Title Page with Subtitle TABLE OF CONTENTS Introduction: Individual inputs on the context that inspired the selection of the topic By Marianne Evangelista By Germaine Teh By Shirley Rocafor Presentation of Alternatives Research Input: Review of Literature Arguments Supporting the Feministic View of the Self Text 1: Simoune de Beauvoir’s The Second Sex (As reviewed by Marianne Evangelista) Text 2: Germaine Greer(As reviewed by Germaine Teh) Counterarguments to the feministic view of the self Text(s) 3: (As reviewed by Shirley Rocafor) Reflection: Choosing of Alternatives and Individual Application By Marianne Evangelista By Germaine Teh By Shirley Rocafor References INTRODUCTION By Marianne Evangelista Since time immemorial the subjugation or oppression of women has always been an unfortunate social fact. Whether in politics/government, in business, in the various sciences, or even the basic level of human rights, women have always been marginalized. In the earlier days, only men were given the right t o be educated while women were forced to stay at home to perform duties expected of women. Even those fortunate women who were able to attain some form of education and some minute form of recognition in this male-dominated world were outnumbered and treated as second class citizens. We (and by ‘we’ I am referring to the whole of womankind) have lived and continue to live by the rules and teachings set out by men. It is in this light that this research pays tribute to the intellectual female philosophers who do not quite get enough exposure to the students of today. We have heard a lot about Sartre, Heidegger, Johann and Kat. But has the average college student ever heard about de Beauvoir? What about Greer? Especially as the current course of our class is enrolled in, Philosophy of the Person, is centered on personal identity – or knowing oneself and learning about the ways each one can be a true human or person – it is important therefore to consider all world views in defining and learning about the self. Poulain de la Barre, a feminist of the seventeenth century once said, put it this way: “All that has been written about women by men should be suspect, for the men are at once judge and party to the lawsuit. Being men, those who have made and compiled the laws have favored their own sex, and jurists have elevated these laws into principles.” Count on a woman to really understand herself. It is like the common saying, “It takes one to know one.” Not at all to belittle or to negate the input of all the great philosophers, it is just that our group is the of the opinion that the offering of these men generalize the view of men for all mankind. Further, there is an unwritten understanding that men have somehow caused this oppression of women. Considering the delicate history of women, whose successes and failures are polar opposites of those of men, the woman’s identity or self should likewise be approached differently. By Germaine Teh By Shirley Rocafor PRESENTATION OF ALTERNATIVES Our individual reasons for pursuing this topic on the woman’s definition of her ‘self’ has led us to come up with two (2) alternatives which we will make a stand on after exploration of the literature on the topic: The first alternative: The Feminist Philosophers’ stand There is a sound foundation of feminist philosophers’ claim that women’s view of her self is different from man. This stand will be supported by the inputs of known feminist philosophers, Simoune de Beauvoir and Germaine Greer. The second alternative: The Critics of Feminist Philosophy There is no difference between how the self is defined for men and women. This stand will be supported by the inputs of known critics of feminist philosophy: RESEARCH INPUT Arguments Supporting the Feministic View of the Self Article 1: Simoune de Beauvoir’s The Second Evangelista) Sex (As reviewed and explained by Marianne Simoune de Beauvoir, in her book, The Second Sex (1949), posed several arguments that contended that a woman’s identity must be defined by woman herself. In other words, the true and accurate view of the woman’s ‘self’ or identity should be gleaned from the lenses of women. Masculinity as Normalcy, Woman as Peculiarity De Beauvoir (1949) begins her book by asking “what is a woman?”. She then gave the response “To state the question is, to me, to suggest, at once, a preliminary answer. The fact that I ask it is in itself significant”. The feminist philosopher states that men would never question their existence in view of their sex. The fact that women do so, and with this, the existence of feminist works, proves that there is a certain peculiarity of the female sex. She claims that “A man would never set out to write a book on the peculiar situation of the human male… A man never begins by presenting himself as an individual of a certain sex; it goes without saying that he is a man.” “But if I wish to define myself, I must first of all say: ‘I am a woman’.” De Beauvoir (1949). In other words, a man does not have to assert his sex in order to be recognized; the default setting for mankind, or being a human being, is masculinity. It is the general and more recognizable sex. Womankind, therefore, is viewed as an oddity or peculiarity. The philosopher expounds: “Man represents both the positive and the neutral, as is indicated by the common use of man to designate human beings in general; whereas woman represents only the negative, defined by limiting criteria, without reciprocity”. De Beauvoir (1949) states that the world we live in recognizes an absolute human type, the masculine. She adds that even in the physiological sense, men view themselves as more empowered and absolute than do women. “Woman has ovaries, a uterus: these peculiarities imprison her in her subjectivity, circumscribe her within the limits of her own nature. It is often said that she thinks with her glands. Man superbly ignores the fact that his anatomy also includes glands, such as the testicles, and that they secrete hormones. He thinks of his body as a direct and normal connection with the world, which he believes he apprehends objectively, whereas he regards the body of woman as a hindrance, a prison, weighed down by everything peculiar to it.” De Beauvoir (1949). Man as Absolute, Woman as Other: Male Philosophers on Femininity De Beauvoir (1949) noted some quotations of male philosophers which confirms man’s view of himself as the absolute self. One philosopher is Artistotle who said ‘The female is a female by virtue of a certain lack of qualities, we should regard the female nature as afflicted with a natural defectiveness.’. Another is St. Thomas who pronounced woman to be an ‘imperfect man’, an ‘incidental’ being. He claims that this is symbolised in Genesis where Eve is depicted as made from what Bossuet called ‘a supernumerary bone’ of Adam. De Beauvoir (1949) claims that (a) humanity is male and (b) man defines woman not in herself but as relative to him; she is not regarded as an autonomous being. Two other male philosophers confirm this shauvinistic view: “Michelet writes: ‘Woman, the relative being ...’ And Benda is most positive in his Rapport d’Uriel: ‘The body of man makes sense in itself quite apart from that of woman, whereas the latter seems wanting in significance by itself ... Man can think of himself without woman. She cannot think of herself without man.’ And she is simply what man decrees; thus she is called ‘the sex’, by which is meant that she appears essentially to the male as a sexual being. For him she is sex – absolute sex, no less. She is defined and differentiated with reference to man and not he with reference to her; she is the incidental, the inessential as opposed to the essential. He is the Subject, he is the Absolute – she is the Other.’” De Beauvoir (1949). The above inputs of male philosophers confirm that masculinity is indeed viewed as the normal or default setting in viewing the self. Another philosophical explanation for this phenomenon is proposed by Hegel: “These phenomena would be incomprehensible if in fact human society were simply a Mitsein or fellowship based on solidarity and friendliness. Things become clear, on the contrary, if, following Hegel, we find in consciousness itself a fundamental hostility towards every other consciousness; the subject can be posed only in being opposed – he sets himself up as the essential, as opposed to the other, the inessential, the object.” If one assumes that the Subject is male, then according to Hegel, it is natural for him to be hostile against those who are different from him—in this light, women is the most different from him. Master – Slave Relation: Why the Woman does Nothing Given that women are aware of this oppression in the recognition of their existence by men, the next question would be, “why is it that women do not dispute male sovereignty? Why does she continue to be submissive to men?” De Beauvoir (1949) states that “No subject will readily volunteer to become the object, the inessential; it is not the Other who, in defining himself as the Other, establishes the One. The Other is posed as such by the One in defining himself as the One. But if the Other is not to regain the status of being the One, he must be submissive enough to accept this alien point of view”. De Beauvoir (1949) says that the reason for this conscious yet continued submission of women is that woman herself fails to bring about the necessary change. De Beauvoir (1949) says that the reason for this is that women lack concrete means for organizing themselves into a unit which can stand face to face with men, the correlative unit. Unlike the Blacks versus the Whites, and the Jews versus the Germans, they have no past, no history, no religion of their own; and they have no such solidarity of work and interest as that of the proletariat. Woman’s existence has been equally dependent on the existence of man. De Beauvoir (1949) says that “woman cannot even dream of exterminating the males. The bond that unites her to her oppressors is not comparable to any other.” To expound the Absolute – Other contention further, De Beauvoir (1949) states that this relationship is likened to that of the Master and his slave, where men are masters and women are their slaves. This relationship is united by a reciprocal need, mostly an economic one, which does not liberate the slave. “In the relation of master to slave the master does not make a point of the need that he has for the other; he has in his grasp the power of satisfying this need through his own action; whereas the slave, in his dependent condition, his hope and fear, is quite conscious of the need he has for his master. Even if the need is at bottom equally urgent for both, it always works in favor of the oppressor and against the oppressed”. Aside from this economic oppression as can be seen in better jobs and opportunities for men, one sees that even in her legal status, as well as the realm of industry and politics, women are marginalized. Even at present where women are slowly beginning to take part in the affairs of the world, it is still a world that belongs to men. For women to renounce their submission to the Absolute male is for her to decline to be the Other, to refuse to be a party to the deal. However, due to the economic advantages conferred by men, the superior caste, to women in lieu of this allegiance, women are reluctant to renounce being the Other. De Beauvoir (1949) presents now a struggle within every woman in asserting her existence and maintaining such advantages and liberties: “Indeed, along with the ethical urge of each individual to affirm his subjective existence, there is also the temptation to forgo liberty and become a thing. This is an inauspicious road, for he who takes it – passive, lost, ruined – becomes henceforth the creature of another’s will, frustrated in his transcendence and deprived of every value. But it is an easy road; on it one avoids the strain involved in undertaking an authentic existence. When man makes of woman the Other, he may, then, expect to manifest deep-seated tendencies towards complicity. Thus, woman may fail to lay claim to the status of subject because she lacks definite resources, because she feels the necessary bond that ties her to man regardless of reciprocity, and because she is often very well pleased with her role as the Other”.