Beyond the Naked Square: the Idea of an Agonistic Public Sphere (this is a draft: do not quote) Sante Maletta University of Calabria, Italy sante.maletta@unical.it The major aim of this paper is to present some reflections about the political domain and the common good that may be helpful in answering one of the issues of this conference: How can religions contribute to the common good? The problematic background of this paper can be summarized by the so-called Dilemma of Böckenförde (“The free secular state lives according to presuppositions that it cannot itself guarantee”), and by the Habermasian notion of a “post-secular society”. I will first discuss the notion of “neutralization” with the support of Carl Schmitt. Then I will present Chantal Mouffe’s doctrine of the “agonistic pluralism” and her partial legitimization of the presence of religions in the political domain. Eventually I will criticize Mouffe’s approach with the help of MacIntyre’s phenomenology of social practices in order to stress the importance of public religions in contemporary liberal societies. 1. “Sovereign is he who decides on the exception.”1 I hold that Schmitt’s emphasis on the category of decision does not imply a sort of irrational ‘decisionism’, but it is a reaction to the formalistic and positivistic approaches prevailing in the philosophy of law at the beginning of the 20th cent. Schmitt stresses the fact that beyond any norms and rules there is always the will of a subject. He means decision as the representation of a transcendent principle―an idea―by a personal authority. Decision is supposed to mediate between the idea and the social reality which needs be ordered. Decisions open up the possibility of conflicts, and conflict is the essence of the political domain. For Schmitt what characterizes the Political is “the distinction of friend and enemy [which] denotes utmost degree of intensity of a union or separation, of an association or 1 C. Schmitt, Political Theology (1922). S. Maletta, Beyond the Naked Square dissociation.”2 This dissociation is utmost as it includes the possibility of a bloody conflict that cannot be turned either into a conflict of interest or into an ideal or normative conflict: “The political enemy need not be morally evil or aesthetically ugly; he need not appear as an economic competitor, and it may even be advantageous to engage with him in business transactions. But he is, nevertheless, the other, the stranger; and it is sufficient for his nature that he is, in a special intense way, existentially something different and alien, so that in the extreme case conflicts with him are possible. These can neither be decided by a previously determined general norm nor by the judgment of a disinterested and therefore neutral third party.”3 The enemy is not private (inimicus) but public (hostis). One is ready to risk her life to fight back when something essential is in danger: without it her life, as a member of a group, has no sense anymore. The political community, as a community, characterizes individuals as a whole because they share the same opinions about non-negotiable issues identifying their political existence. This means that the political authority (the state), i.e. the decision-maker, is what produces the sense of the political community. Therefore in its neutralization of conflicts the state cannot use repressive means only. This is what happens with the end of civil religious wars and the rise of the modern state. The sovereign takes the chance to occupy the theological sphere―i.e. the conflictual “central domain” (Zentralgebiet) in the 16th cent.―and to neutralize it. This is part of the secularization process. The sovereign does it by ‘pouring’ wisely persuasion and coercion. Through this Sinngebung the state keeps the control over the definition of the political identity of the community―i.e. about the friend and the enemy―as it is the only power authorized to define the non-negotiable issues. This neutralization is always unstable and precarious and aims to turn outward any radical antagonism. It is a kind of active neutralization as it is based on a decision that produces community. This means that the disorder, which the decision intends to overcome, is not absolute; there is an ethical prerequisite to the political decision. From this viewpoint, the decision restores order instead of creating a new one. Therefore the neutralization and the secularization embodied by the modern state are possible as long as there is something to neutralize and secularize: i.e. an idea, a truth. But during the modern time the Zentralgebieten change―”from the theological to the metaphysical domain, and from there to the humanitarian-moral and finally to the economic domain”4―and this affects the nature of neutralization. Schmitt considers the first stage of this process―the shift from the theological to the metaphysical domain― as “the strongest and most consequential of all” as it “has determined the direction of all further development”.5 Theology was abandoned because it was controversial (from this viewpoint it was neutralized: “Concepts elaborated over many centuries of theological reflection now became uninteresting and merely private matters”)6 in favor of another domain, taken as neutral, where Europeans “hoped to find minimum agreement and common premises allowing for the possibility of security, clarity, 2 Id., The Concept of the Political (1932), §2. Ivi. 4 C. Schmitt, The Age of Neutralizations and Depolitizations (1929). 5 Ivi. 6 Ivi. 3 2 S. Maletta, Beyond the Naked Square prudence, and peace.”7 But this is an illusion: “Europeans always have wandered from a conflictual to a neutral domain, and always the newly won neutral domain has become immediately another arena of struggle, once again necessitating the search for a neutral domain». 8 The present widespread “belief in technology” is founded on the opinion we have found “the absolute and ultimate neutral ground”: “Technology appeared to be a domain of peace, understanding, and reconciliation”.9 But there is something new in technology: its neutrality is different from the neutrality of the other domains. As it is “always only an instrument and weapon”, technology cannot produce any single decision, “least of all for neutrality”, it is “culturally blind”.10 This means that in the domain of technology people live as if conflicts could be overcome not through personal decisions representing some kind of truth, but through a mere automatic process, that is through technology itself. Schmitt goes back to this question in one of his last works, Political Theology II (1970). Here he doe not stress anymore the unsuccessful neutralizing action of technology but rather he holds that behind this there is a ‘spirit’, i.e. a decision about non-negotiable issues. This kind of neutralization is dangerous as those who are subject to it are unaware of it. There is an ideological dynamic going on: technology claims to be neutral but it is actually subject to some social interests. Behind the mask of its apparent neutrality, technology imposes a social sense (a ‘supersense’) which removes any differences and proclaims the end of any divisions. On the contrary this deceitful neutralization increases antagonism, as it delegitimizes the enemy, who is treated at best as a ‘positive’ fact (in the Hegelian sense of the expression). A good example of this ideological neutralization is given by Chantal Mouffe. Those scholars who nowadays aim to overcome any antagonistic model of the Political in the direction of a discursive democracy tend to use an ideological strategy that goes like this: conflicts are foreclosed through the rhetorical usage of the category of modernization, “whose effect is to discriminate between those who are in tune with the new conditions of the modern, posttraditional world and those who still cling desperately to the past.”11 These scholars are therefore allowed to “draw a political frontier between ‘the moderns’ and ‘the traditionalists or fundamentalists’, while at the same time denying the political character of their move.”12 In other words, the ideological aspect of this move is that this friend/enemy discrimination is hidden by presenting this frontier as sociological evidence. The conclusion, to be agreed with, is that “the political in its antagonistic dimension has not disappeared, but [….] manifests itself under a different guise, as a mechanism of exclusion justified on pseudo-scientific grounds.”13 There are 7 Ivi. Ivi. 9 Ivi. 10 Ivi. 11 Ch. Mouffe, On the Political (2005), p. 54. 12 Ivi, p. 55. 13 Ivi. 8 3 S. Maletta, Beyond the Naked Square two possible consequences of this ideological move: either the excluded stay away from the public domain or they go back to it in an intolerant way: either apathy or fanaticism. 2. Since 1990s Chantal Mouffe used Schmitt’s category of the Political to explain the origins of what she calls “post-political society”, characterized by two just mentioned phenomena, apparently contradictory but actually symbiotic: political apathy and political fanaticism. The postpolitical society is the outcome of the liberalist strategy to expel conflicts from the political domain either through the negotiation among interests or through rational discussion and deliberation (Rawls, Habermas). Mouffe’s Schmittian move is to recall that the principle of the Political is the friend/enemy distinction, that there is no political domain without the exclusion of some ‘other’, without a “constitutive outside” (J. Derrida). What makes the citizens of a political community equal is at the same time what makes them different from those who are outside the community. A political body is such only when it has its own political identity―and identities always entail differences. But Mouffe’s aim is to go beyond Schmitt’s approach, whose main weakness is its impossibility to consider political pluralism in a political body as legitimate. Pluralism actually exists only in the international domain, where―according to the Westphalian system of international relations―sovereign states face each other under the non-written rules of the jus publicum aeropeum. Schmitt explicitly rejects the idea of a pluralist state and holds democracy as incompatible with liberalism, as pluralism makes decision impossible. Mouffe faces the following question: “How can we envisage a form of commonality strong enough to institute a ‘demos’ but nevertheless compatible with certain forms of pluralism: religious, moral, and cultural pluralism as well as pluralism of political parties?”.14 This is possible if we recall that a political identity is never natural or spontaneous; it is a linguistic production and “must be seen as the result of the political process of hegemonic articulation.”15 However such an identity is never “fully constituted” and it can exist only “through multiple and competing forms of identifications.”16 Yes, it is true that “there no hegemonic articulation without the determination of a frontier, the definition of a ‘them’. But in the case of liberal democratic politics this frontier is an internal one and the ‘them’ is not a permanent outsider.”17 A theoretical move is presupposed : the difference between the Political, “the dimension of antagonism that is inherent in human relations”, and politics, the ensemble of practices, discourses and institutions which seek to domesticate hostility and weaken potential 14 Ch. Mouffe, Carl Schmitt and the Paradox of Liberal Democracy (1997). Ivi. 16 Ivi. 17 Ivi. 15 4 S. Maletta, Beyond the Naked Square antagonism.18 This difference is the core of what Mouffe calls agonistic pluralism: “the aim of democratic politics is to construct the ‘them’ in such a way that it is no longer perceived as an enemy to be destroyed, but an ‘adversary’ i.e. somebody whose ideas we combat but whose right to defend those ideas we do not put into question”.19 An adversary is no more an enemy in the Schmittian sense, as with her there is a common ground, the principles of liberal democracy (i.e. liberty and equality for all). In other words, the major aim of democratic politics is to transform antagonism in agonism and “this requires providing channels through which collective passions will be given ways to express themselves over issues, which, while allowing enough possibility for identification, will not construct the opponent as an enemy but as an adversary.” 20 Sharing the same principles does not prevent conflict as they can effect politics only through different interpretations, and this produces a “conflictual consensus”. Conflict avoid apathy and disaffection with political participation because it enables processes of polemical identification; on the other hand the consensus on the basic principles of liberal democracy prevents “the crystallization of collective passions around issues, which cannot be managed by the democratic process”.21 A relevant outcome of Mouffe’s perspective is that pluralism involves the end of any substantive idea of good life as the core of the identity of a political body. No Schmittian active neutralization of the Political is possible anymore. Not a total one, at least: liberal democracy, in fact, cannot hold a relativistic conception of the world: “a liberal democratic state must be agnostic in matters of religion and morality [but] it cannot be agnostic concerning political values, since by definition it postulates certain ethico-political values that constitute its principles of legitimacy.”22 This is a logical consequence of the Wittgensteinian doctrine of the primacy of Lebensformen over rules and procedures: “procedures only exist as a complex ensemble of practices. Those practices constitute specific forms of individuality, which make possible the allegiance to the procedures.”23 Therefore: “What is really at stake in the allegiance to democratic institutions is the constitution of an ensemble of practices that make the constitution of democratic citizens possible. This is not a matter of rational justification but of availability of democratic forms of individuality and subjectivity.”24 In summary, democratic politics requires “a democratic Sittlichkeit.”25 The square cannot be naked. It is now possible to conceive of a notion of citizenship as allegiance to the ethico-political values of liberal democracy which is able to “reconcile the strong meaning it had in the civic republican tradition with the pluralism constitutive of modern democracy.”26 Therefore it is not possible for democratic politics “to do without an idea of political community and a reference to 18 Ch. Mouffe, Deliberative Democracy or Agonistic Pluralism (2000). Ivi. 20 Ivi. 21 Ivi. 22 Ch. Mouffe, Religion, Democracy, and Citizenship (2006). 23 Ch. Mouffe, Deliberative Democracy or Agonistic Pluralism. 24 Ivi. 25 Ch. Mouffe, Wittgenstein and the Ethos of Democracy (2001). 26 Ch. Mouffe, Religion, Democracy, and Citizenship, p. 322. 19 5 S. Maletta, Beyond the Naked Square the common good.”27 This is a delicate point as Mouffe’s aim is to go beyond the liberals/communitarians divide by making a sort of Hegelian synthesis. To be compatible with pluralism, the notions of political community and of common good need a peculiar definition. Political community is to be imagined “as a surface for inscribing demands where a ‘we’ is constituted”.28 The common good is seen as a “vanishing point”, a “horizon of meaning”. It functions as a social imaginary, “that is, as that on which its very impossibility of achieving full representation bestows the role of a horizon that is the condition of possibility of any representation within the space that it delimits.”29 As already seen above, consensus on principles does not prevent the rise of political fights and divisions as these principles work only through conflicting interpretations―each producing its own conception of citizenship―in order to define the common sense and establish an hegemony. Can religions contribute to the common good, then? And how? For Mouffe there is no reason to keep religions outside the political realm as they produce important forms of identification which motivate people to political participation. The unique requirement for religions is to respect the constitutional limits of liberal democratic regimes. As the ethico-political principles which legitimize these regimes are subject to different possible interpretations, also the constitutional limits can anyway change in time and space. So there is of course no space for theocratic or fundamentalist approaches in the political domain. Moreover (but this is controversial: see below) it seems to be no space for any kind of civil religion à la Rousseau intended as an “appropriation of religion by politics for its own purposes”.30 In summary, religious groups can play a public role either in the political society (through the creation of single-issues movements, or institutional lobbying, or electoral mobilization), or in the civil society through the participation in open public debates about public affairs and the common good.31 In all these cases religion identities can be powerful sources for political and civil participation, when they do not pass constitutional limits. 3. Mouffe’s perspective is interesting but not completely persuasive. I identify the most controversial point in her approach is when she holds that what is at stake in the allegiance to democratic institutions is not consent but the practices that make the constitution of democratic citizens possible. These practices―according to the approach peculiar of the second Wittgenstein espoused by Mouffe―are an essential prerequisite for democratic politics, and as such they seem to go beyond any rational justifications. The same is for the common good defined in terms of a 27 Ivi. Ivi. 29 Ivi. 30 R. Beiner, Civil Religion, p. 1. “Civil religion s the empowerment of religion, not for the sake of religion, but for the sake of enhanced citizenship―of making members of the political community better citizens, in accordance with whatever conception one holds of what constitutes being a good citizen.” (p. 2) 31 J. Casanova, What is a Public Religion? 28 6 S. Maletta, Beyond the Naked Square social imaginary, i.e. as a quasi-transcendental condition of possibility for the existence of social sense. In summary, Mouffe’s vis polemica against the models of discursive democracy defended by Rawls and Habermas brings her to hold that the question of the different forms of practical rationality is not relevant for the issue of the allegiance to the democratic institutions. This view is dangerous as it opens the possibility of non-rational developments in the radical democratic approach to the problems of post-political societies. It is not a case that Mouffe legitimizes the presence of passions in the public domain and their support of political participation and justifies any “attempt to mobilize those passions toward democratic designs.”32 There is a danger in such an approach―a danger that is peculiar of any form of political radicalism from Rousseau on: the illusory temptation to justify and perform (for good purposes, of course) an instrumental approach to the modern social imaginary and its emotional potentialities―what Charles Taylor calls “the dark sides of modern social imaginary”.33 The possibility of such a development is strengthened by the fact that in Mouffe’s perspective the main goal of any political fight is hegemony, i.e. the construction of a new common sense, something that necessarily involves also the non-rational aspects of human life. If this is true, in this perspective one could eventually justify some kind of civil religion able to gain the hegemonic position in the society if it works to mobilize individuals in the good direction. I believe that this danger can be avoided if we look for a phenomenology of social practices more accurate than the one provided by Mouffe through her interpretation of the second Wittgenstein. This can be found in the works of MacIntyre. Here I summarize this approach.34 The prerequisite to understand MacIntyrian approach to social practices is to take the “first person viewpoint”, that is the viewpoint of the acting person. To non-participants, in fact, a practice may appear to be constituted only by rule-following behavior; to participants, on the contrary, rules are first of all means to a good internal to the practice. In other words, a practice is not only a rule-conforming behavior but first of all a goal-oriented action where goals are goods that give point and purpose to the rules. MacIntyre’s phenomenology of practices cannot be understood without highlighting the strong interdependence between practices and institutions: they belong to the same single causal order. Institutions support practices first by enforcing the rules and second by acquiring and distributing goods external to practices such as money, power or social status―therefore institutions may corrupt practices by diverting actor’s intentions from internal to external goods. To resist this corrupting power, practices need both intellectual and moral virtues. The first teach us what are the goods internal to a practice and the goods which deserve to be achieved in our lives. The second―such as courage, truthfulness, justice―help us in this intellectual activity. When an individual constantly raises questions about the goods of the practices she is engaged in and what place they should have in her own life, in fact, what she realizes sooner or later is that she 32 Ch. Mouffe, Religion, Democracy, and Citizenship, p. 324. Cf. Ch. Taylor, Modern Social Imaginary. 34 Cf. K. Knight, Practices: The Aristotelian Concept (2008); Rules, Powers, and Goods (2012). 33 7 S. Maletta, Beyond the Naked Square cannot do that without involving those who take part in the practices, that is without a common reasoning and a common deliberation about action. This approach does not deny the existence of conflicts in common practical reasoning. On the contrary, it is well aware of the fact that, when an individual raises questions about the good and the goods of her life, she can do this only from within a certain tradition of moral enquiry, better still from within a particular interpretation of this tradition. Traditions of moral enquiry live on the competition with other traditions and with conflicting interpretations of the tradition itself. A very relevant point that Mouffe misses is that practice, when it is in good order―i.e. when it is a goal-oriented activity ordered by virtues and rules and not corrupted by institutions―requires the educations of desires and their redirection to internal goods. In other words, desires cannot be considered neither as positive data nor as something non-rational that can be changed only through rhetorical means. This is the strongest and most unaware form of contemporary reification: when human beings relate to their own desires as if they were ‘objective things’ (as it happens for instance when they turn to a marriage bureau), they are alienated from themselves. Here we may find a model of political community that relies on a bond which is not cultural, ethic, or linguistic, but rather rational. What generates the social bond is in fact the question of the order of the goods, because it is impossible to tackle this problem without involving the others with whom one is engaged in the activities of practices. It is practical rationality itself, therefore, that has a political dimension. From this viewpoint, politics is to be considered as the activity of answering questions about the ordering of practices in ordinary life. 35 Politics is a second-order practice that, in summary, embodies the common good itself. This approach opens up the possibility of a new assessment of the public role of religions. In general religions do enforce the moral virtues that strengthen our resistance to the corruption power of institutions. Moreover religions―especially those that have always been effective in the Western societies (Judaism, Christianity, Islam)―are to be considered also as intellectual bodies. Therefore they develop in their own educational and research institutions traditions of inquiry into the human good which are still effective in post-secular societies and which cannot legitimately be excluded from the political debate without taking the risk to weaken the moral and the intellectual virtues of the people. But the most relevant beneficial effect of religions can be understood when we consider one major trait of liberal societies, what MacIntyre calls the compartmentalization of roles. Such compartmentalisation occurs when “each distinct sphere of social activity comes to have its own role structure governed by its own specific norms in relative independence of other such spheres”36. The precepts of the virtues are understood as prescriptions for the development of habits that make an individual more efficient in his or her role-playing. Virtues lose the subjective dimension: they no longer support the development of an awareness of the goals included in one’s social role and therefore the possibility of criticising them. The outcome of the 35 36 Cf. M. Murphy, MacIntyre’s Political Philosophy (2003), p. 163. A. MacIntyre, Social Structures and their Threat to Moral Agency, p. 167. 8 S. Maletta, Beyond the Naked Square compartmentalisation of roles is a divided self, who lacks the two virtues basic to the exercise of his moral responsibility—integrity, which sets limits to one’s adaptability to social roles, and constancy, which sets limits to flexibility of character. In summary, the compartmentalisation of roles produces an uncritical and therefore irresponsible moral agent. To avoid this outcome we do not need a positive religious faith: the mere posing of the religious problem―what is the sense of my life? what is my good? how should I live? unde malum?―allows the subject to gain an unitary perspective on her own existence, to take a position from which it is easier for her to resist and criticize the immoral demands of the social roles and the corrupting power of institutions. The more one practises the moral and the intellectual virtues, the more one is able to do that. But this can be done only within communities which, in our Western societies, have generally been and still are religious communities. Religions can and do play a decisive role within contemporary liberal societies: they make possible the constitution of subjects who are able to partially detach from their own social roles and to have a critical stance over them. This is a necessary prerequisite for the existence of different social identities in competition about the definition of the common good. In other words, religions can and do play an important public role as they belong to the small group of social agencies that are still able to educate moral conscience. Conscience brings in the public space what liberals usually try to keep in the private forum, i.e. non-negotiable issues. But when everything is negotiable, it is very difficult to resist the corrupting power of the institutions . Without non-negotiable issues, pace Mouffe, the political domain loses its agonistic spirit and degenerates into apathy and fanaticism. The political domain in a liberal democratic regime lives thanks to a tension between its constitutional limits and the challenges represented by the non-negotiable issues. Democracy is always “to come” (J. Derrida). 9