Copyright © 2015 Avello Publishing Journal ISSN: 2049 - 498X Issue 1 Volume 5: Marquise Émilie du Châtelet Filling the Shell of the Black Woman With Nothing Marquis Bey, Cornell University, USA. “Other than melanin and subject matter, what, in fact, may make me a black writer? Other than my own ethnicity—what is going on in my work that makes me believe it is demonstrably inseparable from a cultural specificity that is Afro-American?” —Toni Morrison, Unspeakable Things Unspoken Birth of a Race Relation Negro-ness. This concept, indeed, this claim initially uttered by Leroi Jones (Amiri Baraka) in his essay “The Myth of a ‘Negro Literature’” was used to criticize the lack of authenticity— black, Negro authenticity—in black literature. With this appellation, Baraka implies that there is something endemic to all black individuals, something that characterizes all individuals who belong to the black race and sets them apart from all people of the white race. “Negro-ness” is indirectly illustrated as “authentic” blackness, as the kernel of blackness that seeps into all that a black American produces. However, Baraka never defines what this "Negro-ness" is; he never explicitly says what it looks like, writes like, thinks like, or behaves like. Perhaps Baraka intended “Negro-ness” to be an ineffable, linguistically inexpressible quality that one “knows when they see it;” perhaps it is a quality incapable of being captured by the inadequacy of language. But if it is linguistically inexpressible and known only when seen, how is one to develop, as Baraka implicitly does, a standard by 1 which to gauge its amount in a work? Or perhaps there is another reason for Baraka’s lack of definition—because one cannot define things that do not exist. Asserting a “Negro-ness,” an innate black quality, denies black individuals autonomy—autonomy in the sense that in designating innate, unalterable characteristics in black individuals, they are deprived of the freedom to be things that contradict or reject those predetermined characteristics. Put otherwise, to assert “Negroness” is to deny black individuals the capacity to fully resist. It is this very capacity that is of central concern for philosopher Catherine Malabou. The capacity to resist connects to her ontology of plasticity that reads being as change. “Negro-ness,” in short, denies the malleability of identity and attempts to rigidify the fluidity of black identity. “The” special experience of African Americans is often cited as the justification for phrases like “Negro-ness” and other exclusively black concepts and theories is the special experience of African Americans. It is said that black Americans have “a” historically unique experience that permeates their lives and shapes their perception of the world. Because of the historical institution of slavery and inimical fights for racial equality in the form of events such as Emancipation and the Civil Rights Movement, black Americans share a common past. This common past promotes a level of solidarity that unifies them because of the racial commonality of the experiences. There seems to be some validity to the claim that a commonality of experience translates into sweeping commonalities in writing, speech, art, etc. of black individuals. Historical racial blights spawned by the onset of racist ideology seem to conjure in the mind of black Americans certain specific talking points and views of the world that seem to be in accordance with all individuals who identify as black; however, what often mistakenly follows is a conflation of unique black experiences with a black essence. 2 I, however, wish to insist that a common experience is not a common essence. To claim that the historical experience is synonymous with an innate black essence makes the mistake of falsely internalizing external circumstances and passing them off as inherent or natural. Furthermore, it jettisons the plurality and diversity within the experiences of black Americans. Baraka, and others like him, contend that it is because of an a priori “blackness of blackness” that one writes literature in a certain way or has a particular perspective. The primary problem with this, however, is that it defines “blackness” as unchanging. The problem is not necessarily that a specific thing is said to characterize black individuals, but that this specific thing can never be anything else. The same point can be made for women. All those who identify and are perceived as belonging to the, what feminist philosopher Chrsitine Battersby calls, “female subjectposition” do not have a common essence underlying their identities. Battersby notes, in her text, The Phenomenal Woman, that Women’s predicaments are infinitely variable – and so are women’s experiences. The identities of individual women are scored by a variety of forces and disciplinary structures. Not all of these scorings relate to issues of sexual difference. Race, nation, religion, education, familybackground, neighbourhood, class, wealth – all contribute to configuring and patterning the individualized self that persists through time. (6) Women’s experiences vary across race, nation, religion, sexuality, etc. There is no monolithic female experience that initiates the establishment of an immutable female essence. Essentialism’s central dogma assumes that within a specific entity of a group, there exists a set of attributes all of which are necessary to its identity and function, and unchanging (Cartwright). Essentialists would believe that all black women possess some inherent trait 3 endemic to them all that always has and always will identify them as black women. The problem with essentializing is that it presupposes an innate, unalterable, fixed quality of an individual of a group that is determined arbitrarily through outward manifestations. This fixity clashes with Malabou’s ontology—that being is change. To essentialize black individuals not only reduces them all to a level of sameness, but also deprives them of their own capacity to resist. To further this point, to say that all black women have a particular essence that has always and always will exist in every black woman, is to falsely reduce their “essence” to one that is immutable. It disregards the foundation of change and shrinks the broad spectrum of possibilities for black women down to a core of arbitrary presuppositions. To assert this is to answer Deborah E. McDowell’s question, “Is there a monolithic black female language? Do black female high school dropouts, welfare mothers, college graduates, and Ph.D.s share a common language?” with a hearty “Yes, always!” Black Women Blotted Out In the burgeoning epoch of second-wave feminism, the purported fight for full women’s equality fell short of its claim because of its failure to include the trials of black women. White feminists often evinced, what Adrienne Rich calls, a “white solipsistic” mentality when fighting for the equality of women. White solipsism, as defined by Rich, is “to think, imagine, and speak as if whiteness described the world. Not the consciously-held belief that one race is inherently superior to all others, but a tunnel-vision which simply does not see nonwhite experience or existence as precious or significant, unless in spasmodic, impotent guilt-reflexes, which have little or no long term, continuing momentum or political usefulness” (Spelman). This sequesters the different realities of black women to the realm of 4 unimportance, which then adds another hindrance to black women and marginalizes them even further. Black women suffer abject erasure when fighting for black or female equality, forcing them to create their own fight for black and female subjectivity and equality, their own militia of women that unsheathe weapons branded with words, theories, and actions that make black women indelibly appear on the palimpsestic tablet of society. Black women have unique gendered as well as racially oppressive forces bearing down on them. The predominantly-white feminist movement’s embodiment of the white solipsistic mentality treated the struggles of white women as universal, disregarding the unique struggles of their black sisters. Black women were blotted out and fell victim to an erasure that made mythical their difficulties while substituting white women’s difficulties for all women’s difficulties. The remedy to this white solipsism is not simply an additive one; the struggles of black women are not simply black struggles plus women struggles. It is “highly misleading to say, without further explanation, that black women experience sexism and racism. For to say merely that suggests that black women experience one form of oppression, as blacks—the same thing black men experience—and that they experience another form of oppression as women—the same thing white women experience” (Spelman; emphasis in original). A black woman does not experience discrimination and oppression the same as a black man does, nor does she experience sexism the same as a white woman. Her experience is quite different than a black man’s because she is not just black (male being the hegemonic and thus invisible characteristic); her experience is quite different from a white woman’s because she is not just a woman. The sexism a black woman experiences influences and is influenced by the racism she experiences (Spelman). To treat the oppression of black women as additive—simply piling the stagnant weight of racism onto that of sexism, “treats the oppression of black women in a sexist and racist society as if it were a further burden than her oppression in a 5 sexist but non-racist society, when, in fact, it is a different burden” (Spelman). Black women’s experience in a racist and sexist society does not give them a “double whammy” but a different experience than anything black men or white women will ever endure. White Black Feminist Womanist Thought Womanist I. From womanish. (Opp. Of “girlish,” i.e., frivolous, irresponsible, not serious.) A black feminist or feminist of color. From the black folk expression of mothers to female children, “You acting womanish,” i.e., like a woman. Usually referring to outrageous, audacious, courageous or willful behavior. Wanting to know more and in greater depth than is considered “good” for one. Interested in grown-up doings. Acting grown-up. Being grown-up. Interchangeable with another black folk expression: ‘You trying to be grown.” Responsible. In charge. Serious. (Walker xi-xii) The above quote tersely, yet poignantly captures the contrast between the demeanor and attitude of black women and that of white women. The intersectionality in play within black women and women of color changes their experiences so much that the purported universality of the woes of white feminists failed to account for black women’s experiences (“The Social Construction”). Because (white) feminism did not speak for the reality of black women, a specialized perspective had to be created. Black Womanist Thought attempts to correct the injustices of second-wave feminism and is a self-defined standpoint of black women’s own oppression. Because black women’s social status externally affects them in a common way and alters their views of the world, they experience a different world. These experiences then bring forth a distinctive Black Womanist consciousness concerning that material reality. This is the murmuring heartbeat of Black Womanist Thought: a subordinate group’s different interpretation of a reality shaped by the dominant group (“Defining Black”). 6 The facticity of the dissimilar experience of black women brought upon by the pallid hands of the hegemonic caste is reaffirmed due to black women’s realities being overlooked. The creation of Black Womanist Thought was necessary because white feminists did not recognize black women’s unique impedances, normalized whiteness, considered it universal, saw white women’s reality as accounting for all women’s reality. For example, in the fight for women’s suffrage during the second-wave of feminism, white feminists disregarded the unique challenges black women were facing and would face. Because white women failed to see black women’s issues as “real issues” and thus continued to lack a comprehensive vision of the persisting troubles specific to black women, the struggles of black women were subsumed under the thought-to-be universal white female experience, thus making invisible the peculiar issues of black women. Since white feminists did not see the unique experiences of black women, while consequently appropriating them into the Feminist movement (the lack of specification implies a “white” qualifier), they did them the disservice of failing to consider their womanness and their blackness. Essential Points of Malabou It has been made clear that blackness, or black essence, has fallen victim to essentialization, that is, common racial pasts have been codified into a common modern racial essence. Black women specifically have suffered under a unique, nuanced position of identity degradation in that their marginalized race as well as their marginalized gender confer upon them inimitable plights. Catherine Malabou, French philosopher combining traditional thinkers such as Hegel and Heidegger with her own implementation of neuroscience, adds much to the conceptualization of identity and essence. Malabou’s book Changing Difference attempts to reconceptualize notions of gender difference in a post-feminist age by radically hollowing 7 out the woman. Being a female philosopher, Malabou must combat the fact that “still today the professional or personal achievements of a woman cannot be seen as anything other than an act of emancipation” and “to be a woman still means to belong to a category that is dominated sexually, symbolically, socially, economically, and culturally” (92). Women are locked in a position that forces them to remain oppressed and makes any attempt at liberation hearken back to her oppression, seen as only an emancipatory act. But Malabou sets up her new articulation of the woman by stating that “there is a secret plasticity in both woman and the feminine” (93). Malabou takes Battersby’s notion that “it is not necessary to think in terns of fixed ‘essences’” (12), and that the Self “is not a ‘thing’ – a ‘substance’ that remains permanent through change – it is more like an ‘event’ that is ‘born’ in the space and time of interactive forces” (8) to its logical end. Woman, for Malabou, becomes constant change, consistent with her notion of the ontological mutability of being. That which underlies our existence is a constancy of change, of mutability. It follows, then, that what constitutes the person is not a palpable static essence or a humanly-constructed imposed essence but a changing one. Once we understand that everything is change, we can liberate ourselves from the rigid dichotomy of essentialism or anti-essentialism, both of which are inadequate for speaking of women’s and all people’s identity. Once we accept that underlying our identities is eternal change, we no longer have to reject strict essentialism or anti-essentialism, because change encompasses both of those options, as well as other conceptualizations of identity. With change as fundamental, everything is possible, freeing us all from confining categories. In discussing the nature of our brain, our identity, and our essence, Malabou divulges her idea of plasticity: the capacity to both receive form and give form, something modifiable, formable, and formative at the same time; however, something that also has the capacity to 8 annihilate, to explode (What Should We Do). An inherent reciprocity exists within the functions of our world; we, and all that encompasses us, receive impressions from external stimuli and experiences while simultaneously impressing ourselves upon our world, shaping it and creating it while also being shaped and created. Also possible is deflagration: a complete rupture of ourselves, annihilating all form. Our brains and our identities are situated between two extremes: “on the one side the sensible image of taking form (sculpture or plastic objects), and on the other side that of the annihilation of all form (explosion)” (What Should We Do 5). In light of her notion of plasticity, Malabou does not identify with either the essentialist or anti-essentialist schools of thought. She repudiates the traditional essentialist characterization because it reduces women to sameness, dilutes their differences and compartmentalizes them into fixed, rigid, unalterable boxes that jettison uniqueness or individuality. Malabou also says that anti-essentialism, characteristic of, for example, queer theory, is an inadequate portrayal of the identities of women because, in trying to uplift women from the depths of marginalization, it “defend[s] the specificity of this violence simply a fall-back to a form of essentialism that confers a determinate identity on ‘woman’” (Malabou, Changing Difference 94). Furthermore, anti-essentialism reduces all categories to social constructions, disregarding the fact that the biological differences between the sexes are significant. Social construction can only account for so much, and the physical, biological differences between the sexes are undeniable. Both approaches are limited, and Malabou specifically points out the shortcomings of both later in her book Changing Difference: In gender studies, “essence” often refers to a combination of natural, biological, or anatomical determinants (all three are treated as synonymous)—the woman’s “sex,” her “body”—and a given social construction, feminine identity as it appears as a product of the heterosexual 9 ideological matrix. Both natural determination and social construction refer to a supposedly stable and unchanging essence. To speak of the “specificity” of the feminine would be essentialist, since this discourse could only be a reclaiming of the “proper,” a preordained anatomical and cultural reality. Few feminist theorists seem to question the crude amalgam that such an understanding of essence conveys, one that reduces biology to nothing more than the science of constituted identities and culture to a movement to re-appropriate these identities for normalizing ends. The anti-essentialism of “queer multitudes” emphasizes the infinite, unlimited, horizontal stability and transformability of bodies, behavior, and gender, as if this constant displacement were able to eradicate supposed stability of essence by itself. (96) The problem with historical renditions of essence, according to Malabou, is that there has been “a consensus regarding a definition of essence as stability, self-presence, and nature, in both the ontological and biological meaning of the term” (98). Addressing the insufficient and inadequate term “essence,” Malabou creates a new definition. She opens up a new avenue for thinking about essence and asks us to “envisage the possibility that, in the name woman, there is an empty but resistant essence, an essence that is resistant precisely because it is emptied, a stamp of impossibility” (98-99; emphasis in original). Redefining essence in this way can in turn redefine the fate of black women. To be sure, Malabou’s empty but resistant essence can indeed be used to liberate all identities, not merely black women. However, Malabou’s concept is particularly insightful and beneficial for black women of modernity because of the onerous oppressive force black women face. The notion of an empty but resistant essence can indeed liberate black men or white women, but because black women face an exponentiated degree of racial and gendered oppression it can prove especially liberatory. Malabou’s essence grants access into a more general yet specific idea of identity 10 that is capable of addressing issues specific to black women but is bereft of the limiting effect of prior notions of essence. It simultaneously liberates black women from confining categories while opening up the possibility of anything being characteristic of black women. It allows that which defines black women to prove insightful for all black women while eliminating the mistake of ascribing that which defines a particular black woman to all black women. As stated, Malabou holds that both the essentialist and anti-essentialist arguments are incomplete and insufficient in achieving the feminist goal of gender equality. She says that “the fierce battle waged within various feminist movements between ‘essentialism’ and ‘antiessentialism’—the label ‘essentialist’ is attached to any discourse that tries to identify anything like a specificity of the feminine—loses its meaning and ultimately turns against feminist efforts” (95). The discourse surrounding feminism is unable to liberate and free women from the shackles of marginalization. As Malabou notes, it often “oppose[s] the feminine—understood as the femininity of woman—to masculine domination, simultaneously restricts the meaning of the feminine understood as openness and plurality. Once again binaries dominate, along with their strict and often uncritical definitions” (27). Feminism and the discursive fight for women’s equality limit women to predetermined essences. It does not allow room for change, the primordial basis of one’s identity. Malabou strongly criticizes queer theory’s and social constructivism’s fundamental premise of stark anti-essentialism. Malabou implicitly states that anti-essentialists assert an essential quality of the woman just as essentialists do. In pointing out the ambiguities of antiessentialism, she asks, “How do you establish an essential difference between women’s studies and other fields of research, how do you define an essential identity for the political attitude of women within the institution, how do you maintain an essential distinction 11 between the male and female guardians of the Law if ‘woman’ or ‘women’ have no essence?” (104). One cannot stand in the position of anti-essentialism and at the same time assert a distinct, specific essence of the target of the oppression that one is trying to eradicate. Antiessentialism rebuffs any inherent essence of a particular group and claims that nothing in a woman is endemic to or characteristic of all women solely by virtue of their womanness. However, people committed to anti-essentialist thought assert the liberation of this specific subject called women—a subject that they implicitly deem, since they specify a particular target of oppression, to have something innate within them all that is the target of this oppression. She also criticizes anti-essentialists for severing ties with the natural sciences and, as stated previously, their acceptance of the inherency of biological differences. Malabou incorporates the facts of science into her philosophy via plasticity, which lies beneath her ontology of change. For anti-essentialists to deny science and biology wholly denies a critical component of the identity of people. There are real, material differences between women and men that cannot be written off. Malabou retains the facts of science while still allowing room for the very fundamental law of change. What Malabou attempts to do is reconcile the two schools and find a way out of the crammed spaces of essentialism and anti-essentialism. Malabou retains ties to the natural sciences but still rejects a strict essentialist thought. She also understands the plasticity and capriciousness of one’s identity but does not succumb to radical constructivism. Ultimately, she attempts to answer the very poignant question “How can we defend the specificity, however unstable, however relative, of a violence done to women if the very notion of ‘specificity’ is subject to the counter-violence of a constant de-appropriation?” The result of this violence is 12 that ‘woman’ is now emptied of her essence only serves the fact that she does not define herself except through the violence done to her. Violence alone confers her being. The violence of the deconstruction of this being, on the one hand, and, on the other, the domestic and social violence constantly exerted on this very absence of being. Woman is nothing anymore, except this violence through which her ‘being nothing’ continues to exist. She's nothing but an ontological amputation, formed by that which negates her. (98) Malabou wonders how this identity we label as “woman” can be liberated if the very violence done to this specified identity is the subject to violence because of its specificity. By specifying what is undergoing violence—that being “woman”—in order to liberate “woman” we subject “woman” to counter-violence. How, then, are we to conceive of the identities undergoing real, palpable oppression and violence? She subsequently provides her answer, and through black women we can see it made manifest. What, Then, Is the Black Woman, This New Thing? Drawing on Malabou, I will show that the identity of black women is plastic: that there is no static or universal entity that characterizes all black women. It shapes and is shaped, forms and is formed, yet also has the potential to explode and become something wholly different. We can no longer think of the identity, the essence, of black women as something a priori or predetermined, nor can we assert that there is a commonality that pervades all black women due to common experiences or a common racial history. The identity of particular black women perennially shape the perception of who black women are and, in consequently, perceptions of black women paint a picture of black female identity for others, a picture that can be accepted or rejected. Also, the identity of black women can undergo radical, impetuous change—what Malabou calls “explosion.” Black women’s essence is thus not 13 something; this would presuppose an innate characteristic. Rather, the essence of black women is emptiness. To be sure, although Malabou only deals specifically with gender it is unclear whether her remarks can apply to race as well. Malabou states that violence confers woman’s being; that there is a balance to be struck between socially constructed and biological influences of sex and gender, demonstrated by her partiality to social constructivism as well as science; that female essence is under a constancy of change; and that female essences are empty but resistant. She makes no mention of whether this all applies to black women, women who undergo not only gender oppression but also racial oppression. Unlike what Malabou says of sex, race has no biological or genetic foundation. It is a complete social construction having no correlation to scientific axioms. One wonders, then, if Malabou’s empty but resistant essence, which she employs for gender uses, can be used on race as well. I aver that it can because the aim of Malabou’s reonception of essence is to, as the title of her book implies, change difference. Like gender, race has palpable, violent consequences. As a materialist, Malabou emphasizes the importance of material reality, therefore, the material consequences of race, brought upon by perceived biological and ideological truths, are also subject to Malabou’s new conception of essence. Malabou’s claim about women’s essence is that “[i]n the name woman, there is an empty but resistant essence, an essence that is resistant precisely because it is emptied, a stamp of impossibility” (98-99; emphasis in original). What does this mean? How can woman have an empty essence? How can an empty essence be resistant? To answer these questions, we must look closely at Malabou’s alternative definition of essence. She begins by saying that in the label “woman”—that group which is marginalized, attacked, oppressed, “othered”—there is an empty essence. This word “empty” is most 14 peculiar because it seems to directly oppose the very definition of essence; it seems paradoxical, oxymoronic. How can there be emptiness and essence? This emptiness opposes essentialism by asserting that instead of some innate “thing” within a particular group of individuals, there is nothing—no-thing. Malabou asks us to first think of woman as empty and undetermined, bereft of characteristics. Thinking of black women in this way clears woman of any arbitrary characteristics that can be imposed upon her and leaves her purely open, completely susceptible to plurality. An empty essence means that nearly all is possible, but nothing is necessary. Before moving further with Malabou’s claim, it is essential to engage Battersby’s articulation of the “female subject-position.” Battersby’s boldly stated claim is that In so far as there is ‘sameness’ between women, this is not a matter of shared experiences or lifehistories. It is, rather, a question of a shared positioning vis-à-vis the founding metaphysical categories that inform our notions of individuality, self and ‘personhood’. Thus, whether or not a woman is lesbian, infertile, post-menopausal or childless, in modern western cultures she will be assigned a subject-position linked to a body that has perceived potentialities for birth. (16) Her argument is a poignant one; however, it fails to acknowledge that even though lesbian, infertile, and post-menopausal women will be perceived to be potential child-bearers, this does not logically usher in the coda that, regardless of a particular woman’s accidental characteristics, all women operate under the same subject-position. In the case of race, white women do not hold fundamentally coequal positions with black women. In a white supremacist society, black women’s experiences are fundamentally different from white women’s experiences, thus showing that their subject positions are not the same. Therefore, there must be something other than a congruent subject-position that unifies women across 15 the multifarious spectrum of identities. Malabou offers a remedy for thinking about the essence of women. Her claim of essence reads: “an empty but resistant essence, an essence that is resistant precisely because it is emptied.” To resist is to push back, to deflect, to oppose, to withstand, and to defy. The empty essence of the woman is the necessary condition for this resistance, this deflection, and it is because of that emptiness that her essence can withstand impositions of her inherent identity. But what is being resisted? Perhaps the case of black women can help illuminate the idea. If a black woman’s identity is in fact empty and resistant because of that emptiness, she resists everything that is not her. That which is not her is everything she resists. She only becomes what she accepts, what she does not resist, meaning that her identity indicates precisely what she has accepted as her and also what she has rejected as not her. What this emptiness and resistance does is rebuke the claim that all black women are this or that and opens up nearly any possibility for the black woman. She is not confined or limited but given a multiplicity of possibilities to define her, possibilities that she chooses. In order to resist unwanted characteristics we must address the question of who is doing the resisting. After all, it would seem that is one’s essence is empty there would be no agent to resist. The resister is precisely who has been inflicted and imposed upon; the resister is who was constantly defined by others. While an empty essence enables resistance, more essential essences diminish the potential for resistance. Her emptiness is required for her many possibilities and ability to be anything. With that requisite met, we must then examine what that emptiness signifies. “A stamp of impossibility.” What about this empty but resistant essence makes it a stamp of impossibility? A stamp marks an impression, a distinctive character or indication, a 16 lasting imprint. Something about this empty but resistant essence gives the essence a distinctive character—an identity. This identity is one of impossibility. But what is impossible? The place of impossibility is “the structural impossibility [woman] experiences of not being violated, in herself and outside, everywhere” (Changing Difference 140). The empty but resistant essence is the name “woman” at the top of the guest list of a new club that puts the old club of the a priori innately Other woman out of business. With old essential notions of identity it was impossible for woman to define herself apart from the violence done to her; in the name “woman” was only impositions from external sources other than herself. What the empty but resistant essence does is rename woman as she who is self-defined, stamping her with an empty but resistant essence, a state of affairs impossible with old notion of essential identity. This empty but resistant essence frees black women of marks of inherent sameness or innate markers of inferiority. This new conception necessarily will change how black women are viewed and thus change their fate. If one were to gaze upon the identity of black women through the empty but resistant lens, it would be impossible to make the mistake of white solipsism because there would be no inherent characteristic of all black individuals at which to scoff. It would be impossible to assert a prejudiced agenda on individuals of a particular group, be it racial, gendered, etc., because there would be no innate, unifying characteristic in which to pinpoint a source of bigotry. The liberation of black women, however, may also critique Malabou’s very claim of changing essence. Malabou rebukes essentialist thought because it rejects biology completely. Biological differences between the sexes are real and material—they are natural, so to speak. However, what is natural for Malabou, what runs beneath the soil of our natural, material world, is change—perennial, everlasting change. So, even biological differences between 17 sexes succumb to the mandate of change. Male and female “essences” and innate physical differences are natural, therefore capable of and unable to escape change. Women—black women in this particular case—can be liberated with the knowledge of plasticity because even their biology, that which differentiates them from the biological characteristics of men, can and will change. However, what of their blackness? Race has come to be proven to have no biological basis. It is a social construct that has permeated our society and resulted in real impediments, material wounds, and inequities, and it has always been changing. Blackness means something different now than it did ten, fifty, one hundred years ago. Blackness— race—has demonstrated its susceptibility to change. However, while it has been susceptible to change, it has also persisted in that it has always been anathema to liberation, reductionist, and restrictive. Why hasn’t plasticity and change liberated blackness from the chains of denigration in America? What, if anything, can the notion of an ontology of change and plasticity do now for race if it hasn’t done anything so far, being that racism and ideas of blackness have shown themselves to be ever-changing with ideas of blackness from chattel slavery, sharecropping, Jim Crow, Civil Rights, etc.? Why has plasticity not liberated blackness from denigration yet? Can it? Although it may be unclear how an ontology of change can address the persisting challenges of the constantly changing concept of race, Malabou’s empty but resistant essence redefines the essence of not only black women but all people. It removes predetermined, arbitrarily imposed identity characteristics and presents an empty slate that each person can choose to fill or leave as empty as they may. I do, however, wish to make clear that even though there is no concrete black female essence, I do not, nor cannot, discredit the unique, real, oppressive experiences black women have faced. Asserting the falsity of inherent group essences does not assert the falsity of real group experiences because the ramifications of 18 assumed identities are palpable events. What Malabou’s new essence does is make room for change. Her conception of essence can enact concrete, material changes by destroying the prime cause of group and individual denigration, discrimination, injustice, oppression, and marginalization: purported innate, unfavorable characteristics of people who appear to share a particular quality. Reimagining essence can lead to reimagining the possibilities of our lives; it opens up a variety possibilities, liberating and freeing us from stagnation. It can promote social justice and equity by devouring the underlying assumptions of group denigration. It can define our world, allowing us all to define ourselves. Bibliography Baraka, Amiri. "The Myth of a ‘Negro Literature.’”." Home: Social Essays (1966): 105-15. Battersby, Christine. "The Phenomenal Woman: Feminist Metaphysics and the Patterns of Identity." Routledge Press. (1998). Cartwright, Richard L. "Some remarks on essentialism." The Journal of Philosophy 65, no. 20 (1968): 615-626. Hill Collins, Patricia. "The social construction of black feminist thought." Signs 14, no. 4 (1989): 745-773. ——. "Defining Black Feminist Thought". In: Collins, Patricia Hill, Black Feminist Thought: Knowledge, Consciousness, and the Politics of Empowerment. (New York: Routledge, 1990), p. 19-40. Hogue, W. Lawrence. "Literary Production: A Silence in Afro-American Critical Practice." Weixlmann and Fontenot 31 (1986): 45. Malabou, Catherine, and Peter Skafish. The Heidegger change. On the fantastic in philosophy. Suny Press, 2011. Malabou, Catherine. What should we do with our brain?. Fordham Univ Press, 2009. ——. Changing difference. Polity, 2011. ——. The future of Hegel: plasticity, temporality and dialectic. Routledge, 2004. McDowell, Deborah E. "New directions for Black feminist criticism." In Black American Literature Forum, vol. 14, no. 4, pp. 153-159. St. Louis University, 1980. 19 Morrison, Toni. "Unspeakable Things Unspoken: T he Afro-American Presence in American Literature." (1988). Palmer, Phyllis Marynick. "White women/black women: The dualism of female identity and experience in the United States." Feminist Studies 9, no. 1 (1983): 151-170. Peltola, Pia, Melissa A. Milkie, and Stanley Presser. "The “Feminist” Mystique Feminist Identity in Three Generations of Women." Gender & Society 18, no. 1 (2004): 122-144. Smith, Barbara. Toward a Black feminist criticism. No. 5. Crossing Pr, 1977. Spelman, Elizabeth. "Theories of race and gender: The erasure of black women." Quest 5, no. 4 (1982): 36-62. Walker, Alice. "In search of our mother's gardens." Making Sense of Women's Lives: An Introduction to Women's Studies (2000): 226. ——. In Search of Our Mothers’ Garden: Womanist Prose. New York: Harcourt (1983). xi-xii. 20