Enjoyment, Reasons, and Value The definition of first-person-reason enjoyment adds to the requirements for plain enjoyment the condition that the “of φ, under A” belief/desire pair functions as first-person reason, under A, to φ. The definition of value-enjoyment adds the definition of first-person-reason enjoyment the requirement that the enjoyer value φ’s having A. We begin with first-person-reason enjoyment. First-Person Reason Enjoyment It would, of course, be wrong to single out such enjoyments as a significant type if the relevant “of φ, under A” belief/desire pair involved an enjoyment were always a first-person reason to φ. But this is clearly not the case, as the following examples show. Enjoyments Without The First-Person Reason Thomas Gouge’s intensely religious upbringing instilled in him the conviction that a man should not feel erotic desire for another man. The adolescent Gouge nonetheless enjoys looking at his best friend under an array of features A indicative of sexual attraction. Thus, in terms of the definition of enjoyment, he believes, of his experience of looking at his friend, under A, that it is occurring, and he desires, of the experience, under A, that it should occur for its own sake. Gouge’s religious convictions, however, lead him to conclude that the belief/desire pair does not provide even the most miniscule degree of justification for looking in a sexual way at 1 his friend; he views the desire as an alien invader to be resisted and destroyed, not a citizen of the realm of desires capable of providing him with a justification for action. Even though the relevant belief/desire pair does not serve as a first-person reason for Gouge, he does enjoy looking at his friend in a sexual way. He regards the enjoyment in the same way in regards its constituent belief/desire: a temptation Satan has placed in his path. But he enjoys nonetheless.1 Such examples abound. Suppose Sarah is eating a desert she mistakenly thought contained no chocolate. She suddenly finds herself with the occurrent belief, of her taste experience, under tasting chocolate, that it is occurring; and with the felt desire, of the experience, under tasting chocolate, that it should occur for its own sake. She reacts with disgust. Until recently, she suffered from an uncontrollable urge to eat to chocolate, and her inability to resist diminished her self-respect; finally, she rebelled and banned chocolate from her diet. She now views any desire for chocolate just as Gouge views any sexual attraction to men, an alien invader to be resisted and destroyed. The sudden taste of chocolate does not undermine Sarah’s convictions; she spits out the desert and attacks the desire by recalling vivid memories of her loss of self-respect and her weight gain. She most certainly does not regard the belief/desire pair as providing any degree of justification for tasting the chocolate.2 1 Weakness of the will. 2 Weakness of the will. 2 Is there another class of examples in which you do not believe that the associated “of φ, under A” belief/desire pair does not provide any justification to φ, but in which that pair nonetheless does not serve as a first-person reason to φ? Suppose, for example, you are having scotch in the lobby bar after a transatlantic flight; the combination of jet lag and alcohol has produced a detached, hazy self-consciousness from which you bemusedly observe the bar. You enjoy the experience, and unlike Gouge and Sarah, you do not view your desire as an alien force; you have no objection to it. Must the associated “of φ, under A” belief/desire serve as a first-person reason to have the experience? Given our purposes, there is no need to answer the question. We do, however, offer the following considerations. One fact is clear. If someone asked you why you were gazing out at the bar instead of preparing for the paper you must present tomorrow. You might well respond, “I am enjoying it,” thereby offering (on our view) that the relevant belief/desire pair as a justification for devoting time to the experience. But suppose neither you nor anyone else ever raise the question of why you are devoting time to the experience. Must the belief/desire pair nonetheless serve as a first-person reason to have the experience? It is impossible to answer without a more detailed account of the motivationaljustificatory role of a reason. A Definition To define first-person reason enjoyment, first consider an example. Imagine Victoria is watching her eight–year old daughter perform in the 3 school play put on by her daughters’ fourth grade class. She enjoys the experience of watching the performance under an array A that includes, among a variety of other features, watching my daughter perform in the school play, watching her daughter do what many other children have done but do it in her particular way as something new to her. Thus, she believes, of her experience, under A, that it is occurring, and she desires, of that experience, under A, that it should occur for its own sake. The belief/desire pair functions as a first-person reason. She regards the pair as providing (at least a partial) justification for watching her daughter perform, a justification she would readily, indeed passionately, offer to others. If she were to offer the pair to others as a justification, she would describe some or all of the features in A, intending thereby to specify the features she believes watching her daughter exemplifies, and with regard to which she is filled with desire. Thus, the belief/desire pair is not merely a first-person reason to watch her daughter perform; it is a reason to have that experience as exemplifying the features in A. We will express this by saying that the pair is a reason under A for Victoria to have the experience. We define first-person-reason enjoyment as follows: x first-person-reason enjoys an experience or activity φ under A if and only if (1) x φ’s, and x's φing causes (2) – (3): (2) (a) x occurrently believes, of φ, under A, that it occurs; (b) and has the felt desire, of φ, under A, that it should occur for its own sake; (3) the belief/desire pair in (2) is a first-person reason under A for x to φ. 4 Two points bear emphasis. First, the first-person reason consists of an occurrent belief and a felt desire, the same belief and desire that are components of the feeling of enjoyment. In this way, the first-person-reason affirmation of φing is manifest in the feeling of enjoyment. One may rightly object that it is not manifest that the belief/desire pair is a first-person reason; it is just the components of that reason, the belief and desire that are present to consciousness. However, if one has sufficient self-knowledge and is sufficiently reflective, one will be able to readily identify the presentto-mind belief and desire pair as comprising a first-person reason. Second, what do we mean by saying that φ causes the first-person reason? Our answer rests on a point we made earlier: a belief/desire pair functions as a first-person reason only if one believes it provides some justification for action. The enjoyed experience or activity causes—or causally sustains—the belief/desire pair in its first-person-reason role by causing (causally sustaining) the belief that the pair provides a justification. We will (as we have been) use ‘cause’ for “cause to come into existence or causally sustain in existence”; we will, however, sometimes use ‘causally sustains’ when contextually convenient. The notion of causation to which we appeal continues to be the pragmatic, context-driven everyday concept of causation. To fully explain a particular use of such a concept, one must exhibit the characteristic patterns in which it is typically deployed. We do so in the course of this section. Our claim is that the definition characterizes a type of enjoyment that plays a central role in our lives. Why think that is true? The question divides 5 into two. What is the rationale for condition (3)—the belief/desire pair is a first-person reason? And, what is what the rationale for including the condition that φ causes the pair to serve as a first-person reason? Indeed, what does that mean? What causal mechanism do we have in mind? To see the rationale for (3), recall the point we made earlier: we guide our actions by the light of the justifications we take our first-person reasons to provide. We may lament that the light is weak, all too subject to distorting factors such as prejudice, and that such light as it does give is too frequently disregarded, but it is the light by which we proceed nonetheless. The point applies to enjoyments insofar as we are able to control when they occur and how long they endure. First-person reason enjoyments figure prominently in our lives because what is of actions generally is true of our enjoyment-seeking actions: we try to perform those for which we find some at least some degree of justification in our belief/desire pairs. To illustrate the point, return to Victoria. When she enjoys the experience watching her daughter perform, the relevant belief/desire serves as a first-person reason to have that experience. Now, recall that an “of φ, under A” belief desire pair is a reason for you under A to φ only if you believe that the pair provides at least some justification for φing. Thus, Victoria believes the pair provides at least some justification for having the experience. This is distinguishes it from the enjoyments illustrated by the Gouge and Sarah examples in which the belief/desire pair is resisted as an alien invader.3 We seek first-person We leave open the possibility illustrated by the jet lag example that there are enjoyments in which you have no objection to the associated belief/desire pair, but in which the pair is not a first-person reason. 3 6 reason enjoyments and avoid as alien those that are not. This is sufficient reason to single such enjoyments out as a type worthy of attention. Causation Now we turn to the rationale for the requirement that φ cause the “of φ, under A” belief/desire pair to serve as a first-person reason under A for x to φ. We begin by explaining the causal mechanism we have in mind. To see what we have in mind, recall that the following is a necessary condition of an “of φ, under A” belief/desire pair serving as a first-person reason under A for x to φ: x must believe that the pair provides some degree of justification for x’s φing. Our claim is that claim is that φ “causes the firstperson reason” by creating or causally sustaining the belief that the pair provides some degree of justification. This is not to claim that φ is causally sufficient for the pair serving as a first-person reason; it is just to claim that φ is a part of the causal ancestry the pair’s serving as a first-person reason. Examples are in order, but first two points bear emphasis to avoid misunderstanding. The first is that the “φ” in an “of φ, under A” belief/desire pair is not a type of experience or activity but a non-repeatable individual. It is the occurrence of that individual that causes one to believe the pair provides a justification for φing. The second point is that, typically at least, we explain the causal power of the experience or activity in part by appeal to what you value. For example, when you wonder what prompted my outburst of protest at a 7 faculty meeting, I explain that it was a passionate defense of a moral principle against the siren call of expediency made me think, and that fact made me think there was at least some justification for it. I add that we are all too easily seduced by expediency, and that I place a high value on defending against such seductions. My addition explains why my regarding my speaking out as the defense of a moral principle lead me to regard that fact about it as providing a justification for doings so—indeed, in this case, a sufficient justification. The explanation is causal on our everyday, pragmatic notion of causation. I understand my speaking out a defense of morality against the seduction of expediency, and that understanding combines with what I value produce in me the belief that my action’ having certain features justifies performing the action. On our everyday, pragmatic understanding of causation, the explanation is causal even if you reason your way to the belief; reasoning is one way to produce a belief. The links between one’s values and one’s beliefs about justification may be far from obvious. Suppose that Victoria has long held the following view on self-defense: when a safe retreat is available, one should retreat instead of defend when attacked with unlawful force. However, when a mugger threatens here with a knife, attitudes inculcated through years of self-defense classes take hold, and, confident she can repel the attack, she stands her ground even though she has a safe retreat. With the clarity that can occur in times of stress, she thinks, “Self-defense, in this situation, is justified.” Afterwards, Victoria remains convinced that she defense was justified, but it is only after 8 considerable reflection and some reinterpretation of her values that she can give herself an adequate explanation of why. We offer some examples, beginning with an extended example concerning sailing. A friend has invited you to go sailing. You accepted the invitation only because you thought it would be impolite to refuse. You have been sailing before and, while you did not find it unendurable, you found it difficult to see what people find so attractive about wandering about a body of water at very slow speeds. Your expressing this opinion of sailing to your friend is what prompted the invitation. The friend had insisted that you give sailing another try on his boat; “you might,” he said, “change your mind.” He was indeed correct. The boat, an ultralight racer, moves with an ease and grace utterly lacking in your early experiences; it is all different—the feel of the graceful motion of the boat and its easy speed, the sense of being not at odds with the wind and waves but in harmony with them. You express your surprise and enthusiasm to your friend by identifying the features of the experience for which you find yourself filled with desire. You are, as you realize enjoying it. The belief involved in this enjoyment is the belief, of the activity, under an array A that captures your new found sense of sailing, that it is occurring; you desire, of the activity, under A, that is should occur for its own sake, and the belief/desire pair serves as a first-person reason to sail. It is this conviction that underlies your enthusiastic specification the array of features your sailing activity has revealed; the discovery of those features is the initial cause of the belief, and their continued presence in your activity is a sustaining cause. 9 Imagine that, after your excursion on your friend’s boat, you go sailing regularly. Suppose that, for the most part at least, you first-person-reason enjoy the activity. The pattern of particular “of φ, under A” belief/desire pairs may reveal one or more significant patterns; you may discover that you prefer sailing alone, or that “φ’s” and “A’s” involving high winds and large waves do, or do not, yield belief/desire pairs you regard as providing justifications. Our experience and activities can clearly cause or causally sustain the belief that a particular “of φ, under A” belief/desire pair provides a justification for φing. In doing so, they may, in various ways the examples illustrate, reveal and illuminate what we value. This is an important aspect of our lives, but why is it one that belongs in a definition of first-personreason enjoyment? Because it provides an explanation of the power enjoyment can exercise over us. It explains in part why one eats another piece of chocolate or has another bottle of wine, why one goes sailing for hours on end, and why, although the annoyance of one’s dinner companion is visibly increasing, one cannot stop gazing at the attractive person at the other table. It exercises this power by holding us in a feedback loop in which a first-person reason enjoyment gives rise to a first-person reason enjoyment, which gives rise to . . . . The Feedback Loop Imagine Howard first-person-reason enjoys the taste of tuna fish and catsup. His taste experience, call it τ, plays a double causal role. (1) It 10 causes him to believe, of τ, under an appropriate array A, that it occurs, and to desire, of τ, under A, that it should occur. (2) It causes the conviction that pair provides at least some degree of justification for having the taste experience thereby causally sustaining the belief/desire pair in its role as a first-person reason. The power of first-person-reason enjoyments does not consist merely in the impulse to satisfy a felt desire; the enjoyments also causally invoke the authority of reason by making us think, “This is justified.” Suppose Howard acts on that reason by continuing to taste the tuna (by taking another bite of his sandwich), and assume: (1) the taste experience τ causes (2) – (3): (2) Howard (a) believes, of τ, under A, that it is occurring; and (b) desires, of τ, under A, that it should occur for its own sake; (3) belief/desire pair to serve as a first-person reason, under A, for Howard to have τ. That is, Howard continues to first-person-reason enjoy having the taste experience τ. In such a case, τ continues to play its double causal role: causing Howard to have the “of τ, under A” belief/desire pair, and causing the belief that the pair provides at least some degree of justification for having τ and thereby causally sustaining the belief/desire pair in its role as a first-person reason. Suppose Howard acts on that reason by continuing to taste the tuna (by taking another bite of his sandwich), and assume (1) the taste experience τ causes (2) – (3) . . . and so on—until the sandwich is gone, or other factors or interests intervene. The feedback loop explains in part why we eat yet another piece of chocolate, have one more bottle of wine, sail for hours on end, and cannot take our eyes off the attractive person at the other table. This is not to say 11 that first-person reason enjoyment always initiates a feedback loop. One may resist the desire to eat another piece of chocolate, to continue to sail, or to continue to look at the attractive person; or one may simply not have the relevant desires to continue. Or one may act and the relevant effects may not occur after, for example, the tenth piece of chocolate, the fifth hour of sailing, or the second the second continuous minute of looking too long at the attractive person.4 Such feedback loops nonetheless play an important explanatory and justificatory role, and it is the importance of this role that forms the final part of the rationale for requiring that the enjoyed experience or activity cause the first-person reason. First-person reason enjoyment is of considerable independent interest, but our primary concern is with the special case of value-enjoyment. To value enjoy φ under A is to first-person-reason enjoy φ under A, and to value φ’s having A. It would, of course, be wrong to single out such enjoyments as a special type if having a first-person reason entailed valuing—if, whenever an “of φ, under A” belief/desire pair served as a firstperson reason, under A, for one to φ, one also one valued φ’s having A. But, as we saw in Chapter 3, this is clearly not the case. We note that Howard can first-person reason enjoy tasting tuna fish and catsup without valuing the experience. Value-Enjoyment We first state the definition fully and then motivate and explain it. 4 Footnote about enjoying writing the last word, etc. 12 x value-enjoys an experience or activity φ under A if and only if (1) x φ’s, and x's φing causes (2) – (4): (2) (a) x occurrently believes, of φ, under A, that it occurs; (b) and has the felt desire, of φ, under A, that it should occur for its own sake; (3) the belief/desire pair in (2) is a first-person reason, under A, for x to φ; (4) x values φ’s having A. Why require that x values φ’s having A? And, why require that x's φing cause x to value φ’s having A? We take the first question first. One reason for requiring that x values φ’s having A is that valueenjoyments “outrank” first-person-reason enjoyments that are not also value-enjoyments. An example illustrates the idea. Imagine Howard first- person-reason enjoying (but not value-enjoying) the taste of tuna fish and catsup when a colleague tells him that a visiting faculty member will give a talk on “The Law and Sociology of Age Discrimination” in about five minutes, and that, if he wants to attend, he cannot bring his sandwich. Howard is quite that he will value-enjoy listening to the talk if he goes, and he abandons the sandwich to do so. Howard illustrates the general truth that we chose value-enjoyments over first-person-reason enjoyments that are not also value-enjoyments—other things being equal. The explanation of the general truth is that our plans aimed at the successful realization of what we value lie at the center of our lives, and our ideal of happiness includes the ideal, not just of realizing enough what we value, but of enjoying enough of that realization as it occurs. The “enough” allows for slippage. Howard may forego the talk for the sandwich without putting his happiness at risk; it is 13 only enough slippage that does that. This is why it is only other things being equal that we prefer value-enjoyments, but this gives the enjoyments sufficient importance to justify singling them out as a type worth consideration. Now why require that the experience or activity φ cause the enjoyer to value φ’s having A? An essential preliminary is explaining the causal mechanism. We describe the typical causal ancestry; there are other possible causal paths, but they do not matter for our purposes. To begin, recall that to value φ’s have A is to think (1) that φ’s having A provides some degree of justification for φ, and (2) that φ’s having A is a sufficient justification for thinking (1). The enjoyed experience or activity causes—or causally sustains—x’s valuing φ’s have A by causing (causally sustaining) the conviction that (1) and (2) are true. An example is in order. Suppose you value activity of playing a particular game of chess as having an array of properties A. A includes the properties of the beauty of forces in dynamic tension and the display of creativity, courage, and practical judgment in an exercise of intuition and calculation akin to both mathematics and art. You value the particular activity at least in part because it causes your engaging in it causes you to believe it realizes A. You value the properties in A. That is, you think (a) that if an activity has A, then its having A justifies (to some degree) your engaging in that activity, and (b) that its having A is sufficient justification for thinking (a). This belief combines with your belief your particular activity has A to lead you to value it. Thus the activity is part of the causal ancestry of the valuing. 14 In the chess example, it may be clear to you the causal path may be clear to you. You may realize both that you value the properties in A and that your valuing A caused your valuing of your chess playing activity. But causation need not always be so transparent. Suppose Jones has always found Chinese landscape painting an uninteresting art form worth at most a passing glance. He nonetheless finds himself valuing looking at Guo Xi’s Snow Mountain. Jones says he values the unbroken flow created by the many separate, orthogonal lines. There are two essentials points. First, Jones has to have some concept of the properties he values. The definition of value requires it. But Jones’ ability to describe the properties may be quite limited. Recall: x has a concept C if and only if (1) x can, at least under ideal conditions, describe a more or less limited range of stereotypes; (2) x has the ability to make judgments of relevant similarity and dissimilarity to the stereotypes; and, (3) the actual and possible pattern of judgments exhibits C-appropriate characteristics. Jones may satisfy these conditions while only being able to indicate Guo Xi’s Snow Mountain as an example and characterize at least one of the relevant properties as unbroken flow created by the many separate, orthogonal lines. Thus—and this is the second point—Jones may have to discover a fuller characterization of the properties in A and in the course of doing so may have to discover what properties he values that caused him to value the experience of looking at Guo Xi’s Snow Mountain. As a further illustration, imagine Gouge exploring his homoerotic side. A wide range of experiences and activities will cause him—or fail to cause him—to value those experiences and activities as having 15 various properties. In this way, he discovers what properties he values. There are many of possibilities. The emerging pattern may, for example, reveal the types of men to whom he is attracted, or, reflecting on the various properties, Gouge may come to the conclusion that gender matters less than certain personality traits that, as he now realizes, he conceptualized as “male.” Why does this causal pattern belong in a definition of valueenjoyment? Because it provides an explanation of the power enjoyment can exercise over us. The Feedback Loop When discussing the feedback loop in the case of first-person reason enjoyment, we noted that part of the explanation of the power of such enjoyments came from their making us think, “This is justified.” Valueenjoyments not only make us think that, they also make us think, “I value this.” The thought can reinforce the causal relations involved in valueenjoyment. It makes us see the “of φ, under A” belief/desire pair, not merely as citizen of the realm of justifiers, but as a privileged member of the inner circle of cases in which find in the world’s being a certain way a sufficient justification for believing a particular having or doing is justified (to some degree). To see how this can reinforce causal relations, return to Howard and Victoria. Howard thinks his tuna fish and catsup belief/desire pair justifies his having the taste experience, but he would not think this if he did not he did not desire to have the experience and expect to continue to 16 enjoy it. Should the desire begin to wane or the expectation to weaken, Howard’s justification for his taste experience will also weaken and in may abandon the tuna fish and catsup concoction in favor of other pursuits. Compare Victoria and imagine the same: her desire to watch her daughter begins to wane and her expectation of enjoyment to weaken. Victoria not only believes that her experience’s having a certain array A of properties justifies her having that experience, she also thinks that the experience’s having A is sufficient justification that belief. The latter thought may reinforce the desire and sustain the expectation of enjoyment. She may think, “This is something I value and so something I should desire and should enjoy.” The thought need not, but certainly may, play a role in causally sustaining the desire and hence the enjoyment. The feedback loop reinforces our value-enjoyments, and is absence can undermine them. The following example illustrates both. Married Jim is having lunch with a much younger woman who is, as he knows, eager to initiate a sexual and romantic relationship. As the lunch begins, he valueenjoys the dinning activity under an array A that characterizes the activity as a romantic rebellion in the name of freedom, love, and passion in the face of social mores that require fidelity in a marriage from which ardor has long been absent. The activity causes him to value it for having A because in general he values the properties in A, and the causal feedback loop operates reinforcing his enjoyment and riveting his attention on the activity. Things change as the lunch progresses. It is one of a recent series of lunches, and, lately, Jim has begun to question the wisdom of pursuing a relationship with 17 the woman. As the lunch progresses, his thoughts keep returning to Brangien’s outburst in Tristan and Isolde after she realizes Isolde and Tristan have accidently drunk the love potion: “Iseult, my friend, and Tristan, you, you have drunk death together.” He begins to see himself trapped in a future of passion, ecstasy, lies, remorse, recrimination, and destruction. This vision of the future grows stronger and more certain until he finally thinks, “I must not do this,” and with that the causal relations required for valueenjoyment collapse. His romantic visions and his enjoyment dissolve, leaving just the brute fact of the woman’s physical presence. Value-Enjoyment and Beauty In the next chapter, we will argue that the enjoyment of beauty is a special case of value-enjoyment. 18