28 April 2014 Project Officer –Assisted Reproductive Technology Health & Research Ethics Section, NHMRC GPO Box 1421, Canberra ACT 2601 Dear Sir/Madam, Re: Review of Part B of the Ethical Guidelines for the Use of Assisted Reproductive Technology in Clinical Practice and Research, 2007 Thank you for the opportunity to make a submission to the Review of Part B of the Guidelines. A submission on behalf of Embryo Donation Network is attached. Please contact me on [NHMRC has removed personal information]if you require any additional information. Regards, Angela Ferguson President Embryo Donation Network [NHMRC has removed personal information] admin@embryodonation.org.au Confidential / Not confidential [Delete as appropriate] www.embryodonation.org.au INC: 9897478 Name: Organisation*: Angela Ferguson & Marieke McPhail Embryo Donation Network *Please only include the name of the organisation here if the submission reflects the views of the organisation About Embryo Donation Network Embryo Donation Network is an independent not-for-profit organisation with a national network. We provide information, support and advocacy around embryo donation. Our volunteers have personal and professional experience relevant to embryo donation, and are available to provide peer support and answer questions. Our comprehensive website (embryodonation.org.au) provides easy to understand information about embryo donation in Australia. Our online public classifieds provide a platform for clients to advertise for an embryo donor or recipient. We also assist clients to find a suitable match by providing a private forum where they can view more detailed profiles of donors or recipients, and help clients to find out more about their potential match before they make direct contact. Scope Of The Submission This review of Part B of the Guidelines is an opportunity for Embryo Donation Network to inform the Committee of the significant issues that those in our network experience. Embryo Donation Network will address in this submission the areas of practice in which we see inconsistency between clinical practice and the Guidelines or alternatively where the issue is not adequately addressed in the Guidelines. We will draw from the research that has informed our practice, as well as the feedback from, and personal experience of, our members. The sections we will refer to are: Section 5.2 Section 6.1 Section 6.9 Section 7 Section 7.2 Section 8 Ethical Basis Of The Submission Embryo Donation Network has based this submission primarily on the following ethical principles, found in the Guidelines: Not confidential ‘Respect for all participants’ (Section 5.1) ‘Respect for human embryos’ (Section 5.2) ‘Use open and consistent decision making’ (Section 5.3), ‘Provide information and counselling’ (Section 5.4), as part of the duty of care that clinics have to patients during their ART journey. We have also made reference to ‘the autonomy and long-term welfare of individuals who take part in ART or research’ (Section 2.6), and the need for ‘informed decision making’ (Section 2.6). Not confidential 5 Ethical principles for clinical practice of ART Specific Questions Section 5.2 Q7. Should there be a mandatory requirement for clinics to have policies and procedures around embryos which are excess to the requirements of patients? Policies and procedures around unused embryos There should be a mandatory requirement for clinics to have policies and procedures around unused embryos. It is widely accepted that decisions about unused embryos can be very difficult for patients (Blyth, Frith, Paul & Berger, 2011; McMahon & Saunders 2009). However, evidence from the literature and our experience suggests that this decision is not always well supported by clinics (see e.g. de Lacey, 2007; Fuscaldo, Russell, & Gillam, 2007; Nachtigall, MacDougall, Lee, Harrington, & Becker, 2010). Therefore clinics should be required to have adequate policies and procedures around embryo disposition and related decision-making. Section 5.2 of the Guidelines should include a requirement for contact to be made with patients by a clinical member of staff (e.g. a counsellor or nurse) a year before the embryos reach the limit of their storage time. The aim of this contact would provide support and information around embryo disposition options, thereby reducing possible psychological distress (Fuscaldo et al., 2007). We would maintain that mandating such contact is commensurate with respecting the emotional, psychological and relational significance of this decision for many patients, and is part of clinics’ duty of care for their patients. Having this contact a full year prior to the storage time limit would allow adequate time to pursue any of the options for disposition of embryos listed at 8.5.1 of the Guidelines, with embryo donation being the most time-sensitive option. In addition, the Guidelines should encourage clinics to provide as many options as possible for patients with unused embryos, so that individuals can find the one that is most closely aligned with their personal preferences. Clinics should provide information on all possible embryo disposition options (as stipulated at 8.5.1), even if not available at that particular clinic. This would then allow patients to participate in informed decision making. Recommendations: Not confidential Section 5.2 should include a requirement that clinics have adequate policies and procedures around unused embryos. Section 5.2 should include a requirement that contact be made with patients by a clinical member of staff a year prior to the embryos reaching the limit of their storage time. Section 5.2 should encourage clinics to provide information on all possible embryo disposition options, even if not available at that clinic. 6 Use of gametes in reproductive treatment programs Specific Questions Section 6.1 (see also Section 7.1) Q14. What assistance is required to support parents in telling their children about their genetic origins? o Should this guidance be included in the ART guidelines? o How, and by whom, should this assistance be provided? e.g. Is there a role for community practitioners such as GPs and maternal-child health nurses? Disclosure Guidance for parents about disclosure to children should be included in the Guidelines, consistent with principles of ‘Respect for all participants’. It is now well established that it is in the best interests of the donor conceived child to be told about their genetic origins, and evidence suggests that there are advantages to early disclosure (Blyth, 2002). Equally, research and experience tells us that many in the wider community lack this understanding (see e.g. Blyth, 2002). For these reasons, parents should receive information and support about the importance of disclosure and how they might disclose. The Guidelines should encourage clinics to put in place policies and procedures around this. It is our experience that community practitioners such as GPs and maternalchild health nurses are in an important position to provide ongoing support to parents about the importance of disclosure. There is a need for training and support for these professionals so that they can provide support in this relatively new area of practice. There is a role here for collaboration between professional associations, in order to integrate such training into continuing Not confidential professional development. Recommendation: Section 6.1 should stipulate that clinics should provide parents with information about the importance of disclosure to donor conceived children, and information to help them in this disclosure. Section 6.9 (see also Section 7.6) Q23. Should conditional donation of sperm, eggs or embryos such as stipulating certain race or social attributes be permitted? e.g. a sperm donor not wanting his sperm to be used for a single woman, a lesbian couple, or a particular race? Embryo Donation Network will address here conditional donation of embryos only. Embryo Donation Network would recommend that conditional donation of embryos be permitted. Whilst it is clear from the literature that not all couples are comfortable with or desire conditional embryo donation (Fuscaldo et al, 2007), it is also clear that for some, it would make it easier for them to donate (Blyth et al, 2011; Millbank et al, 2013). In the interests of patient autonomy and self-determination, individuals should be allowed to find the option that is most aligned with their preferences, as long as it complies with all requirements of legislation and the Guidelines. Therefore, we suggest that conditional donation should be permitted, for those for whom it would be helpful. Recommendation: Section 6.9 should stipulate that conditional donation of embryos should be permitted, as long as it complies with relevant legislation and the Guidelines 7 Use of donated embryos General Questions Q34. Do you think that there are gaps in the current ethical guidance in Section 7? Not confidential Single embryo donation One gap in the current ethical guidance is around ensuring clinics will facilitate donations of single embryos. There are wide variations in clinic practice when potential donors only have a single embryo in storage. Some clinics will facilitate single embryo donations. However it has been reported to us that some clinics refuse to allow single embryo donations, apparently on the basis that it is a significant investment of resources for the recipient, with potentially lower chance of success. It is the view of Embryo Donation Network that if a donor can find a known recipient who is willing to receive a single embryo, clinic protocols should not override the informed consent of these parties. Demand for donated embryos continues to outstrip supply (Blyth et al, 2011; Hammarberg, Johnson & Petrillo, 2011). In this situation, under principles of self-determination and informed consent, recipients should be the ones to decide if a single embryo donation is worthwhile in their case. This would also be consistent with the principle of respect for human embryos. Section 7 should specifically mention that clinic policy allow single embryo donations in situations of fully informed consent. Recommendation: Section 7 of the Guidelines should stipulate that clinic policy should allow single embryo donations in situations of fully informed consent. . . . Embryo donation and genetic disease Another gap in the ethical guidance in Section 7 is around embryos that may carry genetic disease. Patients should not be arbitrarily prohibited from donating embryos based on potential genetic disease of the embryos. Practice that restricts such donation is inequitable and discriminatory, and can cause psychological harm (de Lacey 2007; Millbank et al, 2013). The Guidelines tend to conflate donor gametes and donor embryos at this point, but we would argue that this is an area where there are distinct differences between gamete donation and embryo donation (de Lacey & Norman, 2004; Millbank et al, 2013). Clearly, in gamete donation, guidance about reducing possible transmission of genetic disease is necessary and appropriate. However in the case of unused embryos, these embryos that may carry genetic disease already exist (de Lacey & Norman, 2004). Some in our Network have wished to donate embryos rather than destroy them, but have been prevented from doing so and suffered psychological harm as a result. We would argue that practices around embryo donation should provide for patient self-determination and for individual preferences, and allow as many Not confidential choices as possible about embryo disposition. . . If donors can find a recipient for their embryos who is willing to receive affected or potentially affected embryos, this donation should be facilitated by the clinic as long as it complies with relevant legislation and the Guidelines. Principles of informed consent should undergird decision-making in each of these unique cases, and clinics should interfere only if there are ‘very strong grounds’ (Millbank et al, 2013). Recommendation: Section 7 should include guidance that donation of embryos potentially affected by genetic disease should be facilitated in situations where all parties give informed consent. Specific Questions Section 7.2 Q35. Paragraph 7.2.1 – Is the practice of on-donation of donated embryos acceptable if all parties are involved in the counselling process? On-donation Embryo Donation Network recommends that the Guidelines be changed to state that the practice of on-donation of donated embryos is acceptable if all parties are involved in the counselling process. There is confusion and misinformation evident amongst some patients about whether on-donation is ‘legal’, and this largely seems to stem from the contradiction between actual clinic practice and the stipulations in 7.2.1 that on-donation should not occur. There is much variation in practice between clinics, with some advising that it is ‘illegal’, and others allowing it to go ahead on a case-by-case basis. Our Network includes many who have conceived with donor sperm and/or eggs, and would prefer to on-donate their unused embryos, often to a known recipient. This cohort is often motivated to donate by a sense of gratitude for the gift of donor gametes in enabling them to have children, and a wish to reciprocate. Yet on the whole they are unable to do this. In addition, we have some in our Network who have received a relatively large number of donor embryos, and are unlikely to use all of these embryos. These recipients are often concerned that they will not be permitted to ondonate these embryos. Others have had considerable difficulty finding a clinic that will facilitate on-donation, if their own clinic does not. Not confidential Donors of embryos have also commented that they are unsure of what would happen if their recipients do not use all the embryos, and expressed concern as to whether they as donors would be consulted before any action was taken. Donor identification procedures have improved throughout Australia since the Guidelines were last reviewed, which reduces the need for restrictions on ondonation (Millbank et al., 2013). In addition, the fact that some clinics allow, or are considering allowing, on-donation on a case-by-case basis indicates that Paragraph 7.2.1 of the Guidelines does not align with practice in many clinics and should be updated. Paragraph 7.2.1 should state that on-donation should be possible where all parties give informed consent and where relevant legislation and the Guidelines are complied with. Paragraph 7.2.1 would then be consistent with principles of respect for all participants and human embryos, and also the need for open and consistent decision making by clinics. Recommendation: Paragraph 7.2.1 should be updated to state that ondonation of embryos should be possible where all parties give informed consent and where relevant legislation and the Guidelines are complied with. Not confidential 8 Storage of gametes and embryos Q37. Do you think that there are gaps in the current ethical guidance in Section 8? Storage limits for donated embryos There is a gap in current ethical guidance in Section 8, regarding storage limits for donated embryos. There are members of our Network who have felt rushed by storage time limits, or who have been unable to donate due to time limitations. It is our view that the storage period for donated embryos should be reset at the time of donation (Millbank et al, 2013). This would avoid the difficult situation where donors have inadequate time in which to work through the process of complex decision-making (Nachtigall, Becker, Friese et al, 2005; de Lacey, 2007). In addition, recipients of embryos sometimes have an unreasonably short time span in which to use the embryos because of storage limits. For example, they may be pressured by time constraints to attempt a second pregnancy before it is medically or emotionally advisable; the alternative is that they risk losing the embryos. Recipients of embryos are entitled to at least the same period of time to utilise their embryos that the donors had. Recommendation: Section 8 should state that the storage period for donated embryos should be reset at the time of donation. References: Blyth, E. (2002). Information on genetic origins in donor-assisted conception: is knowing who you are a human rights issue? Human Fertility, 5, 185-192. Blyth, E., Frith, L., Paul, M., & Berger, R. (2011). Embryo relinquishment for family building: How should it be conceptualized? . International Journal of Law, Policy and the Family, 25(2), 260-285. de Lacey, S. (2005). Parent identity and 'virtual' children: why patients discard rather than donate unused embryos. Human Reproduction, 20(6), 1661-1669. de Lacey, S. (2007a). Decisions for the fate of frozen embryos: Fresh insights into patients' thinking and their rationales for donating or discarding embryos. Human Reproduction, 22(6), 1751-1758. de Lacey, S. & Norman, R. (2004). What should we do with donated embryos that may be genetically affected? Human Reproduction, 19(5), 1065-1068. Fuscaldo, G., Russell, S., & Gillam, L. (2007). How to facilitate decisions about surplus embryos: patients' views. Human Reproduction, 22(12), 3129-3138. Not confidential Hammarberg, K., Johnson, L., & Petrillo, T. (2011). Gamete and embryo donation and surrogacy in Australia: The social context and regulatory framework. International Journal of Fertility & Sterility, 4(4), 176-183. McMahon, C., & Saunders, D. (2009). Attitudes of couples with stored frozen embryos toward conditional embryo donation. Fertility and Sterility, 91, 140-147. Millbank, J., Stuhmcke, A., Karpin, I. & Chandler, E. (2013). Enhancing reproductive opportunity: a study of decision-making concerning stored embryos. University of Technology Sydney: Sydney. Nachtigall, R., Becker, G., Friese, C. et al. (2005). Parents’ conceptualization of their frozen embryos complicates the disposition decision. Fertility and Sterility, 84, 431434. Nachtigall, R., MacDougall, K., Lee, M., Harrington, J., & Becker, G. (2010). What do patients want? Expectations and perceptions of IVF clinic information and support regarding frozen embryo disposition. Fertility and Sterility, 94(6), 2069-2072. Not confidential