RATIONAL RECONSTRUCTION, SELF-REFLECTION AND DISCLOSURE IN ACCOUNTING: A SYNTHESIS OF HABERMAS AND HEIDEGGER Helen Oakesa and John Francis McKernanb a KEELE MANAGEMENT SCHOOL KEELE UNIVERSITY KEELE STAFFORDSHIRE ST5 5BG UNITED KINGDOM Email: h.oakes@econ.keele.ac.uk Tel +44 (0)1782 732000 Fax +44 (0)1782 734277 b DEPARTMENT OF ACCOUNTING AND FINANCE UNIVERSITY OF GLASGOW GLASGOW G12 8QQ UNITED KINGDOM Email: John.McKernan@glasgow.ac.uk Tel: +44(0)141 330 3993 Abstract This paper defends Habermas’ reconstructive theory against recent criticisms in the accounting literature of his procedural model, arguing that Habermas creates a communicative rationality that has potentially fruitful implications for critical accounting rather than reinforcing an inappropriate instrumental rationality. We suggest that he identifies and transforms some important aspects of conventional rationalism. However, we acknowledge that his communicative rationality fails to achieve the balance of hermeneutical reflection and “objective” linguistic structuralism that he seems to have intended. It is argued that Heidegger’s theory can help to redress this imbalance. The paper therefore focuses on supplementing Habermas’ theory with themes from Heidegger. We discuss first-order and 1 second-order disclosure concentrating on second-order disclosure where a moment of interpretive insight can open up a myriad of possibilities for accounting change. Moods and emotions are discussed as catalysts for disclosure in accounting. Art, recognition of one’s own mortality and phenomenological time are treated as aspects of disclosure with implications for accounting. A model for the reconstruction of accounting is presented summarising key themes from the synthesis of Habermas and Heidegger. 1.Introduction In the context of the many repressive regimes and exploitative practices that currently exist, it is particularly important that we develop the conceptual resources to be able to envisage new emancipatory possibilities for accounting. A number of accounting researchers have called for a re-conceptualisation of accounting language, processes and ways of thinking as a precursor to accounting transformation (e.g. Laughlin, 1987; Tinker, 1991; Molisa, 2011). Lehman (2010) emphasizes the importance of critique and interpretation in environmental and social accounting. Habermas’ critical theory has been influential in suggesting how new accountings might emerge through his reconstructive approach (e.g. Laughlin, 1987; Gallhofer and Haslam, 1991). In addition, Habermas’ democratic procedures have been regarded by some scholars as crucial for accounting change (e.g. Broadbent and Laughlin, 1997, Unerman and Bennett, 2004; Dillard and Yuthus, 2006). Whilst in practice the planning and decision making process often does not adhere to the idealised model of rational choice theory (Brunsson, 1982) and the implementation of democratically agreed visions and plans may well lead to some unintended consequences, we assume that proposing and discussing emancipatory alternatives has the potential to provide a basis for positive change. There is some empirical evidence to suggest that adopting authentic Habermasian democratic 2 procedures is difficult to achieve in practice in a business context and compromise is often coercive (e.g. Archel et al. 2011). However, in our view Habermasian theory provides a strong basis for the possibility of attaining a more just society in future. This paper synthesizes theory from Habermas (1972; 1974; 1976; 1989;1991; 1996; 1998) and Heidegger (1978) to consider one approach to begin understanding how we can conceptualise new emancipatory accountings. Such an approach depends on the practical knowledge of agents and on their ‘practical ability to see more in things than they are’ (Kompridis, 2006b, p. 258). This paper is concerned with understanding the nature of accounting critique. It also contributes to the discussion concerning what we need to change in and through accounting, and continues the on-going necessary justification for accounting critique in the face of widespread lack of awareness of problems associated with accounting, institutionalised apathy to accounting change and pervasive disinformation. It has been suggested that accounting should move away from its close association with the logic of economics which tends to reduce decisions to purely technical questions (Lehman, 2006). Lehman (2006; 2010) contends that Habermas’ rationalistic emphasis on rules and procedures, and his attempt to offer impartiality through universalism, tend to reinforce the very technical rationality that accounting needs to escape. He also argues that ‘Habermas’ reliance on a procedural approach submerges how language opens people to different ideas and strategies’ (Lehman, 2010, p. 728). This paper attempts to justify Habermas’ procedural approach, but also argues that the approach can benefit from being supplemented by several themes from Heidegger. We focus particularly on Heidegger’s themes of disclosure, intentionality, moods, death and phenomenological time in the search for authentic self and society. In our view introducing Heidegger’s concept of disclosure may allay criticisms of Habermas’ rationalism and may help towards realising Habermas’ intention to combine a 3 hermeneutical and self-reflective dimension with “objective” linguistic structuralism. We suggest that exploring one of the key sources of interpretive research through Heidegger may help to provide a renewed identity for interpretive research that some interpretive researchers believe is lacking (see Ahrens et al., 2008). Drawing on Kompridis (1994; 2006a; 2006b) and Benhabib (1986), we propose that triggered by emotions, Heidegger’s concept of disclosure can enhance Habermas’ process of reconstruction (including rational reconstruction, self-reflection and societal reconstruction) for accounting and society. Guignon (1999) observes that Heidegger’s thought has been highly influential for 20th century philosophy including phenomenology, existentialism, hermeneutics, postmodernism and pragmatism. The paper focuses on Heidegger’s ‘Being and Time’ (1978) which is generally considered to be a major part of Heidegger’s output. We have tried to read ‘Being and Time’ in isolation from information about Heidegger’s associations with Naziism, apparent a few years after the publication of ‘Being and Time’ (see Sheenan, 1999). Heidegger has received relatively little attention in the accounting literature, although his work has clearly influenced accounting research indirectly through research that has drawn on philosophical texts influenced by Heidegger. Ezzamel and Robson (1995) apply Heidegger’s phenomenological approach to time to accounting time. Chabrak (2005) refers briefly to Heidegger when she discusses hermeneutic phenomenology in general and its implications for accounting policy. She argues for the importance of intentionality in accounting policy and we continue to develop the theme of intentionality and its implications for accounting in this paper as part of Heidegger’s concept of disclosure. Although Habermas is critical of Heidegger (discussed in 4.2) we identify some important links between the two theorists. By attempting to reinvigorate Habermas’ theory with themes from 4 Heidegger, we aim to build on existing literature that applies Habermas and Heidegger to accounting issues. The paper briefly examines Habermas’ critical reconstructive theory. Next, Heidegger’s theme of disclosure is introduced drawing on Kompridis’ (1994) distinction between firstorder and second-order disclosure. The following key aspects of Heidegger’s concept of disclosure are explored in separate sections: intentionality, the search for Being, constraints to disclosure, personal responsibility, moods and emotions, disclosure through death and art, and phenomenological time. Within these sections some comparisons between Heidegger and Habermas are drawn, and benefits of Heidegger’s themes for Habermas’ theory are discussed. In addition, some implications of Heidegger’s themes for an emancipatory accounting are considered. The penultimate section is divided into three sub-sections that briefly reflect on our synthesis of Habermas and Heidegger. In the third sub-section a model for the reconstruction of accounting is presented summarising key themes from the synthesis of Habermas and Heidegger. Ways in which the key themes can be applied to accounting are indicated. It is hoped the model could be used by accounting researchers or practitioners when trying to critically reconstruct an understanding of a particular context. The concluding main section draws together key arguments in the paper. 2. Habermas This section briefly discusses Habermas’ critical reconstructive theory to indicate the form that its rationality takes. We justify his procedural approach arguing that his rationalism has much to offer accounting researchers and practitioners. We also illustrate how Habermas 5 attempts to provide a balance between formal rationalism and interpretation that reconciles modernism with postmodernism. Nevertheless, we suggest that his interpretive dimension can be enhanced by being supplemented with themes from Heidegger’s phenomenological theory. We conclude this section by outlining Habermas’ concept of self-reflection and linking it with Heidegger’s concept of disclosure. 2.1 Habermas’ rationalism and reconstructive critical theory Habermas has been rejected for developing an overly rationalistic approach that is unsuitable as a basis for a critique of accounting (Lehman, 2006). There are many examples of rationalism in Habermas’ work. One example is the way he derives a complex, interconnected, theoretical system from the small building block of the speech act (a purposive utterance such as a request or complaint) using traditional philosophical methods of formal and logical argumentation. Habermas (1991) provides further evidence of the rationalist elements of his work by drawing on Kohlberg’s rationalistic theory of moral development and Piaget’s stage theory of child development. The development of individual moral consciousness for Kohlberg and Habermas involves an increasing concern with rules and abstract principles. In this sophisticated version of rationalism, based on Piaget, the individual learns to distinguish themselves from the environment and others and becomes increasingly reflective, critical and morally autonomous. Habermas (1991) adds a seventh stage to Kohlberg’s moral consciousness where a reflective individual learns to assess and contribute to discursively agreed norms. 6 Habermas’ rationalistic faith in rules and procedures is evident in his 1991 depiction of the evolutionary development of society. He argues that society has developed morally over time evidenced through the gradual development of systems of justice. In his analysis, legalistic, rational procedures provide the basis for a legitimacy which underpins social order. He argues that in a historical development within Western society characterised by Rousseau and Kant, formal procedures of reason replaced material principles like Nature or God as justifications for norms and actions. Habermas (1991, p. 184) states that: ‘Since ultimate grounds can no longer be made plausible, the formal conditions of justification themselves obtain legitimating force. The procedures and presuppositions of rational agreement themselves become principles.’ Habermas describes these societal changes as new learning levels which are also reflected in developments in the legal system and the development of democratic systems. Such legal developments affect the individual’s self- perception and identity. For example, role identity is replaced with ego identity and people see themselves as ‘free and equal subjects of civil law’ (Habermas, 1991, p. 114). Linked to the development of moral consciousness through a pre-occupation with procedures, the new societal ‘theoretical attitude’ moves away from dogmatism to become ‘reflective’ (Habermas, 1991, p.105). He places the responsibility for devising ethical codes and political courses of action on society to determine through deliberative democracy. 7 Habermas adopts rationalism and proceduralism for positive purposes with beneficial implications for accounting. For example, he develops communicative rationality rather than instrumental rationality. His universal discourse principle that links to the speech act is used to counter the extreme relativism of postmodernism (where there are no principles for deciding between competing knowledge claims) through a consensus theory of truth. It also provides validity for moral norms which have been subjected to philosophical scepticism since Nietzsche and the turn of the 20th century (McCarthy, 1978). In addition, the universal discourse principle is used as a basis for Habermas’ influential, procedural democratic theory which arguably has the potential to reduce dogmatism and bring about significant accounting transformations because all interested parties are granted equal voice (see Oakes and Oakes, 2012). Furthermore, Habermas problematises the type of instrumental economic rationality that has been criticised by accounting scholars. For example, he argues for a type of intersubjective, consensual, communicative rationality that differs from the selfish individualism of conventional, neo-classical economic rationality where utility is maximised and it is assumed that ‘the egoistic freedom of one is compatible with that of all’ (Habermas cited in McCarthy, 1978, p. 351). Although Habermas is influenced by Kant, his concept of reason differs from Socratic dialogue and the transcendental reason championed by Descartes and Kant (McCarthy, 1978). He attempts to balance his rationalism with interpretive approaches. Thus he proposes a reconstructive critical theory that emphasizes hermeneutic sciences and intersubjective communication rather than technical scientific knowledge and control. His theory promotes analysis and reconstruction of the past with a view to revealing emancipatory possibilities for the future. Furthermore, any reconstruction would be provisional because, following Gadamer, history for Habermas is viewed as constantly being 8 re-shaped and related to the context of the observer (McCarthy, 1978). His theory moves away from instrumental rationality, drawing on interpretive Freudian psychoanalysis. Like psychoanalysts, accounting participants can adopt a reconstructive approach to attempt to bring to light a suppression of understanding (see Laughlin, 1987). Underlying societal distortions are diagnosed in a similar way to psychoanalysis which applies an interpretive framework to reconstruct individual life histories (McCarthy, 1978). Such analysis is intended to allow participants to see themselves and society in new ways and to disclose inequalities, injustices and alternative meanings of which participants may be unaware and which may be symptoms of Habermas’ (1976) legitimation crises. This method avoids a technical approach with rationally goal-directed means and the ‘rational selection of instrumental alternatives’ focusing instead on practical questions ‘with a view to acceptance or rejection of norms’ (Habermas, 1974, p. 3). In the spirit of interpretivism, Habermas accepts that knowledge is socially constructed, contextual and theory laden and therefore the hidden, alternative meanings revealed by psychoanalytic reconstructions should not be read to imply that there are underlying absolute independent truths that can be revealed, hidden beneath existing meanings. Rather they suggest alternative ways of seeing. There is no guarantee that the alternative perspectives which are uncovered are more valid than existing perspectives, apart from their ability to command consensus, and the constraints of an external reality. Critical interpretivism is also suggested in the way Habermas’ reconstructive approach requires individual and social learning and moral development to reveal alternative and hidden perspectives as a precursor to developing new emancipatory theories and social evolution rather than an emphasis on innate ideas or primitive behaviouralism. Since Habermas takes a contextual approach to truth, he will be aware of Kompridis’ (2006b) point that his procedural approach is not 9 neutral or devoid of ethical assumptions or content. For example, Habermas uses his procedural approach to support modernism and a particular form of western rationality. However, in our view, Habermas’ procedural approach does take us away from extreme dogmatism. Habermas (1991) also suggests that his procedural approach provides a defence against postmodern loss of both meaning and motivation. 2.2 Some criticisms of Habermas Although Habermas’ reconstructive theory tries to blend the constructivism of phenomenology and hermeneutics with a type of objectivity provided by the ideal speech situation, some scholars feel that his abstract structuralistic theory and proceduralism lacks something. The unwillingness of the theory to specify and discuss particular normative content seems to be an issue. For example, Molisa (2011) argues that critical accounting theory in general lacks a spiritual dimension and should emphasize love. McKernan and MacLullich (2004) add ethical content to Habermas’ procedural theory. Drawing on Ricoeur’s work, they propose that Habermas’ communicative ethics should be enlarged to promote love for the other in addition to justice. McCarthy (1978) criticises Habermas’ attempt to blend a form of objectivity with interpretive hermeneutics in his reconstructive, critical rationalism, suggesting that through the identification of universal linguistic structures, Habermas’ philosophy becomes more of a Kantian reconstruction of historical materialism as opposed to a phenomenological selfreflection. McCarthy (1978, p. 264) notes that the theoretical nature of Habermas’ work ‘seems to exclude precisely the practical and hermeneutic dimension that made critical theory 10 methodologically distinct from traditional theory.’ Thus in his view Habermas fails to create a materialistically transformed phenomenology. McCarthy (1978, p. 272) reminds us that ‘Habermas’s entire project, from the critique of contemporary scientism to the reconstruction of historical materialism, rests on the possibility of providing an account of communication that is both theoretical and normative, that goes beyond a pure hermeneutics without being reducible to a strictly empirical-analytic science.’ We have argued that Habermas’ procedural approach as vital for a fairer accounting. However, we also agree with Habermas’ critics that there seems be an inadequate development of the phenomenological dimension of his theory crucial to reconciling modernism with postmodernism. As Kompridis (2006b, p. 78) observes, given Habermas’ concern with semantic degradation and impoverishment of everyday life and culture (the “lifeworld”), his lack of explanation as to ‘how modernity might recover its semantic resources’ is surprising. In the next main section we therefore explore some of Heidegger’s ideas to see if they can reduce the abstract quality in Habermas’ philosophy of reconstruction and reinforce the hermeneutic and questioning orientation intended for Habermas’ ideal speech rationality. Before focusing on Heidegger’s concept of disclosure we discuss Habermas’ concept of self-reflection. 2.3 Self-reflection This section outlines an important connection between Habermas’ theory of reconstruction and Heidegger’s concept of disclosure. In ‘Theory and Practice’ (1974, p. 23), Habermas, introduces the concept of reflection into his construct of societal reconstruction. He distinguishes two aspects of reflection which are linked to societal reconstruction: rational 11 reconstruction and self-reflection. He identifies rational reconstruction as the recovery of an unconsciously functioning system of anonymous rules (“know how” or theoretical knowledge) that provides reasoned, posterior justification but no practical consequences. However, self-reflection (analogous to psychoanalytic dialogue) is the recovery of insight that can be tested discursively and has the potential for authenticity and practical emancipatory consequences. According to Habermas (1974, p. 24), rational reconstruction ‘permits the theoretical development of self-reflection’. Habermas’ self-reflection is similar to Heidegger’s concept of disclosure, although the associated ideas are more developed in Heidegger. 3. Heidegger and disclosure The concept of disclosure is central to Heidegger (1978) and it draws upon a pre-reflective world that Habermas acknowledges. For Heidegger and Kompridis (1994; 2006a; 2006b), the insights of the pre-reflective world are disclosed rather than recovered or reconstructed. For Heidegger, disclosure is an ‘‘uncovering’, which draws upon the Greek concept of aletheia as un-concealing possibilities. Heidegger’s disclosure opens up of the ‘space of intelligibility’ (Mulhall, 2005, p. 101). Kompridis (2006a, p. 335) points out that Heidegger’s spontaneous, pre-reflective world produces change which ‘is not rulegoverned...and does not refer back to any rule-governed competence for initiating change.’ Heidegger’s disclosure can introduce alternative meanings and vocabularies that are dissonant with current meanings (Kompridis, 2006b). It can involve refocusing disparate or anomalous facts of our pre-understanding (Kompridis, 2006b), making new connections and uncovering ‘in a different light something that has already been disclosed independently of language’ (Kompridis, 2006b, p. 37). The term ‘disclosure’ suggests that secret meanings 12 and possibilities may not be clearly revealed and may be partial and fragmented, supporting Heidegger’s view that an entirely transparent revelation of meaning as an absolute objective truth or a complete totality is not possible because we are always dependent on pre-existing contextual meanings. For Rouse (1981) Heidegger’s disclosure includes the notion that we are always open to the possibility of our own failure. Kompridis (2006b, p. 220) interprets disclosure to entail the revelation of ‘endangered “local worlds”’ not large scale final visions. In his view, this prevents both the loss of recognition of multiple voices and the foreclosure of on-going critique. However, in our view large-scale visions may be attempted even while we recognise Rouse’s (1981) Heideggarian point that the world will always be more than we can disclose. All disclosures and visions would need to be supported by Habermasian democratic discussion. Kompridis’(1994, p. 29) reading of Heidegger distinguishes first-order disclosure which is the ‘disclosure of an already interpreted, symbolically structured world; the world, that is, within which we always already find ourselves’ and second-order disclosure which ‘describes a meaning-creative process capable of making, unmaking and remaking worlds.’ Secondorder disclosure provokes utopian possibilities. Kompridis (1994) observes that first-order disclosure and second-order disclosure are interconnected and sometimes difficult to distinguish in practice. We see them as extensions of Habermas’ (1974) concept of selfreflection. Kompridis (2006b, p. 34) interprets Heidegger’s disclosure as a dynamic, ‘on-going process’. He develops Heidegger’s disclosure into a non-instrumental ‘self-decentred learning process’ (Kompridis, 2006b, p. 221) that represents ‘the kind of learning that precludes knowing in 13 advance what it is we are going to learn’ (Kompridis, 2006b, p. 222). Furthermore, it is ‘dependent on, receptivity- on paying attention in a way that lets something new happen’ (Kompridis, 2006b, p. 222). Disclosure is not just about enlarging perspectives but also involves changes to our normative self-understanding that aim to ‘renew trust, and to facilitate commitment to ongoing processes of cooperative problem solving’ (Kompridis, 2006b, p. 262). According to Kompridis (2006b p. 222) his own definition of disclosure as a self-decentering learning process renders it impossible to disclose an unjust world. However, we take the view that there is no guarantee that disclosure or Habermasian democratic procedures will result in a just world, although we conjecture that they are likely to represent an improvement to our current social and institutional arrangements. Kompridis (2006b, p. 255) argues that the goal of critique should not (and cannot) be Habermasian consensus, but should be ‘the self-decentering disclosure of meaning and possibility’. However, he overlooks the significance of Habermasian consensus and democratic procedure for practical change. In our view the utopian possibilities suggested through disclosure still need to be assessed according to Habermas’ discursive procedures. It is hoped this might reduce the chance of developing non-emancipatory disclosures in practice. The next few sections discuss several manifestations of disclosure in Heidegger and their implications for re-conceptualising accounting as a precursor to accounting change. We continue by discussing Heidegger’s intentionality as first-order disclosure and include some implications for accounting. We then discuss second-order disclosure in Heidegger. 14 3.1 Intentionality and disclosure Heidegger provides insight into Habermas’ pre-reflective world through his important concept of intentionality. He opposes the traditional representationalist view of theory and practice and Cartesian dualism exemplified in the accounting literature by Mattessich (2003). The Cartesian approach premises a basic ontological disconnection between mental and physical substance and then searches for indubitable connections (e.g. the knowledge of the existence of a thinking subject) (Couzens Hoy, 1999, p. 176). Heidegger’s hermeneutics represents a radical change to orthodox philosophy by viewing the subject as already in the world. Thus, in his view mind and body (subject and object) should be understood as inextricably linked though intentionality rather than being taken as separate entities. The subject and the world are coterminous, forming a hermeneutic circle where knowledge is ‘always already meaning-laden and interpretive’ (Couzens Hoy, 1999, p. 179). Therefore the terms “subject” and “object” as ordinarily understood are misleading. Heidegger avoids the Cartesian problem of a postulating a gap between ourselves and the world and then never being able to close that gap (Rouse, 1981). He refers to the human being as “Dasein”, avoiding the term “subject” that would imply dualism (Dreyfus, 1993). Heidegger’s intentionality or being-in-the-world includes everyday activity that often involves a type of automatic behaviour which cannot be explained as rational purposive action because the person does not experience a sense of having intentions that cause the action (Dreyfus, 1993). Furthermore, they would find it difficult to supply a breakdown of their activities after or during the event. Talking, driving and playing a musical instrument are examples of this type of behaviour. For Heidegger, our everyday engagement in the 15 world involves absorption with a world that is already familiar to us. A person is thrown into the world and therefore understands the world automatically and unreflectively. According to Heidegger, Dasein relates to the objects in the external world in terms of the purposes for which they can be used as ‘ready-to-hand’. When we come across things which have no apparent purpose, we notice them only in so far as they have no use for us. They generally merge into the background as insignificant and we overlook them. Our primordial experience of objects is that we encounter things as equipment ‘in-order-to’ (Heidegger, 1978, p. 97) perform an act and we become absorbed in using these tools. For example, we do not see accounting numbers as lines on a page, but we are unreflectively absorbed with them as meaningful indicators that we can use and manipulate. Similarly, investment appraisal is not viewed as an abstract concept derived from economics, but we are conventionally preoccupied with it as a tool that we believe can assist managerial decision making. Thus, such tools are perspectival and non-neutral. Following Heidegger, Kompridis (1994; 2006a) suggests that our automatic absorption with the world through practical engagement produces a pre-reflective, tacit knowledge that may have the potential to be a source of authenticity and first-order disclosure. This may occur in accountants’ practical engagement with the tools of accounting and can be linked with emotions aroused by accounting (discussed in Section 3.5). Heidegger distinguishes the ‘ready-to-hand’ from the ‘present-at-hand’. In the case of experiencing objects as ‘present-at-hand’, they are experienced inauthentically in the detached manner of conventional dualism or science, offering no possibility of authenticity or disclosure for Dasein. Heidegger argues that existential phenomenology and his version of intentionality represents a much more fundamental explanation of being-in-the-world than attempts to objectify phenomena as ‘present-at-hand’ through mathematical natural sciences. 16 Although both Heidegger and Habermas acknowledge the value of conventional scientific method for certain purposes, they both undermine the notion of instrumental scientific rationality and objective absolute truths (even in logic) because in their view all knowledge is theory-laden and contextual. In Heidegger’s view, all truths arise from the context of Dasein through its automatic connection to the world. Recognising accounting as ‘ready-to-hand’ undermines its instrumental uses. The Heideggarian approach acknowledges that a science that does not overstate its knowledge claims may be usefully applied to accounting (illustrated in Section 4.3). It also emphasizes that scientific language and thinking represents only one of a number of possible accounting languages and ways of thinking about accounting. Heidegger’s hermeneutical intentionality leads to the use of dichotomous terms such as “authentic” or “inauthentic” and “transparent” or “opaque” rather than “true” or “false”, suggesting that interpretive understandings may often be better judged by labels other than “true” or “false” (Couzens Hoy, 1999, p.181). The recognition that truth is not absolute (or monistic) allows for the possibility of rich description that includes multiple, complex, evocative, poetic and subtle interpretations of research findings. It also accepts the incompleteness, ambiguity and indeterminacy of some interpretations. Interpretive accounting literature has provided many examples of rich descriptions (e.g. Boland, 1993; Chua, 1995; Preston et al., 1996; Czarniawska, 2012b) that can be linked back to Heidegger’s intentionality. Combining Habermas with Heidegger aims to ensure that rich interpretations are maintained within research informed by Habermas’ communicative rationality. The representationalist dualistic assumption that the mind is independent of an objective reality can be linked with three key accounting problems that Heidegger’s intentionality arguably overcomes. First, the exaggeration of accounting knowledge claims by presenting them as 17 eternal (absolute) truths because it is believed that they can somehow be known independently from the observer. Second, claiming that accounting knowledge is neutral when it is actually partisan and theory-laden (Tinker, 1991). Third, the implication of accounting in the legitimisation and normalisation of socially undesirable practices through incorrectly presenting accounting as unquestionable, objective and a purveyor of absolute truth (Neu et al., 2001; Chwastiak and Lehman, 2008). 3.2 The search for Being: an objective of disclosure In ‘Being and Time’ Heidegger’s hermeneutics aims to uncover fundamental, primordial commonalities of human existence that apply to everyday, average, general experiences. He is concerned to understand the meaning of Being. Heidegger does not provide a definition of Being but reveals its meaning throughout the text. “Being” in a simplistic sense refers to the meaning of existence. Understanding Being includes the search for who I am, what is my purpose and what is my relationship to the world and others? These are, of course, important questions for the construct of accounting and also for accountants and accounting researchers when considering accounting change. For Heidegger, the understanding of oneself is an essential precondition to enhancing society. Thus Mulhall (2005, p.193) says that Heidegger believes that an individual’s ‘capacity to grasp...the best destiny of her community’ is dependent on ‘an anticipatory grasp of her own future.’ The search for Being involves questioning assumptions and acknowledging the contextual nature of any philosophical questions that are posed. Mulhall (2005, p. 157) regards Heidegger’s quest to understand Being as ‘Heidegger’s attempt to make his own life an integral and singular whole’ or his search for personal authenticity. 18 Being is described by Heidegger as an issue for Dasein in that ‘every choice it makes...is a choice about the form that its own life will take’ (Mulhall, 2005, p. 66). The understanding of Being would be the ultimate objective of disclosure. Heidegger’s notions of intersubjectivity and intentionality mean that any attempt to understanding oneself or any individual authentic disclosure cannot escape its links with the language and culture that we share with others. Furthermore, any individual disclosure is always influenced by others through their actions. Thus a private transformation or following a rule that no-one else could follow is a contradiction in terms (Mulhall, 2005). Similarly, from a Habermasian perspective answers to questions such as “who am I?”, “what is my purpose?” and “what is my relationship to the world and others?” would be intersubjectively constituted. Unlike Heidegger, Habermas would emphasize the importance of open discussion and democratic procedures in addressing these questions. 3.3 Intersubjectivity, “they” and constraints to disclosure Although the relationship of Dasein with others is seen as a fundamental part of the disclosure of Being, such intersubjectivity is portrayed as complex with the potential to hinder or enhance disclosure, lying somewhere on a continuum of a dominating or a liberating relationship. In his words: ‘Everyday Being-with-one-another maintains itself between the two extremes of positive solicitude-that which leaps in and dominates, and that which leaps forth and liberates.’ (Heidegger, 1978, p. 159) 19 The everyday, inauthentic relationship with others is not regarded as fundamentally one of empathy. It is a relationship of intentionality where people come into focus because of their purpose for us and vice versa. Heidegger (1978) acknowledges power relations stating that we may seek to dominate the other or to differentiate ourselves from the other. He describes a particular as a form of domination whereby the individual becomes trapped by unquestioningly following the general view. Thus he says: ‘What is decisive is just that inconspicuous domination by Others which has already been taken over unawares from Dasein as Being-with. One belongs to the Others oneself and enhances their power.’ (Heidegger, 1978, p. 164) Heidegger is more critical of the public than Habermas. Whilst Habermas emphasizes the importance of the public for democratic accountability, Heidegger reminds us that their views may not always result in appropriate conclusions for disclosure. For Heidegger our everyday involvement with “they” can lead to following fashions and trends automatically without reflection or critique. He notes that “they” often show idle curiosity and an obsession with trivial novelty and he describes the “they” as ‘levelling down’ (p.165) and as never getting to ‘the heart of the matter’ (p. 165). The condition of “they” is linked to a form of communication which Heidegger designates “idle talk”. This includes gossip, closing-off discussion and new inquiry and superficial understanding. When engaged in “idle talk”, Dasein is said to be in a state of fallenness, defined as follows: 20 ‘“Fallenness” into the ‘world’ means an absorption in Being-with-one-another, in so far as the latter is guided by idle talk, curiosity and ambiguity.’ (Heidegger, 1978, p. 220) The pre-occupation with idle talk and the opinions of mass culture is associated with complacency, self-delusion, and alienation. Thus Heidegger (1978, p. 222) says: ‘When Dasein, tranquillized, and ‘understanding’ everything, thus compares itself with everything, it drifts along towards an alienation in which its ownmost potentiality-for-Being is hidden from it. Falling Being-in-the world is not only tempting and tranquillizing; it is at the same time alienating.’ The falling of Dasein constrains disclosure and change, as follows: ‘This downward plunge into and within the groundlessness of the inauthentic Being of the “they”, has a kind of motion which constantly tears the understanding away from the projecting of authentic possibilities, and into the tranquillized supposition that it possesses everything, or that everything is within reach’ (Heidegger, 1978, p. 223). 21 According to Heidegger, a preoccupation with the opinions and beliefs of an uninformed public also leads to a lack of individual responsibility and a lack of accountability. In Heidegger’s words: ‘Yet because the “they” presents every judgment and decision as its own, it deprives the particular Dasein of its answerability…It ‘was’ always the “they” who did it, and yet it can be said that it has been ‘no one’. In Dasein’s everydayness the agency through which most things come about is one of which we must say that “it was no one”.’ (Heidegger, 1978, p. 165) Mulhall (2005) interprets Heidegger’s critique of “they” as a critique of popular culture where the unusual and the difficult are avoided, and the prevailing opinion is accepted without question. The theme of idle talk has resonance to-day with the superficial, wasteful and distracting culture of celebrity in which accounting is implicated. Heidegger (1978, p. 223) evokes the image of an insatiable, unreflective consumerism, fuelled by unchecked capitalism, eroding scarce resources by producing endless unnecessary goods overconfidently assuming ‘that everything is within reach’. Such a society is currently supported by accounting, although accounting could use its tools that purport to measure efficiency and effectiveness, and are implicated in resource allocation, to undermine and critique these excesses. The critique of the “they” has resonance with the current context of accounting where there has been a rise of conservative governments ‘that manipulate media and intelligence’ creating ‘a depoliticised and uninformed citizenry’ (Lehman, 2010, p. 734) and where governments are also constrained by a conservative media. 22 In order to be able to detach ourselves from the opinions of “they”, Heidegger’s critique implies a need to supplement Habermas’ theory with proposals for how the public might have access to wider ranging, more transparent and more representative information to enhance democratic accountability. Since we are intrinsically connected to the world and to the other through being-in-the-world, Mulhall (2005, p. 73) observes that the type of change through disclosure envisaged by Heidegger, ‘must be a modification rather than a transcendence’ of our life. Similarly, Kompridis (2006b, p. 73) emphasizes that Heidegger is not arguing that Dasein should or could heroically escape the other, but rather that authenticity depends on transforming both our relationships with others and the constraints of everyday practice in which others are implicated. For Kompridis (2006b, p. 74), Heidegger is not concerned with a critique of mass culture as mass deception, but he is interested in ‘recovering the everyday, rescuing its semantic resources from daily degradation.’ Heidegger’s phenomenology arguably offers an additional dimension to developing ways of analysing micro politics and power relations extending Habermas’ more abstract, formal philosophical argument. Heidegger’s description of the everyday, inauthentic relationships of domination with “they” and his emphasis on emotions (discussed in Section 3.5) suggest that specific individuals can sometimes impose severe emancipatory constraints on others that seem to extend negatively beyond the institutional disciplinary requirements of their role. Whilst this type of abuse of power can cause individual misery for participants who may feel coerced to participate in actions that conflict with their own personal (or professional) ethical principles , it may sometimes be linked to corruption in accounting affecting society more widely (e.g. see Sikka, 2003). 23 3.4 Personal responsibility for disclosure Mulhall (2005, p. 66) observes that Heidegger’s ‘intersubjectivity is not the denial of subjectivity’. We note Heidegger’s emphasis on personal responsibility for disclosure. Such “subjectivity” includes self-awareness and the potential for authentic individualism and personal responsibility. Heidegger emphasizes the importance of personal responsibility in identifying future possibilities and working towards personal authenticity. He also highlights the significance of self-accountability as follows: ‘But this ‘public conscience’-what else is it than the voice of the “they”? A ‘worldconscience’ is a dubious fabrication, and Dasein can come to this only because conscience, in its basis and its essence, is in each case mine…’ (p. 323) Similarly Habermas (1991) highlights the importance of individual self-critique and individual responsibility in the development of moral consciousness. Applied to accounting Habermas’ view combined with Heideggarian themes of individual responsibility and authenticity (personal and societal) implies that many accountants and accounting academics should try to increase their moral responsibility and that it should be directed towards a wider range of stakeholders. 3.5 Moods, emotions and disclosure Mulhall (2005) observes that Heidegger introduces moods and emotions as socially conditioned phenomena that are connected with disclosure. Similarly Rouse (1981, p. 278) notes that for Heidegger ‘mood and understanding are co-determining’ and that certain 24 moods can influence Dasein’s potential to envisage possibilities whereas others may hinder disclosure. Heidegger discusses a variety of moods and emotions which are seen as important to the meaning of Being. Heidegger draws heavily on emotions emphasized in Christian theology including “the call”, “guilt”, “lostness” and a concern with death. Anxiety is an important emotion in the meaning of Being that Mulhall (2005) links with philosophical scepticism. It arises when Dasein becomes aware of its freedom to choose certain paths. Thus Heidegger (1978, p. 232) says: ‘Anxiety makes manifest in Dasein its Being towards its ownmost potentiality-for-Being-that is, its Being-free for the freedom of choosing itself and taking hold of itself. Anxiety brings Dasein face to face with…the authenticity of its Being...’ Dasein tends to behave in an automatic way in its daily routines which Heidegger (1978, p. 229) refers to as ‘fleeing in the face of itself’. However, from time to time it becomes aware of its possibilities and experiences anxiety and ‘uncanniness’ (Heidegger, 1978, p. 233). ‘…as Dasein falls, anxiety brings it back from its absorption in the ‘world’. Everyday familiarity collapses…Being-in enters into the existential ‘mode’ of the “not-at-home”’ (Heidegger, 1978, p. 233). One example of anxiety might be an accountant performing routine tasks and feeling a sense of disappointment or alienation in that accounting appears to be inadequately assisting in the 25 improvement of society. Emotions can trigger first-order disclosure in accounting. For example, in three case studies Oakes and Berry (2009) observed how accounting in its everyday ready-to-hand use was sometimes associated by organisational managers with feelings of pain. We could say that the pain was linked to a raised awareness of accounting as problematic acting as a potential precursor to second order disclosure that considers alternative possibilities. For Heidegger (1978), a basic structure of Dasein is ‘care’ which has three sub-categories: ‘facticity (thrownness), existence (projection), and falling’ (p. 329). We note that although care is a general concept in Heidegger’s ontology, it has emotional elements and connotations. For example, ‘the existential phenomena of death, conscience, and guilt are anchored in the phenomenon of care’ (Heidegger, 1978, p. 365). “Care” is also linked with “concern”. Mulhall (2005, p. 112) interprets Heidegger’s “concern” to mean that ‘Dasein is always occupied with the entities it encounters in the world-concerned about ready-to-hand and present-at-hand entities, and solicitous of other human beings...The world and everything in it is something that cannot fail to matter to it.’ Although concern may involve particular instances of lack of concern, Dasein’s basic orientation is as a being capable of concern (Mulhall, 2005). In our view, this suggests Dasein has, at its root, the potential for positive emotions that can trigger disclosure and positive actions towards others. Two other emotions that have the potential to trigger disclosure are the call of conscience and guilt. Thus, Dasein gains awareness of its potential for self-direction through a call of conscience and it experiences guilt. Heidegger (1978, p. 333) says: 26 ‘This calling-back in which conscience calls forth, gives Dasein to understand that Dasein itself…is to bring itself back from its lostness in the “they”; and this means that it is guilty’. The call of conscience acts as a catalyst for suggesting utopian possibilities (second-order disclosure). It can be read as intersubjective and dialogical, recognising that others can both provide reassurance that we have our own voice and make us question whether the voice that we have is our own (Kompridis, 2006b). In contrast to emotions and moods that have the potential to trigger disclosure, wishing represents a sublimation of Dasein’s authentic awareness of its own possibilities. It involves a perpetual dissatisfaction with current material possessions and a ‘hankering after possibilities’ (Heidegger, 1978, p. 239) and desire for new possessions. A positive reading of Heidegger could envisage authentic versions of Heidegger’s themes of care and concern to recognise the emotional resonance of these constructs. Such a reading (informed by Guignon, 1999, discussed in Section 4.1) would include care and concern for others as well as care for self. Interpreting Heidegger’s theme of care and concern in this way allows us to highlight the emotional impact of accounting on others, to raise awareness of the needs of others and to press for those needs to be satisfied. Various types of respect and love for others have been discussed in accounting research by Macintosh et al. (2009) who draw on Levinas and also by Molisa (2011) who proposes the transformation of egoic consciousness to attain an egoless state. However, Heidegger’s concepts of care and concern do not require the total self-sacrifice of Molisa’s (2011) idealised, unconditional spiritual love 27 of the other or the almost coercive obligation to the other evoked by Macintosh et al. (2009). This chimes with Habermas’ (1996) concern with the rights of the individual as well as the rights of the other and the group. Heidegger could be interpreted as balancing a care and concern for self and self-emancipation with a care and concern for others and their emancipation. Such a view is suggested by the lack of clear distinction between subject and object arising from Heidegger’s intentionality. Care and concern for self would not involve the conventional self-interest of accounting and economics but would focus on a noninstrumentalized co-operation requiring ‘commitment to a process that we can neither control nor direct’ (Kompridis, 2006b, p. 50). It would involve moral and cognitive learning ‘that may require a change in how we, speak, think, and act’ (Kompridis, 2006b, p. 50). It has been argued that Habermas’ rationalism is de-humanised and does not recognise the significance of emotions (e.g. Benhabib, 1986; Mouffe, 1998; Brown, 2009). Benhabib (1986) observes that the ideal speech situation was not intended merely as a legalistic procedure aiming at improving justice but was to be concerned through psychoanalytic reconstruction with improving the happiness of the community and individuals. Heidegger’s approach reinforces Benhabib’s (1986) proposal for an extension to Habermas’ theory. Through privileging emotions and moods and suggesting care for self and others, Heidegger’s theory supports the importance of empowering an individual to be able to express their own emotions and needs to others and can be interpreted to promote the happiness and wellbeing of self and others. It assists in recognising Benhabib’s (1986) notion of distinctive individuals, focusing on their identities, beliefs, needs, desires, feelings and emotions. In addition, the dignity of the other would be acknowledged, along with an empathetic approach towards the other, respecting their ‘differences, individual life-histories and concrete needs’ (Benhabib, 1986, p. 351). 28 3.6 Disclosure through death and art Dasein does not necessarily remain fallen and lost. It can project itself and become aware of its possibilities. Projection is an authentic mode of Being representing an understanding that reveals the ‘truth of existence’ (Heidegger, 1978, p. 264). It is linked to resoluteness where Dasein is aware of its own possibilities through facing up to the inevitability of death. The possibilities which become evident are conceived as practical and achievable as indicated in the following extract: ‘Neither does anticipatory resoluteness stem from ‘idealistic’ exactions soaring above existence and its possibilities; it springs from a sober understanding of what are factically the basic possibilities for Dasein’ (Heidegger, 1978, p. 358). Everyday Dasein evades its own mortality, encouraged by its preoccupation with following the opinions of “they”. However, the ultimate meaning of Being is Dasein facing up to its own inevitable death. In Heidegger’s words: ‘Death is Dasein’s ownmost possibility. Being towards this possibility discloses to Dasein its ownmost potentiality-for-Being, in which its very Being is the issue’ (Heidegger, 1978, p. 307). 29 The acknowledgement of death is a revelatory moment of disclosure for Dasein allowing it to create authentic possibilities for the future, spurred on by the urgency of the relative shortness of life. Recognition of one’s own death frees Dasein from the superficiality of the general opinions of “they”. Heidegger (1978, p. 308) observes: ‘When, by anticipation, one becomes free for one’s own death, one is liberated from one’s lostness in those possibilities which may accidentally thrust themselves upon one; and one is liberated in such a way that for the first time one can authentically understand and choose among the factical possibilities lying ahead of that possibility which is not to be outstripped.’ When Dasein is in this authentic mode in the present it is open to new horizons and visions, as follows: ‘When resolute, Dasein has brought itself back from falling, and has done so precisely in order to be more authentically ‘there’ in the ‘moment of vision’ as regards the Situation which has been disclosed’ (Heidegger, 1978, p. 376). Mulhall (2005, p. 159) notes that ‘resoluteness discloses the current moment of Dasein’s existence as a situation for choice and action’ and it ‘implies a triple but internally related openness to future, past and present’ (Mulhall, 2005, p. 160) with particular emphasis on the future through anticipation. 30 Heidegger’s description of the moment of insight where possibilities for an authentic existence are opened up is linked to an awareness of one’s mortality but also resonates with the disclosure that can be provided in a work of art. For example, he links poetry with disclosure as follows: ‘In ‘poetical’ discourse, the communication of the existential possibilities of one’s state-ofmind can become an aim in itself, and this amounts to a disclosing of existence’ (Heidegger, 1978, p. 205). Kompridis (2006a, p. 335) argues that the rational reconstructions of Habermas ‘can never serve as a bridge between what is and what might be, between actuality and possibility’. Thus they cannot yield the utopian ideas that should be the outcome of critique. Kompridis (1994) notes that instead of Habermasian reason-giving, an alternative Heideggarian rationality is required which may, like a work of art, ‘light up a world’ and ‘open our eyes’ (p. 35) ‘disclosing alternative horizons of meaning’ (p. 40). In our view Heidegger’s moments of insight could supplement Habermasian reason-giving. If accounting were linked to Heideggarian second-order disclosure, it could be viewed more widely as art, and existing connections with artistic and creative thinking could be extended, potentially creating new ways of seeing and opening up the utopian possibilities that Habermas intended. Although Habermas does not regard poetic or fictional language as ideally suited to practical discourse, McKernan and MacLullich (2004) observe that it is widely used in problem solving and are sceptical about Habermas’ attempt to exclude it from debate. Heidegger shows us by example in his writing style that poetry can have a powerful persuasive influence and may on occasion have a more direct appeal for some than the more objective style of 31 Habermas. Thus we suggest that when considering accounting change, Habermas’ idealised “force of the better argument” should include a kind of rationality that after disclosure of possibilities sometimes makes use of non-coercive rhetoric, emotions and poetry to try to achieve consensus as part of a decision-making process. However, we recognise that it is sometimes difficult to distinguish coercive from non-coercive rhetoric. It must be persuasive but not intentionally deceptive and it must be open to self-critique (Kompridis, 2006b). In some cases it would need to be presented with irony to highlight its persuasive and manipulative attributes. 3.7 Disclosure through phenomenological time The recognition of one’s mortality is linked to an existential phenomenological understanding of time. Heidegger refers to the phenomenon of the future, the character of having been and the present as the “ecstasies” of temporality. He says that: ‘Temporalizing does not signify that ecstasies come in a ‘succession’. The future is not later than having been, and having been is not earlier than the Present. Temporality temporalizes itself as a future which makes present in the process of having been’ (Heidegger, 1978, p. 401). Mulhall (2005, p.206) notes that ‘the temporality of Dasein’s Being means that Dasein is [or exists as] time rather than existing in time’. Dasein projects into the future but is also aware of its past or ‘having been’, thus releasing itself from its inauthentic, superficial present where it is distracted by “they”. Time is treated through intentionality as purposeful ‘for-the32 sake-of-which’ (Heidegger, 1978, p. 467) rather than being treated conventionally, and inauthentically, as a scientific object for measurement or as a subjective experience. Time is regarded as fundamental to existence and the quest to understand Being because it relates to the anticipation of death. For Heidegger the conventional view of time covers up the awareness of death and consequential authentic possibilities. He says: ‘The principal thesis of the ordinary way of interpreting time-namely that time is ‘infinite’makes manifest most impressively the way in which world-time and accordingly temporality in general have been levelled off and covered up by such an interpretation. It is held that time presents itself proximally as an uninterrupted sequence of “nows”’ (Heidegger, 1978, p. 476). Heidegger’s emphasis on phenomenological time can be contrasted with disciplinary and political uses of conventional linear accounting time (see Ezzamel and Robson, 1995). Consideration of phenomenological time suggests emancipatory potential for the use of time in accounting with broader societal implications. For example, accounting divides time up artificially and focuses on the short-term, whereas environmental problems require a longterm approach (Jones, 2010). Heidegger’s emphasis on projection towards future possibilities informed by the past supports a long-term strategic approach required for environmental accounting. Mulhall (2005, p. 192) observes that Heidegger’s ‘critique of the present must be guided by a disclosure of the true heritage of existentiell possibilities from which an individual and a community can project that future’. Heidegger’s concept of phenomenological time has links with Habermas’ psychoanalytic reconstruction where the 33 interpretation of the past becomes significant for the present and the future. Indeed future projections are always linked to the past and rendered intelligible by past meanings. Kompridis (2006b) amplifies Heidegger’s emphasis on unclosing the past to reopen the future by noting that in a modernistic age where the past tends to be erased and newness is idolised for its own sake, when developing alternative possibilities we need to be receptive to what has been lost (p. 265) and we need to recover ‘the speech of those who would otherwise have been silenced’ (p. 269), re-awakening utopias. For Heidegger, past, present and future appear to co-exist in the second-order disclosure of new possibilities, triggered by emotions such as anxiety and recognition of one’s mortality. In such disclosure, the past, the present and the future reciprocally question and illuminate one another (Mulhall, 2005). History is fluid for both Habermas and Heidegger. However, for Habermas the process of reconstruction through history is more methodological, scientific and self-conscious than Heidegger’s visionary, intuitive disclosure of possibilities. Heidegger’s concept of time is fundamental to the notion of disclosure and it has important implications for accounting change. In addition to utilising Habermasian reconstructive insights, accounting has the potential to contribute positively to emancipatory goals if it opens up to Heidegger’s phenomenological notion of time, allowing interpretations of past present and future to intermingle. From a Heideggarian perspective, accounting can project new possibilities by drawing on its emotional associations to precipitate disclosure and also by developing its associations with art. It must also recognise the need for timely action given the finitude of an individual’s existence. Mouffe (1998) argues that Habermas’ consensus ultimately closes off possibilities. However, combining communicative rationality 34 with Heidegger’s disclosure through phenomenological time can assist by opening up possibilities for the self and other, accommodating Benhabib’s (1986) extension to Habermas that highlights the importance of giving voice to, and extending rights for diverse groups (e.g. groups categorised by disability, ethnicity, gender, age and sexuality) that are not specifically identified in Habermas’ early texts and are often neglected in accounting and accountability. 4. Reflection on the synthesis of Habermas and Heidegger This section briefly reflects on several key interpretations of Heidegger including Habermas’ critique of Heidegger. It also defends synthesizing Habermas and Heidegger. It concludes by presenting a model for the reconstruction of accounting that includes our synthesis of Habermas and Heidegger. 4.1 Reading Heidegger The ambiguity in Heidegger’s writing suggests many possibilities (Smith, 2002), and we are aware of a number of contradictory readings offered by scholars. For example, Smith (2002) argues that Heidegger has no moral dimension. In contradistinction, Guignon (1999, p.2) indicates that Heidegger takes a Hegelian communitarian stance. He states that because we are inextricably linked to objects and others, Heidegger’s authenticity ‘can be nothing other than a fuller and richer form of participation in the public context’ (Guignon, 1999, p. 228). Thus he argues that Heidegger’s intentionality and intersubjectivity entail a community and moral perspective. Guignon (1999) indicates that Heidegger’s concept of “authentic historicity” supports this interpretation. In his words: 35 ‘Where inauthentic Dasein just drifts along with the latest trends, authentic Dasein “remembers” its rootedness in the wider unfolding culture’ (Guignon, 1999, p. 234) Hence, authentic Dasein does recognise its links with the community and the shared quest for ‘fairness, honesty, dignity, benevolence, achievement, and so on’ (Guignon, 1999, p. 235). Freedom arises from gaining ‘clarity and depth’ about this community context which already shapes our lives, rather than having unconstrained freedom (Guignon, 1999, p. 235). According to Guignon (1999), Dasein understands historicity and community through narratives which always have a normative dimension. Thus fact and value or ‘is’ and ‘ought’, as Heidegger suggests, cannot be separated. For Guignon (1999), Heidegger escapes the relativism of many possibilities with no reason for choosing one over the other, by having a concept of community that provides a reason for making particular choices regarding the future. This reading aligns Heidegger quite closely to Habermas’ notion of communicative action. Furthermore Guignon observes that Heidegger suggests the individual may become more attuned to their moral role, as follows: ‘What is important is building myself as this kind of person, not scoring points or getting rewards “down the road”’ (Guignon, 1999 p. 231). This chimes with Habermas’ (1991) theme of the development of individual moral consciousness. Despite the arguments for Heidegger’s community perspective, we note the 36 powerful narrative of individualism in Heidegger which would reveal itself in Habermasian communicative rationality as Benhabib’s (1986, p. 348) ‘unity-in-difference’. For example, Heidegger (1978, p. 326) states that future vision is personal, localised and contextual, as follows: ‘When the call gives us potentiality-for-Being to understand, it does not give us one which is ideal and universal; it discloses it as that which has been currently individualized and which belongs to that particular Dasein.’ We resolve this slight theoretical mismatch by suggesting that both Heidegger and Habermas offer a balance between individualism and community orientation. 4.2 Some limitations and objections to Heidegger In our view, Heidegger’s emphasis on individualism and his ambivalence towards “they” from whom the individual must break free suggests that his notion of community is different from Habermas’ conception of community. For Heidegger, others are often associated with inauthenticity and seen as a constraint on the freedom of individuals. Furthermore, he does not develop his notion of intersubjectivity and does not specify how others might be viewed in an authentic context. In contrast, Habermas respects and demands the opinion of the ordinary person, speaks positively about grass roots organisations as sources of liberation and critiques the notion of “experts”. We have interpreted Heidegger as championing the concept of individual emancipation and social emancipation through disclosing possibilities as the ultimate meaning of Being, yet unlike Habermas he offers no specific suggestions 37 about how such emancipation might be achieved by an individual or through social mechanisms. Furthermore, whilst Heidegger draws attention to a necessity for individual accountability and individual responsibility for emancipation, unlike Habermas he does not discuss how conflicting individual visions might be resolved. Thus in our view Heidegger’s theory should be regarded as an adjunct to Habermas’ theory rather than being treated as the main theory. Habermas is highly critical of Heidegger and it is unlikely that he would support our synthesis. One key argument offered by Habermas (1998) is that Heidegger never manages to escape the subjectivity of the philosophy of consciousness and therefore Heidegger’s position is solipsistic and he is unable to justify a critical or emancipatory stance. We counter by noting that as a consequence of Heidegger’s intentionality, the individual is automatically connected to others and shaped by others and therefore his subjectivity cannot be solipsistic. Habermas also criticises Heidegger’s individualism and unlike Guignon (1999) does not recognise Heidegger’s concern for the community. Heidegger’s subjectivism is problematic for Habermas (1998) in part because it reintroduces individual needs and the possibility of utilitarianism as a justification for ethical principles where it is assumed that the freedom of one individual can substitute for the freedom of every individual. However, we read Heidegger as supporting a subjectivism that balances a care for self and community. Such subjectivism is capable of suggesting emancipatory possibilities drawing on own our phenomenological relationship with time. A number of scholars have argued that Habermas’ theory is inadequate in general (e.g. Mouffe, 1998) or inadequate for accounting critique (e.g. Lehman, 2006; Brown, 2009). We concur with scholars who have argued that Habermas’ theory although impressively 38 comprehensive and unified, needs extending (e.g. Benhabib, 1986) and we have followed Kompridis (1994; 2006a; 2006b) in using Heidegger to extend Habermasian theory. Furthermore, we observe some similarities between the theories of Habermas and Heidegger that facilitate such a synthesis. First we observe a similarity between Habermas’ privileging of the lifeworld and Heidegger’s privileging primordial experience. Second, Heidegger wishes for a society that moves beyond the world of the uninformed “they” whereas Habermas aims for a society that overcomes the colonization of the lifeworld. Third, they both search for hidden meanings and they both place an emphasis on critically interpreting the past to provide future possibilities. Fourth, they both emphasize the contextual nature of knowledge. 4.3 A reconstruction of accounting We can apply the interplay of the theories of Habermas and Heidegger to propose a reconstruction of accounting that would involve a fundamental re-think of the assumptions of accounting, including its knowledge claims and its objectives. We use the term ‘reconstruction’ to comprise Habermas’ rational reconstruction and self-reflection, Heidegger’s disclosure and Habermas’ societal reconstruction. Habermas’ attempt to link interpretive procedures from hermeneutics and phenomenology with grand social theory, supported by Heidegger’s disclosure, suggests an ambitious framework for accounting researchers and accounting practitioners. It is intended that Heidegger’s phenomenological perspective would be interwoven with a range of critical approaches when reflecting on a context in order to suggest emancipatory possibilities for change underpinned by Habermasian democratic procedures. The framework incorporates five dimensions: historical critique, philosophical critique, phenomenological critique, political critique and emancipatory procedures and possibilities (see figure one). 39 Figure 1: The reconstruction of accounting Historical Critique Philosophical Critique Phenomenological Critique Political Critique Examine changing histories Question assumptions Draw on: Identify: Acknowledge provisional status of knowledge claims Emotions Legitimation crises Intuitive experiences of disclosure Power relations in macro and micro politics Search for hidden meanings Revelation of the relative freedom to consider potentially authentic possibilities Inauthentic consumerism Develop emancipatory approaches Communicative action Deliberative democracy New artistic ways of thinking New symbols and new language Self-critique in moral consciousness Expand lifeworld Extend care and concern for self and others New democratic, ethically conscious accounting tools The historical critique includes attempts to identify possible misinterpretations of tradition and ‘concrete possibilities in the tradition that have currently been lost from sight’ (Couzens Hoy, 1999, p.191) as a basis for disclosing future possibilities. The philosophical critique 40 would include continuing to develop our understanding of the nature of accounting. This could include asking why certain types of management accounting information and financial accounting information are provided rather than other types. It would promote a questioning of assumptions that lie behind International Accounting Standards and Tax avoidance regulations and it would encourage the Heideggerian disclosure of alternatives. The philosophical critique suggests that organisational reports increasingly should become narratives that move beyond the concerns prescribed by convention or by the organisation, discovering other possibilities. As an example, University operational reports in the U.K. could include data on staff and student wellbeing in addition to the typical data on student demand, retention, progression, academic attainment and module evaluation. Heidegger’s idle talk can be applied to orthodox accounting’s assumption that markets represent the best way to allocate resources. Idle talk also occurs when the limitations of markets are acknowledged but there is general unwillingness to develop or consider alternative models. Further examples of idle talk include conventional accounting’s emphasis on the values of business and competition, and its tendency to exclude other discourses, focusing solely on profit and cost reduction. Our Habermasian and Heidegerrian approach suggests that we need to reflect on (and critique) all the tools and regulations of accounting that are implicated in idle talk that glorifies markets and privileges business language and objectives. It suggests that we should devise new tools and forms of accounting where appropriate. Furthermore, the philosophical critique would not overstate the knowledge claims of accounting, acknowledging its uncertainties and limitations. For example, Brown (2009, p. 330) develops a Sustainability Assessment Model (SAM) that ‘seeks to deal openly with scientific uncertainty (e.g. reporting estimates in terms of ranges rather than single 41 numbers)’. Similarly, Gallhofer and Haslam (1996) propose that accountants could demonstrate their uncertainty and fallibility by using question marks in annual reports. The political critique would include analysing inauthentic consumerism and the influence of the “they” in accounting. Heidegger’s critique of consumerism provides further justification for sustainability and environmental reporting and suggests we should carefully consider which businesses are legalised, supported and allowed to advertise. The political critique would explore power relations including disputes and compromises at macro and micro level in which accounting is implicated, developing an historical understanding, and using Habermas’ (1976) Legitimation crisis where appropriate. It could also draw on sociological theories including Boltanski and Thévenot’s sociology of worth described by Annisette and Richardson (2011) to identify current processes of compromise. These processes would then be subjected to philosophical critique as a precursor to trying to understand how we might move towards a more authentically democratic Habermasian compromise, potentially leading to a fairer alternative to capitalism. The political critique suggests that we need to consider whether the types of organisation and society that accounting supports are appropriate for our needs. The Habermasian model of reconstruction should help to secure positive accounting change and beneficial societal reform by encouraging inner reflection and giving voice to all affected parties. Habermasian reconstruction requires a move to new organisation structures with increased democratic power arrangements and an enhanced concern for others in a process of moral development. Through Habermasian reconstruction we hopefully move towards new less selfish ethical principles which we must enact, and we develop new roles for accountants, auditors and tax 42 advisors. Accounting and accountants can become increasingly involved in improving equality of opportunity and justice in regard to ethnicity, age, disability, gender and class, developing appropriate accounting regulations, reports, models and tools. Brown (2009) provides an example of how critical dialogic principles can be applied to the SAM. In Brown’s (2009) model, various participants construct their own SAM which can be used as a basis for negotiation. This gives voice to all interested parties and has the potential to undermine powerful elite groups. Although informed by agonistic democracy, Brown’s (2009, p. 333) dialogic SAM reflects themes from our Habermasian Heideggerian approach including recognizing ‘the subjective and contestable nature of what is included’, enabling ‘accessibility for non-experts’, ensuring ‘effective participatory processes’ and using SAMS ‘to challenge power elites’. Social accounts could be produced by alliances of groups within and across organisations (e.g. trade unions) potentially contributing towards a prefiguration of a new non-capitalist social order (Lee and Cassell, 2008). Applying a Habermasian approach to organisational budgets would make them more transparent and participatory. Genuine rather than pseudo-participation is necessary. In in some organisations, participation in strategy formulation (disclosing the future) may become more authentic to lower level employees if linkages between strategic documents, operational budgets and organisational timeframes are clarified in order to demonstrate how strategic objectives might be enacted. Evans (2004) argues that deliberative democracy is feasible from an economic perspective and provides two examples of deliberative democracy in practice at local level in Kerala and Porto Alegre. Such projects may provide the starting point for a wider development of deliberative democracy at local and national level. The phenomenological critique draws on Heidegger in five key ways. First, through Heideggerian intentionality, we recognise the value of multiple perspectives which supports 43 Habermas’ communicative rationality and deliberative democracy. Second, it acknowledges the value of non-rational, intuitive, improvisatory and artistic approaches to emancipatory thinking in accounting and the significant role of moods in triggering disclosure. Third, it recognises the partial, incomplete nature of knowledge and the way some tacit knowledge cannot be fully grasped or reconstructed. Fourth, the approach acknowledges that two different interpretations may sometimes be equally plausible and equally justifiable. This alleviates any dogmatism that might arise when a Habermasian consensus is required for decision making but there isn’t a “better” argument. Fifth, the phenomenological conception of time connects all parts of the reconstructive disclosure. Past, present and future coincide in the disclosure of new possibilities, triggered by emotions such as anxiety and recognition of one’s mortality. The combination of Habermas with Heidegger’s intentionality provides philosophical justification for alternative social or sustainable accounts. As Cooper and Thomson (2000, p.27) suggest, since accounting ‘is not an independent scientific language’ but is perspectival and politicised, many types of accounts are possible not merely ‘simple single monolithic accounts’ (Cooper and Thomson, 2000, p. 27). They argue for accounts that involve ‘softer valuation concepts, multiple accounting entities, stressing interrelationship rather than dominance, stressing non-financial measures, using narrative, making less claim to objective scientific truth and giving voice to those silenced by current hegemonies’ (Cooper and Thomson, 2000, p. 27). As a specific example, they argue that National Accounts could include many excluded items such as the distribution of income, payment and valuation of domestic labour, valuation of leisure time, an analysis of the quality of work required and an assessment of future costs associated with current activities. 44 Intentionality has implications for models of accounting decision making. The close linkage between orthodox accounting and neo-class economics means that it typically adopts a rational decision making model that privileges self-interest (Shearer, 2002). One reason why this model is inappropriate is because we are not independent rational subjects assessing the world in an unbiased way, as the model suggests. Adopting a Heideggarian approach, we are already thrown into the world and ‘we accept a Symbolic Order which is already in place’ (Cooper and Thomson, 2000, p. 27). Since Dasein is inextricably connected to the world, Heidegger’s view can be argued to decentre humans and emphasize care for all beings and for the environment (Zimmerman, 1999) supporting environmental reporting and reporting for animal rights. Furthermore, since a Heideggarian approach suggests that decision making is perspectival, non-neutral and not absolute, alternative decision making models can be considered. For example, investment appraisal models can focus on other objectives that may place less emphasis on self-interest, profit maximisation, and net present value and more emphasis on care for others. In regard to the value of artistic approaches to emancipatory thinking in accounting, Heidegger suggests a type of reflection which is less rational and less formal than Habermas’ concept of reflection. This type of reflection underpins Heidegger’s disclosure of possibilities and is closely linked to creative thinking and artistic interpretation. It allows us to draw on half formed memories of past events and vague recollections of ethical rules that we think may have guided past decisions. Using Habermasian rationality we can try to bring them in to focus and interrogate them. Creative thinking allows us to draw inspiration from artworks and metaphors which may suggest several partially indistinct ideas as we sketch and design new possibilities for accounting and society. As we clarify and refine our visions for 45 accounting and society, we discuss them with others through Habermas’ deliberative democracy. Czarniawska (2012a) reminds us that accounting is already implicated in generating fictions in organizations. Therefore, an extension of the fictionalizing role of accounting to disclose positive beneficial emancipatory possibilities and utopias seems feasible. Indeed, fictions can be implicated in actions and Heidegger’s possibilities are practical, being inevitably grounded in concrete situations. Thus, society can work towards achieving the possibilities disclosed. Gallhofer and Haslam (1996) exemplify creative disclosure by showing how the form of accounting reports, informed by critical artworks, could be transformed into more authentic and emancipatory forms of communication. For example, they discuss how positive and negative environmental and social implications of projects could be demonstrated through contrasting visual media. In addition, accounting reports could partly be used didactically to raise awareness of emancipatory issue, and their medium of communication could be more diverse (possibly including stories, songs and plays) in order to reach a wider audience (Gallhofer and Haslam, 1996). Our Heideggarian perspective suggests that rather than the discussion and reporting of moods and emotions being discouraged and even eradicated from some forms of organisational discourse, moods and emotions could be routinely discussed and reported as potential indicators of problems that may need addressing. For example, organisations could discuss occasions when accounting is implicated in anxiety and distress and could consider such moments as catalysts for change. Anxiety linked to cost reductions in public sector organisations in the U.K. could be discussed openly in written and verbal communications 46 without fear of retribution. Currently, in some organisations, stress and anxiety is reported anonymously by a Union and is not openly discussed or reported through other channels. Adopting Heidegger’s disclosure and concern with authenticity, U.K. public service organisations in general might openly discuss problems relating to reductions in service quality that are linked to cost reductions, rather than distractingly over-emphasizing other discourses, as is sometimes the case. Those who offer critique, such as ‘whistleblowers’, would be protected rather than vilified, as sometimes occurs. The phenomenological critique would also encourage the reflective approach described by Dunham (2010, p. 524) requiring ‘the full engagement of one’s emotional, imaginative and moral capacities’. In regard to the partial, incomplete nature of knowledge, Gallhofer and Haslam (1996) demonstrate how artistic arrangements of accounting information could be used to demonstrate the perspectival and ambiguous nature of accounting, reinforcing Heidegger’s hermeneutics. Furthermore, in Heidegger’s disclosure we should not be afraid to articulate half formed memories that are not necessarily totally rational and to present ideas in a more artistic format, perhaps using less orthodox forms and extending metaphor. For example, Gibbon (2012) found that the use of a garden metaphor helped to develop her understanding and practical application of social accounting. Re-constructions of accounting theory and accounting tools would be disseminated through accounting teaching, text books and practice. Baxter et al. (2008) note that interpretive research could be further developed to assist in the education of accounting and management students. We suggest that further research could explore ways in which a study of Heidegger could assist in developing managerial approaches to practical problem solving. 47 5. Conclusions The discussion of Habermas’ discursive theory of reconstruction in this paper suggests that Habermas develops a form of rationalism which transcends instrumental, conventional rationalism by developing communicative rationality. The current paper has indicated that Habermas’ reconstructive theory of communicative rationality is significant for accounting change for a number of reasons. First, it emphasizes the need to provide reasons for proposals that would be debated democratically, rather than reverting to irrationality and extreme relativism. Second, it provides a justification of moral truth through procedure with the proviso that such truth is always open to question and capable of change. Third, it offers procedures to enhance democracy and justice. Fourth, it provides a political critique of the status quo. Fifth, it indicates a way forward through extending learning and moral development. Despite the strengths and scope of Habermas’ integrated theory, we concur with McCarthy (1978) that Habermas’ intention to combine a hermeneutical and selfreflective dimension with his “objective” linguistic structuralism has not been realised in the works we have considered. For example, several scholars have argued that Habermas emphasizes rationalism at the expense of hermeneutics (e.g. Benhabib, 1986; Lehman, 2006). The paper has proposed supplementing Habermas’ theory with several themes from Heidegger’s work to help to move towards a balance between rationalism and critical interpretivism. Heidegger’s work discusses a form of disclosure which emphasizes that a range of experiences including tacit learning and creative insight can provide resources for suggesting new possibilities, in addition to formal rationalistic thinking. For example, in first-order disclosure, reflection on our experiences when we are absorbed in the ready-tohand, and reflection on tacit learning can draw attention to practices that may require change. Kompridis (1994) observes that second-order disclosure highlights the importance of 48 moments of insight, intuition and revelation similar to those that can occur when we are contemplating art or engaged in art. These forms of disclosure emphasize interpretive critical reflection and creative processes of imagination crucial to accounting change. Heidegger emphasizes that emotions such as anxiety, concern and the call of conscience can also act as catalysts for disclosure. Furthermore, Heidegger’s use of poetry and rhetoric suggests a possible value in extending their use in accounting. Indeed, Heidegger’s concept of disclosure reinforces the idea that alternative languages and alternative ways of seeing are possible for accounting through our process of reconstruction. A further key aspect of disclosure is Heidegger’s phenomenology of time which suggests that we should not be distracted by the trivial. Instead, spurred on by the recognition of our own mortality, we should draw on our fundamental urge to project future potentially authentic possibilities, acknowledge our relative freedom to create and choose such possibilities, and make choices from these possibilities. Although Heidegger does not focus directly on questions of justice as Habermas does, he can be interpreted to suggest a form of disclosure that opens possibilities for the future and drives us towards exploring utopian possibilities of change through his view of Being and Time. Such disclosure would be partial and on-going and it would be associated with modification rather than transcendence of our lives. It would involve extending self-decentred learning, the renewal of trust, increased individual responsibility for problem-solving, expanding co-operative problem solving (Kompridis, 2006b) and it would require enhancing public access to a wider range of information. The proposed alternatives arising from disclosure would be debated democratically according to Habermasian procedures. Whereas some have felt that Habermas’ modernistic rationality and goal of consensus ultimately fixes and closes off truth and change possibilities (e.g. Mouffe, 1998), Heidegger 49 provides a bridge that opens up theory to allow the adoption of certain ideas from postmodernism (e.g. indeterminacy of meaning, différance) that can enhance our understanding of accounting. Heidegger emphasizes that truth is always open to question and we do not have to rely solely on the scientific view of the world. Thus we can include a range of perspectives and can move away from instrumental rationality. Supplementing Habermas with Heidegger keeps our theoretical options open and expands theoretical space. We have provided a model summarizing a Habermasian reconstructive approach that incorporates Heidegger’s phenomenological perspective and we have illustrated some of the implications of our Habermasian and Heideggerian synthesis for accounting. We have attempted to demonstrate the continuing relevance of Habermas’ theory for emancipatory accounting, even though it has recently been the subject of criticism in some accounting literature. We have suggested that Heidegger’s theory is a significant underpinning theory of interpretive accounting research and we have endeavoured to give a flavour of the potential of both Habermasian and Heideggerian theory for stimulating many further insights and developments in accounting and accounting research. Although it is expected that the Habermasian reconstruction of accounting we have presented would be challenging for accounting researchers and accounting practitioners, we hope that it can be used by these groups when trying to critically reconstruct an understanding of a particular context, with a view to contributing to a move towards a more emancipatory accounting and a fairer society. References Ahrens, T, Becker, A, Burns, J, Chapman, C S, Granlund, M, Habersam, M, Hansen, A, Khalifa, R, Malmi, T, Mennicken, A, Mikes, A, Panozzo, F, Piber, M, Quattrone, P, Scheytt, T. The future of interpretive accounting research—A polyphonic debate. Critical Perspectives on Accounting 2008; 19 (6): 840–66. Annisette M, Richardson A J. Justification of accounting: applying sociology of worth to accounting research. Accounting, Auditing & Accountability Journal 2011; 24(2):229-49. 50 Archel P, Husillos J, Spence C. The institutionalisation of unaccountability: loading the dice of corporate social responsibility discourse. Accounting, Organizations and Society 2011; 36(6):327-34. Benhabib S. Critique, norm and utopia. A study of the foundations of Critical Theory. New York: Columbia University Press; 1986. Boland, R J. Jr. Accounting and the interpretive act. Accounting, Organizations and Society 1993; 18 (2–3): 125–46. Broadbent J, Laughlin R. Developing empirical research: an example informed by a Habermasian approach. Accounting, Auditing & Accountability Journal 1997; 10(5): 622-48. Brown J. Democracy, sustainability and dialogic accounting technologies: taking pluralism seriously. Critical Perspectives on Accounting 2009; 20(3):313-42. Brunsson N. The irrationality of action and action rationality: decisions, ideologies and organizational actions. Journal of Management Studies 1982; 19(1): 29-44. Chabrak N. The politics of transcendence: hermeneutic phenomenology and accounting policy. Critical perspectives on Accounting 2005; 16(6):701-16. Chua WF. Experts, networks and inscriptions in the fabrication of accounting images: a story of the representation of three public hospitals. Accounting, Organizations and Society 1995;20(2/3):111–45. Chwastiak M, Lehman G. Accounting for war. Accounting Forum 2008; 32(4):313-26. Cooper C, Thomson I. The social and political roles of national accounting. In:Simon S, Proops J L R, editors. Greening the Accounts. Cheltenham,UK: Edward Elgar Publishing Ltd; 2000. p. 11-31. Cooper C, Taylor P, Smith N, Catchpowle L. A discussion of the political potential of Social Accounting. Critical Perspectives on Accounting 2005; 16(7):951-74. Couzens Hoy, D. Heidegger and the hermeneutic turn. In: Guignon CB , editor. The Cambridge Companion to Heidegger. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press; 1999. p. 170-94. Czarniawska, B. New Plots Are Badly Needed In Finance: Accounting For The Financial Crisis Of 2007-2010. Accounting, Auditing & Accountability Journal 2012b; 25(5): 1 – 22. Dillard J F, Yuthas K. Enterprise resource planning systems and communicative action. Critical Perspectives on Accounting 2006; 17(2/3):202-23. Dreyfus H L. Heidegger’s critique of Husserl’s (and Searle’s) account of intentionality. Social Research 1993; 60(1):1-13. Dunham L C. From rational to wise action: recasting our theories of entrepreneurship. Journal of Business Ethics 2010; 92 (4): 513-30. 51 Evans, P. Development as institutional change: the pitfalls of monocropping and the potentials of deliberation. Studies in Comparative International Development 2004; 38(4): 30-52. Ezzamel M, Robson K. Accounting in time: organizational time-reckoning and accounting practice. Critical Perspectives on Accounting 1995; 6(2):149-70. Gallhofer S, Haslam, J. The aura of accounting in the context of a crisis: Germany and the first world war. Accounting, Organizations and Society 1991; 16(5/6):487-520. Gallhofer S, Haslam J. Accounting/art and the emancipatory project: some reflections. Accounting, Auditing and Accountability Journal 1996; 9(5): 23-44. Guignon C B. Introduction. In: Guignon CB , editor. The Cambridge Companion to Heidegger. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press; 1999. p. 1-41. Habermas J. Knowledge and Human Interests [Shapiro JJ, Trans.]. London: Heinemann; 1972. Habermas J. Theory and Practice [Viertal J, Trans.]. London: Heinemann; 1974. Habermas J. Legitimation Crisis [McCarthy T, Trans.]. London: Heinemann; 1976. Habermas J. The Theory of Communicative Action, Volume two: The Critique of Functionalist Reason [McCarthy T, Trans.]. Cambridge UK: Polity Press; 1989. Habermas J. Communication and the Evolution of Society [McCarthy T, Trans.]. Oxford: Polity Press; 1991. Habermas J. Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy [Rehg W, Trans.]. Cambridge Massachusetts: The MIT Press; 1996. Habermas J. The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity – Twelve Lectures [Lawrence F, Trans.]. Oxford: Polity Press; 1998. Heidegger M. Being and Time [Macquarrie J, Robinson E, Trans.]. Oxford: Basil Blackwell; 1978. Jones M J. Accounting for the environment: Towards a theoretical perspective for environmental accounting and reporting. Accounting Forum 2010; 34(2): 123-38. Kompridis N. On world disclosure Heidegger, Habermas and Dewey. Thesis Eleven 1994; 37, 29-45. Kompridis N. Disclosing possibility: the past and future of critical theory. International Journal of Philosophical Studies 2006a; 13(3): 325-51. 52 Kompridis N. Critique and Disclosure. Critical Theory between Past and Future. London: The MIT Press; 2006b. Laughlin R. Accounting systems in organisational contexts: a case for critical theory. Accounting, Organizations and Society 1987; 12(5):479-502. Lee B, Cassell C. Employee and social reporting as a war of position and the union learning representative initiative in the UK. Accounting Forum 2008; 32(4):276-87. Lehman G. Perspectives on language, accountability and critical accounting: an interpretative perspective. Critical Perspectives on Accounting 2006; 17(6):755-79. Lehman G. Perspectives on accounting, commonalities & the public sphere. Critical Perspectives on Accounting 2010; 21(8): 724-38. McCarthy T. The Critical Theory of Jürgen Habermas. London: Hutchinson & Co Ltd; 1978. Macintosh NB, Shearer T, Riccaboni A. A Levinasian ethics critique of the role of management and control systems by large global corporations: the General Electric/Nuovo Pignone example. Critical Perspectives on Accounting 2009; 20(6): 751-61. Mattessich R. Accounting representation and the onion model of reality: a comparison with Baudrillard’s orders of simulacra and his hyperreality 2003; Accounting, Organizations and Society 2003; 28(5):443-70. McKernan JF, MacLullich, KK. Accounting, love and justice. Accounting, Auditing & Accountability Journal 2004; 17(3):327-60. Molisa P. A spiritual reflection on emancipation and accounting. Critical Perspectives on Accounting; 2011 article in press, doi:10.1016/j.cpa.2011.01.004 Mouffe C. Deliberative democracy or agonistic pluralism? Central and Eastern European Online Library, Dialogue International Edition 1998; 07-08: 9-21. www.ceeol.com Mulhall S. Routledge philosophy guidebook to Heidegger and Being and Time. Oxon: Routledge; 2005. Neu D, Cooper D J, Everett J. Critical Accounting Interventions. Critical Perspectives on Accounting 2001; 12(6):735-62. Oakes H, Berry A. Accounting colonization: three case studies in further education. Critical Perspectives on Accounting 2009; 20(3):343-78. Oakes, H, Oakes S. Accounting and marketing communications in arts engagement: A discourse analysis. Accounting Forum, 2012 (forthcoming); doi:10.1016/j.accfor.2012.02.002. Elsevier. Preston, A M, Wright, C, & Young, J J. Imag[in]ing annual reports. Accounting, Organizations, and Society 1996; 21(1):113-37. 53 Rouse J. Man and World 1981; 14: 269-90. The Hague:Martinus Nijhoff Publishers. Sheenan T. Reading a life: Heidegger and hard times. In: Guignon CB, editor. The Cambridge Companion to Heidegger. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press; 1999. p. 70-96. Sikka P. The role of offshore financial centres in globalization. Accounting Forum 2003; 27(4): 365-99. Smith SB. Destruktion or Recovery? Leo Strauss’s Critique of Heidegger. In: McCormick, JP, editor. Confronting mass democracy and industrial technology: Political and social theory from Nietzsche to Habermas. London: Duke University Press; 2002. p. 245-66. Tinker T. The accountant as partisan. Accounting, Organizations and Society 1991; 16(3): 297-310. Unerman J, Bennett M. Increased stakeholder dialogue and the Internet: towards greater corporate accountability or reinforcing capitalist hegemony? Accounting Organizations and Society 2004; 29(7):685–707. 54