Chapter 8 Accountability in a House of Mirrors Deborah G. Johnson Surveillance and transparency are framed together, in this volume, as forms of accountability by emphasizing that each involves, at its core, watchers, those who are watched, and accounts (used to make judgments and decisions about the watched). Framing transparency as a form of accountability is not unusual; that is, transparency is commonly viewed as a mechanism for holding individuals and organizations accountable. Surveillance, however, is not generally understood to be accountability, at least not in its positive sense. Transparency is seen as a check on power; it is a mechanism for watching those with power to make sure they are using it in a responsible manner. By contrast, surveillance is a mechanism used by those with power to keep track of those without power. Often it seems that surveillance is viewed as unjustifiable or illegitimate accountability. This is suggested in Foucault’s dense, theoretical analysis as well as in more concrete criticism of common practices such as electronic monitoring of employees or CCTV on public streets. In surveillance, the powerful ‘account for’ the less powerful for some purpose, that is, when the powerful have some interest in the behavior of the less powerful. Each of the five case studies plays out the accountability theme using the house of mirrors metaphor to explore the complexities of accountability practices. This chapter brings the case study analyses together in a fuller analysis – a rethinking – of the notion Chapter 8: Accountability in a House of Mirrors of accountability. The analysis is tilted towards surveillance because surveillance is a more awkward fit with the accountability frame. How, the question is, is our understanding of surveillance, especially its problematic character, informed by treating it as a form of accountability? How does the house of mirrors metaphor help to reveal the similarities and differences in sociotechnical systems? Accountability is a Social Practice involving Shared Norms There are good reasons to be skeptical about at least some accountability practices. That is, some of those who ‘accept responsibility’ seem simply to go through the motions; they publicly acknowledge that they should account for what happened, but their acceptance of responsibility seems ‘pro forma.’ The person or organization goes through the motions, doing what is publicly expected, but this does not amount to much. Worst, the accounts given in public may hide self-interested or corrupt behavior or may draw attention away from deeper injustices and illegalities. When, for example, oil companies such as BP tout their ‘green’ policies as initiatives in the name of corporate social responsibility, a degree of skepticism about their motives seems appropriate. Or, when Richard Nixon famously defended his role in Watergate by saying that he was “responsible but not to blame”, he seemed to acknowledge his accountability for the incident while treating accountability as essentially vacuous.1 1 Watergate refers to an incident in which several men broke in to the offices of the Democratic National Committee headquarters at the Watergate office complex. The FBI was able to connect payments to the burglars to a slush fund used by a Committee to Re-elect President Nixon so the break in was thought to be an intelligence-gathering mission for Nixon’s re-election campaign. 2 Chapter 8: Accountability in a House of Mirrors Despite reasons for skepticism, accountability practices are important. The idea that individuals, representatives, and organizations are accountable for their behavior is deeply embedded in Western thought and practice, and in the idea and practices of democracy. Even more profoundly, many believe, or seem to believe, that there is an ultimate moral reckoning (an accounting) with regard to what one does throughout one’s life – how one has behaved, what kind of a person one is. In this respect, notions of accountability can profoundly shape the way individuals understand their lives. And, accountability is at the very heart of democracy in the sense that the sovereignty of the ruled means at a minimum that they are entitled to an explanation (an accounting) from those who rule. Accountability is also important because it has currency. It is now touted as the solution to problems in many different domains. For example, in education, accountability is seen as a new strategy for improvement. Here, accountability is coupled with assessment and performance evaluation and is often targeted specifically for public schools (Kress, et. al. 2011, Conner and Rabovsky 2011, Gunzenhauser and Hyde 2007). In international relations, accountability is discussed frequently in relation to foreign aid and to the activities of non-profits (Park 2010, Winters, 2010). And more broadly, in public administration, accountability is increasingly seen as an effective strategy for avoiding government regulation while at the same time targeting and measuring progress towards social goals (Anderson, 2009, Martin and Frahm 2010). 3 Chapter 8: Accountability in a House of Mirrors Although they are often implicit and go unnoticed, accountability practices are commonplace. Wherever there are norms and expectations, individuals or groups may be held to account for failure to conform. If one fails to fulfill obligations to family, friends, employers, etc., one may be asked to explain, and if no explanation, or an inadequate explanation, is given, one may be criticized, blamed, or, simply judged to be unworthy, e.g., not such a good person, friend, employee. One is being held accountable for one’s behavior. So, what are we to make of accountability? How do accountability practices operate? What makes them work? Many scholars have discussed the elusive nature of the concept of accountability and its interpretative flexibility. Some trace the roots of the concept or its ‘real’ meaning; others argue for restricting usage or making the concept useful for particular purposes or contexts. Although scholars differ on the details and emphasize different aspects, there is a rough consensus about key element. Bovens (2007) claims that “the most concise description of accountability would be ‘the obligation to explain and justify conduct’.” He goes on to specify more carefully that: “Accountability is a relationship between an actor and a forum, in which the actor has an obligation to explain and to justify his or her conduct, the forum can pose questions and pass judgement, and the actor may face consequences.” 4 Chapter 8: Accountability in a House of Mirrors Mulgan is much more concerned with ongoing changes in (usage of) the concept of accountability that he believes have resulted in a “weakening of the importance of external scrutiny.” Nevertheless, Mulgan (citing Jones, 1992) suggests that the one sense of accountability on which all are agreed is “that associated with the process of being called ‘to account’ to some authority for one’s actions.” The normative aspect of accountability is salient in both Bovens’ and Mulgan’s accounts. At the heart of accountability for Bovens is an obligation to explain and justify conduct; for Mulgan the account giver recognizes an authority to which the account must be given. Accountability practices work when those involved share the norms, i.e., they acknowledge that an explanation is owed or that the recipient is entitled to one. Accountability practices are problematic when there is disagreement about the norms, that is, varying ideas about who or what is owed to whom. For example, when a public official doesn’t believe he or she should have to explain private behavior to constituents, or when an employee believes that his or her employer should accept some absences from work without explanation. In these cases the individual being held to account doesn’t accept their accountability. That accountability involves shared norms helps, in part at least, to understand the performative dimension of accountability. Those involved may accept their obligation but merely go through the motions of fulfilling it. An elected official may recognize that she 5 Chapter 8: Accountability in a House of Mirrors owes her constituents an explanation of her behavior, so she makes a speech in which she presents ‘the state of the district’. If, however, the speech is superficial and says little about the most serious issues of the district, the official might be described as performing the ritual of accountability without really accounting. Particular norms and expectations vary with the context. Sometimes a justification is required only when there is a failure to behave in a particular way (e.g., failure to get work done, failure to comply with a law). Other times, periodic reporting on behavior is expected regardless of failure or lapses, as in the case of political campaigns being required to report quarterly on the donations they receive or a parolee being required to report to their parole officer on a monthly basis. What counts as an adequate explanation or defense also varies with context and may even vary over time as cultural concepts of human nature and social obligation change. For example, in the last century in the U.S. at least, ideas about what fathers owe their children have changed, that is, expectations about what fathers can be held accountable for in relation to their children have changed – informally as well as legally. We might say here that ‘accountability practices’ with regard to being a father have changed. Those who are obliged to account for their behavior and those who are owed an account may be individuals or collectivities (organizations, governments, companies). An employee may, for example, be expected to account to a particular supervisor for work not completed on time, and campaigns are required to report their donations to the 6 Chapter 8: Accountability in a House of Mirrors Federal Elections Commission (FEC). Also, multiple entities may be obliged to provide or owed an explanation/justification. In the case of the employee, an explanation may be owed to the company as well as the supervisor, and in the case of campaign finance, the FEC is the first recipient of campaign finance reports but the FEC posts the reports for viewing by the public, and this in turn results in innumerable recipients. That accountability practices are embedded in a context of norms and expectations is not inconsistent with the triad of accountability used in this volume, but the triad does not explicitly specify the role of norms. Norms are always at work but the extent to which and the ways in which they are shared varies in complicated ways. If we were looking for a theoretical ideal-type – a paradigm – of accountability, then the paradigm would be that watchers and watched share norms with regard to what kind of behavior had to be explained, when an explanation/justification is owed, and what counts as an appropriate or adequate explanation. These shared norms seem to be what makes accountability work. They allow us to evaluate whether a politician’s speech is superficial or if an employee’s work is incomplete or late. Despite the importance of shared norms, in many accountability practices, norms seem to be only vaguely understood. As well, watchers and watched may have different norms or may interpret the same norms differently. Watchers may not be aware that they are being held to account or how they are being held accountable, e.g., Secure Flight. Differences between the norms of the watched and the norms of the watchers are repeatedly illustrated in the case studies. 7 Chapter 8: Accountability in a House of Mirrors It would be a mistake to think that the ideal type of accountability, especially shared norms, has ever, or could ever, exist. Those who are accountable and those to whom they are accountable, i.e., those who owe explanations and those who are entitled to an explanation, generally share norms broadly, but there is typically variation in the interpretation of the norms. This is seen in examples referred to before. An elected official may acknowledge accountability to the public for behavior relevant to the position but have a different interpretation of relevance than segments of his or her constituency. An employee may recognize that her employer has a right to monitor her work but not a right to test for drugs. Norms change over time and some may recognize or embrace the change more quickly than others. So, it may be difficult to identify accountability practices in which all those involved share precisely the same understanding of the norms. The purpose of specifying an ideal type is not simply to look for instantiations. Rather the point is to use the paradigm as a backdrop against which to see variability in the understanding of norms. Of particular interest here is variation resulting from technological instrumentation. Accountability practices constituted in information technology and the Internet are different from those constituted in other material forms. The instrumentation constitutes (materializes) norms in particular ways and this affects the norms of an accountability practice. Norms may shift, may be obfuscated, may be newly interpreted, etc. Accountability is Sociotechnical 8 Chapter 8: Accountability in a House of Mirrors In the case studies in this volume, the house of mirrors metaphor is used to delineate the complexities of accountability practices when they are instrumented with information technologies. Those who view information technology and the Internet as inherently transparent might expect harmoniously shared norms in accountability practices that are instrumented with information technology. That is, if watchers and watched alike have access to the workings of a system – as, for example, with open source software when all users can see the source code – then both are more likely to understand the norms of the system. However, the case studies suggest otherwise. Whatever possibilities are afforded by information technology, hidden and secret norms are among the array, as are obfuscated and poorly articulated norms. In trying to understand the significance of the material, technological components of accountability practices, Bovens use of ‘forum’ (as the audience to whom an explanation/justification is owed) is quite telling. Accountability is, according to Bovens, “a relationship between an actor and a forum …”. ‘Forum’ conjures up an image of the ancient Roman forum, a public square of the city, a built environment in which people assemble, i.e., are physically present. Here a citizen would present an explanation/justification in the form of a speech to an assembled crowd. The material environment of the forum shapes the nature of accountability. An account presented to a physically present audience (the watchers) is shaped by the presence and composition of the audience. An oral presentation depends on the speaker’s voice and mastery of persuasive techniques, and, of course, the presenter’s ability to respond to the immediate feedback the audience may provide. 9 Chapter 8: Accountability in a House of Mirrors The image of the ancient Roman forum stands in stark contrast to modern forms of accountability. Contrast standing before a crowd to sending a report to the FEC with the report subsequently posted on the Web. Contrast a speech before a physically present audience to providing the required information to an airline representative when purchasing a ticket, and having an anonymous set of actors, behind the scenes, decide whether you are ‘cleared for travel’, or not. The materiality of accountability practices makes a difference, though, of course, materiality is only one among many elements that shape accountability practices. In the case studies, the house of mirrors metaphor helps to reveal how information technology and the Internet affect who is accountable to whom, that for which the watched can be held to account, and what consequences can be rendered. Campaigns and candidates have always been understood to be accountable to ‘the public’ but just what it means to be accountable to the public is a matter of practice; it is, at least in part, a matter of the materiality of practices. When campaign finance disclosure is constituted in information technology and the Web, new accountability relationships are created, both in the sense that campaigns and candidates are more immediately accountable to a broader array of watchers and also in the sense that donors come into view so they too can be scrutinized by an array of watchers. [We might think of this as comparable to expanding the size of the ancient forum to include all citizens and then putting a spotlight on those in the crowd to whom the explanation/defense refers.] 10 Chapter 8: Accountability in a House of Mirrors When accountability practices are materialized in information technology and the Internet, individuals and organizations can be held to account for types of behavior inconceivable without the technology. Information technology constitutes unique forms of information, new categories of behavior inconceivable without the technology and inaccessible even to the subjects themselves. Think here of clickstream, search inquiry histories, email traffic, online identities, etc.; these are new terms of accountability. And it is not just new types of information that come into play; individuals and organizations are classified into groups based on patterns of which they could not be aware. Data mining tools identify patterns and categories of behavior that are largely inaccessible without the tools. Individuals and organizations are classified and treated as members of groups that behave in certain ways, without their knowledge that they are members of such a group. This was most salient in the house of mirrors analysis of Google, but it is present in other cases. In Secure Flight, ARC, and CFD, subjects are classified based on their behavior fitting patterns of which the subjects may be entirely unaware. The materiality of accountability affects the norms of accountability in other ways as well. The architecture of a system may, for example, influence the norms by which individuals or organizations are held accountable. A subtle and intriguing example here is Facebook’s requirement that users designate their gender and that they designate it as male or female. In doing this, Facebook’s architecture reinforces the norm of gender as binary. One’s gender identity can only be one or the other, male or female; there are no other possibilities. In this respect, system architecture is far from neutral with regard to the norms of accountability. 11 Chapter 8: Accountability in a House of Mirrors Facebook also illustrates how the norms of peer-to peer accountability can be shaped not just by user profiles, but through connectivity and the availability of photos. For example, the norm with regard to binge drinking seems to be elevated and rendered acceptable by its glorification in photos. Peers see each other engaging in the activity; the photos suggest their bravado, etc.; and this validates binge drinking as a norm. Similarly, the value of international travel may be elevated as Facebook users post pictures from their trips and discuss their travel adventures in other countries. International travel becomes less exotic and more normalized. Be it binge drinking or international travel, the behavior is, in a sense, normalized in Facebook, so that peers may hold each other accountable for engaging (or failing to engage) in these activities. The material or technological component of accountability practices also affects what consequences can be rendered in the name of accountability. In the ancient forum, consequences in the form of cheers or jeers could be rendered as well as an array of other possible behavioral responses during the speech or afterwards, e.g., shunning, stoning. The case studies provide diverse examples of consequences rendered. In Secure Flight a traveler is either cleared for travel or not. In CFD elections are impacted, donors may be intimidated. In ARC, one is allowed to give blood or not. These consequences are afforded by information technology. Of course, travelers can be stopped, elections impacted, and blood donors rejected without information technology, but the materiality of practices makes a difference in what and how consequences are delivered. 12 Chapter 8: Accountability in a House of Mirrors When it comes to consequences, Google’s search engine is, perhaps, the most interesting case. Typically we think of accountability leading to negative or positive consequences – punishment/reward, praise/blame, exonerated/put in jail. Google does not render consequences of this kind exactly. Rather it delivers search results and advertisements. Whether or not this should even be considered accountability is a matter to be taken up in a moment. None of this is to say that information technology, the Web, and the Internet, are, in themselves, determinative of accountability practices. Information technology and the Internet are components in accountability practices and they shape the nature and workings of accountability practices but they are, as mentioned earlier, only one component in complex sociotechnical systems. Who is accountable to whom, what they are accountable for, and what consequences may be rendered are all affected by the materiality of accountability practices as well as other factors. House of Mirrors Accountability In trying to capture the problem with ‘pervasive personal data collection’, Solove (2001) argues that the Big Brother metaphor is misguided. He argues instead for Kafka’s The Trial as the appropriate metaphor. Here Solove implicitly suggests that surveillance is a form of accountability for a trial is a process through which actors are held accountable for seemingly illegal behavior; the defense is an explanation/ justification of the behavior at issue.2 Of course, in Kafka’s The Trial, the accused, Josef K, has a bizarre and 2 The defense may involve denying that the accused engaged in the behavior at issue or it may involve conceding that the accused engaged in the behavior and demonstrating that there were exculpatory reasons 13 Chapter 8: Accountability in a House of Mirrors enigmatic experience. He doesn’t know who is in charge of the process and what, if any, authority is behind it; he doesn’t know of what he is accused. Solove suggests, in effect, that we think of surveillance as a bizarre and fractured form of accountability – accountability without knowing to whom and for what you are accountable and without knowing what the consequences might be for failure to adequately account. The idea that surveillance is a fractured form of accountability is consistent with the house of mirrors metaphor and analyses. While The Trial metaphor illuminates the experience of data subjects, the house of mirrors metaphor describes the processes by which such experiences are produced. The case studies show that fractured and enigmatic accountability is produced by complex operations, operations in which information about data subjects is processed and transformed from an entry point to a rendering through information technology. Information is bounced, combined, highlighted, and shaded for varying purposes and with varying outcomes. Regardless of whether the watched are aware of data being collected, it is effectively impossible for them to understand how and where the data might move, how it may be combined and used, how they might be rendered, and what consequences will result. This seems fairly close to Josef K’s experience. Rendering in Secure Flight leads to certain travellers being prevented from boarding a plane, but the traveler stopped at the airport doesn’t know how the decision to stop her was made, what data was used to make the decision, and who – what agencies or for the behavior. In the former case the defense provides an explanation; in the latter case, the defense provides both an explanation and a justification. 14 Chapter 8: Accountability in a House of Mirrors individuals – was involved. When airline workers are unable to explain why the traveler has been targeted, the traveller’s experience is that of facing anonymous accusers in an opaque environment. A blood donor may be similarly puzzled when he arrives at a new site to give blood and is rejected; the donor has no idea that information revealed on the donor questionnaire many years earlier was stored and is now being used. The house of mirrors analyses show how individuals engage in seemingly simple acts, e.g., submitting a search term, donating to a campaign, buying an airline ticket, and later experience consequences that seem to come out of nowhere. In a world configured around information technology, the operations of accountability take place behind the scenes. Invisible processes produce results – consequences – that are inexplicable to the subject, and certainly not what the subject expected when they gave out the information or behaved in some way. A California citizen makes a donation to support the referendum against gay marriage, and several weeks after the vote on the referendum, the donor is harassed at his home by those who opposed the referendum. A Google user enters a search term and during the next several months, whatever search term she enters, she receives results and advertisements that she can’t quite understand. Accountability and Surveillance/Transparency The paradigm of accountability suggested above is that accountability is a relationship between an actor and a forum in which the actor has an obligation to explain and to justify his or her conduct. As mentioned earlier, the usefulness of the paradigm is not to differentiate between practices that are accountability and those that are not; rather, the 15 Chapter 8: Accountability in a House of Mirrors paradigm provides a basis – a set of elements – for examining the variation in accountability practices. None of the five case studies fits the paradigm neatly and cleanly; rather, each case study can be seen as a distinctive variation on the paradigm. Actor-Forum In all of the cases, we can identify an actor and a forum. In CFD, campaigns and candidates (the actors) account to the public (the forum) through the FEC. In Secure Flight, airline passengers are the actors and the TSA is the forum in which the passengers are held to account. In Google’s search engine operations, users are accountable to Google. In ARC potential blood donors are the actors and ARC is the forum, with ARC, in turn, accountable to the public. Although Facebook involves a complexity of actors and forums, users generally think of themselves as the actors and their friends as the forum. Importantly, the analysis of several of the cases revealed multiple audiences, with multiple accountabilities being constituted simultaneously. In CFD, although ‘the public’ is the forum, the public is a wide array of groups each with different interests including, but not limited to corruption deterrence – the ostensive purpose of CFD. And, in CFD, although campaigns and candidates are the primary actors, donors become actors held accountable in public forums. Secure Flight and Google seem to involve the most stable forums because information about the operation of these systems and about the actors is kept secret. Secrecy limits access to data and therefore restricts the forums in which actors can be held to account. In ARC, the forum also seems restricted because donor 16 Chapter 8: Accountability in a House of Mirrors data stays within ARC. However, the data moves (is accessible) internally from location to location, so this is a case of one forum with many sub-forums. As already mentioned, there are multiple forums in Facebook: friends, Google, advertisers, applications developers, etc. Users are accountable in different ways, i.e., by different criteria in relation to each of these forums. Obligation to Explain The obligatory aspect of accountability is revealing, especially when it comes to surveillance. Although ‘obligation’ often carries moral connotations, the obligations – if we can call them that – at issue in the case studies are not exactly moral; nor are they absolute or categorical. The pull on actors to explain their behavior, or let themselves be accounted for, is conditional and conventional. If you want to run for office, then you are obliged to report how you raise and expend funds. If you want to fly on an airplane, then you will have to allow the Secure Flight system to process information about you. If you want to give blood or use Google or Facebook, then you have to fill out the profile/questionnaire. And so on. To say that the obligations at issue are conventional is not, however, to say that they are always informal. In at least two of the cases, the obligation is specified in legislation. Indeed, the obligation to explain seems to be on firmer ground in government systems in which the obligation is somewhat formally specified. In CFD and Secure Flight, the obligation of actors to account for their behavior derives from legislation and falls within the authority of a government agency. In both cases, there are official documents and a 17 Chapter 8: Accountability in a House of Mirrors historical record describing the justification for the accountability practice. The public understands why campaigns and candidates are required to report on donations, and the public understands why the TSA surveils airline passengers. To be sure, citizens (candidates, travellers) can and do contest the way these systems operate. They question whether the FEC collects the best possible information for deterring corruption, or they question whether Secure Flight is effective at identifying terrorists. Nevertheless, citizens and travellers seem to accept the authority of the agencies at issue to do what they do, and in this respect, the actors involved recognize an obligation to comply and explain their behavior. Importantly, even in these two cases with formal authority, there is a difference in the nature of the obligation. In CFD there is an obligation to explain, i.e., to provide information about one’s activities, but in Secure Flight, there is, at best, an obligation to let information be collected about one’s activities. This goes back to the differences between transparency and surveillance. In transparency the actor accepts or acknowledges an obligation to explain; in the very act of explaining, the actor acknowledges the forum’s right to an explanation – its right to pass judgment. In surveillance, however, the actor doesn’t exactly act. Even when surveillance is done in a way that the watched know they are being watched, the language of obligation seems odd. Typically in surveillance practices, the watched feel the conditional nature of the situation, but they feel it more as a requirement than as an obligation. If one wants to give blood, one is required to fill out the questionnaire; if one wants to use the Google’s search engine, one must allow one’s behavior to be tracked. So, the nature of the pull on 18 Chapter 8: Accountability in a House of Mirrors actors to explain or allow their behavior to be accounted and the conditional character of expected behavior (i.e., what one must do if one wants the service) varies from case to case. Whether formal or informal, the conditional arrangement in each case study has evolved through unique historical, social, and political processes. For example, and by contrast, CFD has a rich legislative history leading to the current requirements, and Facebook has a history involving user protests that have shaped the way Facebook operates today. ARC is a quasi-governmental organization so some aspects of its mode of operation are specified formally, though it has a good deal of latitude in implementing the general requirements. In Google and Facebook, the nature of the actor’s obligation and the authority of the forum are less formal and therefore less stable. The right of both organizations to record, manipulate, and use information is legal, but they have not been legislated. Rather these arrangements have evolved. They have been worked out in the marketplace, but it is much too simplistic to presume that that is all there is to it for both companies have evolved in environments in which neither government nor the public understood the technologies involved, the nature of the operations, or the likely consequences of operating one way or another. Rather than saying that users recognize the ‘authority’ of these companies, it seems more accurate to say, as mentioned earlier, that users recognize the power of each company to require users (not to explain but) to let data about them be gathered and used, in order to get the service. They recognize the 19 Chapter 8: Accountability in a House of Mirrors power of Google and Facebook to conditionally require them to comply, in effect the power to say if you want the service, you must do … Google is an interesting case here. Remember Google doesn’t want its users to adjust to norms or do anything other than what naturally occurs to them when they engage in searches. Google isn’t interested in judging its users or doling out punishments and rewards, at least not in a moral sense. Of course, it does distribute special offers to some groups and not to others but it makes no (moral) judgment in doing so. We can’t say that Google has no interest in the way its users behave because it is very interested in knowing how users behave so that it can deliver search terms and advertising. Google has an interest in being able to predict its users’ behavior so that it can deliver advertisements that will lead to purchases, and in this activity. Thus, Google accounts for the behavior of its users and its users seem to accept this, though there is the issue raised in the case study as to how much users understand about the data being collected or how it is being used. Conclusion The obligatory element of accountability highlights the differences between surveillance and transparency. Surveillance appears to be accountability without an obligation to explain. Rather than obligatory, surveillance involves a requirement to be accounted for and often a requirement that must be fulfilled in order to get access to a service. It is as if, unbeknownst to one, one is brought forward for examination by a forum: the forum 20 Chapter 8: Accountability in a House of Mirrors draws conclusions and doles out consequences. Yet all of this happens without your knowledge. It happens – to use a term coined by Haggerty – to your electronic double. As explained at the beginning of this chapter, accountability practices are important for many reasons. Among other things, they shape how we understand ourselves and how we think about our lives. Accountability practices are embedded in many, if not all, domains of life and are importantly connected to our sense of what we are entitled to expect from others (individuals and organizations), and what they can require or expect of us. Many accountability practices are now being configured with information technology and the Internet, and the new configurations have consequences. The case studies are unambiguous in showing that accountability practices configured with information technology and the Internet are far from transparent, even when the practices are designed to create transparency. Using the house of mirrors metaphor, the five case studies suggest that accountability practices instrumented with information technology and the Internet can be constituted in ways that obscure and obfuscate the operative norms. In turn watchers and the watched can operate with very different norms and expectations, different from one another and different from the reality. Sometimes this results from secrecy but even in systems that make no claims to secrecy, much is hidden from users. The result is that accountability practices instrumented with information technology and the Internet can easily lead to systems of accountability that are experienced as bizarre, enigmatic, and fractured by those who are held to account. 21 Chapter 8: Accountability in a House of Mirrors Among other things, accountability in a house of mirrors undermines trust. Individuals and organizations trust when they have expectations and their expectations are met. That is, when expectations are met, individuals and organizations believe they can rely on the systems constituting their world. When expectations and experience conflict, trust is eroded. When citizens or system users are held to account but they have no way of accurately understanding that they are being held to account and by whom for what, they are rendered powerless. References Anderson, J. 2009. Illusions of Accountability Credit and Blame Sensemaking in Public Administration. Administrative Theory & Praxis Vol. 31, No. 3, pp. 322–339. Bovens, M. 2007. Analysing and Assessing Accountability: A Conceptual Framework. European Law Journal Vol. 13, No. 4, pp. 447-468. Conner, T.W. and T.M. Rabovsky. 2011. Accountability, Affordability, Access: A Review of the Recent Trends in Higher Education Policy Research Policy Studies Journal Special Issue: Public Policy Yearbook 2011 Volume 39, pages 93–112. Gunzenhauser, M.G. and A.M. Hyde 2007 What is the value of public school accountability? Educational Theory Volume 57, Issue 4, pp. 489–507. Kress, S., S. Zechmann, and J. M. Schmitten. 2011. When performance matters: the past, present, and future of consequential accountability in public education. Harvard Journal on Legislation Vol. 48, pp. 185-234. Martin, L.L. and K. Frahm. 2010. The changing nature of accountability in administrative practice. Journal of Sociology and Social Welfare Vol. 37, No. 1, pp. 137-148. Mulgan, R. 2000. ‘Accountability’: An Ever Expanding Concept. Public Administration Vol. 78, No. 3, pp. 555-573. Park, J. 2010. Responsible investing: challenges and opportunities for sustainable strategic management in the global context. International Journal of Sustainable Strategic Management Vol. 2, No. 3, pp. 274-283. 22 Chapter 8: Accountability in a House of Mirrors Solove, D.J. 2001. Privacy and power: Computer databases and metaphors for information privacy. Stanford Law Review Vol. 53, pp. 1393-1462. Winters, M. S. 2010. Accountability, Participation and Foreign Aid Effectiveness. International Studies Review Vol. 12, No. 2, pp. 218–243 23