Kelly 1 Kelly Parker Professor LeQuire English 1000 – 123 25 February 2015 Sweating Over Sweatshops: An Argumentative Analysis In his essay titled “Where Sweatshops Are a Dream,” columnist for the New York Times Nicholas D. Kristof tackles the controversial topic of sweatshops that are used, and often exploited, in our corporate-dominated global economy today. As the piece unfolds, Kristof addresses the efforts being made to improve or remove sweatshops, while presenting an argument for the necessity of these facilities in some parts of the world. Although the argument is lacking in statistical data, it is certainly not lacking in other logical and emotional appeals that evoke an enlightening, new perspective on the topic. By using graphic language, individual, provocative accounts of residents in areas where living conditions are far more atrocious without the employment opportunity that factories provide, acknowledging the opposition to establish common ground, and presenting a credible foundation for his claim, Kristof paints a vivid picture of a world where sweatshops are, in fact, a dream for some. However, he leaves the audience hanging by failing to elaborate on any alternate solutions to the problems he presents. In the very beginning of the paper, Kristof sets the stage by describing the hellish setting that those whom he argues are in need of sweatshops are facing. He uses shocking language and imagery to reel the reader in and depict the gravity of the situation, “This is a Dante-like version of hell. It’s a mountain of festering refuse, a half-hour hike across, emitting clouds of smoke Kelly 2 from subterranean fire” (Kristof 109). By comparing the setting of the place called Phnom Penh that he is using as an example in his paper to that of Dante’s well-known Divine Comedy, Kristof creates a clear mental picture of the circumstances these people are living with, eliciting a strong initial reaction from his audience. He continues, “The miasma of toxic stink leaves you gasping, breezes batter you with filth, and even the rats look forlorn. Then the smoke parts and you come across a child ambling barefoot, searching for old plastic sups that recyclers will buy for five cents a pound” (Kristof 109). And he concludes with the statement, “Many families actually live in shacks on this smoking garbage” (Kristof 109). In this section, Kristof draws from the audience’s prior experience and knowledge by describing how the stench of the setting is so potent that even rats, which we normally associate with filthy environments, struggle to live in this place. The last description we are given, that of a child stuck in this wasteland searching for something as simple as cups, strikes every heart string we possess. So, the audience is successfully hooked just in time for Kristof to make his claim, that “the central challenge in the poorest countries (like Phnom Penh) is not that sweatshops exploit too many people, but that they don’t exploit enough” (109). Kristof furthers his argument by using various testimonies of those who live in places like Phnom Penh, expressing how “cherished” the dream of working in a sweatshop is to the individuals living in these poverty-stricken countries. The accounts include that of a 19-year-old woman and an older mother who “hopes” her 10-year-old boy gets a better life that sweatshops would provide him, describing how “she has seen other children run over by garbage trucks” and how her own son has never received professional medical or dental care, nor has he bathed in Kelly 3 eight years (Kristof 110). By comparison to their current living conditions, all of the people who were asked concluded that conditions in a sweatshop would be far greater. This section of the argument is pure pathos; the audience realizes, from other’s firsthand experiences, the claim Kristof is making, that sweatshops are a dream to some when compared to their current living situations, is true. This realization weighs on us throughout the paper. However, Kristof’s argument lacks any statistical data to support his claim. While the firsthand accounts do serve as an emotional appeal to the audience, statistics regarding the number of people living in similar circumstances all around the world, differences in wages of those working in sweatshops compared to the jobless, the number of countries where this is a reality, and possibly the death rates due to situational incidents, like the child who was run over by a garbage truck that the woman described, would greatly strengthen the argument. Statistics would help the audience gain a better grasp on how wide-reaching this epidemic of poverty truly is, instead of a centralized view on one particular area, and lend more to the author’s credibility. Colorful language and emotional appeals are not a substitute for indisputable facts. Next, Kristof addresses opposition to his argument and attempts to establish some common ground and credibility with his intended audience, stating, “I’m glad that many Americans are repulsed by the idea of importing products made by barely paid, barely legal workers in dangerous factories” (110). He acknowledges that sweatshops are, in fact, problematic, and assumes the best intentions from his audience. Later, he also describes to the audience his background with the situation, explaining how his position about sweatshops stems from personal experience while living in East Asia, specifically his wife’s ancestral village in southern China, where he witnessed firsthand how living conditions improved for residents there Kelly 4 due to sweatshops. By providing this information, Kristof gains the audience’s trust in his awareness of the issue and well-intentioned argument; we want to help him. In the following sections, Kristof combats other oppositions with logical appeals to support his claim. He concedes the opposition—“Labor standards can improve wages and working conditions, without greatly affecting the eventual retail cost of goods”—but explains the negative effects labor standards can lead to, like increasing production costs, therefore driving stingy companies out of poor countries and into those that are more well off, which does not help those whose living conditions would be improved by sweatshops (Kristof 110). He also mentions issues with bribing from management that occur when labor standards are enacted as well as the economic crisis forcing some factories to close due to the aforementioned higher production costs and increasing competition within our international market. However, the argument is, once again, lacking in any statistical data regarding the production costs, bribing frequency, or the number of businesses forced to close due to these reasons. The main downfall of the argument occurs as soon as Kristof makes the seemingly offhanded remark that, “Sweatshops are only a symptom of poverty, not a cause” (110). He introduces a completely new idea, that poverty is the main issue, brilliantly broadening the scope of his argument, and then forces readers to narrow their focus back to what he is arguing—that we should help perpetuate a mere symptom of the main issue, instead of seeking to solve the real problem, which he presents himself. This momentary break in focus begs the audience to doubt whether or not what Kristof is arguing is, in fact, the best course of action. When addressing the opposition that asks him if he would want to work in a sweatshop, Kristof responds, “No, of course not. But I would want even less to pull a rickshaw” (110). His Kelly 5 choice of language, ‘of course not,’ creates a strong, negative association with sweatshops in the reader’s mind. If conditions in these facilities are so terrible that the author himself clearly would never want to work there, then our trust in the argument wavers. Toward the end of the paper, Kristof claims that, “The best way to help people in the poorest countries isn’t to campaign against sweatshops but to promote manufacturing there,” going on to scratch the surface of one possible solution; we could help one country, Africa, by strengthening a program called AGOA that seeks to encourage African imports and push Europe to match it (111). Fantastic. But how exactly do we go about accomplishing that? What are the specific inner-workings, credentials, and goals of AGOA? Kristof never gets around to elaborating on any of these lingering questions the audience is left with; nor does he offer any other possible solutions. Not to mention, some of the necessary channels for carrying out these measures, like the President and Congress, are completely alienated and undermined in as early as the fourth paragraph of the argument by addressing them as “Mr. Obama and the Democrats” (Kristof 109). Finally, Kristof concludes his argument with a statement from a 13-year-old girl who we are told earns less than $1 a day by scavenging in the dump, who is filthy in appearance, and fears for her sister who lost her hand when she was run over by a garbage truck: “It’s dirty, hot, and smelly here…A factory is better” (111). Like the rest of his argument, Kristof leaves the audience with a sorrowful feeling and a desire to act upon it, but does not follow through with ideas for how we can do that. Ultimately, “Where Sweatshops Are a Dream” somewhat succeeds in making its audience aware of extremely impoverished conditions those living in the poorest countries of our world face on a daily basis, but is not developed well enough to succeed in making its audience support the author’s argument in favor of sweatshops. As much as the audience is compelled to Kelly 6 aid the individuals whose accounts are used in the paper, we are not convinced sweatshops are the best solution to do so. The only thing Kristof’s argument in support of sweatshops truly accomplishes is painting a no-win, off-putting scenario that does not incite support or action, only helplessness and disappointment. Kelly 7 Works Cited Kristof, Nicholas D. "Where Sweatshops Are a Dream." Practical Argument: A Text and Anthology (2nd ed.). Kirszner, Laurie G., and Stephen R. Mandell, eds. Boston: Bedford/Saint Martin's, 2013. 109-111. Print.