. “The Enduring Indispensability of the Controlled Comparison.” Comparative Political Studies, forthcoming. Sojo, Carlos. The State under Scrutiny: Public opinion, Stateness and government performance in Latin America. Santiago, Chile: UN, 2011. Stepan, Alfred, Juan J. Linz, and Yogendra Yadav. Crafting State-Nations – India and other Multidimensional Democracies. Baltimore, MD: The John Hopkins University Press, 2011. Suleiman, E. “Bureaucracy and Democratic Consolidation: Lessons from Eastern Europe.” In Transition to Democracy, edited by L. Anderson. New York, NY: Columbia University Press, 1999. Svolik, Milan. “Authoritarian Reversals and Democratic Consolidation.” American Political Science Review 102, no. 2 (2008): 153-168. Tansey, Oisín. “Does democracy need sovereignty?” Review of International Studies 37, no. 4 (2011): 1515-1536. 49 Tilly, Charles. “Reflections on the History of European State-Making.” In: The Formation of National States in Western Europe, edited by Charles Tilly. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1975a. Tilly, Charles. “Western State-Making and Theories of Political Transformation.” In: The Formation of National States in Western Europe, edited by Charles Tilly. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1975b. Tilly, Charles. Democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007. Tilly, Charles, and Sidney Tarrow. Contentious Politics. Boulder, CO: Paradigm Publishers, 2007. UNDP. Democracy in Latin America: Towards a Citizens’ Democracy. Buenos Aires: UNDP, 2004. Van De Walle, Steven. “Measuring bureaucratic quality in governance indicators.” 8th Public Management Conference, Los Angeles, USA, 2005. Weber, Max. Wirtschaft und Gesellschaft. Köln: Kiepenheuer & Witsch, 1964. Weyland, Kurt. „The Diffusion of Regime Contention in European Democratization, 1930-1940.“ Comparative Political Studies 43, no. 8-9 (2010): 1148-1176. Wimmer, Andreas. Waves of War: Nationalism, State Formation, and Ethnic Exclusion in the Modern World. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2013. 50