[Ø KEY] PROJECT A Guide for Understanding Philosophers – Ethics (Aristotle-Mill) By: Brent Burton Research revealed many of the ideas, issues, and questions that tend to be a common concern amongst various ethical philosophers. Additional research uncovered the methods which different philosophers employ in attempt to resolve those issues and answer those questions. Using the research results, this guide was created to provide a framework from which readers can peer into the minds of significant philosophers and see their ideas regarding ethical issues. 1 Dedication This document is written in memory of the University of Kansas philosophy professor Tony Genova (1930 – March 20th, 2010), who is largely responsible for kindling my passion for philosophy. Acknowledgments I would like to thank the people who helped me with the [Ø Key] Project: Sarah Edgerton, Evan Harmon, Trevor Hedberg, and John Meurs. I would also like to thank anyone who has contributed to my ethical knowledge throughout the years, most notably the professors Dale Dorsey, Dawn Gale, and Tony Genova. 2 Table of Contents Dedication ..................................................................................................................................................... 1 Acknowledgments......................................................................................................................................... 1 Introduction to the Document ...................................................................................................................... 3 Aristotle (384-322 BC) ................................................................................................................................... 5 Aristotle’s Definitions................................................................................................................................ 5 Aristotle’s Q&A ......................................................................................................................................... 6 Thomas Hobbes (1588-1679) ........................................................................................................................ 7 Hobbes’ Definitions................................................................................................................................... 7 Hobbes’ Q&A............................................................................................................................................. 7 Richard Cumberland (1631-1718) ................................................................................................................. 9 Cumberland’s Definitions.......................................................................................................................... 9 Cumberland’s Q&A ................................................................................................................................... 9 Samuel Clarke (1675-1729) ......................................................................................................................... 10 Clarke’s Definitions ................................................................................................................................. 10 Clarke’s Q&A ........................................................................................................................................... 10 Francis Hutcheson (1694-1746) .................................................................................................................. 11 Hutcheson’s Definitions .......................................................................................................................... 11 Hutcheson’s Q&A .................................................................................................................................... 11 David Hume (1711-1776) ............................................................................................................................ 12 Hume’s Definitions.................................................................................................................................. 12 Hume’s Q&A............................................................................................................................................ 13 Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) ....................................................................................................................... 14 Kant’s Definitions .................................................................................................................................... 14 Kant’s Q&A .............................................................................................................................................. 14 John Stuart Mill (1806-1873) ...................................................................................................................... 15 Mill’s Definitions ..................................................................................................................................... 15 Mill’s Q&A ............................................................................................................................................... 15 Classification Table...................................................................................................................................... 16 Glossary ....................................................................................................................................................... 16 References .................................................................................................................................................. 18 3 Introduction to the Document This document is designed to present the ideas and beliefs of historical ethical philosophers in a manner which is clear, concise, accurate, and easy-to-follow. It is intended to be used as a key for making distinctions about philosophers that classify and separate them into their perspective categories so that they can be easily compared. The words “ethical” and “moral” will be used interchangeably throughout this document. The exception to this rule is when either of the words appears in a philosopher’s direct quote. In such cases, the words retain the philosopher’s personal definition/understanding of the word. Currently this document only contains a select few philosophers who are primarily from the western tradition. The three main philosophers that are covered thus far are Aristotle, Hobbes, and Hume. The completed document would contain numerous more philosophers; ideally, it would continue to grow until it contained the ethical philosophy of every significant philosopher. Each Philosopher’s section is divided into three main parts: (I) Pertinent information, classifications, and categorizations that identify them This section is broken down further into four sections. Under “Lived” is the philosopher’s lifespan, their birth date and death date. Under “Origin” is the philosopher’s place of birth and the subsequent places which he or she resided. The arrows () represent a shift from one location to the next and are roughly chronological. Under “Classifications” are the terms used to denote different philosophical camps concerning ethics that are applicable to the given philosopher. A tilde (~) appearing before the classification denotes that the classification loosely applies to the philosopher. Under “Ethical/Moral Texts” is a list of the works written by the philosopher which contain a significant amount of their ethical philosophy. (II) The personal definitions and ideas that they use for various important words In his An Enquiry concerning Human Understanding, David Hume says, “But if the question regard any subject of common life and experience; nothing, one would think, could preserve the dispute so long undecided, but some ambiguous expressions, which keep the antagonists still at a distance, and hinder them from grappling with each other” (148). In other words, disputes in regard to the answers of such questions are prolonged because of ambiguous expressions. In order to dispel any ambiguities, this section provides the unique definitions used by the particular philosopher. (III) Their answers’ to different ethical questions This section provides the philosophers’ answers to various ethical questions. Some questions which are commonly addressed by ethical philosophers include: What is virtue and what are the virtues? Does virtue benefit the virtuous? 4 Why should I be moral? How are people motivated to act morally? What is human nature? What is the best life for a human? What is happiness? How can humans distinguish between moral good and evil? 5 Aristotle (384-322 BC) Lived: 384-322 BC Origin: [Greek] – Stagira (Macedonia) Athens Assos Mytilene (Lesbos) (335BC) Athens Chalcis. Classifications: ~Rationalism, Eudaimonist Constraint. Ethical/Moral Texts: Nicomachean Ethics, Eudemain Ethics. Aristotle’s Definitions Happiness: Aristotle’s notion of happiness is closely bound to eudaimonia and summum bonum. Eudaimonia is both an individual’s happiness and the general well being/happiness of all humankind. Summum bonum is the ultimate end which all people should pursue. Happiness is the ultimate good which all goods are directed towards, the end of all actions. It is choice worthy by itself, intrinsically good and unconditionally valuable. Eudaimonia: While in a state of nature all human actions aim towards eudaimonia (both an individual’s happiness and the general well being/happiness of all humankind). Summum bonum: The ultimate end which all people should pursue. Virtue: The mean between two extremes (two ways of carrying out an activity). For example, braveness is the mean between the two extremes of cowardice and rashness. The goal of virtue is aimed at the best (ultimate) good which is happiness. The virtues of character: Mildness, temperance, bravery, truthfulness, generosity, magnificence, magnanimity, the virtue concerned with small honors, friendliness, wit, and shame. The virtues of thought: Wisdom, knowledge, prudence, understanding, deliberation, comprehension, and practical thought. Aristotle’s requirements for being truly virtuous: Prudence (which needs both cleverness and good deliberation) Understanding 1st principles Friendship All of the individual virtues 6 Aristotle’s Q&A Q: Is virtue in the interest of the virtuous? A: Yes – Actions in accord with virtue are pleasant by nature, so that they both please lovers of the fine and are pleasant in their own right. The activities of the virtues are concerned with the things that promote the end (eudaimonia). By promoting the common good, a person secures the greatest of goods for each individual person: “And when everyone strains to achieve what is fine and concentrates on the finest actions, everything that is right will be done for the common good, and each person individually will receive the greatest of goods, since that is the character of virtue” (Irwin 147). Q: Why should I be moral? A: Aristotle’s answer to this question can be explained by appealing to two constituent principles of his philosophy: the good and the function argument. 3 types of goods: 1. Goods of the soul (the highest goods, actions and activities of the soul) 2. Goods of the body 3. External goods The good depends upon how well an individual being, object, or entity performs its function. The human function is virtue: “…the human good proves to be activity of the soul in accord with virtue, and indeed with the best and most complete virtue, if there are more virtues than one” (Irwin 9). Function Argument: P1. Things with functions achieve the good by performing their function well. P2. Humans have a (unique) function [division of the soul: appetite/reason]. P3. The human function is activity of the soul in accord with reason or requiring reason. P4. The best use of the rational part of the soul is the activity of virtue. C. The good, for humans, is the active life of virtue. Therefore, you should be moral because it entails living the active life of virtue and the active life of virtue is pleasurable in itself, because actions in accord with the virtues are pleasant in their own right. 7 Thomas Hobbes (1588-1679) Lived: 1588-1679 Origin: [English] – Malmesbury (Wiltshire) Oxford Devonshire France Devonshire. Classifications: ~Rationalism, Skepticism, Eudaimonist Constraint. Ethical/Moral Texts: Human Nature (the Fundamental Elements of Policy), Leviathan, of Liberty and Necessity, De Cive, De Corpo Politico (of the Elements of Law, moral and politic). Hobbes’ Definitions Power: The ability to fulfill our desires, both future and present. Honor: (not linked with virtue, but rather, linked with power). “Honorable is whatsoever possession, action, or quality, is an argument and sign of power” (Raphael 30). Being honored or feared is power and hence honorable. “To believe, to trust to rely on another, is to honor him; sign of opinion of his virtue and power. To distrust or not believe, is to dishonor” (Raphael 31). Virtue: Belief of the man and the truth of what he says: belief of his virtue, to have faith, to trust or believe a man. Virtue is valued for eminence [high rank of repute] and signifies an opinion of that man’s veracity [conformity to truth]. Intellectual virtues are abilities of the mind which are praised, valued, and desired in themselves. Happiness: Happiness is subjectively determined, everybody’s happiness is different. We desire pleasure as a means to happiness, our desires move us to action; hence, all our actions tend towards happiness. We seek power (ultimately) to secure pleasure, happiness. Hobbes’ Q&A Q: Should I be moral? Why? A: Yes – you should be moral in order to avoid living in a state of nature. A state of nature, according to Hobbes, is a state in which no government or drafted laws exist which happens to be a state of war where every person is in competition with every other person for the preservation and improvement of their own life. While in a state of war (life is short, hostile, rapacious and lonely), all human actions aim towards a person’s subjective desires for pleasure and power without regard for the general wellbeing of humankind. In order to escape the state of war, we must form, and live under, a leviathan which outlines how everyone is expected to act: “Fear of oppression, disposeth a man to anticipate, or to seek aid by society; for there is no other way by which a man can secure his life and liberty.” Q: Is virtue in the interest of the virtuous? 8 A: Yes – Being virtuous is in your interest because it removes you from the state of nature, while not being virtuous will cause you to fall back into the state of nature placing you in a vulnerable position. Q: What is human nature? A: “Man’s nature is the sum of his natural faculties and powers, as the faculties of nutrition, motion, generation, sense, reason, etc” (Human Nature, I.4). 9 Richard Cumberland (1631-1718) Lived: 1631-1718 Origin: [English] – Cambridge (Peterborough). Classifications: Rationalism, Utilitarianism. Ethical/Moral Texts: De Legibus Naturae (1762). Cumberland’s Definitions Cumberland’s Q&A 10 Samuel Clarke (1675-1729) Lived: 1675-1729 Origin: [English] – Cambridge Westminster. Classifications: Rationalism, ~Utilitarianism. Ethical/Moral Texts: A Discourse concerning the Unchangeable Obligations of Natural Religion, and the Truth and Certainty of the Christian Revelation. Clarke’s Definitions Clarke’s Q&A Q: Is virtue in the interest of the virtuous? A: No. Q: Are our moral obligations determined by our sentiments, or are moral facts determined by our faculty of reason? A: They are determined by reason. 11 Francis Hutcheson (1694-1746) Lived: 1694-1746 Origin: [Irish] – Ulster Glasgow Dublin Glasgow. Classifications: Sentimentalism, Utilitarianism, Empiricism, Hedonism. Ethical/Moral Texts: An Inquiry concerning the Original of Our Ideas of Virtue or Moral Good, An Essay on the Nature and Conduct of Passions and Affections with Illustrations on the Moral Sense. Hutcheson’s Definitions Hutcheson’s Q&A Q: Is virtue in the interest of the virtuous? A: No. Q: Are our moral obligations determined by our sentiments, or are moral facts determined by our faculty of reason? A: They are determined by our sentiments. 12 David Hume (1711-1776) Lived: 1711-1776 Origin: [Scottish] – Edinburgh Flèche (Anjou) Edinburgh. Classifications: Sentimentalism, ~Utilitarianism, Empiricism. Ethical/Moral Texts: A Treatise of Human Nature, An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals, An Enquiry concerning Human Understanding, Of the Standard of Taste. Hume’s Definitions Benevolence: (friendship, charity, compassion, etc.) is a [natural] genuine virtue, it is useful for people, and it is praised / esteemed. The internal motivation for benevolence is sympathy. We desire to see others do well and we take pleasure in satisfying our desires. Hence, we get pleasure when we are benevolent. Justice: Honesty with respect to one’s own property. We have a general sense that justice is in our self interests (since property is in our interest) and this is the motive for being virtuous. With justice comes utility. Utility: Things are praised because of their utility. Justice is useful to society -utility- it has a tendency to the public good. The virtues have a tendency to the good of society, or to that of the person possessed of them. The virtues are useful, either to society, or to the person possessed of them. The useful qualities of the mind are virtuous, because of their utility. Passions: The influencing motives of the will – that which determines what ideas are acted upon. Two types of Passions: Violent- e.g., lust, anger, revenge, and rage. Calm- e.g., benevolence, resentment, appetite to good, aversion to evil, and perception of beauty. Reason: (reason as a faculty) reason/science is the comparing of ideas and the discovery of their relations. Impressions: Perceptual experiences of the external world. Ideas: Copies of our impressions. 13 Virtue: It is the nature, and, indeed, the definition of virtue, that it is a quality of the mind agreeable to or approved of by everyone, who considers or contemplates it. Virtue is both a mental quality in the person contemplated, and a perception by those who contemplate the person. Hume’s Q&A Q: Is virtue in the interest of the virtuous? A: Yes – being virtuous is in the interest of the virtuous because it produces pleasure in them. Hume says, “An action, or sentiment, or character is virtuous or vicious; why? because its view causes a pleasure or uneasiness of a particular kind” (Raphael 20). Hence, we take pleasure in seeing other people’s virtuous actions and we take pleasure in knowing that the actions we make are virtuous. Counter-argument: The Sensible Knave: a smart criminal who does not respect justice (knave) and gets away with it (sensible). The sensible knave can reap benefits by committing non-virtuous acts. Hume’s response: The sensible knave thinks that he is better off by committing and getting away with injustice because he attains additional riches, but he is wrong; in reality, he has bad taste, i.e., he thinks cash equals happiness. The invaluable enjoyment of character—peaceful reflection of one’s own conduct—is of a higher value/pleasure than the pleasures attained by riches. The pleasures of the moral sense are more valuable than any other pleasures. Q: Are our moral obligations determined by our sentiments, or are moral facts determinable by our faculty of reason? A: Hume argues that reason alone is not sufficient to distinguish between moral good and evil, but rather, it requires our sentiments. a) Reason is perfectly inert, and can never either prevent or produce any action or affection. b) Since morals have an influence on the actions and affections, it follows, that they cannot be derived from reason. Hume backs up these claims with the following argument: 1. Reason is the discovery of truth or falsehood. 2. Truth or falsehood consists in an agreement or disagreement either to the real relations of ideas, or to real existence and matter of fact. 3. Whatever is not susceptible of this agreement or disagreement is incapable of being true or false, and can never be an object of our reason. 4. Our passions, volitions, and actions are not susceptible of any such agreement or disagreement because they are original facts and realities, complete in themselves and imply no reference to other passion, volitions, and actions (Raphael 9-10). Therefore, it is impossible for our passions, volitions, and actions to be either true or false and to be either contrary or conformable to reason. 14 Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) Lived: 1724-1804 Origin: [German] – Konigsberg (Kalinigrad). Classifications: Rationalism. Ethical/Moral Texts: Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals. Kant’s Definitions Kant’s Q&A Q: Are our moral obligations determined by our sentiments, or are moral facts determinable by our faculty of reason? A: They are determined by our reason. 15 John Stuart Mill (1806-1873) Lived: 1806-1873 Origin: English. Classifications: ~Sentimentalism, Utilitarianism, Empiricism, Hedonism. Ethical/Moral Texts: Utilitarianism, On Liberty, The Subjection of Women. Mill’s Definitions Mill’s Q&A Q: is the sentiment of duty innate? A: Mill believes that morality is acquired, that it is something we must cultivate. There is a sentiment in human nature for benevolence which we must cultivate [educate] to universal benevolence. And, our sense of consciousness is the sanction for just action and it must be cultivated. Hence, it is not natural. This places Mill somewhere between Hutcheson and Hume. 16 Classification Table Diagram 2.2 - This table depicts each philosopher and their respective philosophical camps. An X designates a strong connection, and a \ designates a weak connection. Aristotle Clarke Cumberland Sentimentalism \ X X Rationalism \ X Utilitarianism Skepticism Empiricism Hedonism X Eudaimonist Constraint Hobbes Hume X \ \ X X Hutcheson Kant Mill X \ X X X X X X X X Glossary Empiricism: “The permanent strand in philosophy that attempts to tie knowledge to experience. Experience is thought of either as the sensory contents of consciousness, or as whatever is expressed in some designated class of statements that can be observed to be true by the use of the senses” (Blackburn 114). Eudaimonist Constraint: If morality is worth pursuing then it has to be bound to personal happiness; it must be self-interested, or at least self-regarding. Hedonism: “The pursuit of one’s own pleasure as an end in itself; in ethics, the view that such a pursuit is the proper aim of all action. Since there are different conceptions of pleasure there are correspondingly different varieties of hedonism” (Blackburn 161). Rationalism: The notion that moral commands are known through reason and apply to all rational beings. “Any philosophy magnifying the role played by unaided reason, in the acquisition and justification of knowledge” (Blackburn 308). Sentimentalism: The notion that our sentiments/senses/feelings guide our moral judgments. “The position in moral theory especially associated with Shaftesbury, Hutcheson, and Hume, that sees ethics as founded upon human sentiments, such as sympathy. It was especially defined in opposition to the view that ethics is the deliverance of reason or revelation” (Blackburn 336). Skepticism: The notion that humans, even with our rational ability, lack the capacity to accurately determine moral principles. Utilitarianism: “The ethical theory advanced by Bentham, both James and J. S. Mill, Sidgwick, and many others, that answers all questions of what to do, what to admire, or how to live, in terms of maximizing 17 *utility or happiness. . . In J. S. Mill’s statement of the doctrine, ‘actions are right in proportion as they tend to promote happiness, wrong as they tend to produce the reverse of happiness’” (Blackburn 377). 18 References Blackburn, Simon. Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy Second Edition. Oxford University Press, 2005 D.D. Raphael, ed. British Moralists 1650-1800 vol. I Hobbes–Gay (Hackett Publishing Company, Inc., 1991) D.D. Raphael, ed. British Moralists 1650-1800 vol. II Hume–Bentham and Index (Hackett Publishing Company, Inc., 1991) Hume, David. A Treatise of Human Nature Kant, Immanuel. Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals. Edited by Mary Gregor, Cambridge Texts in the History of Philosophy Mill, J.S. Utilitarianism. Edited by Roger Crisp. Oxford Philosophical Texts Terrence Irwin, trans., Aristotle. Nicomachean Ethics, 2nd ed. Hackett Publishing Company, Inc., 1999 Tom Beauchamp, ed., Hume, David. An Enquiry concerning the Principles of Morals. Oxford Philosophical Texts, 1998 http://w3schools.com/: The primary reference used for programming http://www.iep.utm.edu/home/welcome : Used for the philosophers’ pictures – Aristotle, Hobbes, Hume, Kant, and Mill http://www.britannica.com/ : Hutcheson’s picture http://www.nndb.com/people/462/000107141/ : Clarke’s picture