1AC Plan Text: The United States should legalize physician assisted suicide by granting all those with terminal illnesses the constitutional right to undergo pre-mortem cryopreservation. Reanimation Adv Rapidly advancing cryopreservation technology can be a genuine solution to the suffering of millions, unfortunately restrictions on euthanasia obstruct the physicians ability to adequately vitrify the body and brain- legalizing cryothanasia would optimize the chances for successful reanimation Zoltan Istvan 08/21/2014 "Should Cryonics, Cryothanasia, and Transhumanism Be Part of the Euthanasia Debate?" http://www.huffingtonpost.com/zoltan-istvan/should-cryonics-cryocide_b_5518684.html Zoltan Istvan is a bestselling author and graduate of Columbia University An elderly man named Bill sits in a lonely Nevada nursing home, staring out the window. The sun is fading from the sky, and night will soon cover the surrounding windswept desert. Bill has late-onset Alzheimer's disease, and the plethora of medications he's on is losing the war to keep his mind intact. Soon, he will lose control of many of his cognitive functions, will forget many of his memories, and will no longer recognize friends and family. Approximately 40 million people around the world have some form of dementia, according to a World Health Organization report. About 70 percent of those suffer from Alzheimer's. With average lifespans increasing due to rapidly improving longevity science, what are people with these maladies to do? Do those with severe cases want to be kept alive for years or even decades in a debilitated mental state just because modern medicine can do it? In parts of Europe and a few states in America where assisted suicide--sometimes referred to as euthanasia or physician aid in dying--is allowed, some mental illness sufferers decide to end their lives while they're still cognitively sound and can recognize their memories and personality. However, most people around the world with dementia are forced to watch their minds deteriorate. Families and caretakers of dementia patients are often dramatically affected too. Watching a loved one slowly loose their cognitive functions and memories is one of the most challenging and painful predicaments anyone can ever go through. Exorbitant finances further complicate the matter because it's expensive to provide proper care for the mentally ill. In the 21st Century--the age of transhumanism and brilliant scientific achievement--the question should be asked: Are there other ways to approach this sensitive issue? The transhumanist field of cryonics--using ultra-cold temperatures to preserve a dead body in hopes of future revival-has come a long way since the first person was frozen in 1967. Various organizations and companies around the world have since preserved a few hundred people. Over a thousand people are signed up to be frozen in the future, and many millions of people are aware of the procedure. Some may say cryonics is crackpot science. However, those accusations are unfounded. Already, human beings can be revived and go on to live normal lives after being frozen in water for over an hour. Additionally, suspended animation is now occurring in a university hospital in Pittsburgh, where a saline-cooling solution has recently been approved by the FDA to preserve the clinically dead for hours before resuscitating them. In a decade's time, this procedure may be used to keep people suspended for a week or a month before waking them. Clearly, the medical field of preserving the dead for possible future life is quickly improving every year. The trick with cryonics is preserving someone immediately after they've died . Otherwise, critical organs, especially the brain and its billions of neurons, have a far higher chance of being damaged in the freezing. However, it's almost impossible to cryonically freeze someone right after death. Circumstances usually get in the way of an ideal suspension. Bodies must first be brought to a cryonics facility. Most municipalities require technicians, doctors, and a funeral director to legally sign off on a body before it can be cryonically preserved. All this takes time, and minutes are precious once the last heartbeat and breath of air have been made by a cryonics candidate. Recently, some transhumanists have advocated for cryothanasia, where a patient undergoes physician or selfadministered euthanasia with the intent of being cryonically suspended during the death process or immediately afterward. This creates the optimum environment since all persons involved are on hand and ready to do their part so that an ideal freeze can occur. Cryothanasia could be utilized for a number of people and situations: the atheist Alzheimer's sufferer who doesn't believe in an afterlife and wants science to give him another chance in the future; the suicidal schizophrenic who doesn't want to exist in the current world, but isn't ready to give up altogether on existence; the terminally ill transhumanist cancer patient who doesn't want to lose half their body weight and undergo painful chemotherapy before being cryonically frozen; or the extreme special needs or disabled person who wants to come back in an age where their disabilities can be fixed. There might even be spiritual, religious, or philosophical reasons for pursuing an impermanent death, as in my novel The Transhumanist Wager, where protagonist Jethro Knights undergoes cryothanasia in search of a lost loved one. There are many sound reasons why someone might choose cryothanasia. Whoever the person and whatever the reason, there is a belief that life can be better for them in some future time. Some experts believe we will begin reanimating cryonically frozen patients in 25 to 50 years. Technologies via bioengineering, nanomedicine, and mind uploading will likely lead the way. Hundreds of millions of dollars are being spent on developing these technologies that will also create breakthroughs for the field of cryonics and other areas of suspended animation. Another advantage about cryonics and cryothanasia is their affordability. It costs about $1,000 to painlessly euthanize oneself and an average of $80,000 to cryonically freeze one's body. It costs many times more than that to keep someone alive who is suffering from a serious mental disorder and needs constant 24-hour a day care over many years. Despite some of the positive possibilities, cryothanasia is virtually unknown to people and is often technically illegal in many places around the world . Of course, much discussion would have to take place in private, public, and political circles in order to determine if cryothanasia has a valid place in society. Nevertheless, cryothanasia represents an original way for dementia sufferers and others to consider now that they are living far longer than ever before. Technological avenues for immortality are forthcoming and cryonic reanimation is the key ingredient - brain uploading could be feasible as early as 2025 Marcus Edwards 2012 "The Path to Immortality" http://wiki.eyewire.org/en/The_Path_to_Immortality Edwards is a contributor for the EyeWire project, a game to developed to help Sebastian Seung's Lab at MIT map the brain. Eyewire has grown to over 150,000 players from 140+ countries. It often seems that man is on an unending journey to escape death. From the immortality potions of ancient China to modern scientific endeavors, it may appear as if we are fighting a losing battle. Even with the current developments in medicine and biology, we have been unable to achieve any sense of immortality. Though the life expectancy of people living in developed countries has risen dramatically in the last two hundred years, none have yet eluded death. But imagine for a moment a process for prolonging the human life expectancy from age 76 to eternity. Would this be possible? The answer may lie in the field of cryonics. Cryonics is dedicated to freezing the human body to extremely low temperatures with the hopes that they may one day be revived by some future technology. What interests me in particular is not the cryopreservation of the body, but of the brain. Not surprisingly, the preservation of the brain is known as neuropreservation. After reading Connectome, I asked myself if merely preserving the brain would similarly preserve the connectome— the theoretical home of memories, consciousness and personality. Like many before me, I am enthralled with the possibility of achieving immortality, though I still have some reservations about achieving this through neuropreservation. The technologies to freeze the brain have existed for decades, but how to revive the brain from the inevitable damage that results from freezing it for long periods of time has never been achieved. The world’s leading cryopreservation company, Alcor, may have an answer. Alcor was founded in 1977, and since then has become the foremost authority on cryonics. The company is currently researching new methods of freezing the bodies of clients so that they may withstand eternity, but many of their scientists believe full-body storage is not necessary. Like Dr. Seung, these researchers believe that the brain is the home of human identity. This mindset has created a new division of cryonics: “The Neuropreservation Option.” This has become the most popular option since its inception, as many clients have come to believe that the preservation of the brain preserves the personality and the soul. Not surprisingly, it is also much more affordable to preserve a brain than an entire body. Since the cryopreservation process lasts long after the legal death of the clients, they are required to pay the full amount in advance. Alcor currently charges $200,000 for a full-body preservation while neuropreservation costs less than half that; still a pricey $80,000. But is the cost worth it? If the human brain can be revived, there are still many unknown factors. How will the brain be repaired? What body will the brain occupy? Will the society that greets you even want you back? As for repairing the brain, one solution has already been proposed. Nanotechnology has grown substantially in recent years, and many proponents of neuropreservation argue that nanobots, minuscule robots designed for a specific function, may provide a solution. Nanobots are not yet advanced enough to be able to repair such delicate brain tissue. However, advancements in the future may eventually lead to just that. While many forms of nanotechnology are currently in the research and development phase, progress in the field will likely allow for more advanced procedures. Scientists at Harvard and MIT have been able to specifically target cells with nanobots filled with chemotherapy chemicals. This drastically reduced the damage done by the chemotherapy chemicals typically caused by imprecise delivery methods. In spite of these seemingly miraculous possibilities, I often wonder if there is any point. In Connectome, Dr. Seung posed the question: Does cryogenically preserving a brain similarly preserve the connectome? If not, then it may be futile to maintain frozen brains. Assuming his hypothesis that the neural connections are where consciousness resides, damage to the connectome would result in an irreversible loss of personality. But if the connectome is preserved by the extreme cold, neuropreservation could one day be a viable means of achieving an undetermined life span. Even if the connectome endures, another problem exists. The brain may physically house identity, but it has little purpose without some body to aid its function. Researchers have proposed several solutions to this problem. Recently, media sources have advertised cloning as a method for giving the brain a body. There is no fear of rejection because the cells and DNA of the clone would be identical to the brain in storage, but this raises many ethical questions: Suppose a client walks into Alcor asking for a neuropreservation. He pays the fee, lives for several more years and then dies. His brain is sent to an Alcor facility where it is frozen. Over a century from now, his brain is revitalized using nanobots then placed inside a clone that was created specifically for that purpose. His brain is successfully implanted and he lives a successful life until he dies and the process begins again. I have several problems with this proposal. What would happen to the clone that was raised simply for the purpose of becoming a vessel? The line between what legal rights a clone would have compared to a “normal” human is far too blurry to become practical across the world. Indeed, members of Alcor claimed that cloning is a “crude” method of providing the brain with a body and that a “more elegant means” must be achieved. It may not seem elegant, but far less crude than the cloning option is growing an entire body around the rejuvenated brain. Much like a zygote rapidly multiplies into an infant, a body could be grown around the brain. Imagine using bioengineered catalysts and reactions to facilitate the growth of an entire body around the actual brain. A person could be “born” much like a child, the only difference being that an adult body grows instead. The brain—and presumably the identity—of the patient would already be preserved, so a spine would have to be created around the brain, forming the intricate neural connections that make life possible. In spite of what many researchers at Alcor may think, the path to immortality may not be so complex (from a biological perspective). In Connectome, Dr. Seung also proposed the idea of mapping connectomes, uploading that information to a microprocessor and using that information to achieve digital immortality . Many of the technologies to achieve this extraordinary feat are already in place . Microchips are relatively cheap and are expected to be able to process the amount of information a human brain contains by the year 2025. This could mean that mapping connectomes with increasingly advanced imaging techniques could automate the process, leaving it entirely up to computers. Connectomes could eventually be mapped with unprecedented speed, meaning that any human could have his identity recorded on a microchip when they die, then have it transferred to a computer program prolonging his life indefinitely. While many of the ideas I proposed are only in their beginning stages, the technologies involved are advancing rapidly. Perhaps in the future scientists will look back at us, wondering why we ever believed it was impossible to live forever, just as we question those pessimists who believed that a journey to the moon would never be within our grasp. Dr. Ralph Merkle, inventor of public key cryptography, once said “Cryonics is an experiment. So far the control group isn’t doing that well.” He knew as well as any other that no one has a chance to escape death without trying, and optimism is necessary to keep the spirit of such dreams alive. One day, not too far off, we may scoff at death, knowing that we are not bound to our current biological forms. Whether it be through microchips, cryonics, or some distant technology of the future, we may all hope to walk the path of immortality, carefully treading in a realm once thought to be reserved for the gods alone. The transition to a postmortal society will be smooth and collective R. Michael Perry 2000 "Forever For All: Moral Philosophy, Cryonics, and the Scientific Prospects of Immortality" http://www.foreverforall.org/pdfs/foreverforall.pdf Perry graduated from the University of Chicago in 1969 with a B.S. in Mathematics. He earned a M.S. in Computer Science from Colorado University in 1979 and a Ph.D. in Computer Science from the same institution in 1984. One positive change will involve an attitude toward fellow beings . Today the thought is often expressed that we are primarily machines to perpetuate our genes. The concerns of such beings are focused in rather obvious ways by natural selection, with the emphasis on im-mediate survival needs, mating, and progeny. This we have carried with us, thus far having no choice, even though our lifestyles have been modified greatly by our creation of civilization. Even so, the outlook is not so bleak--the roots of an immortal lifestyle can be seen in our world today, where we are still as we biologically evolved. Despite the pressures to develop a narrowness of interests and an unconcern for strangers, we have formed into societies. We at least pay nodding respect to such concepts as the rights to life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness. Nature has, in fact, prepared us somewhat for the great leap we must now make, though we will have to take the initiative and work beyond the easy answers.¶ For the posthuman future we can imagine that consideration of others will intensify , for simple reasons of self-interest. When we are no longer focused on creating progeny during a brief struggle for existence that must soon end in our demise but on leading rich and hopefully endless lives, our perspectives will broaden. Among other things, we may conjecture that any two individuals must encounter each other again and again, or develop some pathological mutual aversion that will detract from both lives. It should become increas-ingly clear that there is much to gain, personally, through considera-tion for others and acts of benevolence. In this way, then, I foresee a postmortal society that is a harmonious whole, strife and violence having given way to more reasoned interaction.¶ The increased consideration for others should carry over to others of the past who might be resuscitated from a preserved state. It is easy to feel a certain fascination with such an idea even now. I think this feeling will be strong, at least for some people in the future, and probably for most if not all. The generally increased valuing of life must surely translate to concern for those who cannot now participate but could be helped to participate, given the means available. Persons of the past would have unique contributions to make in the lives of those then living, which should hold a special interest. This should be true even if such persons would initially be out of place; they could offer their own perspectives and perceptions in exchange for the new¶ learning they would receive.¶ I think too that resuscitating frozen people, to the extent that it becomes possible, will also be inexpensive by future standards. This seems particularly likely when the possibilities for automation are taken into account. With operations directed by devices that are largely self-repairing and self-maintaining and can proliferate com-ponents in vast swarms as needed (though only as needed), even very complex procedures should become feasible and fast. Included, I imagine, will be whatever is required to repair and resuscitate a fro-zen human. This should not be a great resource drain, though even if it is the chances are good that it will be carried out anyway. Immortality extends life's quantitative potential to infinity- brain uploading independently elevates its intrinsic value to unknown heights Nick Bostrom 2003 “Transhumanism FAQ” http://www.transhumanism.org/index.php/WTA/faq21/63/ Nick Bostrom is a Swedish philosopher at St. Cross College, University of Oxford known for his work on existential risk, the anthropic principle, human enhancement ethics, the reversal test, and consequentialism. He holds a PhD from the London School of Economics (2000). He is the founding director of both The Future of Humanity Institute and the Oxford Martin Programme on the Impacts of Future Technology as part of the Oxford Martin School at Oxford University. Uploading (sometimes called “downloading”, “mind uploading” or “brain reconstruction”) is the process of transferring an intellect from a biological brain to a computer. One way of doing this might be by first scanning the synaptic structure of a particular brain and then implementing the same computations in an electronic medium. A brain scan of sufficient resolution could be produced by disassembling the brain atom for atom by means of nanotechnology. Other approaches, such as analyzing pieces of the brain slice by slice in an electron microscope with automatic image processing have also been proposed. In addition to mapping the connection pattern among the 100 billion-or-so neurons, the scan would probably also have to register some of the functional properties of each of the synaptic interconnections, such as the efficacy of the connection and how stable it is over time (e.g. whether it is short-term or long-term potentiated). Non-local modulators such as neurotransmitter concentrations and hormone balances may also need to be represented, although such parameters likely contain much less data than the neuronal network itself. In addition to a good three-dimensional map of a brain, uploading will require progress in neuroscience to develop functional models of each species of neuron (how they map input stimuli to outgoing action potentials, and how their properties change in response to activity in learning). It will also require a powerful computer to run the upload, and some way for the upload to interact with the external world or with a virtual reality. (Providing input/output or a virtual reality for the upload appears easy in comparison to the other challenges.) An alternative hypothetical uploading method would proceed more gradually: one neuron could be replaced by an implant or by a simulation in a computer outside of the body. Then another neuron, and so on, until eventually the whole cortex has been replaced and the person’s thinking is implemented on entirely artificial hardware. (To do this for the whole brain would almost certainly require nanotechnology.) A distinction is sometimes made between destructive uploading, in which the original brain is destroyed in the process, and non-destructive uploading, in which the original brain is preserved intact alongside the uploaded copy. It is a matter of debate under what conditions personal identity would be preserved in destructive uploading. Many philosophers who have studied the problem think that at least under some conditions, an upload of your brain would be you. A widely accepted position is that you survive so long as certain information patterns are conserved, such as your memories, values, attitudes, and emotional dispositions, and so long as there is causal continuity so that earlier stages of yourself help determine later stages of yourself. Views differ on the relative importance of these two criteria, but they can both be satisfied in the case of uploading. For the continuation of personhood, on this view, it matters little whether you are implemented on a silicon chip inside a computer or in that gray, cheesy lump inside your skull, assuming both implementations are conscious. Tricky cases arise, however, if we imagine that several similar copies are made of your uploaded mind. Which one of them is you? Are they all you, or are none of them you? Who owns your property? Who is married to your spouse? Philosophical, legal, and ethical challenges abound. Maybe these will become hotly debated political issues later in this century. A common misunderstanding about uploads is that they would necessarily be “disembodied” and that this would mean that their experiences would be impoverished. Uploading according to this view would be the ultimate escapism, one that only neurotic body-loathers could possibly feel tempted by. But an upload’s experience could in principle be identical to that of a biological human. An upload could have a virtual (simulated) body giving the same sensations and the same possibilities for interaction as a non-simulated body. With advanced virtual reality, uploads could enjoy food and drink, and upload sex could be as gloriously messy as one could wish. And uploads wouldn’t have to be confined to virtual reality: they could interact with people on the outside and even rent robot bodies in order to work in or explore physical reality. Personal inclinations regarding uploading differ. Many transhumanists have a pragmatic attitude: whether they would like to upload or not depends on the precise conditions in which they would live as uploads and what the alternatives are. (Some transhumanists may also doubt whether uploading will be possible.) Advantages of being an upload would include: Uploads would not be subject to biological senescence. Back-up copies of uploads could be created regularly so that you could be re-booted if something bad happened. (Thus your lifespan would potentially be as long as the universe’s.) You could potentially live much more economically as an upload since you wouldn’t need physical food, housing, transportation, etc. If you were running on a fast computer, you would think faster than in a biological implementation. For instance , if you were running on a computer a thousand times more powerful than a human brain, then you would think a thousand times faste r (and the external world would appear to you as if it were slowed down by a factor of a thousand). You would thus get to experience more subjective time, and live more, during any given day. You could travel at the speed of light as an information pattern, which could be convenient in a future age of large-scale space settlements. Radical cognitive enhancements would likely be easier to implement in an upload than in an organic brain. Restricting an individual's right to life extension is akin to manslaughter Zoltan Istvan 01/31/2014"When Does Hindering Life Extension Science Become a Crime?" http://www.psychologytoday.com/blog/the-transhumanist-philosopher/201401/when-does-hinderinglife-extension-science-become-crime Zoltan Istvan is a bestselling author and graduate of Columbia University Every human being has both a minimum and a maximum amount of life hours left to live. If you add together the possible maximum life hours of every living person on the planet, you arrive at a special number: the optimum amount of time for our species to evolve, find happiness, and become the most that it can be. Many reasonable people feel we should attempt to achieve this maximum number of life hours for humankind . After all, very few people actually wish to prematurely die or wish for their fellow humans' premature deaths. In a free and functioning democratic society, it's the duty of our leaders and government to implement laws and social strategies to maximize these life hours that we want to safeguard. Regardless of ideological, political, religious, or cultural beliefs, we expect our leaders and government to protect our lives and ensure the maximum length of our lifespans. Any other behavior cuts short the time human beings have left to live. Anything else becomes a crime of prematurely ending human lives. Anything else fits the common legal term we have for that type of reprehensible behavior: criminal manslaughter. Biostatic time travel solves grief, death anxiety, and philosophical inquiry Charles Tandy 2009"Entropy and Immortality" Journal of Futures Studies, August 2009, 14(1): 39-50 http://www.jfs.tku.edu.tw/wp-content/uploads/2014/01/141-A03.pdf He is a Senior Faculty Research Fellow in Bioethics at Fooyin University's Research Center for Medical Humanities in Taiwan Perfection of future-directed time travel in the form of suspended-animation (biostasis) seems feasible in the 21st century.13 I believe it even seems feasible to eventually offer it freely to all who want it. Jared Diamond has pointed out that: " If most of the world's 6 billion people today were in cryogenic storage and neither eating, breathing, nor metabolizing, that large population would cause no environmental problems. "14 This might allow them to travel to an improved world in which they would be immortal. Since aging and all other diseases would have been conquered, they might not have to use time travel again unless they had an accident requiring future medical technology. But the ontoresurrection imperative demands more than immortality for those currently alive. In extraterrestrial space we can experiment (e.g. via Einsteinian or Gödelian past-directed time travel-viewing) with immortality for all persons no longer alive. Seg-communities (Self-sufficient Extra-terrestrial Greenhabitats, or O'Neill communities – e.g., see O'Neill, 2000) can assist us with our ordinary and terrestrial problems as well as assist us in completion of the onto-resurrection project. Indeed, in Al Gore's account of the global warming of our water planet, his parable of the frog is a central metaphor. Because the frog in the pot of water experiences only a gradual warming, the frog does not jump out. I add: Jumping off the water planet is now historically imperative. Indeed, it seems unwise to put all of our eggs (futures) into one basket (biosphere). I close with these words from Jacques Choron: "Only pleasant and personal immortality provides what still appears to many as the only effective defense against...death. But it is able to accomplish much more. It appeases the sorrow following the death of a loved one by opening up the possibility of a joyful reunion...It satisfies the sense of justice outraged by the premature deaths of people of great promise and talent, because only this kind of immortality offers the hope of fulfillment in another life. Finally, it offers an answer to the question of the ultimate meaning of life, particularly when death prompts the agonizing query [of Tolstoy], 'What is the purpose of this strife and struggle if, in the end, I shall disappear like a soap bubble?' Above it was shown that mental-reality and all-reality are dimensions of reality which are not altogether reducible to any strictly physical-scientific paradigm. A more believable (general-ontological) paradigm was presented. Within this framework, the issue of personal immortality was considered. It was concluded that the immortality project, as a physical-scientific common-task to resurrect all dead persons , is ethically imperative. The imperative includes as first steps the development of suspended-animation , superfast-rocketry, and seg-communities. Prefer expert consensus on cryonics Gregory Benford et al. 2005 "Scientists’ Open Letter on Cryonics" http://www.evidencebasedcryonics.org/scientists-open-letter-on-cryonics/, Benford is has Ph.D. in Physics from UC San Diego. He is also Professor of Physics at the University of California; Irvine, and 62 other Ph.D. signatories To whom it may concern, Cryonics is a legitimate science-based endeavor that seeks to preserve human beings, especially the human brain , by the best technology available. Future technologies for resuscitation can be envisioned that involve molecular repair by nanomedicine, highly advanced computation, detailed control of cell growth, and tissue regeneration. With a view toward these developments, there is a credible possibility that cryonics performed under the best conditions achievable today can preserve sufficient neurological information to permit eventual restoration of a person to full health. The rights of people who choose cryonics are important , and should be respected. Sincerely (63 Signatories) Transhumanism Adv Pre-mortem cryopreservation is inevitably going to be a question of PAS- drawing the legal 'death for life' distinction now will set a standard that endorses the discipline Ryan Sullivan 2011"Pre-Mortem Cryopreservation: Recognizing a Patient's Right to Die in Order to Live" http://www.quinnipiac.edu/prebuilt/pdf/SchoolLaw/HealthLawJournalLibrary/04_14QuinnipiacHealthLJ 49%282010-2011%29.pdf Sullivan is J.D. from the University of Nebraska, he received his masters from California University of Pennsylvania and bachelors from Colorado State University. A brief look at the massive compilation of scientific, biological and medical advancements of the last two centuries demonstrates that human ingenuity is limitless. Given enough time, it seems anything is possible, even the prospect of immortality . The science of low-temperature preservation has already become mainstream - used today to preserve blood, organs, and even human embryos. Recent developments in cryobiology and nanotechnology have converted cryonicists' once-abstract faith in future science into a tangible, achievable aspiration. Although the technology required for successful human reanimation may still be many years away, the right to pre-mortem cryopreservation should be made available now, so that those future advancements may be reached. The terminally-ill patient's interest in achieving cryonic preservation before ailments destroy all hope of reanimation is legitimate and substantial . When balancing the interests of the individual against the countervailing interests of the state, the court should consider the particular circumstances surrounding the patient's request for assistance in achieving clinical death. The right to pre-mortem cryopreservation should be distinguished from the right to assisted suicide. The terminally-ill cryonicist fervently seeks to extend his life - there is no suicidal intent. Thus, the state's interests in preserving life and preventing suicide are not offended. Further, the ethical integrity of the medical profession will not be tarnished by allowing medical professionals to assist terminally- ill patients in protecting their only chance for survival, no matter how remote this chance may appear to be. The physician assisting in pre-mortem preservation should be treated no differently than the brain surgeon who clinically suspends the life of his patient in order to save his life.236 That doctor knows it is his patient's only chance of survival; the same is true for the terminally-ill brain cancer patient seeking pre-mortem cryopreservation. Additionally, the concerns of abuse and manipulation of the elderly that some courts have asserted when denying the right to assisted suicide are not present here. Rather, the patient is a competent individual, fully aware that his only option for future survival is immediate preservation. For the above reasons, a patient suffering from a degenerative brain disease should be granted a constitutional right to assistance in achieving pre-mortem cryogenic preservation. Denying this right ensures either a prolonged, agonizing death with absolutely no hope of future life, or a cruder, unassisted form of suicide. No state interest is served by either of these outcomes. If the state's interest in preserving life is truly compelling, states should support patients who seek assistance in realizing their only conceivable chance of future life. Our advocacy establishes a personhood contingency standard for the reanimated that transcends normative conceptions of identity- this facilitates a consciousness shift towards collective transhumanism James J. Hughes 2001 "The Future of Death: Cryonics and the Telos of Liberal Individualism" http://www.transhumanist.com/volume6/death.htm Hughes holds a doctorate in sociology from the University of Chicago, where he served as the assistant director of research for the MacLean Center for Clinical Medical Ethics. The current definitions of death, worked out twenty years ago to address the technology of the respirator, are already falling apart. Some are suggesting we dispense with “death” as a unitary marker of human status, while others are pushing for the recognition of a neocortical standard. The twenty first century will begin to see a shift toward consciousness and personhood-centered ethics as a means of dealing not only with brain death, but also with extra-uterine feti, intelligent chimeras, human-machine cyborgs, and the other new forms of life that we will create with technology. The struggle between anthropocentrists and biofundamentalists, on the one hand, and transhumanists on the other, will be fierce . Each proposal for a means of extending human capabilities beyond our “natural” and “Godgiven” limitations, or blurring the boundaries of humanness, will be fought politically and in the courts. But in the end, because of increasing secularization, the tangible advantages of the new technologies, and the internal logic of Enlightenment values, I believe we will begin to develop a bioethics that accords meaning and rights to gradations of self-awareness, regardless of platform. This transformation is unlikely to cause the cryonically suspended to be automatically reclassified as living however. For pragmatic reasons, and due to the uncertainty of information loss, the cryonically frozen are likely to remain dead until proven living. They will be in the status of the soldier missing in action, who has been thought dead, his wife remarried, his estate settled, who is suddenly rescued by some future nanoRambo. Once there has been tangible proof that the prisoners are still in their camp, there will be a reevaluation of the status of the frozen. Getting frozen will then come to be seen as a plausible alternative to death, rather than a bizarre way to preserve a corpse. By this point, however, few people will presumably need to make use of this option. Since this change in the public perception of the status of the frozen is many decades off, and the frozen will be seen as “dead” in the meantime, cryonics organizations should focus more attention on collaborating with choice in dying organizations . Most proposed assisted suicide statues would not allow cryonic suspension as a method. But with secular trends that support further liberalization, and the growing organization of the majority in support of assisted suicide, it seems likely that the coming decades will see laws that allow cryonicists to choose suspension as a part of their “suicide” method. The suggested shift toward a personhood standard for social policy would dramatically effect the reanimated. A personhood standard would open the possibility that the legal identity of a reanimated person would be contingent on their recovery of some threshold of their prior memory and personality. Advance directives of the suspended should address the question of whether they are interested in repairing and reanimating their brain, even if nanoprobes or other diagnostic methods suggest that the resulting person will not be them, but some new person. Finally, I have touched on the truly unpredictable, the equivalent of a bioethical, moral and legal Singularity: the fundamental problematizing of the self. Once technology has fully teased out the constituent processes and structures of memory, cognition and personality, and given us control over them; once we are able to share or sell our skills, personality traits and memories; once some individuals begin to abandon individuality for new forms of collective identity; then the edifice of Western ethical thought since the Enlightenment will be in terminal crisis. The political and ethical trends that are predictable now, as the Enlightenment works towards its telos, will become unpredictable. As transhumanists work to complete the project of the Enlightenment, the shift to a consciousness-based standard of law and ethics, we must also prepare political values and social ethics for the era beyond the discrete, autonomous individual. Shifting to an information theory of death solves the legal dysfunctions that lead to cybernetic war Martine Rothblatt, J.D., Ph.D. 2006"Forms of Transhuman Persons and the Importance of Prior Resolution of Relevant Law" Volume 1, Issue 1, 1st Quarter http://www.terasemjournals.org/PCJournal/PC0101/rothblatt_02e.html Rothblatt started the satellite vehicle tracking and satellite radio industries and is the Chairman of United Therapeutics, a biotechnology company. She is also the founder of Terasem Movement, Inc. If it seems as though making the leap to believe in the possibilities of trranshuman persons is too great, remember that in 1958, it was just as big a leap to cast aside the concept of national sovereignty being based from the core of the earth and reaching in a cone out into space and replace it with the idea that national sovereignty ending at some point. Law must evolve with evolving technology. Copernicus’ theory of the earth’s rotation numbered the days of old-school sovereignty. The notion of sovereignty sweeping out to the cosmos in a fixed cone is rendered irrelevant when we accept that the earth is rotating on an axis because everybody’s cone would sweep the same sectors of cosmic space. Going all the way back to Copernicus, the legal artifice of national sovereignty was already becoming illogical. In the very same way, Turing’s theory of machine consciousness has begun to number the days of oldschool citizenship. Turing asked, what if you could converse with a machine and you couldn’t tell the difference between conversing with a machine and conversing with a person? Is not that machine as conscious as the person ? If we don’t evolve law with evolving technology, we will face conflicts of dysfunctional law. The founders of space law did their best to avoid space conflict (between the US and the Soviet Union in particular) over conflicts of law. Today, we are not at risk for a war with Russia over transhuman rights, but could there be a war between humans and transhumans, between flesh and electronic substrate? That’s certainly a common theme of dystopic[1] science fiction plots and it is something that we can avoid with prior legal development. How might we do in ten, twenty or fifty years? Image 8 depicts some possibilities. Certainly, the bigger challenge we undertake, the longer it will take. A shift to an information theory basis of death is not that big of a change. We just recently made a big leap in the past century from heart death to brain death. So perhaps this is not that big of a leap. It may take a relatively short period of time. At the other end of the spectrum is unifying artificial intelligence and citizenship, which might be a pretty big leap for society to take and may take quite a bit longer. The time to start the dialogue is now. Nanotech is inevitable – transhumanism allows safe stewardship that prevents grey goo Treder and Phoenix 3 [PUBLISHED JANUARY 2003 — REVISED DECEMBER 2003, “Safe Utilization of Advanced Nanotechnology”, Chris Phoenix and Mike Treder, Mike Treder, Executive Director of CRN, BS Biology, University of Washington, Research Fellow with the Institute for Ethics and Emerging Technologies, a consultant to the Millennium Project of the American Council for the United Nations University and to the Future Technologies Advisory Group, serves on the Nanotech Briefs Editorial Advisory Board, is a member of the New York Academy of Sciences and a member of the World Future Society. AND Chris Phoenix, CRN’s Director of Research, has studied nanotechnology for more than 15 years. BS, Symbolic Systems, MS, Computer Science, Stanford University] Many words have been written about the dangers of advanced nanotechnology. Most of the threatening scenarios involve tiny manufacturing systems that run amok, or are used to create destructive products. A manufacturing infrastructure built around a centrally controlled, relatively large, self-contained manufacturing system would avoid these problems. A controlled nanofactory would pose no inherent danger, and it could be deployed and used widely. Cheap, clean, convenient, on-site manufacturing would be possible without the risks associated with uncontrolled nanotech fabrication or excessive regulation . Control of the products could be administered by a central authority; intellectual property rights could be respected. In addition, restricted design software could allow unrestricted innovation while limiting the capabilities of the final products. The proposed solution appears to preserve the benefits of advanced nanotechnology while minimizing the most serious risks. Advanced Nanotechnology And Its Risks As early as 1959, Richard Feynman proposed building devices with each atom precisely placed1. In 1986, Eric Drexler published an influential book, Engines of Creation2, in which he described some of the benefits and risks of such a capability. If molecules and devices can be manufactured by joining individual atoms under computer control, it will be possible to build structures out of diamond, 100 times as strong as steel; to build computers smaller than a bacterium; and to build assemblers and mini-factories of various sizes, capable of making complex products and even of duplicating themselves. Drexler's subsequent book, Nanosystems3, substantiated these remarkable claims, and added still more. A self-contained tabletop factory could produce its duplicate in one hour. Devices with moving parts could be incredibly efficient. Molecular manufacturing operations could be carried out with failure rates less than one in a quadrillion. A computer would require a miniscule fraction of a watt and one trillion of them could fit into a cubic centimeter. Nanotechnology-built fractal plumbing would be able to cool the resulting 10,000 watts of waste heat. It seems clear that if advanced nanotechnology is ever developed, its products will be incredibly powerful. As soon as molecular manufacturing was proposed, risks associated with it began to be identified. Engines of Creation2 described one hazard now considered unlikely, but still possible: grey goo. A small nanomachine capable of replication could in theory copy itself too many times4. If it were capable of surviving outdoors, and of using biomass as raw material, it could severely damage the environment5. Others have analyzed the likelihood of an unstable arms race6, and many have suggested economic upheaval resulting from the widespread use of free manufacturing7. Some have even suggested that the entire basis of the economy would change, and money would become obsolete8. Sufficiently powerful products would allow malevolent people, either hostile governments or angry individuals, to wreak havoc. Destructive nanomachines could do immense damage to unprotected people and objects. If the wrong people gained the ability to manufacture any desired product, they could rule the world, or cause massive destruction in the attempt9. Certain products, such as vast surveillance networks, powerful aerospace weapons, and microscopic antipersonnel devices, provide special cause for concern. Grey goo is relevant here as well: an effective means of sabotage would be to release a hard-to-detect robot that continued to manufacture copies of itself by destroying its surroundings. Clearly, the unrestricted availability of advanced nanotechnology poses grave risks, which may well outweigh the benefits of clean, cheap, convenient, self-contained manufacturing. As analyzed in Forward to the Future: Nanotechnology and Regulatory Policy10, some restriction is likely to be necessary. However, as was also pointed out in that study, an excess of restriction will enable the same problems by increasing the incentive for covert development of advanced nanotechnology. That paper considered regulation on a one-dimensional spectrum, from full relinquishment to complete lack of restriction. As will be shown below, a two-dimensional understanding of the problem—taking into account both control of nanotech manufacturing capability and control of its products—allows targeted restrictions to be applied, minimizing the most serious risks while preserving the potential benefits. Grey goo development causes extinction April Freitas 2000 “Some Limits to Global Ecophagy by Biovorous Nanoreplicators, with Public Policy Recommendations,” Foresight Institute, Senior Research Fellow at the Institute for Molecular Manufacturing, J.D. from Santa Clara University, authoring the multi-volume text Nanomedicine, the first book-length technical discussion of the potential medical applications of hypothetical molecular nanotechnology and medical nanorobotics, 2009 recipient of the Feynman Prize in Nanotechnology for Theory Perhaps the earliest-recognized and best-known danger of molecular nanotechnology is the risk that self-replicating nanorobots capable of functioning autonomously in the natural environment could quickly convert that natural environment (e.g., "biomass") into replicas of themselves (e.g., "nanomass") on a global basis, a scenario usually referred to as the "gray goo problem" but perhaps more properly termed "global ecophagy." As Drexler first warned in Engines of Creation [2]: "Plants" with "leaves" no more efficient than today's solar cells could out-compete real plants, crowding the biosphere with an inedible foliage. Tough omnivorous "bacteria" could out-compete real bacteria: They could spread like blowing pollen, replicate swiftly, and reduce the biosphere to dust in a matter of days. Dangerous replicators could easily be too tough, small, and rapidly spreading to stop - at least if we make no preparation. We have trouble enough controlling viruses and fruit flies. Among the cognoscenti of nanotechnology, this threat has become known as the "gray goo problem." Though masses of uncontrolled replicators need not be gray or gooey, the term "gray goo" emphasizes that replicators able to obliterate life might be less inspiring than a single species of crabgrass. They might be superior in an evolutionary sense, but this need not make them valuable. The gray goo threat makes one thing perfectly clear: We cannot afford certain kinds of accidents with replicating assemblers. Gray goo would surely be a depressing ending to our human adventure on Earth, far worse than mere fire or ice, and one that could stem from a simple laboratory accident. Lederberg [3] notes that the microbial world is evolving at a fast pace, and suggests that our survival may depend upon embracing a "more microbial point of view." The emergence of new infectious agents such as HIV and Ebola demonstrates that we have as yet little knowledge of how natural or technological disruptions to the environment might trigger mutations in known organisms or unknown extant organisms [81], producing a limited form of "green goo" [92]. Extinction in 72 hours Mark Pesce, BS Candidate at MIT, October, 1999, “Thinking Small,” FEED Magazine, http://hyperreal.org/~mpesce/ThinkingSmall.html The nanoassembler is the Holy Grail of nanotechnology; once a perfected nanoassembler is available, almost anything becomes possible – which is both the greatest hope and biggest fear of the nanotechnology community. Sixty years ago, John Von Neumann – who, along with Alan Turing founded the field of computer science – surmised that it would someday be possible to create machines that could copy themselves, a sort of auto-duplication which could lead from a single instance to a whole society of perfect copies. Although such a Von Neumann machine is relatively simple in theory, such a device has never been made – because it’s far easier, at the macromolecular scale, to build a copy of a machine than it is to get the machine to copy itself. At the molecular level, this balance is reversed; it’s far easier to get a nanomachine to copy itself than it is to create another one from scratch. This is an enormous boon – once you have a single nanoassembler you can make as many as you might need – but it also means that a nanoassembler is the perfect plague. If – either intentionally or through accident – a nanoassembler were released into the environment, with only the instruction to be fruitful and multiply, the entire surface of the planet – plants, animals and even rocks - would be reduced to a “gray goo” of such nanites in little more than 72 hours. This “gray goo problem”, well known in nanotechnology acts as a check against the unbounded optimism which permeates scientific developments in atomic-scale devices. Drexler believes the gray goo problem mostly imaginary, but does admit the possibility of a “gray dust” scenario, in which replicating nanites “smother” the Earth in a blanket of sub-microscopic forms. In either scenario, the outcome is much the same. And here we encounter a technological danger unprecedented in history: If we had stupidly blown ourselves to kingdom come in a nuclear apocalypse, at least the cockroaches would have survived. But in a gray goo scenario, nothing – not even the bacteria deep underneath the ground – would be untouched. Everything would become one thing: a monoculture of nanites. Transhumanism solves the human condition Nick Bostrom 2009 “IN DEFENSE OF POSTHUMAN DIGNITY" http://www.psy.vanderbilt.edu/courses/hon182/Posthuman_dignity_Bostrom.pdf Nick Bostrom is a Swedish philosopher at St. Cross College, University of Oxford known for his work on existential risk, the anthropic principle, human enhancement ethics, the reversal test, and consequentialism. He holds a PhD from the London School of Economics (2000). He is the founding director of both The Future of Humanity Institute and the Oxford Martin Programme on the Impacts of Future Technology as part of the Oxford Martin School at Oxford University. The prospect of posthumanity is feared for at least two reasons. One is that the state of being posthuman might in itself be degrading, so that by becoming posthuman we might be harming ourselves. Another is that posthumans might pose a threat to “ordinary” humans. (I shall set aside a third possible reason, that the development of posthumans might offend some supernatural being.) The most prominent bioethicist to focus on the first fear is Leon Kass: Most of the given bestowals of nature have their given species-specified natures: they are each and all of a given sort. Cockroaches and humans are equally bestowed but differently natured. To turn a man into a cockroach—as we don’t need Kafka to show us—would be dehumanizing. To try to turn a man into more than a man might be so as well. We need more than generalized appreciation for nature’s gifts. We need a particular regard and respect for the special gift that is our own given nature.5 Transhumanists counter that nature’s gifts are sometimes poisoned and should not always be accepted. Cancer, malaria, dementia, aging, starvation, unnecessary suffering, cognitive shortcomings are all among the presents that we wisely refuse. Our own species-specified natures are a rich source of much of the thoroughly unrespectable and unacceptable—susceptibility for disease, murder, rape, genocide, cheating, torture, racism. The horrors of nature in general and of our own nature in particular are so well documented6 that it is astonishing that somebody as distinguished as Leon Kass should still in this day and age be tempted to rely on the natural as a guide to what is desirable or normatively right. We should be grateful that our ancestors were not swept away by the Kassian sentiment, or we would still be picking lice off each other’s backs. Rather than deferring to the natural order, transhumanists maintain that we can legitimately reform ourselves and our natures in accordance with humane values and personal aspirations. Meta-analysis of behavioral studies indicate evolutionary tendencies lie at the root of all human violence Mohammed Tadesse 2006, “The Fundamental Causes of Armed Conflict in Human History: Reinterpretation of Available Sources,” Organization for Social Science Research in Eastern and Southern Africa, Ph.D, Harayama University Through a long process of cultural development, human beings are able to score remarkable achievements in their life. However, people are still unable to avoid conflicts of violent /armed character, which are destructive in their nature. Archaeological findings, anthropological interpretations and historical records indicate that people have been engaged in armed conflicts since the prehistoric period. Naturally, the following questions may ensue: What is the nature of this phenomenon? What are the roots and responsible causes of waging limitless destructive wars without interruption? Why are people not in a position to overcome conflicts of armed nature for the last time? Although it seems too ambitious, the paper tries to deal with this crucial problem, which indiscriminately affects all. In all periods of human history, armed conflict has been an important issue of intellectual debate. Great thinkers, politicians, historians, theologians, military theoreticians, and behavioural scientists have exerted maximum efforts to examine and explain the nature of the problem from different perspectives. However, their findings are diversified and influenced by different factors. Some of the conclusions made by these experts have also led their audiences to a muddle. Therefore, it is essential to re-examine the problem for three major reasons: i) Curiosity to learn about the nature and causes of the problem; ii) Misdiagnosis of the nature, sources and/or causes of armed conflict by experts and non-experts; and iii) Unwillingness on the part of the world to learn from its tragic history. The study tries to analyse the following questions: Is violent / armed conflict an eternal phenomenon that cannot be controlled or a social phenomenon that can be controlled? What are the fundamental causes of armed conflicts in the history of humankind? Hence, attempt is made to: a) Re-examine different approaches and theories of scholars in explaining the nature and course of armed conflict; b) Reinterpret the nature of armed conflict in human history, whether it is an innate genetic characteristic of human beings, a social construct or determined and moulded by both; and c) Enrich the existing knowledge on the matter and probably provide some valuable conceptual explanations to the problem. The problem is mainly conceptual in nature, which dictates the method of collecting and analysing the data. Thus, the paper uses a body of concepts from behavioural sciences to apply a thematic approach and scientific methods and techniques, which enable to look for evidences, describe the nature and causes of the problem, and formulate broad statements. The paper uses secondary sources of multidisciplinary character (findings of biology, psychology, anthropology, archaeology, relevant historical and other social science theoretical books, thesis, articles, religious books, etc.). Based on the available materials, the researcher has reviewed and classified different views of scholars regarding the nature of aggressive behaviour in general and armed conflict in particular. Finally, the data is analysed using a descriptive method of study. The findings are as follows: 1. On the nature of armed conflicts: i) the evolutionary development of human intelligence is the primary responsible factor (under conditions) for the origin of aggressiveness in human behaviour, which gradually planted the culture of war in the history of humankind. ii) The present state of human warrior culture is inevitable and a continuous process of evolutionally development and it remains part of human life for a long period. 2. On the causes of armed conflict: Conflicts of violent/armed character are not products of a single factor. Conflicts result from the denial or ignoring or suppression of human biological as well as socio- psychological (ontological) needs. Just for the sake of simplicity, the paper classifies the responsible motives, needs, or causes of armed conflict into fundamental and specific causes: i) The fundamental causes, which are common for all violent conflicts, are grouped into primary and secondary sources. a) Under primary source of fundamental character come: - Human nature - Socio-psychological needs - Economic factors b) Under secondary source of fundamental character come: - Politics and - Culture (the presence of warrior tradition) ii) Specific causes. Each war that had taken place in different periods of human history has its own specific causes of functional character. The specific causes of certain wars may not be the responsible causes for the other and /or all spoils of wars. In one way or the other, specific causes also belong to the fundamental causes. Let us see some of the conflicting events of historical character that can be marked as specific causes, which were used to: ¬ Adopt strangers (assimilation); ¬ Enslave others; ¬ Enlarge territory; ¬ Colonize; ¬ Achieve unification; ¬ Establish sphere of influence; ¬ Settle border conflict; ¬ Separate from the main historical nation-state; ¬ Achieve irredentism, etc. The following initiatives can be taken as possible options to maintain relative security before the outbreak of armed conflict, and if not, to minimize the destruction: 1. Human beings, by their nature of evolutionary development, do not possess the ability to avoid conflicts forever and to maintain peaceful life for the last time. But the findings of this research confirm the possibility of either delaying the development of the responsible factors for the origin of armed conflict and/ or minimizing its all round destruction. This is viable only if the concerned bodies are able to diagnose the sources of armed conflict and take all preventive -measures, which also include maintaining reasonable force of defence and balance of power in their respective areas. Hence, there should not be any magnanimity to disarm the nation unilaterally; 2. Although the paper needs further investigation, it can be used for: - Enriching the theoretical basis and help others to study related topics of specific character - Differentiating the "rational" from the "accidental" causes of violent conflicts No risk of a turn because technology to destroy the world already exists- means there’s only a chance that transhumanism solves extinction by eliminating the drive for violence Mark Walker 2009 “Ship of Fools: Why Transhumanism is the Best Bet to Prevent the Extinction of Civilization ,” The Global Spiral, Feb 5, http://www.metanexus.net/magazine/tabid/68/id/10682/Default.aspx Walker is an assistant professor at New Mexico State University and holds the Richard L. Hedden Chair of Advanced Philosophical Studies This line of thinking is further reinforced when we consider that there is a limit to the downside of creating posthumans , at least relatively speaking. That is, one of the traditional concerns about increasing knowledge is that it seems to always imply an associated risk for greater destructive capacity. One way this point is made is in terms of ‘killing capacity’: muskets are a more powerful technology than a bow and arrow, and tanks more powerful than muskets, and atomic bombs even more destructive than tanks. The knowledge that made possible these technical advancements brought a concomitant increase in capacity for evil. Interestingly, we have almost hit the wall in our capacity for evil: once you have civilization destroying weapons there is not much worse you can do. There is a point in which the one-upmanship for evil comes to an end—when everyone is dead. If you will forgive the somewhat graphic analogy, it hardly matters to Kennedy if his head is blown off with a rifle or a cannon. Likewise, if A has a weapon that can kill every last person there is little difference between that and B’s weapon which is twice as powerful. Posthumans probably won’t have much more capacity for evil than we have, or are likely to have shortly. So, at least in terms of how many persons can be killed, posthumans will not outstrip us in this capacity. This is not to say that there are no new worries with the creation of posthumans, but the greatest evil, the destruction of civilization, is something which we now, or will soon, have. In other words, the most significant aspect that we should focus on with contemplating the creation of posthumans is their upside. They are not likely to distinguish themselves in their capacity for evil , since we have already pretty much hit the wall on that, but for their capacity for good. Debating the issues surrounding transhumanism is essential because the coming technology can and will redefine our very nature Liz Klimas 2013 "‘Transhumanist Movement’ Is Coming: The Ethical Dilemma Posed by Rapidly Advancing Technology" http://www.theblaze.com/stories/2013/02/06/transhumanist-movement-iscoming-the-ethical-dilemma-posed-by-rapidly-advancing-technology/ Klimas graduated from Hillsdale College with a Bachelor of Science, she also has interned for the National Oceanic and Atmospheric Administration (NOAA) and the Association for Women in Science. “Technology is fire. If you can control it, it’s great. If it controls you, you’re in trouble.” This was the theme of the latest episode of the Glenn Beck program on TheBlaze TV. Sure, some technology and ideas Beck showcased on his show Wednesday night might sound crazy and remind you of a science fiction flick — Beck himself acknowledges this — but they’re not, he said. Take drones for example. There was a time when people couldn’t imagine the capabilities of an unmanned aerial vehicle. Now such drones are being used in strikes against hostile adversaries, which Beck said is good. But just this week a memo from the Obama administration said U.S. citizens could be subject to drone strikes if they are a “senior operational” leader of al-Qaeda or “an associated force.” “The president is using drones right now and nobody is really talking about the ethics of this,” Beck said on the show. “We should have seen this day coming but we didn’t. At least as a society, we didn’t.” It is the conversation about the ethics of use of what might now seem like science fiction that Beck says has happen. “It’s not the app, it’s not the gun, it’s not the drone, it’s what you do with it,” he said. Part of the ethical issue regarding the use of technology that Beck has focused upon at length is the transhumanist movement. The groundwork for merging the human body with machines to the point where the concept of the Singularity would be reached, an idea strongly supported by futurist Ray Kurzweil, is well on its way. Beck pointed to the recent breakthrough of 3D-printed human embryonic stem cells that scientists hope will someday allow for 3D-printed organs. He noted a “million dollar bionic man” named Rex that is outfitted with technology to hear, speak, move and even has artificial organs. So if humans are fixing their physical beings to live longer, as they already are today in many respects, how will this affect society? As an example, Beck called up how soldiers are being mended and returning home physically fixed to an extent, but their internal scars are not being addressed. The recent shooting of acclaimed sniper Chris Kyle and his friend Chad Littlefield by a Marine reservist who reportedly had PTSD is an example. Another question if humans are to live longer is if the Earth will be able to support that. In another example, Beck highlighted a water purification system called Slingshot by Deka that can make clean drinking water from any, and we mean, any liquid. If this product were to be made smaller and more cost-effective, millions of people would be saved from conditions that result from a lack of potable drinking water. But some have been saying for years that the Earth is reaching a “tipping point” with regard to its growing population and that more growth would cause “severe impacts” on quality of life. Beck posed the moral dilemma regarding whether this machine would even get to the people who need it based on this argument of finite resources and global warming. And what of the human mind? Kurzweil’s ideas are that humans will not only augment their organs and other physical features with technology but their minds as well. Technology is on its way for computers to begin reading our minds. Take the soon-to-be-released MindMeld app. MindMeld” from Expect Labs is described by San Francisco-based founders as an “always on Siri,” according to Technology Review. Here’s more from about how the app works: Users can sign up or log in through Facebook and hold free video or voice calls with up to eight people through the app. If a participant taps on a button in the app during a call, MindMeld will review the previous 15 to 30 seconds of conversation by relying on Nuance’s voice recognition technology. It will identify key terms in context—in a discussion to find a sushi restaurant, for example, or one about a big news story that day—and then search Google News, Facebook, Yelp, YouTube, and a few other sources for relevant results. Images and links are displayed in a stream for the person who tapped the button to review. With a finger swipe, he or she can choose to share a result with others on the call. Furthermore, where will the line between “what is life and what isn’t?” be drawn, Beck asked. “ We’re in trouble, but the future is bright if we go in with open eyes ,” he said. ”If we lose the concept of the soul and become the creator at the same time, what does the phrase ‘we’re all endowed by our creator with certain unalienable rights’ mean?” Have we past the point of no return? Yale computer science professor David Gelernter, who was a guest on Wednesday’s show, used paint as an example to illustrate his point. He said paint has changed over centuries and has improved, but has the human artist exponentially gotten better? No, because human nature itself hasn’t changed, Gelernter said. Still, the ethical discussion about technology coming down the pike is important now none the less, because it could reach a point where it might be used to alter human nature itself. “We have to talk about technology — the good side and the bad side,” Beck continued. “We need to have the moral and ethical debate.”