Agee 1 Alley Agee Truth PKP 2012 Can No Fault Disagreements Exist? In an age where the beliefs and opinions of others are more prominently displayed and accessible than ever before, it is no wonder that the theory of relativism has been developed and clung to so passionately. When faced with questions of whether one position should or could be preferred over another position, it seems easiest to simply say, “It’s all relative.” Relativism has been defended by many, and the simple argument of “it’s all relative” has been left behind by defenders of the theory, though much of what relativism is about can be traced back to this simple phrase. The issue, then, becomes whether this phrase and the theory can actually hold up in matters of significant value. An important concept in relativism is that of the no fault disagreement (NFD)—this is how certain relativists have explained the phenomena of relativist disagreement. Essentially, an NFD occurs when there is some kind of disagreement, or contradiction between beliefs of two people. The relativist asserts that, although the two people may have different beliefs, they are assessing from differing perspectives—i.e. they have different standard—therefore neither person—or rather, neither belief—is wrong. The beliefs themselves can only be judged relative to the standard within which they were created, therefore neither of two or more parties with different standards concerning the same content will be judged “wrong” or “at fault.” There are certain restrictions and boundaries for a faultless disagreement, as outlined by Herman Cappelan and John Hawthorne. A disagreement must actually exist: Agee 2 It bears emphasis in this connection that there are plenty of cases where one of a pair of people says ‘That is fun,’ but where we have no significant intuition of contradiction between the two assertions. Suppose a caterer says of a certain party ‘That party is not going to be fun. I have to cook hors d’oeuvres all night.’ Suppose that, meanwhile, someone in a separate conversation says of the same party, ‘That party is going to be fun. I get to meet lots of school buddies that I haven’t seen in a long time.’ In this case we have absolutely no strong sense at all that the people are in disagreement.1 What Cappelen and Hawthorne are arguing is that for a no fault disagreement to exist the two parties must be aware of the other’s argument and must be in disagreement with it—two beliefs or statements cannot be pieced together out of context. (It may be important to note that Cappelen and Hawthorne are working from a contextualist perspective, and the chapter this quotation comes from outlines their arguments for why contextualism should be preferred to relativism.) This idea of a no fault disagreement has helped to explain away differences in opinion with the relativist theory. If someone were to say that apples are delicious, but a friend says apples are not delicious, the NFD concept could be applied. First, they would recognize that each of them is coming from a different perspective and has different standards by which they judge the tastiness of apples. Then they can affirm that since their standards are different, neither of them has any fault, and therefore their disagreement, apparently, dissipates. Not everyone can accept this concept, and there have been many different contentions raised—that it is too easy a solution, that the parameters are ill-defined, or that it is impossible to distinguish from an absolutist disagreement and therefore impossible to Herman Cappelen and John Hawthorne, ‘Predicates of Personal Taste,’ Relativism and Monadic Truth, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009), 109. 1 Agee 3 express.2 Perhaps the most convincing of these contentions is that it simply cannot exist— that “cases where the sense of no fault runs deep are the ones where the sense of disagreement runs shallow.”3 In this paper I will examine this contention, but from a perspective of the value and importance of the disagreement. Can a faultless disagreement exist in cases where the beliefs are not shallow, where the beliefs are highly valued by those in the disagreement? To begin to answer this question, an introduction to different types of statements is necessary. In ‘Predicates of Personal Taste,’ Cappelen and Hawthorne draw upon Peter Lasersohn’s vocabulary of autocentric and exocentric,4 and it is this that I will use in the remainder of the paper. Cappelen and Hawthorne explain the usage of the terms well, using the example of taste: …we can say that use of a taste predicate use of a taste predicate is autocentric iff its truth conditions are given by a completion that indexes the predicate to the speaker. Thus, a speaker says ‘That is filling’ autocentrically iff its truth conditions are given by the claim ‘That is filling to me’ in the mouth of the speaker Meanwhile, a use if exocentric iff its truth conditions are given by a completion that indexes it to a person or group other than the speaker, which may, however, include the speaker.5 Put in other words, an autocentric statement refers to a statement made that the speaker intends to apply only to himself or herself, while an exocentric statement refers to a statement that the speaker intends to apply to another person or group. These two types of statements can be applied to the faultless disagreement concept in different ways. No fault disagreements may apply more easily to statements or believes of an autocentric nature. Take Dr. Adam Stewart-Wallace, Lecture, Truth, Pembroke-King’s Programme, July 2012. Cappelen and Hawthorne, 132. 4 Peter Lasersohn, “Context Dependence, Disagreement, and Predicates of Personal Taste,” Linguistics and Philosophy, Vol. 28 (6), 643-686. 5 Cappelen and Hawthorne, 104. 2 3 Agee 4 the example given above. Someone say that apples are delicious, but what they mean is autocentric: apples are delicious for them. Their friend, on the other hand, says that apples are not delicious, but what she means is also autocentric: apples are not delicious for her. The two different perspectives and standards are much more easily understood, and therefore it makes sense that neither person is at fault. One may argue, however, that since both people are speaking autocentrically, there is no disagreement at all—if neither person says the statement with the idea that apples are universally delicious and anyone who thinks otherwise is wrong, then perhaps there is no contradiction, and therefore no NFD. Perhaps no statements that are made autocentrically are disagreements. The only boundary with which faultless disagreements must fall under is that there must be, in fact, a disagreement. If there is no disagreement, then the idea of a faultless disagreement dissipates, at least in relation to autocentric statements. The relativist may not give up so easily though. Other than the idea that neither person is willing to defend their statements outside their own personal taste, there is no indication that a disagreement has not occurred. A relativist might argue that the fact that the two parties are able to accept the other’s position is evidence for the no fault disagreement. This may be a valid argument, but it doesn’t get them out of Cappelen’s and Hawthorne’s critique: that only shallow disagreements are faultless. The apple example certainly is shallow, and it would be difficult to think of an example that isn’t shallow. Furthermore, the relativist is certainly not out of the water for disagreements that arise from exocentric statements. The exocentric statement disagreement is the more interesting of the two; by its very nature it avoids most shallow arguments about personal matters. It also carries with it the Agee 5 idea that someone within the disagreement must be, at least, on the surface level, wrong: if someone believe that apples are universally delicious, at some level he or she does have to believe that someone who doesn’t think they are delicious is wrong. The relativist might be able to claim that both parties could reach some kind of faultless consensus, but the arguments here are much weaker than the same argument applied to the autocentric statements. The potential for statements which are highly important for the individual is also much greater than with autocentric statements, and it is to this idea that I turn to next. In the study of persuasive rhetoric, an idea is commonly held among scholars that, when trying to make a judgment about a particular issue, those with a high involvement value and those who value the issue more will have preconceived notions about the topic that are harder to change than those who do not care very much.6 It seems that this basic idea can also be applied to beliefs of a person within a disagreement. For example, take a person who does not highly value the deliciousness of apples—it is not important to her that she express that idea and that others receive it. Therefore, any “disagreement” she may get into about the deliciousness of apples simply doesn’t intrigue her very much. It is easier, then, for her to accept the idea of a no fault disagreement—it isn’t of any consequence to her to admit that perhaps the other person sees apples from a different perspective. A more important issue, however, may not be dismissed as easily. Let’s say that the same person who thinks apples are delicious (whether autocentrically or exocentrically, it doesn’t matter much) also believes that it is exocentrically wrong to eat meat, implying that it is wrong for everyone. Because of this belief, she gives up the eating of meat. A friend may come along and respond, “I think it’s perfectly acceptable to eat meat, and in fact, I believe it is wrong not to.” What place 6 This refers to Social Judgment Theory. Agee 6 does the faultless disagreement have here? If the eliminating of meat from the human diet is important enough, so important that a person chooses to give it up, then he or she would have to believe that the other person who does eat meat is wrong in his or her belief and lifestyle, particularly if the belief is exocentric. This disagreement is much harder to “dismiss” as no fault than the apple disagreement because both parties are more value-involved. Perhaps we should take the analogy even one step further. Suppose the same woman who believes apples are delicious and that it is wrong to eat meat also exocentrically believes that murder should never be committed. The same friend who believes apples are not delicious and that humans should eat meat also exocentrically believes (for the sake of the analogy) that murder is perfectly acceptable. Now the disagreement is even more valueinvolved. At some level, the first woman simply will not be able to accept that murder is acceptable, especially since she believes that it is wrong for everyone and not just for her. Similarly, the person who believes murder is acceptable will not be able to accept the judgments made by her friend. At this point, faultless disagreement becomes impossible. A committed relativist, however, might try and reply that a no fault disagreement exists, though it may not be acknowledged by both parties. This argument is extremely weak: if NFD’s can exist that are not acknowledged by the parties within the disagreement, then what is the value of the NFD in the first place? Furthermore, many of the other problems with NFD briefly mentioned earlier simply become stronger, particularly the distinction argument and the boundary argument. If NFD’s can exist without acknowledgement, then all arguments have the potential to become NFD’s, making it extremely difficult to distinguish between NFD’s and actual absolutist disagreement. Similarly, if NFD’s exist without acknowledgment the parameters extend infinitely. Agee 7 If NFD’s cannot hold up (or even exist) in disagreements involving beliefs of high value, then what is left for the relativist in justifying disagreements? Presumably, nothing. Does this discount the entire relativist theory? Not necessarily: it simply means that no fault disagreements do not work outside of shallow contradictions. The relativist, then, must come up with a different theory for how relativism plays out in real-world belief clashes, or else some other theory may need to be accepted. Perhaps this paper is a good argument for local relativism—issues that are not highly valued can be considered relative and can have no fault disagreements, whilst more important issues (i.e. those which only global relativists would force into a relative perspective) may need more careful consideration. Regardless, I have presented an area in which it may be more difficult for faultless disagreement to exist: the exocentric, highly valued statements.