An Analysis of the Aesthetic Theories of Immanuel Kant and Soetsu Yanagi in Relation to Contemporary Craft Anastasia Simmons ST09001162 ADC320 Contents Introduction 3 The Concept of the Aesthetic 5 Introduction to The Aesthetic Theories 9 - Immanuel Kant’s Critique of Judgment 9 - Soetsu Yanagi’s Unknown Craftsman 11 Analysis of the Theories 14 - Function 14 - Nature 16 - The Maker 18 The Relevance of the Aesthetic Theories in Craft Today 23 - Are Craftworks Aesthetic Objects? 23 - How can one capture a subtle juxtaposition between an aesthetic 24 approach and a functional one in one’s work? Conclusion 26 Bibliography 27 Cover Illustrations left: Immanual Kant. (http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Immanuel_Kant) right: Soetsu Yanagi. (http://lacepeacock.blogspot.com/2009/01/unknown-craftsman.html) 2 Introduction The promotion and celebration of craft as an alternative to industrial manufacture has brought numerous potentials into the field of design and decorative arts. This transformation began with the Arts and Crafts movement in the United Kingdom spreading to the United States, Europe and Japan. Such theories may have provided a “reactionary” response to industrial capitalism but also helped to focus attention on craft as a way of thinking across the spectrum of art and design. With its strong traditions of functionality, ornamentation and ceremony, craft has always reflected human skill but, in a highly technological society, we no longer need to prove our technological status through our craft. Craft’s function within the industrial world has changed; work is now created that demonstrates our humanity and unique sensibilities. Craft is now intentionally created to fulfil a dual-purpose; whilst makers still refer to historical forms, materials and techniques to often produce functional objects, at the same time they hope provide an aesthetic experience. It is this concept of the aesthetic experience that I wish to explore throughout this dissertation, in order to achieve a greater understanding of aesthetics to inform my own work. By looking at aesthetic theories, I also hope to explore the main questions such as; how best can we understand what an aesthetic value and/or experience is? Can craftworks be aesthetic objects? And if so, how can one capture a subtle juxtaposition between an aesthetic approach and a functional one approach in one’s work? Throughout this paper, I will analyse both Immanuel Kant’s and Soetsu Yanagi’s aesthetic philosophies, in relation to the aforementioned questions. Born in 1724, in Königsberg, East Prussia, Immanuel Kant is still one of the most central figures in modern philosophy. Kant brought together the ideas of rationalism and empiricism to establish and investigate the limits of human knowledge. His approach had an enormous impact on philosophy as well as the 3 fine arts and literature and still influences modern ideas. Kant provides a broader theory of aesthetics, referring to aesthetics regarding art, and therefore may introduce new aesthetic ideas otherwise unthought-of of in the craft world. In contrast, Yanagi provides a more focused theory on aesthetics of craft. Born in 1889, Soetsu Yanagi had a strong enthusiasm for Korean pottery, in particular Yi Dynasty wares, and was interested in the way that they had been made by nameless craftsman. Yanagi believed that there ought to be a similar sort of approach to the Korean pottery in craft and art in Japan. The Japanese Folk Craft Movement was predominantly focused upon Yanagi’s writings, although in the early days Yanagi appeared to be primarily concerned with beauty, his folk craft ideal was a combination of philosophical, religious and aesthetic elements. By comparing and contrasting these two theories I hope to outline an aesthetic for craft, which in turn will aid my own practice as a maker. 4 The Concept of the Aesthetic In order to best understand what an “aesthetic” is; I am going to look into the history behind the concept of the aesthetic and provide a brief explanation of the different schools of thought. In the late eighteenth century the concept of the aesthetic and the issue of beauty began to enter philosophical theories. Descending from the concept of taste, the term ‘aesthetic’ became to be used to designate a certain value in objects, judgments and experience. Many of these values, defining the concept of the aesthetic, have resulted from a development of the immediacy and disinterest theories descending from the concept of taste. Rationalism about beauty is the view that we judge things to be beautiful through reason; this reason may arise from deducing from principles or applying concepts. The immediacy theory arose to counter this rationalist theory of beauty, stating that judgments of beauty are not primarily judged through applying principles or concepts but rather arise through straightforward sensory judgments. In other words, we do not reason things to be beautiful, but rather “taste” that they are. The theory of disinterest is presented to counter the theory of “egoism about virtue”, the view that we take pleasure in and judge an object purely because it serves an interest to the onlooker. The disinterest school of thought, therefore, states that the pleasure we take in an object is not self-interested; we judge objects to be beautiful whether or not the object serves an interest to ourselves. However, it is important to note that disinterestedness does not mean that the viewer is detached or unconcerned with whether looking at an object provides them with delight or not, it just means that their pleasure cannot be reduced to any sensual, practical or theoretical interest. 5 Aesthetic Objects Both the immediacy and disinterest theories of taste discuss whether the artistically relevant properties of an artwork are just formal, where formal properties are regarded as properties understandable by sight or by hearing. The immediacy theory implies that such qualities are formal, stating that there is ‘artistic irrelevance of all properties whose grasping requires the use of reason’ 1. In contrast, the disinterest theory implies that such qualities are also formal but states that there are so through an ‘artistic irrelevance of all properties capable of practical import’2. Aesthetic Judgment Since the eighteenth century, the main debate over the judgment of an aesthetic object is related to the immediacy theory; whether we judge objects to be beautiful by simply applying principles of beauty to them. After much debate, the term ‘aesthetic judgment’ has recently become re-defined and now refers to any judgment in which ‘an aesthetic property is predicated of an object’3. However, some philosophers have issues with the application of this definition, as it requires being able to say, without being directly clear, what an aesthetic property is. Perhaps, a better definition of an aesthetic judgment refers to ‘any judgment in which any property of the class exemplified by beauty is predicted of an object’4. Aesthetic Experience The theories relating to aesthetic experience can be placed into two groups according to the features that are referred to in the explanation of what makes the aesthetic experience; internalist and externalist. The internalist theories refer to features that are internal to experience, characteristically with a more phenomenological approach. According to Monroe Beardsley’s theory of 1James Shelly, ‘The Concept of the Aesthetic’, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2009 http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2009/entries/aesthetic-concept/ (date assessed 05/12/2011) 2 Ibid. 3Ibid. 4Ibid. 6 internalism, all aesthetic experiences have four features in common; focus5, intensity, coherence6 and completeness7. In contrast, the externalist theories refer to the external features that make such experience, how one experiences the features of an object. Beauty Aesthetics is defined as ‘a set of principles concerned with the nature and appreciation of beauty’ in the Oxford dictionary. It is therefore important to define beauty. There are two main opposing traditional judgments of beauty, rationalist and empiricist. At the beginning of the eighteenth century the rationalist view of beauty was the most popular opinion in Europe. A rationalist view of beauty argues that judgments of beauty are judgments of reason; judgment consists in the ‘cognition of an object as having an objective property’8. James Shelley demonstrates this point, writing that in order for a judgment of beauty to occur within an object: Much reasoning should precede, that nice distinctions be made, just conclusions drawn, distant comparisons formed, complicated relations examined and general facts fixed and ascertained. Some species of beauty, especially the natural kinds, on their first appearance command our affection and approbation; and where they fail of this effect, it is impossible for any reasoning to redress their influence, or adapt them better to our taste and sentiment. But in many orders of beauty, particularly those of the fine arts, it is ‘an aesthetic experience is one in which attention is firmly fixed upon [its object]’ Ibid. ‘one thing leads to another; continuity of development, without gaps or dead spaces, a sense of overall providential pattern of guidance, an orderly cumulation of energy toward a climax, are present to an unusual degree’ Ibid. 7 ‘the impulses and expectations aroused by elements within the experience are felt to be counterbalanced or resolved by other elements within the experience, so that some degree of equilibrium or finality is achieved and enjoyed. The experience detaches itself, and even insulates itself, from the intrusion of alien elements’ Ibid. 8HannahGinsborg, ‘Kant’s Aesthetics and Teleology’, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2005 http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kant-aesthetics/ (date assessed 05/12/2011) 5 6 7 requisite to employ much reasoning, in order to feel the proper sentiment.9 The empiricist theory of taste, which mainly British philosophers worked with, was developed in juxtaposition to the rationalist theory of beauty. The fundamental idea behind this theory is that judgments of beauty are an expression of feeling without cognitive content and have the immediacy of straightforward sensory judgments. An early expression of the ideologies of the theory is that of Jean-Baptiste Dubo’s Critical Reflections on Poetry, Painting and Music: Do we ever, in order to know whether a ragoo be good or bad; and has it ever entered into any body’s head, after having settled the geometrical principles of taste, and defined the qualities of each ingredient that enters into the composition of those messes, to examine into the proportion observed in their mixture, in order to decide whether it be good or bad? No, this is never practiced. We have a sense given us by nature to distinguish whether the cook acted according to the rules of his art. People taste the ragoo, and tho’ unacquainted with those rules, they are able to tell whether it be good or no. The same may be said in some respect of the productions of the mind, and of picture made to please and move us.10 Having provided a brief history and introductions to the theories behind the concept of the aesthetic, I am now going to proceed to introduce and analyse Kant’s Critique of Judgment and Yanagi’s Unknown Craftsman. 9James Shelly, ‘The Concept of the Aesthetic’, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2009 http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2009/entries/aesthetic-concept/ (date assessed 05/12/2011) 10Ibid. 8 Introduction to the Aesthetic Theories Immanuel Kant’s Critique of Judgment Kant established the main outlines to the theory of aesthetics as it is known today with the publication of his Critique of Judgment in 1790. His fundamental aim primarily was to analyse how natural beauty is perceived, but his theories also raised questions relating to aesthetics in art. Kant regarded an aesthetic judgment to be based upon feeling, in particularly the feeling of pleasure or displeasure. According to Kant, there are three types of aesthetic judgment; judgments of the agreeable, judgments of beauty and judgments of the sublime. The most distinctive and relevant part of Kant’s theory to this dissertation is his judgments of beauty, although when he refers to nature he discusses the idea of judgments of the sublime. At the beginning of the Critique of Judgment, Kant discusses four particular unique features of aesthetic judgments on the beautiful in the ‘Analytic of the Beautiful’. Calling them ‘moments’, he tries to capture what is characteristic of judgments of beauty. He presents the moments in terms of four logical functions of judgment, exploring the judgment of taste in terms of quality, quantity, relation and modality. In the first moment Kant writes about a judgment of beauty being based upon a feeling, most particularly the feeling of pleasure. This pleasure is of a disinterested nature, meaning that it does not depend on one having a desire for the object, nor does it generate such a desire. Kant claims that an aesthetic judgment must concern itself only with form (shape, arrangement…) in the object, not sensible content (color, tone…), this is because the sensible has a connection to the agreeable and thus to interest. By considering objects in such a manner, judgments of beauty become based upon feeling rather than ‘objective sensation’ and it distinguishes them from cognitive judgments based on perception. 9 The second moment discusses the “universality” or “universal validity” of judgments of beauty. In making a judgment of beauty about an object one believes that others regard the object in a similar nature; one only perceives an object as beautiful if everyone also perceives it in the same manner and shares one’s pleasure in it. Kant however writes that this universality is not ‘based on concepts’11 and that judgments of beauty cannot be proved; there are no guidelines by which to judge beauty. Throughout the second moment, Kant’s philosophies contradict the contemporary cliché of ‘beauty is in the eye of the beholder’; Kant argues that such a belief cannot account for our experience of beauty itself and it cannot account for the social behavior of our claims about what we find beautiful. The third moment introduces the problem of purpose and purposiveness. Kant discusses that judgments of the beautiful do not presuppose an end or purpose that the object is taken to satisfy. He describes purposiveness as being perceived both in the object itself and in the activity of imagination and understanding in their engagement with the object. In the fourth moment, Kant continues to show that aesthetic judgments involve the idea of necessity. Kant writes that objects must pass the test of being ‘necessary’ or ‘universally valid’, which effectively means that everyone who perceives this object in front of me will share my pleasure in it and agree with my judgment of it. However, this concept of the universally valid is not based on a concept or rules but rather it is ‘exemplary’, suggesting that one’s judgment itself serves as an example of how everyone ought to judge an object. The four moments can be placed into a dichotomy of two opposing sets of features. On the one hand, judgments of beauty are based on feeling and they do not depend on considering the object under a concept, the first and the third moment fall into this category. In contrast the second and fourth moment deal with universality and necessity, suggesting that they conform to objective cognitive judgments. Kant believed that alone the moments do not provide 11 Immanuel Kant, Critique of Judgment, United States, Oxford University Press Inc., 2007. p. 50 10 strong enough conditions for an aesthetic judgment, but when presented together, working on these two different levels he believed that they created an aesthetic experience separate from other modes of experience. In claiming that judgments of beauty were both based on feeling and make claim to universal validity, Kant created an aesthetic which reacted against the two main opposing traditional theories - empiricist and rationalist. However, Kant’s insistence with this progressive theory presented him with the problem of merging the two features of the argument. As Kant writes: “how is a judgment possible which, merely from one’s own feeling of pleasure in an object, independent of its concept, judges this pleasure as attached to the representation of the same object in every other subject, and so a priori i.e without having to wait for the assent of others”12. In order to answer his own question, Kant argues that pleasure in the beautiful depends on “free play” or “free harmony”. Kant believes that aesthetic cognition does not have a ‘determinate’ concept that pins down an intuition of what is beautiful; instead intuition is allowed some “free play”. In Kant’s terms, free play therefore expresses “lawfulness without a law”. Soetsu Yanagi’s Unknown Craftsman The ideologies of the Mingei movement, lead by Soetsu Yanagi, flourished in the late 1920s, around 40 years after the Arts and Crafts movement, it was almost equivalent to, and in many aspects directly inspired by, these western parallels. The Unknown Craftsman is an extensive selection of writings by Yanagi and translated by Bernard Leach. Its underlying aim was to preserve and revitalise the Japanese rural folk crafts and through them help establish the Mingei movement as an aesthetic in modern crafts. Yanagi’s folk craft ideal was based upon a combination of philosophical, religious and aesthetic foundations, initially though, his opinions were predominantly concerned with the concept of beauty. Yanagi’s idea of ‘beauty’ was found in everyday objects, often ‘made by a poor 12HannahGinsborg, ‘Kant’s Aesthetics and Teleology’, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2005 http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kant-aesthetics/ (date assessed 05/12/2011) 11 man; used carelessly by its owner; bought without pride’13. These utensils had not been made by famous artists, but were the work of an ‘unknown craftsman’, creating cheaply and in quantity giving them a ‘free’ and ‘healthy’ beauty. Originally Yanagi used the term ‘getemoto’ to describe such common items, a word used at time by the stall operators in the markets meaning ‘vulgar thing’. However, it was picked up by journalists and critics and sometimes connected with the concept of 'vulgarity '. In order to over come this misunderstanding, Yanagi had to come up with a new term for the ‘people’s art’. In 1925, after considerable discussion between Yanagi and two potter friends, Shoji Hamada and Kawai Kanjiro, the phrase that was created to describe the craftsman's work was ‘mingei’. This was a hybrid term, formed from ‘minshu’, meaning 'common people', and ‘kogei’, 'craft '. Yanagi himself emphasized himself that he did not intend to start an ‘art movement’, he did not began with a preconceived theory of art. Instead the Mingei theory was developed through Yangi’s personal experience in ‘just looking’ at crafts without regard to any aesthetic ideals. He called this experience of looking at such objects, ‘direct perception’, which he referred to as the ‘selfless footrule’ and by which to determine beauty. He writes: ‘When you look at things, your eyes can be clouded by knowledge, by habit or by the wish to assert yourself. But this is not the way to look at things. There should be nothing coming between the person who is seeing and the thing that is seen. A thing should be seen for what it is. This is 'direct perception' - just seeing things. You enter into the thing; the thing communicates with your heart. When the two become one, you have direct perception. To know about something, without seeing it directly gives rise to pointless judgment.’14 Yanagi believed direct perception was ‘beyond the self’ and therefore provided an opportunity to see crafts without subjectivity and prejudices. In his observation of Japanese Folk Craft he aimed to put aside all concepts of what constituted beauty and allowing an object to be seen for what it was and to speak for itself. Yanagi argued this was a type of aesthetic appreciation that was 13Soetsu Yanagi,The Unknown Craftsman, London, George Allen &Unwin Ltd., 1972, p. 223 14Ibid. 12 accessible to anyone and through direct perception all can recognize the ‘good’ and ‘beautiful’. 13 Analysis of the Theories Both Kant’s and Yanagi’s theories refer to a large range of different subjects and within the bounds of this dissertation it would be impossible to analyse all of it. Instead I am going to focus on three subjects: function, nature and the maker. These three subjects will be the most relevant in order to try to establish an aesthetic theory for contemporary craft. Function Kant and Yanagi hold opposing opinions on the aesthetic of functional objects. Kant shifted the meaning of the aesthetic towards a ‘transcendental study of objective preconditions of judgments of taste concerning the beautiful’15 leading to an ideology stating that an aesthetic object was one whose primary function was to produce an aesthetic experience of beauty without regard to practical use. As Kant writes, ‘beauty is the form of purposiveness in an object so far as this form is perceived in it without the concept of a purpose’16. Unfortunately, his arguments have become so ensconced in some people’s thinking that a functional object cannot be judged aesthetic or expressive but only ‘right or consistent’17, this way of thinking has helped formalise the separation between function and art. In contrast, Yanagi believed in a strong concept of beauty deriving from function. The main principle of Yanagi’s aesthetic of craftsmanship is where ‘beauty and use are perfectly equated’18. Yanagi argued that beauty came from the use of the utilitarian objects of the folk crafts; apart from use he felt that there was no beauty in craft, writing, ‘things made that do not stand up to use or that ignore utility can barely be expected to contain this kind of beauty’ 19. The ‘use’ Yanagi writes about is not just in the materialistic sense, he believed it had to embrace both mind and matter. Objects are to be both touched and looked at with the responsive feeling of pleasure. Arguing that, if an object was only judged on a Howard Risatti, A Theory of Craft, United States, The University of North Carolina Press, 2007. p. 72 16Ibid. p. 216 17Ibid. p. 219 18 Yanagi, The Unknown Craftsman, p. 212 19Ibid. p. 197 15 14 utilitarian point of view, then pattern, for example, is uncalled for. But Yanagi felt that ‘good pattern adds to the function of that utensil’20, in that, if an object was to completely satisfy on the utilitarian aspects but causes a feeling of ugliness, it detracts from total service. The special beauty of crafts, Yanagi considered, was the beauty of intimacy with the object through use. Writing that ‘people hang their pictures up on walls, but they place their objects for everyday use close to them and take them in their hands’21. It is only through interaction with the object that you can gain a greater sense of the object’s beauty and therefore, Yanagi continues to argue throughout the Unknown Craftsman, that it is important that things that work and serve us from day to day are not things kept in a glass case merely to be looked at. Kant seemed to envisage the demands of function as so all-encompassing that no space is left for the free play of the maker’s imagination: the maker is simply unable to manipulate the object’s form for ends other than function. Kant believes that there is no option for aesthetic expression in the production of functional objects whereas with works of fine art, complete freedom of imagination is offered to the maker. In fine art there are no formal or material limitations to the artist therefore the maker is offered complete aesthetic freedom. Again, Yanagi contradicts this opinion, seeing the ultimate aim of craft ‘not [as] expression of the self but to see true beauty’22, Yanagi felt that the production of folk-craft in comparison to artist-craft was the right direction into achieving this true beauty, he writes that, ‘utility does not permit unsoundness or frailty’23. Kant believed that function demands a faithfulness in objects that does not condone human self-indulgence. When making a functional object, Yanagi believed, the folk-craftsman does not push himself to the foreground thus selfassertion and error are reduced to a minimum, making functional objects 20Ibid. 21Ibid. p. 198 p. 202 23Ibid. p.143 22Ibid. 15 beautiful. Without self surrender, Yanagi believed that there would be an intrusion of the craftsman's 'self' into his work which would in turn lead to high prices, 'artification' and an emphasis on decoration rather than on function. Nature It is when referring to nature that Kant’s and Yanagi’s theories are most profoundly different. Kant refers mostly to nature within the notion of the sublime; the sublime is the name Kant gives to what is ‘absolutely great’24. Kant distinguishes two notions of the sublime, the mathematically sublime and the dynamically sublime. In both notions, the experience of the sublime consists of a feeling of the superiority of our own power of reason over nature. However, Kant’s theory of the sublime is a very comprehensive concept and I believe that his theory of the aesthetic experience of nature is not as relevant as his theory of the aesthetic judgment of nature. Within his aesthetic judgment of nature, although it is much shorter than his aesthetic experience of nature, he refers more to the relationship between art and nature; which is of greater relevance to establishing an aesthetic for contemporary craft and provides more of a comparison with Yanagi’s theory. Kant felt that when dealing with aesthetic judgments of both beauty of art and nature, we make the common assertion that ‘this is beautiful which pleases in the mere judging of it (not in sensation or by means of a concept)’25. He implies that beauty from nature arises from an objective purposiveness on the part of nature, rather than a subjective purposiveness that rests on ones play of the imagination in nature’s freedom. Where Kant felt ‘it is we who receive nature with favour, and not nature that does us a favour’26. He believes that this principle of the ideality of purposiveness is even more apparent in fine art and it is the lack of ‘aesthetic realism of purposiveness’27 that makes art beautiful instead of merely agreeable, similarly to the beautiful in nature. 24Kant, Critique of Judgment, p. 78 p. 136 26Ibid. p. 137 27Ibid. p. 178 25Ibid. 16 Yanagi frequently writes about ‘nature’ throughout the Unknown Craftsman, believing that all craftwork should be ‘focused on nature’ and that beauty can only be born of the natural in the unconscious man. Initially it appears he is referring to the environment, believing that ‘material provided by nature is nearly always best’28, Yanagi felt that crafts are best born near to where the necessary raw materials can be found, stating that the ‘closer to nature, the safer we are’29. Yanagi preferred the unspolit character of raw materials believing that they were richer than the man made. However, Yanagi's concept of 'nature' in fact included two meanings: one referred to the environment, the other to the inner self. When discussing the inner self, Yanagi directly links nature, beauty and selflessness, and it is this thought that differs most fundamentally from Kant’s theory and shows close affinity to Buddhist ideas. Beauty, to Yanagi, was born through nature, in the unconscious man. Thus a craftsman had to leave nature to do the creating; by surrendering his self to nature he could attain a ‘pure land of beauty’. No craftsman had within himself the power to create beauty; the beauty that came from 'self surrender' was incomparably greater than that of any work of art produced by 'individual genius'. Yanagi frequently refers to getemono objects, objects that are ‘representations of nature itself’30. These objects are created with “no-thought” and therefore are likely to satisfy the highest developed perception of beauty. Because the works derive from nature, they may look rough and primitive, yet, Yanagi believed they contain an honest, simple, humble beauty. In contrast to getemono objects, Yanagi writes about products that are made in the “realm of thought”, a process in which he believed nature is destroyed and the objects created ‘run towards opulent display and drown in individualism’31. The idea of creating objects that are representations of nature itself opposes Kant’s opinion that a product of art must be recognised as art and not as nature. 28 Yanagi,The Unknown Craftsman, p.215 29Ibid. 30Ibid. p. 214 31Ibid. 17 Kant writes that, ‘nature proved beautiful when it wore the appearance of art; and art can only be termed beautiful, where we are conscious of its being art’32, however he does also contradict his own opinion, believing that ‘purposiveness in [an objects] form must appear just as free from the constraint of arbitrary rules as if it were a product of mere nature’33. Kant mostly saw the beautiful in nature as a question of the form of the object and links this with the development of the aesthetics of art rather than purely making objects that are representations of nature itself. He writes that plants and animal formations are ‘unnecessary for the discharge of any function on their part, but chosen as it were with an eye to our taste’34 believing that they had been designed entirely with the view to outward appearance using an example of the harmony and variety of colours in pheasants and insects to back up his argument. The Maker Throughout the two theories there are similarities between Yanagi and Kant as to what a maker should pursue. Both refer, in parts, to the maker as a genius. Kant writes that genius ‘is the talent (natural endowment) which gives the rule to art’35 and that it is the innate mental aptitude in the maker through which art is created, this talent, Kant believes, belongs itself to nature. Yanagi also saw role of artist as not only as a ‘proper appreciator of beauty, [but] also its creator, and, in a word a genius’36. Yanagi believed that a large number of conscientious individual artists in the handcrafts are especially needed. The role of these individual artists is to protect beauty, believing that ‘our life would be abominable if we had no artists in this world’37. However, although they both see the maker as a genius, their concepts of the maker are still fundamentally different. Kant idolises his idea of the genius, 32Kant, Critique of Judgment, p. 135 33Ibid. 34Ibid. p. 175 35Ibid. p. 136 36Yanagi,The Unknown Craftsman, p. 218 37Ibid. 18 believing that originality of talent is an essential factor that goes into make up the character of the genius. Writing, ‘genius is a talent for producing for which no definite rule can be given’38, Kant suggests that the skill of the genius cannot be learnt and originality of products is its primary property. He continues to say that products, of the genius, must be ‘exemplary; and, consequently, though not themselves derived from imitation, they must serve that purpose for others’39. Yanagi doesn’t hold his genius in such high regard, he felt that ‘the artist has been kept locked up in his ivory tower of individualism and is out of touch with the people’40 and that artist craftsman’s products are ‘so few and expensive’41. However he did see the importance of the genius, believing that it was only though the work of the artist craftsman, or genius, that there could be a possibility of the return of craftsmanship. Believing that the ultimate aim of craft is not of ‘expression of the self but to see true beauty’42, Yanagi held little regard for the artist or artist-craftsman and instead held a greater value for the craftsman. He felt that it was cold comfort to confine beauty in the hands of a few artists; rather the ‘people’s art’ should be created through the unlettered craftsman by the theoretical concept of 'self surrender'. It was only through this concept and 'direct perception' that Yanagi felt that beauty could be understood and created by anyone in Japanese society, regardless of his or her rank or education. Yanagi uses an example of Sung pottery to support his idea that the greatest crafts are born of the nameless masses and that work of the individual artist will not stand the time. Writing, ‘when others admire the Sung pot, they wish to be makers of similar beautiful wares. Yet everyone knows that Sung pottery is without signatures’43. Yanagi believed that one of the essential causes of these pots’ beauty was in their autonomy; he felt that the objects themselves are 38Kant, Critique of Judgment, p. 137 39Ibid. 40Yanagi,The Unknown Craftsman, p. 204 41Ibid. p. 203 42Ibid. p. 202 43Ibid. p. 223 19 ‘better assurance than any signature could give’44. Yanagi therefore frequently writes that work should not bear the signature of its maker, as when the work has developed properly, Yanagi felt that ‘[one] need not worry about recognition by others … naturally his work will not need his signature’45. He felt that placing a signature on work was wrong and showed a sign of attachment with the work, illustrating that the craftsman is too self-conscious. There is also a difference in both Kant’s and Yanagi’s ideas about the state in which a maker creates. Kant believed that a genius ‘cannot indicate scientifically how it brings about its product’46; they won’t necessarily know how the ideas have entered into his head. Kant believes that such a talent is ‘bestowed upon a human being at birth’47 and it’s through this talent that original ideas are obtained. Whereas, Yanagi believed that, only when the maker has become the work itself and creates the work, does ‘true work become possible’48. In other words, the maker must stop being self-consciousness and become one with the work in a state of fusokufuri49. The Buddhist idea of beauty strongly influenced the ideologies behind the Mingei movement leading to many of the values of Yanagi’s craftsman. According to Buddhism and Yanagi such phrases as “I am now painting a picture” or “I am now weaving a cloth”, ‘express a dualistic relationship from which no true picture or cloth can result’50 instead, the word “I” must be removed from such phrases until the stage where “picture draws picture” or “cloth weaves cloth”. In contrast to the genius, Kant refers to the “block-head”, a maker who can never do more than merely learn and follow a lead. The work produced by a blockhead is never greater than what could have been learned and it never breaks free from 44Ibid. 45Ibid. p. 222 Critique of Judgment, p. 137 46Kant, 47Ibid. 48Yanagi,The Unknown Craftsman, p. 146 English: “unattached and detached”. 50Yanagi,The Unknown Craftsman, p. 145 49in 20 the ‘natural path of investigation and reflection according to rules’ 51, suggesting that Kant perhaps has little regard for the learning of a skill. Kant’s theory of the “block-head” opposes much of Yanagi’s philosophy in terms of the maker. Throughout his theory, Yanagi holds a high regard for traditional manual work, and although tradition is dying out, he felt ‘it is necessary for individual artists to work in place of the tradition… [in order to] … prepare the way to make a new tradition’52. He thought that this new tradition was best conceived through a base of a good technical grounding, which would enable the true character of the unknown craftsman to shine and ‘beautiful unsigned goods are produced’53. Kant, however, does proceed to write that in ‘all free arts something of a compulsory character is still required, or, as it is called, a mechanism, without which the spirit, which in art must be free, and which alone gives life to work, would be bodiless and evanescent’54, suggesting that, in part, he does see the validity of a traditional, focused approach to making, much like Yanagi. This is also supported by Kant’s statement that a ‘genius can do no more than furnish rich material for products of fine art; its elaboration and its form require a talent academically trained, so that it may employed in such away as to stand the test of judgment’55. Yanagi also writes about the maker in relation to industrialization, machine production and profit. These are all subjects that Kant excludes in his Critique of Judgment, however they are still vital in understanding in order to try to establish an aesthetic for contemporary craft. Yanagi refers to the intense co-operation needed between individual artists and industrialists of machine production. Yanagi believed that machines, in themselves, are not bad but thought it is a disaster when they are used to an excess, in a completely mechanised age. Writing that ‘where mechanisation can 51Kant, Critique of Judgment, p.136 52Yanagi,The Unknown Craftsman, p. 220 53Ibid. p. 223 54Kant, 55Ibid. Critique of Judgment, p. 134 p. 139 21 dovetail with handwork it is of obvious benefit to man, but where it destroys the values in the work of the human hand it is down right stupid’56. Yanagi urges that craftsmen don’t become enslaved to the machine, but rather use them freely so that the machine doesn’t become master and man, slave. He felt that the best way to utilise the machine was in moderation, using power in the preparatory stages and hand in the finishing. In this order, the objects produced could still naturally accord to his concept of beauty and in prevents the handwork being ‘too wasteful’57, in reference to preparation, and the ‘machine finish [being] too destructive of quality’58 in the final product. Yanagi further argued about the close connection between incentive for profit and the quality of work produced under a capitalist system of wage labour relations, writing; ‘a craftsman had to feel love for his work and this is impossible when he made things merely for sale’59. He felt that a greed for profit is destructive of both use and beauty, ‘love of profit robs a work of its beauty’ 60. Yanagi’s strong opinions that folk crafts should never be made for anything other than use, lead to his belief that a craftsman’s product should be inexpensive and free from the ailments arising from ‘artfulness’ due to the repeated practice in their technique from being produced in quantity. In order to achieve this, Yanagi felt we had to develop a non-capitalist society that could recognize truth and beauty and, as for the craftsman, they should continue to make beautiful goods that are ‘used as a matter of course in daily life’61. 56Yanagi,The 57Ibid. Unknown Craftsman, p. 207 p. 206 58Ibid. 59Ibid. 60Ibid. 61Ibid. p. 223 22 The Relevance of the Aesthetic Theories in Craft Today Are contemporary craftworks aesthetic objects? Traditional aesthetics, such those developed by Kant, are primarily a philosophy of fine art, and although craft is now closely linked with fine art, these writers main concerns are with painting, poetry and music. Although contemporary craft can now be defined as a type of art, it is fundamentally different to other types of art; it has a closer link with history, materials, technique and function and therefore, undoubtedly, it has a different value of aesthetics. Contemporary art often depends heavily on aesthetics whereas contemporary craft is separate from this and often depends on a much more subtle type of expression and aesthetic. The overriding feature of most contemporary craft objects is in regard to their function, so when viewing a craft object they are often identified and judged in a cognitive and instrumental manner, which is to say, as Kant writes by their function and how well they carry out their function. However, the works of a contemporary craftsman also go beyond the making of a strict utilitarian object, in such objects, function shouldn’t determine the object. Our response to functional objects is not solely objective and therefore our response can also be subjective and relate to Kant’s judgments of taste. When regarding the aesthetic qualities of a craft’s object, it is important to separate them from its function, as the judgments of how well a function may be carried out by an object should be separate from the physical object itself. Howard Risatti in his Theory of Craft supports the idea that contemporary craft objects have both objective, functional, and subjective, aesthetic, features. He uses an example of three chairs to illustrate that all craft objects are not deterministic62 and therefore have qualities of expression: Deterministic objects according to Risatti are ‘objects 100 percent determined in their physical characteristics by the demands of function’ Risatti,A Theory of Craft, p. 220 62 23 Consider three identical chairs. If someone paints one of these chairs yellow and the other red, are they any less functional than the unpainted chair? And could we say that the yellow chair is more or less functional than the red chair? One may prefer the unpainted chair over wither of the painted chairs, but this is a matter of personal preference, of subjective judgments of taste, not a quantitative and objective judgment of “right or consistent” performative function.63 In this statement, Risatti claims that colour is autonomous, subjective and expressive. However, it is not just colour that is autonomous, subjective and expressive and his theory can be applied to other qualities of expression such as mark making. Although functional objects will often have the same traits and constraints, such as a teapot will always have a spout, body and lid, it is important that makers are expressive with in these limitations, as this is what creates the understated aesthetic within craft. If this theory is applied to contemporary craft, a better way to judge functional items is not just by its functionality, but by whether or not it allows the maker complete freedom to manipulate its form within the free play of the imagination. How can one capture a subtle juxtaposition between an aesthetic and functional approach in one’s work? Having studied both Kant’s and Yanagi’s theories in depth, I have explored some areas which I believe enables a contemporary craftsman to create an aesthetic in their work, whilst maintaining a functional approach. I feel that in order for aesthetic qualities to exist within a functional object, the object’s formal demands must be such that they allow for manipulation on the part of the maker in the name of expression and the maker must intentionally exploit this allowance for expression. The objects created don’t necessarily have 63Risatti, 63Kant, A Theory of Craft, p. 226 Critique of Judgment, p. 133 24 to blatantly express something; a subtler, more subjective expression is as equally as valid. In order for the allowance of this manipulation, craft’s dependence on manual skill, materiality and technical knowledge are not problems to overcome but principles to be examined and put into use, in order to aid the creative process. The cotemporary craft maker should no longer feel tied to one material or making process, but instead feel free to experiment with a choice of materials, techniques and forms, in a state of Kant’s “free-play”. Being provided with this freedom, I believe will allow the maker a chance to further their technical, material and formal knowledge, leading in turn to the possibility of further creativity and a greater development of the maker’s sense of being. Yanagi’s notion of developing an anti-capitalist society in order to aid with the production of beautiful and useful objects is an extreme view and highly unlikely scenario in a modern society. However, I believe, in parts, it is a valid point; without the worry of money and profit it would be considerably easier for a maker to enter a sense of Kantian free-play, enabling new and otherwise undiscovered qualities to emerge in their work. Therefore, I feel, it is vital for craftsmen to allow themselves a period of experimentation and play alongside their everyday work, as it can only aid and deepen their underlying principles of making. However, whilst I believe it is important to apply these points to one’s making philosophy in order to create an aesthetic in craft works, it is vital to understand that an aesthetic of craft will always be separate from an aesthetic of contemporary art. A craftsman should always acknowledge this. It is important to understand and respect the fact that craft objects celebrate our ancient human relationship to formed matter, delving into historical techniques and materials that reflect human forms of living that originated in prehistory. Creating an aesthetic in craft, though has much in common with creating an aesthetic in other types of art, must take this into consideration. 25 Conclusion Through analyzing both Kant’s and Yanagi’s theories I have not only gained a deeper knowledge of concept of the aesthetic but it has also led to a development of a greater value in my own practice and a heightened awareness of how to achieve expressive qualities in my work. I have discovered that by combining the two philosophies, a juxtaposition of skill and expression can be created; I have learnt that it is not only through mastering the technique of throwing that I can achieve a more spontaneous and creative approach to making but also I have realised that free-play can play a vital part in the aesthetic development of my work. It is only though this combination of the two philosophies that I will be able to create a more subjective expression, that I believe is required in contemporary work. In order to develop my philosophy behind my own practice further and gain a deeper understanding of contemporary aesthetics of craft I aim to read, in more detail, Howard Risatti’s A Theory of Craft and Richard Sennett’s The Craftsman. This would not only help in understanding and valuing contemporary craft in relation to art, but also help further articulate an aesthetic role for craft in contemporary society. As a result of my exploration of the themes of my dissertation I aim to further my study by looking at aesthetics in relation to phenomenology. Phenomenology is the study of the conscious experience and by researching it in relation to aesthetics it would help to understand the conditions for the content of conscious experiences of aesthetic objects in relation to judgment and experience. 26 Bibliography COHAN, Ted, and GUYER, Paul, Essays in Kant’s Aesthetics, United States, The University of Chicago Press, 1982 CORSE, Sandra, Craft Objects, Aesthetic Contexts, United States, University Press of America, 2009 DORMER, Peter, ‘The Culture of Craft: Status and Future’, The Design Journal, vol I, Manchester University Press, 1997 GINSBORG, Hannah, ‘Kant’s Aesthetics and Teleology’, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2005 http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kant-aesthetics/ KANT, Immanuel, Critique of Judgment, United States, Oxford University Press Inc., 2007 RISATTI, Howard, A Theory of Craft, United States, The University of North Carolina Press, 2007 SHELLY, James, ‘The Concept of the Aesthetic’, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2009 http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2009/entries/aestheticconcept/ YANAGI, Soetsu, The Unknown Craftsman, London, George Allen &Unwin Ltd., 1972 27