Secularists, Humanists and Religious Education: Religious Crisis and Curriculum Change in England, 1963-1975. Corresponding Author: Dr Rob Freathy Graduate School of Education University of Exeter Heavitree Road Exeter Devon EX1 2LU Email: r.j.k.freathy@ex.ac.uk Co-Author: Dr Stephen Parker Institute of Education University of Worcester Henwick Grove Worcester WR2 6AJ Email: s.parker@worc.ac.uk 1 Secularists, Humanists and Religious Education: Religious Crisis and Curriculum Change in England, 1963-1975. Dr R. J. K. Freathy1 and Dr S. G. Parker Abstract With particular reference to religious education, this article provides an account of the campaigns of Secularists and Humanists in England in the 1960s and 1970s and locates them within their broader religious context. These campaigns, which have been both underplayed and overstated in the existing historiography, failed to garner the levels of support required to fulfil their ultimate aims. Nevertheless, Secularists and Humanists did make a significant contribution to public and political discourses at the time and created opportunities with the potential to exert influence over the development of Religious Education, Collective Worship and moral education. Their involvement was welcomed, indeed fostered, by many leading Christians and religious educationists. Secularist and Humanist campaigns also precipitated parliamentary discussion and provoked considerable opposition from Christians in other quarters. Finally, some observations are made about the ways in which this episode in the religious history of education can contextualise comparable contemporary debates. Keywords: Religious Education; Secularists; Humanists; De-Christianisation 1 Corresponding author. Email: r.j.k.freathy@ex.ac.uk. 2 Introduction This article provides a detailed analytical description of the concerted and organised campaigns of Secularists and Humanists in England in the 1960s and 1970s with particular reference to Religious Instruction (later known as Religious Education) (RI/RE).2 It is based upon a study of a wide-range of primary documentary sources which were either written by, or demonstrate the influence of, Secularists and/or Humanists. Some of the published sources have already been cited en passant by Dennis Bates, Penny Thompson, Terence Copley and other historians of RE, but they are here collated for special attention for the first time.3 Other unpublished sources have previously been neglected, such as the National Archive files ‘Religious Instruction 1959-66’ (ED 147-544) and ‘Department of Education and Science [DES]: Schools Branch (Registered Files). Correspondence on revised education bill and provisions’ (ED 183.5).4 This article focuses on the work of two organisations, the National Secular Society and the British Humanist Association, and specific individuals, such as David Tribe, Brigid Brophy, Harold J. Blackham, James Hemming, Lionel Elvin and Harry Stopes-Roe. Among their aims, as will be shown below, these campaigning organisations and individuals sought to abolish RI (and sometimes RE), establish a secular alternative, and/or secularise its aims and broaden its content to include world religions and secular worldviews. The purpose of this article is not to provide a philosophical or theoretical evaluation of the arguments underpinning these proposals, but to explore the nature and purpose of these campaigns, to assess their contribution to public, political and professional discourses concerning RI/RE, and to provide historical perspective on comparable contemporary issues. Before doing so, however, it is necessary to outline the religious context in which these campaigns occurred, describe the major theoretical developments in RI/RE at the time, and discuss selected contextual factors which impacted upon them. The religious context The Second World War was frequently portrayed by British clerics and politicians as a spiritual and moral crisis threatening the Christian foundations of civilisation, freedom and democracy. Such rhetoric was repeatedly coupled with an assertion that Britain’s social and political traditions and values could only endure the threat of idolatrous totalitarianism abroad and pre-war trends towards faithlessness at home, if the nation’s Christian identity was reinforced and reinvigorated.5 In this context, the 2 In the 1944 Education Act, religious education referred to Collective Worship and the curriculum subject called Religious Instruction (RI). Between 1963 and 1975, primarily for pedagogical reasons, an increasing number of writers used the term Religious Education to refer to the curriculum subject. This practice was adopted by the 1988 Education Reform Act which used Religious Education (RE) to refer to the classroom subject only. In this article, the term religious education, in the lower case, encompasses Religious Instruction, Collective Worship and other religious elements of schooling, while the curriculum subject alone will be referred to as RI, RE or RI/RE, all in the upper case, depending on whether it is important to make a distinction between RI and RE. 3 D. Bates, ‘Christianity, Culture and Other Religions (Part 2): F. H. Hilliard, Ninian Smart and the 1988 Education Reform Act’, British Journal of Religious Education (BJRE) 18, no. 2 (1996); P. Thompson, Whatever happened to religious education? (Cambridge: Lutterworth, 2004) and T. Copley, Teaching Religion (Exeter: Exeter University Press, 2008). 4 The archival research for this article was funded by a British Academy Small Grant (Ref. SG-54151) and undertaken by Jonathan Doney (University of Exeter). 5 S. Parker, ‘Reinvigorating Christian Britain: the spiritual issues of the war, national identity, and the hope of Religious Education’, in God and War, ed. S. G. Parker and T. Lawson (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2012), 61-79; R. Freathy, ‘The Triumph of Religious Education for Citizenship in English Schools, 1935-1949’, History of Education (HoE) 37, no. 2 (2007): 295316. 3 churches and the state collaborated in passing the 1944 Education Act. This legislation, pertaining only to England and Wales, sought to reaffirm the nation’s Christian character by requiring all pupils, except those withdrawn by their parents, in both fully publicly-funded county (Local Education Authority [LEA]) schools and partially publicly-funded voluntary (mainly church) schools, to receive a daily act of Collective Worship and RI.6 In county schools, RI was to be defined by an Agreed Syllabus prepared or adopted by a local conference consisting of four committees which represented religious denominations, the Church of England, teacher associations and the LEA. These committees had to reach unanimous agreement before the Agreed Syllabus could be adopted by the LEA.7 Local authorities were also permitted to constitute Standing Advisory Councils for Religious Education to advise them on religious educational matters. Through these measures, the post-war welfare state was given responsibility for Christian nurture.8 If this was not an anachronism founded on wartime idealism and a national myth, it would later be perceived as one. In the shorter term, however, its religious settlement, although not a ‘final solution’,9 obscured and contained, even if it did not finally bury, decades of antagonism between the Christian denominations over the nature and purpose of religious education and created a semblance of unity which temporarily muted the voices of Secularists, who had long argued that state-maintained schools should not provide religious education.10 Indeed, the inclusion of the ambiguous concept of spiritual development as one of the overarching purposes of the statutory system of public education in the 1944 Education Act11 could be interpreted as either further support for the dominance of Judaeo-Christian assumptions or a deliberate attempt to encapsulate a wider spectrum of beliefs and practices than those traditionally associated with religious education.12 By the 1960s, the cultural climate was less conducive to the state-sponsored Christianisation envisaged by those who were responsible for piloting the 1944 Education Bill through both Houses of Parliament.13 Focusing on popular-based cultural change amongst ‘ordinary people’ rather than any longer-term elite-led intellectual phenomenon, Callum Brown argues that, in 1963, ‘something very profound ruptured the [Christian] character of the nation’14 and that the comprehensive collapse of British-organised Christianity across the decade was evident on all indices of adherence, practice and identity.15 For him, this was primarily due to the erosion of established patterns of social and familial life linked to changing attitudes to sexual intercourse, orientation and equality, particularly amongst the young and women, which led to the de-feminisation of Christian piety and the deChristianisation of femininity. Additionally, according to Hugh McLeod, mass communication, immigration, ethnic diversification and the ‘enormous increase in the 6 Education Act 1944, 7 & 8 GEO. 6. Chapter 31, Part II, Section 25(1-4), (London: HMSO), http://www.legislation.gov.uk/ukpga/1944/31/pdfs/ukpga_19440031_en.pdf (accessed 18 August 2011). 7 Op cit., Section 29(4) and Fifth Schedule. 8 S. J. D. Green, The Passing of Protestant England (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2011), 239. 9 M. Cruickshank, Church and State in English Education (London: Macmillan, 1963), 169. 10 Ibid., 12. 11 Education Act 1944, 7 & 8 GEO. 6. Chapter 31, Part II, Section 7. 12 For an extended discussion, see T. Copley, Spiritual Development in the State School (Exeter: University of Exeter Press, 2000), 66-9. 13 C. Cannon, ‘The Influence of Religion on Educational Policy, 1902-1944’, British Journal of Educational Studies (BJES) 12, no. 2 (1964): 143-160. 14 C. Brown, The Death of Christian Britain (London: Routledge, 2001), 1. 15 Callum G. Brown. ‘What was the Religious Crisis of the 1960s?’, Journal of Religious History 34, no. 4 (2010): 468-79. 4 range of beliefs and world-views accessible to the majority of the population’ (e.g. new forms of Christianity, other religions, alternative spiritualities and new political faiths) facilitated a cultural relativism in which increasingly no ideology ‘could claim a condition of privilege’.16 The 1960s also ‘witnessed a frenzy of legislation that effectively de-Christianised and liberalised British law and society’ including, in 1967 alone, the repeal of the 1697 Blasphemy Act, the legalisation of abortions and the decriminalisation of homosexual acts.17 Many within the churches responded with hostility and fear to ‘the permissive society’ which was seemingly being created. Yet, as Matthew Grimley argues, the moral authority of the churches had not completely waned, as shown by the Church of England’s prominence in a number of campaigns for legal reform.18 For him, a reluctant acceptance that the nation was no longer a Christian moral community, a desire to protect Christian teaching from secularising trends, and a belief in the possibility of distinguishing between crime and sin, law and morality, and public and private life, at a time when calls for the separation of Church and state were re-surfacing, led moderate reformers to become active agents in the secularisation of the law. Their pragmatic, preservationist, approach differed from the ‘new morality’ or ‘situational ethics’ promoted by ‘South Bank’ liberal theologians, such as the Anglican Bishop, John A. T. Robinson,19 and the radical theologians, such as Harvey Cox,20 who considered ‘the secular society’ to be ‘a condition neutral in faith that was egalitarian, democratic and pragmatic in morals’.21 According to Brown, by the end of 1967, ‘British society as a whole - including the government and the churches - became aware of secularisation as an intense cultural and ecclesiastical revolution’.22 In this context, as David Nash observes, sociologists self-consciously constructed a secularisation thesis which assumed ‘that the importance of religious practice and belief is in inexorable (and inevitable) decline as a fundamental process introduced by the arrival of modern society and its consequences’ (e.g. urbanisation, industrialisation and scientific progress).23 For him, much of this pioneering sociological work had ‘an evangelical modernist tone and, in its more messianic moments [appeared] to be hoping for and even working towards a rationalist utopia’.24 Similarly, as Alister Chapman has noted, secularisation theory became a more central part of ecclesiastical discourse ‘in part because churchmen and others were looking for explanations for sharply declining church attendance’.25 Indeed, ‘the secularisation thesis came to be something of a self-fulfilling prophecy: not so much a theoretical construct above the societal fray, but a genuine participant in events on the ground’.26 In other words, it not only sought to provide an explanation for secularising trends, but also perpetuated them. 16 H. McLeod, The Religious Crisis of the 1960s (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007), 1-2 and 78. 17 C. Brown, Religion and Society in Twentieth-Century Britain (Harlow: Pearson Longman, 2006), 267. 18 M. Grimley, ‘Law, Morality and Secularisation: The Church of England and the Wolfenden Report, 1954–1967’, Journal of Ecclesiastical History (JEH) 60, no. 4 (2009): 726. 19 Ibid., 739-41. 20 H. Cox, The Secular City (New York: Macmillan, 1965). 21 Brown, Religion and Society, 233. 22 Ibid., 225. 23 D. Nash, ‘Reconnecting Religion with Social and Cultural History: Secularization’s Failure as a Master Narrative’, Cultural and Social History 1, no. 3 (2004): 303. See, for example, B. Wilson, Religion in Secular Society (London: C. A. Watts, 1966) and D. Martin, A Sociology of English Religion (London: SCM, 1967). 24 Nash, ‘Reconnecting Religion with Social and Cultural History’, 314. 25 A. Chapman, ‘Secularisation and the Ministry of John R. W. Stott at All Souls, Langham Place, 1950–1970’, JEH 56, no. 3 (2005): 498. 26 Ibid., 513. 5 Just over a decade later, drawing upon extensive data evidencing the declining participation and membership rates of Christian denominations, Alan D. Gilbert’s The Making of Post-Christian Britain became the standard account of the secularisation of modern British society.27 Yet Gilbert’s premises and arguments, and even the concept of secularisation, have latterly been questioned,28 with many historians and sociologists becoming more sceptical about whether religiosity generally or Christianity particularly has declined. For some, religious change and diversification, rather than decline, occurred after 1945. The English became a nation of ‘believers’ retaining private religious beliefs, even if they were not ‘belongers’ participating in the Christian church.29 For others, ‘the associational deficit’ implied by declining ‘mainstream religious participation’ has ‘not been filled by emerging new religious movements’, but rather accompanied ‘a degeneration of common religious belief’.30 For Simon Green, the demise of English Protestantism, which he focuses on specifically, was a gradual process, rather than a sudden death, hinging upon the long-term impact of the churches’ lessening influence over young people, especially represented by the precipitous decline of Sunday School attendance from six million in 1906 to half a million in 1941.31 This served to diminish the religious and moral sensibilities of subsequent generations such that, by the 1960s, the trend was irreversible and placed young people ‘beyond the reach of all of the conventional mechanisms by which protestant England had traditionally socialised its young’.32 He argues that the decreasing exposure to orthodox Christian doctrine in Sunday Schools (due to a lack of patrons) or in maintained schools (due to a lack of will or competence) resulted in larger numbers of people experiencing the religious within an entirely heterodox framework and contributed to the declining social significance of religion. On the matter of religious education, Brown also notes that although it was retained in schools in the 1960s, ‘despite secular pressure’, it became ‘a mere shadow of the Christian instruction it had formerly been’.33 Thereby, although disagreeing about the timeframe for the historical process variously called, for example, ‘secularisation’,34 ‘the crisis of Christendom’,35 and ‘de-Christianisation’,36 Green and Brown have both identified religious education in churches and schools as both one of its causes and effects.37 There is insufficient space in the present article to fully explain and justify our position within the secularisation debate. However, in contextualising the campaigns of Secularists and Humanists in England in the 1960s and 1970s, we have found useful the three key strands identified by Jeremy Morris in his differentiated account of ‘secularisation’ by which he means ‘de-Christianisation’ (i.e. ‘what has happened to 27 A. D. Gilbert, The Making of Post-Christian Britain (London: Longman, 1980). T. W. Heyck, ‘The Decline of Christianity in Twentieth-Century Britain’, Albion 28, no. 3 (1996): 437. 29 G. Davie, Religion in Britain since 1945 (Oxford: Blackwell, 1994). 30 S. J. D. Green, ‘From Puritanism to Pantheism - Reflections on the Degeneration of English Life Since 1945’, Machray Review 7 (1997), http://prayerbook.ca/online-libraryarticles/73-research-into-historical-questions/198-from-puritanism-to-pantheism-reflectionson-the-degeneration-of-english-life-since-1945-by-sjd-green-machray-review (accessed July 28, 2011). 31 Green, The Passing of Protestant England, 161. 32 Ibid., 271. 33 Brown, Religion and Society, 269. 34 Brown, The Death of Christian Britain. 35 H. McLeod and W. Ustorf, eds., Decline of Christendom in Western Europe, 1750-2000 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003), 18. 36 McLeod, The Religious Crisis. 37 Green, The Passing of Protestant England; Brown, The Death of Christian Britain. 28 6 Christian belief and practice in Britain’).38 These key strands are: (i) ‘institutional marginalisation’, which is ‘the progressive disentanglement of established religion in Britain from structures of local and national government, and the corresponding evolution of approaches to social and educational policy that were largely divorced from explicit religious commitment’;39 (ii) ‘institutional attenuation’, which refers to the decline in church attendance within the context of other indices of occasional or symbolic identification, endogenous growth, geographical differences, and the continuance of institutional relevance and vigour;40 and (iii) ‘cultural displacement’, which recognises the removal of Christianity as the sole ‘referent of public and private morality’ and the emergence of ‘a marketplace of diverse secular and religious standpoints’, as well as acknowledging the resilience of Christianity in the public sphere and the complexity and pervasiveness of religious identities.41 The developments in RI/RE theory, to which we next turn, are one example of ‘institutional marginalisation’. They were frequently justified by many leading Christians and religious educationists, among others, as a response to ‘institutional attenuation’ within, and the ‘cultural displacement’ of, Christianity. These processes were, in turn, commonly perceived to be indicators of secularisation and/or pluralisation. Theoretical developments in Religious Instruction/Education Intellectual leadership for the developments which occurred in RI theory in the first half of 1960s was provided by Harold Loukes, Richard Acland and Ronald Goldman. On the basis of social and psychological research, and in response to increasingly negative assessments of the effectiveness of RI, they sought to make the subject, which remained ‘fundamentally Christian in orientation, assumptions and world view’, more child-centred and relevant to pupils’ everyday lives, and ‘less centred on abstract religious ideas or the essentially academic study of the Bible or church history’.42 However, by the late 1960s, theories about the nature and purpose of RI (progressively known as RE) ‘began to take account of the increasing secularisation and pluralism of British society’43 and to disclaim ‘any overtly religious or spiritual function’ for the subject.44 For Gerald Parsons, the three most significant publications were Edwin Cox’s Changing Aims in Religious Education (1966), J. W. D. Smith’s Religious Education in a Secular Setting (1969) and Ninian Smart’s Secular Education and the Logic of Religion (1968).45 The latter author was also a key figure in, firstly, the establishment of the Department of Religious Studies at the University of Lancaster, and secondly, alongside John Hinnells and Geoffrey Parrinder, the foundation of the highly influential Shap Working Party on World Religions in Education. The consequent curriculum changes, which are usually associated with the Schools Council’s Working Paper 36: Religious Education in Secondary Schools (1971), have been characterised as a shift from child-centred, neo-confessional, Christian instruction to phenomenological, non-confessional, multi-faith RE.46 At the same time, two significant projects undertaken at the University of Oxford sought to J. Morris, ‘The Strange Death of Christian Britain: Another Look at the Secularisation Debate’, The Historical Journal, 46, no. 4 (2003): 971. 39 Ibid., 972. 40 Ibid., 973-4. 41 Ibid., 975-6. 42 G. Parsons, ‘There and Back Again? Religion and the 1944 and 1988 Education Acts’, in vol. 2 of The Growth of Religious Diversity, ed. G. Parsons (London: Routledge, 1994), 170-2. 43 R. Jackson, ‘Religious Studies and Developments in Religious Education in England and Wales’, in Turning Points in Religious Studies, ed. U. King (Edinburgh: T&T Clark, 1990), 107. 44 Parsons, ‘There and Back Again?’, 174. 45 Ibid., 173-4. 46 Ibid. 38 7 develop a discrete form of moral education independent of RI/RE.47 Working Paper 36 endorsed this, asserting that ‘the study of ethics and the study of religion are separate and distinct academic disciplines or areas of study’.48 Secularisation theories penetrated the academic and professional discourses associated with RI/RE. Some participants actively welcomed the secularisation of the subject as a democratic response to the pluralistic society, whilst at the same time condemning secularism for being antithetical to religion and for representing a narrowing doctrine which would lead to the abolition of religious options.49 As an example, John Hull, who was the editor of Learning for Living (1971-8) and the British Journal of Religious Education (1978-96), welcomed the secularisation of RI in terms of the subject’s changing sponsors, teaching force and objectives.50 First, he called for the ‘Christian hegemony in Agreed Syllabuses’ to end, which would represent ‘a small but significant shift’ in church and state relations,51 thereby enabling the subject to be determined not by ecumenical definitions of commonly-held Christian truths, but by multi-faith definitions of educationally-justifiable content and methods.52 Indeed, although legally Agreed Syllabuses could be seen as ‘one of the final pockets of ecclesiastical domination over a sphere of secular expertise’,53 Hull noted that, in practice, curriculum development was increasingly being led by educational professionals through teacher’s centres, working parties and projects.54 Second, Hull noted that the development of multi-faith RE had ‘dealt the death blow’ to the belief that teachers must be committed believers in the faith they are teaching.55 Thereby, it had made possible the notion of the ‘secular religious educator’ whose professional credentials to teach RE are not dependent upon any particular religious affiliation.56 Third, Hull highlighted the movement away from Christian doctrinal instruction and biblical and theological teaching towards open discussion and life-centred methods and, more significantly, the study of world religions and secular alternatives.57 For him, this critical, but tolerant, descriptive approach was consistent with the nature of Christian thought and could be justified by the increased plurality of beliefs in society.58 This conception aroused political and public debate, he argued, because RI had become a ‘symbol for the ambiguity of the culture’ it had traditionally conveyed.59 If the religious traditions and beliefs of the educating society were no longer identifiable with Christianity, then fully publicly-funded education, including Collective Worship and RI, could no longer be based on Christian presuppositions or be used for Christian nurture.60 For Hull, the value-laden ‘formal principles’ of education should encourage open enquiry and the questioning of everything, while the ‘material principles’, governing its content and methods, should be ‘neutral’ with regard to differing schools of thought and ideologies (e.g. Christianity, Islam, Humanism and 47 J. Wilson, N. Williams and B. Sugarman, Introduction to Moral Education (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1967); P. McPhail, Moral Education in the Secondary School (London: Longman, 1972). 48 Schools Council, Working Paper 36 (London: Evans Methuen, 1971), 67 and 70. 49 J. G. Priestley, ‘Religion, Education and Secularization’, in Religion Belongs in the Public School, ed. E. Johns (Toronto: Ecumenical Study Commission on Public Education, 1985). 50 J. Hull, School Worship (London: SCM, 1975), 87. 51 J. Hull, Studies in Religion and Education (Lewes: Falmer, 1984), 88. 52 Ibid., 86. 53 Hull, School Worship, 79. 54 Ibid. 55 Ibid., 87. 56 Ibid. 57 Ibid., 81. 58 Hull, Studies in Religion and Education, 1-2 and 96. 59 Ibid., 122. 60 Ibid., 99. 8 Communism).61 Thus, rather than promoting religious faith and truth, RE should advance religious knowledge and understanding to prepare pupils to undertake informed and thoughtful roles in a pluralistic society.62 The alternative, he argued, would be unfair and inimical to good community relations, forcing increasing numbers of non-Christian pupils to withdraw from RI and/or leading to a new sectarian system of voluntary-aided schools.63 In summary, for Hull, ‘[RE] is nothing but what education is, within the content area of religion’.64 The increasing eagerness of RI/RE teachers to secure independence from ecclesiastical control and develop the subject in a more academic and ‘educational’ direction has been described by Adrian Bell as a process of professionalization.65 One contributory factor was the ‘revolution’ in the academic field of the philosophy of education in the 1960s,66 which also contributed to the almost complete disappearance of Christian theology from educational studies in universities and colleges of education.67 In terms of RI, the most prominent philosopher of education was Paul H. Hirst whose work exemplified two key philosophical strands identified recently by Trevor Cooling.68 First, the ‘argument from fairness’ asserts that ‘in a religiously plural democracy … no belief system should be privileged in education’ and ‘pupils should be free to create their own identity’.69 Second, the ‘argument from objectivity’ asserts that epistemological, ethical and educational principles should be stated (and derived) rationally, critically and independently of (religious) ontological commitments and that education should promote autonomous rationality.70 On such bases, Hirst argued that fully publicly-funded schools should refrain from providing RI, Collective Worship or Christian moral education,71 but instead provide ‘factual instruction about the beliefs that have played and do play so large a part in our history, literature and way of life’ and confine moral education ‘to the common pool of natural moral principles that all share’.72 The only consistent alternative to this model was ‘the thorough-going pluralist system ... in which maintained schools offering education according to different religious principles are readily available to all children’.73 Through a ‘publications explosion’ in the philosophy of education, Hirst’s work became renowned among educationists,74 including religious educationists such as John Hull above, and thereby contributed to the on-going development of RI/RE theory. 61 Hull, School Worship, 84-85 and 103. Hull, Studies in Religion and Education, 109. 63 Ibid., 87. 64 Ibid., 88. 65 A. Bell, ‘Agreed syllabuses of religious education since 1944’, in Social histories of the secondary curriculum, ed. I. Goodson (Lewes: Falmer, 1985). See also J. Sullivan, ‘Dismembering and Remembering Religious Education’, in Inspiring Faith in Schools, eds. M. C. Felderhof, P. Thompson and D. Torevell (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2007), 127. 66 R. F. Dearden, ‘Philosophy of Education, 1952-82’, BJES 30, no. 1 (1982): 60. 67 J. Arthur, ‘Christian Commentary and Education 1930-1960’, HoE 41, no. 3 (2012): 339359. 68 T. Cooling, Doing God in Education (London: Theos, 2011). 69 Ibid., 18. 70 Ibid., 17. 71 P. H. Hirst, ‘Christian education: A contradiction in terms?’, Learning for Living (LfL) 11, no. 4 (1972): 6-11. 72 P. H. Hirst, ‘Morals, Religion and the Maintained School’, BJES 14, no. 1 (1965): 13 and 15. 73 Ibid., 15. 74 Dearden, ‘Philosophy of Education, 1952-82’, 59. 62 9 The above theoretical developments have become the focus of many recent publications, such as those by Philip Barnes,75 Kevin O’Grady,76 and Geoff Teece.77 Within this literature, there has been much criticism of the extent to which the writers of the time were shaped by Enlightenment commitments, as evident in their arguably naïve use of terms such as ‘objectivity’, ‘neutrality’ and ‘rationality’ when discussing educational aims and methods, and in their promotion of ‘common’, ‘shared’, ‘natural’ or ‘universal’ moral principles. For Barnes and Andrew Wright, confessional, committed and indoctrinatory RI did not give way to neutral, professional and educational RE, but to a partisan and uncritical confessionalism that was ‘moderate, liberal, ecumenical and in certain respects secular’.78 Barnes has also argued that the separation of religious and moral education ensured that RE lost much of its relevance to young people and that the positive contribution of religion(s) to the development of character and the cause of morality became overlooked.79 By contrast, in an earlier article we have challenged Dennis Bates’ assertion that a ‘liberalised establishmentarian view’ which sought ‘to secure the influence of Christianity in English culture’ was replaced by a ‘liberal secular view’ which sought ‘to foster an empathetic ... understanding of major world religions and secular worldviews’.80 Instead, we maintain that RE curriculum reformers conceded to the demands for, and promoted, the teaching of world religions, whilst simultaneously asserting the pre-eminent curricular place of Christianity. Thus, the movement towards the secularisation of curriculum aims and the pluralisation of curriculum content did not end Christian hegemony in RE because the primacy given to knowledge about Christianity continued to be justified for historical and cultural reasons, even if its veracity was no longer assumed.81 Moreover, these secularising and pluralising trends were themselves frequently predicated upon a Christian theological foundation disseminated by religious educationists, such as John Hull, and professional organisations, such as the Christian Education Movement (established in 1965). The present article seeks to contribute to these on-going debates about the nature of the transitions which occurred in RI/RE theory in England in the 1960s and 1970s by further exploring a particular aspect of their historical context. Contextualising the theoretical developments L. P. Barnes, ‘Working Paper 36, Christian Confessionalism and Phenomenological Religious Education’, Journal of Education & Christian Belief 6, no. 1 (2002): 3-23; ‘The Disputed Legacy of Ninian Smart and Phenomenological Religious Education: A Critical Response to Kevin O’Grady’, BJRE 29, no. 2 (2007): 157-68; ‘Developing a new post-liberal paradigm for British religious education’, Journal of Beliefs and Values (JBV) 28, no. 1 (2007): 17-32; and ‘An honest appraisal of phenomenological religious education and a final, honest reply to Kevin O’Grady’, BJRE 31, no. 1 (2009): 69-72. 76 K. O’Grady, ‘Professor Ninian Smart, Phenomenology and Religious Education’, BJRE 27, no. 3 (2005): 227-37; and ‘Honesty in religious education: some further remarks on the legacy of Ninian Smart and related issues, in reply to L. Philip Barnes’, BJRE 31, no. 1 (2009): 65-8. 77 G. Teece, ‘Traversing the gap: Andrew Wright, John Hick and critical religious education’, BJRE 27, no. 1 (2005): 29-40. 78 L. P. Barnes and A. Wright, ‘Romanticism, representations of religion and critical religious education’, BJRE 28, no. 1 (2006): 65-6. For a discussion of the empirical basis of these claims, see R. Freathy and S. Parker, ‘The necessity of historical inquiry in educational research: the case of religious education’, BJRE 32, no. 3 (2010): 229-243. 79 L. P. Barnes, ‘What has Morality to do with Religious Education?’, JBV 32, no. 2 (2011): 131-41. 80 Bates, ‘Christianity, Culture and Other Religions (Part 2)’, 86. 81 S. G. Parker and R. J. K. Freathy, ‘Ethnic Diversity, Christian Hegemony and the Emergence of Multi-faith Religious Education in the 1970s’, HoE 41, no. 3 (2012): 381-404. 75 10 It is our contention that the developments in RI/RE curriculum theory described above were influenced by the religious, ecclesiastical, theological, legal, cultural and philosophical contexts in which they occurred, as well as by more specific factors, such as the campaigns of Secularists and Humanists which are the focus of this article. As will be seen, many of the arguments of Secularists and Humanists were similar to those of Paul Hirst above, even though he explicitly denied he was presenting a Humanist position.82 They also received more publicity than those of academics and professionals, and were thus better known amongst the participants in the on-going public and political debates about the religious clauses of the 1944 Education Act. The contributions of Secularists and Humanists to these discussions were notably recognised by numerous contemporary academic commentators, such as Ronald Goldman who, in identifying the causes of the enduring controversies, cited ‘pressures from humanist, agnostic or other groups’, alongside the continuing decline of church membership and ‘the ineffectiveness of much current religious education’.83 Similarly, John Hull stated, ‘it has been mainly Christian educators who have advocated the secularisation of religion in schools, even though ably supported by humanist criticism’.84 Although the pressure group activity of Secularists and Humanists has been documented in the existing historiography, it has been both underplayed and overstated. At one extreme, following John Hull above, Dennis Bates argues that ‘the leading proponents [of the study of world religions in English schools] were Christian theologians and educationists, not secularists as is often thought’ and that ‘the major division of opinion ... has not been between Christians and secularists but between theologically liberal Christians and theologically conservative or establishmentminded Christians’.85 Yet, in lending historical perspective to contemporary debates in the early 1990s, Bates may have downplayed the importance of Secularists and Humanists to counter accusations from a ‘religiously conservative minority’ who, firstly, associated the development of multi-faith RE with the erosion of the place of Christianity in English society, and secondly, had managed to persuade the Conservative Government to support the continuation of ‘traditional English Christian culture’ through the religious clauses of the 1988 Education Reform Act.86 Consequently, Bates’ research, like that of Terence Copley,87 neglects to pay due attention to the campaigns of Secularists and Humanists. At the other extreme, in subsequent research, Penny Thompson argues that the most significant change in RI/RE in English schools was the move away, in the 1960s, from the presumption of the truth and worth of Christianity ‘following the failure of the profession to stand up to the attacks ... made (not for the first time) by the humanists’.88 She notes that from 1962 the professional journal, Learning for Living, reported challenges to RI from Humanist organisations, but ‘whereas previously humanist arguments had been firmly rejected, now it was a different story’.89 Evidencing ‘a certain crumbling of support for RE in schools’,90 she quotes M. V. C. Jeffreys who argued that the subject ‘has been suffering from a loss of nerve. We take refuge in neutrality, in teaching about religion instead of teaching religion, in doubtful scruples about Hirst, ‘Morals, Religion and the Maintained School’, 5. R. Goldman, Readiness for Religion (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul), 3. 84 Hull, School Worship, 81. 85 D. Bates, ‘Christianity, Culture and Other Religions (Part 1): The Origins of the Study of World Religions in English Education’, BJRE 17, no. 1 (1994): 6. 86 Ibid., 5. 87 Copley, Teaching Religion. 88 Thompson, Whatever happened to religious education?, 170. 89 Ibid., 11. 90 Ibid., 13. 82 83 11 “indoctrination” because we are bewildered by the confusion of theological voices within the Churches and the new aggressive self-confidence of the secular humanists’.91 Consequently, Thompson’s research may suffer from the attribution of too much influence to ‘humanists’ and ‘secular humanists’. As a corrective to these criticisms of the existing historiography, we next seek to provide an analytical description of the nature and purpose of the campaigns of Secularists and Humanists. The two most important pressure groups, the National Secular Society and the British Humanist Association, will be discussed successively. The campaigns of Secularists and Humanists National Secular Society According to Edward Royle, since the 1700s, ‘Free-thinkers’ in England have promoted social and democratic reforms and attacked the privileges enjoyed by Christianity and the Church of England in particular.92 In this tradition, in 1866, Charles Bradlaugh established the National Secular Society (NSS) which attained particular prominence between 1880 and 1886 when Bradlaugh became ‘the personification of radicalism and popular democratic rights’ as a result of his effective campaign to gain membership of the House of Commons despite being initially barred because of his atheism.93 In terms of education, both Secularists and some Christian Dissenters were aligned in voicing their opposition, albeit for different reasons, to the inclusion of religion in publicly-funded schools.94 Their mutually beneficial co-operation achieved some success with regard to the 1870 Elementary Education Act in so far as, although religious education was permitted, there was no obligation to provide it. Moreover, where it was provided, it had to be voluntarily funded, exclude the catechism of any particular religious denomination (the CowperTemple clause)95 and take place at the beginning or end of a school session (i.e. outside of normal curriculum time).96 Contrary to the wishes of the Church of England’s National Society, a ‘conscience clause’ also stipulated that schools had to allow parents the opportunity to withdraw their children from religious education.97 These conditions remained intact until the 1944 Education Act which repealed all bar the Cowper-Temple and conscience clauses. Nevertheless, in terms of the broader ambition of Secularists to abolish the ‘dual system’ of church and state schools, Marjorie Cruickshank argues that, despite the logic of their views and the pressures they brought to bear, they ‘never rallied the country as a whole’ or ‘decisively influenced practical politics’.98 Although the secularist movement went into decline from the mid-1880s, the NSS continued as a largely inconspicuous pressure group until its resurgence in the 1960s99 with a re-invigorated leadership, a growth in membership and the establishment of new branches and affiliations.100 By 1965, its Executive Committee was able to proclaim that, in the light of the decline in religious belief and influence, Ibid., 25. (See M. C. V. Jeffreys, ‘Truth is not neutral’, LfL 8, no. 2 (1968): 9) E. Royle, ‘Secularists and Rationalists, 1800-1940’, in A History of Religion in Britain, eds. S. Gilley and W. Sheils (Oxford: Blackwell, 1994), 406. 93 Ibid., 415. 94 Cruickshank, Church and State in English Education, 54. 95 Elementary Education Act, 1870, 33 & 34 VICT, chapter 75, section 14[2]. 96 Op cit., section 7 [2]. 97 Op cit., section 7 [1]. 98 Cruickshank, Church and State in English Education, xv. 99 Royle, ‘Secularists and Rationalists, 1800-1940’, 416. 100 Anonymous, A Year of Expansion (London: NSS, 1965), 9-10. National Archives (NA), ‘Religious Instruction [RI] 1959-66’ (ED 147-544). 91 92 12 the decreasing size of church congregations, the weakness of the ‘South Bank gospel’, and the trend in which religion was increasingly ‘seen to be the handmaiden of political and social institutions, the nursemaid of emotional uncertainties or the custodian of conventional morality’,101 the time was ‘most propitious for Secular Humanism’.102 The NSS promoted ‘naturalism in science, rationalism in morals, and humanism in life’;103 the ‘unquestioned and inalienable rights’ of freedom of thought, speech, publication and action;104 and ‘the complete separation of the Church from the State, and the abolition of all privileges granted to religious organisations’. 105 The resistance it received from ‘backwoodsmen’ and ‘moral re-arming snoopers’106 engendered a determination to recruit more members, generate more income and use all its resources to combat the wealth, influence and strategic unity of the churches.107 To achieve these aims, the NSS embarked on a concerted and organised campaign which systematically sought publicity on a wide range of religious, moral and social questions through press releases; letters to newspapers; articles and reports; and television appearances by David Tribe, who was President of the NSS between 1963 and 1971, and who had done much ‘to rouse [the Society] from the lethargic and moribund state into which it had slipped’.108 Media exposure was also sought through the publication of leaflets on a wide range of issues,109 highlighting various forms of discrimination against Secular Humanists, including the overly-generous allocation of time for religious broadcasts afforded by the British Broadcasting Corporation (BBC).110 The notable exception to this were the two talks, entitled Morals Without Religion, given by the psychologist, Margaret Knight, on the BBC’s Home Service (5th and 17th January 1955). Knight argued that, firstly, morality should be based on scientific reason and evidence and a humanistic concern for happiness and development in this life,111 and secondly, the best method of engaging the social impulses of children was to ensure that they were brought-up in a loving atmosphere112 and provided with altruistic codes of behaviour.113 The talks provoked much correspondence and countless articles and letters in newspapers in Britain and overseas.114 They became paradigmatic for how Secular Humanists could promote their cause and were symptomatic of a change amongst religious broadcasters from 101 Ibid., 3. Ibid., 5. 103 Anonymous, What is Secularism? (London: NSS, Undated), 3. NA, ‘RI 1959-66’ (ED 147544). 104 C. Cohen, The Meaning and Value of Freethought (London: NSS, Undated), 2. NA, ‘RI 1959-66’ (ED 147-544). 105 Anonymous, Membership Application. Centenary Year (London: NSS, Undated), 3-4. NA, ‘RI 1959-66’ (ED 147-544). 106 Anonymous, Centenary Year (London: NSS, 1966). NA, ‘RI 1959-66’ (ED 147-544). 107 Anonymous, A Year of Expansion, 10. 108 Anonymous, Centenary Year. 109 M. Knight, Christianity - The Debit Account (London: NSS, Undated); K. Mouat, The Problem of Loneliness (London: NSS, 1965); D. Tribe, The Problem of Death (London: NSS, 1965); D. Tribe, Agnostic Adoption (London: NSS, 1965); Anonymous, Religion and the Law (London: NSS, Undated); and Anonymous, Looking and listening - A Call for Greater Freedom on TV and Radio (London: NSS, Undated). NA, ‘RI 1959-66’ (ED 147-544). 110 Anonymous, Religion and the Law, 2-4. 111 M. Knight, Morals Without Religion (London: Dennis Dobson, 1955), 28 and 36. 112 Ibid., 42. 113 Ibid., 50. 114 Ibid., 59. 102 13 a concern to promote Christianity towards the provision of a forum in which Christian and non-Christian views could be discussed.115 For the NSS, the place of religion in schools represented a yardstick for the standing of Christianity within society. As part of its ‘concentrated campaign’ to make this ‘a national talking point’, the NSS designated November 1965 ‘Secular Education Month’, during which it encouraged Secularists to write to Members of Parliament (MPs) and the Department of Education and Science (DES).116 David Tribe’s Religion and Ethics in Schools (1965) and Secular Education (Undated)117 received publicity through television programmes, national and professional newspapers, and public meetings.118 A copy of Religion and Ethics in Schools was also submitted to the Secretary of State for Education and Science, Anthony Crosland, by William J. McIlroy, who was General Secretary of the NSS between 1963 and 1970.119 On 26th February 1966, to celebrate its centenary, the NSS held a gala dinner followed by speeches from Lord Willis, Michael Foot and Brigid Brophy. In June 1966, the latter also gave a lecture to the politically left-wing Fabian Society on Religious Education in State Schools.120 Indeed, with Tribe, McIlroy and three others, Brophy also formed part of a NSS delegation which was received by the Minister of State for Education and Science, Edward Redhead, on 18th April 1966, to discuss the Government’s proposal (realised in the 1967 Education Act) to increase the government’s maintenance grant for church schools from 75% to 80% and to provide building grants for new church schools.121 The NSS’ objection was the only protest received by the DES,122 but the articulacy of the Society and the publicity it generated123 persuaded civil servants to receive the delegation and to keep correspondence with the Society on file. News of the deputation was later reported in The Times, The Daily Telegraph, Guardian and The Sun newspapers and provoked predictable concerns.124 According to Tribe, the NSS made ‘the issue of secular education its number one contemporary priority’ because, to his mind, ‘the entire school system has become a vehicle for Christian indoctrination’.125 For Brophy, this was ‘an abuse of democracy and tolerance, and an offence against the moral duty we owe to our children’.126 Collective Worship and RI, according to Tribe, lacked ‘acceptable intellectual credentials’127 and were ‘morally dishonest’ because there was no way of 115 K. M. Wolfe, The Churches and the British Broadcasting Corporation, 1922-1956 (London: SCM, 1984), 453. 116 Anonymous, A Year of Expansion, 8. 117 D. Tribe, Religion and Ethics in Schools (London: NSS, 1965); D. Tribe, Secular Education (London: NSS, Undated). NA, ‘RI 1959-66’ (ED 147-544). 118 Anonymous, ‘This World’, Freethinker 86, no. 6 (1966): 44. 119 W. McIlroy, Untitled letter to C. A. R. Crosland (November 17, 1965). NA, ‘RI 1959-66’ (ED 147-544). 120 B. Brophy, Religious Education in State Schools (London: Fabian Society, 1967). 121 W. McIlroy, Untitled letter to C. A. R. Crosland (February 17, 1966); and M. B. Baker, Untitled letter to W. McIlroy (April 12, 1966). NA, ‘RI 1959-66’ (ED 147-544). 122 D. H. Leadbetter, Untitled letter to M. B. Baker (March 3, 1966). NA, ‘RI 1959-66’ (ED 147544). 123 J. M. Grinham, Untitled letter to D. H. Leadbetter (March 2, 1966). NA, ‘RI 1959-66’ (ED 147-544). 124 D. C. James, Untitled letter to E. C. Redhead (April 19, 1966). NA, ‘RI 1959-66’ (ED 147544). 125 Tribe, Religion and Ethics in Schools, 5 and 16. 126 Brophy, Religious Education in State Schools, 12. 127 Tribe, Secular Education, 4. 14 independently verifying the suppositions upon which they were based. 128 Likewise, Brophy argued that ‘it is an immoral imposture’ to claim we are so certain of the existence of God ‘that we dare guarantee it to our children’.129 She objected to church schools, on the basis that a ‘segregated institution for indoctrinating children is an intolerant institution’, and to fully publicly-maintained schools, because they were guilty of indoctrinating in ‘a more wishy-washy mode’.130 Neither Tribe nor Brophy believed the parental right to withdraw children from Collective Worship and RI was sufficiently well advertised,131 and Tribe maintained that parents would not exercise this right even if adequate alternative provision was available because children would still be ‘made to feel different, “special”, isolated, even if not actively victimized’. 132 Similarly, although the 1944 Education Act stated that teachers in LEA schools should not be disadvantaged if they refused to attend Collective Worship or give RI,133 Tribe held that ambitious teachers regarded opting out as disastrous for their promotion prospects.134 Both Tribe and Brophy recommended the removal of all state subsidies from church schools and the abolition of Collective Worship and RI in LEA schools. Tribe argued that schools should remain impartial and guarantee freedom of belief and expression to their citizens, and that the promotion of religion should be left to the churches and Sunday Schools.135 For him, teaching in ‘secular’ LEA schools should be limited to that which ‘is capable of universal verification according to the highest standards’ and should leave ‘to the individual conscience formulation of views on ultimate reality’.136 Instead, he recommended the introduction of an impartial ‘syllabus of social morality and citizenship for all students’ and the provision of ‘comparative religion and philosophy to senior students’.137 He maintained that, as morality is ‘independent of and superior to religion’, schools should provide practical and relevant moral training rather than RI.138 Religion would not be excluded because, in junior schools, different views of the world could be discussed in History, English and Social Studies, and in senior schools, it could be incorporated into the non-doctrinal moral instruction provided by Social Studies or a new subject called ‘Living Together’ which could ‘emphasise the importance of the things we have in common, the necessity for tolerance, and the desirability of goodwill and co-operation’.139 This would ensure that students see themselves as ‘national and world citizens’ rather than ‘in sectarian terms’.140 Similarly, Brophy argued that state schools should (i) be tolerant, neutral and open to ‘all religious and irreligious denominations, but offering worship and instruction in none’; (ii) replace RI with moral education founded upon reason and the imagination; and (iii) give children ‘tolerably unbiased’ accounts of the ‘the various religious beliefs and disbeliefs held in the world’.141 British Humanist Association 128 Tribe, Religion and Ethics in Schools, 17. Brophy, Religious Education in State Schools, 20. 130 Ibid., 12 and 14. 131 Tribe, Secular Education, 2-3; Religion and Ethics in Schools, 19; Brophy, Religious Education in State Schools, 3. 132 Tribe, Religion and Ethics in Schools, 19-20. 133 Education Act 1944, 7 & 8 GEO. 6. Chapter 31, Part II, Section 30. 134 Ibid., 19-20. 135 Ibid., 17 and 21. 136 Tribe, Secular Education, 2. 137 Tribe, Religion and Ethics in Schools, 24. 138 Ibid., 21. 139 Ibid. 140 Tribe, Secular Education, 5. 141 Brophy, Religious Education in State Schools, 19, 20 and 17. 129 15 The British Humanist Association (BHA) had its roots in the Union of Ethical Societies which was founded in 1895 by the American Stanton Coit.142 Ethicists envisaged ‘a universal and synoptic morality which would unite individuals of different creeds’.143 One of their initiatives was the formation of the Moral Instruction League in 1897 to promote systematic and secular moral instruction based on social or civic morality rather than duty to God. After the First World War, the League was abolished and the Union of Ethical Societies fell into decline, that is, until 1963 when the BHA was founded through an alliance of the Union of Ethical Societies and the Rationalist Press Association (est. 1899). (The second organisation withdrew after legal problems in 1967.) The inaugural meeting of the BHA was held in the House of Commons with A. J. Ayer (President of the BHA, 1965-70) among those present. From its inception, the BHA began campaigning for the elimination of world poverty, the repeal of Sunday Observance Laws, freedom of speech, the removal of privileges given to religious groups, and the reform of the 1944 Education Act. The BHA’s first Executive Director, between 1963 and 1968, was Harold J. Blackham. He had succeeded Stanton Coit in 1935 as Chairman of the Union of Ethical Societies and established the International Humanist and Ethical Union in 1952 with the Dutch philosopher Jaap van Praag.144 Blackham’s efforts to bring the Ethical and Rationalist organisations in Britain together have led him to be called the founder of the BHA.145 In terms of education, he argued that ‘religion in state schools’ should adopt ‘a genuine [open] educational approach that is not a Christian monopoly’ and which can ‘conciliate non-Christians and gain the support of all genuine educators’.146 The aims of such a programme would include a commitment to moral development based upon a ‘common foundation in social morality and personal relations’.147 According to Blackham, this would inevitably lead to consideration of the fundamental sets of beliefs, allegiances and values, namely Abrahamic monotheism, Indian metaphysics, politico-cultural absolutes (e.g. Marxism and Fascism) and Humanism, as well as the confrontations and dialogues between them.148 Blackham hoped that such an approach would meet the ‘real needs of the growing child’ and concentrate ‘upon the attainment of responsible living and thinking’.149 If this change did not occur, he threatened, ‘an increasing demand on the part of Humanists for alternative courses in the secondary schools and the training colleges’.150 In a later publication, Blackham also argued that it was unrealistic and unwise to expect ‘the nation’ to determine the philosophical foundations of moral education in fully state-maintained schools.151 This could only be derived from the shared tasks and ideals of school communities themselves which must seek to enable pupils ‘to think for themselves and to make their own responsible decisions’.152 Royle, ‘Secularists and Rationalists’, 419. S. Wright, ‘“There is something universal in our movement which appeals not only to one country, but to all”: international communication and moral education 1892-1914’, HoE 37, no. 6 (2008): 811. 144 M. Taylor, ‘Obituary: Harold Blackham (1903–2009)’, Journal of Moral Education 38, no. 2 (2009): 247. 145 BHA, ‘BHA mourns Harold Blackham (1903-2009): “architect of the humanist movement”’, http://www.humanism.org.uk/news/view/209 (accessed September 7, 2011). 146 H. J. Blackham, ‘A Humanist View of Religious Education’, LfL 4, no. 2 (1964): 19. 147 Ibid. 148 Ibid., 20. 149 Ibid. 150 Ibid., 19. 151 H. J. Blackham, ‘Introduction’, in Let’s Teach Them Right, ed. C. Macy (London: Pemberton Books, 1969), 3. 152 Ibid., 6. 142 143 16 Some of Blackham’s proposals were repeated in the BHA’s Religion in Schools: Humanist Proposals for State-Aided Schools in England and Wales (1967).153 It argued that fully publicly-funded schools should develop new ways of teaching about Christianity and other religions and ways of life, such as through History, Literature and Social Studies. They should also develop ‘methods of moral education not related to religious beliefs, using all aspects of school life as well as the opportunities that the classroom can give’.154 These recommendations, and the requisite amendments to the 1944 Education Act, could be justified on the basis that (i) ‘a harmful conflict’ may develop between the teaching and practice of the school and home; (ii) the rights of pupils and teachers to withdraw from Collective Worship and RI were not working; and (iii) moral education should not be based on widely questioned beliefs and sanctions, but on the common values, influences and experiences of the whole-school community.155 The BHA’s critiques of Christian (moral) education represented one element of a much broader campaign to promote the establishment of a more open, just and democratic society.156 In ‘Education for the Open Society’, the psychologist James Hemming saw the ‘speed of communication and travel’ presaging the end of the ‘oldstyle, conformist, self-perpetuating society, with its unquestioning acceptance of authoritarian controls’ and the beginning of the open society in which there is a greater variety of ideas, attitudes and opinions.157 On this basis, he desired the establishment of an open and inclusive education system that maximises individual personality and creativity, works through children’s curiosity and aspirations, and promotes socially-responsible interaction.158 Its moral foundation would be ‘the authority of agreement’ that comes about through ‘the implementation of commonly accepted purposes, directed to the realization of human aims and aspirations’.159 For this reason, he called upon schools to become ‘humane, participant, democratic communities’160 and for the establishment of a core curriculum based upon universal human experience, which would be socially-relevant and provide a ‘pattern of sense, meaning and involvement’ and a feeling of ‘unity and purpose’ which is important for social cohesion and world-mindedness.161 Summary The reinvigoration of Secularist and Humanist organisations in England in the 1960s coincided with an intense social and cultural revolution marked, amongst other things, by ‘institutional attenuation’ within the Christian churches, and the ‘institutional marginalisation’ and ‘cultural displacement’ of Christianity. In accordance with the zeitgeist, Secularists and Humanists promoted the future establishment of a more liberal and democratic society in which ethical and educational principles would be grounded in objectivity, rationality and universality rather than conformism, authoritarianism and sectarianism. On the basis of arguments from fairness and/or objectivity, Secularist and Humanist individuals and organisations, including the NSS and BHA, undertook concerted and organised campaigns with the intention of either abolishing RI (often, but not always, as distinct from the emerging concept of RE), 153 BHA, Religion in Schools (London: BHA, 1967). Ibid., 14. See also M. Hill, Moral Education in Secondary Schools (London: BHA, 1967). 155 BHA, Religion in Schools, 3, 6 and 8. 156 BHA, ed., Towards an Open Society (London: Pemberton Books, 1971), vii. 157 J. Hemming, ‘Education for the Open Society’, in Towards an Open Society, ed. BHA, 121. 158 Ibid., 119 and 123. 159 Ibid., 121. 160 Ibid., 124. 161 Ibid., 122 and 126-7. 154 17 establishing a secular alternative (such as moral education), or secularising the subject’s aims and broadening its content to include world religions and secular worldviews. This article next seeks to assess how these proposals contributed to the on-going public and political discourses about the religious clauses of the 1944 Education Act and the nature and purpose of RI/RE. Public and political response Opinion polls According to Christopher Macy, much of the public discourse concerning the beleaguered subject of RI/RE in the 1960s and 1970s focused on the question of ‘What The People Want’162 and drew upon the findings of a whole series of surveys of public, professional, parental and pupil opinions.163 The most often cited piece of research was based on a questionnaire survey of 1,730 parents in the North-East of England. It concluded that ‘five out of six parents are still in favour of the present legal obligation upon the schools to provide [RI] and the support for compulsory daily school worship is about as high’.164 In responding to the survey on behalf of the NSS, Maurice Hill argued that, because they do not understand the subject-matter, ‘the majority [of respondents] will usually vote for the status quo unless long and full public discussion has taken place’.165 Furthermore, he maintained that the questionnaire was biased towards Christianity, RI and Collective Worship; most of those who disagreed with its religious attitude are likely to have remained silent (46.5% of questionnaires were not returned); confusing impressions were given of what happens in schools; and respondents were not given an opportunity to consider alternative ways of teaching about Christianity or non-religious forms of moral education.166 A year later, Hill167 provided a critique of a Gallup Poll168 and a survey undertaken by Ronald Goldman.169 According to Hill, nothing in either survey provided ‘any support for the imposition by Christian parents of religious teaching upon other people’s children’.170 In fact, he maintained, ‘[t]he vast majority of adults in Britain are not practising Christians’ and assume that the alternative to forcing ‘other people’s children to suffer religion’ would be a ‘moral, historical and cultural vacuum’.171 Yet his critique was undermined by his failure to demonstrate that the educational proposals of the NSS or BHA received widespread public support. If anything, the opinion polls suggested that, firstly, Secularists and Humanists had underestimated the residual sympathy for Christian education to be found amongst the non-churchgoing population, and secondly, on the basis of the high nonMacy, Let’s Teach Them Right, viii. For example, E. Blishen, ed., The School That I’d Like (Harmonsworth: Penguin, 1969); M. Jahoda and N. Warren, eds., Attitudes (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1966); P. R. May, ‘Why Parents Want Religion in Schools’, LfL 6, no. 4 (1967): 14-18; ‘Why teachers want religion in school’, LfL 8, no. 1 (1968): 13-17; and ‘Teachers’ Attitudes to Religious Education’, Educational Research 11, no. 1 (1968b): 66-70; National Opinion Polls, Moral and religious education (London: BHA, 1969); and D. S. Wright, ‘A Study of Religious Belief in Sixth Form Boys’, Research and Studies, 24 (1962): 1-8. 164 P. R. May and O. R. Johnston, ‘Parental Attitudes to Religious Education in State Schools’, The Durham Research Review 5, no. 18 (1967): 137. 165 M. Hill, RI and Surveys (London: NSS, 1968), 1. 166 Ibid., 10. 167 M. Hill, Surveys on Religion in Schools (London: NSS, 1969). 168 Social Surveys (Gallup Poll) Ltd, Television and Religion (London: University of London Press, 1964). 169 R. J. Goldman, ‘Do we want our children taught about God?’ New Society 5, no. 139 (1965): 8-10. 170 Ibid., 1. 171 Ibid., 6. 162 163 18 completion rates, a large proportion of the population was apathetic rather than antipathetic with regard to the existing legislation governing religious education in schools. Reactions from policy-makers and politicians Although there is little to suggest that there was significant political support for the NSS’ or BHA’s educational proposals, Lady Bridget Plowden’s report for the Central Advisory Council for England titled Children and their Primary Schools (1967) does provide evidence that comparable arguments had gained limited recognition by educational policy-makers. The Council was divided in its views on religious education. At one extreme were a majority who believed religious education ‘should influence the entire curriculum and set the tone of living and learning for the whole school community’.172 At the other extreme were a minority, including A. J. Ayer, who argued in a note of reservation at the end of the report that religious education should not figure in the primary school curriculum at all. The main reason given was that religious education, when undertaken seriously, would involve theology and ‘theology is both too recondite and too controversial a subject to be suitable for inclusion in the curriculum of primary schools’.173 If religious education remained obligatory, then it was argued that the moral element should ‘predominate over the theological’ and that moral examples should not be exclusively Christian.174 A second note of reservation was included from an individual who maintained that an ‘alternative programme of moral or ethical education’ should exist for parents who wish to withdraw their children from religious education.175 Both notes of reservation generated parliamentary debate. The Labour MP, David Kerr, asked the Secretary of State for Education and Science, in the House of Commons, whether he had any proposals for introducing ‘courses in the principles of humanism as an alternative to [RI]’ and whether he would be consulting the BHA on ‘the excellent minority Report’ on religious teaching.176 William Hamling (Labour MP) asked what steps the Secretary of State was going to take to amend the regulations concerning RI and Collective Worship in fully state-maintained schools177 and, with particular regard to ‘the disabilities which humanist parents suffer’, Peter M. Jackson (Labour MP) asked whether the Secretary of State intended to implement the report’s recommendation that parents should be told of their right to withdraw their children from RI and Collective Worship.178 The negative answers that were received disappointed the questioners, but their questioning evidences both the pressure being brought upon the government at this time from a small lobby group of Humanist MPs and the insufficiency of their lobbying in terms of securing governmental support. In this sense, it represents both a limited success and a critical failure of the campaigns of Secularists and Humanists. In fact, in 1969, the Secretary of State, Edward Short, began to make plans for a new Education Act which would defend RI and Collective Worship from the ‘increasingly violent attack’ from Secularists and Humanists. For him, ‘all who care about the preservation of the Christian character of our community must man the barricades’ 172 Central Advisory Council for Education, Children and their Primary Schools (London: HMSO, 1967), 203. 173 Ibid., 489. 174 Ibid., 492. 175 Ibid. 176 Great Britain. House of Commons. Official Reports. Parliamentary Debates (London: HMSO, 23rd February and 13th April 1967): Vol. 741. Cols. 1933-5 and Vol. 744. Cols. 1357-8. 177 Ibid., 7th December 1967, Vol. 755. Col. 357. 178 Ibid., 24th October 1968, Vol. 770. Cols. 1560-1. 19 because ‘[i]f we do not do so ... Britain will cease to be a Christian country within two generations’.179 Nevertheless, the possibility of reform catalysed further lobbying. On the 25th March, for example, Peter M. Jackson called for the ‘moral basis of public education’ to shift ‘from conformity to traditional religion to the actual school community with its respected differences and shared tasks and ideals’ and for the 1944 Education Act to be amended, so that religion is neither ‘taught in any evangelical sense’ nor ‘taught to children between the ages of 5 and 12’ whose critical faculties are undeveloped.180 However, there was to be disappointment for those who hoped that the abolition or reformation of RI would be another ‘permissive’ reform enacted by the Labour Government. Secularist and Humanist individuals and organisations were neither invited to the expert seminar which the Secretary of State held at St George’s House, Windsor, in March 1969 to discuss the problems and prospects for RI181 nor consulted by the DES.182 By 12th May 1969, the DES had ‘received 2,268 letters in favour of the retention of the compulsory religious education provisions in the Education Acts and [only] 123 against’.183 In the end, the Labour Party was removed from office before the Bill could be introduced into parliament, but there is nothing to suggest it would have satisfied Secularists or Humanists. Indeed, one of its basic intentions was to thwart them. Summary For the general public, politicians and policy-makers, the carefully-planned, clearly articulated and well-publicised campaigns of Secularist and Humanist individuals and organisations, including the NSS and BHA, made palpable the purported process of secularisation and, at least partially, substantiated nascent secularisation theories. They did so not only through the promulgation of relevant philosophical arguments and empirical evidence, but also by personifying the progress of this sometimes imperceptible process. Their proposals provoked responses from both supporters and, more frequently, detractors in the on-going public and political debates about the religious clauses of the 1944 Education Act. Even if not persuasive enough to garner the level of support necessary to repeal the existing legislation, the arguments of Secularists and Humanists were sufficiently prominent and exacting to contribute, alongside other more pervasive secularising or de-Christianising contextual factors, to the emergence of a critical climate in which the long-term survival of religious education, and perhaps even Christianity itself, seemed under-threat and in need of defence. Against this background, it is perhaps unsurprising that some Christians and educationists chose to enter into dialogue with some of their supposed antagonists. Dialogue between Humanists, Christians and educationists In contrast to their largely indifferent or negative reception by the general public and the majority of politicians, the arguments of Humanists, which were generally more conciliatory than those of Secularists, found a more sympathetic hearing amongst many moderate, liberal and ecumenically-minded Christians and educationists. Joint discussions on ‘The Educational Justification for Religious Teaching in State Schools’ 179 E. Short, Speech by the Secretary of State for Education & Science. At the Opening of Alnwick Church of England Junior School (January 10, 1969). NA ‘DES: Schools Branch (Registered Files). Correspondence on revised education bill and provisions’ (ED 183.5). 180 Great Britain. House of Commons. Official Reports. Parliamentary Debates (London: HMSO, 25th March 1969): Vol. 780. Cols. 1480-1501. 181 DES, Religious Education, Present and Future (London: HMSO, 1969); and Prospects and Problems for Religious Education (London: HMSO, 1971). 182 Great Britain. House of Commons. Official Reports. Parliamentary Debates (London: HMSO, 27th March 1969): Vol. 780. Cols. 349-50. 183 Ibid., 12th May 1969, Vol. 783. Cols. 176-7. 20 between the Institute for Christian Education and the Union of Ethical Societies (represented by Blackham) had occurred as early as 1962,184 but from the mid-1960s an increasing number of religious educators decided to walk ‘hand-in-hand’ with Humanists as coadjutors.185 For Kathleen Bliss, in a 1965 special issue of Theology focusing on the 1944 Education Act, this meant showing sensitivity to the objections of Secularists and Humanists; voluntarily according ‘to the children of secular humanist homes’ protection from religious proselytisation; and being sympathetic ‘to the secular humanist’s dilemma both as parent and teacher’.186 Collaboration between Christians and Humanists was also promoted by Bliss in order to address ‘the tide of unbelief ... in everything but scientifically accredited facts’ and ‘the growth of secular cynicism’ which fails to provide answers to fundamental questions such as ‘who am I? what is life’s meaning and its purpose?’.187 For her, the Christian faith in a ‘secular world’ is characterised by ‘continuous dialogue with those who do not share our views’ and for this reason exposure to ‘the constructive and informed criticism of secular humanists will do much good’.188 A number of examples of dialogue between Humanists, Christians and educationists are provided below. First, in April 1965, a study conference on religion in education, organised by Alexander Wedderspoon at the University of London’s Institute of Education, included a ‘highly articulate delegation of four from the [BHA]’ among its invited membership189 and one of the conference aims was ‘[t]o consider the standpoint of the secular humanist’.190 This was provided by Lionel Elvin who was a member of the BHA and Director of the Institute of Education between 1958 and 1973. In the Foreword to Tribe’s Religion and Ethics in Schools (1965), Elvin had noted that one of the reasons why there was increasing disquiet about the religious requirements of the 1944 Education Act was because liberal Christians ‘dislike the fundamentalist approach’ found in many schools.191 Indeed, at the London conference, he contrasted the advocacy by liberal Christian educationists and Secular Humanists of the ‘open’ approach to RE, which meant ‘teaching about religion rather than the teaching of religion’, with the views of ‘the majority of less liberal Christians’ who continued to support RI.192 Elvin also suggested that ‘if Christian believers would combine forces’ with Humanists to separate religious and moral education, then Humanists would ‘put more of their energies into this than in getting the religious education period as such abolished’.193 The list of conference recommendations included the suggestion that RE in the Sixth Form (16-18 year olds) should include ‘intelligent and responsible discussion ... of secular agnosticism’.194 However, in his personal conclusions, Wedderspoon criticised Secular Humanists for being ‘vociferous out of all proportion to their numbers’, unreasonable in proposing to deny RE to the majority of parents who are not agnostic, and incorrect to describe RI as ‘brainwashing’ or ‘indoctrination’.195 He stated that, whilst it was commendable for Anonymous. ‘News and notes’. LfL 2, no. 4 (1963): 36-8. H. F. Mathews, Revolution in Religious Education (Wallington: Religious Education Press, 1966), 115. 186 K. Bliss, ‘Should the 1944 Education Act be Changed?’ Theology 68 (1965): 324-5. 187 Ibid., 326. 188 Ibid., 327. 189 A. G. Wedderspoon, ed., Religious Education 1944-1984 (London: George Allen & Unwin, 1966), 190. 190 Ibid., 14. 191 L. Elvin, Foreword to Tribe, Religion and Ethics in Schools, 2. 192 L. Elvin, ‘The Standpoint of the Secular Humanist’, in Religious Education 1944-1984, ed. Wedderspoon, 175 and 177. 193 Ibid., 183-4 and 187. 194 Wedderspoon, Religious Education 1944-1984, 200 and 229. 195 Ibid., 226-7. 184 185 21 ‘Christian educationalists and humanists’ to ensure that religious and moral education ‘represent the fairest possible expression of the prevailing situation’, the real problem was ‘the basic cleavage’ between their conceptions of truth and knowledge and between the religious and ‘secularist and materialist’ principles upon which they respectively believed the education system should be based.196 In this regard, he noted that the majority of conference members were unwilling ‘to abandon future generations ... to the fatuities of secularism, still less to the bleak negations of “the humanist alternative”’.197 Second, in the same year, Religious and Moral Education in County Schools was published by a group of Christian educationists including Colin Alves, F. H. Hilliard and Roy Niblett, and BHA members including Hirst, Blackham, Elvin, Hemming and Derek Wright. The twenty-two authors agreed that pupils in county schools ‘need to be taught about the Christian religion as part of their cultural history’ and ‘have the opportunity to share in an experience of the Christian religion as part of their total education’.198 However, RE should adopt a genuinely ‘open approach’ to help pupils make ‘as freely as possible’ their own personal commitments.199 To avoid the possibility that a rejection of religion may remove any moral foundation, the authors agreed that moral education in secondary schools ‘should be explicitly planned to help [pupils] prepare themselves for responsible living’ and to consider ‘the nature and destiny’ of humankind.200 In the Sixth Form, for example, they called for a compulsory course in moral and religious education including ‘some study of religions other than Christianity and of [non-religious] ideologies such as communism’.201 Lower down the secondary school, they called for provision by teams of teachers with varied beliefs and standpoints, the use of discussion-based methods relating to real-life issues, and an emphasis on common moral values,202 whilst in primary schools, they advocated classrooms characterised by honesty, sincerity and respectfulness, and the presentation of common moral values in such a way that pupils remain free to develop their own values.203 In terms of Collective Worship, the authors suggested making it easier for pupils and teachers to opt out; concentrating on shared values; alternating between Christian worship and non-religious options; allowing older pupils to excuse themselves; and encouraging a wide range of staff to participate. In a sequel publication, Hemming and Howard Marratt argued that moral education should neither be founded upon classical or theological ideas nor ‘a new religion or morality … which is an artificial synthesis’. Instead, ‘[i]f we are to educate pupils to live in a society which is open, or pluralistic, then they must be allowed to consider a variety of viewpoints’.204 A third example of Christians and Humanists working together is Education or Indoctrination by Tim Beaumont and Colin Bloy. Here they maintained that fully statemaintained schools should not be responsible for religious nurture because the public have voted decisively against organised religion (and militant Humanism).205 For 196 Ibid., 227. Ibid., 238. 198 C. Alves et al., Religious and Moral Education (Leicester: Blackfriars, 1965), 2. 199 Ibid. 200 Ibid., 3. 201 Ibid., 4. 202 Ibid., 7-10. 203 Ibid., 11-12. 204 J. Hemming and H. Marratt, Humanism and Christianity (Leicester: Blackfriars, 1969), 236. 205 T. Beaumont and C. Bloy, Education or Indoctrination: a combined Humanist and Christian approach to Religious Education in State Schools by two members of the Liberal Party (London: Prism Education Pamphlets, 1969). 197 22 them, Agreed Syllabus Conferences, which determine the content of RI/RE, should include representatives of non-Christian religious and ethical groups and should ‘teach knowledge of the faiths by which large numbers of the world live, and in particular of the Christian faith, still held by a large number of English people and inextricably part of [Western] culture’.206 The type of provision would be amenable to the scientific method, in which all can participate, because it trains pupils to find, receive, interpret and communicate information.207 Beaumont and Bloy also called for a policy of ‘contracting in to religious education rather than contracting out’; the obligatory provision of alternative lessons for those withdrawn; and for voluntary (mainly church) schools to inform parents of the right of withdrawal.208 Finally, they advocated replacing Collective Worship with ‘[a]ssemblies acceptable to Christians, followers of other religions and members of non-religious ethical groups’ in order to teach basic human values.209 The penultimate example is drawn from a conference on ‘comparative religion’ held in Shap in Cumbria at Easter 1969 and which led to the foundation of the Shap Working Party on World Religions in Education. Perhaps it was an indication of the esteem with which he was held and the credible position that Humanism had attained for itself that Blackham was invited to present a paper at this conference. Blackham supported the comparative study of religion because: (i) ‘education is broadened by including some acquaintance with the diversity of cultures in the world’; (ii) education would be deepened because ‘[s]tandards are formed only by comparisons’; and (iii) it provides ‘an opportunity for the study of religion as such, as a distinctive type of experience’.210 Nevertheless, the purpose of such study was not to provide pupils with ‘a faith to live by’, but ‘to give some insight into different ways of thinking about the world and human life, some sense of the history of ideas, some understanding of distinctively religious experience and claims’.211 For him, RI as defined by the 1944 Education Act, moral education and comparative religion represented three independent programmes of study, and, in the interests of increased flexibility and professional rather than ecclesiastical control, he called for the repeal of the religious clauses of the 1944 Education Act because they were no longer related to contemporary actualities or educational needs.212 The last example of collaboration between Humanists, Christians and educationists is the Social Morality Council (SMC) (later the Norham Foundation) which was cofounded in 1967 by the BHA for ‘joint study and action on moral issues by religious and non-believers’ and ‘to promote morality in all aspects of the life of the community’.213 Its President was the Roman Catholic Auxiliary Bishop B. C. Butler and its Vice-President was the Humanist Lord Ritchie-Calder. Butler believed that the SMC was the latest and most significant manifestation of ‘ecumenism’ because it sought a ‘[r]approchement between religious believers and non-believers’ which is where ‘the cleavage of society is most acute’. Thereby, he hoped ‘common ground’ could be found ‘to face the vast moral issues of our time’.214 A working party of the 206 Ibid., 11 and 13. Ibid., 8 and 11. 208 Ibid., 6 and 13. 209 Ibid., 9 and 13-14. 210 H. J. Blackham, ‘A Humanist Approach to the Teaching of Religion in Schools’, in Comparative Religion in Education, ed. J. R. Hinnells (Newcastle-upon-Tyne: Oriel Press, 1970), 55-6. 211 Ibid., 57. 212 Ibid. 213 Social Morality Council, Moral and Religious Education in County Schools (London: SMC, 1970), 1. 214 Ibid. 207 23 SMC published Moral and Religious Education in County Schools (1970). It was chaired by Blackham (who, in 1971, went on to co-found the Journal of Moral Education which was owned by the SMC) and included Christians, Humanists, Jews and observers from Her Majesty’s Inspectorate and the Schools Council Project on RE in Secondary Schools. It called upon county schools to encourage a ‘sympathetic understanding of a religious approach to life’ and reinforce ‘common foundations in moral values’ based upon ‘underlying solidarity in the nexus of interdependence which is the basis of human existence and the source of inviolable obligation’.215 Methodologically, it advocated a whole-school approach to moral education, including regular discussion periods,216 and an open-ended, multi-faith and discussion-based form of RE which enables pupils ‘to understand what the Christian faith means in the context of other beliefs sincerely held by men and women of integrity and goodwill who do not find it possible to accept a Christian commitment’ and ‘to create in [pupils] a more sensitive understanding of their own beliefs and of the different beliefs by which others govern their lives’. 217 The working party accepted that because ‘society today is truly plural, in the sense not only that numerous religious communities co-exist in it but also that a large section of it is non-believing’, the ‘State cannot legislate for a unity in the schools which does not exist outside them’.218 Furthermore, it recommended the replacement of Agreed Syllabus Conferences with national and local advisory councils involving representatives of religious faiths, humanism, parents, teachers and pupils.219 Summary On the basis of the ‘common ground’ they had identified between them, many Humanist individuals and BHA members sought together with moderate, liberal and ecumenically-minded Christians and educationists to develop educationally-valid and multi-faith forms of ‘open-ended’ RE and moral education which would be suitable for all pupils and teachers regardless of their religious or secular backgrounds. It was a vision which cohered in many ways with that of numerous academics and professionals associated with RE in the late 1960s and early 1970s, such as John Hull and countless members of the Christian Education Movement. It was also evident in mainstream policy documents, such as the Schools Council’s Working Paper 36 (1971). Whether this congruence of ideas was a co-incidence, a correlation due to other contextual factors or the result of direct causation is a moot point. There were certainly opportunities for Secularists and/or Humanists to contribute to the secularisation of the aims and methods of RI/RE and the pluralisation of its content through their invited participation in official processes of ecclesiastical policy-making and curriculum decision-making. This will be demonstrated below with regard to, firstly, the Anglican Commission on Religious Education in Schools, and secondly, the Birmingham Agreed Syllabus of 1975.220 Church of England policy Perhaps it is unsurprising, given the publicity afforded to the campaigns of Secularist and Humanist individuals and organisations, and the extent of the collaboration between Humanists, Christians and educationists, that both the BHA and NSS were invited to submit evidence to the joint commission of the Anglican Church of England’s Board of Education and National Society on religious education (est. 215 Ibid., 6 and 12. Ibid., 7-9. 217 Ibid., 13. 218 Ibid., 6. 219 Ibid., 9. 220 City of Birmingham Education Committee, Agreed Syllabus of Religious Instruction (Birmingham: City of Birmingham Education Committee, 1975). 216 24 1967). This was chaired by the Bishop of Durham, Ian Ramsey, who was also a member of the SMC’s Executive Committee. In its evidence, the BHA argued that, in an increasingly plural society, ‘the State does not have the moral authority to impose ... public education in, and practice of, a particular faith’ or otherwise to finance or recognise the ‘religious teaching of individual Churches or religious bodies’.221 Instead, ‘religion should be dealt with in secondary schools in an open way as teaching about religions’ and should be excluded altogether from primary schools.222 Although favouring ‘complete secularisation’, the NSS recognised that it would be wrong to prohibit religious teaching of all kinds because ‘teachers and pupils of all religions and none [should] be able to express their opinions, and to compare and contrast views in an atmosphere of freedom’.223 As a result, it recommended that knowledge about ‘what members of different religious groups believe … could be given either in a course on comparative religion, or as part of history, literature, or social studies courses’.224 In terms of moral education, the BHA argued that this should be ‘rooted in the child’s experience of the school as a community’ rather than in Christian teaching or worship, and the NSS suggested undertaking moral education through the example of teachers, school atmosphere, free discussion, fund-raising and practical help. The BHA believed that (i) ‘[p]arents should be ... required annually to state whether ... they wish their children to attend the act of worship and/or receive [RI]’; (ii) ‘[p]roper provision should be made for those who are excused’; and (iii) ‘[t]he right should be exercised by the child ... from the age of 14’.225 Comparable recommendations were made by the NSS. Both organisations recognised the benefit of assemblies rather than Collective Worship226 and condemned any ‘segregation of schoolchildren on religious lines’.227 For the BHA, this was because ‘sharing a common school experience’ was the best preparation for an open society.228 Lastly, unlike the NSS, the BHA acknowledged that education should ‘play some part in the search of young people for a way of life’ and it recommended the development of social-scientific ‘life-centred’ courses which would be taught by teachers from a diversity of outlooks and specialisations and enable pupils to see themselves and their society in the context of evolution and history.229 Some of the recommendations of the Anglican commission’s final report, titled The Fourth R, cohered with the NSS and BHA proposals. Although primarily concerned to advance an educational case for the continuation of a Christian-centred approach to RE and Collective Worship,230 the report provided a rationale for world religions teaching, endorsed the study of secular alternatives to religion, described the legal machinery for defining RE as a relic of the ecclesiastical era, and expressed readiness to accept greater flexibility in any future revision of 1944 Education Act. It is implausible that these recommendations were solely the result of the intervention of Secularists and/or Humanists. As we have seen, a number of their proposals concurred with those of many Christians and educationists. However, in discussing the evidence submitted by the NSS, Terence Copley argues that they ‘had, perhaps unwittingly, written a brief for how RE was to try to develop in the decade ahead’.231 If 221 Commission on Religious Education in Schools, The Fourth R (London: National Society/SPCK, 1970), 327. 222 Ibid., 326. 223 Ibid., 346. 224 Ibid., 345. 225 Ibid., 326. 226 Ibid., 345. 227 Ibid., 326-7. 228 Ibid., 327. 229 Ibid., 329. 230 Bates, ‘Christianity, Culture and Other Religions (Part 2)’, 91. 231 Copley, Teaching Religion, 98. 25 so, it was deliberate rather than unwitting. The Established Church, like the state, was an obvious target for the lobbying activities of Secularist and Humanist individuals and organisations, particularly given that it retained control of RI/RE through the statutory power of its representative committees to veto the otherwise unanimous decisions of Agreed Syllabus Conferences. Indeed, the campaigns of Humanists would draw most publicity as a result of their later attempts to influence the development of, and ensuing discourse about, the Birmingham Agreed Syllabus of 1975 which became paradigmatic for subsequent Agreed Syllabuses nationally. The Birmingham Agreed Syllabus During the 1960s and 1970s, few places in England exhibited the issues of ethnic diversity and religious plurality in schools better than Birmingham and these perceived ‘problems’ became key justifications for revising Birmingham’s existing Agreed Syllabus of Religious Instruction.232 However, as soon as the process of revision had begun, in May 1969, the BHA engaged in considerable and persistent lobbying for representation on the Agreed Syllabus Conference and, by the end of the year, the city’s Standing Advisory Council for Religious Education decided that their requests should be heeded. As a consequence, Harry Stopes-Roe was coopted to the Co-ordinating Working Party and the Sixth Form Working Party. He became highly influential in promoting the inclusion of Humanism in the new Agreed Syllabus and monitoring the extent to which it endorsed faith-nurturing aims. StopesRoe was Chairman of the BHA and a university-friend of John Hick who was Chairman of the Co-ordinating Working Party. The first version of the new syllabus was completed in Autumn 1973 and generated considerable publicity because it included ‘stances for living’ which was an inclusive term, coined by Stopes-Roe, to describe both secular and religious ways of life.233 Those who objected brought into question whether the statutory syllabus, which was only a single-page, fulfilled the requirements of the 1944 Education Act.234 The decision of the Anglican Diocesan Director of Education, Brian Rice, to seek legal advice from the National Society was expressive of persistent anxieties within the Established Church, particularly amongst the local clergy and laity, about the developing nature of religious education in fully publicly-funded schools.235 As a consequence of such concerns, and in response to the legal advice sought by the LEA, the aims and content of the syllabus were extended and clarified to ensure that the non-religious subject matter was used only to advance instruction in religion rather than taught for its own sake.236 The final version of Birmingham’s Agreed Syllabus of Religious Instruction was published in May 1975.237 It provided an ‘educational’ rationale for RE and rejected the aim of fostering the claims of particular religious standpoints.238 It required a multi-faith approach from the first year of primary school, which covered six world religions, and expected pupils to compare and contrast religious and non-religious ‘stances for living’. While Humanism was specifically mentioned in the statutory 232 City of Birmingham Education Committee, Agreed Syllabus of Religious Instruction (Birmingham: City of Birmingham Education Committee, 1962). See S. G. Parker and R. J. K. Freathy, ‘Context, complexity and contestation: Birmingham’s Agreed Syllabuses for Religious Education since the 1970s’, JBV 32, no. 2 (2011): 247-263 and Parker and Freathy, ‘Ethnic Diversity, Christian Hegemony and the Emergence of Multi-faith Religious Education in the 1970s’. 233 Hull, Studies in Religion and Education, 83. 234 Ibid., 85. 235 The Birmingham Post, 10 June, 1974. 236 Hull, Studies in Religion and Education, 85; H. V. Stopes-Roe, ‘Education and the Law in Birmingham’, LfL 15, no. 4 (1976): 134. 237 City of Birmingham Education Committee, Agreed Syllabus of Religious Instruction. 238 Ibid., 4. 26 syllabus, Communism was specified as an alternative in the accompanying nonstatutory handbook.239 As a consequence, there was coverage in the local and national British press, debates in both British Houses of Parliament, dedicated publications and a conference. Furthermore, the revisions that had been undertaken between the 1973 and 1975 versions provoked ardent criticism from Stopes-Roe. He maintained that the original had been fair and balanced with respect to religious and non-religious ‘stances for living’, but that the final version was ‘dominated by religion’.240 For him, ‘the material as a whole is slanted in a religious direction’ and, ‘particularly for the younger ages, fundamental emotional forces [e.g. wonder, mystery and love] are taken over by religion’.241 Religious domination was also evident in the contrasting statements regarding the primary purposes of RE. The original version stated that it is ‘to enlarge and deepen the understanding of the different stances for living to which different people are committed’, whereas the final version stated that it is ‘to enlarge and deepen the pupils’ understanding of religion’ which included ‘increasing their sensitivity to the areas of experience from which a religious view of life may arise’.242 Stopes-Roe concluded that the realisation of this aim would establish ‘religious indoctrination’,243 and subsequent attempts to refute this charge were rather unconvincing.244 A new law? The thwarted attempts of Stopes-Roe and other Humanists to eradicate religious partiality in the new Birmingham Agreed Syllabus led the BHA to call for the abolition of RI/RE as a ‘compulsory’ curriculum subject. In its pamphlet Objective, Fair and Balanced: A New Law for Religion in Education, the BHA advocated amending the religious clauses in the 1944 Education Act to replace RI with ‘Education in Stances for Living’.245 This new subject, they argued, would provide pupils with an opportunity to be educated together in an objective, fair and balanced manner about the religious and non-religious outlooks and systems of belief upon which people build their lives.246 To facilitate this, the pamphlet presented ‘a draft Bill’247 ready to be introduced in the next Session of Parliament as a Private Members Bill by Geoffrey Edge (Labour MP). In fact, Edge got no further than submitting a written question answered negatively - to the Secretary of State which asked whether he would remove the compulsory act of Collective Worship in fully state-maintained schools and replace compulsory RI with optional teaching of comparative religious and nonreligious studies for life.248 It was the third question to have been asked in the House of Commons that year about the statutory requirements for RI (see also the debates on 4th February and 6th May 1975). City of Birmingham Education Committee, Living Together: A teachers’ handbook of suggestions for religious education (Birmingham: City of Birmingham Education Committee, 1975). 240 Stopes-Roe, ‘Education and the Law in Birmingham’, 133. 241 Ibid., 135. 242 Ibid., 134. 243 Ibid., 135. 244 J. Hick, ‘Education and the Law – a comment’, LfL 15, no. 4 (1976): 135-6; J. Hull, ‘Religious Indoctrination in the Birmingham Agreed Syllabus?’, Faith and Freedom 30 (1976): 27-35. 245 BHA, Objective, Fair and Balanced (London: BHA, 1975). 246 Ibid., 32. 247 Ibid., 1. 248 Great Britain. House of Commons. Official Reports. Parliamentary Debates (London: HMSO, 7th November 1975): Vol. 899. Col. 328. 239 27 At the time, John Hull argued that the religious clauses of the 1944 Education Act were not under serious political threat,249 but the possibility of abolition was palpable enough to persuade Raymond Johnstone, the Marchioness of Lothian, Charles Oxley and Mary Whitehouse to launch the ‘Save Religion in State Schools’ campaign in January 1976 which soon garnered substantial public and political support. For these campaigners and their successors, whom David Rose has labelled ‘Christianisers’ and ‘cultural restorationists’,250 the secularisation of the aims of RI/RE and the broadening of its content to include world religions and secular worldviews was symbolic of a broader attack upon the Christian heritage, identity and morality of Britain and principally perpetrated by militant Secularists and Humanists. In similar terms, the majority of those who responded and contributed to the twenty-six questions and debates focusing on RI/RE in the British Houses of Parliament during the 1970s asserted ‘an inextricable association’ between traditional Christian instruction and ‘the moral development of young people, the quality of national life, and (in the view of some) the very survival of Britain’.251 According to Adrian Bell, the underlying assumptions of such discourses were rejected by ‘the most influential segments of professional opinion’ who continued to promote multi-faith RE even though it ‘represented a minority view within the population as a whole’. 252 Nevertheless, these public and political discourses help to contextualise later rearguard actions to preserve Christian morality in schools.253 Gerald Parsons argues that the clash of assumptions ‘between an essentially liberal, secular and pluralist educational establishment and a number of religiously conservative groups [was] made explicit and brought forcefully into public debate by the religious aspects of the 1988 Education Reform Act’.254 Although retaining the main clauses of the 1944 Education Act governing RI (now RE) and Collective Worship in schools, the 1988 legislation stipulated that, firstly, each LEA was required to establish a Standing Advisory Council for Religious Education, mirroring the constituency of Agreed Syllabus Conferences, to advise on RE and Collective Worship; secondly, Agreed Syllabuses had to ‘reflect the fact that the religious traditions in Great Britain are in the main Christian whilst taking account of the teaching and practices of the other principal religions represented in Great Britain’; and thirdly, Collective Worship had to be ‘wholly or mainly of a broadly Christian character’.255 Such provisions, which remain extant, evidence the long-term failure of the campaigns of Secularist and Humanist individuals and organisations, including the NSS and BHA, to garner the levels of public and political support required to repeal, or at least substantially reform, the religious clauses of the 1944 Education Act. Summary Despite failing to precipitate the revocation or significant reform of the existing legislation governing RI and Collective Worship, Secularist and/or Humanist campaigners were successful in creating opportunities with the potential to exert influence over the developing theories and practices of RI/RE, Collective Worship and moral education. These openings included dialogue with Christians, academics and educational professionals, involvement in ecclesiastical policy-making in J. Hull, ‘Editorial’, LfL 15, no. 4 (1976b): 123. D. Rose, ‘The voice of the cultural restorationists: recent trends in RE policy-making’, Curriculum Journal 14, no. 3 (2003): 305-26. 251 Bell, ‘Agreed syllabuses of religious education since 1944’, 139. 252 Ibid.,193-5. 253 F. Tulloch, ed., Curriculum Christianity (London: Unity Press, 1977). 254 Parsons, ‘There and Back Again?’, 183. 255 1988 Education Act. Part 1. Chapter 1. Section 8(3) and 7(1). 249 250 28 education, participation in local curriculum decision-making, and membership of relevant bodies, such as the Religious Education Council of England and Wales, which was established in 1973 to represent the collective interests of professional associations and faith communities. Secularists and Humanists also made conspicuous contributions to public and political discourses concerning religious education. Both the NSS and BHA received widespread publicity for their views through national print and broadcast media outlets, as well as through the educational and ecclesiastical press. For many of those who produced and consumed such coverage, Secularists and Humanists played the role of devil’s advocates constantly challenging their supposed antagonists to defend the existing statutory requirements and to justify prevailing theories, policies and practices. Their campaigns garnered support and opposition, as well as precipitating numerous parliamentary questions and debates about the maintenance, reformation or abolition of religious education. For some, the vocal presence of Secularists and Humanists in the public sphere was symptomatic of broader social and cultural changes which were challenging the Christian (moral) foundations of national institutions, traditions and values. In this context, reactionary campaigners saw an inextricable link between the fate of Christian education and worship in schools and the future of Christian Britain. In the next section, comparable questions concerning the relationship between religion, education and identity will be discussed with regard to selected contemporary educational issues. Contemporary relevance There are parallels to be drawn between the campaigns of Secularists and Humanists in England in the 1960s and 1970s and those of today. The BHA, for example, continues to call for inclusive (non-religiously affiliated) school assemblies; impartial, fair and balanced RE which includes the study of world religions and secular worldviews; and the phasing out of faith schools.256 Both the NSS and BHA continue to contribute to public and political discourses concerning educational issues and to receive disproportionately extensive publicity, considering the size of their memberships. The BHA also continues to be represented on bodies concerned with the maintenance and improvement of RE, for example, as one of the ‘faith and belief communities’ on the steering group which supported the development of Religious Education: The Non-Statutory National Framework.257 It is not possible, without further research, to ascertain whether the levels and detailed content of this campaigning, and the extent of professional, political or public engagement with it, have remained constant or changed over time. It is clear, however, that the potentially profound influence which schools have over the beliefs, morals and values of successive generations continues to be recognized by interest groups across the religious and secular spectrum. A growing number of academic commentators have begun to highlight the extent to which the ‘institutional marginalisation’ of Christianity in schools and the provision of multi-faith RE, which adopts a predominantly procedural and practical rather than ideological agnosticism, may have led to decreasing exposure to Christian knowledge, exacerbated the relativising effects of religious pluralisation, and thereby, furthered the secularisation or de-Christianisation of English society. First, Terence Copley believes that the omission or marginalisation of religion in schools constitutes a form of secular indoctrination.258 Second, Trevor Cooling argues that the adoption of a secular (or Humanist) view of the objective nature of shared human knowledge 256 See, for example, BHA, A Better Way Forward (London: BHA, 2006). Qualifications and Curriculum Authority, Religious Education (London: Qualifications and Curriculum Authority, 2004). 258 T. Copley, Indoctrination, Education and God (London: SPCK, 2005). 257 29 and values as a basis for the life and curricula of fully state-maintained schools has been unfair to those of a religious faith because it excludes a religious interpretation of the meaning and significance of what is otherwise shared human knowledge.259 Third, and most recently, Marius Felderhof argues that Secular Humanism now dominates the curriculum of fully state-maintained schools since nearly all subjects pursue knowledge ‘as if God did not exist’.260 For him, RE should be an exception to this and deploy a religious methodology to explore “what it might mean to understand oneself and the world religiously, i.e. as an agent ‘before God’ or ‘before the transcendent’”.261 Where such an approach is denied, Felderhof believes the state is acting intolerantly with regard to the right of citizens to maintain and manifest their religion. Whether one agrees with these criticisms and proposals greatly depends on one’s theological, political and educational viewpoint, but they are clearly part of a broader historical and contemporary discourse about the function of religious education in schools and the place of religion in society. Zaki Cooper and Guy Lodge have recently noted, in contrast to the predictions made in the 1960s regarding ‘the inexorable decline of religion’, that there has been a ‘sharp rise in religious affiliations, practices and beliefs’ and a growing sense of antagonism between ‘some religiously minded groups and individuals’ on the one hand, and ‘liberal secularists’ and ‘the ethics of the democratic secular state’ on the other.262 According to them, this has led faith communities to ‘feel more alienated and apart from the cultural mainstream’ and for their contribution ‘to the life and cohesion of communities’ and as ‘vital sources of civic mobilisation and social campaigning’ to be overlooked by political progressives and liberals.263 For Michael Kenny, one of the factors exacerbating such feelings is ‘the resurgence of a sharp-edged secularism associated with a variety of high-profile commentators (Martin Amis, Richard Dawkins, A. C. Grayling and Christopher Hitchens among others)’ who view secularity, rather than religious diversity, as the foundation for national identity and democracy.264 For Kenny, this is because they, like many progressives, ‘still take their bearings from the secularist ambition of removing religion from state and public square, and the unquestioned premise that religious belief is only ever a source of division within the body politic’.265 This is an educational and political issue of global proportions. It has been argued, for example, that a partiality towards secularism in the European context could be leading potentially to the complete removal of the religious dimension from public education.266 Meanwhile, it has been suggested that democratisation in the Arab world may depend upon a re-conceptualisation of the relationship between democracy, religion and secularism.267 The relevance of our historical research on RI/RE in the 1960s and 1970s to the above contemporary issues is clear. While Secularists and Humanists were successful in disclosing the Christian assumptions embedded within the sometimes hidden curricula of fully publicly-funded schools in England, they were often less 259 Cooling, Doing God in Education, 22 and 39. M. Felderhof, ‘Secular Humanism’, in Debates in Religious Education, ed., L. Philip Barnes (London: Routledge, 2012), 152. 261 Ibid., 153. 262 Z. Cooper and G. Lodge, eds., Faith in the Nation (London: IPPR, 2008), 3-6. 263 Ibid., 5. 264 M. Kenny, ‘Conclusion: Secular or sacred? Towards a new settlement between faith and the public realm’, in eds. Cooper and Lodge, Faith in the Nation, 62-4. 265 Ibid., 64. 266 J. Arthur and M. Holdsworth, ‘The European Court of Human Rights, Secular Education and Public Schooling’, BJES 60, no. 2 (2012): 129-149. 267 B. Watson, ‘Democracy, religion and secularism: reflections on the public role of religion in a modern society’, JBV 32, no. 2 (2011): 173-183. 260 30 adept at redirecting this critical lens upon the conceptions of reality and truth which underlay their own proposals.268 Through their use of terms such as ‘objective’, ‘rational’, ‘neutral’, ‘unbiased’ and ‘impartial’, many Secularists and Humanists promoted the idea that educational theories, policies and practices could be divorced from ontological assumptions and that supposedly value-free ‘secular' education could guarantee absolute freedom of thought, conscience and religion. On such bases, pluralist arguments in favour of faith schools or religiously-differentiated curricula were deemed illegitimate. Our research cannot resolve philosophical debates about such issues. It does suggest, however, that the promotion and institutionalisation of inter-faith cooperation, as well as interaction between those with and without a religious affiliation, to ensure faith-sensitive deliberative policymaking,269 will not thrive unless all participants genuinely value plurality and, in the context of education, are mindful of the institutional, curricular and pedagogical implications of their ontological and epistemological assumptions, as well as the potential ideological implications of pragmatic methodological decisions. The history of RI/RE theory, policy and practice is littered with examples of partiality towards religious or secular worldviews. Honing the historiographical record is one method of bringing these to the fore, whether the lessons extrapolated are used to justify rapprochement or retrenchment has yet to be seen. Conclusion The religious history of education, and of RI/RE in particular, should gain a higher profile in debates about secularisation or de-Christianisation in England. None of the existing accounts, for example, identify the concerted and organised educational campaigns of Secularists or Humanists, or the responses of Christians, academics or professionals associated with religious education, as being of significance. Perhaps the campaigns have been perceived as accidental effects, rather than deliberate causes, of secularisation or de-Christianisation. Maybe their instigators wished to play down their involvement, preferring to present secularisation or deChristianisation as unavoidable consequences of modernisation and/or intellectual progress. Yet our research has unearthed evidence of premeditated attempts by Secularists and Humanists to bring about the ‘institutional marginalisation’ of Christianity within the life and curricula of fully state-maintained schools in England. This was justified on the basis of arguments from fairness and objectivity, but also with reference to ‘institutional attenuation’ within the churches and the ‘cultural displacement’ of Christianity. Indeed, in the public and political discourses concerning religious education, the often erroneous or simplistic generalisations made by Secularists and Humanists, as well as by their opponents, about the religious or secular identity of England can be interpreted as rhetorical devices by which they sought to promote or prevent secularisation or de-Christianisation. At the same time, on the basis of the ‘common ground’ they had identified between them, many Christians and educationists collaborated with Humanists to develop approaches to religious and moral education that were divorced from explicit religious commitment, thereby helping to dismantle some of the mechanisms by which fully state-maintained schools endorsed Christian principles. It was a vision which cohered with that of many academics and professionals associated with RE and was evident in some mainstream policy documents. These collaborations and congruences militate against any simple binary opposition between Secularists and Humanists on the one hand and Christians and religious educators on the other. The complex relationships between these sometimes competing and co-operating groups evidence ideological similarities and differences both within and between them. The 268 269 Priestley, ‘Religion, Education and Secularization’, 16. Kenny, ‘Conclusion: Secular or sacred?’, 68. 31 number of individuals who belonged to both the NSS and BHA, for example, also prevent clear distinctions being made between their respective campaigns. Nevertheless, an understanding of what motivated Christians and religious educators to co-operate with Humanists would engender deeper insight into the secularising and pluralising trends within RI/RE theory in the 1960s and 1970s. It is possible, for example, that some Christians, motivated by missionary zeal, had such confidence in the Christian message that they believed its veracity would be recognised by their supposed antagonists during the course of open dialogue. Alternatively, perhaps some were influenced by radical secular theology which embraced ‘secular society’ or by moderate Anglican reformism which supported the secularisation of the state and its law in order to differentiate it from, and thereby to protect, the Church and Christian morality.270 In this sense, it may have been partand-parcel of ‘trends to reform, liberalism, and radical political and theological thought within the Christian churches which … constituted the effervescence of a benevolent humanistic Christianity’.271 From these viewpoints, Christian dialogue with Humanists and the development of supposedly non-confessional multi-faith approaches to RE could be interpreted positively as part of a re-positioning of Christianity and the churches within the new secular and religiously plural context. Then again, the collaboration could be interpreted negatively as a fearful response to the threat of legislative change resulting from persistent charges of indoctrination and/or a potentially exaggerated sense of the progress of secularisation or deChristianisation. In this vein, for some, it could have been a deliberate strategy in which concessions were made in order to retain the predominant role of the churches in the control and organisation of voluntary schools, RE and Collective Worship. The retention of some religious influence over fully publicly-funded education would have been all the more important bearing in mind the extent to which ‘institutional attenuation’ within the churches had weakened their ability to take sole responsibility for Christian socialisation. Overall, it is clear that further research on this matter is required. In conclusion, the history of RI/RE has, at worst, been represented as a logical and uninterrupted sequence of theoretical developments based upon the literature of selected academic writers and ignoring wider intellectual discourses, professional, public and political debates, and the multiple contexts, complexities and contestations that influence curriculum change.272 This historiographical deficiency has an analogue in broader religious and ecclesiastical history. According to Callum Brown, ‘[m]uch of the historical writing about the religious crisis [of the 1960s] adopts a fairly strong “church gaze”’ in which ‘the church becomes the primary agent of its own decline – an effect accentuated even more when the outcomes … are determined to be “not necessarily bad” or, even more, actually “good things”’, for example, liberal theology, liberal Christian assaults on social and political evils, and ‘the erosion of constraints upon civil liberties … through the marginalisation of conservative Christian political influence’.273 He argues that such accounts fail to analyse external challenges to Christian hegemonic culture and the wider establishment (i.e. state, judiciary, church, landed classes and others), such as from the religiously apathetic and affluent young whose desire for liberty engendered a rejection of church and parental controls.274 Our article has taken seriously the religious, ecclesiastical, theological, legal, cultural, philosophical and other contexts Grimley, ‘Law, Morality and Secularisation’. Brown, ‘What was the Religious Crisis of the 1960s?’, 469. 272 Parker and Freathy, ‘Context, complexity and contestation’. 273 Brown, ‘What was the Religious Crisis of the 1960s?’, 473-4. 274 Ibid., 475. 270 271 32 in which RI/RE curriculum theories developed, and focused on specific factors, namely, the campaigns of Secularists and Humanists. We conclude, following Brown, that the internal impulses to reform RI/RE in the 1960s and 1970s in a moderate, liberal, ecumenical and in certain respects secular direction are inexplicable without an understanding of the external threats which enabled those reforms to succeed. Notes on contributors Dr Rob Freathy is Director of Taught Programmes for the College of Social Sciences and International Studies and Director of Education for the Graduate School of Education at the University of Exeter. His research interests include religious education, education for citizenship, the historiography of twentieth century education and the application of historical methods in educational research. He is the Book Reviews Editor of History of Education and a member of the History of Education Society (UK) Executive Committee. He has published articles in History of Education, History of Education Researcher, Oxford Review of Education, Religious Education (USA), British Journal of Religious Education and Journal of Beliefs and Values. Dr Stephen Parker is Head of Postgraduate Studies and Research Degrees Coordinator at the Institute of Education, University of Worcester. His research interests include the cultural, political and ideological history of religious education, religious education in the broadcast media, RE teachers’ lives, and the effects of religious education on students’ values and worldviews. He is a Fellow of the Royal Historical Society, a member of the History of Education Society (UK) Executive Committee, and a Book Reviews Editor for the Journal of Beliefs and Values. He has published articles in the Journal of Beliefs and Values, History of Education, British Journal of Religious Education and Midland History. Drs Freathy and Parker and are undertaking two research projects on the history of religious education funded by the British Academy and the Westhill Endowment Trust. With Leslie J. Francis, they are co-editors of Religious Education and Freedom of Religion and Belief (Oxford: Peter Lang, 2012). 33