Wild-Type – First Draft II - Exeter Biological Interest Group

advertisement
The Concept of Wild-Type in Transmission Genetics: Ideas of Species, Variation
and Environment Amongst the Early Mendelians
INTRODUCTION
Wild-type is a term that has for nearly a century been used ubiquitously in genetics in a
manner that would suggest it represents an unproblematic concept, and it is treated in
genetics textbooks as if it were such. When referring to a particular model organism, wildtype is said to denote the common, ‘normal’ phenotype, this being “the type observed in the
wild, in other words, in nature”. This phenotype is related to genotype in that “All essential
genes must be capable of producing their functional products in order to produce this wildtype phenotype. These normally functioning alleles are called wild-type alleles”. Wild-type is
contrasted with mutants, these being “exceptional discontinuous variant phenotypes”1 whose
alleles “tend to be rare in natural populations”. The effect of mutation is furthermore
characterised as being commonly detrimental, as the absence of the functional products
produced by the wild-type allele results in the incompletion of often vital biochemical
pathways.2
Even as so defined, the concept of wild-type contains considerable ambiguities, most notably
regarding whether it refers to the prevalence of single traits within a population considered in
isolation or to a composite (abstract) ‘average organism’ which possesses all prevalent traits
(as could be inferred from assertions such as “All essential genes must be capable of
producing their functional products in order to produce this wild-type phenotype”). This
particular ambiguity is arguably a product of vagueness in the definition of ‘phenotype’ and
‘genotype’, which ostensibly refer only to particular traits and genes but are also sometimes
used to refer to many or even all traits and genes. That wild-type is used to refer both to
phenotype and genotype can also become problematic when it leads, through an attribution to
the allele of the power to cause the trait, to an ignoring of the pervasive part that
environmental influences play in shaping the phenotype. In addition to these problems of
what exactly wild-type refers to, the term has from its inception been entangled in the debate
over the true nature of species, in particular what the typical range of variation is within and
1
Anthony J.F. Griffiths, William M. Gelbart, Jeffrey H. Miller, & Richard C. Lewontin, Modern Genetic
Analysis, W.H. Freeman and Company, 1999, pp. 15 & 70
2
Robert J. Brooker, Genetics: Analysis and Principles, 2nd Ed., The McGraw-Hill Companies Inc., 2005, pp. 76
& 436
~ Page 1 ~
between species, and what, if any, norms does it comply to. To this is added the question of
what differences in norms of variation exist between wild and domesticated organisms and
whether a domestic organism can legitimately be used as an experimental substitute for a
wild one. It has been a common accusation within these debates that the wild-type concept as
it is generally used in the genetics community fundamentally misrepresents the true nature of
intraspecific variation and the wild/domestic dichotomy.
In order to understand the origins of the wild-type concept and its latent ambiguities, it is
necessary to turn to history. The focus for this study will primarily be the work of four
prominent ‘early Mendelians’ – William Bateson, Hugo de Vries, William E. Castle and
Thomas Hunt Morgan. Their choice is justified on account of their prominence within their
field, but also on grounds that they each represent distinct positions on the question of ‘wild
type’ and the nature of species and variation in nature. To clarify, the term ‘early Mendelian’
was one popularised to refer to the geneticists of the first decade of the twentieth century by
historical accounts such as Mayr’s but was also previously used by R.A. Fisher to refer
(negatively) to these predecessors. The label refers to the prevalence of ‘Mendelian’ as a
label for biologists studying discontinuous heredity prior to the institution of ‘genetics’ and
‘geneticist’ after 1908 as standard nomenclature.3 It is acknowledged that many other
significant early geneticists have been left out of this study, for example Wilhelm Johannsen,
Lucien Cuénot and Carl Correns, and that, with the exception of de Vries, all the chosen
figures are from the Anglophone world. These exceptions and the lack of representation of
the European continent are in part due to a lack of space or an absence of a distinctive
thought-style, but are also a product of the problem of the reliability of terminology when
utilising sources from another language. I cannot, for example, necessarily assume that the
German or Russian equivalent of ‘wild-type’ necessarily contains within it the same
conceptual associations as does the English term. Moreover, as a monoglot, I can only work
with such sources in translation, but I cannot necessarily rely on the correct transposition of
concepts in the original into the English. This is also a reason why I have used Species and
Varieties as opposed to the more well-known Die Mutationstheorie as the former was
originally written by de Vries for an English-speaking audience, so any (mentally) translated
concepts will at least have been interpreted by the author himself as opposed to a translator
3
Ernst Mayr, The Growth of Biological Thought: Diversity, Evolution and Inheritance, The Belknap Press of
Harvard University Press, 1982, pp. 547
~ Page 2 ~
who might misrepresent them.4 Regarding other reasons for omitting particular continental
schools of genetics, Russian genetics had arguably little global impact in the period studied
owing to the fact that it only established as a science in the Soviet period,5 and German
genetics, whilst a very active school, was in general more interested in the role of Mendelian
inheritance in development rather than variation in wild and domestic populations, so does
not seem to have had much to say about wild-type.6
My methodology in researching for this project was initially heavily based on electronic
media, in particular using ‘search’ and ‘find’ functions in order to locate occurrences of my
key term ‘wild type’ in JSTOR journals and within texts downloaded from the Internet
Archive, from which I also downloaded texts by my key early geneticists. I quickly
discovered, however, that searching for key terms did not turn up many of the instances in
these texts where the wild-type concept is in some form clearly either being invoked or is
forming an essential part of the background of a thought. That uncovering how the wild-type
concept was being conceptualised among the early Mendelians has often required some
detective work is a consequence of its somewhat inchoate and plastic nature at this point, it
not yet having a given place in the thought-structure of genetics. It also is often called by
different names, some of them pure synonyms, others not fully conceptually overlapping, and
is furthermore paired with different opposites with dissimilar natures. The nature of wild-type
itself is of course a key area of examination, but it is rarely when utilised as a term clearly
defined by its users, so much of their understanding of its nature has to be disclosed through
studying their interpretation of broader phenomena including, crucially, the question of what
is a species, what variation exists within a species, and what differences in variation might
exist between domesticated organisms and wild ones of the same species. It is for this reason
that I have subtitled this essay ‘Ideas of Species, Variation and Environment Amongst the
Early Mendelians’, for it has often been only through the study of these ideas, which take
centre-stage in much of early Mendelian literature, that an understanding of the historical
development of the concept of wild-type can be attained.
4
Hugo de Vries, Species and Varieties: Their Origin by Mutation, Daniel Trembly MacDougal (ed.), The Open
Court Publishing Company, 1905, pp. vii-viii
5
Ernst Mayr, The Growth of Biological Thought: Diversity, Evolution and Inheritance, The Belknap Press of
Harvard University Press, 1982, pp. 732
6
Michel Morange, ‘The Developmental Gene Concept: History and Limits’, The Concept of the Gene in
Development and Evolution, Peter J. Beurton, Raphael Falk, & Hans-Jörg Rheinberger (eds.), Cambridge
University Press, 2000, pp. 194
~ Page 3 ~
This research technique is admittedly at times one of rational reconstruction in that it, in the
absence of open expression of the wild-type concept, will seek instead to discern its shape in
the mind of the geneticist by trying to establish in what way that mind’s thoughts regarding
wild-type might be limited by their known beliefs regarding species, variation and
environment. In my defence, however, I would argue that rational reconstruction is a
necessity when researching the history of any idea as, especially in its youth, a concept is
often fairly amorphous, not just ‘fuzzy’7 – it does not only, in other words, lack distinct
boundaries, but is also not fixed in place by a given thought-structure and lacks a clearly
defined content. At this stage, the plasticity of a concept can often impede, as opposed to aid,
their proper use, and they can contain contradictory elements producing tension. The wildtype concept until its institutionalisation by the Drosophilists was arguably such an overly
plastic, ‘leaky’ concept, one whose content was imposed more by the theoretical medium into
which it was placed than by its retaining a strict meaning. Even when it became established,
moreover, it still contained tensions within it that have largely remained unresolved. These
tensions have in part been the product of its being conceived not singularly but rather in
conjunction by a group of esoteric circles of thought. Bateson, de Vries, Castle and Morgan, I
would argue, were each centre figures of their own particular circle, with their own individual
methodologies and groups of followers. These circles were not hermetically sealed from one
another, allowing research and ideas to migrate fairly freely between them, but the process of
communication, as Ludwik Fleck has insisted, “always involves a stylized remodeling”, with
each group interpreting the work of others in their own light.8 The construction of the wildtype concept in modern genetics was a joint effort of all these collectives, but the
hybridisation of the different strands of this idea has never been complete, leaving wild-type
unstable as a concept and open to interpretation.
THE WILD-TYPE CONCEPT BEFORE 1900
It is necessary to begin by noting that the wild-type concept in its embryonic form greatly
predates the dawn of the discipline of genetics. A quick JSTOR search for the term ‘wild
type’ arrives at 15 relevant and distinct references prior to 1900.9 In addition to these direct
Hans-Jörg Rheinberger, ‘Gene Concepts: Fragments from the Perspective of Molecular Biology’, The Concept
of the Gene in Development and Evolution, Peter J. Beurton, Raphael Falk, & Hans-Jörg Rheinberger (eds.),
Cambridge University Press, 2000, pp. 222
8
Ludwik Fleck, Genesis and Development of a Scientific Fact, Fred Bradley and Thaddeus J. Trenn (trans.),
The University of Chicago Press, 1981, pp. 111
9
In chronological order: (1) Anonymous, ‘Four Hundred and Eightieth Meeting. April 10, 1860. Monthly
Meeting’, Proceedings of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences, Vol. 4, 1857-1860, pp. 411-416; (2)
7
~ Page 4 ~
references to the existence of a ‘wild type’, biologists in the second half of the nineteenth
century were also utilising a host of synonyms and related terms in order to express their
underlying beliefs regarding the nature of wild and domestic organisms and populations,
including ‘wild stock’,10 ‘original type’,11 ‘parental type’,12 ‘ancestral type’13 and ‘aboriginal
stock’.14 This being a pre-genetics context, these terms and concepts were used to refer to
quite different phenomena from those to which wild-type is familiarly applied today. This
alternate initial application relates to the original roots of the wild-type concept, which lie in
the more general development from the late eighteenth century onward of an idea of heredity
as the transmission of abstract properties.15 Prior to this conceptual shift, there was no real
need to invoke a wild-type concept, as it was generally assumed by the Aristotelianism
dominant in the early modern period that the environmental conditions at the time of
conception played a major role in determining the nature of the offspring, and that it was thus
places which ‘inherited’ their inhabitants and not vice versa.16 Such a world-view necessarily
Hodder M. Westropp, ‘On the Sequence of the Phases of Civilisation, and Contemporaneous Implements’,
Journal of the Anthropological Society of London, Vol. 5, 1867, pp. cxcii-cc; (3) Chauncey Wright, ‘Review:
[untitled], Reviewed work(s): Contributions to the Theory of Natural Selection by Alfred Russel Wallace, On
the Genesis of Species by St. George Mivart, The Descent of Man, and Selection in Relation to Sex by Charles
Darwin, On the Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection, or the Preservation of Favored Races in the
Struggle for Life by Charles Darwin’, The North American Review, Vol. 113, No. 232, 1871, pp. 63-103; (4)
Lyons M. J., ‘Radicalism and ransom: a lecture delivered to working men Radicalism and ransom: a lecture
delivered to working men’, Bristol Selected Pamphlets, 1885, 24 pages; (5) Anonymous, ‘Botany at the
American Association Botany at the American Association’, Botanical Gazette, Vol. 11, No. 9, 1886, pp. 221224; (6) Anonymous, ‘Botany’, The American Naturalist, Vol. 21, No. 6, 1887, pp. 572-577; (7) R. C. Auld,
‘The Wild Cattle of Great Britain’, The American Naturalist, Vol. 22, No. 258, 1888, pp. 498-509; (8)
Anonymous, ‘Review: [untitled], Reviewed work(s): Experimental Evolution by H. de Varigny’, The British
Medical Journal, Vol. 1, No. 1676; 1893, p. 296; (9) L. H. Bailey, ‘Whence came the Cultivated Strawberry’,
The American Naturalist, Vol. 28, No. 328, 1894, pp. 293-306; (10) D'Arcy Power, ‘An Experimental
Investigation Into The Causation Of Cancer’, The British Medical Journal, Vol. 2, No. 1760, 1894, pp. 636-638;
(11) L. H. Bailey, ‘The Plant Individual in the Light of Evolution’, Science, New Series, Vol. 1, No. 11, 1895,
pp. 281-292; (12) Anonymous, ‘Great Frost of 1895’, Bulletin of Miscellaneous Information (Royal Gardens,
Kew), Vol. 1896, No. 109, 1896, pp. 5-10, (13) W. T. Thiselton Dyer, ‘The Cultural Evolution of Cyclamen
latifolium (Sibth)’, Proceedings of the Royal Society of London, Vol. 61, 1897, pp. 135-147; (14) John M.
Macfarlane, ‘Inheritance of Acquired Characteristics’, Science, New Series, Vol. 5, No. 129, 1897, pp. 935-945;
(15) E. J. Hill, ‘Vitis Labrusca and Its Westward Distribution’, Bulletin of the Torrey Botanical Club, Vol. 25,
No. 6, 1898, pp. 342-343
10
Hodder M. Westropp, ‘On the Sequence of the Phases of Civilisation, and Contemporaneous Implements’,
Journal of the Anthropological Society of London, Vol. 5, 1867, pp. cxcix
11
Anonymous, ‘Botany’, The American Naturalist, Vol. 21, No. 6, 1887, pp. 374-5
12
Charles Darwin, On the Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection, or the Preservation of Favoured
Races in the Struggle for Life, Penguin Classics, 2009, pp. 21
13
L. H. Bailey, ‘Whence came the Cultivated Strawberry’, The American Naturalist, Vol. 28, No. 328, 1894,
pp. 297
14
Charles Darwin, On the Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection, or the Preservation of Favoured
Races in the Struggle for Life, Penguin Classics, 2009, pp. 23
15
Staffan Müller-Wille & Hans-Jörg Rheinberger, ‘Heredity – The Formation of an Epistemic Space’, Heredity
Produced: At the Crossroads of Biology, Politics, and Culture, 1500-1870, Staffan Müller-Wille & Hans-Jörg
Rheinberger (eds.), The MIT Press, 2007, pp. 5
16
Ibid., pp. 18
~ Page 5 ~
assumed that the process of domestication would have an effect on the form and disposition
of an organism, so there is therefore no need for a further conceptual category given the
existing wild/domestic dichotomy. The changes in world-view that brought about the wildtype concept may broadly be identified with three of the five categories Müller-Wille and
Rheinberger identify as sources for the development of the idea of heredity, namely natural
history, animal and plant breeding and hybridisation experiments. Of the other two
categories, the study of hereditary disease only became an influence on the wild-type concept
after the birth of genetics with the development of mutation theory and Garrod’s studies of
‘metabolic sports’, and anthropology has arguably had little influence overall.17
Natural history’s contribution to the establishment of the wild-type concept lay largely in its
providing a new framework through which biological phenomena could be interpreted and
categorised. One of the most important of these categorisations was the distinction between
species and varieties, which with Linnaeus became canonical within taxonomy. Species were
claimed to be fundamentally distinct from one another, whereas varieties were believed to be
for the most part climatic variants which would revert to the species type if transplanted to
the normal species environment.18 In essence, the Aristotelian interpretation of variability as
environmentally determined was thus retained as the explanation for differences between
wild and domestic organisms. Linnaeus and other systematists furthermore established an
influential social and methodological demarcation between naturalists and cultivators by
essentially eliminating varieties as an object of natural history.19 The true unit of natural
history was the species and the job of the naturalist was one of “reducing varieties to their
species” through such means as transplantation and hybridisation; they did not, in other
words, study variation in and of itself.20 It was only with Darwin that variation was
reintroduced as an object of natural history and this was at the expense of species as a realist
category, Darwin denying there to be any significant difference between a species and a
17
Ibid., pp. 12
Staffan Müller-Wille, ‘Figures of Inheritance, 1650-1850’, Heredity Produced: At the Crossroads of Biology,
Politics, and Culture, 1500-1870, Staffan Müller-Wille & Hans-Jörg Rheinberger (eds.), The MIT Press, 2007,
pp. 192
19
Marc J. Ratcliff, ‘Duchesne’s Strawberries: Between Growers’ Practices and Academic Knowledge’, Heredity
Produced: At the Crossroads of Biology, Politics, and Culture, 1500-1870, Staffan Müller-Wille & Hans-Jörg
Rheinberger (eds.), The MIT Press, 2007, pp. 211-2
20
Staffan Müller-Wille, ‘Collection and collation: theory and practice of Linnaean botany’, Studies in History
and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences,
Volume 38, Issue 3, September 2007, pp. 545
18
~ Page 6 ~
variety as both are equally just convenient labels for sets of closely resembling individuals.21
With Darwin, moreover, the nature of variation within the epistemology of natural history
dramatically shifted in that its study became a means of understanding species, whereas
before it had been considered a hindrance. That variation was considered a hindrance prior to
Darwin did not mean that natural historians denied its reality; indeed, they tended to be
‘lumpers’; who admitted fewer species than those systematists who came before, resulting in
more varied specific units. Linnaeus, for example, reduced John Ray’s 18,500 described
species to a mere 7,000.22 The motive for discounting varieties was instead the belief that
specific differences were more fundamental than varietal differences and that they could be
distinguished through appropriate methods.23 Linnaean species varied more than those of
Ray, but their distinct characteristics were more constant in different environments.
Evolutionary thinking again turned these concepts of natural history on their head by
stressing that what was epistemologically interesting was inconstancy and novelty as opposed
to climatically and temporally unchanging features.
Where the techniques of the eighteenth century natural historians had before Darwin already
run into some difficulties was the discovery of varieties such as the strawberry Fragaria
monophylla, found by Antoine-Nicolas Duchesne in 1763.24 This was a distinct variety
produced through hybridisation but which reproduced constantly from seeds and was
unchanged by novel environmental conditions. The existence of these ‘constant varieties’
blunted the razor of the dichotomy between specific and varietal traits and weakened the
argument that there is a one-to-one relationship between organismic and environmental
variation, permitting a distinction to be made between ‘wild’ and ‘wild type’. It moreover
acted to permit within a species the possibility of internally, as opposed to externally,
determined variation, which therefore suggested that inheritance of specific characters might
be differential as opposed to uniform. If specific characters were unevenly distributed within
the species and through time, it demanded a new method of study if such variation was to be
21
Charles Darwin, On the Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection, or the Preservation of Favoured
Races in the Struggle for Life, Penguin Classics, 2009, pp. 56
22
Marc J. Ratcliff, ‘Duchesne’s Strawberries: Between Growers’ Practices and Academic Knowledge’, Heredity
Produced: At the Crossroads of Biology, Politics, and Culture, 1500-1870, Staffan Müller-Wille & Hans-Jörg
Rheinberger (eds.), The MIT Press, 2007, pp. 211
23
Staffan Müller-Wille, ‘Collection and collation: theory and practice of Linnaean botany’, Studies in History
and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences,
Volume 38, Issue 3, September 2007, pp. 544
24
Marc J. Ratcliff, ‘Duchesne’s Strawberries: Between Growers’ Practices and Academic Knowledge’, Heredity
Produced: At the Crossroads of Biology, Politics, and Culture, 1500-1870, Staffan Müller-Wille & Hans-Jörg
Rheinberger (eds.), The MIT Press, 2007, pp. 205-6
~ Page 7 ~
tracked, that of genealogy, as the existing method of comparing individuals to a type
specimen could only suggest limits to variation, not track patterns of variability.25 These
genealogical methods were similar to the primitive phylogenies of early Darwinians such as
Haeckel, but focusing on constancy as opposed to divergence. Due to the focus on
evolutionary divergence in the latter nineteenth century, constancy was consequently
downplayed and only to return into focus with the rediscovery of Mendel’s mathematical
ratios.26
Animal and plant breeders, like the pre-Darwinian natural historians, employed methods of
hybridisation and transplantation in their work, but for the completely different end of
producing, not reducing, variation. In pursuing this alternate goal, breeders understood their
task as one of imposing artifice on nature, not of returning organisms to their ‘natural
place’.27 As part of their artificially imposing on nature, they utilised a host of additional
techniques foreign to the natural historian, including grafting in plants and inbreeding in
animals, with the specific aim of producing novel, sometimes monstrous variety in order to
produce stock of greater commercial value. The breeders’ understanding of how their
methods worked were not uniform and developed alongside the honing of practices. Their
beliefs were rooted in folk wisdom such as the conviction that ‘like begets like’ and that
‘blood’ was the vehicle of heredity in animals. Early modern breeders, like the natural
historians of the time, deemed that likeness was as much determined by uniformity of
environmental as ancestral influence, Roger J. Wood quoting an eighteenth century
Englishman’s assertion that “Every soil has its own stock” as being typical of his time.
Breeders moreover considered fluctuations in external conditions to possess the power to
knock generation off course, so control over them was considered as vital for producing good
stock as selective breeding.28 The two factors which led to a decreased emphasis on
environmental maintenance and a greater focus on the role of physiological factors in the
process of heredity were mobilisation and improved breeding techniques. Mobilisation, as
Müller-Wille and Rheinberger rightly emphasise, was a necessary precondition in order to
25
Ibid., pp. 214-5
Ernst Mayr, The Growth of Biological Thought: Diversity, Evolution and Inheritance, The Belknap Press of
Harvard University Press, 1982, pp. 725
27
Marc J. Ratcliff, ‘Duchesne’s Strawberries: Between Growers’ Practices and Academic Knowledge’, Heredity
Produced: At the Crossroads of Biology, Politics, and Culture, 1500-1870, Staffan Müller-Wille & Hans-Jörg
Rheinberger (eds.), The MIT Press, 2007, pp. 209-10
28
Roger J. Wood, ‘The Sheep Breeders’ View of Heredity Before and After 1800’, Heredity Produced: At the
Crossroads of Biology, Politics, and Culture, 1500-1870, Staffan Müller-Wille & Hans-Jörg Rheinberger (eds.),
The MIT Press, 2007, pp. 229-30
26
~ Page 8 ~
distinguish between inherited and environmentally induced traits in organisms, as only when
the ties between soil and stock were broken would patterns of heredity incongruous with
existing beliefs reveal themselves.29 Wood identifies the successful establishment in the
1720s of merinos, native to Spain, in the apparently hostile climes of Sweden as a key tipping
point towards a ‘harder’ view of heredity amongst sheep breeders, as the success of such
dramatic transportations and the continued quality of the ‘displaced’ breeds convinced
influential members of the breeding community that ancestral influence outweighed the
environment’s in determining likeness of progeny. Novel breeding techniques played a key
role in the success of breed displacement, for example the use of ‘grading’, the gradual
infusion of foreign blood into local stock over a number of generations, to produce the
Swedish merino. These techniques, however, came to take on a life of their own with
improvements in selection methods. These improvements were tied, like those of
mobilisation, to the opening up of agriculture to global mercantilism and the increased and
international networking of practitioners, which allowed them to choose from a much larger
pool of variation than would otherwise have been possible. This combined with the
development of ‘population thinking’ and more systematic management allowed skilled
breeders such as Robert Bakewell to impose artifice upon nature to a degree not seen before,
resulting in breeds that maximised commercially desirable traits whilst minimising those
detrimental to sale value.30 Breeders thus sought to impose the new capitalist order on nature
by removing inefficiencies and increasing production, this being the very opposite of the goal
of Linnaeus, that of, through collection and the reduction of variety, restoring to nature “the
order of paradise”.31
Artificial selection was not, however, unhindered in its power. As much as they tried to
maintain the constancy of their stocks through inbreeding, breeders found themselves unable
to prevent the occasional production of ‘degenerative’ offspring in which the achievements of
selection appeared to be reversed. This phenomenon was variously dubbed ‘reversion’ or
‘atavism’, and it was regarded, de Vries would later observe, as “the greatest enemy of the
Staffan Müller-Wille & Hans-Jörg Rheinberger, ‘Heredity – The Formation of an Epistemic Space’, Heredity
Produced: At the Crossroads of Biology, Politics, and Culture, 1500-1870, Staffan Müller-Wille & Hans-Jörg
Rheinberger (eds.), The MIT Press, 2007, pp. 17-8
30
Roger J. Wood, ‘The Sheep Breeders’ View of Heredity Before and After 1800’, Heredity Produced: At the
Crossroads of Biology, Politics, and Culture, 1500-1870, Staffan Müller-Wille & Hans-Jörg Rheinberger (eds.),
The MIT Press, 2007, pp. 231-8
31
Staffan Müller-Wille, ‘Gardens of Paradise’, Endeavour, Vol. 25, No. 2, 2001, pp. 49
29
~ Page 9 ~
breeder, and… a definite force”.32 The source of this mysterious power was regarded as lying
within the distant ancestry of the degenerate individual, this judgement being based on the
fact that their traits resembled more closely those of older breeds or their wild counterparts
more than those of their parents. It was the latter resemblance to wild organisms known or
believed to be the non-selected descendants of the ancestral populations from which
domesticated animals and plants were derived that arguably birthed the wild-type concept, in
that the atavist was asserted to have ‘reverted to the wild type’. Such a concept, as previously
stated, could not have come about without a ‘hardening’ of the idea of heredity that
discounted a one-to-one relationship between environment and form. The discovery of
atavism in domestic animals further troubled lingering Aristotelian ideas of heredity as it
further demonstrated the lack of parallelism between difference in environment and
difference in variety. Breeders consequently stopped attributing such setbacks to
environmental influences, whose power was now doubted, and instead tended, like all good
craftspersons, to blame their application of method. Reversion was thus usually attributed to a
failure to maintain pedigree, the presence of “foreign blood” being the causal factor, either
reintroducing or reactivating ancestral traits. This could not, however, always be appealed to,
as ‘wild type’ individuals did on occasion appear in stocks believed ‘pure’, which led to the
belief that more remote ancestors must be responsible. Darwin, for example, believed
inbreeding was required for up to twenty generations to foreclose the possibility of reversion
within a breed.33 Even breeds which had become ‘fixed’, however, required continuous
inbreeding to prevent degeneration.34 Because of this stress on generational distance as the
measure of vulnerability to atavism, the breeders’ wild-type concept was a highly
genealogical one and one, moreover, which tended to stress a proportional view of ancestral
influence, with increasing generations of pure-bred individuals being necessary to expunge
the deleterious influence of their forebears.35 It furthermore served a comparative purpose for
measuring progress in that it established a start point, the wild or ordinary domestic organism,
from which the breeder would seek to deviate from towards their own ideal organism.
Progress, however, was never considered permanent, as atavism was interpreted to act as a
32
Hugo de Vries, Species and Varieties: Their Origin by Mutation, Daniel Trembly MacDougal (ed.), The Open
Court Publishing Company, 1905, pp. 185
33
Charles Darwin, On the Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection, or the Preservation of Favoured
Races in the Struggle for Life, Penguin Classics, 2009, pp. 32-3
34
Roger J. Wood, ‘The Sheep Breeders’ View of Heredity Before and After 1800’, Heredity Produced: At the
Crossroads of Biology, Politics, and Culture, 1500-1870, Staffan Müller-Wille & Hans-Jörg Rheinberger (eds.),
The MIT Press, 2007, pp. 239
35
Ibid. pp. 231 & 237 – see comments on ‘grading’ and ‘blood’
~ Page 10 ~
counterweight to the breeder’s efforts that would pull a stock back towards wild-type if not
vigilantly resisted.
Hybridisation experiments, as we have already seen, played a major methodological role in
the work of both natural historians and breeders. They, however, like all forms of
experimentation, had a life of their own independent of their being requisitioned by these two
disparate groups,36 and it was through their capacity to produce peculiar results, such as
reversion, which drove the gradual move in studies of heredity from biometrical methods to
Mendelian crossing techniques.37 Mendel’s own experiments are, of course, a classic example
of using hybridisation to explore inheritance, and may be interpreted as essentially an in
depth examination of atavistic phenomena. Mendel himself viewed his work as exploring the
role that hybridisation might play in producing variation, not directly focusing on reversion,
but he nonetheless played a vital role in establishing that reversion was not the effect of a
mysterious force but rather one explained in terms of simple dominance and recession of
character pairs.38 This combined with his doctrine of gametic purity acted to limit ancestral
influence to the parental generation. This demystification of atavism not only, as Robert Olby
concurs, rendered it, as ‘traditionally understood’, impossible but also provided what in many
ways was a superior means of analysing inheritance in that it lacked the loophole to which
generationally proportional accounts could make ad hoc appeals to in cases of unpredicted
variation, namely that of the influence of very distant generations.39 The hybridisation
experiments of Mendel and others had, by demonstrating discontinuity, a further effect of
encouraging the move from a belief in inheritance as a statistically analysable magnitude to
one of inheritance as structured and composed of units. This idea of heredity as structured
furthermore lay behind a shift away from ideas of it as a vaguely defined force and towards
particulate theories, which were accompanied by cytological searches for these units’
material foundation.40 All these developments contributed to a further ‘hardening’ of ideas of
inheritance and a corresponding downplaying of the role of the environment. Wild-type,
36
Ian Hacking, Representing and Intervening: Introductory Topics in the Philosophy of Natural Science,
Cambridge University Press, 1983, pp. 150
37
Elof Axel Carlson, The Gene: A Critical History, W.B. Saunders Company, 1966, pp. 3-5
38
Daniel L. Hartl & Vitezslav Orel, ‘What Did Gregor Mendel Think He Discovered?’, Genetics, Vol. 131,
1992, pp. 247
39
Robert Olby, ‘The Dimensions of Scientific Controversy: The Biometric-Mendelian Debate’, The British
Journal for the History of Science, Vol. 22, No. 3, Genetics, Eugenics and Evolution: A Special Issue in
Commemoration of Bernard Norton (1945-1984) 1989, pp. 316-7
40
Jean Gayon, ‘The Philosophical History of the Concept of Heredity’, The Concept of the Gene in
Development and Evolution, Peter J. Beurton, Raphael Falk & Hans-Jörg Rheinberger (eds.), Cambridge
University Press, 2000, pp. 77-8
~ Page 11 ~
meanwhile, was firmly disconnected from ‘wildness’ with the realisation that reversion to the
wild-type was usually explained by simple dominance, not occult forces working against the
breeder, and could subsequently be ‘produced’ with the appropriate domestic parents by the
same mechanism as its production in the wild.
Despite this apparent redundancy, wild-type remained in broad use amongst breeders and was
brought into the terminology of the new discipline of genetics. Part of the reason for its
retention was arguably due to the continued influence of generationally proportional
interpretations of ancestral influence, in part due to doubts as to the universality of gametic
purity amongst some of the early Mendelians.41 A belief in the power of reversion was thus
not eliminated, and the original breeders’ concept of wild-type for a time maintained some
reality as a conceptual category among certain geneticists. This may explain its entry into
genetics and initial survival, but does not explain its rise to prominence and increased vigour,
particularly as tolerance of doubts about gametic purity dramatically decreased in the same
period as wild-type’s institutionalisation in the terminology of genetics.42 What is evident,
therefore, is that wild-type as a concept required a transformation in order to survive in
genetics, and that this change acted to sever its relationship with the ‘traditional’
interpretation of atavism on which it had previously been dependent. Detecting where and
when this transformation occurred requires a close analysis of the conceptualisation of wildtype among early geneticists. What must, however, also be thoroughly investigated is to what
degree this transformation was complete and whether any traces of old ideas about wild-type
were retained in the conception of it inherited by modern genetics, as this may explain the
origin of the ambiguous components and contradictory interpretations that have plagued it.
WILLIAM BATESON
Whilst not among the original three ‘rediscoverers’ of Mendelism, William Bateson is
arguably one of the most important of the ‘early Mendelians’ in that it was his ideas and
language which for the first decade of the twentieth century arguably defined the orthodox
interpretation of genetics in Britain, America and much of Europe. It was his war of words
with the British biometricians which helped carve a legitimate niche for Mendelism in a
space formerly dominated by Galtonism, it was he who gave ’genetics’ its name and who
Robert Olby, ‘The Dimensions of Scientific Controversy: The Biometric-Mendelian Debate’, The British
Journal for the History of Science, Vol. 22, No. 3, Genetics, Eugenics and Evolution: A Special Issue in
Commemoration of Bernard Norton (1945-1984) 1989, pp. 316-7
42
Elof Axel Carlson, The Gene: A Critical History, W.B. Saunders Company, 1966, pp. 36-8
41
~ Page 12 ~
introduced many of the now ubiquitous terminology used in the discipline, including ‘allele’
and the paired terms ‘homozygous’ and ‘heterozygous’.43 In studying the wild-type concept,
his views should therefore be given prior consideration due to their likely influence.
Bateson entered genetics with some very definite ideas concerning intra- and interspecific
variation, but was to an extent forced to revise some of his earlier opinions once the
evidential base of the discipline began growing. He had already been interested in
discontinuous variation prior to the rediscovery of Mendel’s laws, in 1894 publishing a
volume, Materials for the Study of Variation, in which he compiled various evidence from
the animal and plant world for the preponderance of discontinuity as opposed to continuity
among living things. In introducing this evidence, he asserts that “The forms of living things
are diverse. They may nevertheless be separated into Specific Groups or Species, the
members of each such group being nearly alike, while they are less like the members of any
other Specific Group”. Between some specific groups, he admits, there are known to be
intermediate forms, but these are rare and in the “immense majority” of species, in which no
transitional forms exist, there are differences which may be deemed “Specific”, i.e.
distinctive. These ‘specific differences’ “are indefinite and hence not capable of definition”,
but nevertheless act to render the forms of living things as discontinuous, and their existence
thus represents “no merely subjective conception, but an objective, tangible fact”.44 Species
for Bateson are thus discontinuous, which leads him to ask whether it might not also be
possible that “the Variation by which Species are produced be discontinuous too”. Bateson
does not dismiss the fact of continuous variation but asserts that it is likely a process distinct
from discontinuous variation operating according to different rules.45 He moreover does not
believe continuous variation to be an important agent of evolutionary change because he
considers the general discontinuity of species to be best explained if discontinuous change
has been responsible for speciation.46 He is further persuaded that evolution is saltational by
the fact of the existence of discontinuous variations that produce new forms “from their first
beginning more or less of the kind of perfection that we associate with normality”, i.e. that
43
Elof Axel Carlson, The Gene: A Critical History, W.B. Saunders Company, 1966, pp. 9-16
William Bateson, Materials for the Study of Variation treated with Especial Regard for to Discontinuity in the
Origin of Species, Macmillan and Co., 1894, pp. 2
45
Ibid., pp. 18
46
Ibid., pp. 567
44
~ Page 13 ~
these variations appear to constitute a new norm and not merely be pathological derivations
of the parent-type.47
Bateson thus entered the new world of genetics with a pre-existing belief in the importance of
discontinuous variation as a source of evolutionary change and a concept of species that
emphasised that each possesses its own distinguishing marks and a separate norm of
‘sickness and health’. What emerged from the experimental results garnered by early genetic
studies was that this norm did not possess a standard form in all species. Notable is Bateson’s
clear astonishment that the wild-type of the sweet pea (blue flower, erect standard) is
heterozygous, that it “does not breed true, but continues to throw off the other two types”
(these other types being blue flower, hooded standard, and red flower, erect standard).48
Similarly, regarding Doncaster’s research on the moth Abraxas grossidariata, which
appeared to show that all wild-type females were heterozygous, possessing the recessive
lacticolor allele, he comments “In all the discussions of the stability and fitness of species
who ever contemplated the possibility of a wild species having one of its sexes permanently
hybrid?”.49 Bateson was subsequently forced by this evidence to revise some initial
assumptions, such as his intuition that homozygotes would generally be dominant in number
within species. These violations of expectation appears to have led him towards a greater
overall openness to unexpected results in genetics, which he even came to see as valuable,
maintaining “Treasure your exceptions!... Keep them always uncovered and in sight.
Exceptions are like the rough brickwork of a growing building which tells that there is more
to come and shows where the next construction is to be”.50 He moreover came to discourage
the making of generalising assumptions based on the limited evidence so far obtained,
asserting that “The results of genetic research are so bewilderingly novel that we need time
and an exhaustive study of their inter-relations before we can hope to see them in proper
value and perspective”.51 He furthermore stressed the need for further investigation since “As
yet the genetic behaviour of animals and plants has only been sampled”, that the work of
geneticists had yet to be “done on a scale so large as to provide generalisations”.52 On this
evidence, it could perhaps be argued that Bateson had come to have an instrumentalist
47
Ibid., pp. 568
William Bateson, ‘Facts Limiting the Theory of Heredity’, Science, New Series, Vol. 26, No. 672, 1907, pp.
655
49
William Bateson, The Methods and Scope of Genetics, Cambridge University Press, 1908, pp. 46-7
50
Ibid., pp. 22
51
Ibid., pp. 46
52
William Bateson, Problems of Genetics, Yale University Press, 1913, pp. 250
48
~ Page 14 ~
attitude towards the concepts utilised in early genetics as he recognised that much of the
conceptual framework of the discipline was merely provisional, and that anomalous results
possessed value in pointing to where that framework required alteration or further
development. Bateson’s hesitancy to generalise from limited proofs is also likely a symptom
of schooling in the sceptical empiricist methodologies that prevailed in much of biology at
the turn of the twentieth century.53
That Bateson preferred that geneticists adopt an open-minded and evidence-based approach
to their work as opposed to resorting to abstract theorisations did not, of course, preclude him
from committing to, or at least favouring, certain particular theories regarding the nature of
intra- and interspecific variation in wild populations. Famously, he championed as an
alternative to Mendel’s system of dominant and recessive factors a model which proposed
that ‘dominant’ alleles be instead regarded as ‘present’ and ‘recessive’ alleles as ‘absent’.54
This different model may well have been inspired by the physician Archibald Garrod’s study
of ‘chemical sports’ in humans, especially his demonstration that the cause of the disease
alkaptonuria is the absence of an enzyme that decomposes a specific amino acid, and
furthermore that this is a recessive hereditary condition.55 Bateson did not, unlike his student
Wheldale, ever seriously entertain the notion that enzymes might be the actual biochemical
units of heredity,56 stating that “It is scarcely necessary to emphasise the fact that the ferment
itself must not be declared to be the factor or thing transmitted, but rather, the power to
produce that ferment, or ferment-like body”.57 He did, however, consider it highly likely,
based on the common correlation between presence of factor and effect of enzyme, that “the
operations of some units are in an essential way carried out by the formation of definite
substances acting as ferments”.58 Based on this deduction that the correlation between factor
presence and enzyme effect implied a causal linkage between factor and enzyme, Bateson
then made the apparently logical conclusion that the lack of an enzyme effect where normally
one would occur, as in the case of the alkaptonuric as opposed to the normal healthy human,
implied the absence of the factor producing that enzyme. Regarding hereditary diseases,
Bateson therefore made the following surmises: “If… a disease descends through the affected
Nils Roll-Hansen, ‘Drosophila Genetics: A Reductionist Research Program’, Journal of the History of
Biology, Vol. 11, No. 1, 1978, pp. 159-60
54
Elof Axel Carlson, The Gene: A Critical History, W.B. Saunders Company, 1966, pp. 58-62
55
Ibid., pp. 166-7
56
Robert Olby, The Path to the Double Helix: The Discovery of DNA, Dover Publications Inc., 1994, pp. 133-5
57
William Bateson, Mendel’s Principles of Heredity, Cambridge University Press, 1909, pp. 268
58
William Bateson, Mendel’s Principles of Heredity, Cambridge University Press, 1909, pp. 266
53
~ Page 15 ~
persons, as a dominant, we may feel every confidence that the condition is caused by the
operation of a factor or element added to the usual ingredients of the body. In such cases
there is something present, probably a definite chemical substance, which has the power of
producing the affection… On the contrary, when the disease is recessive we recognize that its
appearance is due to the absence of some ingredient which is present in the normal body”.59
Bateson’s ‘presence and absence’ explanation of allelism may be viewed as related to his preestablished view of species as having norms of sickness and health, in particular because it is
similarly represented as a duality. However, as should be ascertained from his above remarks,
Bateson considers the relationship between presence and absence and sickness and health as
essentially contingent on norms. Presence is not always healthy and absence is not always
detrimental, as is illustrated by the case of dominant hereditary diseases. What is pertinent is
whether a particular factor is present or absent in the ‘normal body’. It is this normative
presence or absence which renders the alternate condition pathological. It is, furthermore,
only in the context of this ‘normal body’ that the pathological condition is ‘sick’. That the
sickness of the pathological condition is contextual for Bateson must be emphasised against
the claim that his belief in the existence of species normativity is evidence of ‘typological’
thinking, i.e. that deviation from the norm of health is somehow a deviation from essence. As
Bateson had previously elaborated, he believed disease to be a state discontinuous from
health that varied around its own norm, so in this sense it is not so much a deviation from the
‘normal body’ as a departure altogether. He moreover felt there to be a parallel between
disease and variation in that each represents a ‘disturbance’ to the system of an organised
being (the ‘normal body’), and that consequently the study of the problem of species may be
viewed as a study of pathology, endorsing Virchow’s assertion that “every deviation from the
type of the parent animal must have its foundation on a pathological accident”.60 What this
implies is that, for Bateson, evolutionary variation is by its very nature a violation of the
species norm of the parent-type, but that such novel varieties are not ‘sick’ in any objective
sense for they possess their own norm of variation and are not subject to that of their parents’.
This indicates that for Bateson wild-type is only typical, and mutants aberrant, according to
its own norm; mutants have their own independent norms and, outside of the context of the
wild-type, cannot be said to be pathological.
William Bateson, Mendel’s Principles of Heredity, Cambridge University Press, 1909, pp. 232
William Bateson, Materials for the Study of Variation treated with Especial Regard for to Discontinuity in the
Origin of Species, Macmillan and Co., 1894, pp. 74
59
60
~ Page 16 ~
Bateson’s conception of evolution can be summarised as consisting in the founding, through
discontinuous variation, of new norms, not new types. It must further be emphasised that
Bateson believes that whilst the typical characteristics associated with the norm are “fixed in
so far as they are adapted to environmental exigency”, both their degree of variation and
variability are ‘sporadic’ in nature,61 being randomly determined products of “the internal
constitution of organisms”.62 The ‘normal type’ of a species must neither be viewed as a
product of an underlying static ‘essence’, as he regards variation and variability as in no true
sense physiologically canalised, nor determined by environmental factors, these external
forces being instead constraints of viability limiting expression. Bateson moreover does not
consider these constraints as especially restricting since he does not think of natural selection
as an omnipotent, omnipresent force destroying all but the supremely adapted. He similarly
expresses doubts regarding the alleged power of artificial selection, stating that “the belief in
origin [of domestic varieties] within the period of human civilization from one simple
primitive wild type seems on a balance of probabilities insecurely founded”, proposing it
more likely that domestic breeds have multiple origins and also that “Elements… have come
in since their captivity began”.63 The norm-environment relationship is overall for Bateson an
indirect and relatively unimportant one when considering the nature of variation.
Furthermore, species norms themselves do not constitute the true units of nature as species,
Bateson believes, are mere aggregates of individuals64 whose shared or distinguishing
features are ultimately “arbitrary and capricious”.65 Bateson might thus be considered a
species anti-realist, an attitude further evidenced by his observations regarding local
differentiation: “When the two forms are found co-existing in the same area they are usually
recorded as one species if intergrades are observed, and as two species if the intergrades are
absent. On the other hand when two forms are found occupying separate areas, when, that is,
the process of replacement is completed in one of the areas, then forthwith each is named
separately either as species or subspecies”.66
Bateson on the above evidence had an idea of wild-type as in a sense existing in that there is
a normal range of variation in wild populations, but as he considered variation and variability
61
William Bateson, Problems of Genetics, Yale University Press, 1913, pp. 131
Ibid., pp. 30
63
Ibid., pp. 90
64
Ibid., pp. 131
65
Ibid., pp. 24
66
Ibid., pp. 146
62
~ Page 17 ~
as essentially arbitrary and shifting facts of physiology, this ‘normal type’ too was likely
viewed by him as kinetic and changeable. In this manner, he is actually very close to Darwin
in his view of wild-type. This may not be obvious given Bateson’s very visible criticism of
some aspects of contemporary evolutionary theory, criticisms which are moreover associated
with the later claim that Bateson was an anti-Darwinian, a view which R.A. Fisher, Julian
Huxley and Ernst Mayr in particular have been accredited with promulgating.67 That this
ascription is erroneous is demonstrated by closer inspection of the actual major targets of
Bateson’s critique. As has been argued by Erik Peterson, Bateson primarily agitated against
not Darwin or Darwinism in general, but rather a particular school of evolutionary theory,
that of the pan-selectionists. This interpretation of Darwinism was associated with Weismann
and Wallace and held natural selection to be an omnipresent force in nature with power over
all organismic traits, with the consequence that all evolution is directed by selection and all
traits are to be viewed as owing their existence to their utility.68 Bateson contrarily believed
that “The scope of Natural Selection is closely limited by the laws of variation”, and
considered the pan-selectionists to have invested the principle of selection with “supernatural
attributes” which it in fact lacks.69 Attacking the proposition that all evolutionary change is
selection driven, he instead sought to show that interspecific differences between close
phylogenetic relatives are often constituted by trivial traits that represent no selective
advantage or disadvantage. He gives the example of the sparrows Passer domesticus (house
sparrow) and montanus (tree sparrow), which differ only in small distinctions in colourmarkings and in secondary sexual characteristics (domesticus is dimorphic, montanus is
monomorphic). Regarding the latter differentiation, Bateson feels that “we can form no
surmise as to any economic reason why the one species should be differentiated in the one
way and the other in the other way, and I believe it is mere self-deception which suggests the
hope that with fuller knowledge reasons of this nature would be discovered”.70 There is, in
other words, no clear evidence such minor differentiations are moderated by selection, and in
the absence of such proof their origination may just as well be assumed an arbitrary product
of non-directed variation. Bateson also targeted what he viewed as the unjustified attribution
by pan-selectionists of the necessity of particular traits for a species’ survival. In particular,
he observes that such attributions tend to be reserved for non-varying traits, a tendency he
Erik L. Peterson, ‘William Bateson from "Balanoglossus" to "Materials for the Study of Heredity": The
Transatlantic Roots of Discontinuity and the (Un)naturalness of Selection’, Journal of the History of Biology,
Vol. 41, No. 2, 2008, pp. 294-8
68
Ibid., pp. 291-2
69
William Bateson, Mendel’s Principles of Heredity, Cambridge University Press, 1909, pp. 289
70
William Bateson, Problems of Genetics, Yale University Press, 1913, pp. 22-3
67
~ Page 18 ~
critiques on the basis that such designations of essentiality are entirely contingent on human
knowledge of a trait. Invisible or unencountered variation in a trait may exist, but, in
ignorance of this, essentiality may be attributed in the belief that the species is uniform for
this characteristic.71 These claims regarding intraspecific variation are clearly related to
Bateson’s species anti-realism, in particular his assertions regarding the presence or absence
of intermediate forms as crucial in determining in how species and subspecies status are
attributed. Bateson’s views regarding both inter- and intraspecific variation are also evidently
mediated by his empiricist scepticism of theoretical extrapolations, which is additionally a
further source for his contempt of the often weakly grounded claims of the pan-selectionists.
Bateson on this interpretation is no anti-Darwinian; he is instead a critic of those theoretical
biologists who make what he perceives to be evidentially unjustified claims as to the power
and prevalence of natural selection. Bateson was in this respect not unusual, as within the
scientific community of his time there were many detractors of pan-selectionism, including
among their number fairly conservative Darwinists such as Bateson’s famed adversary the
biometrician Weldon.72 By contrast, the later scientific community which Fisher, Huxley and
Mayr were part of was one in which pan-selectionist ideas had become mainstream. These
biologists all considered themselves Darwinists and, reflecting on their differences with
Bateson and his contemporaries, saw him as not fitting into their idea of Darwinism and
therefore conceived that he must be an antagonist. They perhaps did not consider that the
norms of schools of thought, like those of variation within species, are kinetic, that the
‘normal’ Darwinian of c. 1950 was evolutionarily divergent from its c. 1900 ‘normal’
ancestor. The degree of this divergence is commented on by Stephen Jay Gould in his
analysis of the celebratory symposiums of 1909 and 1959, which marked the centennial
anniversaries of Darwin’s birth and the Origin’s publication respectively. He observes that
these festivities occurred at “maximally disparate moments in the history of evolutionary
theory”, 1909 being “the heyday of doubt about natural selection as a potent mechanism”,
1959 “the apotheosis of certainty about the nearly exclusive power of selection as an agent of
evolutionary change”.73 Whilst Bateson would not have fitted into the fold of mid-twentieth
century Darwinism, he was quite comfortably within the fringes of the Darwinism of fifty
71
Ibid., pp. 130
Erik L. Peterson, ‘William Bateson from "Balanoglossus" to "Materials for the Study of Heredity": The
Transatlantic Roots of Discontinuity and the (Un)naturalness of Selection, Journal of the History of Biology,
Vol. 41, No. 2, 2008, pp. 292
73
Stephen Jay Gould, The Structure of Evolutionary Theory, The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press,
2002, pp. 566
72
~ Page 19 ~
years before. Yes, he was certainly not a modal Darwinian, but neither were pan-selectionists
such as Wallace, and to call Bateson an anti-Darwinian because he was not a 1959 Darwinian
is anachronistic. It is furthermore an unfair evaluation because Bateson himself professes to
believe that “By the arbitrament of Natural Selection all must succeed or fail”, that nothing in
Mendelism runs counter to this “cardinal doctrine”, instead only acting to correct the “abuses
of the principle” commit by Wallace and Weismann, abuses that after all, Bateson believes,
were only made possible by Darwin’s lack of understanding of the nature of heredity.74
Having established that he was not in any historical sense an anti-Darwinian, it should be
noted that Bateson’s real bone of contention with Darwin was not in fact natural selection,
but rather the latter’s overwhelming emphasis on gradual and continuous variation as the
major evolutionary source for speciation. Bateson in contrast favoured sudden and
discontinuous variation, which he felt better explained taxonomic discontinuity than
Darwin’s claim that the absence of intermediates was explained by their extinction.
Moreover, because he believed the norms of individual species to be independent he did not
condone the idea that species norms might vary into one another, and this is the basis for his
criticism of the treatment of species by some evolutionists as “a mere figment of the human
mind”.75 Bateson contends that there is “striking and inscrutable” evidence of the relative
fixity of species,76 and believes genetics, by studying these discontinuous variations, will
allow science to determine “whether specific difference is or is not a physiological reality”.77
Such statements have been interpreted as implying typological thinking, but as we have seen
claims such as Mayr’s that “Bateson did not think in terms of populations but in terms of
discrete types” hold no water given Bateson’s own insistence that individuals are the true
units of nature.78 The erroneous interpretation that Bateson has a typological conception of
species has its source in the failure to recognise that when he speaks of species fixity he is
referring to the constancy of discontinuity between species, not the adherence to type within.
Bateson recognises the significance of intraspecific variation and that species norms can
change with time. Bateson believed, in other words, in the possibility of minor evolution
within lineages through continuous variation, but not in speciation without saltation, as it
requires discontinuity to establish an independent species norm. This norm is not in any sense
William Bateson, Mendel’s Principles of Heredity, Cambridge University Press, 1909, pp. 289
Ibid., pp. 21
76
Ibid., pp. 16
77
William Bateson, Problems of Genetics, Yale University Press, 1913, pp. 130
78
Ernst Mayr, The Growth of Biological Thought: Diversity, Evolution and Inheritance, The Belknap Press of
Harvard University Press, 1982, pp. 545
74
75
~ Page 20 ~
an essence as the relationship of individuals to the norm changes with time as it is a moving
mean the position of which is dependent on the composition of the population as a whole.
The distinctiveness of a species as a phenotypic cluster in morphological space is thus only a
present phenomenon; if the dimension of time is added, the species will be shown to over its
lifetime shift in character to such an extent that no ‘type’ is visible. Finally, it must be
stressed that Bateson considers many of the characteristics that compose a species norm to
essentially be arbitrary products of physiology, not dictated from without by natural selection
or from within by an essence. Individuals, as the true units of nature, share differently these
‘normal’ characters, are ‘normal’ only in terms of present trends which may in future change
and are contingent in their membership of their species on the chance events of their
evolutionary past.
HUGO DE VRIES
Though he was one of the original rediscoverers of Mendel, Hugo de Vries and his followers
came to in many ways represent a biological school distinct from the work of the other early
Mendelians. Whilst aspects of his theory of mutation became popular among many early
geneticists, indeed would come to be fully integrated into mainstream genetics, his
unorthodox ideas regarding the nature of species and of wild-type greatly differentiated de
Vries from others in his field.
Regarding species, de Vries claims that most of the species recognised by systematists, what
he dubs ‘systematic species’, are in truth compound entities, each being “not a really existing
form, but [an] abstraction of the common type of all [its members], just as it is in the case of a
genus or of a family”.79 The “real units” existent in nature are what he calls ‘elementary
species’. Because in the wild “The mixed condition is the rule, purity is the exception”,80
elementary species “can only in rare cases be determined on the sole ground of fieldobservations”, but they are renderable as distinct through pedigree-culture.81 Amongst these
elementary species “there is no real type; no one of them predominates because all are
considered to be equal in rank”.82 Consequently, each may be regarded as representing its
own legitimate ‘type’, though de Vries appears to distinguish between ‘type’ in general and
79
Hugo de Vries, Species and Varieties: Their Origin by Mutation, Daniel Trembly MacDougal (ed.), The Open
Court Publishing Company, 1905, pp. 128
80
Ibid., Species and Varieties, pp. 102
81
Ibid., pp. 12
82
Ibid., pp. 127
~ Page 21 ~
‘wild type’, the latter term only being reserved for those elementary species which are
capable of independently propagating themselves in nature. This distinction is evidenced by
his statements regarding Oenothera lata, one of his famed evening-primrose ‘mutants’, which
he judged due to its need to cross-fertilise with other elementary species to reproduce to be
“unfit to found a wild type”.83
De Vries makes a significant effort to establish a distinction between his elementary species
and what he calls ‘retrograde varieties’.84 He makes this distinction because of “the general
belief, that varieties are distinguished from true species by their repeated reversion”.85 Only
by showing that his elementary species do not revert to type but rather maintain their own
distinct type can he legitimise his claim that they constitute the ‘real units’ of species. His
primary attempt to differentiate the two categories lies in claiming a different kind of origin.
Retrograde varieties are “of a derivative nature”, being distinguished from the ‘normal’ type
by “the disappearance of some superficial character”.86 This ‘lost’ character is central to their
distinct identity as a variety, de Vries asserting that “In nearly every instance, where true
varieties and not elementary species are concerned, a single term expresses the whole
character”.87 Contrarily, elementary species “are distinguished from their nearest allies in
almost all organs”.88 Moreover, their cause of origin is not loss of characters but rather
addition, a process de Vries emphasises as being a progressive form of variation in that new
qualities are attained, as opposed to the case of retrograde varieties which “have only thrown
off some peculiarity, previously acquired by their ancestors”.89 These distinctive external
qualities are the product of the acquisition of novel physiological characters which de Vries
terms ‘unit-characters’.90 It is these unit-characters that form the true biological basis for the
distinction between individual elementary species.91
The chief means of distinguishing elementary species from retrograde varieties is, according
to de Vries, through the study of hybrids, and the means of studying hybrids is Mendelism.
Hugo de Vries, ‘The Origin of Species by Mutation’, Science, New Series, Vol. 15, No. 384, 1902, pp. 727
Hugo de Vries, Species and Varieties: Their Origin by Mutation, Daniel Trembly MacDougal (ed.), The Open
Court Publishing Company, 1905, pp. 14
85
Ibid., pp. 187
86
Ibid., pp. 13-14
87
Ibid., pp. 126
88
Ibid., pp. 124
89
Ibid., pp. 14
90
Ibid., pp. 249
91
Ibid., pp. 307
83
84
~ Page 22 ~
As previously stated, elementary species differ from one another by unit-characters.
Retrograde varieties visibly differ from their parent-type in that one or more morphological
characters disappear, but this disappearance is usually not due to the actual loss of the
physiological unit-character that produces this phenotype but rather due to its being rendered
latent.92 A latent character can, if the retrograde variety is crossed with its parent-type, be
reactivated in the offspring of the cross due to the parent-type’s reintroducing of the active
character unit whose previous loss produced the variety.93 In other words, retrograde varieties
are Mendelian recessives and will if crossed with their dominant-carrying parent-type
produce parent-type offspring in the first generation. More importantly for de Vries, they do
not at any point produce intermediates between parent-type and variety but rather “sport into
one another”. This is to be contrasted with hybrids between elementary species, which de
Vries claims are generally “otherwise constituted” than their parents, being usually
transitional, and consequently “do not give the impression of atavistic reversion”.94 The cause
of this alternative constitution of elementary species hybrids is the mechanism of Mendelian
inheritance. De Vries believes that, whereas “No unpaired qualities occur in normal
offspring”, the unit-characters that differentiate the parents of the elementary species hybrid
will lack allelic pairs. It is this allelic imbalance which de Vries asserts to be the cause of the
numerous defects and peculiarities of elementary species hybrids, notably their common
sterility.95 This symptom is particular to elementary species hybrids and is foreign to ‘varietal
hybrids’. Hybrid infertility is thus maintained by de Vries to be the standard by which to
ultimately judge whether a variety is retrograde or an elementary species.96
It appears, however, that de Vries did not feel hybrid infertility a persuasive enough proof of
his claim of the prevalence of elementary species, believing that many would be persuaded
otherwise in many cases by the large body of evidence for atavism in well-known constant
varieties. The evidence for this claim is that he spends considerable effort rubbishing as
mistaken or unreliable claims of atavism’s being a widespread phenomenon. This is not to
say that he denies the existence of atavism, but he seeks to restrict its range within definite
limits so as not to threaten his claim of the typological distinctness of elementary species. De
Vries begins by casting doubts as to the veracity of claimed cases of atavism. He clarifies that
92
Ibid., pp. 631
Ibid., pp. 307
94
Ibid., pp. 199
95
Ibid., pp. 253-4
96
Ibid., pp. 278
93
~ Page 23 ~
“Atavism or reversion is the falling back to a prototype”, but asks what such a prototype can
be. He identifies two kinds of prototype, the ‘physiologic’ and the ‘systematic’. The former
kind is “a very narrowly restricted one, and includes only those ancestors from which a form
is known to have been derived”. Identifying a physiologic prototype is dependent on accurate
historical records of the circumstances under which a variety sported from its parent-type, but
de Vries maintains that “In most cases we must be content with the testimony, given
somewhat later, and recorded after the new variety has had the opportunity of showing its
greater merits”.97 This lack of historical documentation of the birth of varieties has in de
Vries’ view been a source of erroneous claims of atavism, which leads him to conclude that
“cases of atavism given without recording the circumstances… should always be
disregarded”.98 In the case of reversion to systematic prototypes, de Vries is even more
sceptical that such atavism can be ascertained, as in these cases the evidential basis is wholly
dependent on comparative studies due to a lack of historical records.99
In addition to the paucity of historical records as a cause of mistaken attributions of atavism,
de Vries, identifies a further factor, one he names ‘vicinism’. Vicinism is defined by de Vries
as indicating the effect of a variety crossing with its neighbours, especially when such
crossing is subliminal.100 Lack of proper historical documentation and thorough observation
is one manner in which such hidden hybridisations can occur. De Vries, however, also warns
that “a hybrid may easily be taken for a specimen of the pure race” and that if such a plant’s
seeds be sown without entertaining the possibility that the parent may be a hybrid, “you will
be astonished at finding among its progeny some of a wholly different type… you may think
that you are assisting at the origination of a new variety”. Familiarity with vicinism will
prevent such an inference, but de Vries asserts that, as this principle was formerly “unknown
and not even guessed at, it is evident that many mistakes must have been made”.101 He
concludes by establishing that the phenomenon called atavism “by gardeners” does exist and
that “It must be conceded to be a fact, that varieties as a rule revert to their species under the
ordinary circumstances of commercial culture”, but objects to the explanation that this
97
Ibid., pp. 170-1
Ibid., pp. 175
99
Ibid., pp. 171-2
100
Ibid., pp. 192
101
Ibid., pp. 214
98
~ Page 24 ~
phenomenon is an instance of inconstancy of type, alternatively maintaining that “nearly all
these ordinary reversions are due to crosses”, being ‘vicinists’ not atavists.102
That it is vital for de Vries to successfully show that atavism is only applicable to retrograde
varieties, not his precious elementary species, is because one of his prime arguments for the
existence of such elementary species is constancy in a pedigree-culture. As he himself
observes “If the breeders' atavism is due to crosses, and only to this cause, it has no bearing at
all on the question of the constancy of varieties. And the general belief, that varieties are
distinguished from true species by their repeated reversion and even that such reversibility is
the real distinction of a variety, would not hold”.103 By showing that elementary species do
not revert and are constant, de Vries can shore up his argument that such constant varieties,
not systematic species, are the ‘real units’ of nature. The constancy of these ‘real units’ is
correctly identified by Morgan as the most important aspect of de Vries’ theory of variation
and is to be contrasted with the Darwinian belief that variation is wholly continuous and does
not have true and stable units.104 De Vries goes to considerable ends to show that many
elementary species are not only constant in a pedigree-culture but moreover have been
constant throughout their life-history, as opposed to continually fluctuating as Darwinism
would suggest. He not only appeals to “our daily experience of the constancy of species”,105
but also cites archaeological and palaeontological evidence, for example the fact that the
plants used in funeral wreaths found in the tombs of ancient pharaohs are “still [the same]
now cultivated in Egypt”, and that the phanerogamic plants of the Miocene are “strikingly”
similar to their present day descendants. He considers these findings to be evidence that
species can exist as constant entities for longer than whole geological eras.106
De Vries’ insistence on constancy in species is bound up with his adoption of a particular
conception of the nature of species, namely the view, which he attributes to Gillot, that “Each
species is an individual… having a birth, a lease of life, and an inevitable death. From the
moment of birth until the time of death, it remains the same”.107 Species have not, in other
words, “slowly changed into new types” as Darwin believed, but have rather been born
102
Ibid., pp. 198-9
Ibid., pp. 187
104
Thomas Hunt Morgan, Evolution and Adaptation, The Macmillan Company, 1903, pp. 297-8
105
Hugo de Vries, ‘The Origin of Species by Mutation’, Science, New Series, Vol. 15, No. 384, 1902, pp. 725
106
Hugo de Vries, Species and Varieties: Their Origin by Mutation, Daniel Trembly MacDougal (ed.), The
Open Court Publishing Company, 1905, pp. 698-9
107
Hugo de Vries, ‘The Origin of Species by Mutation’, Science, New Series, Vol. 15, No. 384, 1902, pp. 725
103
~ Page 25 ~
suddenly from their parent-species as distinct species in themselves; the parent-type
meanwhile “remains unchanged throughout this process, and may repeatedly give birth to
new forms”.108 The process by which this occurs is what de Vries calls mutation. Mutations
are single, relatively large variations “of very rare occurrence”, which can “be considered as
sudden and definite steps”. Mutations are to be contrasted with fluctuation, also known as
‘individual variability’, which is that form of variation present within a species that
differentiates individuals.109 Fluctuation, unlike mutation, can only act linearly, “amplifying
or lessening the existing qualities, but not really changing their nature” – it does not, in other
words, produce anything new, but rather oscillates around an average, an average to which it
regresses if removed from and cannot ultimately be freed from. This is in contrast to the
products of mutation which “are seen to be quite free from their ancestors, and not linked to
them by intermediates”.110 Mutations do not oscillate around a mean – “There is no mean for
them to be grouped around and the extreme only is to be seen, and it is wholly unconnected
with the original type”.111 Mutations thus represent not deviations from the parent-type but
rather the establishment of new types which have their own norms of variation independent
of those of their progenitor.
The mechanism of mutation operates through the unit-characters responsible for the heredity
of type (differential heredity amongst individuals is caused by fluctuation; de Vries assumes
all members of a type share the same unit-characters). Mutation is the act of change in the
unit-characters. De Vries identifies three kinds of change which come under the banner of
mutation: progressive, which is constituted by the acquisition of a novel unit-character,
retrogressive, wherein an existing unit-character becomes latent, and degressive, in which a
latent unit-character reactivates.112 It is only progressive mutations which de Vries associates
with the production of new elementary species, retrograde varieties being resultant from
retrogressive mutations. The latter are often unable to permanently establish themselves as
independent types due to their vulnerability to reversion through crossing. That said, de Vries
does consider retrogressive mutations to have a place in evolution, not least because their
vulnerability to atavism is balanced out by their being far more common than progressive
mutations, stating that “Progression and regression are seen to go hand in hand everywhere.
108
Hugo de Vries, Species and Varieties: Their Origin by Mutation, Daniel Trembly MacDougal (ed.), The
Open Court Publishing Company, 1905, pp. vii
109
Ibid., pp. 190-1
110
Ibid., pp. 18
111
Ibid., pp. 569
112
Ibid., pp. 223
~ Page 26 ~
No large group and probably even no genus or large species has been evolved without the
joint agency of these two great principles”.113
De Vries recognises that, by introducing the transformative factor of mutation, he appears to
bring in an element contradictory to the evidence he has already cited for the constancy of
species. He believes he has solved this problem through the idea that mutability is not a
permanent condition but is rather a periodic one, “producing at times new qualities, and at
other times leaving the [species] unchanged during long successions of generations”, with
each mutable state being preceded and succeeded by one of immutability. He believes that
mutability, like unit-characters, has the capacity to be in states of activity and latency, being a
power of development remaining dormant through periods of constancy.114 He further
hypothesises that in such active periods mutations may occur in cascades, as when a
particularly significant and intrinsic mutation occurs such as the acquisition of a new unitcharacter, it sets off a chain reaction of analogous mutations as a result of its establishing of
novel networks of relationships within the hereditary mechanism.115 De Vries doesn’t answer
as to what causal power might create new unit-characters, but does indicate his belief that,
whilst the capacity for mutability is internal, the actual trigger is an external factor, and that
the discovery of this factor would constitute the true opening up of mutation as a field of
experimental investigation.116 He moreover asserts that whilst searching for mutable species
in nature may yield results more quickly, successfully inducing mutation artificially would be
a research technique of far greater scope, potentially yielding results of far more
importance.117
That de Vries is ultimately more interested in the artificial production of new types as
opposed to the study of existing types in nature and domesticity is widely alluded to in his
writings. He presents himself as pioneering a new form of evolutionary biology: whereas
Lamarck had taken the first step in recognising the origin of species as a natural phenomenon,
and Darwin the second in establishing it as a legitimate object of enquiry, De Vries positions
himself as having opened up evolution as a legitimate object of experimental inquiry.118 Such
experimental enquiry will have little to do with the comparative taxonomy and reliance on
113
Ibid., pp. 704-5
Ibid., pp. 691-3
115
Ibid., pp. 703
116
Ibid., pp. 691
117
Ibid., pp. 688
118
Ibid., pp. v
114
~ Page 27 ~
palaeontology typical of Darwinian evolutionary studies, for de Vries believes the usefulness
of such methods is coming to an end, and that “Any advance in our knowledge depends on
the possibility of seeing species originate. Of course this does not refer to present species.
Such a thing would be as impossible, as absurd, as expecting to witness the birth of an
individual already inhabiting the earth. The species living at present are too old. But they may
give rise to new ones”.119 De Vries may here be contrasted with Bateson, who believed
existing variation to provide sufficient evidence for the study of evolution.120
Due to his focus on artificially producing new types, de Vries does not consider the study of
‘wild types’ especially important. This is compounded, however, by his belief in the essential
non-difference between wild and domestic types and his denial of the power of artificial
selection. He does not deny that that nature and cultivation represent different environments
with different selective pressures, that elementary species which in the wild “have as a rule
but a very short lease of life” due to their being outcompeted may in the experimental garden
be permitted to thrive and mature through human intervention.121 Excluding such intrusions
and particular selective pressures, however, the same general forces of natural selection are at
play in domesticity as they are in the wild.122 Moreover, because it is not selective pressures
which determine mutability, natural selection being “only a sieve” sorting out pre-existing
variety, and “not a… direct cause of improvement”,123 no form of culturing method, contrary
to ‘current belief’, can be an actual cause for the production of improved types as long as it
only alters selection pressures.124 Domestic organisms are overall no more variable than their
wild counterparts, and this leads de Vries to propose that much of the apparent variability in
the former is due to their having multiple wild ancestors.125 He does not deny that new forms
have arisen from time to time in domesticity through mutation as they have in the wild,126 but
ascribes the greater part of what has been considered domestic variation to being due to the
choice of wild elementary species and varieties and their subsequent improvement through
Hugo de Vries, ‘The Origin of Species by Mutation’, Science, New Series, Vol. 15, No. 384, 1902, pp. 728
William Bateson, Materials for the Study of Variation treated with Especial Regard for to Discontinuity in
the Origin of Species, Macmillan and Co., 1894, pp. 6 & 80
121
Hugo de Vries, ‘The Origin of Species by Mutation’, Science, New Series, Vol. 15, No. 384, 1902, pp. 723
122
Hugo de Vries, Species and Varieties: Their Origin by Mutation, Daniel Trembly MacDougal (ed.), The
Open Court Publishing Company, 1905, pp. 803
123
Ibid., pp. 6
124
Ibid., pp. 511
125
Ibid., pp. 65-6
126
Ibid., pp. 90
119
120
~ Page 28 ~
pedigree-culture and appropriate husbandry.127 The latter methods do not change the types
taken from nature, merely purify them and allow them to reach full potential, the innate
capacity for which they fully possessed in the wild. Artificial selection has no power to create
variability; rather “The richness of the [domestic varieties] of the present day was already
present in the large range of original wild elementary species, though unobserved and
requiring improvement”.128 Whilst de Vries clearly hopes that science will uncover the means
to artificially induce mutability, existing methods have, in his view, clearly failed to generate
new variety, only produced the illusion of doing so.
In summary, de Vries’ thoughts on species and variation can be seen as an attempt to
synthesise the Darwinian belief in the power of natural selection with the new theories and
discoveries in the study of heredity of the turn of the twentieth century. As part of doing so,
he rejects the evolutionary significance of gradual continuous variation and the Lamarckian
‘soft inheritance’ upheld by some Darwinians129 in favour of saltationary discontinuous
variation and Weismannist ‘hard inheritance’. This leads him to a belief in the reality of
‘type’ in nature, the unit of which is the elementary species, but also a rejection of there being
a significant difference between domestic and wild types as he does not consider the
domestication process as being able to causally influence variation, which is instead dictated
by the mysterious, but material and potentially tractable, mechanism of mutation.
WILLIAM E. CASTLE
Whilst Europe was its birthplace, and Europeans arguably dominant among the early
Mendelians, genetics also managed to rapidly establish itself in the United States. One of the
earliest American supporters of Mendelism was the Harvard zoologist William E. Castle,
who as early as 1903 declared Mendel’s hereditary law as “one of the great discoveries in
biology”.130 Prior to the emergence of the Morgan school as the dominant paradigm in
American genetics, Castle was possibly the most eminent and influential geneticist in the
Western Hemisphere, being “one of the most ingenious experimenters in early genetics” and
a founding figure in the establishment of mammalian genetics.131 He is additionally credited
127
Ibid., pp. 108
Ibid., pp. 78
129
Ernst Mayr, The Growth of Biological Thought: Diversity, Evolution and Inheritance, The Belknap Press of
Harvard University Press, 1982, pp. 549
130
William E. Castle, ‘Mendel’s Law of Heredity’, Science, New Series, Vol. 18, No. 456, 1903, pp. 397
Ernst Mayr, The Growth of Biological Thought: Diversity, Evolution and Inheritance, The Belknap Press of
Harvard University Press, 1982, pp. 785 & 889
128
~ Page 29 ~
with, in 1901, introducing Drosophila into the laboratory, the organism upon which the
success of the Morgan school would be founded.132 Examining Castle’s views on wild-type
gives important detail as to what kind of conceptions of it were prevalent in American
genetics circles before the emergence of the ‘Drosophilists’.
Like Bateson, Castle found through his investigations that many wild-type traits are in fact
composite traits requiring several factors to be present in order to develop, and that variations
are produced by the loss or non-function of one of these factors. For example, he studied coat
colouring in small mammals such as guinea-pigs, whose ‘agouti’ wild-type coats can under a
microscope visibly be seen to in fact be the products of three pigments, black, chocolate and
red-yellow. Castle infers that these pigments are each the product of an individual factor and
that the occurrence of black, chocolate and yellow varieties in guinea-pig could thereby be
attributed to the loss of one or more of the factors responsible for pigment, with albinism
being explained as the result of a separate ‘lost’ factor enabling pigment manifestation.133
Castle also observes what he believed to be evidence for the gaining of factors, citing in
particular the case of the rough coat of the ‘Abyssinian’ guinea-pig breed, a character he
considered “surely not an ancestral condition” but which, because it is commonly dominant
over ‘wild-type’ coat, “can scarcely be explained by loss; the only alternative is to consider it
an acquisition”. He considers these observations as being possible evidence for instances of
de Vries’ two major categories of mutational variation, namely retrogressive and
progressive.134 The example of the Abyssinian’s rough coat he furthermore feels to be firm
evidence that “ancestral characters are not necessarily dominant over new characters in
heredity”, and that consequently reversion of domestic varieties to wild-type is not a
universal or inevitable phenomenon, allowing the departure from type necessary for evolution
to occur.135
Castle understands atavism to be wholly explained in terms of Mendelism, namely as the
consequence of the bringing together of two or more separate heritable factors which only in
132
Robert E. Kohler, Lords of the Fly, The University of Chicago Press, 1994, pp. 23
William E. Castle, Heredity of Coat Characters in Guinea-pigs and Rabbits, the Carnegie Institute of
Washington, 1905, pp. 6
134
William E. Castle, Heredity in Relation to Evolution and Animal Breeding, D. Appleton and Company, 1911,
pp. 89-90
135
William E. Castle, Heredity of Coat Characters in Guinea-pigs and Rabbits, the Carnegie Institute of
Washington, 1905, pp. 75
133
~ Page 30 ~
unison can produce the reversionary character.136 He further comprehends that such
heterozygous composite characters, ‘agouti’ coat for example, can become prevalent and
‘fixed’ in a wild population if they are evolutionarily favoured traits and if there is significant
outbreeding.137 Significantly, he recognises that the Mendelian explanation of reversion
demonstrates the falsity of the long-standing belief, brought into scientific circles by Galton,
in the ‘law of ancestral heredity’. This is the theory that the power of heredity extends beyond
the parental generation and into the mists of time, there being a direct correlation between the
number of ancestors sharing a trait, e.g. albinism, and the number of offspring with this trait
in the first filial generation.138 Galtonism, in other words, considered heredity an effect of
pedigree, and purity of stock relates directly to ancestry. Castle realised what has since been
observed by Jean Gayon, namely that with the arrival of Mendelian genetics pedigree
becomes a mere tool for the production of strains, and is no longer a fundamental concept.139
Purity of stock, moreover, is no longer absolute as “No animal or plant is 'pure' simply
because it is descended from a long line of ancestors possessing a desired combination of
characters”. On the other hand “any animal or plant is pure if it produces gametes of only one
sort, even though its grandparents may among themselves have possessed opposite
characters”.140 If ancestry has no influence on type beyond the parental generation, what is
relevant in attempting to ‘fix’ a variety is not pedigree but rather the correct selection for
further breeding of homozygous individuals from amongst the offspring of a cross.141 In
summary, with Mendelism, stock purity becomes relative to stock selection and is not
absolute.
If it is the Mendelian characters and not pedigree which determines hereditary outcomes, the
number of generations an organism spends in domesticity is equally irrelevant in analysing
the result. Subsequently, wildness and domesticity cannot be tied to type as they have no
causal influence on it. Furthermore, Mendelism, if correct, allows, so long as one is given
organisms with an appropriate genetic disposition, the production of ‘wild type’ and
William E. Castle, ‘On a Case of Reversion Induced by Cross-Breeding and its Fixation’, Science, New
Series, Vol. 25, No. 630, 1907, pp. 151
137
William E. Castle, Heredity in Relation to Evolution and Animal Breeding, D. Appleton and Company, 1911,
pp. 149
138
William E. Castle, Heredity of Coat Characters in Guinea-pigs and Rabbits, the Carnegie Institute of
Washington, 1905, pp. 19
139
Jean Gayon, ‘The Philosophical History of the Concept of Heredity’, The Concept of the Gene in
Development and Evolution, Peter J. Beurton, Raphael Falk & Hans-Jörg Rheinberger (eds.), Cambridge
University Press, 2000, pp. 75
140
William E. Castle, ‘Mendel’s Law of Heredity’, Science, New Series, Vol. 18, No. 456, 1903, pp. 401
141
Ibid., pp. 401
136
~ Page 31 ~
‘domestic type’ organisms to become essentially a matter of manufacture. In many cases,
wild organisms can be taken, analysed through crossing and inbred to produce strains
resembling domesticated breeds in relatively few generations thanks to the advance of
Mendelian analysis of heredity.142 Producing ‘domestic type’ becomes almost as simple as
producing ‘wild type’ atavistically by crossing domestic varieties. Castle, however, could not
wholly accept this idea that ‘type’ can be produced mechanically through Mendelian methods
as opposed to traditional artificial selective means. As a result, he makes a distinction
between original traits actually found in wild organisms – which he on occasion used as sires
for his lineages – 143 and in ‘ordinary’ domestic variants,144 and the ‘extracted’ incidence of
these traits in their laboratory descendants which, whilst strongly resembling those of their
ancestors, he observed to sometimes behave differently.145 An example of such an apparently
ancestral trait behaving differently is given of a “synthetically produced” instance of the
wild-type ‘agouti’ coat in guinea-pigs, which underneath its visual homogeneity is
behaviourally heterogeneous due to its being highly unstable, only reappearing in a minority
of descendants, in contrast with agouti’s normal dominance.146 It is perhaps due to these
observations that Castle, when referring to the incidence of agouti in domestic guinea-pigs,
stresses that whilst this trait in domestics is visibly and usually behaviourally identical to
wild-type, this constitutes only a resemblance which may hide genetic idiosyncrasies.147
Experimental proof that ‘wild-type’ traits are extractable non-atavistically from domestic
lineages was provided in Castle’s subsequent breeding experiments with ‘hooded’ (pied) rats,
in which he was able through appropriate selection to produce after several generations ‘self’
(all black) rats resembling the wild-type.148
Despite Castle’s insistence on distinguishing original from ‘extracted’ traits, he does not
appear to consider the difference between wild and domesticated organisms significant
enough that the former cannot be substituted by the latter if of an appropriate genetic
constitution. This is evidenced by his use of a “a pure reddish gray pigmented animal of the
William E. Castle, ‘The Inconstancy of Unit-Characters’, The American Naturalist, Vol. 46, No. 546, 1912,
pp. 354
143
William E. Castle, Heredity of Coat Characters in Guinea-pigs and Rabbits, the Carnegie Institute of
Washington, 1905, pp. 26
144
Ibid., pp. 64
145
Ibid., pp. 47
146
Ibid., pp. 31
147
William E. Castle, ‘On a Case of Reversion Induced by Cross-Breeding and its Fixation’, Science, New
Series, Vol. 25, No. 630, 1907, pp. 152
148
William E. Castle, ‘Is Selection or Mutation the More Important Agent in Evolution’, The Scientific Monthly,
Vol. 2, No. 1, 1916, pp. 96
142
~ Page 32 ~
breed known as the Belgian hare” in place of a wild parent when repeating an experiment of
Raspall’s which had originally mated a domestic female to wild males.149 This belief in the
substitutability of wild with domestic is related to the fact that Castle sometimes does treat
wild populations as if they are not especially variable, most markedly in his suggestion that a
particular set of mouse phenotypes can be obtained in the offspring of a cross between an
albino and “a wild house-mouse of the kind every barn contains”. This ignores the fact that
house-mice do geographically vary, though to be fair to Castle, he does emphasise that this
wild parent be “properly selected”.150
Whilst some of his early work in genetics displayed occasional slips into ‘typological’
thinking, Castle later came out strongly against what he called ‘fixity’ in organisms. This is in
no small part because, unlike many of his fellow early Mendelians, Castle was a committed
traditional Darwinian and continued to consider natural selection as the major engine for
evolutionary change and continuous variation as its source of material.151 He therefore
opposed the “different doctrine” he attributed to de Vries and Johannsen that reduced natural
selection to a ‘sieve’ and rendered fluctuating variability as a mere coming and going, “like
the wavelets on the ocean beach, but hav[ing] no more relation to evolution than the waves
have to the tides”.152 As a further consequence of his opposition to fixity, Castle came to
attack the idea of unit-characters as being “as changeless as atoms”.153 In reference to
Bateson’s comparison of unit-characters to simple bi-elemental compounds, which, if they
change at all, can only change radically in nature, he points instead to the complex nature of
the biochemical candidates for the physical vehicles of heredity, which are “made up, it is
thought, of very many atoms, often hundreds in a single molecule”. He contends that “it is
quite possible that an atom or two might be transposed in position within the molecule
without wholly altering its chemical nature, and that thus slight changes in the germ-plasm
149
William E. Castle, Heredity of Coat Characters in Guinea-pigs and Rabbits, the Carnegie Institute of
Washington, 1905, pp. 72
150
William E. Castle, Heredity in Relation to Evolution and Animal Breeding, D. Appleton and Company, 1911,
pp. 83
151
William E. Castle, ‘The Inconstancy of Unit-Characters’, The American Naturalist, Vol. 46, No. 546, 1912,
pp. 354
152
William E. Castle, Heredity in Relation to Evolution and Animal Breeding, D. Appleton and Company, 1911,
pp. 106-7
153
William E. Castle, ‘The Inconstancy of Unit-Characters’, The American Naturalist, Vol. 46, No. 546, 1912,
pp. 354
~ Page 33 ~
might result, which, however, would be as permanent as more profound changes”.154 In such
a way, gradual changes in the unit-character might accumulate over time.
What is more, Castle believed that such accumulating changes in the unit-characters can be
caused by factors such as crossing, which he asserted responsible for what he considered
otherwise unexplained variability in some of the Mendelian characters he studied.155 This led
him to deny gametic purity and assert instead that when heterozygous factors separate after
meiosis they will tend to swap small amounts of material and lose their purity, a position that
has since become known as the ‘contamination theory’.156 Castle believed that a consequence
of gametic contamination in heterozygous alleles was that artificial selection, contra de Vries,
does have real power to affect variability and, moreover, the power to modify unitcharacters.157 He considered himself to have experimental proof of this through his ‘hooded’
rats breeding experiments. The ‘hooded’ character is known to behave as a Mendelian
recessive in crosses with ‘self’ (totally pigmented) and ‘Irish’ (white-bellied) rats.158 Through
selection, Castle sought to show that this character, whilst Mendelising, is not constant. The
methodology of this experiment was to first through inbreeding remove any modifying
factors that might alter the Mendelian behaviour of ‘hooded’. From the resulting animals the
most extreme variations were then selected and separately bred in two groups, a ‘minus
series’ of the whitest animals and a ‘plus series’ of the blackest. Through further selective
breeding, Castle reports that “The plus series has become steadily darker, the minus series
lighter, until two very distinct races have resulted”. Furthermore “With advance in the mean
grade of the offspring has gone advance in both the upper and the lower limits of their
variation”. This leads him to conclude that the hooded character “though itself a simple
Mendelian unit in heredity” is subject to constant slight quantitative variation, and that such
variation is grouped around a mean “the position of which may be altered gradually but
permanently by repeated selection”.159
154
William E. Castle, Heredity in Relation to Evolution and Animal Breeding, D. Appleton and Company, 1911,
pp. 110-1
155
William E. Castle, ‘Is Selection or Mutation the More Important Agent in Evolution’, The Scientific Monthly,
Vol. 2, No. 1, 1916, pp. 93
156
Elof Axel Carlson, The Gene: A Critical History, W.B. Saunders Company, 1966, pp. 25
157
William E. Castle, ‘The Inconstancy of Unit-Characters’, The American Naturalist, Vol. 46, No. 546, 1912,
pp. 355
158
William E. Castle, Heredity in Relation to Evolution and Animal Breeding, D. Appleton and Company, 1911,
pp. 123
159
William E. Castle, ‘Is Selection or Mutation the More Important Agent in Evolution’, The Scientific Monthly,
Vol. 2, No. 1, 1916, pp. 93-6
~ Page 34 ~
If Castle’s experiments proved artificial selection to not after all be powerless, the implication
was that the belief so scornfully denied by de Vries that “varieties are improved by continued
culture” has some validity after all.160 This moreover re-establishes the reality of the divide
between wild and domestic organisms in that the latter are once more considered products of
human intervention as opposed to being pre-existing types largely selected from nature and
insignificantly refined by cultivation. Castle’s analysis, however, would do away with the
idea of ‘type’ as anything more than a human label in that he does not consider there to exist
stable ‘real units’ in nature. ‘Type’, furthermore, is in Castle’s mind a manifestation of the
idea of fixity among organisms, a belief he asserts to be “one which the human mind is loath
to give up and which has to be constantly combated in the advancement of biology”.161 De
Vries and many other Mendelians had been guilty of attaching to the unit-character an
unwarranted intransience, treating them as if they are absolute and independent entities when
in truth, Castle believed, “They are not things in themselves distinct and separate from the
organism concerned; each is a quantitative variation plus or minus in some one character
possessed by the organism”.162 This variation operates around a norm, but this norm has no
objectivity, being merely a mathematical mean, a mean which is moreover mobile and
subject to selection. Within such a viewpoint, Castle is happy to distinguish between wild and
domesticated animals as the process of artificial selection operates in a manner distinct from
natural selection, but there is no room for ‘type’, wild-types being merely the average
instances of the species encountered in nature.
Unfortunately for Castle and his theory of inconstant unit-characters, the very breeding
experiment which he had used as his primary evidence for inconstancy, his hooded rats,
eventually produced results which contradicted his claims in favour of the Morgan school’s
theory that such apparent variations in the unit-character were in fact the result of multiple
factors influencing a single trait.163 In the face of this failing, Castle effectively accepted the
defeat of his research programme, acknowledging that his results “favor the widely accepted
view that the single gene is not subject to fluctuating variability”, and that discontinuous, not
160
Hugo de Vries, Species and Varieties: Their Origin by Mutation, Daniel Trembly MacDougal (ed.), The
Open Court Publishing Company, 1905, pp. 511
161
William E. Castle, ‘Is Selection or Mutation the More Important Agent in Evolution’, The Scientific Monthly,
Vol. 2, No. 1, 1916, pp. 97
162
William E. Castle, ‘The Inconstancy of Unit-Characters’, The American Naturalist, Vol. 46, No. 546, 1912,
pp. 358
163
Elof Axel Carlson, The Gene: A Critical History, W.B. Saunders Company, 1966, pp. 38
~ Page 35 ~
continuous variation is the only source of evolutionary change.164 He thereby endorsed
mutationism, a position he had only three years prior unfavourably compared to nineteenth
century catastrophism.165
THOMAS HUNT MORGAN
The younger Thomas Hunt Morgan has often been presented as being overly under the
influence of de Vries, being considered one of his most significant champions in the United
States in the first decade of the twentieth century. However, whilst it is true that his visit to de
Vries in Holland in 1903 left a strong impression on him, one very much detectable in the
contents of the book he wrote the same year, Evolution and Adaptation, on closer inspection
even at this stage Morgan very much had his own idiosyncratic and independent view of the
nature of species and variation.166 He evidentially, for instance, recognised some of the
shortcomings in de Vries’ evidential basis for his mutation theory, asserting, regarding the
claim that mutations are ‘scattering’, that is occurring in all directions, that “On this point it
seems to me that de Vries may be too much prejudiced by his results with the evening
primrose”.167 He also had a background in developmental studies and was strongly against
what he saw as the preformationism of Weismann’s particulate theory of inheritance,168
which may be contrasted with de Vries’ own training in the reductionist-mechanist laboratory
of Julius Sachs.169 Morgan furthermore was highly broadminded when it came to
experimental biology, simultaneously working in many different fields with numerous
species of model organism (over fifty in his lifetime), which strongly contrasted with de
Vries’ overt focus on mutational variation, evidence for which he could only discover in a
small number of species.170 Morgan’s more dilettante approach to model organism utilisation
may well explain his caution in accepting de Vries’ Oenothera based findings, as he preferred
that such evidence first be collaborated through studies of further species before being
generalised. This broader approach to experimental biology did not change in later years;
despite the tremendous success of Drosophila as a model organism, Morgan continued to
William E. Castle, ‘Piebald Rats and the Theory of Genes’, Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences
of the United States of America, Vol. 5, No. 4, 1919, pp. 130
165
William E. Castle, ‘Is Selection or Mutation the More Important Agent in Evolution’, The Scientific Monthly,
Vol. 2, No. 1, 1916, pp. 91
166
Elof Axel Carlson, The Gene: A Critical History, W.B. Saunders Company, 1966, pp. 40-1
167
Thomas Hunt Morgan, Evolution and Adaptation, The Macmillan Company, 1903, pp. 292-3
168
Elof Axel Carlson, The Gene: A Critical History, W.B. Saunders Company, 1966, pp. 39-41
169
Ernst Mayr, The Growth of Biological Thought: Diversity, Evolution and Inheritance, The Belknap Press of
Harvard University Press, 1982, pp. 708
170
Robert E. Kohler, Lords of the Fly, The University of Chicago Press, 1994, pp. 26
164
~ Page 36 ~
explore new lines of research using new organisms both inside and outside the field of
genetics, including, for example, studies of sexual selection in birds and fiddler crabs in the
early 1920s.171
Nonetheless, it must be said that Morgan in Evolution and Adaptation is highly sympathetic
to de Vries’ views and antagonistic towards much of contemporary Darwinism, a fact he
recognises himself when he notes in his introduction that “In attempting to state the problem
as clearly as possible, I fear that it may appear that at times I have "taken sides"”.172 Indeed,
where he most departs from de Vries is in his criticism of Darwin and his contemporary
adherents, for as already discussed, de Vries himself, despite his mutation theory’s arguable
lack of compatibility, considered himself to be synthesising evolution by natural selection
with the new insights from heredity of the fin de siécle. Morgan on the other hand attacks
contemporary Darwinism as a “doctrine” which biologists have protected from what they
know to be legitimate reservations and doubts, and concludes that “the claim of the
opponents of the theory that Darwinism has become a dogma contains more truth than the
nominal followers of this school find pleasant to hear”. Morgan does rejoinder this
inflammatory statement by conceding that biologists should not “too hastily conclude that
Darwin's theory is without value in relation to one side of the problem of adaptation” as he
does believe that “the fact that living things must be adapted more or less well to their
environment in order to remain in existence may, after all, account for the widespread
occurrence of adaptation in animals and plants”.173
Though he does thus accept the utility of adaptation in the struggle for existence, Morgan
does however maintain that “we can profitably reject… much of the theory of natural
selection”, in particular citing as worthy of disposal the idea that adaptations arise because of
their usefulness.174 More radically still, he suggests the possibility of a form of ‘neutral’ nonselected evolution, whereby mutations might accumulate without selection having any effect
and that this “could account for evolution without supposing any other process to intervene”.
Selection under these circumstances is limited to “the destruction of those variations
incapable of living, or of competing with other forms”, having a wholly negative, non-
171
Ibid., pp. 185
Thomas Hunt Morgan, Evolution and Adaptation, The Macmillan Company, 1903, pp. vii
173
Ibid., pp. ix
174
Ibid.
172
~ Page 37 ~
creative value.175 Nature, in Morgan’s view “does not remodel old forms through a process of
individual selection”,176 but rather brings forth new ones which “appear at a single advance,
and fully formed”.177 It is only once they arrive in the world that these novel forms are
subjected to the selective pressures imposed by their environments, but these pressures have
no power over form itself and can only have effect on evolution by more or less successfully
killing off particular variants. “Nature's supreme test is survival”, Morgan affirms.178 She
does not, he implies, select varieties across the generations promoting gradual change. What
is of importance in evolution is whether or not the original carrier of a new mutation survives
to propagate it. Once reproduced in sufficient numbers, the mutation is outside of the remit of
selection and is effectively immortal as long as it continues to be propagated. Whether it is
expressed is a different matter, as we shall see below, but the salient claim here is that at no
point in this process does the mutant factor, once arisen, change. It is indeed ironically
Morgan’s rejection of natural selection as a powerful agent in evolution that led him to
disagree with de Vries regarding the latter’s theory of scattering mutations, for Morgan
believed that if Oenothera Lamarckiana’s production of multiple new ‘elementary species’
were truly representative that there should be a considerably greater richness of species in
both the present day and in the fossil record. He did not, in other words, consider nature as
capable an exterminator as de Vries. Consequently, Morgan considers it to be more likely that
mutations producing one or only a very few new forms are typical and that ‘scattering’
mutations are exceptional.179
Part of the reason for Morgan’s considering natural selection to be impotent in terms of
instigating evolutionary change is his belief that artificial selection, which Darwinists had
long utilised as a source of analogous evidence for their beliefs, does not furnish such
support. Whilst it has produced “interesting and suggestive” results, artificial selection cannot
be used to substantiate Darwin’s most important argument, namely the origin of species
through selection in nature, as, despite the greatest efforts of horticulturalists and animal
breeders, “new species comparable in all respects to wild ones have not been formed, even in
those cases in which the variation has been carried farthest”. Morgan moreover doubts that
those changes brought about in domesticated animals and plants can be attributed by and
175
Ibid., pp. 97
Ibid., pp. 464
177
Ibid., pp. 297
178
Ibid., pp. 464
179
Ibid., pp. 292-3
176
~ Page 38 ~
large to selection of continuous variations, “for this is not established with any great degree
of probability by the evidence”.180 This is not to say that he believes that artificial selection
cannot have an effect on organisms, for “there can be no doubt that a certain standard, or
fixity of type, can be obtained by selecting fluctuating variations”, but rather that he considers
the extent to which the process can be carried as “overestimated”,181 there being a very real
limit to variation “beyond which it is impossible to go”.182
Like de Vries, Morgan believes that much of what has been attributed to the effects of
artificial selection is actually the product of other factors such as intercrossing, the bringing
of new elementary species into cultivation, the effect of different environmental and
nutritional conditions and, of course, mutation.183 His conception of the nature of mutation is,
however, not identical to de Vries’, and he makes an effort to point this out when he states
that he uses the term ‘mutation’ “in a very general way… as synonymous with discontinuous
and also definite variation of all kinds”, not intending that the word convey only de Vries’
conception of it.184 One especial manner in which Morgan’s conception of mutation differs
from de Vries is in his interpretation of how ‘mutation periods’ function. As aforementioned,
he does not consider ‘scattering’ mutations producing multiple and clearly differentiated
types, as discovered by de Vries in Oenothera, to be typical, and thus rules out their
evolutionary importance. He furthermore considers the Darwinian claim that discontinuous
variation cannot be evolutionary important because it is rare and usually “swamped by
intercrossing” to have some validity, observing that “We see then that discontinuity in itself,
unless it involved infertility with the parent species, of which there is no evidence, cannot be
made the basis for a theory of evolution”. He therefore, like de Vries, appeals to the idea that
during a mutation period a species may give rise through discontinuous variation to multiple
individuals of the same type, which allows the mutant type to either differentiate from the
parent form by finding a different ecological niche, which lessens occurrences of
intercrossing, or to absorb the parent-type if it is genetically dominant or adaptively
favoured.185
180
Ibid., pp. 102-3
Ibid., pp. 456
182
Ibid., pp. 103
183
Ibid., pp. 456
184
Ibid., pp. 340
185
Ibid., pp. 286-7
181
~ Page 39 ~
What is different in Morgan’s appeal to multiple mutations is that he also believes such a
dynamic may allow for the construction of distinct species out of different small mutations
occurring in the same direction as well as through single large ones, and that the former
means of speciation may well be the more evolutionarily viable. He points to the fact that
what is essential in the nature of a mutation is not its involving considerable change,
appealing to de Vries’ own observation that many mutations lie within the extremes of a
species’ normal range of fluctuating variation, but rather that it is constant in its
inheritance.186 He then introduces Weismann’s idea that a given form’s surviving may
determine its future evolution to continue in the same direction and applies it to discontinuous
variation to suggest that once a mutation moves the type norm in a particular direction, it is
easier for it to continue in that same direction rather going backwards.187 In this way,
mutational evolution might be limited to producing forms in a particular trajectory. Morgan,
however, admitted that, whilst “the general problem of evolution from a purely theoretical
point of view is very much simplified, if we assume that the kinds of mutating forms may
often be very limited, and that mutations may often continue to occur in a direct line”,188 the
evidential basis for such a theory was lacking at the time of his writing Evolution and
Adaptation.189 It was his desire to provide the data necessary to validate this theory of
directed mutation which led him to commit himself to a prolonged series of animal
experiments attempting to induce mutating periods, an experimental series that would
unintentionally lead him away from evolutionary studies and into transmission genetics. 190
Before moving on to his later and more famous work with the Drosophilists, it is worth
pausing on another point of conflict between Morgan and de Vries, namely the issue of
‘type’. As stated above, they had contrasting influences regarding biological ontology,
Morgan being an epigenetic developmental biologist suspicious of speculative claims of the
particulate nature of inheritance, de Vries having a more mechanistic and reductionist
conception of organisms. These underlying differences in ontological outlook did not prevent
Morgan from embracing de Vries’ mutation theory wholeheartedly. What he does not care
much for, however, is de Vries’ claim that elementary species constitute ‘real units’ in nature,
that they are the atoms of evolutionary descent as it were. Morgan does not deny that there
186
Ibid., pp. 289-90
Ibid., pp. 461
188
Ibid., pp. 293
189
Ibid., pp. 462
190
Robert E. Kohler, Lords of the Fly, The University of Chicago Press, 1994, pp. 41
187
~ Page 40 ~
are groups of similar forms which repeat themselves in each generation, which are called by
systematists species.191 What is more, whilst all individuals in each group differ slightly, they
all “conform, more or less, to a sort of ideal type” which remains constant across the
generations.192 Morgan nonetheless cautions that “We should always keep in mind the fact
that the individual is the only reality with which we have to deal, and that the arrangement of
these into species, genera, families, etc., is only a scheme invented by man for purposes of
classification. Thus there is no such thing in nature as a species, except as a concept of a
group of forms more or less alike. In nature there are no genera, families, orders, etc. These
are inventions of man for purposes of classification”.193 That organisms can be arranged into
such groups is explained by their common descent, and their differences are explained as the
result of mutations, but how these groups are actually arranged is ultimately a matter of
artificially imposing categories upon nature and not uncovering ‘real units’. ‘Type’ for
Morgan, unlike de Vries, is in the human mind, not existent in the living world.
Given this anti-realist interpretation of ‘type’, it may be asked why Morgan allowed it, in the
form of ‘wild-type’, to so thoroughly infest the terminology of his research group’s later
genetic studies. The choice of the term ‘wild-type’ to refer to laboratory organisms may seem
more mysterious given Morgan’s recognition of the role of environment in determining the
expression of type. For example, he observes that changes in external conditions may result
in the appearance within a species of a new ‘mode’. Whilst he considers this change
contingent on conditions remaining the same and not, therefore, permanent in an evolutionary
sense, Morgan certainly recognised that the transferring of wild animals into the laboratory
represents just such a change in conditions and that, as result, these laboratory organisms will
likely have a different mode compared to their wild counterparts and not that of true wild
types.194 Furthermore, whilst ““In most cases different genetic types produce different results
in any ordinary environment” and that, as a consequence, the effects of the environment can
be ignored or taken for granted, Morgan knew that certain mutations only express themselves
in particular environments, otherwise appearing ‘normal’. Indeed, he and his colleagues
found a few such mutations in Drosophila, for example ‘abnormal abdomen’, which varied
from fully expressed to indistinguishable from wild-type according to whether reared on
moist or dry food. In such cases Morgan et al assert that “Where [the] environment [required
191
Thomas Hunt Morgan, Evolution and Adaptation, The Macmillan Company, 1903, pp. 30
Ibid., pp. 340
193
Ibid., pp. 33
194
Ibid., pp. 458
192
~ Page 41 ~
for the mutation’s expression] is not the normal one, its discovery is an essential element of
the experiment”.195
That Morgan was fully aware of the “artificial and unnatural conditions” typical of the
laboratory environment, and the potential influence they might have on the ‘type’ of his
laboratory organisms, is clearly demonstrated by his defence of his practices in A Critique of
the Theory of Evolution. Morgan is responding to the criticism that the results of his
experiments and those of other geneticists do not provide reliable evidence for the actual
operation of evolution “in the "open", nature "at large" or to "wild" types”. To this Morgan
replies that, if those rejecting the results obtained from the breeding pen, the seed pan, the
flower pot and the milk bottle are to be consistent, “this same objection should be extended to
the use of the spectroscope in the study of the evolution of the stars, to the use of the test tube
and the balance by the chemist, of the galvanometer by the physicist. All these are unnatural
instruments used to torture Nature's secrets from her”.196 It is in this answer here that we are
perhaps given our most revealing clue as to why Morgan considers the use of the term ‘wildtype’ as legitimate, that the wild-type concept is itself a tool, being a necessary part of the
cognitive equipment needed to process and order the findings of research. That it is an
artificial category appealing to things that may not truly be existent in nature, such as ‘type’,
or that it arguably misrepresents the nature of the entities placed within it, such as the heavily
selected domestic strains described as ‘wild’, is not of great significance, for in this it is little
different from the equally distorting physical utensils of genetics experiments. ‘Wild-type’ is
for Morgan an instrumentally useful label for particular domestic strains that it is felt can
‘stand in’ for actually wild organisms, being apparently similar enough that research
conducted utilising them can be assumed to be safe to extrapolate to the species as a whole,
without simultaneously being difficult to keep and unreliable due to the invisible genetic
variation often typical in actual wild populations. This attitude to wild-type is further
evidenced by his own admission in his 1910 paper ‘Sex Limited Inheritance in Drosophila’
that ‘wild’ flies merely need to be of unrelated stock, not necessarily undomesticated, in order
for crosses with mutant strains to produce Mendelian ratios.197 Flies which produce the
desired results may thus be considered adequate substitutes for truly wild stocks. Morgan
195
Thomas Hunt Morgan, Alfred H. Sturtevant, Hermann J. Muller, & Calvin B. Bridges, The Mechanism of
Mendelian Inheritance, Henry Holt and Company, 1915, pp. 38
196
Thomas Hunt Morgan, A Critique of the Theory of Evolution, Princeton University Press, 1916, pp. 84-5
197
Thomas Hunt Morgan, ‘Sex Limited Inheritance in Drosophila’, Science, New Series, Vol. 32, No. 812,
1910, pp. 121
~ Page 42 ~
further considers wild-type strains as providing a necessary counterpart to mutant ones as
“we cannot study a single mutant factor without at the same time studying one of the factors
responsible for normal characters, for the two together constitute the Mendelian pair”.198 That
these strains are almost always genetically and ecologically quite removed from their truly
wild counterparts, so are only ‘normal’ in a broad sense, is acknowledged, but what Morgan
wants additionally acknowledged is the necessity of working with those limited available
tools that actually produced controlled or verifiable data. Nature must be treated unnaturally
if it is to be studied, and to forego such means would render biology a non-science.
Further proof that Morgan considers the labels of genetics as providing instrumental as
opposed ‘real’ categories is given in his paper ‘What are ‘Factors’ in Mendelian
Explanations’. Here he observes that “In the modern interpretation of Mendelism, facts are
being transformed into factors at a rapid rate. If one factor will not explain the facts, then two
are invoked; if two prove insufficient, three will sometimes work out. The superior jugglery
sometimes necessary to account for the result, may blind us, if taken too naïvely, to the
common-place that the results are often so excellently “explained” because the explanation
was invented to explain them. We work backwards from the facts to the factors, and then,
presto! explain the facts by the very factors that we invented to account for them”. He does
not consider this ‘juggling’ of invented factors as bad science, indeed states that it is
extremely valuable that geneticists are thus enabled to marshal their results under a few
simple assumptions. What he does consider paramount is that “we do not lose sight of the
purely arbitrary and formal nature of our formulae”. He believes this is already occurring, not
so much within the actual research community but rather amongst “those who know the
results at second hand”, that such persons “are likely to exaggerate the importance of the
interpretations and to minimize the importance of the facts”. Morgan considers this
particularly dangerous because “Mendelian results are only average results”, not absolute
ones. He further, like Castle, contests the claim of gametic purity, condemning the idea that
factors are entities “that may be shuffled like cards in a pack, but cannot become mixed” as
inherently preformationist. He favours instead a more epigenetic view of inheritance that sees
factor symbols as representing developmental potentialities contained within the sex cells, a
perspective that does not, unlike, he believes, the preformationist viewpoint, imply that these
germ-cell materials may be equated with the adult characters they eventually may produce.
198
Thomas Hunt Morgan, A Critique of the Theory of Evolution, Princeton University Press, 1916, pp. 86
~ Page 43 ~
Moreover, Morgan cautions that preformationist methods, whilst often providing “immediate,
if temporary, successes”, are flawed in that, unlike epigenetic techniques, they do not leave
open “the door for further examination and re-examination”, and that it is only through such
re-treading and re-analysis that true scientific advances take place.199
It may be objected that the later successes of Morgan and his associates, the ‘Drosophilists’,
in discovering genes to have a very real physical nature and location, namely as linearly
arranged along chromosomes, led Morgan away from an epigenetic developmental
perspective on inheritance and towards a more mechanistic and particulate interpretation that
admitted factors to be ‘real units’ in nature. This, however, is to arguably misunderstand the
role of Morgan within his research group. As Kohler highlights, he acted as ‘boss’ to his
‘boys’, being the figurehead and focal point helping to keep together and maintain order
amongst a rather heterogeneous group of students.200 Whilst he laid the foundations upon
which the group did its work, namely by pioneering the successful use of Drosophila mutants
to study associate inheritance, he was, once the group was firmly established, no longer the
major creative force within it, though he still took credit for its successes.201 Instead, he acted
as a critical force demanding that his pupils’ claims be based on empirical evidence, and in
this way helped curb overly speculative tendencies within the group, though at the same time
frustrating some members, especially Muller, who favoured greater theoretical conjecture.202
Whilst his own experiments with Drosophila did convert him to a particulate theory of
inheritance, it was, as Roll-Hansen notes, only “an incomplete and reserved conversion”.203
What is more, though Morgan’s critical and anti-speculative perspective “did play a more
subordinate role in his writings during the years 1910-1920 than before”, “There is no reason
to believe that Morgan ever gave up his empiricist methodology”. Morgan kept his scepticism
largely private, Roll-Hansen surmises, because he did not want to undermine the successes of
his own research group as “Empiricism was useful for chastising theoretical speculations, but
not for pushing research on the chromosomal theory forward”.204
Thomas Hunt Morgan, ‘What are “Factors” in Mendelian Explanations?’, American Breeders Association
Reports, Vol. 5, 1909, pp. 365-7
200
Robert E. Kohler, Lords of the Fly, The University of Chicago Press, 1994, pp. 110
201
Nils Roll-Hansen, ‘Drosophila Genetics: A Reductionist Research Program’, Journal of the History of
Biology, Vol. 11, No. 1, 1978, pp. 177
202
Ibid., pp. 165-6
203
Ibid., pp. 182
204
Ibid., pp. 191
199
~ Page 44 ~
Another proof of Morgan’s instrumentalism is demonstrated by his apparently selfcontradictory choice, given his statement in ‘What are ‘Factors’ in Mendelian Explanations’
that “we are not justified in speaking of the materials in the germ-cells as the same thing as
the adult characters until they develop”, of labelling mutants according to the mature
characteristics that rendered them distinct from wild-type.205 Such a system seems to
reinforce a preformationist interpretation of the gene, contrary to Morgan’s own perspective,
and promote confusion of the adult characteristic with its developmentally causal factor in the
gamete. It may thus, as Roll-Hansen observes, in hindsight “be tempting to suggest that the
whole system of referring to factors by the name of characters was a source of confusion
which it took constant effort to overcome”, and therefore that an alternative system whose
symbols did not refer to adult characters would be preferable.206 The fact is, however, that
Morgan did consider such a system, one designed by Baur and Hagedoorn, but when he
attempted to use it he in practice found it “extremely difficult to understand what any formula
means without continual reference to the key of symbols used”, and as a result abandoned it
in favour of a modified version of the existing system.207 Such a formal system lacked
intuitive meaning, unlike labelling according to adult characters, which acts as a mnemonic
heuristic and was consequently favoured by Morgan, despite its potential to cause
confusion.208 Morgan’s judgement regarding the suitability of terminology in genetics was
thus ultimately determined by utility, not realism.
The cause of the move to the new system of labelling mutants according to adult
characteristics had been the failure of the existing ‘presence and absence’ system instituted
by Bateson. This failure had been due to the discovery of multiple allelism, which the
Batesonian system, explaining as it did ‘normal’ and ‘mutant’ conditions as due to the
presence or absence of a singular factor, could not cope with as it left no room for further
allelic conditions, e.g. double recessives.209 The need for a new system was particularly
pressing for Morgan and his Drosophilists due to the flood of new mutants their laboratory
205
Thomas Hunt Morgan, ‘What are “Factors” in Mendelian Explanations?’, American Breeders Association
Reports, Vol. 5, 1909, pp. 367
206
Nils Roll-Hansen, ‘Drosophila Genetics: A Reductionist Research Program’, Journal of the History of
Biology, Vol. 11, No. 1, 1978, pp. 188
207
Thomas Hunt Morgan, ‘Factors and Unit Characters in Mendelian Heredity’, The American Naturalist, Vol.
47, No. 553, 1913, pp. 16
208
Nils Roll-Hansen, ‘Drosophila Genetics: A Reductionist Research Program’, Journal of the History of
Biology, Vol. 11, No. 1, 1978, pp. 189
209
Elof Axel Carlson, The Gene: A Critical History, W.B. Saunders Company, 1966, pp. 62
~ Page 45 ~
experienced after their fruit-fly breeding programmes were scaled up in 1910.210 This
explains the changing of the ‘mutant’ allele category to allow plurality; it does not
immediately appear to explain the supplanting of the ‘normal’ allele by ‘wild-type’. One
explanation may have been that the Batesonian system was founded on normativity and that
this normativity tended (despite Bateson’s arguable intentions) to act dualistically, i.e. placing
individuals into either a ‘normal’, ‘healthy’ category or into an alternative ‘abnormal’, ‘sick’
category into which all mutants were lumped. Wild-type, by contrast, does not necessarily
operate normatively; as long as ‘type’ is not interpreted in essentialist terms, it can merely
refer to typicality, i.e. what is encountered in general experience. Mutants are by nature
exceptional, allowing a meaningful distinction between them and the commonplace wildtype. By treating them as empirical exceptions instead of normative dissonance, the new
system moreover can be seen to have removed mutants from their previous association with
pathology, which segued with Morgan’s own evolutionary theories which treated mutation as
the arising of new variation with independent norms, not as deviation from a norm.211
A question here arises, however, as to what degree the replacement of ‘normal’ with ‘wildtype’ was really Morgan’s authorship. The book which in many ways can be said to have
institutionalised the use of wild-type in the terminology of the Drosophilists was 1915’s The
Mechanism of Mendelian Inheritance. By institutionalisation I mean that from this point on
wild-type appears to have always been favoured, though not exclusively so, over ‘normal
type’ and other competing labels. ‘Normal type’ is used once in this book.212 ‘Wild type’, in
contrast, is used 18 times.213 Such clear terminological favouritism is not at all evident in
Morgan’s writings of the preceding five years. He instead uses a variety of synonyms and
near-synonyms, such as ‘wild’,214 ‘wild stock’215 and ‘normal type’.216 ‘Wild type’ does start
210
Robert E. Kohler, Lords of the Fly, The University of Chicago Press, 1994, pp. 46-7
Thomas Hunt Morgan, A Critique of the Theory of Evolution, Princeton University Press, 1916, pp. 87-8
212
Thomas Hunt Morgan, Alfred H. Sturtevant, Hermann J. Muller, & Calvin B. Bridges, The Mechanism of
Mendelian Inheritance, Henry Holt and Company, 1915, pp. 40
213
Ibid., pp. 8, 9, 16, 25, 31, 57, 84, 149, 154, 159, 160, 168, 219 – Repeated usage in pp. 160 (twice), 168
(thrice) & 219 (thrice)
214
Thomas Hunt Morgan, ‘Sex Limited Inheritance in Drosophila’, Science, New Series, Vol. 32, No. 812,
1910, pp. 121 & Thomas Hunt Morgan, ‘No Crossing over in the Male of Drosophila of Genes in the Second
and Third Pairs of Chromosomes’, Biological Bulletin, Vol. 26, No. 4, 1914, pp. 201-3
215
Thomas Hunt Morgan, ‘The Origin of Nine Wing Mutations in Drosophila’, Science, New Series, Vol. 33,
No. 848, pp. 498-9, Thomas Hunt Morgan, ‘The Origin of Five Mutations in Eye Color in Drosophila and Their
Modes of Inheritance’, Science, New Series, Vol. 33, No. 849, pp. 536, & Thomas Hunt Morgan & Sabra Colby
Tice, ‘The Influence of the Environment on the Size of Expected Classes’, Biological Bulletin, Vol. 26, No. 4,
1914, pp. 217
216
Thomas Hunt Morgan, ‘Simplicity Versus Adequacy in Mendelian Formulae’, The American Naturalist, Vol.
47, No. 558, 1913, pp. 374
211
~ Page 46 ~
appearing in 1912 in the paper ‘The Linkage of Two Factors in Drosophila That are not SexLinked’, and then in 1914’s ‘Another Case of Multiple Allelomorphs in Drosophila’, but here
it is again used alongside synonyms such as ‘normal stock’.217 The mass prevalence of ‘wild
type’ in The Mechanism of Mendelian Inheritance may thus appear odd. However, it must be
stressed that this was a collaborative work between Morgan and his three pupils Alfred
Sturtevant, Hermann Muller and Calvin Bridges and the actual amount that Morgan
contributed to this project is unclear. Muller later claimed to have written Chapters 2, 8 and 9,
and it is in these chapters that use of ‘wild type’ clusters (10 out of 18 instances).218 Muller
may thus be considered the most likely candidate from amongst the Drosophilists to have
pushed for the institutionalisation of wild-type as a substitute for ‘normal type’.
Muller’s motives for wanting such a linguistic shift likely had their origins in his own
conception of variation within species in the wild. These beliefs differed substantially from
those of Morgan, Muller believing that an optimising natural selection tends to render
heterozygosity very rare in nature as optimal genes are always most optimal in a homozygous
state.219 For Muller it was thus very much meaningful to speak of wild-type as a real category
in the world, whereas Morgan regarded it as an instrumental bracket into which individuals
may be shuffled in and out according to what kind of variation is being experimentally
investigated. Muller’s views cannot be said to be representative of the Drosophilists as a
whole, who were in any case a very heterogeneous group, with differing theoretical and
philosophical attitudes that on occasion spilled over into antagonism,220 differences only held
together by a shared model organism, shared projects and a shared social etiquette.221
Nonetheless, Muller’s realist interpretation of wild-type proved to be highly influential and
helped in the post-war period found the ‘classical’ view of population genetics.222 The
opposing ‘balance’ school was led by another Drosophilist, Theodosius Dobzhansky, and his
Thomas Hunt Morgan & Clara J. Lynch, ‘The Linkage of Two Factors in Drosophila That are not SexLinked’, Biological Bulletin, Vol. 23, No. 3, 1912, pp. 176, & Thomas Hunt Morgan, ‘Another Case of Multiple
Allelomorphs in Drosophila’, Biological Bulletin, Vol. 26, No. 4, 1914, pp. 231-2
218
Nils Roll-Hansen, ‘Drosophila Genetics: A Reductionist Research Program’, Journal of the History of
Biology, Vol. 11, No. 1, 1978, pp. 190
219
John Beatty, ‘Weighing the Risks: Stalemate in the Classical/Balance Controversy’, Journal of the History of
Biology, Vol. 20, No. 3, 1987, pp. 291
220
Nils Roll-Hansen, ‘Drosophila Genetics: A Reductionist Research Program’, Journal of the History of
Biology, Vol. 11, No. 1, 1978, pp. 165
221
Robert E. Kohler, Lords of the Fly, The University of Chicago Press, 1994, pp.91-2
222
John Beatty, ‘Weighing the Risks: Stalemate in the Classical/Balance Controversy’, Journal of the History of
Biology, Vol. 20, No. 3, 1987, pp. 289-91
217
~ Page 47 ~
view of wild-type as an unreal category merely “convenient for descriptive purposes” was
arguably much closer to Morgan’s own interpretation of it.223
CONCLUSION
Muller and Dobzhansky, whatever the importance of their debates for the concept of wildtype, lie, however, outside of my focus group for this essay, the early Mendelians. That I here
draw a line and exclude them from detailed analysis is, moreover, motivated by their being of
a different scientific generation to the four men this essay has concentrated on, one which
grew up with the concrete successes of genetics and was not educated in the culture of
sceptical empiricism and instrumentalism which pervaded the late nineteenth century life
sciences.224 If I maintain my concentration on the early Mendelians as opposed to the
generation that succeeded them, those ‘born-into-genetics-ists’, what can I say regarding their
ideas of species, variation and environment and how these ideas influenced their conception
of wild-type?
Regarding species, the only one of the four whose ideas can really be said to be ‘typological’
is de Vries, who not only considered species constant and restricted in form but also as
unchanging in time, even across geological epochs. Even given this, however, his beliefs are
more nuanced than later historians such as Mayr would have us believe, as he does not
consider ‘systematic species’ to be real entities and denies they have a type, only attributing a
type to the smaller elementary species from which systematic ones are composed. De Vries’
eclectic position should arguably not be seen as directly related to the eighteenth century
systematists and their attempts to isolate unchanging original specific characters, as might be
argued by those who see him as an essentialist, but rather be considered as an attempt to relegitimise varieties as an object of science by claiming them to be the true fundamental units
of nature. Of the other three early Mendelians, Morgan might be expected to be closest to de
Vries, but he is in fact outspokenly anti-type, considers individuals to be the true units of
nature and asserts that taxa are actually artificial construction humans impose on nature.
Morgan is thus actually closer to Bateson, who similarly considers species mere aggregates of
individuals and who, whilst emphasising that, due to the discontinuous nature of
Theodosius Dobzhansky, ‘Recombination and Variability in Populations of Drosophila pseudoobscura’,
Dobzhansky’s Genetics of Natural Populations I – XLIII, Richard C. Lewontin, John A. Moore, William B.
Provine & Bruce Wallace (eds.), Columbia University Press, 1981, pp. 446
224
Nils Roll-Hansen, ‘Drosophila Genetics: A Reductionist Research Program’, Journal of the History of
Biology, Vol. 11, No. 1, 1978, pp. 159-61
223
~ Page 48 ~
physiological variation, Specific groups are identifiable from amongst the diversity of life,
stresses that the nature of these differences may change over time, adopting what may be
termed a ‘presentist’ view of species contrasting de Vries’ permanentism. Castle is the most
adamantly anti-type of the four, considering it not so much a human idea imposed on nature
as a delusion, but even so he is actually not as far removed from Morgan and Bateson as
typically presented (Morgan’s closeness here to Castle’s position, which was especially so
before 1910, is illustrated by the glowing review Morgan gave of Heredity of Coat
Characters in Guinea Pigs and Rabbits based on its evidence for factor inconstancy).225
As to variation, all four admit the existence of both discontinuous and continuous variation
but differently interpret their nature and contribution to evolutionary change. Castle is
admittedly alone in believing continuous variation to be the main cause of evolution, de Vries
and Morgan both agreeing that such ‘fluctuating’ variation does not produce anything new
and Bateson believing that whilst such fluctuations can shift species norms, discontinuous
variations are the major source of speciation. The latter three all assert mutations to be
normatively independent from their parent-type, but whereas de Vries assumes all members
of an elementary species share the same unit-characters, being individuated only by
fluctuation, Bateson and Morgan both favour considerably greater variation within a species
and, like Castle, recognise that some ‘normal’ species characteristics can actually be
composite, being either heterozygous conditions or the product of multiple factors. Morgan
also shares with Castle a recognition that norms of species and inheritance can often only be
taken to be mathematical means to which no further reality can be attributed without falling
into speculation. All parties recognise the implications that Mendelism has for the
‘traditional’ conception of atavism as the effect of ancestral heredity, but full rejection of
ancestral influence is not forthcoming in Morgan and Castle’s case, with the latter going as
far as to distinguish ancestral traits from the ‘extracted’ traits reproduced in their descendants
after crossing. Castle also is critical of the use of mere resemblance as a guide to identifying
membership of a type (e.g. a wild-type), as he believes superficial appearances can obscure
hidden physiological variety. Finally, neither Bateson or Castle provide detailed accounts
regarding how variation can result in speciation, but this is the crux of a major difference
between de Vries and Morgan. Both believe mutations are periodic, with constancy the norm,
but de Vries believes that they are ‘scattering’ in all physio-morphological directions, and
225
Thomas Hunt Morgan, Review: [untitled], Reviewed work(s): Heredity of Coat Characters in Guinea Pigs
and Rabbits by W. E. Castle, Science, New Series, Vol. 21, No. 541, 1905, pp. 737-738
~ Page 49 ~
tends to stress large changes, whereas Morgan prefers a directional mutation account
whereby smaller mutations can accumulate and reinforce a move in a particular evolutionary
trajectory.
The interpretation of the effect of the environment upon species and variation is notably
considered by all four early Mendelians to be relatively minor. Even Castle, the archDarwinian among them, appears to support a ‘neutralist’ interpretation of evolution wherein
factors can change in very slight manners gradually over time without incurring any
significant selective pressures. He does believe in selection’s having creative power and
thought himself to have demonstrated evidence of this with his hooded rats, but even so it
does not appear that Castle though selection to be the omnipresent, omnipotent force that
Wallace and Weismann, for example, believed it to be. Bateson and Morgan are highly
critical of such pan-selectionism and de Vries, though believing natural selection a powerful
enough force to weed out most mutants, shares with them a view of it as a wholly negative,
uncreative process which simply ‘sieves’ through independently engendered variation. De
Vries and Morgan do believe, unlike Bateson, for whom variation is wholly physiologically
caused, that environmental pressures can trigger mutation periods, but believe that these must
be quite extraordinary in order to do so. Regarding the contribution of the environment
towards wild-type, de Vries considers it a matter of viability (the ill-adapted cannot establish
themselves as wild-types) and Bateson and Morgan believe it a case of the environment
determining the ‘mode’ of a species, but that this modality does not constitute a permanent,
evolutionary change but merely shifts with climatic change. Castle believes there may be real
differences between domestic and wild organisms, but not in terms of a ‘type’. He does not,
moreover, consider it inappropriate to substitute a wild with a domestic animal in an
experiment. Morgan, on the other hand, can see why this might be thought problematic, and
is moreover highly aware that some variation is hidden outside of certain environments,
which inspires some caution when extrapolating findings. He defends the extension of results
gathered in the artificial environment of the laboratory to theorising about wild populations
on purely instrumental grounds, namely that there is no other way to gather such information.
The laboratory environment is thus acknowledged by Morgan as an invaluable tool for
studying genetics, but he recognises the need to when possible approximate by using
subjects, conditions and instruments that can ‘stand in’ for wild ones, an example of which is
of course ‘wild-type’ strains of domesticated Drosophila.
~ Page 50 ~
Methodologically, all four early Mendelians appear to be strong empiricists, as is evident in
Bateson’s pursuit of exceptions, Castle’s willingness to acknowledge his being wrong and
Morgan’s similar openness to unexpected results (his discovery of associative sex-limited
characters, for example, pushed him from scepticism regarding the theory that chromosomes
contain hereditary material to advocacy).226 De Vries too sought a strong evidential basis for
his theory but in the end was largely forced to depend on his flawed studies of Oenothera.
His willingness to stick with a poorly supported theory may in part have been due to his
having a different background to the others, being influenced by reductio-mechanist accounts
of biology which may well have encouraged theorising to a greater extent than the sceptical
empiricism Bateson and Morgan were educated in. This background also explains de Vries’
search for ‘real units’ in nature, whereas Bateson, Morgan and Castle were satisfied with
provisional units and useful categories, in part because they were not certain whether they
would ever truly find anything more ‘real’. Bateson and Morgan’s methodologies were also
considerably more exploratory than de Vries’, both geneticists utilising a broad base of model
organisms in order to conduct their research. Castle was more of a specialist, working as he
did mainly with small mammals, but he also utilised birds and amphibians and may be
considered as following the same research spirit as Bateson and Morgan.227 All in all,
genetics was new scientific territory and its pioneers could not afford to restrict themselves to
particular organisms or areas of study without the threat of tunnel vision, as the boundaries of
phenomena had not yet been established. De Vries was an unfortunate victim of such
narrowed vision, as choosing the atypical evening-primrose as his model organism prevented
him from elaborating a theory that could successfully be applied across taxa, so that
consequently many of his observations had little general biological scope.
What becomes clear from this brief comparison of my four early Mendelians is that their
interpretations of wild-type do not fit easily into either the pre-genetic conception of it or
later interpretations. Certainly they played a key role in establishing its new relationships
within a novel epistemological framework, notably by placing it as contrasted with mutants
as opposed to its former atavism-mediated status as the point to which domestic breeds
returned if artificial selection was withdrawn. Furthermore, rather than being a lurking
influence within the ancestry of a variety, wild-type became itself a strictly bred lineage, it
and mutant lines being treated as related but possessing independent norms. What the early
226
227
Elof Axel Carlson, The Gene: A Critical History, W.B. Saunders Company, 1966, pp. 45-7
Robert E. Kohler, Lords of the Fly, The University of Chicago Press, 1994, pp. 27
~ Page 51 ~
Mendelians did not promote, with the exception of de Vries, was the interpretation of wildtype as a realist category, it being instead a convenient label and way of dividing up the new
world of genetics. Realist interpretations only arose with the succeeding generations of
geneticists who, having taken part in or seen the success of the chromosome linkage project
in granting the gene a material, structural and locational reality, were less inclined towards
scepticism as to the reality of the ontological categories which their predecessors had largely
drafted as stop-gap solutions in the absence of knowledge of the true nature of the role of
species, variation and environment in heredity and evolution.
Bibliography
Anonymous, ‘Botany’, The American Naturalist, Vol. 21, No. 6, 1887
Bailey, L. H., ‘Whence came the Cultivated Strawberry’, The American Naturalist, Vol. 28,
No. 328, 1894
Bateson, William, Materials for the Study of Variation treated with Especial Regard for to
Discontinuity in the Origin of Species, Macmillan and Co., 1894
Bateson, William, ‘Facts Limiting the Theory of Heredity’, Science, New Series, Vol. 26, No.
672, 1907
Bateson, William, The Methods and Scope of Genetics, Cambridge University Press, 1908
Bateson, William, Mendel’s Principles of Heredity, Cambridge University Press, 1909
Bateson, William, Problems of Genetics, Yale University Press, 1913
Beatty, John, ‘Weighing the Risks: Stalemate in the Classical/Balance Controversy’, Journal
of the History of Biology, Vol. 20, No. 3, 1987
Brooker, Robert J., Genetics: Analysis and Principles, 2nd Ed., The McGraw-Hill Companies
Inc., 2005
Carlson, Elof Axel, The Gene: A Critical History, W.B. Saunders Company, 1966
Castle, William E., ‘Mendel’s Law of Heredity’, Science, New Series, Vol. 18, No. 456, 1903
Castle, William E., Heredity of Coat Characters in Guinea-pigs and Rabbits, the Carnegie
Institute of Washington, 1905
Castle, William E., ‘On a Case of Reversion Induced by Cross-Breeding and its Fixation’,
Science, New Series, Vol. 25, No. 630, 1907
Castle, William E., Heredity in Relation to Evolution and Animal Breeding, D. Appleton and
Company, 1911
~ Page 52 ~
Castle, William E., ‘The Inconstancy of Unit-Characters’, The American Naturalist, Vol. 46,
No. 546, 1912
Castle, William E., ‘Is Selection or Mutation the More Important Agent in Evolution’, The
Scientific Monthly, Vol. 2, No. 1, 1916
Castle, William E., ‘Piebald Rats and the Theory of Genes’, Proceedings of the National
Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, Vol. 5, No. 4, 1919
Darwin, Charles, On the Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection, or the
Preservation of Favoured Races in the Struggle for Life, Penguin Classics, 2009
de Vries, Hugo, ‘The Origin of Species by Mutation’, Science, New Series, Vol. 15, No. 384,
1902
de Vries, Hugo, Species and Varieties: Their Origin by Mutation, MacDougal, Daniel
Trembly (ed.), The Open Court Publishing Company, 1905
Dobzhansky, Theodosius, ‘Recombination and Variability in Populations of Drosophila
pseudoobscura’, Dobzhansky’s Genetics of Natural Populations I – XLIII, Lewontin, Richard
C., Moore, John A., Provine, William B. & Wallace, Bruce (eds.), Columbia University
Press, 1981
Fleck, Ludwik, Genesis and Development of a Scientific Fact, Bradley, Fred and Trenn,
Thaddeus J. (trans.), The University of Chicago Press, 1981
Gayon, Jean, ‘The Philosophical History of the Concept of Heredity’, The Concept of the
Gene in Development and Evolution, Beurton, Peter J., Falk, Raphael, & Rheinberger, HansJörg (eds.), Cambridge University Press, 2000
Gould, Stephen Jay, The Structure of Evolutionary Theory, The Belknap Press of Harvard
University Press, 2002
Griffiths, Anthony J.F., Gelbart, William M., Miller, Jeffrey H., & Lewontin, Richard C.,
Modern Genetic Analysis, W.H. Freeman and Company, 1999
Hacking, Ian, Representing and Intervening: Introductory Topics in the Philosophy of
Natural Science, Cambridge University Press, 1983
Hartl, Daniel L., & Orel, Vitezslav, ‘What Did Gregor Mendel Think He Discovered?’,
Genetics, Vol. 131, 1992
Kohler, Robert E., Lords of the Fly, The University of Chicago Press, 1994
Mayr, Ernst, The Growth of Biological Thought: Diversity, Evolution and Inheritance, The
Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 1982
~ Page 53 ~
Morange, Michel, ‘The Developmental Gene Concept: History and Limits’, The Concept of
the Gene in Development and Evolution, Beurton, Peter J., Falk, Raphael, & Rheinberger,
Hans-Jörg (eds.), Cambridge University Press, 2000
Morgan, Thomas Hunt, Evolution and Adaptation, The Macmillan Company, 1903
Morgan, Review: [untitled], Reviewed work(s): Heredity of Coat Characters in Guinea Pigs
and Rabbits by W. E. Castle, Science, New Series, Vol. 21, No. 541, 1905
Morgan, Thomas Hunt, ‘What are “Factors” in Mendelian Explanations?’, American
Breeders Association Reports, Vol. 5, 1909
Morgan, Thomas Hunt, ‘Sex Limited Inheritance in Drosophila’, Science, New Series, Vol.
32, No. 812, 1910
Morgan, Thomas Hunt, ‘Factors and Unit Characters in Mendelian Heredity’, The American
Naturalist, Vol. 47, No. 553, 1913
Morgan, Thomas Hunt, ‘Simplicity Versus Adequacy in Mendelian Formulae’, The American
Naturalist, Vol. 47, No. 558, 1913
Morgan, Thomas Hunt, ‘Another Case of Multiple Allelomorphs in Drosophila’, Biological
Bulletin, Vol. 26, No. 4, 1914
Morgan, Thomas Hunt, ‘No Crossing over in the Male of Drosophila of Genes in the Second
and Third Pairs of Chromosomes’, Biological Bulletin, Vol. 26, No. 4, 1914
Morgan, Thomas Hunt, A Critique of the Theory of Evolution, Princeton University Press,
1916
Morgan, Thomas Hunt & Lynch, Clara J., ‘The Linkage of Two Factors in Drosophila That
are not Sex-Linked’, Biological Bulletin, Vol. 23, No. 3, 1912
Morgan, Thomas Hunt & Tice, Sabra Colby, ‘The Influence of the Environment on the Size
of Expected Classes’, Biological Bulletin, Vol. 26, No. 4, 1914
Morgan, Thomas Hunt, Sturtevant, Alfred H., Muller, Hermann J., & Bridges, Calvin B., The
Mechanism of Mendelian Inheritance, Henry Holt and Company, 1915
Müller-Wille, Staffan, ‘Gardens of Paradise’, Endeavour, Vol. 25, No. 2, 2001
Müller-Wille, Staffan, ‘Collection and collation: theory and practice of Linnaean botany’,
Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of
Biological and Biomedical Sciences, Volume 38, Issue 3, 2007
Müller-Wille, Staffan, ‘Figures of Inheritance, 1650-1850’, Heredity Produced: At the
Crossroads of Biology, Politics, and Culture, 1500-1870, Müller-Wille, Staffan, &
Rheinberger, Hans-Jörg (eds.), The MIT Press, 2007
~ Page 54 ~
Müller-Wille, Staffan & Rheinberger, Hans-Jörg, ‘Heredity – The Formation of an Epistemic
Space’, Heredity Produced: At the Crossroads of Biology, Politics, and Culture, 1500-1870,
Müller-Wille, Staffan & Rheinberger, Hans-Jörg (eds.), The MIT Press, 2007
Olby, Robert, ‘The Dimensions of Scientific Controversy: The Biometric-Mendelian Debate’,
The British Journal for the History of Science, Vol. 22, No. 3, Genetics, Eugenics and
Evolution: A Special Issue in Commemoration of Bernard Norton (1945-1984), 1989
Olby, Robert, The Path to the Double Helix: The Discovery of DNA, Dover Publications Inc.,
1994
Peterson, Erik L., ‘William Bateson from "Balanoglossus" to "Materials for the Study of
Heredity": The Transatlantic Roots of Discontinuity and the (Un)naturalness of Selection’,
Journal of the History of Biology, Vol. 41, No. 2, 2008
Ratcliff, Marc J., ‘Duchesne’s Strawberries: Between Growers’ Practices and Academic
Knowledge’, Heredity Produced: At the Crossroads of Biology, Politics, and Culture, 15001870, Müller-Wille, Staffan & Rheinberger, Hans-Jörg (eds.), The MIT Press, 2007
Rheinberger, Hans-Jörg, ‘Gene Concepts: Fragments from the Perspective of Molecular
Biology’, The Concept of the Gene in Development and Evolution, Beurton, Peter J., Falk,
Raphael, & Rheinberger, Hans-Jörg (eds.), Cambridge University Press, 2000
Roll-Hansen, Nils, ‘Drosophila Genetics: A Reductionist Research Program’, Journal of the
History of Biology, Vol. 11, No. 1, 1978
Westropp, Hodder M., ‘On the Sequence of the Phases of Civilisation, and Contemporaneous
Implements’, Journal of the Anthropological Society of London, Vol. 5, 1867
Wood, Roger J., ‘The Sheep Breeders’ View of Heredity Before and After 1800’, Heredity
Produced: At the Crossroads of Biology, Politics, and Culture, 1500-1870, Staffan MüllerWille & Hans-Jörg Rheinberger (eds.), The MIT Press, 2007
~ Page 55 ~
Download