The future of the theory and philosophy of history Willem Styfhals (Centre for Metaphysics and Philosophy of Culture – Institute of Philosophy, KULeuven) Pseudomorphosis and Re-occupation: the philosophical nature of historical change and epochal transition Introduction Change is the condition of possibility of history. In a universe where everything is essentially fixed and unchangeable and where the same things eternally return, it does not make sense to talk about history. One can only inquire into the past as past if it is significantly different from the present, i.e. if there is at least a minimal amount of change or discontinuity between then and now. In this sense, the concept of change is a methodological and even ontological presupposition of the historical sciences. As such, the discipline of history itself cannot define or make explicit its conception of change, as it cannot be perceived empirically. Ultimately, the nature of historical change is a philosophical question that requires theoretical reflection. In this paper, I elaborate on a specific type of historical change, namely the change that takes place in the transition between two historical epochs. In this regard I focus on two philosophical attempts to conceptualize epochal transition in the history of ideas: first, on Oswald Spengler’s concept of Historical Pseudomorphosis, second, on Hans Blumenberg’s concept of Umbesetzung – often translated as Re-occupation. Both notions share sensitivity to a practical complexity of historical change and epochal transition. Although historical change is intuitively understood as the discontinuity between successive historical facts, proper change cannot equal mere discontinuity. Discontinuity as such is historically unintelligible, and the one-sided focus on sudden change and inexplicable difference is simply uninteresting. What is more, if there were not even a minimal continuity or causal relation between two successive epochs, the historical interpretation of their respective decline and genesis would be impossible. In this regard, historical science would be restricted to the mere empirical registration of disconnected facts. Paradoxically, a practicable conception of change thus has to take continuity as well as discontinuity into account, sameness as well as difference. In light of this, Blumenberg’s concept of re-occupation can be considered as an attempt to 1 explain how a legitimately new and fully-fledged modern epoch is by definition bound to premodern problems and questions. These questions do not intrinsically belong to the new epoch, but neither can they be eliminated. Similarly, Spengler’s notion of Pseudomorphosis shows how a properly new epoch – or ‘Culture’, to put it in his own terminology – can be determined by the cultural vocabulary of the preceding one. In spite of an undeniable structural affinity between these two concepts, however, I will argue that Spengler’s underlying ontology of history is less convincing than Blumenberg’s. Ultimately, Spengler’s rigid conception of the intrinsic essence of a culture does not allow him to account for a real historical interaction or a reciprocal influence between two epochs/cultures. In other words, it does not allow him to make epochal transition and historical change really intelligible. Oswald Spengler: historical pseudomorphosis In Der Untergang des Abendlandes, Oswald Spengler famously develops a philosophy of history by trying to uncover universal laws that structure the course of world history. He drops the traditional triadic division between antiquity, middle ages and modernity, and replaces it by a less Eurocentric perspective that recognizes at least eight higher cultures or epochs in the history of the world – Babylonian, Egyptian, Chinese, Indian, Mexican, Classical (Apollonian), Arabic (Magian) and Western (Faustian). For Spengler, each of these cultures’ historical development is determined by the same unchangeable laws. Although the specific essences and worldviews of different cultures are fundamentally incomparable and even inaccessible to one another, each culture is structured according to the iron logic of genesis, flourishing and decline. Consequently, certain phases or events in one culture, though incomparable qua content, structurally return in other cultures. Spengler, for example, refers to the structural affinities between the phases of Hellenism in the classical culture and the period before the First World War in the Western/Faustian culture. He even calls these historical phases “contemporaneous.” In spite of this shared cyclic determinism of growth and decline, the historical gap between cultures is fundamentally unbridgeable. Cultures are impenetrable, indivisible, unchangeable, and thus closed historical entities – much like Thomas Kuhn’s scientific paradigms. In this sense, the evolution of a culture is determined exclusively by its internal logic, not by any external cultural influence. This position is not only historically counterintuitive, but, more than that, this perspective also retrains Spengler from elaborating on the problem of epochal transition. If there is no connection whatsoever between cultures, he can only account for the genesis of a new culture as a sudden, inexplicable and discontinuous 2 appearance lacking any determinate historical cause. Accordingly, in Spengler’s perspective, historical change is only intelligible within the development of a culture, while the transition from one culture to another (epochal change) is absolutely unintelligible. However, in the Chapter Problems of the Arabian Culture, Spengler introduces a concept that might allow him him to develop the interrelation between two independent cultures: this is the concept of Pseudomorphosis. This notion explains how a new culture’s development is influenced, but especially curtailed by the legacy of an older one. As it happens, Spengler borrows the notion of pseudomorphosis from geology. In this scientific context, the concept refers to a complex mineralogical phenomenon where crystals in a rockstratum are gradually washed out by streams of water. In this process, the crystal eventually disappears, but the mold it created in the rock-stratum remains. In this hollow mold, a new crystal can develop that necessarily takes the external shape of its predecessor. Spengler argues that a similar process can take place in world history as well. He defines Historical pseudomorphosis as the case in which “an older alien Culture lies so massively over the land that a young Culture cannot get its breath and fails not only to achieve pure and specific expression-forms, but even to develop fully its own self-consciousness.”1 In short, the new culture’s development is contained within the historical mold its predecessor left behind. Because the new culture has not yet developed its proper means of expression, it develops a radically new content in the older and outdated form of the previous culture. Although an different cultural dynamic is at work, the new culture takes the shape (morphè) of the older one, and appears as if (pseudo) it were still the older.2 The question, however, remains whether Spengler’s pseudomorphosis is a practicable concept for the understanding of historical change. I argue that it is not: first, because pseudomorphosis does not function and is not meant to function as a concept of historical change in Der Untergang des Abendlandes, second, and more importantly, because pseudomorphosis does not allow for an intrinsic interrelation between two cultures. In Spengler’s perspective, two independent cultures can influence each other’s forms of expression, but they cannot influence or change the inner nature of the culture itself. Accordingly, pseudomorphosis cannot really grasp the change itself taking place in the transition between these two cultures. Since pseudomorphosis changes a culture on a merely 1 Oswald Spengler, The Decline of the West, ed. Helmut Werner, Arthur Helps and Charles Francis Atkinson (New York: Vintage Books, 2006), 268. 2 In the chapter where Spengler develops the notion of pseudomorphosis, he specifically focuses on the restrictive climate of a dominant classical culture in which the Arabian/Magian culture (the culture of the monotheistic religions) struggles to develop its own self-consciousness – hence the title of this chapter: Problems of the Arabian Culture. 3 superficial and extrinsic level, the confrontation between two cultures cannot give rise to something fundamentally new. Consequently, the novelty a culture does arise in relation to its predecessor, but is as it were presupposed in Spengler’s perspective. Despite the possibility of a structural interrelation between two cultures, Spengler thus sticks to an essentialism of cultures: each culture has a specific essence that is radically fixed and historically unchangeable. A scientific analogy can be illuminating here: the pseudomorphic relation between two cultures is not the one of a chemical reaction between two substances giving rise to a completely new substance; rather it is a mere mixture, an emulsion of two substances whose molecular structures do not alter by being brought together. Moreover, if every culture has a specific and intrinsic essence that cannot be altered, any external influence on this culture is considered to be a restriction of the inner development of its essence rather than a positive enrichment of this essence – hence pseudomorphosis’ negative connotation. I can conclude this section on Spengler by affirming what I stated earlier: Spengler’s position cannot explain real epochal transition or historical change. Ultimately, he cannot grasp how and why specific new cultures or epochs arise in world history. Therefore, I turn to Hans Blumenberg’s concept of epochal transition. His concept of Re-occupation is structurally almost identical to Spengler’s pseudomorphosis, but, interestingly enough, Blumenberg discards Spengler’s historical essentialism of cultures. To Blumenberg, there are no fixed cultural identities or universal historical laws. Indeed, he radically rejects the “substantialistic ontology of history” that presupposes “the existence of constants in the history of ideas.”3 The rise and the nature of an epoch rather result from a complex and contingent dynamic of different historical and cultural elements. Hans Blumenberg: Umbesetzung/Re-occupation In Die Legitimität der Neuzeit, Blumenberg develops the concept of re-occupation (umbesetzung) in response to the concept of secularization. In the 1950s and 60s, the latter notion was used in and out of fashion to explain the nature of modernity or different modern phenomena. In the form of the formula “modern phenomenon X is the secularization of premodern/theological phenomenon Y”, secularization became a central topic in the postwar debate about modernity. Karl Löwith, for example, defined progress as secularized Christian eschatology, and Carl Schmitt argued that the sovereignty of the modern statesman is the secularization of divine omnipotence. Blumenberg’s Legitimität der Neuzeit fundamentally 3 Hans Blumenberg, The Legitimacy of the Modern Age, trans. Robert Wallace (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1983), 113. 4 questions the explanatory value of this topical notion of secularization. By overemphasizing the fundamental continuity between modern and pre-modern culture, ultimately, secularization does not explain anything. In the perspective of secularization theory, modernity is the mere rephrasing of Christian content into secular terms. Accordingly, these theories gloss over the real epochal difference between the Middle Ages and modernity, and reduce it the to a superficial and formal distinction. In this regard, Blumenberg wants to do away with the concept of secularization altogether. His disavowal of secularization, however, does not reject any continuity between modernity and pre-modernity. On the contrary, Blumenberg wanted to develop a conceptual framework that would allow him to grasp the historical interrelation between modernity and pre-modernity without compromising modernity’s legitimately new content, i.e. without succumbing to secularization theory’s pitfall of defining modernity as mere watered down Christianity. Here, the notion of re-occupation comes in. The concept explains how a legitimately new and fully-fledged modern epoch is essentially bound to pre-modern problems and questions. These questions do not belong to this new epoch, but neither can they be eliminated. Unlike the theory of secularization, Blumenberg thus refuses to recognize a continuity of content between modernity and pre-modernity in which theological ideas are transposed from the one epoch to the other. He argues that the interrelation between modernity and pre-modernity implies the continuity of questions rather than the continuity of answers. “What mainly occurred in the process that is interpreted as secularization … should be described not as the transposition of authentically theological contents into secularized alienation from their origin but rather as the re-occupation of answer positions that had become vacant and whose corresponding questions could not be eliminated.”4 In this respect, re-occupation shows, not unlike Spengler’s pseudomorphosis, how a new culture or epoch “is bound to the frame of reference of what it renounces.” 5 To put it in Spengler’s terminology, a new culture or epoch arises in the historical mold the preceding epoch left behind. For Blumenberg, this mold is the set of answer positions that have become vacant for modernity after the decline of the Christian middle ages. Accordingly, modernity 4 5 Ibid., 65. Ibid., 69. 5 can only express its legitimately new and original content in the form of the preceding culture’s framework of questions that remains to be meaningful. In spite of the structural similarity between pseudomorphosis and Re-occupation, there is, however, at least one crucial difference between the two notions of epochal transition. Contrary to Spengler, Blumenberg maintains that re-occupation constitutes rather than restrains the development of the new epoch. Instead of imprisoning the new content, the historical mold in which modernity arises is the condition of possibility of its manifestation. It is the language in which new ideas can be expressed before they are able to give rise to their own proper modes of expression. In this respect, the relation with the older epoch fundamentally determines the development and even the nature of the new epoch. Consequently, the essence of an epoch cannot be understood without reference to the way in which it deals with the legacy of its predecessor. Unlike pseudomorphosis, re-occupation thus influences the inner constitution of a culture or epoch. To come back to my scientific analogy, the relation of re-occupation is not a mere mixture of two stable substances. Rather, re-occupation resembles the relation of a chemical reaction: the substances that are brought together change each other’s molecular structure and generate a completely new substance. Conclusion For two reasons, Blumenberg’s conception of epochal transition is a more practicable tool for the historical understanding of epochal change in the history of ideas than Spengler’s pseudomorphosis. First, Blumenberg’s re-occupation accounts for the complex relation between continuity and discontinuity that characterizes real historical change. He neither overemphasizes continuity between modernity and pre-modernity, like the theories of secularization, nor mere discontinuity, like Spengler. Blumenberg namely recognizes the continuity of questions and answer positions, but a discontinuity of content. Second, this approach allows him to grasp how a preceding epoch can change the internal structure of a new epoch, but without compromising the originality and legitimacy of this new epoch. Unlike Blumenberg’s re-occupation, Spengler’s pseudomorphosis does not allow for this complex intrinsic interrelation between cultures that is necessary for a historical understanding of change and epochal transition. 6