Marxist Jurisprudence

advertisement
MARXIST JURISPRUDENCE
TUTOR: CHRIS BEHRENS
STUDENT: DAVID RISSTROM: 9106105
In the social production of their existence, men inevitably enter into definite relations, which are independent of their will,
namely relations of production appropriate to a given stage in the development of their material forces of production. The
totality of these relations constitute the economic structure of society, the real foundation, on which arises a legal and
political superstructure and to which correspond definite forms of social consciousness.
Karl Marx, Preface to A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy, 521.1
Marxist jurisprudence posits that legal relations are determined by the economic base of particular kinds of
society and modes of production.2
Marxist thought’s primary focus rests on political economy and the
corresponding power relations within society, providing the most extensive critique to date of liberal
tradition on which many of our legal presuppositions are founded. To this end, this essay examines law, its
structure, motivation and consequences for justice and rights from a Marxian jurisprudential perspective.
MARXISM AND LAW
Your ideas are but the outgrowth of the conditions of your bourgeois production and bourgeois property, just as your
jurisprudence is but the will of your class made into a law for all, a will, whose essential character and direction are
determined by the economical conditions of existence in your class.
Karl Marx, The Communist Manifesto, 24.
Law is not of central concern to Marxists jurisprudentialists, as law in the capitalist mode of production is
seen as an instrument of class oppression perpetuated as a consequence of its particular historical, social and
economic structures. Indeed, wishing to avoid liberal predisposition towards legal fetishism, Marxists deny
the degree of importance jurisprudence typically affords law in analyses of the composition and
determination of social formations.3
WHAT IS MARXISM?
Marxist theories of political economy, expounded upon the notions of Karl Marx (1818-83) and Friedrich
Engels (1820-95), consider law an instrument of class oppression that benefits the ruling class through
oppression of the proletariat. The common law system of criminal and civil law, which protects personal
and private property rights, as well as facilitating predicability in social life, is regarded as “no more than a
system of coercion designed to protect bourgeois ownership of the means of production”. 4
1
2
3
4
Marx, K., ‘Preface to A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy’ in Karl Marx and Frederick Engels Selected
Works, Moscow: Progress Press, 1989 521.
Balbus, I., ‘Commodity Form and Legal Form’ in Reasons, C., The Sociology of Law, Toronto: Butterworths, 1978 83.
Collins, H., Marxism and Law, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987 98.
Barry, N., An Introduction to Modern Political Theory, London: Macmillan, 1989 53.
Left Critique: Marxism / David Risstrom / Page 1
Yet, despite Marx and Engels’ failure to develop a systematic approach to law 5, and claims of failure in
Eastern Europe and the Soviet Union, Marxism’s materialist emphasis, particularly concerning the notion of
alienation and its consequences as outlined by Ollman6, assists its contemporary paucity.7
HISTORICAL MATERIALISM
Men have history because they must produce their life, and because they must produce it moreover in a certain way: this is
determined by their physical organisation; their consciousness is determined in just the same way.
Marx, The German Ideology, 49.
The determinist relationship between the economic base and social superstructure, known as Historical
Materialism, is first described in The German Ideology.8 Historic materialism contends that the catalyst
behind societal evolution is materially determined, being predicated on contradictions between the forces
and means of production.
consciousness”9,
As “it is not consciousness that determines life, but life that determines
law is a reflection of the economic base, rather than the reserve as liberals such as Dworkin
would propose.
Under increasing industrialisation Marx foresaw crystallisation of society into two classes; bourgeoisie and
proletariat.
These relations of production developed due to particular forces of production under the
capitalist mode of production that coerced the bourgeoisie to extract surplus value as profit from the
proletariat. Laws, as Marx detailed in Capital, as one element of the social superstructure, assisted in forcing
down wages.10
Collins characterises two Marxist approaches; crude materialism, in which law is simply a reflection of the
economic base; and secondly, class instrumentalism; in which rules emerge because the ruling class want
them to.11
This distinction continues as an area of debate, as demonstrated by O'Malley’s attacks of
Quinney and Chambliss’ crude materialist claim that law is a direct tool of powerful classes or groups,
favouring the more interactionist, and less conflict premised theory of legislative change.12
Autonomy Thesis is such a theory.
The Relative
Contemporary Marxists such as Marcuse, suggest mechanisms
analogous to the Factory Acts and Vagrancy Acts remain instruments of the ruling class perpetuating
conditions reinforcing this arrangement, especially in relation to the alienating nature of modern
technological rationality.13
BASE AND SUPERSTRUCTURE IN THE CAPITALIST MODE OF PRODUCTION
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
Cain, M., and Hunt, A., 1979, Marx and Engels on Law, London: Academic Press.
Ollman, B.,1976, Alienation; Marx’s Conception of Man in Capitalist Society, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Collins, H., op cit., 10.
Marx, K., and Engels, F., 1976, The German Ideology, Moscow: Progress Press.
Marx, K., The German Ideology, Moscow: Progress Publishers, 1976 42.
Marx, K., ‘Bloody Legislation against the Expropriated, from the end of the 15th. century: Forcing Down Wages by
Acts of Parliament’ in Capital, 1986 686.
Collins, H., Marxism and Law, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987 24.
O’Malley, P., ‘Theories on Structure Versus Causal Determination’ in Tomasic (ed.) Legislation and Society in
Australia, Allen and Unwin, 1980 140.
Marcuse, H., One-Dimensional Man, Boston: Beacon Press, 1968 xv.
Left Critique: Marxism / David Risstrom / Page 2
Much of our law, such as Contract, Property and Commercial Law, is predicated on the existence of the
capitalist mode of production. As Marx’s major project was the critique of capitalism, irrespective of a belief
in revolution, Marxism has a great deal to notify us of in our contemporary jurisprudence. Marxism
postulates that in the social production of their existence, people, independent of their will, enter into
definite relations of production appropriate to a given stage in the development of the materials forces of
production.14
Consequently the societal superstructure, including but not dominated by law, amongst
other hegemonic devices, is determined by the economic base and the organisation of power in society. 15
Marxist jurisprudence concentrates on the relationship between law and particular historical, social and
economic structures, seeing law, unlike liberal theory, as having no legitimate primacy.
encountered legal rules and doctrine, argue
Gramsci16
and
Althusser17,
Frequently
establish modern liberal
jurisprudential hegemony.18
SCIENTIFIC SOCIALISM
Marxist epistemology, with dialectic materialism as the centrepiece of Marxism’s scientific claim, proclaims
in real life, where speculation ends, positive science; the representation of the practical activity, of the
practical progress of development of men, begins.19
Whilst Marx’s materialism does not refer to the
assumption of a logically argued ontological position, Marx adopts an undoubtedly Realist position, in
which ideas are the product of the human brain in sensory transaction with a knowable material world. 20
These claims contrast with those of natural lawyers such as Aquinas who believe religion should
normatively guide law; those desiring utilitarian tendencies such as Austin and Bentham; or objective
consistency as some positivists such as Hart, or perhaps integrity, as perhaps only Dworkin can fully
endorse. Nevertheless, whilst debate as to the scientific credentials of Marxism continue, Collins claims
Marxism’s desire for class reductionism to explain the dynamic interaction between man and nature risks
misconstruing the diversity of social phenomena in order to confirm the ‘rigid systemic framework of
historical materialism’.21
LAW AND THE DICTATORSHIP OF THE PROLETARIAT
Law, morality, religion, are to him so many bourgeois prejudices, behind which lurk in ambush as many bourgeois
interests.
Karl Marx, The Communist Manifesto, 18
Marxism saw development of the relations of production dialectically, as both inevitable, and creating
hostility. Accelerated by increased class consciousness, as the contradictions of capitalism perforate the
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
Marx. K., Preface To ‘A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy’ in Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels Selected
Works, 1989 521.
Collins, H., op cit., 9.
Gramsci, A., Selections from the Prison Notebooks, London: Lawrence and Wishart. 1971 195.
Althusser, L., For Marx, London: New Left Books, 1977 114.
Collins, H., Marxism and Law, Oxford University Press, 1982 50.
Marx, K., The German Ideology, Moscow: Progress Publishers, 1976 38.
Giddens, A., Capitalism and Modern Social Theory: An Analysis of the writings of Marx, Durkheim and Weber, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1971 21.
Collins, H., op cit., 45.
Left Critique: Marxism / David Risstrom / Page 3
bourgeois hegemony, inevitable revolution and a dictatorship of the proletariat would facilitate “socialised
production upon a predetermined plan.”22
Given the scientific nature of Historic Materialism, and upon
recognising the role the state and its laws supply, the proletariat will seize political power and turn the
means of production into state property23, then according to Marxist jurisprudence, “As soon as there is no
longer any class to be held in subjection; as soon as class rule and the individual struggle for existence … are
removed, nothing more remains to be repressed.”24
COMMUNISM AND THE END OF LAW
The meaning of history, that man’s destiny lies in creation of a Communist society where “law will wither
away”25 , as men experience a higher stage of being amounting to the realisation of true freedom, will after
transition through Socialism, be achieved.
JUSTICE AND RIGHTS
Communism abolishes eternal truths, it abolishes all religion, and all morality, instead of constituting them on a new basis.
Karl Marx, The Communist Manifesto, 24
Marxism argues there is no absolute concept of justice, justice being dependent on the requirements of a
given mode of production.26 Lukes claims Marx believes justice, “Does not provide a set of independent
rational standards by which to measure social relations, but must itself always in turn be explained as
arising from and controlling those relations”.27
Marxism believes that rights are simply a bourgeois creation, and that justice is something only the rich can
achieve in capitalist modes of production. Anatole France (1894) encapsulated this distinction between
formal and substantive justice as entitlement, drawing attention to “the majestic egalitarianism of the law,
which forbids rich and poor alike to sleep under bridges, to beg in the streets and to steal bread.” 28 Formal
justice as entitlement therefore allows equal opportunity to the individual without any reference to the
unequal ability to use it, with rights only being anti-socialist if individuals are taken to be “inherently and
irredeemably self-interested.”29
Marxist dispute over how rights and justice will operate in practice are answered by the materialist
proposition that the “distribution of burdens and benefits should not be taken in accordance with a book of
rules, but in the light of the objectives of social policy.”30
Campbell distinguishes between Socialist and
Bourgeois Rights, arguing that an interest based theory of rights, rather than the contract based notions such
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
Engels, F., Socialism: Utopian and Scientific, Moscow: Progress Publishers: 1954 79.
Ibid., 73.
Ibid., 73.
Marx, K., The German Ideology, Moscow Progress Press, 1976 51.
Wacks, R., Jurisprudence, London: Blackstone Press, 1987 175.
Lukes, S., Marxism, Morality and Justice’ in Parkinson, G., Marx and Marxisms, Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1982 197.
Gamble, A., An Introduction to Modern Political and Social Thought, Hampshire: Macmillan, 1987 101.
Campbell, T., Justice, London: Macmillan, 1988 189.
Campbell, T., The Left and Rights, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1983 33.
Left Critique: Marxism / David Risstrom / Page 4
as Pashukanis’ incorporated in his commodity exchange theory of law31, allow protection of the
individual32, thereby negating the logical connection between rights and justice. 33
IN SUMMARY
Marxist jurisprudence and Marxist critiques of law provide invaluable challenges to our thinking as people
under law in a liberal democratic society. This essay is only the briefest of introductions in a field rich with
reflections concerning the assumptions we construct into our law. Whether you accept the claims of its
doctrine, its influence on shaping the society we live in is more significant than most of us realise.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Althusser, L., 1977, For Marx, London: New Left Books.
Balbus, I., 1978, ‘Commodity Form and Legal Form’ in Reasons, C., The Sociology of Law, Toronto:
Butterworths.
Baradat, L., 1991, Political Ideologies: Their Origins and Impact, 4th Edn., New Jersey: Prentice Hall.
Barbalet, J., 1983, Marx's Construction of Social Theory, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Barry, N., 1989, An Introduction to Modern Political Theory, 2nd Edn., London: Macmillan.
Berger, P. and Luckmann, T., 1975, The Social Construction of Reality, Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Blackburn, R., (Ed.), 1991, After the Fall: The Failure of Communism, London: Verso.
Cain, M., and Hunt, A., 1979, Marx and Engels on Law, London: Academic Press.
Campbell, T., 1988, Justice, London: Macmillan.
Campbell, T., 1981, Seven Theories of Human Nature, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Campbell, T., 1983, The Left and Rights, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Collins, H., 1982, Marxism and Law, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Connell, R., 1977, Ruling Class, Ruling Culture, London: Cambridge University Press.
Cotterrell, R., 1989, The Politics of Jurisprudence: A Critical Introduction to Legal Philosophy, London:
Butterworths.
Easton, L and K, Guddat (Eds.), 1967, Writings of the Young Marx on Philosophy and Society, New York:
Anchor.
Engels, F., 1954, Socialism: Scientific and Utopian, Moscow: Progress Press.
Foucault, M., 1979, Discipline and Punish-The Birth of the Prison, Middlesex: Penguin.
Frankel, B., 1983, Beyond the State?; Dominant Theories and Socialist Strategies, London: MacMillan.
31
Warrington, R., ‘Pashukanis and the commodity form theory’ in Sugarman, D., Legality, Ideology and the State,
London: Academic Press, 1983 43.
32 Campbell, T. 1983, op cit., 123.
33 Ibid., 124.
Left Critique: Marxism / David Risstrom / Page 5
Frolov, I. (ed.), 1980, Dictionary of Philosophy, Moscow: Progress Publishers.
Fromm, E., 1973, Marx's Concept of Man, New York: Frederick Ungar Publishing.
Gamble, A., 1987, An Introduction To Modern Social And Political Thought, Hampshire: Macmillan.
Giddens, A., 1981, Capitalism and Modern Social Theory; An analysis of the writings of Marx, Durkheim and Weber,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Gramsci, A., 1971, Selections from the Prison Notebooks, London: Lawrence and Wishart.
Habermas, J., 1970, Toward a Rational Society, London: Heinemann.
Harris, J., 1980, Legal Philosophies, London: Butterworths.
Kellner, D., 1984, Herbert Marcuse and the Crisis of Marxism, London: Macmillan.
Luhmann, N., 1982, The Differentiation of Society, New York: Colombia University Press.
Lukes, S., 1986, Power: A Radical View, London: Oxford University Press.
Marcuse, H., 1975, One-Dimensional Man, Boston: Beacon Press.
Marx, K., 1986, ‘Bloody Legislation against the Expropriated, from the end of the 15th.
Century: Forcing Down Wages by Acts of Parliament’ in Capital, Moscow: Progress Press.
Marx, K., 1986, Capital; A Critique of political Economy, Vol 1; The Process of Production of Capital, Moscow:
Progress Publishers.
Marx, K., 1977, Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts of 1844, Moscow: Progress Publishers.
Marx, K.,1975, Early Writings, London: Penguin.
Marx K. and Engels F., 1848, Manifesto of the Communist Party; authorised English translation from the MarxEngels Institute, Melbourne: International Bookshop.
Marx, K., 1989, ‘Preface to A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy’ in Karl Marx and Frederick
Engels Selected Works, Moscow: Progress Press.
Marx, K., and Engels, F., 1965, The German Ideology, Moscow: Progress Publishers.
Marx, K., and Engels, F., 1989, Selected Works, Moscow: Progress Publishers.
Marx, K., 1902, Wage, Labour and Capital, New York: New York Labor News Company.
McLellan, D.,1971, Marx’s Grundisse, London: Macmillan.
McLellan, D.,1980, The Thought of Karl Marx, London: Macmillan.
McMurtry, J., 1978, The Structure of Marx’s World View, New Jersey: Princeton University Press.
Offe, C., 1985, Disorganised Capitalism: Contemporary Transformations of Work and Politics, Cambridge: Polity
Press.
Ollman, B.,1976, Alienation; Marx’s Conception of Man in Capitalist Society, Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
O’Malley, P., 1980, ‘Theories on Structure Versus Causal Determination’ in Tomasic (Ed.) Legislation and
Society in Australia, Sydney: Allen and Unwin.
Left Critique: Marxism / David Risstrom / Page 6
Tucker, R., (ed.),1972, The Marx-Engels Reader, New York: Norton.
Wacks, R., 1987, Jurisprudence, London: Blackstone Press.
Warrington, R., 1983, ‘Pashukanis and the commodity form theory’ in Sugarman, D., Legality, Ideology and the
State, London: Academic Press.
Left Critique: Marxism / David Risstrom / Page 7
Download