1 [A Trio of Seminars—Short Version: Seminar One: 15.iv.13] A Trio of Seminars on Sovereignties: Seminar One* The First Sovereignty Seminar: The Political Peter McCormick Political Sovereignties Overviews §4. Political Sovereignties: A State Sovereignty Account 4.1 A Contemporary Account 4.2 The Sovereign States System 4.3 Presuppositions and Critical Questions Discussion Seminar One §4 and Concluding Remarks §5. Political Sovereignties and Signs of Power Funereal Masks and Mycenae’s “King Agamemnon” 5.1 Mycenaean Civilization 5.2 Golden Masks 5.3 After the New Archeologies 5.4 Status Burials Discussion Seminar One §5 and Concluding Remarks *Copyright C 2013 by Peter McCormick. All rights reserved. Draft Only: not authorized for citation in present unrevised form. 2 §6. Burials, Institutions, and Cultural Meanings 6.1 Evolutionary Development and Decline 6.2 General Institutional Balance 6.3 Relative Cultural Pre-eminence Discussion Seminar One §6 and Concluding Remarks §7. Philosophical Significance: Law and Limited Political Sovereignties 7.1 Rules, Laws, and Political Limits 7.2 The Rule of Law and the Nature of Law 7.3 Law and the Limits of Political Sovereignties Discussion Seminar One §7 and Concluding Remarks §8. A First Set of Interim Conclusions: Bounded Sovereignties I 8.1 Kinds of power 8.2 Forms of political life 8.3 Results of developing dependencies Concluding Remarks and Transition 3 In Brief One influential account of sovereignty today1 in the history of ideas focuses sharply on the nature of political sovereignty in particular. Besides providing both a series of distinctions between different types of political sovereignties and an extensive historical presentation of the development of political sovereignties since the late 16th and early 17th centuries, this account highlights the key notion of state sovereignty. State sovereignty here is to be understood in the jurisdictional sense according to which the bordered territories of states “are spheres of authority exclusive to themselves.” 2 Historically, European nation states have developed a system of state sovereignty that has several distinguishing features. This system today has become globalized and, despite the challenges of some alternative state systems such as those based not on political sovereignty but on the checks and balances model, the sovereign states model remains the major international geopolitical framework today. Like every such overarching conceptual framework, the globalized sovereign states system has a number of presuppositions. These presuppositions raise a series of critical questions. They also suggest as well the interest of renewed historical inquiry into the origins of European culture in the Aegean Bronze Age 1 See R. Jackson 2007. 2 Ibid., p. 149. 4 especially where much recent work has provided new archeological, cultural, and philosophical understanding. Inquiry into the earliest European backgrounds for an enlarged understanding of today’s overly narrow interpretations of sovereignty as almost exclusively political sovereignty focuses on the idea of state sovereignty as a limited sovereignty. Proto-European Mycenaean culture in roughly the second half of the Aegean Late Bronze Age (ca. 1600-1200 BCE), despite its conquest of the Minoan culture of Crete and the destruction of the culture of Troy in Asia Minor, arguably reached its zenith in Mycenae itself ca. 1500 BCE. The symbolic representations of this highpoint of Mycenaean culture may be found especially in the golden funereal masks entered with the bodies of the highest of Mycenae’s several leaders in the shaft graves of Mycenae’s grave circles. Archeological interpretations of these artifacts point to a unique institution in Mycenae at its zenith not of a king as such but of a king-like figure called a wanax. Mycenae’s wanax enjoyed extraordinary political sovereignty over his own fortified town as well as over virtually all the Mycenaean towns of the southern Greek mainland Argolid. Nonetheless, this political sovereignty, however extraordinary, was clearly limited by at least two rather distant and rival centers of political sovereignty, Pylos in Messenia and Thebes in Boitia.3 Reflection on the character of this limited political sovereignty indicates the importance of three of its key elements: For putting Greek expressions into English I follow throughout the “usual messy-ish compromise” (Osborne 2008). “The usual messy-ish compromise,” Osborne writes, “has been made in turning Greek words into English, opting sometimes for the traditional form, sometimes for the strict transliteration” (p. viii). 3 5 evolutionary development and decline, general institutional balance, and relative geo-political equilibrium. §4. Political Sovereignties: A State Sovereignty Account In this section we take up the first of the three types of sovereignties that these seminars will be considering in detail, political sovereignties. We start with an influential contemporary account from mainly a political science perspective of the meaning of political sovereignty in its current worldwide form of the system of state sovereignties. 4.1 A Contemporary Account For some years now, the distinguished Canadian political scientist and historian of ideas, Robert Jackson, has been developing a nuanced and widely influential account of state sovereignty.4 With others, he has underlined the fact that political sovereignty in its modern form derives mainly from the political settlements in Europe after the Peace of Westphalia ended the terrible catastrophes of the Thirty Years War. 5 In this historical sense, then, political sovereignty as we know it today is “a specifically European innovation." 6 But today sovereignty is no longer just a European concept but now also a globalized concept as well. “The European way of government,” Jackson 1990, Jackson 2000, and the relevant chapters in Jackson and Sorensen 2013. 4 See for example the historical account of Philpott 2010, partially cited in the Endnotes below, and his earlier discussions in Philpott 2001. 5 Jackson 2007, p. 144. See Jackson’s summary historical sketch of the developments of the notion of sovereignty from the Tudor monarch Henry VIII’s 1534 Act of Supremacy to the 2005 French and Dutch rejection of the European Constitution (pp. 2-5) which he then elaborates in three chapters, pp. 24-113. 6 6 Jackson writes, “became a global system, and the only one known to history. The entire planet was enclosed by it.” 7 4.2 The Sovereign States System A review of modern European history from the perspective of the history of political ideas shows the rather constant development of democracies from monarchies. Although there have been many intervening stages between the early modern dominance of monarchical forms of government to contemporary forms of democracy,8 the number of sovereign states has continued to multiply to our own day. This fact of increasing sovereignty has brought with it increasing homogeneity among different populations. Thus, “populations have been shaped into peoples, knitted together by transportation and communications networks, political and military mobilization, public education and the like. . . . Parliaments have been elected by an ever widening and now universal franchise. Aristocratic and oligarchic political factions have become political parties.” 9 Still, however new in its continuing historical developments, the phenomenon of state sovereignty has preserved its old foundations. That is, the European nation states making up the European system of state sovereignty today continue to insist on their absolute state authority. While cooperating with the United Nations and other international organizations, these states recognize finally no higher governing authority than their own. In a word, there is no world 7 Ibid., p. 144. 8 Ibid., pp. 144-150. 9 Ibid., pp. 148-149. 7 government to which the sovereign authority of European nation states is subordinated. Although European constitutions vary widely, whether written or unwritten and so on, nonetheless we can put this idea of the absolute sovereign authority of those European nation states making up the state sovereignty system in constitutional terms. Thus, European states “continue to possess constitutional independence, which is the liberty to enact their own laws, to organize and control their own armed forces and police, to tax themselves, to create and manage their own currencies to make their own domestic and foreign policies, to conduct diplomatic relations with foreign governments, to organize and join international organizations, and in short to govern themselves according to their own ideas, interests, and values.” 10 It is of course true that these European sovereign states appear to have ceded some at least some of their otherwise absolute sovereignty to the still emerging EU. Thus, the EU’s various instances have been authorized to sign certain agreements with non-EU states on behalf of all the EU member states. But this authorization has not in any way replaced the persisting sovereign powers of individual member states to sign other agreements with non-EU states in their own names regardless of the EU. Moreover, while certainly according in some matters the priority of EU law over national law, EU nation states nonetheless still reserve the priority of their own national law over many of the most areas of state sovereignty, such as budgetary control and defense matters. Thus, the ongoing development of the EU as a supranational organization does not so far entail any major cessions of state sovereignty, as the February 2013 contentious quarrels over the next EU five year budget demonstrated. Whether this will remain the case over the near to mid-future seems relatively certain. 10 Ibid., p. 149. 8 The European state sovereignty system then is to be understood today and for the indefinite future as an almost absolute form of state sovereignty. This form can be understood relatively easily in both jurisdictional and constitutional terms. Whether there may be good reason for anticipating some more advanced forms of limited state sovereignty in the European cultural values eventually to be entrenched in a new European constitution remains unclear. For the presuppositions of the actual European state sovereignty system remain for the most part unaddressed in any sustained critical form. 4.3 Presuppositions and Critical Questions What then are these presuppositions? One effective way to identify many if not all of the presuppositions of the actual European state sovereignty system is to enumerate some of what most citizens in these European states appear to assume with respect to proper government. Thus most European citizens today live on the working assumptions that the state in which they are citizens has clearly defined borders. This is especially the case after the extremely consequential following the First World War in 1922 and then those following both the agreements among the victorious allies close to the conclusion of the Second World War at Potsdam and the informal adjustments following upon the reunification of Germany in 1991 and the collapse of the Soviet Union in 1993. After such unparalleled experiences as what some have called “The European Civil Wars,” European state borders became sacred – they could no longer be modified. A first presupposition of the 9 European state sovereignty system then might be called “The Unchangeable Borders Assumption” (say, the BA assumption) 11 Most citizens also assume that there highest political responsibilities and obligations are those deriving from their own national governments. These governments are the highest political authorities for the citizens of European states. Citizens’ rights and responsibilities do not derive either from a political party, or from the EU, or from the UN, or from any other political instance whether European or global. We might call this second presupposition “The Highest Political Authority Assumption” (say, the PA assumption). Still another presupposition of the citizens of those states forming part of the European state sovereignty system is that the laws of their own country are those that directly apply to their activities and that the laws of other countries have no proper bearing on those activities. If there are EU laws, then citizens assume that only those EU laws that are recognized by their own country’s highest legal instances are in force. And those EU laws are in force not because of any EU higher legal authority but only because their own particular state has in its own right carried over these laws into their own national sphere. Perhaps this third presupposition we might call “The Highest Legal Authority Assumption” (say, the LA assumption). A final presupposition for our purposes is the assumption on the part of most citizens in their own state that, just as their own European sovereign state is composed of citizens, so other European states are also composed of citizens. The idea that one’s own state may also include persons who are not citizens, or who are merely transient, or In current international law this assumption is called, somewhat obscurely, “The uti possidetis Principle” (“as you have, so may you hold”). This principle applies both to a colony’s borders when it becomes a state as well as to a state’s retaining any moveable public property “in its possession on the day hostilities ceased” ( Oxford Dictionary of Law 2009). 11 10 who are citizens of more than one state, or who are also citizens of the EU (as the passports of member states of the EU show on their covers), does not ordinarily come to mind for most European citizens. Here then is a fourth presupposition of the European sovereign state system, one we might call “The Citizenship Assumption” (CA). Now each of at least these four working assumptions point to certain presuppositions of the European state sovereignty system. Thus, this system presupposes that all actual European nation states are territorially sovereign in the sense that their borders can no longer be modified. Further, the system presupposes that legitimately elected European nation state governments enjoy quasi-absolute political sovereignty in the sense that there are no higher political authorities to which its citizens are properly to be subjected. Moreover, the system also presupposes similarly that a European nation state’s legal institutions are completely sovereign in the sense that the code of laws they administer are subject to no other code of laws elsewhere. And finally the European system of state sovereignty presupposes that a European nation state’s citizenship is sovereign in that it takes absolute priority with respect to rights and responsibilities over any other membership or citizenship in another state or states. But even when charitably taken together instead of interrogated one by one, these presuppositions of the actual European state sovereignty system raise serious issues that invite further reflection. For as a whole these presuppositions confront reflective persons with the basic issue of the extent of political sovereignty as such. Can political sovereignty, under its present working understandings in the nation state of the European state sovereignty system, be properly understood as absolute, as quasi-absolute,or a relative? And if relative, as arguably is the case, then to what extent relative? 11 Concluding Remarks Are we finally to understand at the end of these reminders from the domains of political science and the history of ideas that political sovereignty is in some strong sense not absolute but limited sovereignty? Moreover, if political sovereignty is limited sovereignty, are there good enough reasons for holding after further reflection that political sovereignty is, necessarily, limited? To try to get some critical distance on such issues that arise from certain presuppositions of the European state sovereignty system I would now like to put into discussion a historical case study. The case in question will be one of three that I will select from the very origins of European culture where questions of sovereignty whether absolute or limited took a very different but nonetheless very consequential form for our own continuing reflections today. We do well then I believe to look for a moment at the related ideas of political power in Mycenaean culture in the Aegean Bronze Age. 12 §5. Political Sovereignties and Signs of Power Funereal Masks and Mycenae’s “King Agamemnon” We begin our concerns here with enlarging current overly political understandings of sovereignties by recalling culturally meaningful and philosophical significant features of some of the most important artworks from the origins of European civilization today in the formative Aegean Bronze Age (ca. 3000 to 1200 BCE).i We first take up several salient features only of the manifold cultural meanings of the appearance in the middle and late second millennium BCE of the embossed golden funerary masks of the Middle Helladic Period Mycenaean civilization (ca. 1800-1500 BCE). The objects come from the Argolid peninsula on mainland southern Greece and its natural sub-regions of low mountains and valleys south of Corinth and off the Saronic Gulf opposite the island of Aegina and Salamis near Athens. In order to bring out some of the philosophical significance and not just cultural meaningfulness of these extraordinary funereal masks, we will draw on several suggestive discussions today in both contemporary archeological approaches to understanding the Aegean Bronze Age and in contemporary moral and political philosophy. In the case of archeology we will take our bearings from recent interpretive approaches that have followed on the diversification of archeological theorizing at the outset of the new millennium. And in the case of moral and political philosophy, which we have not yet written up here for these preliminary seminars, we will take our bearings from debates about the nature of those ethical and political values at issue in the quite important ongoing discussions between two internationally distinguished philosophers of law, Ronald Dworkin and Scott Shapiro, about, in particular, political sovereignties. 13 We will come to find that an historically representative preamble to any eventual EU constitution would do well to make room for incorporating at least some of the ethical and political values of norms and lawfulness that may emerge from fresh interpretative reflection on several of the deeply suggestive Mycenaean origins of Europe today. 5.1 Mycenaean Civilization We may begin by stepping back from the well-known catastrophes of the Persian Invasions of mainland Greece of 490-480 BCE to an earlier and less well-known set of catastrophes in roughly the mid-1500s BCE. These events took place quite close to the very cultural beginnings of Europe that began to terminate the most successful period of Mycenaean Civilization at the end of the Early Palatial Period.ii And it is just here that we come upon some of the most extraordinary artworks of that civilization. Archeologists have uncovered these buried artworks and those like them within fortified citadels and various kinds of graves in the Argolid at Mycenae, Epidaurus, Argos, Tiryns, Nauplion, Asiné, and Midea and at Lerna on the Argolic Gulf across from Nauplion. They are dated to roughly the late sixteenth century BCE. What archeologists today call “Mycenaean Civilization” 12 encompasses a variety of quite different sites and finds first centered mainly in the hilly Argolid region on the north-east corner of the Peloponnese. Later in their history, the mainland Mycenaeans invaded many of the Aegean Islands as well as Crete (from about 1450 BCE).13 In general, for Mycenaean civilization see Bintliff 2012, pp. 181-205, with bibliographies, Chadwick 1976, Shelton 2010, pp. 139-148, Wright 2008, and Crowley 2008. For the Greek texts see especially Duhoux and A. Morpurgo Davis 2008-2011. 12 14 Some hold that, in alliances with other cities of Achaia and the Peloponnese, they also besieged Troy,14 the Ilios of Homer15 (who refers to “Asiné” but once), on the Anatolian or Ionian coast.iii In central and eastern Crete they established a thriving province of its own centered on the much older conquered palace city of Knossos. Mycenaean culture reflected closely the contemporaneous somewhat severe high palace cultures on the Greek mainland. But the more developed Cretan palace cultures continually enriched the later Mycenaean culture that conquered them. For multiple reasons, however, and very much like other cultures in the very late Aegean Bronze Age, Mycenaean civilization itself collapsed roughly in the period from 1200-1150 BCE.16 Each of these archeological sites on Greece’s southern mainland of course has its own history, and several have their own archeological museums.iv But the major part of the most important artifacts discovered in the later Argolid Mycenaean cities such as in Mycenae itself as well as in Epidaurus,17 Argos,18 Tiryns,19 and others, are still to be found in the extraordinary collections of the National Archeological Museum in Athens.20 13 Morkot 1996, pp. 26-27. 14 Jablonka 2010. 15 See Morris and Powell 1997. See the nuanced discussion in Bintliff 2012, pp. 184-185. For the collapse of the Aegean Bronze Age generally see Deger-Jalkotzy 2008. 16 17 See Finley 1977, pp. 160-161. 18 See Finley 1977, pp. 158-159. 19 Maran 2010. 15 Here, we may consider briefly the Mycenaean masks and crowns found in the so-called “Treasury of Atreus” v at Mycenae,21 the place that Homer, in one of his many memorable epithets, called “rich in gold.” 5.2 Golden Masks Perhaps the most important of the several embossed golden masks from Mycenae and from other related sites in late Helladic Period Greece is the so-called “Mask of Agamemnon,” now on view in the outstanding Mycenaean Collection of the National Archeological Museum of Athens.22 In the 1870s, when Heinrich Schliemann discovered this quite beautiful artifact used to cover the face of an immensely wealthy royal personage, he believed that the mask was the death mask of Mycenae’s historical but also much fabled King Agamemnon.23 Accordingly, Schliemann thought that the mask was to be dated from sometime in the thirteenth century BCE. Later examination, however, demonstrated that the mask was to be dated more accurately from the mid-sixteenth century and hence could not be Agamemnon’s. But the name Schliemann gave the mask remains to this day. Schliemann uncovered the “Mask of Agamemnon” in Grave V of 20 Zafiropoulou 2009. 21 See French 2002, and French and Iakovidis 2003. Demakopoulou 2009. Colour photographs of selected Mycenaean materials can be seen in Iakovidis 1979, pp. 54-65, and in Demakopoulou 2009, pp. 17-23. 22 23 For the history of archeology see Trigger 1995. 16 Grave Circle A of the royal shaft graves24 of the Mycenaean royal leaders or “kings” in the fortified acropolis of Mycenae in the Argolid dominating the Argos plain to the south-east. The golden mask was but part of the many luxurious funerary objects25 which Schliemann discovered in 1877 in the six tombs of Grave Circle A dating from ca. the 1500s. Very much later, in 1951, archeologists discovered many other richly fabricated grave goods in the still earlier tombs of Grave Circle B.26 Besides the so-called Mask of Agamemnon in Grave V of Grave Circle A, Schliemann also discovered two other gold embossed funereal masks in Grave IV of Grave Circle A. Accompanying the two masks from Grave IV were a golden drinking vessel, called a rhyton,27 in the form of an lion’s head and a silver rhyton in the shape of a bull’s head. Also found in Grave IV and in Grave V accompanying the Mask of Agamemnon were bronze dagger blades elaborately but rather severely inlaid with gold, amber, and a black precious filling called niello.28 These items were deposited with the bodies in the royal tombs as part of elaborate funeral services whose details have only very gradually come to light.29 A recent and brief overview of the peculiar nature of these shaft graves and the two shaft grave circles (Shaft Grave Circles A and B) is in Bintliff 2012, pp. 171-172. 24 Photographs are in Higgins 1997, p. 153 and pp. 138-139; Preziosi and Hitchcock 1999, p. 151; and in Iacovidis 1979, pp. 60-65. 25 This tomb circle is called “Grave Circle B” instead of “Grave Circle A” because of its discovery only after the discovery of the chronologically later Grave Circle A. 26 A rhyton is “a type of drinking vessel, often in the form of an animal’s head, with one or more holes at the bottom through which the liquid can flow” (ODE). 27 Niello is “a black composition of sulphur with silver, lead, or copper, for filling engraved designs on silver or other metals” (ODE). 28 17 While keeping in mind the artifacts that daggers accompanied in these royal graves, comparing and contrasting briefly the three golden funerary masks with each other is instructive. Since archeologists consider the Mask of Agamemnon from Grave V to be perhaps the most expressive of these objects, we may best begin with the two other, reputedly less expressive masks from Grave IV. But first we need to recall the situation of Aegean Bronze Age archeology today. 5.3 After “The New Archeology” How are we to understand these extraordinary artifacts in general and in particular the golden funerary masks and warrior arms? Methodological approaches in archeology have developed very greatly since the 1960s when traditional methods dating from the late nineteenth century continued largely unchanged after the First World War.30 Some of these newly developed approaches became so important as largely to merit the name, “The New Archeology.” Most archeologists began to use this expression to denote mainly the characteristic and persistent application of recent scientific developments and instrumentation, including information technology, not just to the description but also to the explanation and understanding of archeological artifacts. The New Archeology, however, quickly inspired a reaction among some more strictly historically oriented archeologists. Many of them argued that, however helpful and often even necessary new scientific methods and technologies might be, such approaches were not 29 See Cavanaugh 2008, pp. 337-339, and Bintliff 2012, pp. 192-194. 30 Cf. Johnson 2010 and Hodder 2012. 18 sufficient in themselves to elucidate adequately many archeological items. On their view, exclusively scientific approaches could not deal fully satisfactorily with many of the cultural and symbolic aspects of the artifacts, assemblages, features, and sites that archeology studies. The result was the emergence recently of more nuanced approaches, at least to the interpretation of many artifacts if not to their scientific descriptions and functional explanations. Studies especially of the symbolic aspects of artifacts have led to still further development of such rather traditional subsections of archeology itself as social archeology31 and archeology and anthropology.32 Moreover, these studies have led even to the relatively new subdivisions of cognitive and even neuro-scientific archeology.33 When we return then to trying better to understand the artifacts at issue here, the golden funerary masks and military arms of the heyday of mainland Mycenaean civilization in the Argolid as well as other artifacts we will be considering below, I think we do well to consider briefly their cultural meaningfulness under the various headings of the newer, more interpretive, or so-called “postprocessual” vi kinds of contemporary archeology.34 We may then leave for the professionals some of the importance and interest of the many controversial chronological issues, geomorphological, chemical, and paleo-botanical problems, and here the metallurgical details as well. And perhaps we may focus more broadly on the general elucidation of the architectural contexts and cultural indices surrounding the find sites of these artifacts. 31 Cf. Renfrew and Bahn 2012, pp. 169-222; cf. Insoll 2011. 32 See for example Flannery and Marcus 2011 and the review by Turchin 2013. 33 Renfrew and Bahn 2012, pp. 381-420; cf. Renfrew and Zubrow 1994. 34 Renfrew and Bahn 2012, pp. 43-45. 19 5.4 Status Burials As we have noted already, these artifacts are found in several Mycenaean tombs dating from roughly the middle of the sixteenth century BCE. The tombs are of a special sort. They are found inside a special construction. That construction is situated at a special place. And the site itself is to be found in an unusual locale. We may take these briefly in reverse order. Archeologists unearthed these particular funerary artifacts at Mycenae at the northern edge of the Plain of Argos in the Argolid Peninsula. Mycenae was but one of four Mycenaean settlements there, each situated at one of the respective cardinal points of the Plain of Argos, which also included the settlements of Argos itself as well of Tiryns and Midea.35 For some time, however, until it came to surpass Argos itself as the most important settlement bordering the Plain of Argos, Mycenae’s relative status among the other Plain of Argos settlements remained unclear. Moreover, when Mycenae finally did achieve political preeminence over Argos, whether Mycenae became then merely a first among equals or the clear leader in “a four-tier settlement hierarchy” 36 remains unclear even today. But what does seem rather evident is that Mycenae achieved a leadership position as a state-run palatial redistributive economy amid the Argolid Mycenaean settlements. And this was the case even if the very important Mycenaean settlements at Pylos in Messenia and Thebes37 in Boeotia38 continued to be its rival.39 35 Marzolf 2004. 36 Bintliff 2012, p. 186. 37 For Thebes see Dakouri-Hild 2010b, esp. pp. 694-696. 20 The major index that shows the political pre-eminence of Mycenae at this period is the rather sudden appearance of the prestigious, very high status type of tomb called the tholos tomb. The tholos tomb occurs first in Pylos in Messenia. But the buried objects from Mycenae are not just in tholos-type tombs but in the still more distinctive shaft-grave sub-type of tholos tomb. The shaft-grave sub-type of tholos tomb has the highest status level of all the Mycenaean tombs of this period, from the archaic pit and cist graves, to the most common chamber tombs, to the tholos tombs themselves. 40 The archeological record shows that at one point elites in Mycenaean Pylos41 in Messenia in the southwest of the Peloponnese ceased to build such tombs. But subsequently the building of such tombs first became the prerogative of the wealthy and powerful Mycenae elite and finally the privilege of “the uppermost princely dynasties” in Mycenae alone.42 Later, the wealthy and powerful in Tiryns, Lerna,43 and Asiné seem to have imitated these tombs.44 But, to date, the nine tholos shaft tombs found at Mycenae are the highpoint of Mycenaean status burial sites. This evidence of high status burial sites becomes one of the bases for the archeological view that sees Mycenae reaching the peak 38 For Boeotia see Dakouri-Hild 2010b, esp. pp. 617-619. 39 Bintliff 2012, pp. 185-186, and 193. 40 Cananagh and Mee 1998, and Mee and Cavanagh 1990. 41 Davis 2010, esp. pp. 683 and 697. 42 Bintliff 2012, p. 193. 43 Wienke 2010, esp. pp. 664 and 667. 44 Ibid. See also Voutsaki 2010, pp. 603-604. 21 of its power with the construction of the shaft grave burials with their extraordinary golden artifacts. A further point in favor of this hypothesis is that the particular shaft graves in which these objects are found at Mycenae, Shaft Graves IV and V, are among those to be found inside and not outside the so-called “Grave Circle A” that Schliemann first uncovered on the west side of the Mycenae acropolis. The Mycenaean elites constructed Grave Circle A and the somewhat earlier circle45 Grave Circle B that encloses these shaft graves at the summit of the acropolis as presumably a place of quite special dignity reserved for their very highest leaders.46 These leaders must have been particularly resourceful. For “the extension of the citadel to the west to enclose the Grave Circle and the Cult Center,” as one specialist has written recently, “was a very considerable enterprise and must have commanded the city’s full resources. The plan included changing the approach, constructing a monumental gate (the Lion Gate . . .) and completely altering and refurbishing the Grave Circle . . . at a higher level to make a singularly impressive sight to one entering the walled acropolis.” 47 The person who issued such commands must have been the leader himself of a settlement, the settlement having now become perhaps the leading city of the Mycenaean culture itself. This person or his immediate predecessors or followers were those who were buried in Shaft Graves IV and V with the golden As already noted, these tombs were discovered later and hence called according, to the order of discovery and not to the chronological order, “Grave Circle B.” 45 Cf. French 2010, p. 673. French reproduces annotated maps of both Greater Mycenae and Mycenae from the Mycenae Archive resources available to scholars. 46 47 Ibid., p. 675. 22 funereal masks and the warrior arms. Such a person was the leader of Mycenae. He was no longer merely a chieftain, or a so-called “Big Man,” the leaders of earlier much less developed settlements. Who was this person? He was perhaps a king-like figure. Most probably this person was what the Mycenians themselves called not a “lawagetas” or “leader of the people,” but a “wanax” or “supreme leader.” This is what Homer had in mind when he called Agamemnon the “wanax” or “lord of men.” 48 What we need to note in particular, however, is that the sixteenth century Mycenaean king-like figure, or wanax, could not have at that time exercised absolute political sovereignty over the Mycenaen civilization. For there were members of his own presumably dynastic family to consider. There were also the leaders of the rival cities of the Plain of Argos, especially of the Argos elites who wanted to reassert their earlier dominance. Farther away to the southwest were the elites of Homer’s “sandy Pylos” who were still developing their own power, perhaps more intermittently than those of Mycenae but nonetheless rather steadily. And there were above all the elites of Mycenaean Thebes not so far away to the northeast whose appetites for eventual absolute sovereignty49 were still tempered by their rivals in Orchomenos.50 That is to say, the political sovereignty of the Mycenaean lord or wanax was not an absolute but a truly limited political sovereignty. 48 Shelmerdine and Bennett 2008, pp. 290, 29O, and 292 respectively. Partially evident perhaps in their construction of the island fortress, Gla, at the northeast of Lake Copias in central Greece. See Bintliff 2012, pp. 190-191 and the aerial photograph reproduced from Schoder 1974. 49 Cf Bintliff 2012, pp. 192-199. Note that Mycenaean Linear B tablets do not include any political and diplomatic archives. See Palaima 2010, esp, pp. 358-359. 50 23 We need then to investigate first just what such a limited political sovereignty might mean in itself, and then second to specify if we can the philosophical significance of such a limited political sovereignty in the contexts of an eventual prelude to an EU constitution. 24 §6. Burials, Institutions, and Cultural Meanings 6.1 Evolutionary Development and Decline When from the perspective of our concerns with enlarging today’s rather constricted understandings of sovereignty as almost exclusively political or state sovereignty, we look back over these brief reminders about Mycenaean culture at the origins of European civilization, several considerations are salient. Perhaps foremost is the idea of a culture’s rise and fall. Mycenaean culture, like the several major Aegean Bronze Age cultures that preceded it, namely the Minoan culture and the still earlier Cycladic culture, developed in what might be called, rather roughly,51 an evolutionary fashion. 52 The importance of this general point is that any attempt to interpret not unsatisfactorily such material remains of this culture as the golden artifacts of the high status burials in Mycenae must always struggle with difficult matters of dating and chronology. For the cultural meanings53 of such artifacts are necessarily rooted in a particular moment of that culture’s development. Thus, the dating of the burial of the so-called golden mask of Agamemnon matters much. This is very important qualification given the notable failings of “cultural evolutionism” dating from E. B. Tayor’s nineteenth-century work on the so-called “cultural evolution” of religious beliefs. Some of these failings appear to be still prevalent in several otherwise distinguished anthropological works today. See for example the critical comments of Bashkow 2013 in his review of Diamond 2013. 51 “The idea of evolution has been of central significance in the development of archeological thinking” (Renfrew and Bahn 2012, p. 27.). See for example White 1959. 52 53 On cultural meanings and archeology see Renfrew and Bahn 2012, pp. 381-420. 25 For if such an elite burial dates from a period in the particular history of the settlement at Mycenae that is contemporaneous with the elite burial practices of the Mycenaean settlement at Pylos, then one might reasonably find in it much less cultural meaning than if it dates from a later period when the elite burial practices at Pylos had already ceased. In the first case, the golden artifacts found in the Mycenaean elite burial sites would have to be compared with other fine artifacts found in the Pylos sites. In the latter case, however, the Mycenaean golden artifacts, with all their implications of not just high but perhaps even of royal status, would have rather different cultural meanings. Archeologists today are reasonably sure that the dating of the Mycenaean artifacts are subsequent to the dating of the Pylos artifacts. Accordingly, there are reasonable grounds for thinking that the Mycenaean artifacts had a particularly strong cultural meaning in terms of political leadership. Indeed, some would argue, as we have noted, that Mycenae at this period was not just first among equals amidst the three other major Mycenaean Argolid settlements; it was pre-eminent. That is, Mycenae at this period exercised pre-eminent political sovereignty over the Argolid. 6.2 General Institutional Balances Looking back through the reminders we have assembled above about Mycenaean culture, however, we come quickly upon another salient point. This point is a linguistic one. We recall the hesitations some archeologists still entertain about the difficult issue of how exactly to characterize the pre-eminent leader or leaders of Mycenae. Where Homer appears to have had no doubts about the status of Agamemnon as King of Mycenae, today’s archeologists hesitate to speak of Mycenae’s rulers as kings and 26 royalty. Perhaps these hesitations are not fully grounded. Nonetheless, even so astute an archeologist as Schliemann himself jumped all too quickly to the rash conclusion that the golden mask he had uncovered was the mask of King Agamemnon. Yet when the specialists had finished their scientific investigations it turned out that the mask in question was much older than any mask of the historical King Agamemnon could have been. So the question arose as to whether at that particular period in the development of Mycenaean culture the indisputable elite burials were the burials of kings and royalty properly speaking, or rather of pre-eminent leaders to be identified in other, perhaps related but still quite different terms. In these contexts the proposal arose that the elite burials in the Mycenaean Shaft Graves of this period contained the remains of at least several individuals who during their lives were not known precisely as “kings” but as wanax. And once again, just as in the case of the contemporaneity or not of the elite burials at Mycenae and Pylos, the question arose as to whether, unlike a city-state’s king, a Mycenaean settlement could have at one time more than one wanax. Of course we cannot predict the future results of further investigations of the Mycenaean settlements in the Argolid, in Messenia, or in Boiotia. Perhaps further discoveries will resolve this question definitively one way or another. But right now we can already see that if the political structure of Mycenae allowed of more than one wanax at the same time, then however extensive the political sovereignty of a wanax was, it was certainly not unlimited. That is, Mycenaean political sovereignty in the period under discussion was perhaps limited not just regionally, as the still controversial relative datings of the Pylos elite burials might suggest. Perhaps Mycenaean political sovereignty was also limited – 27 and this is the second point -- with respect to any claim to individual uniqueness. 6.3 Relative Cultural Pre-eminence Reviewing still further the brief reminders of several of the most remarkable features of Mycenaean culture when Mycenae itself was arguably at the apogee of its cultural development brings into view a third and for now final point. For whatever the indisputable military powers of Mycenaean culture that enabled this mainland settlement to project its interests to Crete and even to install that power at some of the very culminating sites of Minoan culture such as Knossos, Mycenae seems to have enjoyed even at its greatest extent less than any properly speaking absolute political sovereignty. Recall that Mycenae certainly gradually developed its own cultural identity in the Argolid in conjunction with the other key Mycenaean settlements there. Perhaps Mycenae was also able to rise to a position of at least first among equals if not pre-eminence before the consolidation of its commanding positions in Crete. Still, archeologists have not had great difficulty in demonstrating that much of Mycenaean culture generally in this period betrays the almost overwhelming influence of Minoan culture on the Mycenaeans. Although the historical situation of the Mycenaean occupation of Knoss, for example, must certainly have evolved over time, nonetheless the general cultural relationships between Mycenae and Knossos seem to have been rather stable. What were those relationships? The Mycenaeans who establish themselves by conquest at Knossos were certainly not to be understood as military barbarians without any culture of their own. We have already seen just how varied 28 and extensive Mycenaean culture was before the spreading to Crete. That culture we know was far more extensive than simply the construction of elite tombs. The architecture, the social organisations, the complex diplomatic relations among the different Argolid settlements, and so on – all testify to an extensive indigenous culture. Still, many archeologists have come to believe that, however extensive their own culture was and however dominant their own position as conquerors was in Crete, the Mycenaeans who came to Crete fell quickly under the cultural influence (some would say dominance) of the Minoans. For the Minoans represented not only an older culture than the Mycenaean; the Minoans had developed that culture to a greater degree than the Mycenaeans had developed their own. The evidence stood before the eyes of the Mycenaeans when they occupied the palace at Knossos with its truly extraordinary architecture, spaces, frescoes, and so on. Moreover, even more impressive to the Mycenaeans was the testimony to a higher cultural achievement of the conquered Minoans furnished by their now written languages. For, in settling themselves comfortably at Knossos and perhaps also at Phaistos, the Mycenaeans came upon not only Linear A and Linear B scripts; they also came upon the so-called pre-palatial Archanes script. 54 What very much seems to be the case, then, is that Mycenaean political sovereignty was not only limited individually and regiona lly but even more so in terms of the larger world. No Mycenaean leading political figure visiting the conquered territories of Crete could neglect the evidence of his eyes. However powerful his armed forces, that leader’s cultural pre-eminence could no longer be simply assumed. For the extraordinary extensiveness of Minoan cultural developments 54 See Tomas 2012 in Cline 2012, pp. 342-343. 29 clearly demonstrated that the political sovereignty was now limited in at least a third and truly significant way. Mycenaean political sovereignty seems to have also been limited culturally. 30 §7. Philosophical Significance: Law and Limited Political Sovereignties When we look back through the analyses of sovereignty in the almost exclusive terms of political state sovereignty, and then the descriptions and apparent cultural meanings of the signs of Mycenaean political powers, we come upon the realities of definite limits. In this final section of Seminar One we now need to reflect on the nature of these limits on both the historical realities of Mycenaean power politics and their philosophical suggestiveness with respect to the nature of limited political sovereignties. 7.1 Rules, Laws, and Political Limits Both the history of the European early modern period at the time of the Peace of Westphalia after the Thirty Years War of 1618 to 1648 and the history so much earlier towards the end of the European Aegean Bronze Age of the Mycenaean ascendancy from roughly 1500 to 1200 BCE, show the omnipresence of regulations and rules. For each widely separate period in European history in however different ways shows many of the hallmarks of the political state. Above all, there is the centralization of economic, social, and individual power based upon a relative monopoly of military dominance. Contemporary political science and social theory, however, have taught us rightly that such degrees of centralization are impossible without the imposition of strict behavioral guidelines, regulations, and rules for governing groups of people with individual needs, interests. Moreover, whatever the differences in both the Westphalian and the Mycenaean cases, the imposition of such different kinds of effective governance rules is physically enforced. And in both cases the 31 instruments of physical enforcement are various forms of military force. The evidence of such enforced regulation is of course quite different in each case. For the order that the European state leaders imposed on their peoples at the end of the Thirty Years War we have, most notably, fully preserved written evidence in the form of the Treaty of Westphalia. For the order, however, that the Mycenaean leaders imposed on their peoples at the zenith of their hegemony over the rival towns of the Argolid we have but partially preserved monumental evidence in the form of extraordinarily made ashlar fortifications and golden funerary artifacts. But, however different the character of this evidence, in each case such evidence could not exist without the conditions of rule-governed political, social, and individual behaviors having been fully met. The central point here then becomes apparent. For groups of people to succeed in organizing their lives with sufficient security and well-being, rules of some sort and their physical enforcement are necessary. What forms these rules and their enforcements take, however, are contingent on various factors such as climate, geography, demography, and so on. But among the most important factors shaping these contingent forms of regulation and enforcement is the relative social development of the groups in question. And to some important degree this social development can be measured.55 In some but not all cases of socially developed societies the necessary rules for the governance of complex groups assume the form of laws. In the history of European civilization, rather compendious lists of inscribed laws appear quite early, for example in the law codes56 of Hammurabi in Babylon or in the early Israelite law 55 Morris 2010, pp. 623-645, and Morris 2013, pp. 1-52. 56 In general see Grandpierre 2010, pp. 275-285 and in particular Roth 1997. 32 codes in the Hebrew Bible’s books of Leviticus and Numbers.57 But before such inscriptions of law codes, oral rules surely most have been prominent. And, as the Israelite sources show, some of these oral prescriptions were surely law-like. Thus, effective social groupings, the archeological and historical records show, required kinds of organized rules and regulations, that properly enforced, sometimes assumed the form of inscribed or written laws that governed and thereby limited both individual and social behaviors. If we now narrow our concerns to the nature of the law itself, we may come to understand somewhat better just how not just rules and regulations but also and pre-eminently laws themselves necessarily limit sovereignties. 7.2 The Rule of Law and the Nature of Law The major principle of social organization in both the Aegean Bronze Age Mycenaean societies and in the Early Modern European societies, one might be tempted to say, was one that both held in common, although in different forms. This major principle was finally “the rule of law.” In the case of Mycenae, the rule of law was effectively what the ultimate leader, the wanax, wanted; in the case of the Westphalian polities, the rule of law was effectively what the treaty codifed. This view however would be mistaken. For although so-called rule of law in so far as it specifies rules and regulations, penalties and punishments that allow for the effective governance of social groups whether in the Bronze Age or in Early Modern Europe, might appear to 57 In general see Knight 2011 and in particular Coogan 2010; pp. 141-245. 33 be a common European cultural inheritance, in fact the rule of law is an expression that is rife with ambiguities.58 Moreover, the rule of law is opposed to the rule of despots which could arguably have been the case in either Mycenae or in one of the Westphalian states. The discussion today of just what constitutes the rule of law goes back mainly to the important work of the late nineteenth century, Oxford Professor of Law, A. V. Dicey.59 And commentators today continue to interpret both the matter itself as well as Dicey’s own views in remarkably different ways.60 One of the most authoritative and recent works on the concept of the rule of law summarizes the core of this notion as currently understood: “all persons and authorities within the state, whether public or private, should be bound by and entitled to the benefit of laws publicly made, taking effect (generally) in the future and publicly administered in the courts.” 61 Now such an understanding will not fit either the Westphalian or the Mycenaean cases, for neither could satisfy at once all the conditions here, however few. The rule of law on current understanding then is “not comprehensive and not universally applicable.” 62 Nevertheless, once the expression is examined carefully, one comes upon a more elaborate representation of the rule of law that can help us see the differences between the ancient and the modern Cf. a standard definition of “the rule of law” as “A system of governmental behavior and authority that is constrained by law and the respect for law in contrast to despotic rule” (Bedau 2005). 58 59 Dicey 1945. 60 See Bingham 2010, pp. 3-5. 61 Ibid., p. 37. 62 Loc. cit. 34 understandings of the regulatory nature of the effective governance of human societies. On the same distinguished reading this elaboration of the rule of law involves at least eight major claims that we may cite as follows.63 “The Accessibility of the Law (1) The law must be accessible and so far as possible intelligible, clear and predictable” (p. 37). Here, if intelligibility and clarity are reasonably to be found in both of our test cases, predictability is problematic in the ancient one. “Law not Discretion (2) Questions of legal right and liability should ordinarily be resolved by application of the law and not the exercise of discretion” (p. 48). Here, both the early modern and the ancient cases would seem to award a strong place to discretion. “Equality Before the Law (3) The laws of the land should apply equally to all, save to the extent that objective differences justify differentiation” (p. 55). Here, it is difficult to see how such equality before the law could hold the case in either case. “The Exercise of Power (4) Ministers and public officers at all levels must exercise the powers conferred on them in good faith, fairly, for the purpose for which the powers were conferred, without exceeding the limits of such powers and not unreasonably” (p. 60). Here, assuming we are talking about honest ministers, then this aspect of the rule of law does seem applicable in both cases. 63 Bingham 2010, pp. 37-129. 35 “Human Rights (5) The law must afford adequate protection of fundamental human rights” (p. 66). But the notion of human rights is absent in the ancient case and present only very implicitly in the early modern one. “Dispute Resolution (6) Means must be provided for resolving, without prohibitive cost or inordinate delay, bona fide civil dispute which the parties themselves are unable to resolve” (6). Both the early modern and the ancient case appear to incorporate this notion. “A Fair Trial (7) Adjudicative procedures provided by the state should be fair” (p. 90). Historical evidence appears to show that neither the early modern nor the ancient instance could satisfy this notion. “The Rule of Law in the International Legal Order (8) The rule of law requires compliance by the state with its obligations in international law as in national law” (p. 110). Here, the evidence appears to show that in the ancient case this aspect did not apply whereas in the early modern case, owing to the international character of the treaty, this aspect did apply. Now, when we go through the results of this attempt to understand more fully the nature of the constraints the various rules and regulations, punishments and penalties that comprised effective governance in both the ancient and the early modern examples, we come upon two important points. First, the greatly ambiguous notion of the rule of law, even when elaborated in detail, does not allow of sufficient generalization to account for the practices in both the early modern state and the ancient one. And, second, the notion of law that 36 the polyvalent expression “the rule of law” incorporates requires elucidation. We will now take up that elucidation in the following subsection. 7.3 Law and the Limits of Political Sovereignties Unsurprisingly, contemporary philosophers of law disagree about just what the law is. Looking at one of the major disagreements today about what law is will bring us to a fuller appreciation here of just what the limits of political sovereignty come to. The majority contemporary view on the nature of law in Englishlanguage philosophy of law (also called legal philosophy)vii comes down from the work of the Oxford philosopher of law, H. L. A. Hart (19071992), especially from his most prominent work, The Concept of Law (1961) and Law, Liberty and Morality (1963).64 Hart’s most illustrious student, successor at Oxford, and prolific critic was the American philosopher of law, Ronald Dworkin (1931-2013) whose most important works were probably the two books, Law’s Empire (1986) and Justice for Hedgehogs (2011).65 Hart’s later student and successor at Oxford, defender, and critic of Dworkin is Joseph Raz (1941 -- ). His most important works include The Authority of Law (1979), Practical Reason and Norms (1990 [1975]),66 and The Practice of Value (2003). In the philosophy of law today it is customary to distinguish between analytical and critical philosophy of law.67 Roughly speaking, 64 See Hart 1994, Coleman 2001, and Hart 1963. On Hart cf. MacCormick 2004. See also Dworkin 1978, Dworkin 1985, and Dworkin 2000. On Dworkin cf. Guest 2013. 65 66 See also Raz 1986 and Raz 2009. On Raz cf. Marmor 2011, pp. 60-83. 67 See Finnis 2005 in Honderich 2005, pp. 500-504. 37 analytical legal philosophy treats, among other matters, the definition of law and of legal concepts, while critical legal philosophy treats, also among other things, the evaluation of laws and legal systems.viii In analytical works we find a variety of accounts of the nature of law. Two of the most recent and distinguished deserve our attention here. The first, Scott Shapiro’s Legality (2011) is strongly in the tradition of Hart and Raz, while the second is the final magisterial work of Dworkin himself, Justice for Hedgehogs (2011). Roughly, for Shapiro what determines the nature of law is society and in particular social facts; what specifies those social facts is empirical description. 68 In contrast, for Dworkin what determines law’s nature is morality and in particular moral values; and what specifies social facts is not description but moral evaluation.69 “Dworkin clearly believes,” his most accomplished commentator writes, “that the rightness of an interpretation is a matter of the moral evaluation of actual or imagined facts of legal practice, not a matter of a description of those facts.” 70 In these terms, of course, the contemporary debate about the nature of law seems to be a version of the Humean doctrine of a strict separation between facts and values, here between social facts and moral values. Thus, on Dworkin’s view “no fact contradicts any judgment of value. Hume’s principle governs completely. That means Shapiro’s has been so far less prolific than Dworkin. Besides his major 2011 work see however his joint collection, Coleman and Shapiro 2004, and his article, “Authority,” in that collection, pp. 382-439. 68 For an up-to-date bibliography of Dworkin’s extensive writings see Guest 2013, pp. 271-286. 69 70 Guest 2013, p. 58. 38 that social facts have legal meaning only insofar as they are explained or justified, or nested within judgments of moral value.” 71 There is, however, more than a nuance here that we need to underline. The distinction between these two views about what constitutes the nature of law is not between social facts on one side and moral values on the other. Rather, the disagreement is between those who hold that only social facts determine the nature of law, and those who hold that both social facts and moral values determine law’s nature. 72 This nuance has important consequences. For, “if the positivist is right [for example, Hart 1961] and the existence and content of legal systems are ultimately determined by social facts alone, then the only way to demonstrate conclusively that a person has legal authority or that one is interpreting legal texts properly is by engaging in sociological inquiry . . . . [but] if the natural law theorist [for example, Finnis 1980] is right and the existence and content of legal systems are ultimately determined by moral facts as well, then it is impossible to demonstrate conclusively what the law is in any particular case without engaging in moral inquiry.” 73 We need not here enter into the discussion of just what defines a legal positivist theorist or a legal natural law theorist before grasping the major point here. Dworkin and those who follow his views on the nature of law believe that the law is through and through moral – “law is a branch of politics, which is a branch of morality.” 71 Loc. Cit. 72 Cf. Shapiro 2011, p. 29. 73 Ibid., pp. 29-30. 74 Guest 2013, p. 58. 74 Shapiro and 39 those who follow his views believe that the nature of law is not through and through moral.75 In particular, Shapiro holds that “social science cannot tell us what the nature of law is . . . [because] social scientific theories are limited . . . being able to study only human groups and hence cannot provide an account about all possible instances of law.” 76 The only example he gives, however, of other non-human instances of law are those he takes from, of all things, science fiction. 77 On these rather shaky grounds Shapiro goes on to reject the view of many other legal theorists who argue that analytical legal philosophers in their attempts to understand the nature of law must consult the social sciences, since part of the tasks of the social sciences is to study social institutions, and law is certainly at least partly a social institution. Accordingly, Shapiro tries to explain away Hart’s explicit statement that his own work in legal theory was “an exercise in descriptive sociology” 78 in order to claim Hart as effectively holding his own views, he writes, “My own view is that Hart was right with respect to the concept of law.” 79 But that can be the case only on appeal to his own revisionist interpretation of what Hart himself actually wrote. For Shapiro’s interpretation appears to stand on no steadier evidential bases than on science fiction ones. The matter here in fact is more general than may at first appear. The issue is how to account for social dependence of values without falling into cultural relativism. Cf. Raz 2003, pp. 15-36 and 121-156. 75 76 Shapiro 2011, p. 407. 77 Ibid. 78 Hart 1961, p. vi; cited in Shapiro 2011, p. 406. 79 Ibid. 40 In the end, Shapiro comes back to a more stable understanding of the nature of the law. Regardless of the difficult matter of the extent to which the nature of the law is independent or not in some strong senses of what social facts are taken to be, Shapiro insists “that it is part of our concept of law that groups can have legal systems provided they are more or less rational agents and have the ability to follow rules.” 80 And legal systems here are understood as fundamentally certain systems of rules. Dworkin disagrees. The nature of law, he argues is not to be understood as a function of systems of rules of whatever kind. For law consists of much more than rules arranged in some systematic order.81 To see why Dworkin thinks this, we need to note above all his programmatic objective to replace what he calls the ordinary, orthodox picture of law and morality forming two separate systems of norms with his own, reformed picture of law and morality forming but one.82 The orthodox belief, Dworkin thinks, is that law “belongs to communities, that it is made by people, that it is contingent.” Moreover, many philosophers, whether “conventionalists or relativists or skeptics of some other form” think that, just like law, morality too belongs to communities, is made by people, and is contingent.83 In short, although there may be questions about how these two systems interact, on an orthodox account systems comprise very similar although not identical kinds of norms. Ibid., p. 407. Note, however, several questions in Marmor 2013 about the appropriateness of conceptual analysis only for the explanation of the nature of law. 80 81 Dworkin 1978, chapter one. 82 See McCormick 2012, pp. 99-107. 83 Dworkin 2011, p. 401. 41 Dworkin rejects the orthodow view. He thinks law and morality, although similar in being collections of norms, are fundamentally dissimilar in collecting very different kinds of norms. And this nonidentity of kinds of norms is perhaps the most important feature that makes the systems of law and morality themselves non-identical. Thus, morality, unlike law, does not belong to a community, because morality “consists of a set of standards or norms that have imperative force for everyone.” 84 Further, morality, unlike law, “is not made by anyone (except, on some views, a god). . . .” 85 Still more, morality, unlike law, “is not contingent on any human decision or practice.” 86 But if Dworkin is right, then he must answer satisfactorily a central and difficult question. For if indeed there are two systems of very different kinds of norms, how exactly are they related? By way of response Dworkin highlights two approaches to this question. One he calls, without qualification,87 the “legal positivism” approach, the other the “legal intrepretivism” approach. The first, presumably, is that of Hart and his followers including Shapiro, who hold for a complete independence between the two systems of norms. 84 Ibid., p. 400. 85 Loc. cit. 86 Loc. cit. Here, unlike Shapiro 2011, pp. 269-277, Dworkin does not distinguish between inclusive legal positivism (the view that social facts ultimately determine legal facts) and exclusive legal positivism (the view that social facts alone determine legal facts). More explicitly, exclusive legal positivism holds that “not only do social facts determine the content of the law at the highest level, but they do so at every point in the chain of validity. Under no conditions may the truth of a legal proposition depend on the existence of a moral fact” (p. 269). Cf. Waluchow 1994, Himma 2004, and Marmor 2004. 87 42 This is the orthodox and indeed majority position. And the second is his own, the reformed and minority position, which denies that the two systems are completely independent. On the legal positivist account, “what the law is depends only on historical matters of fact: it depends finally on what the community in question, as a matter of custom and practice, accepts as law.” 88 By contrast, on the legal interpretivist account, what the law is depends “not only [on] the specific rules enacted in accordance with the community’s accepted practices but also [on] the principles that provide the best moral justification for those enacted rules.” 89 What stands behind the interpretivist account is a particular understanding of the polyvalence of Hart’s expression, “the concept of law.” Dworkin thinks that there this expression confounds three different senses of “the law.” There is what he calls the sociological sense of the law “as when we say that law began in primitive societies,” what he calls the aspirational sense “as when we celebrate the rule of law,” and what he calls the doctrinal sense that “we use to report what the law is on some subject. 90 Although both positivism and interpretivism both consider the concept of the law in its doctrinal sense, each takes the concept of law in a different way. For the positivist, the concept of the law is a criterial concept, that is, a concept that satisfies “the tests of pedigree that lawyers . . . share for identifying true propositions of doctrinal law.” For the interpretivist, the concept of law is an interpretive concept, that is, a concept that “treats lawyers’ claims about what the 88 Ibid., p. 401. 89 Ibid., p. 402. 90 Loc. cit. 43 law holds or requires on some matter as conclusions of an interpretive argument. . . .” 91 Now, this interpretivist picture of the two systems of law and morality as collections of very different kinds of norms which Dworkin first sketched out in 1977 is, he went on in 2011 to argue surprisingly, fatally flawed. “The two-systems picture . . . faces an apparently insoluble problem: it poses a question that cannot be answered other than by assuming an answer from the start.” 92 How so? “Once we take law and morality to compose separate systems of norms,” he writes in 2011, “there is no neutral standpoint from which the connections between these supposedly separate systems can be adjudicated.” 93 That is, we cannot adjudicate in any neutral way any answer to the question whether one view or another is the more accurate. For that question itself – “Which is the more accurate view of the law, the positivist or the interpretivist?” – raises the more fundamental question – “But what kind of a question is that, a legal one or a moral one?” Dworkin goes on to demonstrate that answering the second question either way turns out necessarily to be viciously and not virtuously circular. 94 Still, once we concede that law is not a criterial but an interpretive concept, a notion Dworkin explores at some length,95 then Dworkin believes there is a persuasive approach to handling the circularity issue if not a finally demonstrative one. That approach 91 Loc. cit. 92 Dworkin 2011, p. 403. 93 Ibid., pp. 402-403. 94 Ibid., p. 403. 95 Ibid, pp. 157-158. 44 involves spelling out just how we come to understand what an interpretive concept like the concept of law comprises. We begin an analysis of the concept of law then in a quite particular way. We begin, he writes, “by identifying the political, commercial, and social practices in which the concept figures. . . . We [go on to] construct a conception of law . . . by finding a justification of those practices in a larger integrated network of political value. We construct a theory of law, that is, in the same way that we construct a theory of other political values – of equality, liberty, and democracy. [And he adds:] Any theory of law, understood in that interpretive way, will inevitably be controversial, just as those latter theories are.” 96 This is the approach to the concept of law as an interpretive kind of concept rather than as a criterial kind that brings Dworkin to his conclusion. Law is not to be treated as separated from political morality, as in the orthodox two-system picture. Rather, in the reformed one-system picture, law is to be “treated as a part of political morality.” 97 More fundamentally, on Dworkin’s interpretivist account of law, law has its proper place in what he calls “a tree structure.” Thus, law is a branch of political morality.98 Political morality itself branches from personal “morality” in Dworkin’s special sense of how we should act towards others. And personal morality branches from what Dworkin calls “ethics” in his special sense of how we should live.99 96 Ibid., pp. 404-405. 97 Ibid., p. 405. On Dworkin’s complicated views on the relations between law and morality see Marmor 2011, “Is Law Determined by Morality,” pp. 84-108. 98 Ibid., pp. 13-15 and 191; see Guest 2013, pp. 160-163. Still other “branches” of Dworkin’s tree structure can be glimpsed in an excerpt in The New York Review of 99 45 What comes clear in this opposition between a legal positivist criterial concept of law and a legal interpretivist conception of law is the fundamental limiting role of law on political sovereignties. No political sovereign, whether in a Westphalian system or in a Mycenaean system, can dispense with the absolutely fundamental role of rules. For without rules no system of government is possible. But rules make up a collection. And whether we conceive of that collection in general as something so historically developed as “the rule of law” or as something much more ancient as say “the rules of the leader” whether a wanax or a king, these collections of governance rules are of their very nature constraints on political sovereignty. In most of the much later European cases they are constraints imposed by social communities on their rulers whether chosen or not. And in most of the much earlier European cases they are constraints imposed by the sovereign on himself. In the first instance, these constraints cannot be easily changed; in the second, they persist at the whim of the sovereign himself. Still, even in the very early case of Mycenaean polities one basic reason for the as yet undetermined nature of the political leader, the wanax, is persisting uncertainty as to the role of other quasi-royal elites. For Mycenae concealed more than the so-called grave and mask of Agamemnon. But these other political elites could not be what they were without having the powers to exercise some kinds of constraints on the wanax himself. Otherwise, they could not have held the privilege of enjoying like the wanax the highly distinctive right to shaft grave burials in tholos tombs. Rules, the rule of law, law itself – all necessarily involve constraints on political sovereignty of whatever kind. Finally, the Books, April 4, 2013, “Religion Without God,” taken from his forthcoming book of the same name. 46 arguments here converge on the idea that there can be no political sovereignty without constraints of some kind. No political sovereignty therefore can be absolute. In short, political sovereignty is always limited; political sovereignty is necessarily bounded sovereignty. Concluding Remarks and Transitions §8. A First Set of Interim Conclusions: Bounded Sovereignties I A brief case study of the archeological findings of the Mycenaean shaft graves in an historical and cultural period close to the beginnings of European civilization in the Aegean Bronze Age suggests for further critical discussion about the values to be entrenched in the Preamble to any eventual EU constitution at least three major points about the nature of political sovereignties. 8.1 Political sovereignties are limited with respect to major kinds of political power that exist within the same geo-political realm. 8.2 Political sovereignties are also limited with respect to major forms of political life that exist in other, more developed polities, and with respect to the ineluctable dependencies that various kinds of economic, military, and social change bring about. 8.3 Political sovereignties are limited still more with respect to the very nature of rules, laws, and the rule of law on which every polity must depend. After our brief investigations here, then, of the limited nature at the outset of European civilization of political sovereignties at a 47 highpoint of Mycenaean culture, we need now to narrow our focus to the nature of social sovereignties with the help of a further reflective step back into the reaches of the still earlier Minoan cultures of the Aegean Bronze Age. If both political sovereignties can be properly described only as limited sovereignties, our question now will be whether, nonetheless, social sovereignties may in some senses still be properly taken as unlimited. Trying to deal not inadequately with that question will be our main task in the second seminar. 48 Endnotes With simplifications and adaptations, for the Mycenaean Civilization I use here Bintliff’s 2012, p. 181 calibrated Carbon 14 dated chronologies (that is, “including corrections to direct dates to allow for atmospheric carbon fluctuations”: p. 46) and abbreviations as follows (dates give the approximate beginnings of the BCE periods): Bintliff 2012, p. 181. i 1800/1700-1500: LH 1, or Late Helladic 1 1500-1400: LH 2 1400-1250/1200: LH 3A-B 1250-1200: LH 3 C Note that on the Greek mainland the Aegean Bronze Age is called “The Helladic Period” (see Table 1 in Kline 2010, p. xxx). Except where otherwise indicated, throughout this essay I follow the general (p. 6) and particular (passim) chronologies in Bintliff 2012 and more specifically Manning 2010, while consulting the “Approximate Chronology” of Kline and Voutsaki in Cline 2010, p. xxx, the chronologies in Shelmerdine 2008, pp. 4-5, and the careful observations of Deger-Jalkotzy 2008. Note the technical debates between those like Manning et al. 2006 who favor a so-called “High Chronology” and those like Warren and Hankey 1989 who favor a “Low Chronology.” For the difficult matter of relative chronologies (that is, “the temporal ordering of objects and events relative to each other”) versus scientific or science-based chronologies (that is, the allocation of “Western calendar timescale [thus dates AD/CE or BC/BCE] to archeological contexts, objects, or discussions”) see Manning 2012 in Kline 2012, pp. 11-28, Tables 2.1 and 2.2, and the extensive bibliography. (The citations above are from Bintliff 2012, pp. 12 and 18 respectively.) Keeping in mind one archeologist’s remark is essential. “The Egyptian records,” this expert writes recently, “are, for the most part 49 contemporaneous with the events they describe (and date). Modern scientific dating techniques, however sophisticated, still represent modern attempts to reconstruct a chronology for events that happened three or four thousand years ago. The more we work with the range of scientific dating techniques available to the modern scholar the more we come to realize the complexities of each technique and the number of variables that have to be understood and accounted for” (Muhly 2010, p. 7). This terminology is derived from the application to continuing excavations of Mycenae on the mainland of the currently more reliable Cretan periodization into Early Palatial, Palatial, and Postpalatial periods. See French 2010, pp. 672-673, and Preston 2008, pp. 319-310, note 1. ii The main evidence comes not from the multiple excavations at Troy beginning already early in the nineteenth century but from mentions of Mycenaean attacks in Hittite cuneiform archives from the Hittite capital, Hattusa that refer to “Ahhiyawa” (“Achaioi” or the Greeks) which most scholars today identify with Mycenaean Greece (Jablonka 2010, pp. 857-858). iii For a selection from different museums in the Argolid see Iakovidis 1979. Mycenae’s relatively new museum exhibits a model of the site of Mycenae and a copy of the “Mask of Agamemnon” together with an extensive collection of funerary objects from the “Treasure of Atreus” and the tomb circles. iv “The Treasury of Atreus” is the most important of the nine tholos or elite beehive tombs uncovered in Mycenae so far. Prestigious tholos tombs generally advertise wealthy and powerful families, and Mycenae gradually achieved a monopoly in their use (see Bintliff’s 2012 discussion, pp. 192-194). The fabled family of King Atreus, the first of a royal dynasty, included the famous figures of Atreus’s brother, Thyestes, Thyestes’s son, Aegisthes who assassinated Atreus, and Atreus’s his own sons, Menelaus and Agamemnon. Agamemnon sacrifices his daughter, Iphigeneia, and, on his return to Mycenae from v 50 the conquest of Troy, is murdered by his wife, Clytemnestra. Her son, Orestes, later murders her and her paramour, Aegisthes, and, after placating the goddesses (the Erynyes), becomes king of Mycenae and of Argos. Homer and the tragedians tell their stories. According to the SOED, the rather recent mid-twentieth century word, “processual,” means “pertaining to a social or linguistic process.” Renfrew and Bahn’s Glossary entry on “processual archeology” reads: “An approach that stresses the dynamic relationship between social and economic aspects of culture and the environment as the basis for understanding the processes of culture change. Uses the scientific methodology of problem statement, hypothesis formulation, and subsequent testing. The earlier functionalprocessual archaeology has been contrasted with cognitive-processual archaeology, where emphasis is on integrating ideological and symbolic aspects” (p. 582). vi Note that a distinction holds between legal philosophy or philosophy of law on the one hand, and, on the other, legal theory and jurisprudence. Legal philosophy “attempts to unravel the sort of problems that might concern moral or political philosophers,” whereas legal theory “is often used to denote theoretical theories about law ‘as such’ that extend beyond the boundaries of law as understood by professional lawyers (e. g. the economic analysis of law). . . .” (ODL) Jurisprudence may be distinguished from both legal philosophy and legal theory “by its concerns with those questions (e. g. about the nature of a particular right or duty, or a particular line of judicial reasoning) that arise within or are implied by substantive legal disciplines” (Ibid.) vii On these definitions, our concerns here to specify what is at issue in a major disagreement today on the nature of law itself appears not to be a jurisprudential inquiry for it is more general. Our concerns then might seem to be more a matter of legal theory than of legal philosophy. For the theories we are concerned with appear to be “theories about law ‘as such’ that extend beyond the boundaries of law as understood by professional lawyers.” 51 But the theories we are concerned with here also seem to be “attempts to unravel the sort of problems that might concern moral or political philosophers.” For these theories about the nature of law certainly do concern both kinds of philosophers. So let us say that in pursuing what separates two distinguished contemporary views on the nature of law we are looking into a matter that has its place in both the legal philosophy and legal theory. This stipulation will allow us to formulate our conclusions perhaps with somewhat more flexibility than were we to stipulate our inquiries more narrowly as either legal philosophy or legal theory. “Legal philosophy is often (e. g. John Austin, H. L. A. Hart, Joseph Raz) divided into analytical and critical. Analytical jurisprudence is to consider the definition of law, the theory of legal system, the analysis of legal concepts such as duty, transaction and intention, and the theory of legal reasoning, especially in adjudication. Critical philosophy of law is to evaluate law and legal obligation, the minimum substantive content of legal systems, the interlocking virtues called the rule of law, etc. But against such a division, and the similar recent division between conceptual (or explanatory) and justificatory, it can be said that legal systems are created and maintained for reasons, and these like every reason for action presuppose and / or propose evaluation(s). Any general account of legal systems (or of the concept of law and legal system) must identify those shaping evaluations” (Finnis 2005, p. 500). viii