THE FAILURE OF DETERRENCE The reactions of Slobodan Milosevic and Joseph Kony to international legal sanction threats From left to right: Slobodan Milosevic, the ICTY, the ICC and Joseph Kony Master thesis by Tom Buitelaar Supervised by P.A.M. Malcontent, PhD Utrecht University International Relations in Historical Perspective 2012-2013 16 December 2013 1 2 "The belief in a supernatural source of evil is not necessary. Men alone are quite capable of every wickedness." - Joseph Conrad, Under Western Eyes (1911) "Light thinks it travels faster than anything but it is wrong. No matter how fast light travels, it finds the darkness has always got there first, and is waiting for it." - Terry Pratchett, Reaper Man (1991) "Evil is always unspectacular and always human. And shares our bed...and eats at our table." - W.H. Auden, Herman Melville (1939) 3 4 Contents Introduction ........................................................................................................................................... 8 Chapter 1: Analytical Framework ..................................................................................................... 17 §1.1 Understanding the Man ............................................................................................................. 17 §1.1.1 Rationality .......................................................................................................................... 17 §1.1.2 Motivation .......................................................................................................................... 27 §1.1.3 Personality.......................................................................................................................... 32 §1.2 The relationship between the court and the criminal ................................................................. 36 §1.2.1 Deterrence .......................................................................................................................... 36 §1.2.2 Extralegal Sanction Threats ............................................................................................... 46 §1.2.3 Legitimacy .......................................................................................................................... 49 §1.3 Summarizing the findings of this Chapter ................................................................................. 53 Chapter 2: Slobodan Milosevic and the Yugoslav wars ................................................................... 56 §2.1 The conflict in the former Yugoslavia....................................................................................... 56 §2.2 Slobodan Milosevic, “good communist”, “Serb national hero”, and “Butcher of the Balkans” 74 §2.2.1 A ‘Mad Man’ or a Calculating Mastermind: the Rationality of Slobodan Milosevic ........ 74 §2.2.2 Milosevic’s motivation........................................................................................................ 77 §2.2.3 The personality of Slobodan Milosevic .............................................................................. 80 §2.3 Slobodan Milosevic and the International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia ........ 84 §2.3.1 The International Criminal Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia ...................................... 84 §2.3.2 Milosevic’s legal responsibility for crimes committed during the Yugoslav wars ............. 87 §2.3.3 The factors influencing the deterrence capability of the ICTY ........................................... 90 §2.3.4 The social context and extralegal sanction threats ............................................................ 95 §2.3.5 The legitimacy of the ICTY ................................................................................................. 98 §2.4 Summarizing the findings of this chapter ................................................................................ 102 Chapter 3: Joseph Kony and the International Criminal Court .................................................. 104 §3.1 Joseph Kony and the conflict in Northern Uganda.................................................................. 104 §3.2 Joseph Kony, “messianic madman”, “freedom fighter”, “devil” ........................................... 122 §3.2.1 A bunch of lunatics led by a psychopath? Joseph Kony’s rationality .............................. 122 §3.2.2 Mony me ngom and mony me polo: Kony’s motivation .................................................. 126 §3.2.3 “Somehow you believe”: Joseph Kony’s personality....................................................... 130 §3.3 Joseph Kony and the International Criminal Court ................................................................. 132 §3.3.1 The International Criminal Court .................................................................................... 132 §3.3.2 Kony’s legal responsibility for crimes committed in Northern Uganda........................... 138 5 §3.3.3 Factors influencing the deterrence capability of the ICC ................................................ 140 §3.3.4 Extralegal sanction threats............................................................................................... 145 §3.3.5 Legitimacy of the ICC ....................................................................................................... 148 §3.4 Summarizing the findings of this chapter ................................................................................ 153 Conclusion .......................................................................................................................................... 155 Literature used .................................................................................................................................. 162 6 Acknowledgments This work has taken almost six months to complete, which is quite a bit longer than I had initially expected. These six months were interrupted by an internship at the Dutch Ministry of Defense and a four weeks holiday in France. I have found the process of writing a thesis to be both fun and, at times frustrating. It was fun because I love the subject, seeing as it combines my interest in psychology and criminology with the history of violent inter- and intrastate conflict, and I enjoy doing research work. It was frustrating because time went much faster than I expected and the amount of work that had to be done, including the thesis work for my Master’s in military history, kept pressing on my shoulders. Still, some people have helped in making fun prevail in the end. First, I would like to thank my thesis supervisor, dr. Peter Malcontent, for reading through all my work, keeping my nose in the right direction, and supporting me along the way. Moreover, I would like to thank him for introducing me to the subject of Transitional Justice during a course he gave, which sparked my interest and gave rise to the ideas that were the basis of this thesis. Second, I wish to express gratitude to Jorne de Bruin, Hans Buitelaar, Annelein Koot, Wouter Koot, Justus Reisinger, and Jeanine de Roy van Zuijdewijn for reading and commenting on earlier drafts of (parts of) this thesis. Of course, it must be stressed that any faults that remain are entirely my own. Third, I would like to note that this product is the result of studying history for a little over five years, years during which I was supported by my mother and father, who enabled me to devote most of my life to my studies and always supported me at the right moments. Lastly, I am eternally grateful to Annelein Koot, who has made me enthusiastic for psychology and criminology, and has suffered through me being a boring boyfriend during my days behind the computer. 7 Introduction In January 2013 more than fifty countries urged the United Nations Security Council to refer the situation in Syria – the civil war between the government forces of Bashir al-Assad and opposition fighters which started in March 2011 and continues today – to the International Criminal Court (ICC).1 By doing so they hoped to “send out an unequivocal message” that all parties should respect international humanitarian law, a message that would have to have “an important dissuasive effect”.2 Indeed, Amnesty International stressed that “[p]eople often underestimate the deterrent effect a referral would have – try asking senior Syrian officials with blood on their hands or the leaders of groups like ISIS and Jabhat al Nusra if they would feel confident in a dock at The Hague”.3Although both France and Britain backed the proposal, the three other veto-holding powers of the Security Council – China, Russia and the United States – did not respond. In the meantime, with the international community lacking the will – and/or the capacity – to forcefully put an end to the Syrian conflict, the civil war rages on, with the latest numbers indicating at least 120.000 dead and over a million refugees.4 It would not be the first time for the Security Council to refer a situation in a state that has not ratified the Rome Statute to the jurisdiction of the ICC. In March 2005, with eleven votes in favor and four abstentions, it passed Security Council Resolution 1593, which gave the ICC a mandate to investigate potential crimes against humanity and other human rights abuses in Darfur, Sudan, where the Sudanese government was allegedly committing genocide.5 Furthermore, in February 2011, Security Council Resolution 1970 was passed, which referred the quickly escalating civil conflict in Libya to the jurisdiction of the ICC.6 Both referrals eventually led to arrest warrants. Top officials from the Sudanese government, including the country’s president Omar Hassan Ahmad al-Bashir, were indicted for crimes 1 The ICC only has jurisdiction in states who have ratified the Rome Statute of 1998. Since Syria has not ratified the Rome Statute, only the U.N. Security Council, under Article 13 (b) of the Rome Statute, can give the ICC the jurisdiction to investigate allegations of human rights abuses and war crimes in the Syrian conflict. See also: Amnesty International, ‘Dozens of UN members urge immediate ICC referral of ‘desperate’ situation in Syria’, (14 January 2013), available online at: http://www.amnesty.org/en/news/dozens-un-members-urgeimmediate-icc-referral-desperate-situation-syria-2013-01-14 (6 December 2013). 2 Philippe Sands, ‘Referring Syria to the International Criminal Court is a Justified Gamble’, The Guardian, (16 January 2013), available online at: http://www.guardian.co.uk/commentisfree/2013/jan/16/syria-internationalcriminal-court-justified-gamble (6 December 2013). 3 Amnesty International, ‘The countries that support referring Syria to the International Criminal Court – and some absent ‘friends’’, (20 September 2013), available online at: http://www2.amnesty.org.uk/blogs/campaigns/syria-icc-international-criminal-court (6 December 2013). 4 Bassem Mroue, ‘Watchdog: More than 120.000 killed in Syria war’, The Washington Times, (31 October 2013), available online at: http://www.washingtontimes.com/news/2013/oct/31/watchdog-more-120000-killedsyria-war/ (6 December 2013). 5 Kenneth A. Rodman, ‘Darfur and the Limits of Legal Deterrence’, Human Rights Quarterly 30:3 (2008) 529560, 546. See also: United Nations Security Council, ‘Resolution 1593 (2005)’, (31 March 2005), available online at: http://www.un.org/en/ga/search/view_doc.asp?symbol=S/RES/1593(2005) (6 December 2013). 6 John J. Llolos, ‘Justice for Tyrants: International Criminal Court Warrants for Gaddafi Regime Crimes’, Boston College International & Comparative Law Review 35:2 (2012) 589-602, 593-594. See also: United Nations Security Council, ‘Resolution 1970 (2011)’, (26 February 2011), available online at: http://www.un.org/en/ga/search/view_doc.asp?symbol=S/RES/1970(2011) (6 December 2013). 8 against humanity, war crimes and genocide.7 In Libya also, the ICC’s prosecutor decided to file a warrant for the arrest of Muammar Mohammed Abu Minyar Gaddafi, the country’s longtime dictator. He was accused of serious human rights abuses in the violent crackdown of the 2011 Libyan uprising.8 In both cases, the referral to the ICC was meant to deter future violence. However, in neither case did the threat of international prosecution succeed in doing this. Although the worst violence in Darfur may have stopped, the human rights abuses have not. Furthermore, Omar al-Bashir remains at large, disputing the ICC’s legitimacy and evading arrest by staying in countries friendly to him. Libya’s uprising eventually ended in the toppling of Gaddafi’s regime, aided by NATO airstrikes and military assistance. Although the worst violence has therefore stopped, this was not due to the threat of international prosecution, but rather due to Gaddafi being defeated militarily. After the toppling of his regime, he was captured and killed by local militants, making it impossible for him to be held accountable for his crimes. In the meantime, the situation in Libya has deteriorated, with armed militias causing serious security concerns.9 The Security Council referrals to the ICC bear semblance to an earlier effort by the international community to stop violence in a conflict area. In the early 1990s, Yugoslavia disintegrated and a murderous struggle broke out between its different ethnic groups. On several occasions ethnic cleansings took place and other grave human rights abuses were committed. In 1993, the Security Council responded with Resolution 827, founding the International Criminal Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia (ICTY), which would have to keep a check on the violence by issuing arrest warrants for those most responsible for mass atrocities.10 It was the hope of the international community that the threat of international prosecution would put an end to the atrocities taking place. However, the ICTY did not live up to this hope.11 The violence continued and did not end until NATO responded militarily with the bombing campaign of Operation Deliberate Force. In the end, it was military force that succeeded where the international tribunal had failed. It can be argued that the creation of the ICTY was a symptom of the unwillingness of the international community to intervene militarily in the Yugoslav conflict. By threatening with prosecution, the international community could sooth its conscience by stating that it was at least doing something, “[b]elieving that the establishment of an international tribunal and the prosecution of persons 7 International Criminal Court, The Prosecutor v. Omar Hassan Ahmad al-Bashir, Case No. ICC02/05-01/09, available online at: http://www.icccpi.int/en_menus/icc/situations%20and%20cases/situations/situation%20icc%200205/related%20cases/icc02050 109/Pages/icc02050109.aspx (6 December 2013). 8 Llolos, ‘Justice for Tyrants’, 589-592. His indictment was withdrawn after he was killed in 23 August 2011. 9 Mohammed Omar Beayo, ‘Following the Revolution, Militias Continue to Terrorize Libya’, Al-Monitor, (27 June 2013), available online at: http://www.al-monitor.com/pulse/tr/contents/articles/politics/2013/06/libyamilitias-brute-force-benghazi.html# (12 December 2013). 10 United Nations Security Council, ‘Resolution 827 (1993), (25 May 1993), available online at: www.un.org/en/ga/search/view_doc.asp?symbol=S/RES/827(1993) (6 December 2013). 11 Lilian A. Barria and Steven D. Roper, ‘How Effective are International Criminal Tribunals? An Analysis of the ICTY and the ICTR’, The International Journal of Human Rights 9:3 (2005) 349-368, 358. 9 responsible for the […] violations of international humanitarian law will contribute to ensuring that such violations are halted and effectively redressed.”12 The same can be said of the referral of the Sudanese case to the ICC.13 Although the Sudanese regime is showing no signs of giving in to the demands of the international community, it is so far unwilling to forcibly stop Omar al-Bashir and deliver him to justice. A similar analysis seems applicable to the call for a referral of the Syrian crisis to the ICC. The international community is unwilling to forcibly intervene and it thinks the involvement of international criminal justice is an effective alternative solution. Despite this, the idea that international prosecutions can stop violence in conflict areas still seems to be widespread, as is evident from the cases mentioned above. 14 All founding documents of the international tribunals established so far stress the belief in the deterrent effect of legal prosecutions.15 For example, the ICC has as one of its guiding principles that it should “put an end to impunity for the perpetrators of [the most serious crimes] and thus contribute to the prevention of such crimes”.16 The former head prosecutor for the ICC, Luis Moreno-Ocampo, repeatedly stressed the same idea, stating that “the value of the law to prevent recurring violence is clear”.17 Indeed, in the case of the ICC, the assumption that the ICC would be able to pose as an effective deterrent, is an important factor that led to its foundation18 and is “the central utilitarian argument in support” 19 of it, that “gives [it] its distinctive rationale”.20 However, there seems to be hardly any evidence for this idea. Its proponents do not seem to be able to cite any case in which violence stopped after the threat of international prosecution. Indeed, the high amount of grave human rights abuses taking place today – with the war crimes in Syria21 and 12 United Nations Security Council Resolution 827. Rodman, ‘Darfur’, 530. 14 Christopher W. Mullins and Dawn L. Rothe, ‘The Ability of the International Criminal Court to Deter Violations of International Criminal Law: A Theoretical Assessment’, International Criminal Law Review 10:5 (2010) 771-786, 772-773; Julian Ku and Jide Nzelibe, ‘Do International Criminal Tribunals Deter or Exacerbate Humanitarian Atrocities?’, Washington University Law Review 84:4 (2006) 777-834, 787-790. 15 James Meernik, ‘Justice, Power and Peace: Conflicting Interests and the Apprehension of ICC Suspects’, International Criminal Law Review 13:1 (2013) 169-190, 175. See also Ku and Nzelibe, ‘Deter or Exacerbate’, 779, who note that “contemporary justifications for these tribunals stress their potential to deter future humanitarian atrocities”. 16 International Criminal Court, Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court, (17 July 1998), available online at: http://www.icc-cpi.int/NR/rdonlyres/ADD16852-AEE9-4757-ABE79CDC7CF02886/283503/RomeStatutEng1.pdf (6 December 2013). 17 Luis Moreno-Ocampo, ‘The Role of the International Community in Assisting the International Criminal Court to Secure Justice and Accountability’, in: Raymond Provost and Payam Akhavan (eds.), Confronting Genocide (Berlin: Springer, 2011) 279-289, 288 18 Georghios M. Pikis, The Rome Statute for the International Criminal Court. Analysis of the Statute, the Rules of Procedure and Evidence, the Regulations of the Court and Supplementary Instruments (Leiden: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, 2010) 13. 19 Payam Akhavan, ‘Are International Criminal Tribunals a Disincentive to Peace?: Reconciling Judicial Romanticism with Political Realism’, Human Rights Quarterly 31:3 (2009) 624-654, 628. 20 Ku and Nzelibe, ‘Deter or Exacerbate’, 789. 21 Tomas Jivanda, ‘Syria crisis: ‘Massive evidence’ implicates Bashar al-Assad in war crimes says UN’, The Independent, (2 December 2013), available online at: http://www.independent.co.uk/news/world/middleeast/massive-evidence-implicates-bashar-alassad-in-war-crimes-says-un-8978193.html (10 December 2013). 13 10 impending genocide in the Central African Republic22 just being a few of the examples – seems to powerfully detract from the idea that international criminal prosecution exercises a meaningful deterrent effect. Payam Akhavan, one of the ardent defenders of the deterrent power of international justice, has, in his 2009 article ‘Are International Criminal Tribunals a Disincentive to Peace?: Reconciling Judicial Romanticism with Political Realism’,23 tried to cite three cases – Cote d’Ivoire, Sudan and Uganda – in which, according to him, the threat of international prosecution has contributed to ending mass atrocities. It is interesting to note, then, that in all three situations, violence has either continued or reignited despite the ICC involvement. Joseph Kony, leader of the Lord’s Resistance Army and one of the men sought in connection to the violence in Uganda, is still roaming Central-Africa and committing human rights abuses with impunity24; Omar al-Bashir remains in power in Sudan and militias connected to Khartoum continue their streak of violence, this time in South Kordofan25; and Cote d’Ivoire once more had to witness grave human rights abuses after the ICC intervention.26 But what is the reason behind this apparent failure of international prosecution threats to put an end to genocides, crimes against humanity and other serious human rights abuses taking place? A number of scholars have tried to provide an answer to this question. Often, they stress the limited credibility of the threat being issued by the courts. Kenneth Rodman argues that, because the ICC does not have its own police force, it is wholly reliant on the cooperation of state parties to apprehend its suspects. However, because states like Sudan – and also, recently, Kenya – are not willing to cooperate in arresting the ICCindictees, and third actors are usually unwilling to commit forces to the apprehension of suspects, this often means that ICC-indictees have a low chance of being apprehended if they have not first been significantly weakened in other ways.27 David Wippman has likened this small chance of actually being sentenced for committing mass atrocities to “losing the war crimes prosecution lottery”.28 Sadly, Akhavan’s remark from 2009 that “the balance is still firmly on the side of political expedience and submission to power rather than to justice”, still seems to ring true today.29 Thus, these scholars stress Daniel Wagner and Giorgio Cafiero, ‘The Central African Republic’s Coming Genocide’, The Huffington Post, (3 December 2013), available online at: http://www.huffingtonpost.com/daniel-wagner/the-central-africanrepub_2_b_4377563.html (9 December 2013). 23 Akhavan, ‘A Disincentive to Peace?’. 24 This is discussed in detail in the third chapter. 25 James Verini, ‘The Battle for South Kordofan’, Foreign Policy, (22 January 2013), available online at: http://www.foreignpolicy.com/articles/2013/01/22/the_battle_for_south_kordofan_sudan (6 December 2013). 26 Human Rights Watch, A Long Way from Reconciliation, (19 November 2012), available online at: http://www.hrw.org/reports/2012/11/18/long-way-reconciliation (6 December 2013); Office of the High Commissioner for Human Rights, ‘Côte d’Ivoire: UN call for investigations into serious human rights abuses by traditional hunters’, (6 December 2013), available online at: http://www.ohchr.org/EN/NewsEvents/Pages/DisplayNews.aspx?NewsID=14071&LangID=E (9 December 2013). 27 See: Rodman, ‘Darfur’. 28 David Wippman, ‘Atrocities, Deterrence, and the Limits of International Justice’, Fordham International Law Journal 23 (1999) 473-488, 477. 29 Akhavan, ‘Disincentive to Peace?’, 652. 22 11 that, as the threat of prosecution is not deemed credible, it is not able to significantly alter the decision making process of war criminals. The lack of credibility of the sanction threat, is also used as an important explanation in criminological comments on the potential deterrent effect of legal sanction threats. The criminological discipline of perceptual deterrence theory is an important source of knowledge for the way that sanction threats are perceived by (potential) offenders. The articles that have applied criminological viewpoints to the workings of deterrence by international tribunals cite the extremely low certainty – seen by deterrence theorists as the most important factor in deterring crimes – of international prosecution as one of the main reasons for the fact that international tribunals do not seem to be able to effectively deter mass atrocities.30 Others have questioned the effectiveness of international tribunals at reaching the grassroots. An example of this is the ‘awareness problem’, which means that not every single rebel commander or state leader is aware of the fact that he risks international prosecution when he commits crimes that fall under the jurisdiction of an international tribunal. This awareness problem is linked to the challenge of outreach. Janine Natalya Clark notes the fact that the ICTY did not have an Outreach section for the first five years, leaving the grassroots to be influenced by nationalist leaders that consistently portrayed the ICTY as illegitimate.31 Therefore, as the targets of prosecution were still receiving support from their constituents, and they did not have to be afraid of being arrested within their own zones of influence, they did not have any reason to stop the violence. Dawn Rothe and Victoria Collins note here that the perceived legitimacy of international criminal tribunals seems to be linked to the certainty of the legal sanction threat issued by these tribunals. In general, tribunals that are perceived to be illegitimate will have a hard time at securing support for the execution of their arrest warrants.32 Furthermore, Kenneth Rodman and David Wippman have noted the fact that, for many leaders of groups that commit crimes against humanity and/or genocide, these crimes are a way to stay in power.33 They need them to maintain support for their (political and military) leadership. This often means that, when they are threatened by international prosecution, the alternatives are either to surrender and be sentenced, or to continue the violence through which they secure their hold on power. It is not surprising that most leaders choose the latter. Some have also questioned the assumption that those who commit atrocities are capable of considering the consequences of their actions. Mark A. Drumbl asks if “genocidal fanatics, industrialized into well-oiled machineries of death, make cost-benefit analyses prior to beginning Mullins and Rothe, ‘The Ability’; Ku and Nzelibe, ‘Deter or Exacerbate’; Dawn L. Rothe and Victoria E. Collins, ‘The International Criminal Court: A Pipe Dream to End Impunity?’, International Criminal Law Review 13:1 (2013) 191-209. 31 Janine Natalya Clark, ‘International War Crimes Tribunals and the Challenge of Outreach’, International Criminal Law Review 9:1 (2009) 99-116, 100-106. 32 Rothe and Collins, ‘Pipe Dream’, 33 Rodman, ‘Darfur’, 530-532; Wippman, ‘Atrocities, Deterrence’, 479. 30 12 work”.34 The repulsiveness of some stories of grave human rights abuses indeed seems to defy rational analysis. How can we possibly explain or understand “torturers who insert a tube into a man’s anus or a woman’s vagina and seal into it a rat, which then tries to get out by gnawing its way through the victim’s body?”35 What kind of well-thinking individual would cut off ears, lips, noses, and kill babies by throwing them against trees, like Joseph Kony’s Lord’s Resistance Army has been doing? Surely, these men must be suffering from some sort of psychological defect, or be swept up by primordial hatred. Yet, many stress the fact that the perpetrators of such crimes are in fact not crazy. Rather, they are ‘ordinary men’, who are not necessarily swept up by some century-old, inescapable hatred.36 Moreover, when looking at the enormous amount of people involved in genocides such as those in Rwanda, Yugoslavia, and Nazi Germany, James Waller comes to the conclusion that it is statistically and diagnostically impossible that they all suffered from some sort of psychological deficiency that explains their acts.37 Rarely though, do scholars give an actor-oriented explanation, founded in psychological and criminological research, for the aforementioned problem. This contribution will do exactly that. With a multidisciplinary approach, it will try and answer the question of why the legal sanction threat of international criminal prosecution seems unable to deter (future) perpetrators from committing atrocities. To do so, it will perform two case studies, one of former Serbian president Slobodan Milosevic, who was threatened by prosecution by the ICTY, and one of Joseph Kony, the leader of the Lord’s Resistance Army, who has been operating in Northern Uganda, South Sudan, the Democratic Republic of Congo and the Central African Republic and has come under the jurisdiction of the ICC. These case studies will try to explain how the threat of international prosecution was perceived by Milosevic and Kony and how they reacted to this threat. There are various reason for the choice of these case studies. First, both Milosevic and Kony have been held responsible for grave human rights abuses and atrocities such as crimes against humanity, war crimes and genocide and were or are emblematic for the institution by which they were – or are – prosecuted. The case against Kony was the first for the ICC and an important part of its institutional credibility was attached to it. The case against Milosevic was also seen as one of the most important cases for the ICTY. Milosevic is often held most responsible for the violence that ravaged the former Yugoslavia in the 1990s and it was seen as indispensable to hold him accountable. Second, Milosevic and Kony were chosen to achieve a level of representativeness. According to Alex Alvarez, the two 34 Mark A. Drumbl, Atrocity, Punishment and International Law (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007) 171. 35 Ervin Staub, The Roots of Evil: The Origins of Genocide and Other Group Violence (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989) xiii. 36 Payam Akhavan, ‘Beyond Impunity: Can International Criminal Justice Prevent Future Atrocities?’, The American Journal of International Law 95:1 (2001) 7-31, 7; Staub, The Roots of Evil, xiii-xiv. 37 James Waller, Becoming Evil: How Ordinary People Commit Genocide and Mass Killing (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002) 69. 13 groups who are most often responsible for mass atrocities are government agents and militia groups.38 Milosevic can be seen as a representative of the first group: he was a government leader who once walked among the Western elites and ordered crimes from his desk. Kony, on the other hand, is a representative of the second group: he is a militia leader who operates primarily in the bush and is more directly involved in the crimes he is responsible for. Thus, by studying the effects of international prosecution on a member of each group, a clearer image can be obtained of the effect of deterrence by international legal prosecution. Although scholars such as Emile Durkheim and Max Weber have argued that actors are a product of their society and they only play irrelevant roles compared to the larger, structural forces that shape history, in this piece it is assumed that actors in fact do shape history. This is because it is often the acts of individuals that drive world politics. We cannot deny the enormous impact leaders such as Slobodan Milosevic have had for the history of their countries. Nor can we underestimate the impact that Joseph Kony’s decisions have had on the inhabitants of Northern Uganda. Still, it is of course true that leaders act in their historical, economic, cultural, and political context and that this context plays a role in the way they make their decisions. This contribution therefore sees national decision making as being shaped by the “leader in context.”39 In the case studies the context in which Milosevic and Kony committed their crimes will therefore be thoroughly explored. The view described here is congruent with the findings of political psychology. One sub-discipline of this research field is especially useful for the present contribution, namely the discipline of political profiling which is used by governments worldwide to assess the potential reactions their counterparts might take.40 In the cases of Joseph Kony and Slobodan Milosevic, considerable power was centered in one person. The most important decisions were being made by these leaders. Although Milosevic was ‘democratically’ elected as Serbia’s president in 1991, he made sure to aggregate as much power as possible in the hands of political allies. Through this autocratic leadership he made sure that it would be him who would be making the most important decisions. Joseph Kony was the undisputed leader of the Lord’s Resistance Army. His spiritual authority was enormous, which made his rebels follow him everywhere, even in death. Both Milosevic and Kony, then, had considerable power to make decisions on their own. Therefore, their personalities and their decision making processes had a significant influence on the course of events as the Yugoslav wars and the LRA’s insurgency unfolded. And hence, the question of why the threat of international prosecution rarely stops mass atrocities from taking place, can be meaningfully answered by studying the decision making processes of these two men. Alex Alvarez, ‘Militias and genocide’, War Crimes, Genocide, & Crimes against Humanity 2 (2006) 1-33, 3-4. 39 Jerrold M. Post, Leaders and their Followers in a Dangerous World: The Psychology of Political Behavior (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2004) 13. 40 Ibid., xv-xvii. 38 14 Research question and structure As has been outlined above, this contribution will try to answer the question of why international criminal prosecution seems to be unable to deter (potential) offenders from committing mass atrocities. This question is answered by conducting two case studies, which try to answer it by studying the perception that Joseph Kony and Slobodan Milosevic had of the legal sanction threat against them, and how, based on this perception, they responded to it. First, however, an analytical framework will be built on the basis of psychological, criminological, and transitional justice literature. This framework will outline these disciplines’ relevant theories that can be applied to the case studies. Core concepts will be described that can help us to better understand the actions of war criminals threatened by international prosecution. Then, in the second chapter the focus will be on Slobodan Milosevic. A short overview of the conflict in the former Yugoslavia and Milosevic’s role in it will be given. Thereafter it will analyze Milosevic ‘the man’ and his relationship to the ICTY. The same will be done for Kony in the third chapter. The present contribution will close with some concluding remarks and a discussion. Thus, by analyzing the reactions of Milosevic and Kony through the analytical framework built in the first chapter, this piece will contribute to a better understanding of the role that threats of international prosecution, be it through the ICC or through future ad hoc courts, can play in preventing mass atrocities from taking place around the world. Methodology As this study takes an actor-oriented approach and is interested in the interaction of criminals with judicial institutions, it will use findings from multiple scholarly fields, with an emphasis on criminology, (political) psychology and transitional justice. Also, insights will be used from criminal profiling, genocide studies, political science, and sociology. It is important to stress that, to understand the way that Milosevic and Kony reacted to the threat of international prosecution, it will be their points of view that are relevant for this study. Therefore, it is essential to analyze in-depth the factors that were involved in the decision making process of these state leaders. Or, to quote political psychologist Jerrold M. Post: “In order to effectively counter leaders such as […] Slobodan Milosevic as they promote deadly conflict, clear actor specific models of their psychology and decision making are an absolute requisite.”41 As such, it is what Post has termed the fifth, “personality-driven level [of analysis]”42 – referring to the four levels of national decision making which have been identified by Graham Allison in his classic Essence of Decision43 - which will be the focus of this study. Even though it seems well placed to study the subject, criminology has long ignored international crimes. Roelof Haveman and Alette Smeulers have gone so far as to call this unwillingness 41 Post, Leaders and their Followers, 261. Ibid., 16. 43 The four levels being: (1) The bureaucratic level, (2) the policy level, (3) the group level, and (4) the individual level. See: Graham T. Allison Graham, Essence of Decision: Explaining the Cuban Missile Crisis (Boston 1971). 42 15 to study international crimes “a state of denial”.44 Yet, there has been a recent upsurge in criminological interest for the study of international crimes. An April 2007 conference in Maastricht, which called for more attention for the subject, has resulted in a large variety of research programs, education opportunities, and publications.45 The resulting discipline, called supranational criminology, is of high use to this study and will be used extensively. Considerable use will also be made of the criminological discipline of deterrence theory, which originates in the work of the Enlightenment philosophers Cesare Beccaria and Jeremy Bentham. Although this theory has been constructed for domestic use, it is the author´s contention that this theory’s core concepts, which will be further explored in the first chapter, are also applicable to the international context. Of course, there are limitations to this study. It is very hard to conclusively present the way that Joseph Kony and Slobodan Milosevic perceived the world around them or to describe their personalities beyond reasonable doubt. This is especially true since one of them has died and the other is hiding in the bush, making any serious clinical observation almost impossible. We cannot crawl into their heads. Yet, this does not mean that it is entirely impossible to understand these men. We can make inferences from their behavior which are thoroughly founded in psychological and criminological knowledge. This is exactly what will be done in this piece. As a final caveat, it must be noted that I am not a psychologist or criminologist. I am a historian by education. Yet, I have thoroughly studied a large amount of psychological and criminological research and I hope to have properly understood the various psychological and criminological theories which are presented in this contribution. Roelof Haveman and Alette Smeulers, ‘Criminology in a State of Denial – Towards a Criminology of International Crimes: Supranational Criminology’, in Alette Smeulers and Roelof Haveman (eds.), Supranational Criminology: Towards a Criminology of International Crimes (Berlin: Springer, 2008) 23-26, 4. 45 An overview of all this work can be seen on: http://www.supranationalcriminology.org/. See also: David O. Friedrichs, ‘Towards a Criminology of International Crimes: Producing a Conceptual and Contextual Framework’, in: Alette Smeulers and Roelof Haveman (eds.), Supranational Criminology: Towards a Criminology of International Crimes (Springer, Berlin, 2008) 29-49, 29-30. 44 16 Chapter 1: Analytical Framework The analytical framework presented here is meant to assess the reactions of Slobodan Milosevic and Joseph Kony to the threats of international prosecution that were issued by respectively the ICTY and the ICC. As it is mainly concerned with human reactions in criminal situations, this framework has been built from relevant psychological and criminological research. Although, because of space limits, the evidence has been picked somewhat selectively to fit the case studies following in the next chapters, it should also be possible to use this analytical framework to analyze similar situations in the past and in the future, such as the way in which Bashir al-Assad reacts to the potential referral of the Syrian situation to the ICC. To accurately understand the personalities and motivations of Milosevic and Kony, this chapter will first describe some general notions about human nature. Are humans by and large rational actors? What do people really want? How should we define and how should we accurately assess personality and what is the impact of personality? After having answered these questions, the focus will be on the factors that are important for the relation between the court that is issuing a threat, and the individual being threatened. This includes factors such as legitimacy, deterrence, and extralegal sanction threats. §1.1 Understanding the Man As has been noted, if the actions of Slobodan Milosevic and Joseph Kony are to be accurately understood, it is first necessary to give a description of some important notions on human nature in general. This description will focus on three important factors, which are meant to answer three equally important questions: (1) How does he make his decisions?; (2) What motivates him?; and (3) How can we accurately assess his personality? §1.1.1 Rationality An important question that needs to be answered in this chapter is: How did the organizers of mass killings make the decision to commit their crimes? Were they “raving mad monsters” – to use a description once ascribed to Muammar Gaddafi?1 Were they ideological fanatics so caught up in their own world that they lost connection with reality, not able to consider any adverse consequences they might have to face for the committal of such serious crimes? Or were they coolly calculating, manipulative and completely rational cynics who abused nationalist and ethnic sentiments to satisfy 1 Andrew Roberts, ‘Raving Mad Monster’, Newsweek 158:10 (2011) 41. 17 their lust for power? Although, of course, there are some war criminals who fall in either extreme category, for most of them the answer probably is: a little bit of all of the above.2 It is significant to note, however, that many international commentators, analysts, and diplomats, as well as proponents of the deterrent effect of international prosecution threats, assume that the proper typology of the men they are dealing with, would be to see them as rational actors. This might have two different reasons. First, the idea that (almost) all statesmen or rebel leaders are by and large rational actors, might be a reflection of their view on human nature in general. Second, this preference might have to do with the fact that rational actors are a better target for policies which are meant to direct their behavior in the desired direction. This section will deal with the first reason. The second will be dealt with further below, in §1.1.2. The assumption that most humans are by and large rational actors has its scientific foundation in rational choice theory. Rational choice theory as a scientific discipline has its roots in neoclassical economics.3 The neoclassical economic view on rationality holds that when a person makes a choice, it is based on a conscious, objective consideration and weighing of all the relevant costs (pains) and benefits (pleasures).4 This consideration results in a decision that is both hedonic and utilitarian. More specifically, in this view, a particular choice is only made when its benefits outweigh its costs. 5 What the exact contents of the consideration are is not necessarily relevant for a particular decision to be considered rational. Rather, it is the consistency and logicality of the consideration, the conscious and objective weighing of costs and benefits, which are most important. As long as the decision making process adheres to basic rules of logic and probability theory and it remains uninfluenced by immaterial factors like emotions or mode of presentation, it can be seen as rational. As such, it is the consistency, and not the substance of the decision making process that matters.6 In Western societies the assumption that most – if not all – humans are rational is quite widespread. It is often seen as one of the things setting us apart from other animals. It has “come to constitute perhaps the most common and pivotal assumption underlying theoretical accounts of human behavior in various disciplines”.7 Rational choice theory has also spread into most social sciences, especially into international relations theories. The theory of Realism, in particular, has a strongly held view of man as a primarily self-serving agent, constantly calculating his way forward by choosing the Alette Smeulers, ‘Perpetrators of International Crimes: Towards a Typology’, in: Alette Smeulers and Roelof Haveman (eds.), Supranational Criminology: Towards a Criminology of International Crimes (Antwerp: Intersentia, 2008) 233-265. 3 J. Robert Lilly, Francis T. Cullen, and Richard A. Ball, Criminological Theory: Context and Consequences (5th Edition; Thousand Oaks: Sage Publications, 2011) 20-22. 4 The view that humans are mostly occupied with the acquirement of pleasure is further discussed in §1.1.2 below. 5 Anna Bonanno, ‘The Economic Analysis of Offender’s Choice: Old and New Insights’, Rivista Internazionale di Scienze Economiche e Commerciali 53:2 (2006) 193-224, 196-198. 6 Eldar Shafir and Robyn A. LeBoeuf, ‘Rationality’, Annual Review of Psychology 53 (2002) 491-517, 492-493. 7 Ibid., 492. 2 18 path that maximizes gains and minimizes losses.8 The assumption that humans are rational actors is also an important assumption of proponents of the deterrent power of legal sanctions, which will be further discussed in §1.2.1. Rational choice theory has as its main benefit that it offers a conceptual framework for human decision making that is easily operational.9 As such, it makes it easier to understand the decisions people make and devise policies that should be able to change these decisions. Yet, at the same time, a “widely held skepticism” remains as to rational choice theory’s accuracy and comprehensiveness. 10 This skepticism is fed, almost to obesity, by social psychological research into human rationality which has taken place in the past forty years, which has produced a long list of ways in which judgments and decisions are both flawed and biased.11 The most important factors that are severely hampering our judgment and decision making capabilities are computational difficulties, cognitive biases, emotions, and individual determinants of behavior. These factors will be discussed below. 1. Computational difficulties First of all, the proponents of rational choice theory assume that the human decision maker is able to coolly assess all available options, carefully weigh their pros and cons and, taking heed of their probability, arrive at the best option available. However, to objectively and accurately do so would require the decision maker to “think like Albert Einstein, store as much memory as IBM’s Big Blue, and exercise the willpower of Mahatma Ghandi”.12 Most people evidently do not fit these requirements. As Richard Thaler and Cass Sunstein, two prominent behavioral economists, note: “Real people have trouble with long division if they don’t have a calculator, sometimes forget their spouse’s birthday, and have a hangover on New Year’s Day. They are not homo economicus; they are homo sapiens.”13 As such, real people are limited in their computational capabilities. We usually do not have the time, attention or memory to properly consider all the available options when we have to make a choice.14 If we cannot objectively weigh all potential alternatives, nor have the time for the process itself, then decisions made in this way would not fulfill the normative criteria that, according to rational choice theorists, make a decision making process rational. Computational difficulties are therefore an important stumbling block for the achievement of ideal rationality. These computational difficulties are more pronounced in situations of uncertainty and crisis. Leaders often have to make decisions in exactly such circumstances. As Henry Kissinger, former Minister of 8 Robert Jackson and Georg Sørensen, Introduction to International Relations: Theories & Approaches (4th Edition; Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010) 59-92. 9 Frank Kalter and Clemens Kroneberg, ‘Rational Choice Theory and Empirical Research: Methodological and Theoretical Contributions in Europe’, Annual Review of Sociology 38 (2012) 73-92, 86. 10 Kalter and Kroneberg, ‘Rational Choice Theory’, 74. 11 Richard H. Thaler and Cass R. Sunstein, Nudge: Improving Decisions About Health, Wealth, and Happiness (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2008) 7-8. 12 Ibid., 6. 13 Ibid., 6-7. 14 Shafir and LeBoeuf, ‘Rationality’, 492-493. 19 State of the United States of America, has stated: “Historians rarely do justice to the psychological stress on a policy-maker.”15 This kind of stress can cloud the judgment of these leaders, because it makes it harder to think straight and keep a cool head. Errors in perception and judgment are more prone to occur when the decision maker is under crisis-induced stress.16 Moreover, in crisis situations the amount of time that can be allocated towards the decision making process is limited, because such situations ‘demand action’ and therefore the decisions often need to be made quickly, intensifying the influence of more simple associative processes and personality characteristics.17 All of this adds to the computational difficulties that limit the full rationality of such decision making processes. As such, when decisions need to be made under stress, as is often the case in crisis situations, it is harder to make decisions in a rational way. 2. Cognitive biases A second, and more important limitation to qualifying human decision making as rational, is the existence of cognitive biases, or what social psychologists call ‘heuristics’. In general, cognition is “the collection of mental processes and activities used in perceiving, remembering, thinking, and understanding, as well as the act of using those processes [italics in original].”18 In an ideal rational process, the acquirement of information would proceed in a purely objective manner. If the best decision is to be made, then all relevant information must be obtained, this information must be processed in a cool and rational fashion and a subsequent calculation must result in a choice that leads to the best path. However, this does not seem to happen. Social psychological research has long demonstrated that human decision making is systematically biased by the methods employed when making choices.19 These cognitive biases are a much more fundamental problem for the rational choice theories than the computational difficulties that humans encounter. At its core, it means that “human cognition is incapable of reaching a rational ideal, even under perfect circumstances”.20 This is because the human brain is not “designed to weigh all information in a coolly rational fashion.”21 Carefully considering each and every choice we have to make would take far too much energy and time, which would significantly delay our day-to-day business.22 15 Henry Kissinger, White House Years (New York: Little, Brown and Company, 1979) 483. Thanks to Jorne de Bruin for suggesting this quote. 16 Jerrold M. Post, Leaders and their Followers in a Dangerous World: The Psychology of Political Behavior (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2004) 100. For a further exploration of this subject, see: Ibid., 100-122. 17 Ibid., 20-21. See also the conclusion of §1.1.1 for the more simple associative processes and §1.1.3 for more on how personality influences behavior. 18 Mark H. Ashcraft and Gabriel A. Radvansky, Cognition (5th Edition; Upper Saddle River: Pearson, 2010) 9. 19 Lilly et al., Criminological Theory, 345; Thaler and Sunstein, Nudge, 7-8. 20 Stuart Ford, ‘A Social Psychology Model of the Perceived Legitimacy of International Criminal Courts: Implications for the Success of Transitional Justice Mechanisms’, Vanderbilt Journal of Transnational Law 45:2 (2012) 405-476, 419. 21 Lilly et al., Criminological Theory, 345. 22 Shafir and LeBoeuf, ‘Rationality’, 499-500. 20 This is why the human brain employs mental shortcuts, rules of thumb, or in psychological terms, heuristics. These heuristics allow for a more swift decision making process, which requires less effort and gives a positive cognitive feeling.23 An example of this is the ‘availability heuristic’. The definition of this heuristic is that information that is more easily retrievable has a greater impact on our decision making than information that is harder to obtain. The probability of an event is assessed by the ease with which occurrences of it can be brought to mind.24 For example, after the terrorist attacks of 9/11, in which hijackers flew commercial airplanes into the Twin Towers and the Pentagon, many Americans decided to take a car to reach their destination. Flying was deemed to be unsafe, even though the chance of having an accident is far higher in car traffic than in air traffic.25 The catastrophic events of 9/11, being on the top of these Americans’ minds, in this way clearly biased their decision making, since objectively it would have still been safer to fly than to drive. Another example of a cognitive bias is the confirmation bias, which refers to the human tendency to systematically select, interpret, and remember information that confirms their preexisting beliefs, denying or ignoring information that does not.26 An example of this confirmation bias is given by Stuart Ford, who uses it to explain why the International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia (ICTY) was perceived in such a negative way by much of the Serbian population, even after the ICTY started a meaningful outreach campaign. In Ford’s view, as the Serbian population had a strong, preexisting negative opinion about the ICTY, the information that became available by the ICTY’s outreach efforts was consistently ignored or interpreted in such a way that it confirmed the Serbs’ negative view about the tribunal. The Serbian population selected only those pieces of information that did not conflict with their preexisting beliefs. In this way, because of the confirmation bias, the ICTY’s outreach efforts, which tried to counter these negative narratives, had only limited effect.27 A third phenomenon that stands in the way of an objective assessment of the costs and benefits of any given choice, is what is known to psychologists as ‘loss aversion’.28 This means that a loss of an object is considered more aversive than the gain of the same object is considered attractive.29 Therefore a choice can be framed to influence the decision that is made. A different presentation of events, where something is presented as a loss instead of a gain, can thus significantly alter the choice being made, Rainer Greifeneder, Herbert Bless, and Michel Tuan Pham, ‘When Do People Rely on Affective and Cognitive Feelings in Judgment?: A Review’, Personality and Social Psychological Review 15:2 (2010) 107141, 109-110. 24 Amos Tversky and Daniel Kahneman, ‘Availability: A Heuristic for Judging Frequency and Probability’, Cognitive Psychology 5:2 (1973) 207-232. 25 Thanks to Annelein Koot for the example. 26 Raymond S. Nickerson, ‘Confirmation Bias: A Ubiquitous Phenomenon in Many Guises’, Review of General Psychology 2:2 (1998) 175-220. 27 Ford, ‘Social Psychology Model’, 433-439. 28 Amos Tversky and Daniel Kahneman, ‘Loss Aversion in Riskless Choice: A Reference Dependent Model’, Quarterly Journal of Economics 106:4 (1991) 1039-1061. 29 Shafir and LeBoeuf, ‘Rationality’, 496. 23 21 even though the objective situation is the same.30 Related to this is the ‘endowment effect’, “wherein the mere possession of a good can lead to a higher valuation of it than if it were not in one’s possession […] [and] the disadvantages of departing from it loom larger than the advantages of the alternatives”, which leads to “a general reluctance to […] depart from the status quo”.31 Loss aversion and the endowment effect are phenomena that seem to occur frequently in politics. As attractive it is to acquire power, power is also often hard to give away after it has been acquired. After a significant social status is achieved, the risk of losing it can weigh heavily on a person’s mind. This may result in a significant effort to maintain it. There are plenty examples of genocidaires who linked their social status to the crimes that they ordered. For them, these crimes are a way to maintain their hold on power. As such, stopping these crimes because of a threat of international criminal prosecution might result in a loss of power for them and therefore looks like a disadvantageous option. The endowment effect can thus give a behavioral economical perspective on history’s many examples of political leaders doing everything they can to maintain their hold on power. 3. Emotions The third problem with (neoclassical) rational choice theory is that it assumes that decisions are made in an objective, emotionally ‘cool’ manner. This implies that factors such as mood, emotional state and feelings should not affect the decision making process. Therefore, in this view, a person would make the same decision in a happy mood as in a sad mood. However, once again, social psychological research has shown that this view is incorrect.32 There are many ways in which such transient moods affect choice and judgment. For example, a positive mood leads to a higher perceived frequency of desirable events.33 This is often seen in day-to-day life. When a person is in a very happy mood, he is ‘away with the fairies’, unrealistically positive in his expectations. This works the other way around when someone is in a very negative mood. An extreme example of transient moods affecting behavior is bipolar disorder. People who suffer from bipolar disorder, formerly known as manic depressive disorder, are frequently experiencing extreme manifestations of both positive moods – manic episodes, in which they think that everything is great, that they can do everything they want, that no harm can come to them etc., often with disastrous effects – and negative moods – depressive episodes, in which they can become suicidal, cannot concentrate, do not want to eat etc.34 Our mood, being happy or sad, therefore clearly affects our decision making process. This contradicts the tenets of rationality, which subsumes that emotions do not Amos Tversky and Daniel Kahneman, ‘Rational Choice and the Framing of Decisions’, The Journal of Business 59:4 (1986) 251-278. 31 Shafir and LeBoeuf, ‘Rationality’, 496. See also Daniel Kahneman, Jack L. Knetsch and Richard H. Thaler, ‘Experimental Tests of the Endowment Effect and the Coase Theorem’, Journal of Political Economy 98:6 (1990) 1325-1348. 32 Greifeneder et al., ‘Affective and Cognitive Feelings’, 107. 33 Shafir and LeBoeuf, ‘Rationality’, 498. 34 Benjamin J. Sadock and Virginia A. Sadock, Kaplan & Sadock’s Synopsis of Psychiatry (10th Edition; Philadelphia: Lippincott Williams & Wilkins, 2007) 527-562. 30 22 – or should not – play a role in the making of decisions, because that would mean that the decision making process is not always the same for the same person.35 Besides these transient moods, it has also been shown that visceral factors – “the cravings associated with drug addiction, drive states (e.g. hunger, thirst, and sexual desire), moods and emotions, and physical pain”36 – can have a direct impact on behavior. They change the perceptions of costs and benefits, of risks and opportunities, and subsequently the perception of what behavior is appropriate.37 George Loewenstein describes the process in which strong visceral factors, such as a strong sexual desire, extreme anger, or physical pain, can give the experiencer the feeling of being ‘out of control’. It can lead them to act in a direct contradiction to their self-interest. Even when they are perfectly aware of the irrationality of their desire, the desire is stronger than the ‘rational’ mind, and the person has to act on it.38 Visceral states impact behavior in three ways. First, they narrow the person’s attention to those things that are related to the specific visceral state. Second, visceral states focus the person’s mind on short-term decisions to resolve the state quickly. Third, the attention of the person experiencing the visceral state moves primarily inward, making it much harder to show concern for others when deliberating an action.39 These extreme emotional states therefore significantly shortcut rational deliberation, focusing the person’s entire attention towards the satisfaction of his own needs. Sexual arousal, for example, has been shown to have a significant effect on the willingness of a potential offender to engage in sexual coercion.40 When war criminals make decisions, then, emotions or moods such as anger and fear might impact their decision making process. Slobodan Milosevic was known to throw tantrums against the West and, although to some extent these might have been mere theater, it does not seem unreasonable to assume that at times he was genuinely angry, feeling victimized and unrecognized. Such emotions most definitely would have had a large impact on his behavior. This will be further explored in the case studies below. Another emotional factor that has been shown to impact judgment, are affective feelings. Affective feelings towards a given subject impact a person’s behavior towards it. As one meta-review states, “the list of judgments on which affective feelings have been shown to have an impact appears to be endless”.41 This has led some scholars to suggest the existence of an ‘affect heuristic’.42 It is often heard that someone does something because it “feels right” or does not do something because it does Shafir and LeBoeuf, ‘Rationality’, 498-499. George Loewenstein, ‘Out of Control: Visceral Influences on Behavior’, Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 65:3 (1996) 272-292, 272-273. 37 Ibid., 273. 38 Ibid., 273-274. 39 Jeffrey A. Bouffard, ‘The Influence of Emotion on Rational Decision Making in Sexual Aggression’, Journal of Criminal Justice 30:2 (2002) 121-134, 122. He summarizes Loewenstein, ‘Out of Control’, 274-276. 40 Paradoxically, sexual arousal seems to increase the awareness of negative consequences that sexual coercion might have. For more on this, see: George Loewenstein, Daniel Nagin and Raymond Paternoster, ‘The Effect of Sexual Arousal on Expectations of Sexual Forcefulness’, Journal of Research in Crime and Delinquency 34:4 (1997) 443-473. For a further exploration of this paradox, see: Bouffard, ‘The Influence of Emotion’, 122-123. 41 Greifeneder et al., ‘Affective and Cognitive Feelings’, 109. 42 Shafir and LeBoeuf, ‘Rationality’, 499. 35 36 23 not “feel right.” Such feelings are especially influential when they are salient in someone’s mind.43 The reliance on feelings in forming our judgment goes further than this, however. We form judgments about objects, often unconsciously, on the basis of how they make us feel.44 It has been shown, for example, that political candidates are often chosen for the way that people “feel” about them – not just about their political statements but about the person him- or herself.45 This is often a significant reservoir of support for charismatic leaders. The fact that they are chosen is less a consequence of their political opinions, than it is a consequence of the way that they make people feel.46 The reason why this is problematic for the assumptions of rational choice theory, is that these feelings are not quantifiable, objective, or ‘rational’ sources of information. They are often extremely subjective. When a person makes a choice in an intuitive way – because he “feels good” about it –, it rarely leads him to the outcome that is objectively ‘best’ for him.47 4. Individual differences A fourth counterargument against the view that humans are rational actors, is the persistence of individual differences as determinants of behavior. These differences go further than the substance level of judgment and decision making, which, as has been noted above, does not necessarily run counter to rational choice theory. Individual differences also significantly affect the consistency level of people’s decision making processes, which means that not everybody makes decisions in the same way. One clear example of people who make decisions in a clearly irrational way are people with psychopathological problems, like paranoid schizophrenia, clinical psychopathy, or psychotic illnesses. Although there are some instances in history in which state or rebel leaders suffered from these mental difficulties – Joseph Stalin was thought to suffer from or at least have characteristics of paranoid schizophrenia,48 Adolf Hitler is often described as a psychopath49 - we can assume that most people who have made it to the leadership position of a social group or state, have shown that they are able to think straight and are not severely hampered in their decision making capabilities by some sort of debilitating mental disease. Therefore people with mental illnesses could be put away as anomalies and we could still assume that most of us are rational in the same way. However, there are many other differences between individuals that have a large impact on the way that decisions are made. They alter the perceptions of costs and benefits and dictate what choices are seen as desirable. These individual differences therefore significantly affect the decision making Greifeneder et al., ‘Affective and Cognitive Feelings’, 113. Ibid., 129-130. Shafir and LeBoeuf, ‘Rationality’, 499. 45 Greifeneder et al., ‘Affective and Cognitive Feelings’, 111. 46 David P. Redlawsk, ‘Hot Cognition or Cool Consideration? Testing the Effects of Motivated Reasoning on Political Decision Making’, Journal of Politics 64:4 (2002) 1021-1044, 1039-1041. 47 Shafir and LeBoeuf, ‘Rationality’, 499. However, for an argument that there is in fact nothing wrong with the use of feelings as a guideline for action, see: Greifeneder et al., ‘Affective and Cognitive Feelings’, 130-132. 48 See, for example: Robert Service, Stalin: A Biography (Harvard: Harvard University Press, 2006). 49 See, for example: Ian Kershaw, Hitler: 1936-1945 (New York: W.W. Norton, 2000). 43 44 24 process and thus lead to different behavioral tendencies. An important example of the way that individual differences impact our behavior, is the finding by criminologists that people differ in their criminal propensity.50 There are certain individual traits and characteristics that are stable over time, which have been shown to predict crime. One of these is what has been called self-control, a psychological construct that, at its core, describes the extent to which individuals are present-oriented (as opposed to future-oriented).51 Present-oriented individuals tend to overrate the gains that can be gained in the here and now, while significantly underrating costs that lay in the future.52 Since most crimes offer direct satisfaction, it has been suggested that individuals who score high on presentorientation, are more attracted to criminal options and therefore more criminally prone.53 Also, according to Raymond Paternoster, since legal sanctions often follow only much later – if at all – the criminal justice system is ineffective at deterring these individuals.54 Furthermore, decision making processes can be influenced by cultural imperatives, like the prevalent attitudes towards risk taking.55 In some cultures, risk taking is discouraged – “better safe than sorry” – while in others it is accepted and sometimes even encouraged, with the end justifying the means. At the same time, differences between cultures in their attitudes towards impulsivity and emotionality can have a large impact on decision making processes. While in some cultures it is not accepted to “speak out of turn”, other cultures glorify the impulsive, intuitive response. Thoughtful, carefully considered actions, are therefore not always the proper choice. Cultural attitudes like the ones named above can significantly alter the way that the decision making process takes place, or sometimes even shortcut rational considerations. A last important individual difference that has a large impact on decision making is personality. It has been shown that personality is a significant predictor of behavior. As it is so important, personality is described in a separate section, §1.1.3. Daniel S. Nagin and Raymond Paternoster, ‘Enduring Individual Differences and Rational Choice Theories of Crime’, Law and Society Review 27:3 (1993) 467-496, 469-470. 51 Michael R. Gottfredson and Travis Hirschi, A General Theory of Crime (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1990) 85-120. 52 Greg Pogarsky, ‘Deterrence and Decision Making: Research Questions and Theoretical Refinements’, in: Marvin D. Krohn et al. (eds.), Handbook on Crime and Deviance (Berlin: Springer, 2009) 241-258, 243. 53 Nagin and Paternoster, ‘Enduring Individual Differences’, 471-473. 54 Raymond Paternoster, ‘How Much Do We Really Know About Criminal Deterrence?’, The Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology 100:3 (2010) 765-823, 821. For a counterpoint, see: Greg Pogarsky, ‘Deterrence and Individual Differences Among Convicted Offenders’, Journal of Quantitative Criminology 23:1 (2007) 5974. 55 Post, Leaders and Their Followers, x-xi. Foreword by Alexander L. George. 50 25 In conclusion Having outlined four major limitations of rational choice theory – computational difficulties, cognitive biases, emotions, and individual differences – it must be concluded that the idea that humans are rational decision makers who consciously and carefully make decisions on the basis of hedonic cost-benefit calculations is by and large incorrect. The evidence emanating from social psychological research, which shows that humans are not simply self-serving, rational agents, is overwhelming. Although rational choice theory offers a simplified conceptual framework for understanding human decision making which is easily operational, in the face of such overwhelming evidence, it seems unreasonable to hold on to the belief that the explanation which it offers is either comprehensive or accurate. Rationality scholars, and especially its critics, have proposed multiple alternatives to rational choice theory. One of these is the dual process model, which holds that there are two coexisting processes of reasoning and judgment within the human brain. The first is a process of reasoning, “that makes relatively automatic inferences and judgments through mainly associative means”,56 which would be the process that we use in our day-to-day decisions and activities. The second process would be the one that is used for more deliberate, important decisions, a process that “makes relatively effortful inferences by following a set of explicitly normative rules”.57 This dual process model would explain why most of us are able to rationalize many decisions, in fact sometimes do spend some time to calculate the best decision, yet at the same time make many spontaneous, impulsive and unconscious decisions which are not always in our best interests. However, even the second process of reasoning, the more deliberate one, falls prey to the many limits on rationality which have been described above. It would still suffer from cognitive biases in the collection of information, for example. Because of the inherent flaws of human decision making, some scholars have suggested that we should not see human decision making as the cost-benefit calculus that rational theory scholars propose. Rather, we should see it as ‘bounded rationality’, or ‘instrumental rationality’.58 This view has two main aspects. First, human behavior can be understood as purposive: we act to achieve goals. Second, humans attempt to avoid outcomes that they perceive to be undesirable and strive to achieve outcomes that they perceive to be desirable.59 In this way, human behavior certainly does respond to incentives and disincentives, although in different manners and definitely not always in the way that we expect them to. This more nuanced view on human rationality is much more plausible and is the one that will be adopted in this study. It will be helpful in explaining why Slobodan Milosevic and Joseph Kony did not respond to the threats of international prosecution in the way that the issuers of those threats expected them to. Shafir and LeBoeuf, ‘Rationality’, 500. Ibid. 58 Kalter and Kroneberg, ‘Rational Choice Theory’, 86. 59 J. von H., Holtermann, ‘A “Slice of Cheese” – a Deterrence-Based Argument for the International Criminal Court’, Human Rights Review 11:3 (2010) 289-315, 295; Pogarsky, ‘Decision and Decision Making’, 241. 56 57 26 §1.1.2 Motivation Despite all the limitations on our judgment and decision making capabilities, it would be folly to say that we are just doing something. We do things for a reason. What is it then that motivates us? Why do we do what we do? What do people really want? As answering these questions is critical to adequately explaining a person’s behavior,60 this section will explore how scientists have usually explained what motivates human behavior. Multiple answers to the questions outlined above have been suggested. One of the most influential ones is that people want to maximize pleasure and minimize pain, arguably “[t]he most common answer historically”.61 There is little question that this hedonic explanation of human behavior is very often an appropriate answer. The want of pleasure is sometimes even more important than the need for survival. As motivation scholar E. Tory Higgins states, “[i]t has been known for over half a century that animals will choose on the basis of hedonic experiences independent of any biological need being satisfied”.62 However, a major problem with the ‘pleasure and pain’-explanation is that it is often used for the motivation of simplified policies which are intended to influence human behavior.63 When maximizing pleasure and minimizing pain is really all that people want, then wielding what is called the carrot and the stick should be effective in guiding someone’s behavior in the direction that is desired. Simply by promising pleasure – the carrot – and/or threatening with pain – the stick – the desirable behavior should be achieved. This policy of “wielding the carrot and the stick” is something that is often seen in diplomacy. An example of this is the behavior of the Western world towards states like Iran and North Korea. Both states are pulling in directions that are perceived to be undesirable by the Western world, in particular by the United States. To influence their behavior, a wide range of sanctions has been imposed. International prosecution is also at its core based on this idea. However, this policy is quite often unsuccessful in achieving the outcome that is desired by the Western world. In part, this is because this answer to the question of why people do what they do might be oversimplified. The duality of ‘pleasure’ versus ‘pain’ leaves out options that lay in between as well as goals that cannot be classified as either a ‘pleasure’ or a ‘pain’. Furthermore, in international relations, the avoidance of pain might not be as important to some actors as it is to others. In the examples of North Korea and Iran this pain only reaffirms the perceived hostility emanating from the West. As such, it is a useful tool to reconfirm pre-existing feelings of victimization and isolation within the general populace and therefore this ‘pain’ converts into a ‘pleasure’. Thus, the notion that humans are motivated See: Daniel J. Goldhagen, Hitler’s Willing Executioners: Ordinary Germans and the Holocaust (New York: Vintage, 1997) 19-22, who argues convincingly for the need to understand the motives of the perpetrators of mass atrocities. 61 E. Tory Higgins, Beyond Pleasure and Pain: How Motivation Works (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011) 29. 62 Ibid., 29-30. Survival of course, is also a very important motivational force. People who are poor, can spend whole days being occupied with the acquirement of sufficient nutrients. According to Abraham Maslow’s ‘hierarchy of needs’, the fulfillment of physiological needs is the most important. These need to be fulfilled before human beings start wanting more complex things that are higher in his hierarchy. See: Abraham Maslow, ‘A Theory of Human Motivation’, Psychological Review 50:4 (1943) 370-396. 63 Higgins, Beyond Pleasure and Pain, 11-12. 60 27 by the maximization of pleasure and the minimization of pain does not seem to give a satisfactory answer to this section’s questions. Higgins offers a more convincing answer. His idea is that what people really want is to be effective.64 Motivation, then, is “directing choices in order to be effective”.65 He identifies three forms of effectiveness that are essential in his eyes. The first is ‘value effectiveness’, which he defines as “being successful in having what’s desired”.66 Second, ‘truth effectiveness’ – which he sees as “being successful in establishing what’s real”.67 Third and last, he identifies “control effectiveness” as an important component of being effective which is desired by humans. Having control effectiveness means “being successful in managing what happens”.68 According to Higgins, these three components, which are especially strong when working together,69 are the main motivators of human action. The visions described above are essentially meta-visions of human motivation. The idea that people want to be successful in having what they desire, leaves much room to explain the differences between the desires of certain individuals and how intensely they seek to acquire them. Much of this room can be filled by values. Values are an important source of motivation. They are factors that are inherent to a person and guide his actions. More specifically, they are “cognitive representations of desirable, abstract, trans-situational goals that serve as guiding principles in people’s life”,70 or “an experience of strength of motivational force”.71 We strive to obtain the things that we value, be it some sort of abstract construct – power, recognition, and the like – or a rather concrete object, like food or money. As such, the valuation of a specific goal leads to an experience of motivation to obtain it. What is interesting to note, especially for the case studies, is that multiple experiments have shown that a person values something higher, when he has to overcome an obstacle to obtain it. In psychological terms: the opposition of an interfering force leads to higher strength of engagement with the completion of the goal, which in turn makes the person assign a higher value to the goal.72 When a person is highly committed to a goal, an intervention, such as a threat of prosecution, will only increase his commitment. Thus, in such a situation, an intervention can be counterproductive. It must be noted, however, that when enough opposition is encountered a goal will in most cases be dropped eventually. There are instances, however, in which people refuse to give up a goal, even in the face of overwhelming 64 Ibid., 44. Ibid., 42. 66 Ibid., 49-51. 67 Ibid., 51-52. 68 Ibid., 53-56. 69 Ibid., 4-5, 13-14. 70 Gian V. Caprara et al., ´Personality and Politics: Values, Traits, and Political Choice’, Political Psychology 27:1 (2006) 1-28, 3. 71 E. Tory Higgins, ‘Value from hedonic experience and engagement’, Psychological Review 113:3 (2006) 439– 460, 442. 72 Ibid., 444. 65 28 opposition.73 In the cases of Slobodan Milosevic and Joseph Kony, this kind of zealotry seems to have played an important role in explaining their refusal to give in to international prosecution threats. This will be further explored in the case studies below. The fulfillment of ideological goals can also be an important motivator of action. An ideology can be seen as an organized set of values. It gives meaning to the world by assigning value to some things and not to others. It sets goals for its believers and as such guides their behavior in a certain direction. Not all ‘believers’ are the same in their conviction, of course. Other motives often override ideological imperatives. People can be hypocrites. However, it is important to note that psychologists have found that, in general, people have the desire to act in accordance with their beliefs. When someone acts in direct contradiction with their own self-identity, it “elicits an intense negative affect.”74 Thus, although people may sometimes act in direct contradiction to the ideology they say they believe in, when an ideology or some other set of values is an integrated part of a person’s self-identity, he will at least try to act in consistency with it.75 Power in and of itself can also be an important goal and is often cited as the main reason for rebel leaders and heads of state to commit crimes against humanity. Both Slobodan Milosevic and Joseph Kony are often seen as men primarily motivated by power.76 They are seen as leaders who exploit nationalist and racist sentiments to gain support and therefore many commentators doubt their commitment to the ideology that they say they believe in. But even for those who do bit fully believe in an ideology, the constant dissemination of propaganda advocating the ideology’s viewpoints irreversibly has an effect on those that are subjected to it. Even though the leaders of a group are the ones disseminating the propaganda, they will also be affected by the group ideology “and find it increasingly difficult to move in new directions.”77As such, it will be important to examine the ideology propagated by Milosevic and Kony. This will be done in the case studies below. Related to values are moral norms. Moral norms are beliefs about what is right and what is not. Differing from person to person, they can sometimes be externally given, emanating from a religion, a social group or a state. When they are internalized, moral norms can influence behavior in a significant way, forming restraints or creating motives. For example, moral norms play an important role in crime causation. It has been shown that a person with strongly internalized norms against committing a certain crime, does not even consider instrumental incentives for it.78 73 Ibid., 456-457. Sam A. Hardy and Gustavo Carlo, ‘Identity as a Source of Moral Motivation’, Human Development 48:4 (2005) 232-256, 236. 75 Caprara et al., ‘Personality and Politics’, 3. For more on the importance of this ‘fit’, see: Higgins, Beyond Pleasure and Pain, 9. 76 Smeulers, ‘Typology’, 244. 77 Ervin Staub, The Roots of Evil. The Origins of Genocide and Other Group Violence (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989) 124. 78 Clemens Kroneberg, Isolde Heintze, and Guido Mehlkop, ‘The Interplay of Moral Norms and Instrumental Incentives in Crime Causation’, Criminology 48:1 (2010) 259-294, 283-284. 74 29 As noted, values differ from person to person. It is when a person’s specific values are activated that the strongest motivation comes into play. It has been shown that intrinsic motivation, “behavior driven by factors internal to the person [having] inherent value or meaning to them irrespective of the outcome”,79 leads to a better task performance. Also, being intrinsically motivated by a task means that performing it will lead to higher satisfaction.80 This intrinsic motivation is opposed to extrinsic motivation, which means that an activity is being done “in order to attain some separable outcome”. 81 When a person is extrinsically motivated, he is doing something because of a reward or threat that is externally given. He does it, not because he wants to do so himself, but because there is an incentive or disincentive that is making him do it. These external motives, such as rewards, threats or competitive pressure have been shown to have a negative impact on enjoyment and motivation.82 It is not surprising therefore that people prefer to act on intrinsic rather than extrinsic motivation and often feel intrinsic motivation to be a more proper guideline.83 Yet, there is a variety in the types of extrinsic motivation. According to Edward Deci and Richard Ryan, intrinsic and extrinsic motivation can be placed on a continuum, with extrinsic motivation on the far left side and intrinsic motivation on the far right.84 In between are various, milder, forms of extrinsic motivation. Although full discussion of all these varieties falls outside of the scope of this study, it is interesting to note the options of ‘external regulation’ and ‘integration’. When an act is motivated by external regulation, it means that it is performed because of a salient punishment. For example, someone who disagrees with a parking ticket pays it anyway for fear of prosecution. He has the feeling that his act is caused by outside forces, does not identify with the source of the motivation and therefore perceives the act to be entirely extrinsically motivated. In Deci and Ryan’s terms, ‘the perceived locus of causality’ is external.85 However, extrinsic motivation may also lead to the integration of the norms espoused by the external motivator. These norms are brought “into congruence with one’s other values and needs” and therefore the perceived locus of causality will also be internal.86 The integration of the norms of an extrinsic motivator usually only takes place when the motivator has some legitimacy and the norms espoused by it to some extent resonate with the person’s own norms and values.87 Lucy J. Robinson et al., ‘Effects of Intrinsic and Extrinsic Motivation on Attention and Memory’, Acta Psychologica 141:2 (2012) 243-249, 243. 80 Sheena S. Iyengar and Mark R. Lepper, ‘Rethinking the value of choice: A cultural perspective on intrinsic motivation’, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 76:3 (1999) 349–366, 349. 81 Richard M. Ryan and Edward L. Deci, ‘Intrinsic and Extrinsic Motivations: Classic Definitions and New Directions’, Contemporary Educational Psychology 25:1 (2000) 54-67, 60. 82 Robinson et al., ‘Attention and Memory’, 243. 83 Higgins, ‘Engagement’, 456. 84 For the diagram, see: Ryan and Deci, ‘Intrinsic and Extrinsic Motivations’, 61. 85 Ibid., 61-62. 86 Ibid., 62-63. 87 In §1.2.3 the role of legitimacy in the integration of norms is discussed in further detail. 79 30 The integration of norms disseminated by an external motivator is exactly what is advocated by proponents of an “expressionist” role for international criminal tribunals.88 The main argument of these scholars is that international criminal tribunals should communicate messages to the world population about the norms that should be adhered to. By prosecuting – and punishing – those that offend them, these norms are reaffirmed and can subsequently be integrated into people’s value sets. As such, these norms become one’s own and the chance that they are offended is therefore correspondingly diminished. However, the problem with threats of international criminal tribunals, is that, very often, they conflict with the values that are internal to those that are threatened. Furthermore, they are rarely perceived to be legitimate. As will be noted in chapters 2 and 3, both the ICTY and the ICC had and have major legitimacy problems. As these two factors are essential for the integration of norms that come from external motivators, it does not seem likely that the message that is communicated by international criminal tribunals will truly be taken up by the world’s population, integrated into people’s self-identity and as such voluntarily and willingly adhered to. This is another explanation for why the use of external incentives and disincentives, such as legal sanction threats, has limited power in guiding behavior in the desirable direction. In conclusion The answer to the question of “why do we do what we do?” can thus be answered with the following. On a meta-level, we want to survive, we want pleasure, and we want to be effective. On the individual level, we act on a previously formed set of values. Our behavior is moderated by moral norms, which dictate which actions are appropriate and which actions are not. We strive to act in accordance with our own values and prefer to act out of intrinsic motivation rather than out of extrinsic motivation. This is problematic for the deterrent potential of international legal sanction threats, because for many war criminals these threats are seen as an extrinsic motivator, whose norms and values are not in accordance with their own. Marlies Glasius, ‘Too much law, not enough justice? The dominant role of the legal discourse in transitional justice’, Paper Presented at the Conference “Making Peace and Justice: Images, Histories, Memories”, 22 March 2013, Ottone, Utrecht, NL. 88 31 §1.1.3 Personality Individual differences in values and the way that we seek to fulfill them are to a large extent explained by differences in personality. As noted above, someone’s personality is an important determinant of his or her behavior. Personality, then, is a diffuse term, which can mean multiple things and be understood in many ways. It is therefore not surprising that various definitions of ‘personality’ have been given. In this piece, the emphasis will be on the psychological perspectives on personality. The relevant scholarly discipline for this is personality psychology. Also, insights from political profiling, which can be seen as a mix of political psychology and personality psychology, will be used. One authoritative handbook on personality psychology defines personality as “the set of psychological traits and mechanisms within the individual that are organized and relatively enduring and that influence his or her interactions with, and adaptations to, the intrapsychic, physical and social environments [italics in original]”.89 This definition emphasizes the fact that our personality is defining for the way that we react to certain situation and as such has important explanatory power in understanding why an individual responds to a certain situation in a certain way and why these responses differ from one individual to the other. As this study aims to understand why Slobodan Milosevic and Joseph Kony seemed impervious to international prosecution threats, it is thus incredibly important to properly understand their personalities. Therefore, this section will try to answer the question of how we can accurately assess their personality. Personality is one of the things that sets one human being apart from the other. Most personality psychologists tend to see a personality as consisting of a set of traits, an approach to personality that is known as the ‘dispositional approach’.90 Traits are “dimensions of individual differences in tendencies to show consistent patterns of thoughts, feelings, and actions”.91 The English language is rife with words that describe people’s traits. Lexical analysis in the 1930s identified 17.953 ‘trait terms’.92 In the 2010s the amount of ‘trait-descriptive adjectives’ has expanded to over 20.000.93 From this vast array of terms that describe someone’s personality, personality psychologists have, in the past twenty years, identified five traits that are thought to be most essential and most enduring in shaping the way that we respond to various stimuli.94 These Big Five – called dispositional traits, since they are relatively stable aspects of individuals –are (1) Extraversion, (2) Agreeableness, (3) Conscientiousness, (4) Emotional Stability, 89 Randy J. Larsen and David M. Buss, Personality Psychology: Domains of Knowledge About Human Nature (4th Edition, New York: McGraw Hill, 2010) 4. For a detailed analysis and explanation of this definition, see: Ibid., 5-10. 90 Other approaches to personality psychology are: biological, intrapsychic, cognitive-experiential, social and cultural and adjustment. See: Ibid., 14-18. 91 Robert R. McCrae and Paul T. Costa, Personality in Adulthood (New York: Guilford Press, 1990) 23. 92 Larsen and Buss, Personality Psychology, 78. 93 Ibid., 4. 94 Alan S. Gerber et al., ‘The Big Five Personality Traits in the Political Arena’, Annual Review of Political Science 14 (2011) 265-287, 266. 32 and (5) Openness to Experience.95 Although questions have been raised about the Big Five’s comprehensiveness,96 a remarkable consensus has been achieved around it.97 Furthermore, clinical psychiatrists have found that it is also applicable in the psychotherapeutic context.98 With only five different traits, it is relatively easily measured. This has made it possible for a wide variety of disciplines to use the model to study links between personality and certain behaviors.99 Personality traits are thus important in explaining different individual behavioral tendencies. It must be noted, however, that the Big Five are of limited use for this study. Milosevic has been dead for some time now and Joseph Kony is not known for his opacity or approachability to psychologists who want to measure how he scores on the Big Five personality traits. And yet, some research has been done that has looked at links between the Big Five and various attitudes and political behaviors. With the knowledge that has arisen from this research, we can make some founded assumptions about the way that the personalities of Milosevic and Kony would have fit in these Big Five. This research is analyzed below. A direction of research that is particularly interesting for this study has looked for links between the Big Five personality traits and prejudice. Especially Milosevic has directed violence at particular ethnic groups – amongst others Albanians, Bosniacs, and Croats. Certain prejudices must have led to the dehumanization which made it possible to try and wipe out whole ethnic groups. Multiple researchers have shown that there are clear links between certain personality traits and prejudice. One recent metaanalysis, reviewing 71 empirical studies in this direction, found that low Openness to Experience – “the breadth, depth, originality, and complexity of individuals’ mental and experiential life”100- and low Agreeableness – which “contrasts a prosocial and communal orientation toward others with antagonism”101 – significantly predict prejudice.102 These personality traits were not linked directly to prejudice, however. Two social attitude constructs, Right-Wing Authoritarianism (RWA) – emphasizing “submission, conventionalism, and aggression”103 – and Social Dominance Orientation (SDO) – which “taps endorsement of intergroup hierarchies and inequalities resulting from a tough-minded personality The Big Five are sometimes referred to as ‘the Five Factor Model’. See: Larsen and Buss, Personality Psychology, 77-78; Chris G. Sibley and John Duckitt, ‘Personality and Prejudice: A Meta-Analysis and Theoretical Review’, Personality and Social Psychology Review 12:3 (2008) 248-279, 251. 96 See for example, Sampo V. Paunonen and Michael C. Ashton, ‘Big Five Predictors of Academic Achievement’, Journal of Research in Personality and Social Psychology 81:3 (2001) 524-539. 97 Caprara et al., ‘Personality and Politics’, 6; Gerber et al., ‘Political Arena’, 266; Larsen and Buss, Personality Psychology, 87-88. 98 Timothy R. Miller, ‘The Psychotherapeutic Utility of the Five-Factor Model of Personality: A Clinician’s Experience’, Journal of Personality Assessment 57:3 (1991) 415-433, 431-432. 99 See for example: Gerber et al., ‘Political Arena’; Sibley and Duckitt, ‘Personality and Prejudice’. 100 Gerber et al., ‘Political Arena’, 267. 101 Ibid. 102 Sibley and Duckitt, ‘Personality and Prejudice’, 266. 103 Gordon Hodson, Sarah M. Hogg, and Cara C. Macinnis, ´The Role of “Dark Personalities” (Narcissism, Machiavellianism, Psychopathy), Big Five Personality Factors, and Ideology in Explaining Prejudice’, Journal of Research in Personality 43:4 (2009) 686-690, 687. 95 33 and competitive worldviews” 104 – have been shown to have important mediating effects, meaning that, for example, low Openness to Experience, predicts RWA, which is directly linked to prejudice.105 Both social attitude constructs play a role in the explanation of the way in which Slobodan Milosevic and Joseph Kony formed their beliefs, what their personality was like and how they were able to gather such a large following. This will be further explored in the case studies below. In the last decade there has also been a surge in interest for ‘dark personalities’, subclinical personality traits that are strongly linked to negativity towards others and seem to play a large role in explaining prejudice and (the perception of) intergroup threats. These dark personalities are narcissism, Machiavellianism, and (subclinical) psychopathy.106 People with subclinical psychopathy are “characterized by high impulsivity, callousness, interpersonal manipulation, exploitation, and stimulation-seeking, and by low empathy, anxiety, and remorse”.107 Interpersonal manipulation and exploitation is also seen in Machiavellianism, along with the deception of and disregard for others. 108 Narcissism is marked by an excessive sense of self-importance, ideas of grandiosity and an extreme sensitivity to criticism.109 Although these personality types are not necessarily harmful in and of themselves, when they are combined they can be disastrous. The problem is that these personality types are related to each other and often overlap. The Dark Triad, especially narcissism, is often found in authoritarian politicians and rebel leaders.110 It is not hard to imagine some examples of these personalities being found with committers of mass atrocities. The descriptions given above are to some extent also applicable to our case studies, as will be shown in the chapters below. The links described above are just a few examples of personality traits affecting political behavior. There are many more ways in which personality has an effect on the way that people act in a political context. Idiosyncratic personality features are especially influential in authoritarian social settings. When there is a single, charismatic person with a large amount of authority, who is accustomed to making decisions mostly on his own, personality will have the greatest effect on the decisions being taken. In crisis situations this effect is even more intensified (see also §1.1.1).111 So, knowing how personality psychologists view personality, this study now turns to the main question that this section tries to answer: how can we accurately assess someone’s personality? According to personality psychologists, this can be done with four different types of sources, all with their own pros and cons. These sources are self-report data, observer-report data, test data, and life-outcome data.112 104 Ibid., 687. Sibley and Duckitt, ‘Personality and Prejudice’, 266. 106 Hodson et al., ‘Explaining Prejudice’, 686. 107 Ibid. 108 Ibid. 109 Ibid. 110 Post, Leaders and Their Followers, 25 111 Ibid., 20-21. 112 The part about sources for personality assessment follows Larsen and Buss, Personality Psychology, 24-36. The pros and cons of the different sources can also be found here. 105 34 For the case studies, observer-report data and life-outcome data will be the most useful. Self-report data has some use, although it is necessarily limited because of the limited access to the people whose personalities have to be described. Still, there have been a number of interviews with Milosevic and Kony, although these were not conducted by psychologists but by journalists. Test data has no use at all, since no clinical tests have taken place. Thus, in assessing the personalities of the case studies, this piece will mostly make use of observer-report data – profiles, biographies, and the like – and lifeoutcome data – the historical events in their lives and the things that they did. Personality psychologists are not the only scientists interested in the accurate assessment of individuals’ personalities. Political psychologists, especially those who try to profile political leaders, are equally interested in explaining the acts of individuals through personality assessments.113 State leaders have much use for an accurate profile of their political adversaries. In this way they know how to properly interpret these adversaries’ actions and devise their policies accordingly. Political profiles are often made with only a small amount of information. Political psychologists who profile politicians’ personalities usually look at their youth, important life events that shaped their self-image, their (political, bureaucratic, business, etc.) experience, the effects of mentors and role models, cultural influences, their personal life, as well as ego-documents and speeches.114 Political psychologist Jerrold M. Post has also looked at “the psychopolitics of illness in high office”.115 By analyzing these pieces of information, a good political psychologist can give a relatively accurate assessment of the individual’s personality. Insights from this discipline will therefore be used in the personality assessments of Slobodan Milosevic and Joseph Kony. In conclusion To conclude, personality consists of a set of organized values and traits that acts as significant predictors of behavior. Psychologists have analyzed a Big Five of personality traits which are most important in influencing behavior and other disciplines have picked up this five factor model to research correlates between personality characteristics and all sorts of behaviors. To assess the personalities of Slobodan Milosevic and Joseph Kony, multiple sources can be used, most importantly observer data and lifeoutcome data. Also, political profiling offers valuable insights into personality assessment. 113 See for example: Post, Leaders and Their Followers. Ibid., ix-x. Foreword by Alexander L. George. 115 Ibid., 50-67. 114 35 §1.2 The relationship between the court and the criminal After having answered some more general questions about human nature, this study now turns to the specific relationship between the men in question – war criminals, people who ordered mass atrocities – and the legal institution that is issuing threats which are meant to stop them. In the case of Slobodan Milosevic, this institution was the ICTY; for Joseph Kony, it was the ICC. To adequately understand this relationship, there are a number of features of it that need to be discussed. The first feature that merits discussion is the general assumption that these tribunals are able to stop (potential) war criminals by simply threatening them with prosecution. The second feature that needs to be discussed is the influence of extralegal sanctions on the decision to commit crimes. This feature is especially interesting in the context of mass atrocities. The third, and final, topic that will be discussed is the relevance of the legitimacy of these international criminal tribunals to understanding the way in which they influence the behavior of these war criminals. The features of the specific relationship between the ICTY and Milosevic and the ICC and Kony will be addressed in the case studies below. The main source of knowledge for all of these features is criminology, especially the criminological discipline of deterrence theory, which studies the (potential) deterrent effect of legal sanctions. §1.2.1 Deterrence Deterrence theory forms the scientific background for the assumption of international criminal justice proponents that legal sanction threats are able to deter potential criminals. As was noted in the Introduction, the belief that legal sanction threats are able to fulfill this role still seems to be widespread. This belief is grounded in two important assumptions. The first assumption is that criminals make the decision to commit a crime on the basis of a rational analysis of costs and benefits, and only commit the crime when its benefits outweigh its costs.116 The second assumption is that the risk of legal sanctions can pose as a significant cost in this analysis. A cost that, when high enough, is able to outweigh the benefits of a crime and therefore deter a potential offender from committing it.117 Thus, when international criminal tribunals are propagated as an effective tool for stopping the perpetration of mass atrocities, it is assumed that these mass atrocities are committed on the basis of some sort of rational analysis of costs and benefits, and that the legal sanction threats emanating from international criminal tribunals will be able to influence this analysis in such a way that the perpetration of these crimes is no longer feasible. Bonanno, ‘Economic Analysis’, 196-198; Lilly et al., Criminological Theory, 20-22; Paternoster, ‘How Much’, 770-772. 117 Ibid., 783. 116 36 1. The first assumption: humans are rational The first assumption, that crimes are committed on the basis of rational, hedonic calculations of costs and benefits, has to a large extent already been discussed in §1.1.1. Here, it was concluded that the idea of human decision making as being based on a rational analysis of costs and benefits, seems to be misguided. Rather, we should see it as purposive and usually responsive to incentives and disincentives, although not always in the ways that we expect it to be. In the context of the crimes that are the subject of this study – war crimes, crimes against humanity, genocide and other international crimes that are severe enough to fall under the jurisdiction of international criminal tribunals – several scholars have doubted that those who commit such crimes are really engaging in some sort of rational cost-benefit analysis.118 Reading some of the accounts of what happened during the ethnic cleansings in the former Yugoslavia, and knowing of the torture and other sadistic treatments that innocent civilians were submitted to by members of the LRA, might indeed prompt such arguments. Somehow, these crimes must have been the work of a primordial, blind hatred against another ethnic group – as in the case of Serbians ethnically cleansing their Bosnian neighbors. Otherwise, its perpetrators must have been fanatics, blindly following an ideology which forced them to murder thousands of innocent people – such as the ideology espoused by Joseph Kony, who portrays himself as the Messiah, “the Wizard of the Nile”. In this view these crimes simply defy comprehension and must have been the work of ‘mad men’. After all, ‘normal’ people would never have been able to commit such horrible acts. For the sake of this section’s argument, it is useful to make a distinction here between those who ordered the crimes and those who carried them out. In other words, a line must be drawn between “senior leadership and on-the-ground troops”.119 In the case of the latter, it is indeed hard to imagine that they always carefully considered their acts in a rational fashion.120 Several factors seem to have eliminated such rational considerations, such as inebriation or intoxication,121 obedience to authority,122 extreme hatred of the other group,123 and a whole host of social psychological factors that is too exhaustive to Martin Mennecke, ‘Punishing Genocidaires: A Deterrent Effect or Not?’, Human Rights Review 8:4 (2007) 319-339, 325; David Wippman, ‘Atrocities, Deterrence, and the Limits of International Justice’, Fordham International Law Journal 23 (1999) 473-488, 476; Dawn L. Rothe and Victoria E. Collins, ‘The International Criminal Court: A Pipe Dream to End Impunity?’, International Criminal Law Review 13:1 (2013) 191-209, 194-195. 119 Christopher W. Mullins and Dawn L. Rothe, ‘The Ability of the International Criminal Court to Deter Violations of International Criminal Law: A Theoretical Assessment’, International Criminal Law Review 10:5 (2010) 771-786, 774-775. 120 According to Smeulers, in some cases, even law-abiding citizens make conscious choices about their involvement in international crimes. When the options are such that the choice is between being involved and being left out, and as a consequence being left out from society altogether, a large segment of the population seems to prefer the former. For an overview of these cases, see: Smeulers, ‘Towards a Typology’, 243-260. 121 Ibid., 783. 122 Stanley Milgram, Obedience to Authority: An Experimental View (New York: Harper & Row, 1974); See also: Smeulers, ‘Typology’, 235-240. See also: Herbert C. Kelman and V. Lee Hamilton, Crimes of Obedience: Toward a Social Psychology of Authority and Responsibility (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1989). 123 Mennecke, ‘Punishing Genocidaires’, 325-326. 118 37 fully mention here.124 Yet it is striking that in some cases, the foot soldiers who carried out the murder of innocent civilians, seem to have felt that their acts were perfectly justifiable. For example, in the context of the ethnic cleansings of Bosnian Muslims by the Serbs, many of those who carried out these atrocities felt that they were acting out of self-defense. The other side was allegedly doing the same thing and in a ‘total war’-setting the line between civilians and combatants supposedly was not all that clear.125 As such, even after a consideration of the rightfulness of their acts, these perpetrators still concluded that they were both just and necessary. Because in such an ‘inversion of morality’, the atrocities are both accepted and promoted, it does not seem fair to describe such people as ‘mad’, however comforting that may be.126 As was noted above, classifying someone as ‘rational’ does not necessarily mean that his ideas need to conform to some sort of liberal democratic standard. It is not the substance of the decision making process, but rather the consistency of it that matters. In many instances, therefore, even “terribly and terrifyingly normal” men are capable of carrying out crimes against humanity.127 These ‘on-the-ground troops’ are not the focus of this study, however. Both Milosevic and Kony belonged to the senior leadership. They both held high ranks: Milosevic was the president of Serbia, Kony was and is the leader of the Lord’s Resistance Army. Moreover, international criminal tribunals generally focus on those who are deemed to be the most responsible, the people who ordered and organized the crimes. Since this piece is occupied with studying the reactions of those who are threatened by international criminal prosecution, it will focus on the senior leadership. For this group of people, the on-the-ground social psychological mechanisms are harder to observe. The amount of planning and organization that goes into most genocidal activities seems to preclude an explanation that is focused on the irrationality of its senior leadership. Most of it clearly is goal-oriented behavior that serves some sort of purpose to its perpetrators.128 The ones that organize and plan for violations of international criminal law seem to make at least some sort of calculation about the way in which this is to be done. To some extent, the pros and cons of alternative routes of action are considered – although this consideration might limit itself to the choice of whom or what to target. Therefore, they seem to adhere to the bounded rationality model that was offered in §1.1.1 above. This means that they do respond to incentives and 124 For an overview, see: Alette Smeulers and Fred Grünfeld, International Crimes and Other Gross Human Rights Violations: A Multi- and Interdisciplinary Textbook (Leiden: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, 2011) 203-241; Staub, Roots of Evil, 13-34. For an interesting case study in which these social psychological factors are applied to the Nazi genocide, see: Christopher R. Browning, Ordinary Men. Reserve Police Battalion 101 and the Final Solution in Poland (London: Vintage, 1992) 159-189. 125 Wippman, ‘Atrocities, Deterrence’, 477-479. 126 Waller emphasizes that, given the enormous amount of perpetrators involved in genocide, crimes against humanity and war crimes, it is statistically and diagnostically impossible that they all suffered from some sort of psychological deficiency which explains their acts. See: James Waller, Becoming Evil: How Ordinary People Commit Genocide and Mass Killing (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002) 69. Waller is quoted in: Smeulers, ‘A Typology’, 234. 127 Hannah Arendt, Eichmann in Jerusalem: A Report on the Banality of Evil (New York: Penguin Books, 2006 [1963]) 264. 128 Mullins and Rothe, ‘The Ability’, 775-776. 38 disincentives, although not always in the same way, and not always in the way that we expect them to. As such, because some sort of calculation is made, they should be more susceptible to legal sanction threats than the on-the-ground troops.129 In the discussion below of how legal sanction threats can pose as disincentives, it is important not to lose track of the powerful incentives that mass atrocities can offer to some actors. First of all, hatred and prejudice can play important roles in the decision to commit these crimes. Often, those who engage in mass atrocities are supported by an ideology (or at least a belief) that is based on feelings of some sort of (ethnic) superiority.130 In these ideologies, the murder and torture on members of the ‘outgroup’ – the other racial, tribal, ethnic or religious group, other political faction etc. – is often justified and even encouraged.131 Therefore, although these crimes might not be “spontaneous outbursts” of “primordial hatred”,132 hatred of the victims of mass atrocities can definitely be an important incentive to commit these crimes. Moreover, hatred of an out-group dehumanizes its members, significantly facilitating the commitment of horrendous crimes against them.133 Second, as has been noted earlier, acting in accordance with one’s own values elicits a positive feeling. Therefore, believers of extreme ideologies that command the death of innocent civilians, prefer to act on the values espoused by these ideologies. Third, as has been mentioned earlier, human behavior is goal-driven. When we take into account the amount of energy and enthusiasm with which many perpetrators try to achieve the goals put forward by their ideologies, we have to conclude that these value-systems can also act as important incentives in their decision to commit mass atrocities. Fourth, and last, for many leaders of groups that commit crimes against humanity and/or genocide, these crimes are a way to attain power or maintain their hold on it.134 For leaders who order mass atrocities, the lust for power seems to pose as an important incentive in the decision making process. The four factors outlined above, then, heavily influence the incentive side of the decision making process. This incentive side should not be forgotten, when this study now turns to the study of the potential disincentive that international legal sanction threats can deliver. Rothe and Collins, ‘Pipe Dream’, 195. According to Alex Alvarez, all genocides are supported by some sort of ideology. See: Alex Alvarez, ‘Destructive Beliefs: Genocide and the Role of Ideology’, in: Alette Smeulers and Roelof Haveman (eds.), Supranational Criminology: Towards a Criminology of International Crimes (Antwerp: Intersentia, 2008) 213231, 215. 131 Rothe and Collins, ‘Pipe Dream’, 196. 132 Payam Akhavan, ‘Beyond Impunity: Can International Criminal Justice Prevent Future Atrocities?’, The American Journal of International Law 95:1 (2001) 7-31, 7. 133 For this process of dehumanization, see, inter alia: Eric Markusen, ‘The Genocidal Mentality at the Dawn of the Twenty-First Century’, The Aegis Review on Genocide 1 (2003) 11-14; G. Tendayi Viki, Daniel Osgood, and Sabine Phillips, ‘Dehumanization and Self-Reported Proclivity to Torture Prisoners of War’, Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 49:3 (2013) 325-328. 134 Akhavan, ‘Beyond Impunity’, 12. See also: Jack Snyder, From Voting to Violence: Democratization and Nationalist Conflict (London: W.W. Norton & Company, 2000) 45-91. 129 130 39 2. The second assumption: Punishment deters future offenders The second assumption of the adherents of deterrence theory is, that the threat of legal punishment can pose as a significant disincentive to those who are considering to commit a crime. Deterrence is achieved when the potential offender perceives the disincentive of the legal sanction threat to be so strong that this disincentive outweighs the incentives of the crime that is under consideration.135 There are three properties of the potential punishment that are important in this context. These are the potential punishment’s certainty, severity and celerity (swiftness). All three are thought to have an inverse relation to crime. Thus, this line of reasoning argues, when sanctions are more certain, more severe and/or more swift, less crimes will be committed.136 However, there are several problems with this line of reasoning. First of all, the empirical evidence for the second assumption of deterrence theory is very weak. Research on the relationship between the objective properties of punishment and crime rates has delivered extremely mixed results. Therefore, strong evidence for the idea that legal punishment can directly deter future crimes is lacking.137 To some extent the lack of a clear link between objective sanction properties and crime rates, has been explained by the fact that it is not the objective properties of punishment which matter to a potential criminal, but rather the way in which he perceives these properties. Since he is the one that has to make the decision, it is his perception of the legal sanction threat which is factored into the decision making process. This is a notion stressed by perceptual deterrence theorists.138 Criminologists have shown that the objective properties of punishment rarely correlate positively with the way in which these properties are perceived.139 In other words, people do a poor job at estimating the actual certainty of arrest, the maximum penalty that stands for the crime, and the average time it takes for law enforcement officials to apprehend the criminal. There seems to be no link between the objective properties of legal sanctions in a certain area, and its inhabitants’ perception of them.140 What this means, is that raising the objective certainty, severity, and celerity of punishment does not necessarily translate into higher risk estimates by potential offenders. Therefore, as far as deterrence goes, improving the objective properties of punishment is useless. This runs counter to the argument made by many commentators on the deterrent effect of international legal punishment. 141 In their view, the main reason why violators of international criminal law barely seem to be bothered by the chance of international legal prosecution, is that the chance of actually being arrested is so appallingly low – a chance that has been likened by David Wippman to “losing the war crimes Bonanno, ‘The Economic Analysis’, 197; Paternoster, ‘How Much’, 783. Robert Apel, ‘Sanctions, Perceptions and Crime: Implications for Criminal Deterrence’, Journal of Quantitative Criminology 29:1 (2012) 67-101, 69; Paternoster, ‘How Much’, 782-787; Pogarsky, ‘Deterrence and Decision Making’, 241. 137 Paternoster, ‘How Much’, 818. 138 Lilly et al., Criminological Theory, 346. 139 Gary Kleck et al., ‘The Missing Link in General Deterrence Research’, Criminology 43:3 (2005) 623-660, 653; Paternoster, ‘How Much’, 804-810. 140 Kleck et al., ‘The Missing Link’, 642-650. 141 See, for example: Mullins and Rothe, ‘The Ability’. 135 136 40 prosecution lottery.”142 They plead for an increased effort to raise the certainty of legal sanctions, thus empowering the deterrent effect of legal sanction threats. However, in the view of the criminological findings outlined above, as long as potential offenders do not actually perceive the legal sanction to be more certain – which increasing the legal sanction’s objective certainty does not guarantee – this increased effort is useless as far as deterrence goes. Perceptual deterrence research has resulted in some evidence for an inverse relationship between the perceived certainty of legal punishment and the decision to commit a crime. Yet, there is no convincing evidence for a significant correlation between the severity or celerity of legal punishment and the willingness to commit a crime.143 Certainty has therefore been identified as the most important variable in crime control. However, even for certainty the empirical evidence has been judged to be “modest to negligible.”144 The fact that a link between the perceptual properties of punishment and the decision to commit a crime has not been empirically established in a convincing way, remains one of the biggest challenges for the assumption that punishment can deter crime. This lack of evidence is even greater for the idea that international criminal tribunals can deter potential war criminals.145 Although strong empirical evidence does not exist in either direction – one empirical analysis finds almost no role for the ICC in deterring future offenders,146 while another actually finds a much stronger deterrent effect147 – the problems that exist for deterrence theory on the national level, are even stronger on the international level. In part this is because it is problematic to extrapolate what is essentially a national theory of crime control to the international level.148 But more importantly, this is because those who propose that international criminal tribunals are the best way to prevent mass atrocities, fail to put forward a single case in which the threat of international prosecution deterred a potential offender in a meaningful way. A second qualification of the assumption of deterrence advocates that legal sanction threats can deter crime is the fact that criminologists have shown that different individuals respond to legal sanction threats in different ways. Economic analyses of offender’s choice have usually disregarded the influence of personal differences on offender decision making.149 As was noted in the previous sections, however, Wippman, ‘Atrocities, Deterrence’, 477. Mullins and Rothe, ‘The Ability’, 773; Daniel S. Nagin and Greg Pogarsky, ‘Integrating Celerity, Impulsivity, and Extralegal Sanctions into a Model of General Deterrence: Theory and Evidence’, Criminology 39:4 (2001) 865-892, 883; Paternoster, ‘How Much’, 812. However, for a counterargument against the idea that certainty is the only sanction property that matters, see: Silvia M. Mendes and Michael D. McDonald, ‘Putting Severity Back in the Deterrence Package’, Policy Studies Journal 29:4 (2001) 588-610. 144 Lilly et al., Criminological Theory, 347. 145 Mennecke, ‘Punishing Genocidaires’, 323-324. 146 Julian Ku and Jide Nzelibe, ‘Do International Criminal Tribunals Deter or Exacerbate Humanitarian Atrocities?’, Washington University Law Review 84:4 (2006) 777-834. 147 Hunjoon Kim and Kathryn Sikkink, ‘Explaining the Deterrent Effect of Human RIghts Prosecutions for Transitional Countries’, International Studies Quarterly 54:4 (2010) 939-963. 148 Mennecke, ‘Punishing Genocidaires’, 323. 149 Bonanno, ‘Economic Analysis’, 194. 142 143 41 psychologists and criminologists have shown that personal traits are highly influential in the way that we respond to incentives and disincentives. In this way, some of us are more deterrable than others. Deterrability, then, “refers to the offender’s capacity and/or willingness” to respond to sanction threats.150 Greg Pogarsky identifies three different categories of deterrability, which can be placed along a hypothetical continuum. On the one end of this continuum are “acute conformists”, persons “for whom extralegal influences ensure compliance with the law” and who consequently do not need to be deterred.151 On the other end of this continuum are the “incorrigibles”, persons who are “impervious to dissuasion”, who often suffer from psychopathological difficulties and therefore cannot be deterred. 152 In the middle of this continuum are the deterrable offenders. They are willing to respond to legal sanction threats and are “neither strongly committed to crime nor unwaveringly conformist”.153 Many scholars place the senior leadership of those groups that commit mass atrocities in this deterrable category. These scholars stress the relative rationality that goes into planning these crimes and furthermore emphasize that the leadership figures, because of their social and political position, are the ones who have the most to lose from being targeted by international prosecutions.154 Therefore, those in the senior leadership should be ideal targets for legal sanction threats. However, individuals differ in their deterrability in another way, in what is known as ‘risk sensitivity’. Risk sensitivity describes the extent to which the offender is aware of the risk of being caught and takes measures to minimize this risk.155 Individuals who score high on risk sensitivity would fall squarely into the category of deterrable offenders, since they are willing to commit crimes and make instrumental calculations about which crime to commit or whether not to commit a crime at all. However, the paradox is that, even though this group of offenders might be most susceptible to sanction threats, they are also among the most difficult to deter. Risk sensitive offenders always come up with new ways to avoid being caught. They employ new tactics, change their targets or avoid areas that are frequently patrolled by law enforcement agencies.156 As such, since the perceived certainty of legal sanctions is very low and risk sensitive offenders constantly seek ways to minimize it, these offenders might be among those who are the most difficult to deter. This means that, even for those offenders who are deemed to be most susceptible to legal sanction threats, these threats might not be effective enough to deter them. Bruce A. Jacobs, ‘Deterrence and Deterrability’, Criminology 48:2 (2010) 417-441, 417. Greg Pogarsky, ‘Identifying “Deterrable” Offenders: Implications for Research on Deterrence’, Justice Quarterly 19:3 (2002) 431-452, 433. 152 Ibid. 153 Nagin and Paternoster, ‘Enduring Individual Differences’, 471. 154 Mullins and Rothe, ‘The Ability’, 774. 155 Jacobs, ‘Deterrence and Deterrability’, 422-423. 156 This process is known as ‘restrictive deterrence’. For example a criminal decides to rob a grocery store instead of a bank, because he knows that the bank employs better security measures. Although in this example the offender shows a susceptibility to the threat of being apprehended, he still commits a crime and thus is not meaningfully deterred. See: Ibid., 433. 150 151 42 Risk sensitivity is a trait that seems to be applicable to many violators of international criminal law, especially those in the senior leadership. There is much anecdotal evidence of perpetrators trying to minimize their apprehension risk. In Bosnia, for example, after the ICTY was erected, on-the-ground soldiers started to try and avoid identification. They wore black ski masks while they committed their atrocities, and, when NATO forces closed in, they “intensified efforts to conceal mass graves and hide evidence of criminal conduct”.157 Slobodan Milosevic, also, tried to minimize evidence of his involvement in the ethnic cleansings that took place under his command. He had his name removed from the records of meetings which discussed the crimes and denied any knowledge of the mass atrocities taking place.158 Furthermore, Joseph Kony changed his tactics when African countries intensified their efforts to apprehend him. He changed his area of operations and lowered the profile of his attacks.159 In addition, many leaders of mass atrocities use proxies to carry out the atrocities. For example, Omar al-Bashir, the target of an arrest warrant issued by the ICC for his alleged involvement with the genocide in Sudan’s southern province of Darfur, used the Janjaweed militias to attack civilians in the area, and in this way maintained plausible deniability.160 Another tactic that senior leadership figures employ is the ‘rogue agent’-scenario: they claim that there was a ‘bad apple’ in their midst who committed the crimes without their knowledge or consent.161 Tactics like those outlined above are often used by violators of international criminal law to avoid detection or identification. They are aware that they need to minimize the chance of being apprehended, and they constantly find ways to do so. Therefore, it seems justified to call these people ‘risk sensitive’. This will be explored in more detail in the case studies below. The fact that individuals differ in the way that they respond to legal sanction threats, challenges deterrence theory in two distinct ways. First, it complicates the evidence for deterrence which does exist. Often, when someone does not commit a crime, it is not the legal sanctions which ensure compliance, but rather the fact that the person does not consider crime as an option at all. Therefore, it is unlikely that legal sanction threats are responsible for the fact that most people do not commit crimes. Second, it needs to be realized that legal sanction threats do not have the same effect on everyone. Some criminals Wippman, ‘Atrocities, Deterrence’, 480. Tom J. Farer, ‘Restraining the Barbarians: Can International Criminal Law Help?’, Human Rights Quarterly 22:1 (2000) 90-117, 94. 159 Bill Oketch, ‘”Kony 2012” Campaign Too Late in North Uganda’, Institute for War and Peace Reporting, (20 March 2012), available online at: http://iwpr.net/report-news/kony-2012-campaign-too-late-north-uganda (26 April 2013). 160 Pablo Castillo, ‘Rethinking Deterrence: The International Criminal Court in Sudan’, UNISCI Discussion Papers 13 (2007) 167-184, 173. 161 Jamieson described this process as juridical ‘othering’. See: R. Jamieson and K. McEvoy, ‘State Crime by Proxy and Juridical Othering’, The British Journal of Criminology 45:4 (2005) 504-527. See also: Dawn L. Rothe and Christopher W. Mullins, ‘Beyond the Juristic Orientation of International Criminal Justice: The Relevance of Criminological Insight to International Criminal Law and its Control: A Commentary’, International Criminal Law Review 10:1 (2010) 97-110, 108-110; Alex Alvarez, ‘Militias and genocide’, War Crimes, Genocide, & Crimes against Humanity 2 (2006) 1-33, 17-21. 157 158 43 simply cannot be deterred, while others are highly susceptible to legal sanction threats, yet constantly find ways to minimize the risk of being apprehended. Because these ‘risk sensitive’ offenders perceive the chance of legal sanctions to be so small, they are not deterred from committing crimes. It is interesting to note in this context that criminologists have shown that offenders learn from their experiences with the criminal justice system. An offender updates his perception of the chance of being caught for a certain crime by looking at the amount of times he got away with it, relative to the times he did not.162 Evading arrest multiple times therefore downgrades the offender’s perception of the chance of arrest. For example, when someone has committed multiple atrocities and he got away with it, he will downgrade his perception of the certainty of punishment for this crime. Moreover, offenders learn from their surroundings.163 Informal networks of communication transfer the experiences of peers with the criminal justice system to the potential offender, meaning that when he sees or hears about someone else getting away with a crime, he will also downgrade his own perception of the chance of being caught. Criminologists have dubbed the combination of these two effects the ‘experiential effect’.164 This experiential effect can be an important factor in explaining some of the lack of a deterrent effect of international criminal tribunals.165 The culture of impunity which is still associated with the commitment of crimes against humanity tells the potential perpetrator that there is only a very small chance that he will actually be indicted.166 Furthermore, even those who are indicted often escape conviction as the international community fails to take serious its obligation to apprehend these criminals. To quote Akhavan, “the balance is still firmly on the side of political expedience and submission to power rather than justice”.167 Slobodan Milosevic was able to avoid arrest for a long time after he was indicted by the ICTY in 1999: he was not arrest until 2001, after he fell from power. People like Joseph Kony and Omar al-Bashir of Sudan have been escaping arrest even longer, since October 2005 and March 2009 respectively. In the meantime, the violence against civilian populations continues. Taking into account the experiential effect therefore means that these people’s perception of the certainty of arrest is significantly downgraded. Furthermore, when people like Syria’s Bashir al-Assad, who has been threatened by ICC prosecution, take a look at their surroundings, they will hardly have the idea that they face a serious threat of legal sanctions. Seeing how few perpetrators actually get indicted and arrested, they will downgrade their perception of the certainty of international legal sanctions. As such, Julie Horney and Ineke H. Marshall, ‘Risk Perceptions Among Serious Offenders: The Role of Crime and Punishment’, Criminology 30:4 (1992) 575-594, 587-590. 163 Jacobs, ‘Deterrence and Deterrability’, 434-435; Pogarsky, ‘Deterrence and Decision Making’, 247-248. 164 Horney and Marshall, ‘Risk Perceptions’, 575-577; Jacobs, ‘Deterrence and Deterrability’, 434-435; Pogarsky, ‘Deterrence and Decision Making’, 247. 165 Rothe and Collins, ‘Pipe Dream’, 196. 166 Mennecke, ‘Punishing Genocidaires’, 325; Kenneth A. Rodman, ‘Darfur and the Limits of Legal Deterrence’, Human Rights Quarterly 30:3 (2008) 529-560, 554. 167 Akhavan, ‘Disincentive to Peace’, 652. 162 44 the effect of the disincentive that these sanction threats can deliver, is minimized even further. These issues will be treated in further detail in the case studies below. The third problem with the assumption of deterrence theorists that legal sanction threats can deter future offenders, is the fact that criminologists have for a long time established that extralegal influences are more influential in guiding our behavior than legal influences. The threat of extralegal sanctions usually looms much larger in a person’s mind than the threat of legal sanctions. For example, using the criminal offense of drinking and driving, Raymond Paternoster argues that, “if I refrain from drinking and driving because I fear that my spouse will think less of me if she finds out that I have been drinking and driving, my inhibition is not due to deterrence but to an extralegal process (social censure or embarrassment)”.168 Extralegal sanction threats such as these play at least as important a role in preventing crime as legal sanction threats do.169 The way in which these extralegal sanction threats influence the decision to commit crimes – and how this affects the potential deterrent effect of international criminal tribunals – will be further discussed in the next paragraph. In conclusion In this section it has been shown that the assumptions that deterrence theorists make when they state that legal punishment can deter future offenders are riddled with problems. First of all, the empirical evidence for this assumption is weak. Second, individual differences account for the difference in deterrability of different people. Phenomena such as risk sensitivity, the experiential effect and the perception of the certainty of legal sanctions are important to understand why international criminal tribunals seem to have such a hard time deterring offenders. By exploring these problems, some light can be shed on the reasons why Slobodan Milosevic and Joseph Kony did not seem to care much about the chance that they would be prosecuted or apprehended. The reactions that they displayed towards these threats will be analyzed in full detail in the case studies presented in the chapters below. Paternoster, ‘How Much’, 781. Nagin and Pogarsky, ‘Model of General Deterrence’, 865; Charles R. Tittle, Ekaterina V. Botchkovar, and Olena Antonaccio, ‘Criminal Contemplation, National Context, and Deterrence’, Journal of Quantitative Criminology 27:2 (2010) 225-249, 238. 168 169 45 §1.2.2 Extralegal Sanction Threats Essentially, extralegal sanctions – sometimes also called informal sanctions – are all the negative consequences of behavior that fall outside the scope of the legal system. 170 In general, they can be grouped into two different categories: social censure and self-disapproval. Social censure can take the form of social isolation, loss of interpersonal contacts or a lowering of community respect.171 The ‘shaming’ of people who violate group norms is a common example of this. Informal sanctions can also take more violent forms, however, such as corporal punishment and sometimes even death. Selfdisapproval takes place when an act elicits a negative feeling within the person, such as shame. More specifically, self-disapproval is “the internal dissonance from having violated an internalized behavioral norm”.172 This dissonance occurs because, as was noted in §1.1.2, human beings have the desire to act on these internalized norms and values. Moral norms are also important here. Not everybody feels the same about the appropriateness of different forms of criminal behavior.173 Therefore, while in some social circles murdering someone leads to extreme social and self-disapproval, in other social contexts – such as street gangs, terrorist organizations and, as will be shown later, genocidal situations – this disapproval is lacking. The threat of extralegal sanctions can have a large impact on people’s behavior. It can pose as a strong disincentive and in this way significantly guide the decisions that people make. The threat of extralegal sanctions has been shown to play a much larger role in deterring the general population from criminal conduct than the threat of legal sanctions does.174 There is some evidence that suggests that these extralegal sanction threats are even more important in situations in which the rule of law is lacking and/or the trust in and legitimacy of formal sanctioning mechanisms is generally low. 175 Since sanctioning institutions that are not perceived as legitimate are not seen as a proper restriction of behavior – for more on this, see §1.2.3 –, the importance of extralegal sanctioning mechanisms for controlling crime is increased. In contexts that lack a rule of law, social disapproval and moral norms need to be relied upon to deter potential offenders from committing crimes. Further undermining the already limited deterrent effect of criminal justice systems in these contexts, is the fact that they are often characterized by a lack of effectiveness in the apprehension of perpetrators, which results in a lower certainty of legal sanctions.176 Paternoster, ‘How Much’, 781. Kirk R. Williams and Richard A. Hawkins, ‘Perceptual Research on General Deterrence: A Critical Review’, Law and Society Review 20:4 (1986) 545-572, 558. Williams and Hawkins also emphasize that extralegal and legal influences can work together. For example, making a specific act punishable under criminal law can lead to the social condemnation of the act. See: Ibid., 558-566. Payam Akhavan furthermore stresses that indictments can isolate, stigmatize, and delegitimize leaders. See: Akhavan, ‘Disincentive to Peace’, 652-654. 172 Nagin and Pogarksy, ‘Model for General Deterrence’, 869. 173 Kroneberg et al., ‘Moral Norms’, 264-269. 174 Paternoster, ‘How Much’, 817. 175 Tittle et al., ‘Criminal Contemplation’, 238-244. 176 Such contexts lack a ‘rule of law’, are characterized by a ‘culture of impunity’, etc. 170 171 46 Interestingly, serious international crimes often take place in precisely such contexts. Many of the African countries that witness crimes against humanity, for example, have formal sanctioning institutions that are ineffective, politicized, and perceived by the local populace to be illegitimate.177 Therefore, according to the evidence summed up above, in these countries extralegal sanction threats will usually be much more influential in the criminal decision making process than the threat of legal sanctions. Moral norms and social censure have high potential to pose as a significant disincentive. Sadly, however, the social context in which crimes against humanity take place, is often characterized by an ‘inversion of morality’.178 In this context, the murder, torture and other cruel treatment of members of the out-group is no longer off-limits. Rather, it is accepted and even encouraged.179 The perpetrators are told that the victims ‘deserve to die’, that they are not human beings or that the killing is needed to serve some sort of higher purpose, such as the fulfillment of ideological goals. In this way, the crime is made legitimate.180 Moral norms that forbid the killing of innocents are no longer relevant and the hatred of the victimized group can significantly shortcut considerations about the appropriateness of the crime. Dehumanization of the out-group can further facilitate the act, overriding moral norms that would normally forbid murder.181 In such a context, the disincentive of “internal dissonance” – if it is encountered at all – is negated by the incentive of achieving group or individual goals. Thus, in this context of inverted moral norms, self-disapproval and particularly social censure, do not take place when the potential offender commits a crime, but rather when he does not. The social norms in this case demand the crime. The problem is that the potential offender has to fear extralegal sanctions when he does not conform to these social norms. As the impact of extralegal sanction threats on the decision making process is so great, it can be said that the potential offender is deterred from not committing the crime. This notion is important to explain the mass involvement of normally law-abiding citizens which often characterizes international crimes: they are, in Smeulers’ words, “conformists to the extreme”.182 In the case of the senior leadership, people like Slobodan Milosevic and Joseph Kony may fear that they will lose standing with their peers or face disapproval from their community when they do not further the goals espoused by their ideologies. For example, when Milosevic would have given in to NATO pressures to stop the ethnic cleansings taking place in the former Yugoslavia, it is Katherine Erbeznick, ‘Money Can’t Buy You Law: The Effects of Foreign Aid on the Rule of Law in Developing Countries’, Indiana Journal of Global Legal Studies 18:2 (2011) 873-900, 892-895. 178 Mennecke, ‘Punishing Genocidaires’, 325-326. 179 For an elaborate account of the dehumanization of Jews, the legitimization of their extermination and the way in which this greatly facilitated the work of the people who had to carry out this extermination, see: Goldhagen, Hitler’s Willing Executioners. 180 Rothe and Collins, ‘Pipe Dream’, 196. For a case study on the effect of group norms on the willingness to commit genocide in Rwanda, see: Ravi Bhavnani, ‘Ethnic Norms and Interethnic Violence: Accounting for Mass Participation in the Rwandan Genocide’, Journal of Peace Research 43:6 (2006) 651-669. 181 For example, in Rwanda the dehumanization of the Tutsis took extreme forms. Hutu radio stations constantly called for the elimination of the Tutsi inyenzi (literally cockroaches). See also: Ibid., 656. 182 Roelof Haveman and Alette Smeulers, ‘Criminology in a State of Denial – Towards a Criminology of International Crimes: Supranational Criminology’, in: Alette Smeulers and Roelof Haveman (eds.), Supranational Criminology: Towards a Criminology of International Crimes (Antwerp: Intersentia, 2008) 3-26, 9. 177 47 probable that he would have lost his reins on power and be shunned by his community. Indeed, not long after Milosevic gave up Kosovo, he was deposed. As such, extralegal sanction threats which are the result of the inversion of morality which characterizes the social contexts in which crimes against humanity take place, can pose as a strong disincentive for giving in to international legal sanction threats. In conclusion Extralegal sanctions, those sanctions that fall outside the scope of the legal system, can be grouped into social censure and self-disapproval. Extralegal sanction threats have been shown to weigh heavily in the criminal decision making process, much heavier than legal sanction threats. Such threats play an important role in controlling crime in situations in which the ‘rule of law’ is wanting. However, the problem is that most genocidal situations are characterized by an inversion of morality. This means that a potential offenders has to fear extralegal sanctions when he does not commit the act that is demanded by the group norms. As such, he is deterred from not committing the crime. 48 §1.2.3 Legitimacy The legitimacy of a court that is issuing a sanction threat has been identified as an important factor in shaping a person’s reaction to the threat. Legitimacy however, can be defined in multiple ways. Tom R. Tyler, one of the principal criminologists who have studied legitimacy in the legal context, sees it as a psychological property of an institution. When the institution is perceived as legitimate, the public holds the view that its actions and decisions are “appropriate, proper, and just.”183 This also means that the public feels that its decisions “ought to be followed”.184 Max Weber, a sociologist whose study of political legitimacy is still a “central point of reference in the study of legitimacy”,185 defined it as “the probability that to a relevant degree the appropriate attitudes will exist, and the corresponding practical conduct ensues”.186 Political scientists, who focus more on the legitimacy of authorities and governments, see a power-holder as legitimate, when it is “justified in claiming the right to hold power”, or, when it has a recognized “right to govern”.187 This means that it can rule with a certain consensus, instead of relying on what Joseph Raz has termed “naked power”.188 The distinction between ‘power’ and ‘legitimacy’ is of fundamental importance here. A consistency in these definitions is the idea that for an institution to be legitimate, it needs some sort of approval from the wider audience, a recognition that it is ‘morally right’ to follow the rules and decisions these institutions make. This has been termed ‘audience legitimacy’ 189 or ‘consent legitimacy’.190 Other approaches ‘purposive legitimacy’ – meaning that the institution is legitimate when it pursues goals that are “broadly shared and approved by the institution’s constituency”191 – and ‘performance legitimacy’ - which sees an institution as legitimate when it performs the goals that are set for it in a proper way.192 As the central concern for this study is the reaction of Milosevic and Kony to international prosecution threats, it will be the way that they perceived the legitimacy of international criminal tribunals that is most relevant. As such, ‘audience legitimacy’ needs to take center stage here. But what does it take for a court to be recognized as legitimate? The answer to this question depends on which definition of legitimacy is used. For example, from the viewpoint of performance legitimacy, a court is legitimate when it has shown to be able to competently handle cases and adhere to the principles of a fair trial. Audience legitimacy, which requires the wider audience to recognize its Tom R. Tyler, ‘Psychological Perspectives on Legitimacy and Legitimation’, Annual Review of Psychology 57 (2006) 375-400, 376. 184 Ibid., 375. 185 Anthony Bottoms and Justice Tankebe, ‘Beyond Procedural Justice: A Dialogic Approach to Legitimacy in Criminal Justice’, Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology 102:1 (2012) 119-170, 126. 186 Max Weber, Economy and Society (4th Edition; Berkely: University of California Press, 1978) 214. Originally published as Wirtschaft und Gesellschaft in 1921-1922. 187 Bottoms and Tankebe, ‘Beyond Procedural Justice’, 124-125. 188 Joseph Raz, Between Authority and Interpretation (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009) 128. 189 Bottoms and Tankebe, ‘Beyond Procedural Justice’, 132. 190 Antonio Cassese, ‘The Legitimacy of International Criminal Tribunals and the Current Prospects of International Criminal Justice’, Leiden Journal of International Law 25:2 (2012) 491-501, 492 191 Ibid., 492. 192 Ibid., 493. 183 49 moral right to make decisions and prescribe rules which need to be followed, is much harder to obtain. In this context, Tyler has stressed the importance of procedural justice. According to his research, there is a strong correlation between the belief that the actions of authorities are consistent with just and fair procedure, and the belief that authorities are legitimate.193 This has led Tyler to conclude that it is procedural justice which is the main defining factor for the legitimacy of institutions. Moreover, a court can increase a person´s perception of its legitimacy by espousing norms and values that are, to some extent, shared by that person.194 Hence, there has to be a certain amount of shared consensus.195 When a court wants to be perceived by the audience as being procedurally fair, several criteria will have to be fulfilled. One important criterion is that the court has to give a fair treatment to the person being prosecuted. It has to respect his dignity and punish him in a fair way. 196 Furthermore, it is important that the court´s prosecution activities are not perceived to be discriminatory. 197 When a population does have the feeling that it is being discriminated by the court, it will have the feeling that it is being treated unfairly. Such a lack of perceived procedural fairness is an important criticism of both the ICTY and the ICC. The ICTY was accused by the Serbs of selectivity in its handling of gross human rights violations in the former Yugoslavia. In the eyes of the Serbs the court focused too much on the Serbian people and ignored the violations committed by other ethnic groups.198 The ICC has also been accused of selectivity, because, up to now, all of the situations it has under investigation are centered in Africa.199 These accusations of discrimination and selectivity are significantly impacting the perceived legitimacy of these international courts in a negative way.200 With the danger of stating the obvious, it is also important to note that a person’s perception of a court’s legitimacy is influenced by what he is told by other people about their perception court.201 The existence of a dominant negative narrative, can be a big obstacle on its path to obtain audience legitimacy. This is also the main argument of Stuart Ford´s social psychology model of international tribunals´ perceived legitimacy. He analyzes six factors, put forward by various scholars, which are thought to be relevant to an international criminal court´s legitimacy. These are “(1) the process by which the court is created, (2) the location of the court[,] (3) the composition of the staff, (4) the institutional structure, (5) the procedures used during the trials, and (6) the court’s outreach efforts”.202 Tyler, ‘Psychological Perspectives’, 382. Ibid., 392, 195 Morris Zelditch, ‘Processes of Legitimation: Recent Developments and New Directions’, Social Psychology Quarterly 64:1 (2001) 4-17, 8-9. 196 Karen A. Hegtvedt and Cathryn Johnson, ‘Power and Justice: Towards an Understanding of Legitimacy’, American Behavioral Scientist 53:3 (2009) 376-399, 378-380. 197 Tom R. Tyler, ‘Procedural Justice, Legitimacy, and the Effective Rule of Law’, Crime and Justice 30 (2003) 284-357, 324. 198 Ford, ‘Social Psychology Model’, 413-414. 199 Rodman, ‘Darfur’, 543. See also the Situations page on the ICC-website: International Criminal Court, ‘All Situations’, (26 April 2013), available online at: http://www.icccpi.int/en_menus/icc/situations%20and%20cases/situations/Pages/situations%20index.aspx (26 April 2013). 200 Rothe and Collins, ´Pipe Dream´, 197-200. 201 Morris Zelditch, ‘The Normative Regulation of Power’, Advances in Group Processes 20 (2003) 217-249. 202 Ford, ‘Social Psychology Model’, 408-409. See also his notes 13-18 for the relevant literature. 193 194 50 However, according to Ford, all of these factors are only minimally relevant for the way in which the grassroots population perceives international criminal tribunals. Using psychological insights on cognitive biases – see also §1.1.1 – and motivational reasoning (which holds that people only reach those conclusions that they want to reach203) he arrives at his ‘social psychology model of perceived legitimacy’. First, he notes that international criminal tribunals usually have to deal with conflicts in which societies were deeply divided along ethnic, national or religious lines. Often, the different sides strongly identify with their own group, which has a dominant internal narrative of what happened in the conflict.204 In such a context, Ford argues, the tribunal’s legitimacy will be a zero-sum game, in which the perception of its legitimacy “will be driven largely by whom it indicts”.205 In the end, Ford concludes that in such a situation it is almost impossible for an international criminal tribunal to be perceived as legitimate by the entire grassroots population.206 But why is it so important that courts have a positive perceived legitimacy? This is because it has been shown that the perception of the court’s legitimacy has important consequences for the way in which individuals react to the prosecution threats that these courts issue.207 As noted, when an institution is perceived to be legitimate its rules and decisions are respected and people feel obliged to follow these rules. This, in turn, leads to improvements in legal compliance.208 The norms and values that are espoused by the institution will be internalized by those people, and they become self-regulating, “taking on the obligations and responsibilities associated with those norms and values as aspects of their own motivation”.209 Furthermore, perceiving a court as legitimate helps to create a positive perception of the court as a whole, which has the effect that negative outcomes that follow will be more easily accepted.210 This internalization of norms and values is important, because, as we have seen above, people prefer to act on norms and values that are their own. Also, when a court is not seen as legitimate, it will not form a “right and proper restriction of behavior”,211 and, without any threat of a forceful enforcement of authority, will not be seen as a factor that needs to be seriously considered in the decision making process. The reaction of Omar al-Bashir to the ICC’s threat of prosecution – defying and ignoring it – is a clear example of the devastating effects a lack of perceived legitimacy can have on the deterrent power of legal sanctions. 203 Ibid., 419-439 Ibid., 458-461. 205 Ibid., 440, 461. 206 Ibid., 475-476. However, he does not conclude that this is a sign of failure. According to Ford, the tribunal can contribute in an important way to the changing of internal narratives that are dominant in the post-conflict area. By creating a record of what has ‘actually happened’, these narratives might change, which would be an important stepping stone to reconciliation between the conflict’s warring parties. 207 Rothe and Mullins, ‘Beyond the Juristic Interpretation’, 103. 208 Bottoms and Tankebe, ‘Beyond Procedural Justice’, 155; Hegtvedt and Johnson, ‘Power and Justice’, 392; Jonathan Jackson et al., ‘Why Do People Comply with the Law?: Legitimacy and the Influence of Legal Institutions’, British Journal of Criminology 52:6 (2012) 1051-1071, 1062-1064; Kroneberg et al., ‘Moral Norms’, 263. 209 Tyler, ‘Psychological Perspectives’, 378. 210 Ibid., 383. 211 Rothe and Mullins, ‘Beyond the Juristic Interpretation’, 103. 204 51 Lastly, there seems to be a relationship between the certainty of legal sanctions, the perceived legitimacy of the sanctioning institution and the willingness to engage in crime.212 A low certainty of legal sanctions decreases the institution’s legitimacy: it can be said that it has a low performance legitimacy. A lack of perceived legitimacy furthermore decreases the certainty of legal sanctions. When a certain social group sees a legal institution as illegitimate, the group will diminish its assistance to enforcement agencies, which offers the indicted person the opportunity to hide or flee. Examples of this were seen in the former Yugoslavia. Men like Radovan Karadzic and Ratko Mladic were able to evade arrest for a long time after they were indicted by the ICTY. Karadzic only got arrested in 2008,213 Mladic in 2011.214 The support they had in the areas in which they took refuge, gave them the opportunity to remain beyond the enforcement agency’s reach for a long time.215 As such, when an international criminal court is lacking both a positive perceived legitimacy and a certainty of legal sanctions, its deterrent effect will be minimized even more, and is almost negated. In conclusion Legitimacy plays an important role in moderating the deterrent effect of legal sanctions. When a person perceives an institution to be legitimate, he will internalize its norms and values, more easily respect its decisions and feel obliged to follow its rules. To attain audience legitimacy, an institution’s actions must be procedurally fair and its norms and values must be shared to some extent by the broader public. It cannot be perceived to be discriminatory. The lack of perceived legitimacy that troubles international criminal tribunals is an important factor in explaining why some murderous leaders are not seeing them as a proper restriction of behavior. Rothe and Collins, ‘Pipe Dream’, 196-197. Ellie Tzortzi, ‘Karadzic Arrested in Serbia, worked as doctor’, Reuters, (22 July 2008), available online at: http://www.reuters.com/article/2008/07/22/us-warcrimes-karadzic-idUSL2196241820080722 (26 April 2013) 214 Peter Beaumont and Adam Gabbatt, ‘Ratko Mladic arrested, Serbian president confirms’, The Guardian, (26 May 2011), available online at: http://www.guardian.co.uk/world/2011/may/26/ratko-mladic-arrested-serbianpresident (26 April 2013). 215 See notes 213 and 214. 212 213 52 §1.3 Summarizing the findings of this Chapter The analytical framework presented here is meant to act as a guide in explaining why rebel and state leaders who commit mass atrocities usually do not seem to care about international legal sanction threats. In the present contribution the analytical framework will be used to conduct two case studies. The first studies the response of Slobodan Milosevic to the ICTY, the second Joseph Kony’s reaction to the ICC. The structure of these case studies has been described in the introduction. This conclusion is meant to give an organized overview of the most relevant findings that have been presented in this chapter. Table 1 summarizes the findings of §1.1, which are especially important in understanding the men’s decisions, their motivation and their personalities. Therefore, in the case studies below, the behavior of Milosevic and Kony will be analyzed by applying these findings. Table 2 gives an overview of the most relevant criminological findings on deterrence, extralegal sanctions, and legitimacy, which were presented in §1.2. These findings are important to understand the relationship between the court and the person who is being indicted for the crimes he allegedly committed. In describing the international criminal tribunals that were meant to deter Milosevic and Kony from committing mass atrocities, a special emphasis therefore will be on the perceived certainty, severity and celerity of the court’s legal sanctions, the social context which was issuing extralegal sanction threats, and the way in which the legitimacy of these international legal sanctioning institutions was perceived. As this study now turns to the study of two of the most illustrious war criminals of the last few decades, it is important to keep in mind that they were not ‘mad men’, nor were they fully rational actors, only acting to maximize pleasure and minimize pain. In devising ways to stop them, the emphasis has too often been on either extreme category. Often, the simple idea that the threat of legal prosecution would be a disincentive strong enough to stop them, has given false hope to the proponents of international criminal tribunals. And, to be blunt, has probably wasted innocent lives.216 Finally, it must be stressed that, to give a meaningful account of what has happened and to adequately explain the acts of Milosevic and Kony, it will be less important to give an account of what objectively happened, than to try and explain how these individuals perceived these events, how they were filtered through their referential framework and how they eventually formed their decision making process. 216 The genocide in Srebrenica was conducted after the ICTY was erected, and after both the ICTY and the international community made it very clear that the perpetrators of mass atrocities would be held accountable for their abhorrent acts. Clearly, Mladic and other Serbian commanders were not worried about these threats. More than five thousand men were systematically executed, a horrific example of the impotency of international legal sanction threats. The international unwillingness to intervene more forcefully and pinning their hopes on the international tribunal, in this sense can be held responsible for the deaths of these men. 53 Table 1: Understanding the Man Category Rationality Main Question How does he make his decisions? Relevant factors Computational Difficulties Cognitive biases Emotions Individual Differences Motivation What motivates him? Values Important points Explains imperfect decisions Information processing is systematically biased Emotions shortcut rational considerations People do not make decisions in the same way People act on their values Strength of Engagement Personality Overcoming obstacles increases engagement strength Acting in When someone accordance with disseminates own self-identity values they demand action Intrinsic/extrinsic People prefer to motivation act on intrinsic motivation How can we Big Five Five accurately personality assess his traits that personality? predict certain behaviors ObserverAlso insights report/self-report from political data most profiling important 54 Psychological stress increases judgment errors Loss aversion -- Moods affect judgment Affective feelings Values, moral norms, cultural Imperatives, and personality all affect decision making Ideology as an organized set of values -- -- -- -- -- -- Prejudice is linked to low Openness and low Agreeableness -- Social attitudes moderate links: RWA/SDO -- -- Moral norms as moderators -- Table 2: The relationship between the court and the criminal Category Deterrence Relevant Factors Important points Certainty/severity/celerity Only empirical thought to have inverse proof for certainty relationship to crime rates Experiential Effect Risk sensitivity Extralegal sanctions Social censure Disapproval coming from the social group Self-disapproval Negative feeling from offending personal values/norms Formal sanctioning institutions ineffective… Inversion of morality makes extralegal sanctions more probable The way the court is perceived by the wider audience Stronger effect than legal sanctions, especially when rule of law is wanting Potential offenders are deterred from not committing a crime Legitimacy Offender’s learn from their experiences with the criminal justice system The extent to which measures are being taken to avoid detection and/or capture Audience legitimacy Procedural fairness Interplay of legitimacy and certainty Being procedurally fair increases perc. legitimacy High perc. certainty increases perc. legitimacy 55 Severity/celerity are important theoretically Offender also updates his information by looking at peers It is the potential offender’s perception that matters, which is not always directly linked to reality -- Risk sensitive offenders might be among the criminals that are hardest to deter Can take the form of embarrassment but also has more violent forms -- -- And illegitimate… Trust in formal sanctioning institutions low Group norms that demand crime Violation leads to extralegal sanctions Needs consensus about norms and values Dominant narratives that contradict the court’s narrative has negative impact on legitimacy Court must respect social status of indictee Court cannot be perceived as discriminatory Low perc. legitimacy decreases certainty -- -- -- Chapter 2: Slobodan Milosevic and the Yugoslav wars Slobodan Milosevic was one of the most notorious characters of the 1990s. His policies brought down a nation. The wars he ignited ended the lives of hundreds of thousands of people, wounded many more, and caused an exodus of millions of refugees from the former Yugoslavia.1 Furthermore, it is alleged that during these wars, he was responsible for war crimes, crimes against humanity, grave violations of the Geneva Convention of 1949, and genocide. The nicknames he collected during his years in power, range from ‘the slickest con man in the Balkans’ to ‘the Peace Maker of Dayton’; from ‘the Butcher of Belgrade’ to ‘the savior of Serbia’.2 This colorful personality is the subject of this chapter. By applying the analytical framework presented above, it will analyze Milosevic’s rationality, his motivation, his personality, the efforts of the International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia (ICTY) to stop him, and the way in which Milosevic reacted to these efforts. To do so, the chapter is structured into a number of paragraphs. First, by giving a short overview of the conflict that erupted in the former Yugoslavia in the beginning of the 1990s, and Milosevic’s role in this conflict, the context of Milosevic’s crimes is sketched. The second paragraph will portray Milosevic in further depth, and analyze his rationality, motivation, and personality. Third, to understand the ICTY’s fruitless efforts to stop the atrocities being committed in the former Yugoslavia, the third paragraph scrutinizes this institution by considering how the factors that were summed up in the analytical framework above, affected its operations in the former Yugoslavia. Thus, this paragraph investigates the interaction between the court and the criminal, between the ICTY and Slobodan Milosevic. Together, these paragraphs will attempt to explain why prosecution threats being issued by the ICTY did not deter Slobodan Milosevic from committing serious international crimes. §2.1 The conflict in the former Yugoslavia Before its violent disintegration in the 1990s, the Federal Socialist Republic of Yugoslavia/Socialist Federal Republic of Yugoslavia3 was a relatively stable multi-ethnic, communist federation. A result of 1 The exact number of victims in the Yugoslav wars is still unknown. Moreover, the exact involvement of Serbia and its president, Milosevic, is a matter of enduring controversy amongst historians. However, there seems to be some agreement that Milosevic’s policies were for a large part responsible for the violence following Yugoslavia’s break-up. Although Milosevic has always denied the involvement of Serbs in the wars in Croatia and Bosnia, claiming that they were ‘civil wars,’ the historical record, amplified by evidence from the ICTY’s trial against Milosevic, completely contradicts this claim. See: Judith Armatta, ‘Historical Revelations from the Milošević Trial’, Southeastern Europe 36:1 (2012) 10-38, 35-36; Norman Cigar and Paul Williams, Indictment at the Hague: the Milosevic regime and crimes of the Balkan War (New York: New York University Press, 2002) 19-33. 2 Lenard J. Cohen, Serpent in the Bosom: the Rise and Fall of Slobodan Milošević (Boulder: Westview Press, 2001) 65; Jerrold M. Post and Lara K. Panis, ‘Tyranny on Trial: Personality and Courtroom Conduct of Defendants Slobodan Milosevic and Saddam Hussein’, Cornell International Law Journal 38 (2005) 823-836, 824. 3 The federation’s name was later changed to the Socialist Federalist Republic of Yugoslavia (SFRY). The namechange was suggested by Milosevic in 1963, while he was still an unremarkable law-student. According to him, 56 the break-up of the Austro-Hungarian and Ottoman empires, Yugoslavia was created by the Versailles Treaty in the aftermath of World War I. It spent its first three decades as a kingdom, uniting the Southern Slav (or Yugoslav) people living in Serbia, Bosnia, Croatia, Montenegro, and Macedonia.4 Although belonging to the same race and speaking the same language – Serbo-Croatian – Yugoslavia’s inhabitants differed from each other in culture, ethnicity, and religion: there were Catholics, orthodox Christians, and Muslims; Serbs, Croats, Bosnians, Macedonians, Albanians, and Slovenes. Most identified themselves more with their own ethnic group, than with some sort of pan-Slavic ideal.5 Especially in Kosovo, a Serbian province, a long history of conflict fuelled tensions between ethnic Albanians and ethnic Serbs. Although they were in the minority, it was the Serbs who ruled Kosovo.6 Throughout Yugoslavia, the Serbs saw themselves as “a distinct nation heading a multiethnic state”, who deserved the predominant position in the state structure.7 This all changed when, in 1941, Yugoslavia was invaded and occupied by Nazi Germany. 8 In Croatia, a puppet-state emerged, headed by the fascist Ustasha party. The Independent State of Croatia (NDH), as it was called, implemented a policy of ethnic cleansing against its more than two million Serbian inhabitants, massacring tens of thousands and deporting many more. 9 This highly polarized ethnic situation left a legacy of anxiety and distrust. Complicating the situation even more was the civil war between the two groups that opposed the German occupation. The Partisans, communist resistance fighters under the leadership of Josip Broz Tito, fought against the royalist, anti-communist Chetniks.10 Tito emerged victorious and founded the Federal Socialist Republic of Yugoslavia (FSRY). Tito hoped to bury the Second World War’s “historical record of ethnic bloodletting”,11 by giving each ethnic group its own governing institutions – setting up what Jack Snyder calls ‘ethnofederalism’12 – and propagating the new credo ‘Brotherhood and Unity’. the new name would better emphasize the socialist aspect of the federation. See: Slavoljub Djukic, Milosevic and Markovic: A Lust for Power (Montreal & Kingston: McGill-Queen’s University Press, 2001) 9. 4 At first, its official name was the “Kingdom of Serbs, Croats, and Slovenes.” Only in 1929 was it named the “Kingdom of Yugoslavia.” However, even before 1929, the name Yugoslavia was widely in use. See: Cohen, Serpent in the Bosom, 10. 5 Adam leBor, Slobodan Milosevic: Biografie (Amsterdam: Uitgeverij Balans, 2002) [translated to Dutch from Milosevic – A Biography (London: Bloomsbury, 2002)] 20. 6 Cohen, Serpent in the Bosom, 10-12. 7 Jack Snyder, From Voting to Violence: Democratization and Nationalist Conflict (New York: W.W. Norton & Company, 2000) 207. 8 LeBor, Slobodan Milosevic, 20. 9 Ibid., 22; Snyder, From Voting to Violence, 208. 10 LeBor, Milosevic, 22-23; Louis Sell, Slobodan Milosevic and the Destruction of Yugoslavia (Durham: Duke University Press, 2002) 12. 11 Ibid., 33. 12 Snyder, From Voting to Violence, 208-210. 57 Slobodan Milosevic’s formative period and capitalist years, 1941-1984 In the year that Nazi-Germany invaded Yugoslavia, on the 20th of August 1941, Slobodan Milosevic was born in the small Serbian town of Pozarevac.13 His parents were both teachers of Montenegrin descent: Svetozar, his father, taught Russian and literature; his mother Stanislava was a teacher at a lower school. He also had an older brother, Borislav. The capture of Pozarevac by the Partisans in the winter of 1944, marked the onset of Slobodan’s life in Titoist Yugoslavia, which was to last until 1980. Tito was, in many ways, inescapable. Although Tito had abandoned Stalin’s Soviet Union in 1948 – embarking on a somewhat more liberal, capitalist course14 – he was no stranger to personality cults. Adoration of the authoritarian Tito penetrated Yugoslav society, and marked Milosevic’s high schoolyears.15 In these years, Milosevic seemed to be somewhat isolated. He did not have many friends, did not like sports, and was known mostly for always sitting in front of the class wearing his white-shirtand-tie. Yet, in 1958 he met the love of his life, Mirjana Markovic. Mirjana, born in a Partisan hide-out in the midst of communist resistance during World War II, was a descendant of a well-known and wellrespected communist family in Pozarevac. Mirjana’s mother, Vera Miletic, died under mysterious circumstances shortly after giving birth. According to the dominant narrative she was executed by a communist firing squad for betraying her communist comrades. For this reason, Mirjana’s father, Moma Markovic, did not formally accept his daughter until she was sixteen.16 Mirjana and Slobo – as she affectionately called him – were extremely attracted to each other. In Pozarevac, they were quickly known as ‘Romeo and Juliet II of Pozarevac’.17 Mirjana saw something in Milosevic. It is said that Mirjana once pointed to one of the many portraits of Tito, which in Titoist Yugoslavia adorned every public building, saying: “That’s where my Slobo’s picture will be one day.”18 Soon, he would become the vessel for her political ambitions. After high school, Slobodan went to law school in Belgrade. Here, his life was filled with both major career steps and family tragedies. To start with the first, one of Milosevic’s most important political choices was to befriend Ivan Stambolic – the promising, intelligent, and well-connected son of Petar Stambolic, one of the most prominent Partisan leaders of Serbia. Through Stambolic, he secured various functions in the student association of the communist party. In these functions, he displayed the typical characteristics of a communist apparatchik. Noticed for his rigid adherence to the party line and his “genius for party politics”, he was also condescending to his inferiors and a “toady” to those above him.19 Although he did not excel with his grades, he ensured a promising future for himself through his loyalty to Stambolic. He graduated from college in 1964. A year before, when Milosevic was 21, his 13 LeBor, Milosevic, 17. Sell, The Destruction of Yugoslavia, 21. 15 Ibid., 18-19. 16 Laura Silber, ‘Milosevic Family Values’, New Republic 221:9 (1999) 23-28, 24. 17 Cohen, Serpent in the Bosom, 46. 18 Djukic, Milosevic and Markovic, 11. 19 Sell, The Destruction of Yugoslavia, 20. 14 58 father committed suicide. Svetozar had already abandoned Stanislava in 1947 – reportedly over ideological differences: Stanislava embraced communism, while Svetozar remained deeply religious – after which Milosevic had had little contact with him. Milosevic did not bother to go to his father’s funeral, and did not seem to be particularly shocked by it.20 In the decades after 1960, while Yugoslavia was reforming its economy according to marketoriented, Western guidelines, Milosevic was making his career in the business and banking world. Stambolic made sure that Milosevic would succeed him in the functions he left behind. In this way, Slobodan became director of the Belgrade firm Technogas and, in 1978, head of the most important financial institution of the Balkans, the Udruzena Beogradska Banka (UBB). 21 During his time at the UBB, Milosevic fashioned himself into a Western-styled capitalist banker. On his numerous trips to the United States, he became fluent in English, made friends with some of the world’s most prestigious bankers, and developed a strong affection for the culture of the United States.22 Milosevic’s capitalist, internationalist outlook was congruent with Yugoslavia’s outlook in this period in general. His international contacts and reputation as a capitalist cosmopolitan would be of great use in the decades that followed. Although Yugoslavia was still ruled by an authoritarian one-party oligarchy, and its companies were often state-run, the country increasingly tried to become part of the West.23 In 1974, to keep off demands for democratization, reform the economy, and reduce ethnic tensions, Tito introduced a new constitution which turned the Yugoslavian federation into “a decentralized confederation in all but name”.24 Apart from its control over the army, the federal state was stripped of almost all authority. Most power was redistributed to the republics, which were highly ethnic in orientation. Kosovo and Vojvodina, part of Serbia but already possessing significant self-rule, in effect became autonomous republics within the greater Serbian republic.25 Yet, Tito did not manage to solve the nationalities problem, nor did he modernize the one-party communist rule.26 Just like his period in law school, Milosevic’s ‘capitalist period’ was marked by the suicide of one of his parents. His mother Stanislava, the woman he loved the most next to Mirjana, hung herself in 1973.27 Unlike the death of his father, the death of his mother shocked Milosevic. As a small boy he was LeBor, Milosevic, 49. According to Laura Silber, Svetozar “shot himself in the head upon learning that a student of his had committed suicide after receiving a bad grade.” See: Silber, ‘Milosevic Family Values’, 25. 21 LeBor, Milosevic, 67. 22 Ibid., 65-79. 23 Although the country witnessed a significant economic boom in this period, the gap between the developed regions – such as Slovenia – and the less developed region – especially Kosovo – actually increased. Cohen, Serpent in the Bosom, 17-27; Sell, The Destruction of Yugoslavia, 22. 24 Ibid., 23. 25 Snyder, From Voting to Violence, 209-210. 26 These issues are frequently analyzed as Tito’s ‘biggest mistakes’. See: Sabrina P. Ramet, ‘Review Essay: In search of the ‘real’ Milosevic: new books about the rise and fall of Serbia’s strongman’, Journal of Human Rights 2:3 (2003) 455-466, 457-458. Here she refers to: LeBor, Milosevic, 9-10; Sell, The Destruction of Yugoslavia, 19. 27 Laura Silber once again, gives a tendentious reason for her suicide: “Stanislava had traveled to her son’s Belgrade apartment to take care of her grandchildren, but, when she arrived late, Mira slammed the door in her face. Hours later, Stanislava was found dead.” See: Silber, ‘Milosevic Family Values’, 25. Strangely however, 20 59 smothered by her, but after graduating from college they saw each other less and less. To some extent, this was because of the influence of Mirjana, who was not keen on letting other women in Milosevic’s life.28 Meanwhile, the relationship between Mirjana and Slobo remained powerful as ever. During Milosevic’s college years and his subsequent ‘capitalist’ period, Mirjana worked on her academic career. In 1979, she received her PhD in sociology at the state university in Nis and quickly became a professor of the same discipline at the University of Belgrade.29 In her work, she showed herself to be a staunch defender of orthodox communism. She insisted on being called ‘comrade’ and was the founder of two communist parties in the 1990s.30 This was partly caused by her obsession with the legacy of her mother, Vera Miletic. Mirjana worked hard to prove that her mother had not betrayed her comrades. To support her cause, she took over her mother’s war name – Mira – and imitated her mother’s habit of wearing a red rose in her hair. The fact that her husband was working to promote capitalism in Yugoslavia, fraternizing with communism’s arch-enemies – such as the Wall Street bankers – did not seem to bother her. She was very much her own woman: for example, she did not change her last name after marrying Milosevic in 1965. Yet the bonds between Markovic and Milosevic only became stronger and stronger. Markovic gave birth to their daughter Marija in 1965, and in 1974 their son Marko was born.31 As parents, they spoiled their kids, giving them everything they wanted and more. In the relationship, Milosevic was, as ever, clearly Markovic’s inferior. Markovic saw her PhD as a sign of her intellectual superiority. Milosevic accepted this and seemed to garner to her every need. This dominance of Markovic over Milosevic only increased when Milosevic entered the political fray.32 Milosevic’s first political years: Failing Titoism, emerging nationalism, 1984-1987 In 1984, when Ivan Stambolic resigned his position as head of the Belgrade city organization to become head of the Serbian League of Communists, Milosevic moved in behind him. This put him at the center of power in the federation’s capital: Milosevic’s political career now began in earnest.33 However, Yugoslavia’s state system was crumbling. The rise of nationalism, together with economic crises and a failure of the existing state institutions to deal with these problems, eroded support for the state elite. When Tito died in 1980, he left behind a state structured along ethnofederal lines, with republics that Silber says she committed suicide in 1994. I did not find this date corroborated in any other sources. According to LeBor, this happened in 1973; according to Sell, in 1972. They also give an alternative reason for the suicide of Stanislava: she might have felt forsaken after both her sons and her husband had left her alone in Pozarevac. Cf.: LeBor, Milosevic, 61; Sell, The Destruction of Yugoslavia, 16. 28 Ibid. 29 According to Silber, Mirjana’s PhD would not exactly pass the test of any Western university. Moreover, she implies that Mirjana only landed her job as a professor because she was Milosevic’s wife. Silber, ‘Milosevic Family Values’, 25. 30 Louis Sell, ‘Slobodan Milosevic: A Political Biography’, Problems of Post-Communism 46:6 (1999) 12-28, 22. 31 Cohen, Serpent in the Bosom, 48. 32 This is why Slavoljub Djukic coined the oft-quoted phrase that Slobodan Milosevic cannot be properly understood without first understanding his wife. Djukic, Milosevic and Markovic, xii. 33 Sell, ‘A Political Biography’, 21. 60 were increasingly occupied with their own interests, disregarding those of the federal Yugoslav state.34 Communist officials desperately sought ways to regain support from Yugoslavia’s population. Many of them chose to ride on the powerful current of the nationalist sentiments that swept the nation. By doing so, they hoped to “reconcile popular politics with continued authoritarian leadership”.35 Slobodan Milosevic was one of these officials. After becoming the head of the Serbian Communist Party – he replaced Stambolic who became President of Serbia36 - Milosevic first further consolidated his power by removing most of the communist officials that opposed him, replacing them with a group of loyal allies which became known as the ‘Small Politburo’.37 During his rise to power in the communist party, Milosevic distinguished himself by his apparent belief in communism and his fight against ‘counter-revolution’ – the communist term for nationalism –, with some calling him a “good communist”.38 However, it was his nationalist rhetoric that caused his rise to prominence. In April 1987, Stambolic sent him to calm demonstrators in the small town of Kosovo Polje.39 This fateful decision changed the course of Milosevic’s career in significant ways. At that time, riots by ethnic Serbs plagued Kosovo. When Slobodan met with communist officials in the local House of Culture on the 24th of April, a Serb crowd stormed the building, pelting the cordon of policemen with rocks, who responded by beating the Serbs back with their clubs. When Milosevic came out to assess the situation, he was visibly shaken. After an old man begged him to stop the beatings by the police, he muttered “you will not be beaten again”. In his speech to the crowd, he upped the ante: “[Y]ou must stay put. This is your land. […] Yugoslavia will disintegrate without Kosovo. Yugoslavia and Serbia will not give it away!”40 Milosevic’s friends, especially in the media, were quick to fashion his actions on this day into a true Milosevic myth, portraying him as the hero of the Serbs, the savior of Kosovo.41 Before 24 April he was a typical communist apparatchik. When he came back he refashioned himself as a Serbian nationalist, aware of the power of the crowd and the potential of Serb nationalism for the acquirement of power. Nationalism and the break-up of Yugoslavia, 1987-1991 With his newfound popular support, Milosevic moved against the communist state structure. On 23 September 1987, during the 8th Plenary Session of the Communist Party of Serbia, Milosevic got rid of 34 Sell, The Destruction of Yugoslavia, 22-23; Snyder, From Voting to Violence, 208. Snyder, From Voting to Violence, 210-213. 36 Cohen, Serpent in the Bosom, 55-56. 37 Sell, ‘A Political Biography’, 21. 38 Cohen, Serpent in the Bosom, 56; Djukic, Milosevic and Markovic, 159. 39 Kosovo at that time was an autonomous region in the greater Serbian republic. As such, Kosovo fell under the authority of the Serbian republic. Stambolic, in his capacity as President of Serbia, would also have been a logical choice to assess and deescalate the situation. However, Sell reports that Stambolic “had spoken at a similar protest meeting in Kosovo the previous year and so, to his later regret, sent Milosevic, who had long been his protegé”. See: Sell, The Destruction of Yugoslavia, 2. 40 Djukic, Milosevic and Markovic, 17. 41 Snyder, From Voting to Violence, 214-215. 35 61 almost all of his communist opponents, one of whom was his long-time ally Ivan Stambolic.42 The last years of the 1980s were used by Milosevic to further increase his popularity and consolidate his power. Nationalist propaganda, espoused by the Milosevic-controlled media and Serbian intellectuals, significantly aided him in his pursuit, and, by whipping up images of Serbian victimization and inequality, created a climate for ethnic conflict.43 One of the most powerful manifestations of the rise of Serbian nationalism in the 1980s was the xenophobic Memorandum of the Serbian Academy of Sciences and Arts (SANU) published in September 1986, which called for an end to the ‘genocide’ by Kosovar Albanians of the Serbian people in Kosovo.44 Feelings of victimization like these had dominated Serbian nationalism since the 1389 battle of Kosovo Polje, in which according to Serbian myth the Serbs made a heroic stand for Western civilization against the Ottoman invaders.45 The defeat the Serbs suffered in this battle allegedly introduced a period of Ottoman repression and Croatian persecution during the Second World War did much to reinforce these feelings of victimization.46 Milosevic promised to put an end to the (perceived) suffering of the Serbs and ensure Serbian dominance within the Yugoslav federation. During the 600-year anniversary of the battle of Kosovo Polje, in Gazimestan, Milosevic played up his image as the Serbs’ national hero. He addressed a crowd of over a million people, making an ominous statement, televised live throughout the nation: “Six centuries later, we are in battles again. And facing new ones. They are not armed battles, though such battles should not be excluded yet.”47 Milosevic tried to ensure the dominance of Serbia within the Yugoslav federal structure, by organizing the so-called anti-bureaucratic revolutions – mass rallies attended by (mostly Kosovar) Serbs – against his political opponents. These were very effective in Kosovo, Montenegro, and Vojvodina. Controlling four of the eight votes of the Yugoslav presidency, he needed only one more vote to change the 1974 constitution to establish a Serbian dominance under his leadership.48 However, Milosevic’s nationalism in Serbia had sparked counter-nationalisms across Yugoslavia. Men like Croatia’s Franjo Tudjman and Slovenia’s Milan Kucan rose to power over fears of Milosevic’s ambitions of creating a 42 Cohen, Serpent in the Bosom, 67-70; Djukic, Milosevic and Markovic, 22-24. Sell, The Destruction of Yugoslavia, 111; Snyder, From Voting to Violence, 213-214. 44 LeBor, Milosevic, 109-113; Snyder, From Voting to Violence, 212. For the text of the Memorandum (in English), see: Serbian Academy of Arts and Sciences, ‘Memorandum 1986 (the Greater Serbian Ideology’, (24 September 1986), available online at: http://www.trepca.net/english/2006/serbian_memorandum_1986/serbia_memorandum_1986.html (21 October 2013). 45 For the way in which this mythmaking influenced the history of Serbia, see: Branimir Anzulovic, Heavenly Serbia: From Myth to Genocide (New York: New York University Press, 1999). 46 Cohen, Serpent in the Bosom, 5, 81. For the role of previous feelings of victimization in the causation of genocide, see: Alex Alvarez, ‘Destructive Beliefs: Genocide and the Role of Ideology’, in: Alette Smeulers and Roelof Haveman (eds.), Supranational Criminology: Towards a Criminology of International Crimes (Antwerp: Intersentia, 2008) 213-231, 222. 47 Agneza Bozic-Roberson, ‘Words Before the War: Milosevic’s Use of Mass Media and Rhetoric to Provoke Ethnopolitical Conflict in Former Yugoslavia’, East European Quarterly 38:4 (2005) 395-408, 402. With this speech Milosevic established himself as the new Prince Lazar, the Serbian prince who heroically defied the Ottoman empire six centuries earlier. See: LeBor, Milosevic, 165-170. 48 Sell, ‘A Political Biography’, 14. 43 62 Greater Serbia.49 When Milosevic tried to use the same tactics he used in other republics in Sloevnia, announcing a ‘meeting of truth’ in the Slovenian capital Ljubjana, Kucan closed the borders, mobilized the police and threatened to use force against any Serbs who dared to show up. On the 14th Congress of the League of Communists of Yugoslavia, in January 1990, the Slovenes decided they had enough and walked out, initiating the collapse of the communist party which had ruled Yugoslavia for more than forty years.50 These events precipitated Yugoslavia’s disintegration and laid the groundwork for the ensuing Croatian and Bosnian wars. Milosevic, having failed to become Yugoslavia’s ‘second Tito’, adapted a new strategic goal: unite all Yugoslav Serbs in a Greater Serbia under his personal rule.51 The political upheaval that followed the Slovenian walk-out had serious consequences for the Yugoslav federation. In the months that followed, Slovenia’s freshly elected nationalist leaders made great steps towards more sovereignty. These steps culminated in a January 1991 plebiscite which called for independence. Tudjman similarly made demands of greater sovereignty for Croatia. At the same time, he took steps that marginalized Serbs in Croatia. Symbols were adopted that had also been used by the Ustasha during World War II, evoking powerful memories among Croatian Serbs of fascist massacres.52 Bosnia’s nationalist parties achieved a landslide victory as well, leading to a nationalist ‘partnership in power’, with Croats, Serbs, and Muslims sharing the government.53 In Serbia, Slobodan Milosevic got overwhelming support for his newly created, moderately nationalist Socialist Party of Serbia (SPS).54 The increasing polarization between Yugoslavia’s republics ended in the 25 June 1991 declarations of independence by Slovenia and Croatia. The Yugoslav National Army (JNA) did not accept this, however, declaring war on Slovenia on the 27th of June. But the battle was over rather quickly, with a humiliating retreat by the JNA formalized by the European Community (EC)-negotiated Brioni Agreement of 7 July 1991.55 The eruption of ethnic conflicts in Bosnia and Croatia, 1991-1992 The civil conflict breaking out in Bosnia and Croatia, both inhabited by large minorities of Serbs, saw much heavier fighting. The Bosnian and Croatian Serbs demanded independence and wanted to join the Serbian-Montenegrin republic.56 In Serbian Croatia, Radio Knin espoused racist propaganda, inflaming the tense ethnic situation in the republic.57 Although Milosevic has always denied any Serbian involvement in the Croatian and Bosnian wars, declaring them ‘civil wars’, the involvement of Serbia and Milosevic himself was clear. Starting in 1991, Serbian separatists living in Croatia, supplied with 49 Snyder, From Voting to Violence, 212-213. Sell, ‘A Political Biography’, 14. 51 Sell, The Destruction of Yugoslavia, 108. 52 Ibid., 115. 53 Neven Andjelic, Bosnia-Herzegovina: The End of a Legacy (London: Frank Cass, 2003) 188-202. 54 Cohen, Serpent in the Bosom, 120. 55 Alastair Finlan, The Collapse of Yugoslavia 1991-1999 (Oxford: Osprey Publishing, 2004) 17. 56 Sell, The Destruction of Yugoslavia, 111. 57 This radio station was dominated by Milosevic. See: Finlan, The Collapse of Yugoslavia, 23. 50 63 weapons by Milosevic, used armed force to carve out new borders in the Krajina, They removed nonSerbs from Serbian majority areas, implementing a policy of ethnic cleansing on a scale not seen in Europe since the Second World War.58 Tudjman did not accept the Serbian separatism and ordered his troops to retake the towns. When JNA troops got mixed in the fighting as well, full-scale war broke out. The JNA, although officially part of the Yugoslav federal structure, was dominated by officers who were appointed by Milosevic, and was thus a proxy for Serbian interests.59 In the late spring of 1991, fighting intensified in the region known as Eastern Slavonia. The brutal siege of Vukovar became one of the prime examples of the savagery of the war in the former Yugoslavia. The brutality was made even worse by the increasing role of extremist paramilitary groups – such as Arkan’s Tigers –, which had strong links to Milosevic in Belgrade. Well-equipped, they were especially responsible for the ethnic cleansing that took place.60 In 1992, similar events unfolded in Bosnia. Bosnia’s government of Alija Izetbegovic wanted greater sovereignty from the centralized Yugoslav federal structure. Getting nothing from the now Serbian-dominated federal government,61 he declared his independence from Yugoslavia in the spring of 1992, leaving the Yugoslav federation to consist of nothing but the Serbian republic, Montenegro, and Macedonia. The Bosnian declaration of independence provoked intervention by the JNA, and a secessionist uprising by the republic’s Serb minority.62 Under the leadership of Radovan Karadzic, and supplied by Milosevic’s Serbia, the Bosnian Serbs established an independent republic called Republika Srpska, with a ‘capital’ in Pale.63 Their military organization enabled the Bosnian Serbs to gain large swaths of territory, especially in the first months of fighting, crushing the unprepared and unorganized Bosnian troops.64 Just like the Serbs in Croatia, the Serbs here put much effort into ethnically cleansing their new republic. Taking town after town, burning villages and murdering non-Serbs, they undertook a siege of Bosnia’s ethnically mixed capital Sarajevo. This was to be one of the longest and most cruel sieges of the Yugoslav wars. Taking position on the surrounding hills, Bosnian Serbs randomly sniped innocent civilians and shelled civilian targets, putting the residents of Sarajevo in a state of terror which would last for three years.65 The Bosnian war also saw the reinvention of concentration camps, which 58 James Gow, The Serbian project and its adversaries: a strategy of war crimes (London: C. Hurst, 2003) 145. Ibid., 51-89. 60 Finlan, The Collapse of Yugoslavia, 28. For an account of the notorious Arkan, see: Christopher S. Stewart, Hunting the Tiger – the Fast Life and Violent Death of the Balkans most Dangerous Man (New York: Thomas Dunne Books, 2007). Another well-known group was the Scorpions. For them, see: Samuel Tanner and Massimiliano Mulone, ‘Private Security and Armed Conflit: A Case Study of the Scorpions during the Mass Killings in Former Yugoslavia’, The British Journal of Criminology 53:1 (2013) 41-58. 61 Since the Croats and Slovenes had left, Milosevic now controlled four of the six votes. 62 An agreement between Tudjman and Milosevic seems to have foreseen these events. In March 1991 they agreed at Karadjordjevo to partition Bosnia into Croatian and Serbian parts, leaving the Muslim Bosniacs, the region’s largest ethnic group, with no territory of their own. See: Finlan, The Collapse of Yugoslavia, 37. 63 Gow, The Serbian Project, 150. 64 Finlan, The Collapse of Yugoslavia, 39-40. 65 LeBor, Milosevic, 302-317. For a military history of the siege of Sarajevo, see: Curtis S. King, ‘The Siege of Sarajevo, 1992-1995’, in: William G. Robertson and Lawrence A. Yates (eds.), Block by Block: The Challenges of Urban Operations (Fort Leavenworth: U.S. Army Command and General Staff College Press, 2003) 235-290. 59 64 the Serbs used to imprison non-Serbs they had collected during their ethnic cleansing campaigns. The most notorious of these camps was at the north-west Bosnian town of Omerska, in which thousands of non-Serbs had to endure systematic beatings, rapes, and want-on killings.66 Further aggravating the situation in Bosnia was the outbreak of a savage civil war between Bosnian Croats and the Muslim population in October 1992. Just as Bosnia’s Serbs were supported by Serbia’s Milosevic, Bosnia’s Croats were supported by Tudjman’s Croatia.67 International response, continued fighting and the role of Milosevic, 1991-1994 The response of the international community during these crises was, although well-intentioned, often weak and ineffective. The Brioni Agreement, which was negotiated by the EC and ended the war between Slovenia and Yugoslavia, gave false hope that the Western world would be able to manage the violence by diplomacy alone.68 The quick recognition of the independence of Slovenia, Croatia, and Bosnia probably only worsened the situation in the former Yugoslavia. The recognitions were an easy target for Milosevic’s propaganda machine, which portrayed them as evidence that the international community treated the Serbs unfairly.69 The United Nations was quick to respond with sanctions against Serbia, recognizing the republic’s involvement in the Croatian and Bosnian wars. Moreover, in February 1992, the Security Council sanctioned a deployment of 14.000 UNPROFOR (United Nations Protection Force)-peacekeepers to Croatia.70 Apart from sending peacekeepers, U.N. the May 1993 Security Council Resolution 827 established the International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia, which was meant to deter further atrocities by prosecuting those most responsible for them. 71 Starting in early 1993, six ‘safe areas’ were created in Bosnia, where the U.N. troops were mandated to protect them “by all necessary measures”.72 All of these measures amounted to a significant commitment by the international community to end the conflict in the former Yugoslavia. However, there was a general unwillingness to become involved in a large-scale military conflict. Countries like the United States and Great Britain felt little for a costly military enterprise in a region where they felt they had no core For a personal and dramatic account of the siege of Sarajevo, see: Zlata Filipovic, Zlata’s Diary – A Child’s Life in Sarajevo (London: Puffin Books, 1995). 66 Gow, The Serbian Project, 134-138. 67 Charles R. Schrader, The Muslim-Croat Civil War: A Military History, 1992-1994 (College Station: Texas A&M University Press, 2003) xvii. 68 Finlan, The Collapse of Yugoslavia, 22-23. 69 Sell, The Destruction of Yugoslavia, 154. 70 The forces deployed under UNPROFOR had only a very limited mandate. They were not to fire unless fired upon, and were supposed to remain impartial in the conflict zone. It is important to stress here, that they had “a purely humanitarian role in which the soldiers in blue helmets could only try and encourage peace, not enforce it”. UNPROFOR eventually swelled to over 30.000 troops in 1994, deploying to Croatia, Macedonia, and Bosnia. See: Finlan, The Collapse of Yugoslavia, 29. For a reproduction of the Rules of Engagement, see: Ibid., 32. 71 For the Resolution’s text, see: United Nations Security Council, ‘Resolution 827 (1993)’, (25 May 1993), available online at: http://www.un.org/en/ga/search/view_doc.asp?symbol=S/RES/827(1993) (30 September 2013). 72 These six safe areas were Bihac, Gorazde, Srebrenica, Sarajevo, Tuzla and Zepa. See: Finlan, The Collapse of Yugoslavia, 48-49. 65 interests at stake. A limited mandate for the peacekeepers, together with this general reluctance to become involved, made sure that the international involvement in the Yugoslav wars initially became a failure.73 In the years after 1991, Milosevic established what is often called a ‘soft dictatorship’ in Serbia.74 With his extended control over the media and his cronies in place in the government’s and economy’s top positions, his leadership was almost uncontested. Not only was the opposition weak and crippled by in-fighting, the republic’s inhabitants actually favored Milosevic. Although his nationalist populism somewhat decreased after he had comfortable control over power, many Serbs still saw in their ‘Slobo’ a true defender of the Serbs, someone who would not give up on the Serbs’ rights in Kosovo and who would not give in to external pressures targeting the Serbs. As such, Milosevic’s propaganda found a fertile soil among the Serbian population.75 By integrating a powerful economic, intellectual and state elite, making them his clients, Milosevic consolidated his hold on power even further. His wife’s political party, the hardline communist Yugoslav United Left (JUL), played an important role in this process. Those who profiteered from the Bosnian and Croatian wars, what Laura Silber calls “a rabble of war profiteers, smugglers, and criminals”, joined her party, understanding that Mira’s connection to Slobodan was crucial in the acquirement of government contracts or important political and military decisions.76 Although JUL had very little political support, it was thus to become one of the most powerful political parties in Milosevic’s Serbia. In the meantime, Milosevic kept insisting that Serbia had nothing to do with the fighting in Bosnia and Croatia. Even when coffins started arriving from Bosnia on a daily basis, he declared that “no Serbs took part in the fighting”. Still, he supplied the Croatian and Bosnian Serbs with weapons, money, training, and even troops. Moreover, the Serb-dominated JNA was an important part of Milosevic’s strategy in Bosnia and Croatia. Even before the republics declared their independence, JNA troops were supplying Bosnian and Croatian troops with arms. When the JNA disbanded, its troops simply went to the Serbian side.77 Furthermore, intercepted phone records, presented at his ICTY trial, clearly show him orchestrating coordinated operations with the Serbs in Croatia and Bosnia.78 However, there is some discussion as to the amount of influence Milosevic had over the Croat and Bosnian Serbs. The paradox is that, on the one hand, he declared himself powerless over the Croatian and Bosnian Serbs. When he was accused of planning with them and supporting their operations, he claimed he could not stop them and that he had no influence over them. On the other hand, however, Milosevic constantly 73 Ibid., 40. Cohen, Serpent in the Bosom, 97; Sell, The Destruction of Yugoslavia, 193. 75 Snyder, From Voting to Violence, 217-218. On this, see also: Takis S. Pappas, ‘Shared culture, individual strategy and collective action: explaining Slobodan Milosevic’s charismatic rise to power’, Southeast European and Black Sea Studies 5:2 (2006) 191-211; Stacy Sullivan, ‘Milosevic’s Willing Executioners’, New Republic 220:19 (1999) 26-32. 76 Silber, ‘Milosevic Family Values’, 26. 77 Gow, The Serbian Project, 75-79. 78 Josip Glaurdic, ‘Inside the Serbian War Machine: The Milosevic Telephone Intercepts’, East European Politics and Societies 23:1 (2009) 86-104, 94-97. 74 66 propagated himself as the go-to man for a peace deal in the Balkans, for which he apparently would have enough influence with this ethnic brethren. Yet, his control was not always as direct and complete as he might have wished. This became clear when the international community increased its commitment to a negotiated end to the conflict. After a series of failed peace efforts, Special Envoy for the Secretary-General of the United Nations Cyrus Vance and EC-delegate David Owen managed in January 1993 to have their peace plan – which would partition Bosnia into ten ethnic provinces with a decentralized government structure – signed by the conflict’s major actors, including Milosevic and Karadzic. It was mostly Milosevic who conducted the negotiations and he practically forced Karadzic to sign the peace deal. However, the Bosnian Serbs disliked the plan and, despite strong pressure from Milosevic, rebuked it during a Pale assembly in May.79 It turned out that the Bosnian Serbs were not merely puppets in Milosevic’s hands. They were autonomous actors who, although with significant support from Serbia, were still capable of making their own decisions. Milosevic had much leverage with them, but this only went so far. Even Ratko Mladic, who was sent by the JNA to take over military command of the Bosnian Serb armed forces (VRS) in May 1992 and over whom Milosevic exercised significant control, voted against the Vance-Owen peace plan.80 The Bosnian Serbs’ refusal put a temporary stop to the diplomatic peace efforts by the EC. Increasing diplomatic efforts and the Dayton peace process, 1994-1995 In 1994 European pressure caused the U.S. to increase its role in the region. Under the leadership of Bill Clinton, NATO threatened airstrikes unless Serbs agreed to put their heavy weapons around Sarajevo under U.N. observation.81 By February, after an agreement between Karadzic and the Russian president Boris Yeltsin resulted in the deployment of Russian peacekeepers, which lessened fears of reprisal and made a NATO strike impossible, the Bosnian Serbs complied. Moreover, U.S. involvement ended the fighting between Croats and Bosniacs. On 18 March 1994, the two sides signed an agreement in Washington, creating the Moslim-Croat Federation of Bosnia. With this alliance, the military balance started to turn against the Bosnian Serbs.82 Sanctions against Serbia increased as well. Ratko Mladic did not seem to care about America’s increased role, however. He stepped up the military campaign, and intensified the ethnic cleansing operations. When Bosnian Serbs tested the international community’s resolve, it turned out every single time that Mladic could remain openly defiant without the international community pushing through their threat.83 The Pale leadership 79 Sell, The Destruction of Yugoslavia, 207-209. Armatta, ‘Historical Revelations’, 19-20. 81 The immediate cause of this threat was the shelling of Sarajevo’s Markale Market on 5 February, which killed over sixty people. Sell, The Destruction of Yugoslavia, 214. 82 Ibid., 215. 83 This situation was worsened by the unwillingness of military leaders in the region to interpret their mandate more broadly. They were reluctant to increase violence levels, partly because of fears of escalation, and partly because they were unsure of the political response to military action. 80 67 remained hostile to any peace agreement that did not accept the Bosnian Serbs’ right to an independent state. They rejected a 12 July Contact Group proposal, calling for a 51:49 division of territory – 51 percent for the Bosniac-Croat federation, 49 for the Bosnian Serbs. This led to a quarrel between Milosevic, who saw the Bosnian Serbs’ implacability as an obstacle to the lifting of sanctions on Serbia, and Karadzic, which culminated in the cessation of contacts between Belgrade and Pale.84 When the Bosnian Serbs started new offensives against U.N. safe areas towards the end of 1994, NATO tried to bomb them into compliance. As a response, 165 U.N. peacekeepers were taken hostage. This made the international community wary of more air strikes and taught Karadzic and Mladic that they could defy the international community without serious consequences. Yet, events in 1995 caused the international community to change its strategy from peacekeeping to peace enforcement and to finally take serious military steps to end the conflict. After a series of brutal campaigns by the Bosnian Serbs against U.N. safe areas –including the capture of Srebrenica on 10 July 1995, followed by the massacre of over 5.000 Bosniac men by Mladic’s Serbs – NATO changed its air strikes policy from air support operations to a sustained bombing campaign, which could be initiated by the commander of U.N. troops in the area.85 UNPROFOR-commander General Rupert Smith did so on the evening of 28 August 1995, after mortar shells fired by Bosnian Serbs exploded in the Markale Market in Sarajevo, killing thirty-seven and wounding around ninety.86 At first Mladic and Karadzic remained defiant. However, a combination of Operation Deliberate Force – as the NATO bombing campaign was called – and mediation by Milosevic made them finally accept NATO’s demands on 21 September. They agreed to cease hostilities, respect the safe areas, and put their heavy weapons around Sarajevo under U.N. inspection.87 The bombing put a definitive end to the fouryear long siege of Sarajevo, and was a strong signal to all warring parties that negotiations would have to be taken seriously this time.88 Another factor pushing the Serbian parties to the negotiation table, was their changed military fortunes. As was mentioned earlier, the end of the war between Bosnian Croats and Bosniacs significantly changed the military balance in Bosnia to the detriment of the Bosnian Serbs. Furthermore, on 4 August 1995, the Croatian army – rebuilt with U.S. military assistance – initiated Operation Storm which recaptured almost all territory held by the Croatian Serbs. While the operation was a military success, there were also countless reports of atrocities by Croats against Serbs. 89 Making use of the 84 The supply of the Bosnian Serb army by Serbia did not stop, however. Goods were still smuggled across the Dvina on a regular basis. Sell, The Destruction of Yugoslavia, 217-218. 85 Finlan, The Collapse of Yugoslavia, 79-80. 86 Sell, The Destruction of Yugoslavia, 246-247. According to Cohen, 38 people were killed, and 85 were wounded. Furthermore he states that only a single mortar shell was fired. See: Cohen, Serpent in the Bosom, 156. Following Sabrina Ramet, I tend to agree with Sell, rather than with Cohen. See: Ramet, ‘Review Essay’, 463464. 87 Finlan, The Collapse of Yugoslavia, 81-82. 88 Piers Robinson, ‘Misperception in foreign policy making: Operation ‘deliberate force’ and the ending of war in Bosnia’, Civil Wars 4:4 (2001) 115-126, 120. 89 Finlan, The Collapse of Yugoslavia, 80. 68 weakened Serbian position, Bosnian Croat and Muslim troops attacked the Bosnian Serb positions in September 1995 to regain as much territory as possible to strengthen their negotiating position, sending waves of refuges into Serbia and Montenegro. The changed military situation on the ground, together with increasing military and diplomatic pressure, culminated in the negotiations that were finally able to put an end to the wars in the Balkans.90 These negotiations were led by U.S. diplomat Richard Holbrooke and held in October 1995 at the Wright-Patterson Air Force base in Dayton, Ohio. Representatives from Croatia, the different parties in Bosnia, and Serbia were invited. During the bombing, Milosevic had forced Karadzic to sign an agreement which gave him the power to negotiate for the Bosnian Serbs.91 Milosevic had strong incentives to sign a peace agreement. His domestic position had been seriously weakened: war, sanctions, political corruption and economic mismanagement had crippled the Serbian economy; and the bombing and Operation Storm had impaired the war effort in Bosnia and Croatia.92 Although Milosevic was empowered by the Pale leadership to negotiate for the Bosnian Serbs, they still sent their own delegate, Momcilo Krajisnik. During Dayton, Milosevic seemed to despise the Bosnian Serbs. He frequently humiliated Krajisnik and often acted contrary to the Bosnian Serbs’ wishes.93 That Milosevic seemed to be the go-to-man for the Americans, reveals something about the true power relations in the Balkans.94 In the end, the agreement accepted on 21 November 1995 by all parties, included the partitioning of Bosnia into two largely autonomous republics – similar to the Contact Group plan of 51 percent for the Bosnian Croat-Muslim Federation and 49 percent for a Bosnian Serbian Republic –, a cessation of all hostilities and an easing of sanctions against Serbia.95 Furthermore, after personal negotiations between Milosevic and Tudjman, all of Croatia – including the eastern part of the country which was still controlled by the Krajina Serbs – was given back to Tudjman.96 U.N. forces would be sent in to enforce the peace agreement, this time with sizeable deployments of ground troops from the U.S. Milosevic the peacekeeper and the Kosovo wars, 1995-1999 When Milosevic signed the Dayton accords, he was of the contention that all of the sanctions against his country would be lifted. However, when the peace accords did not result in a complete abandonment of sanctions – for example, they continued barring Serbia from the so desperately needed international financial institutions – Milosevic felt betrayed.97 The powerful disappointment he felt, increased Mira’s 90 LeBor, Milosevic, 328. Moreover, Karadzic and Mladic had been indicted by the ICTY, barring them from travel to the United States. See: Cohen, Serpent in the Bosom, 158. 92 LeBor, Milosevic, 319. 93 To Haris Siladjzic, the Bosnian prime minister, Milosevic said: “You deserve Sarajevo because you fought for it and those cowards killed you from the hills.” The cowards were the Bosnian Serbs. Quoted in: Ibid., 327. 94 Ibid., 329-330. 95 Ibid., 321-322. 96 Ibid., 328-329. 97 Sell, ‘A Political Biography’, 22. 91 69 hold over him. Meanwhile, JUL’s influence in the government amplified significantly. The failure of Milosevic to repair the Serbian economy, together with growing discontent about the way in which Milosevic and Markovic ruled the country, culminated in large-scale protests in 1996-1997. The demonstrations were sparked by Milosevic’s shameless manipulation of the October 1996 election results. Milosevic, who thought the protests were a U.S. conspiracy against his rule, reacted with increasingly authoritarian measures. The fact that he remained in power despite the large demonstrations, can be explained by his strong hold on power and the disorganization of the Serbian opposition, which was not able to unite the Serbian people against what now more and more seemed to be a Balkan tyrant.98 The Dayton agreements made Milosevic a ‘peacekeeper’ for the international community. He was seen as an essential cog in the stability of the Balkans.99 However, the outbreak of violence in Kosovo between Kosovar Albanians – united in the Kosovo Liberation Army (UCK), which fought for an independent Kosovo – and Kosovar Serbs and its subsequent escalation in 1998, and especially Milosevic’s response to it, started to undermine his peaceful image.100 The Serbs in the autonomous region felt persecuted and discriminated by the Albanian majority. Now faced with increasing opposition to his rule, Milosevic decided to once again use Serbian nationalism to maintain his hold on power. Milosevic’s campaign in Kosovo started in 1998 with operations by Serbian paramilitary units and the Serbian army. The fight against the Albanian UCK quickly took on the form of an ethnic cleansing campaign, which removed hundreds of thousands of ethnic Albanians from the province. In March 1998 the U.N. Security Council decided that the Kosovo conflict was a threat to international peace. The threat of NATO airstrikes brought about an agreement between Milosevic and Holbrooke in October 1998 to install an unarmed Kosovo Verification Mission (KVM) by the Organization for Security and Co-operation in Europe (OSCE), which would have to maintain peace in the province.101 However, the UCK decided in November that progress towards a political settlement was not going quick enough and stepped up their attacks against Serbian and KVM-targets.102 After the killing of three Serbian policemen by the UCK, the Serbs retaliated by attacking Albanian civilians in Racak in January 1999. When KVM-observers found out about the massacre, the Contact Group was “galvanized into action”.103 The coercive diplomacy ending in an interim settlement proposed by the Contact Group at Rambouillet was unsuccessful, however. Milosevic was not to be deterred by the in his perception incredible threat of NATO air strikes.104 It turned out that the attack on Racak was just the beginning. As NATO was debating air strikes against Serbian targets, Milosevic was putting into effect the 98 LeBor, Milosevic, 344-348. Ibid., 331-332. 100 Alex J. Bellamy, Kosovo and International Society (New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2002) 65-66. 101 Sell, The Destruction of Yugoslavia, 288-291. 102 Bellamy, Kosovo and International Society, 110-111. 103 Ibid., 119. 104 Michael Ignatieff, Virtual War: Kosovo and Beyond (London: Chatto & Windus, 2000) 59-61; Sell, The Destruction of Yugoslavia, 299-304. 99 70 previously organized Operation Horseshoe, a large-scale military operation to retake the province on which he had staked all of his political fortunes.105 Milosevic might have gotten away with abandoning the Croatian and Bosnian Serbs at Dayton, but letting Kosovo go would mean the end of his political career, if not of his life. Operation Horseshoe, a carefully planned move into Kosovo by the Serbian Army which entailed the ethnic cleansing of the province, was implemented on 26 February 1999.106 The last negotiations in Paris took place in March, while 20.000 Albanians had already been forcibly dislodged from their homes.107 After the Paris negotiations had failed as well, NATO started Operation Allied Force, a sustained bombing campaign against Serbian targets. Milosevic at first seemed defiant, especially when on 27 May 1999 he was indicted for war crimes by the ICTY.108 However, after 78 days of NATO bombing he seemed to accept the inevitable and in June 1999 gave up his operations in Kosovo, accepting the intervention of the international community.109 In the end, Milosevic agreed to retreat the army from Kosovo and install a U.N. peacekeeping mission there.110 Endgame, 1999-2006 Milosevic’s failure to hold on to Kosovo – the province where his rise to power began, the province that had always been central in his political campaigns – was one of the more significant factors leading to his downfall, eroding any political support he still had left. Milosevic once again responded against opposition with authoritarian measures. Disappearances of his opponents became a regular phenomenon, with Ivan Stambolic vanishing in August 2000. In the elections of September 2000, he suffered an embarrassing defeat, losing to the democratic opposition which had finally organized itself in the Democratic Party of Serbia (DOS) around Vojislav Kostunica. Only after a final attempt to rig the elections resulted in the storming of the Serbian parliament by an angry crowd of hundreds of thousands of people on 5 October 2000, did Milosevic accept his defeat. He retired to his Belgrade mansion, “realizing that the game was up”.111 Thus, the failure of Milosevic to hold on to Kosovo was an important factor contributing to his fall in 2000. By this time, the region had already started to rebuild from almost a decade of war and conflict.112 Kostunica, the new President of Serbia did not intend to let Milosevic live in peace, however. In the end of March 2001, Kostunica sent the Serbian police to arrest Milosevic for corruption and abuse 105 Ibid., 48. Bellamy, Kosovo and International Society, 164-165. 107 Ibid., 151. 108 Sell, The Destruction of Yugoslavia, 318. 109 Charlie Lyon, ‘Operation Allied Force: A Lesson on Strategy, Risk, and Tactical Execution’, Comparative Strategy 20:1 (2001) 57-75. 110 Sell, The Destruction of Yugoslavia, 308-310. 111 Dragan Bujosevic and Ivan Radovanovic, The Fall of Milosevic: The October 5th Revolution (New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2003) 8; Finlan, The Collapse of Yugoslavia, 88-89. 112 See, inter alia: Ola Listhaug, Sabrina P. Ramet, and Dragana Dulic (eds.), Civic and Uncivic Values: Serbia in the post-Milosevic era (Budapest and New York: Central European University Press, 2011); Sabrina P. Ramet, Konrad Clewing, and Reneo Lukic (eds.), Croatia since Independence: War, Politics, Society, Foreign Relations (Munich: R. Oldenbourg, 2008). 106 71 of power. Milosevic remained defiant. His bodyguards fired back at the police, sending them into retreat. In the end, Milosevic only surrendered after being guaranteed that he would not be sent to The Hague, and that his family would receive protection and be allowed to remain in Belgrade. On 31 March he was arrested and taken to jail in downtown Belgrade. The linking of U.S. assistance to the new government with the extradition of Milosevic to the ICTY, however, finally convinced Kostunica to comply with his obligations to the Tribunal. On 28 June he was transferred to Scheveningen to face war crimes accusations.113 Milosevic was furious that he was sent to The Hague. He did not recognize the Tribunal’s legitimacy and, during his entire trial, remained openly hostile and defiant to the Tribunal’s procedures. His behavior caused significant delays in the trial’s proceedings. Furthermore, the difficulties the Prosecution was having in building up its case against him, exacerbated these delays. On 11 March 2006, all the efforts of the Prosecution proved to have been too late. Milosevic was found dead in his prison cell, reportedly having suffered a fatal heart attack due to medical complications, although his family remains convinced that he was poisoned.114 Thus, in a lonely prison cell in Scheveningen, on trial before the International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia, Milosevic’s life ended. In conclusion In this paragraph, a (relatively) short overview has been given of the conflicts that erupted in the Balkans after Yugoslavia disintegrated in the early 1990s. The short Slovenian war of 1991 proved to be the easiest one to end. The complexity and large numbers of actors, who were aligned along ethnic lines but often fought in varying alliances against different enemies, made the Bosnian and Croatian wars, which erupted in 1991-1992, much harder to solve. The support and involvement of states such as Croatia, Serbia, and Albania aggravated the situation even further. Although the Bosnian and Croatian wars effectively ended with the Dayton peace accords of 1995, this did not mean the end of massive violence in the Balkan. Serbia’s Kosovo campaign of 1998-1999 once again saw the ethnic cleansing of thousands of people and the perpetration of large-scale massacres. A huge NATO bombing operation finally ended this conflict in June 1999. Much of the conflict in the former Yugoslavia was characterized by ethnic tensions, leading to savagery and atrocities on a scale which Europe had not seen since the Second World War. The atrocities taking place during these conflicts, have often been blamed on one man in particular, Slobodan Milosevic. Slobodan ‘Slobo’ Milosevic’s life saw many of the major historic trends in Yugoslavia. Although he probably did not remember it, Milosevic witnessed the dramatic effects of the occupation by Nazi Germany’s forces and the massacres against the Serbs by the Croats’ Ustasha party. During his high school years, he joined in the praise of the omnipresent Tito. When in law school, he participated in the communist youth organization, filling various functions and befriending the future 113 Sell, The Destruction of Yugoslavia, 353-354. His death and the surrounding controversies are treated at length in: Branislav Jakovljevic, ‘From Mastermind to Body Artist: Political Performances of Slobodan Milosevic’, The Drama Review 52:1 (2008) 51-74, 52-56. 114 72 President of Serbia, Ivan Stambolic. From his twenties to his forties he reaped the benefits of the marketoriented reforms of the 1960s and 1970s, which made Yugoslavia one of the most beloved communist dictatorships in the West. When in the 1980s Yugoslavia’s communist state structure lost legitimacy and nationalist sentiments were on the rise throughout the federation, Milosevic was one of the first and most successful politicians to use this nationalism to make a bid for power. His participation in the violent disintegration of the SFRY in the 1990s and his aggressive use of force against the Kosovar Albanians in 1999, finally put him in the place where he would spend the last years of his life, a prison cell in Scheveningen. In this way, he unwillingly became part of the reconciliation efforts that were being undertaken by the international community in the former Yugoslavia. 73 §2.2 Slobodan Milosevic, “good communist”, “Serb national hero”, and “Butcher of the Balkans” The purpose of this paragraph is to adequately understand the man who is often held most responsible for the chaos that engulfed the Balkans in the 1990s. To do so, it will analyze his rationality along the guidelines that were presented in the analytical framework. The second and third section will do the same for, respectively, his motivation and his personality. §2.2.1 A ‘Mad Man’ or a Calculating Mastermind: the Rationality of Slobodan Milosevic In the analytical framework, it was mentioned that deterrence theory assumes that crimes are committed after a conscious, rational analysis of costs and benefits. It was stressed, however, that human decision making often does not conform to this conceptualization. There are various ways in which the decision making process deviates from it and in which the capacity of humans to make fully rational decisions is limited. It was suggested that computational difficulties, cognitive biases, emotions, and individual differences were important in this limitation. In this section, the rationality of Milosevic will be studied to analyze the ways in which the fallacies of Milosevic’s decision making process restricted his conscious weighing of the possible costs and benefits of his actions, which would have been important for deterrence to be achieved. According to many observers of Milosevic – those who have worked with him as well as international commentators – he was an excellent tactician, but a mediocre, or even bad, strategist.115 It is now clear that he made many ‘bad’ decisions. These decisions were made with limited foresight and had the goal of ensuring survival in the short term. Although, through these decisions, Milosevic was able to maintain his hold on power for over a decade, in the end they ensured his downfall. In many ways, Milosevic displayed great intelligence and a powerful grasp of party politics.116 During the endless stream of negotiations in the 1990s, Milosevic was noted for his excellent case knowledge, often speaking without prepared notes, able to remember many small details.117 He had a knack for playing people against each other, with himself coming out on top. However, since he was also human, his computational abilities were clearly limited. Especially his lack of foresight limited a proper weighing of costs and benefits. Moreover, Milosevic seemed to employ a gambler’s mentality, resulting in a highrisk attitude of ‘all or nothing’ in favor of a more nuanced policy.118 In Bosnia, Croatia, and Kosovo his policies seemed to be directed towards the maximization of his gains in the regions, simply hoping that the negative consequences would be minimal, or outweighed by his gains. Yet, he did seem to be aware 115 Ramet notices this consensus in four accounts of Milosevic (Cohen, LeBor, Sell, and Snyder). See: Ramet, ‘Review Essay’, 455. 116 Sell, The Destruction of Yugoslavia, 172. 117 LeBor, Milosevic, 313. 118 Sell, ‘A Political Biography’, 23-24. 74 of possible negative consequences of his behavior. For example, he made efforts to evade identification by erasing any documentary trail of his involvement in the Yugoslav wars. With the minimization of evidence against him, he hoped to reduce the chance that he would be held accountable by any judicial institution. As such, it would be an overstatement to say that Milosevic was only occupied with the achievement of short-term goals, and only able to see the short-term consequences of his actions. Yet, the image of him that emerges from outsider and insider accounts certainly seem to stress his general lack of foresight. His failure in Kosovo is often blamed on miscalculation: in his eyes, NATO would not have the guts to bomb Serbia.119 The computational difficulties described above limited Milosevic’s capability to rationally calculate the costs and benefits of his actions. When we study the influence of cognitive biases on Milosevic’s decision making, there are a number of factors which consistently played a role. First of all, a powerful confirmation bias prevented Milosevic from adopting a more nuanced worldview. The interaction between him and his wife Mira produced a situation in which they relied heavily on each other to confirm each other’s worldviews. Milosevic was reported to only believe those pieces of information that suited his beliefs. In this way, fantastical notions like his firm belief that Serbians – especially Mira and himself – were not aggressors, but rather the victims of aggression by the United States, remained unchallenged.120 Milosevic often seemed to genuinely believe in his innocence, and simply denied any accusations of involvement with, or sometimes even the existence of, ethnic cleansing as false. For example, in an interview, when asked about his accountability for the crimes committed during the war and a possible trial in The Hague, Milosevic replied: “My conscience is completely clear.”121 This situation was reinforced by the fact that he surrounded himself with ‘yes men’ and the replacement of those around him who were too critical in their approach. Those who worked for Milosevic often did not dare to inform their boss about events which would make him angry. Moreover, Milosevic did not want to hear bad news. As such, the limited information pool – limited both because of the availability heuristic and the confirmation bias – on which Milosevic based his decision making process, biased its outcome. Furthermore, there seems to have been a process of ‘loss aversion’ at work. Especially Milosevic’s venture into Kosovo was a last pursuit to hold on to power. The possible negative consequences of this action – the ICTY-indictment, NATO bombings, and finally his fall from power – were clearly downplayed. The chance of a loss of power which was looming after the protests of 1996-1997 and the increasing opposition to his rule, had to be fended off at all cost. Third, Milosevic’s decision making process was also significantly affected by his powerful affective moods. According to the Milosevic family’s doctors, both Slobodan and Mirjana were emotionally unstable. When the Bosnian Serbs rejected the Vance-Owen peace plan, Slobodan 119 Cohen, Serpent in the Bosom, 272-274. Silber, ‘Milosevic Family Values’, 23, 27. 121 Sell, The Destruction of Yugoslavia, 174. 120 75 reportedly suffered from a depressive episode.122 He thrashed his office out of anger during the protests of 1996-1997 and the NATO bombing of 1999.123 Moreover, his regular fits of rage against the West saw him – amongst others – accusing the West of harboring a neo-Nazi plan to destroy Yugoslavia, implementing a neo-colonial design to create a ‘Greater Albania’ and fabricating atrocities to bring him and the Serbian people down.124 As was mentioned in the analytical framework, although these tantrums might in part have been for show, the anger at times also seems to have been genuine. Milosevic did not only rage against his enemies while in front of the camera, but also in private situations. His emotional instability must have seriously shortcut rational considerations. It only increased the commitment to his own goals, decreasing the willingness to compromise with his enemies (non-Serbs, NATO, the U.S., the U.N., etc.). In conclusion In all these ways, the capacity, capability, and willingness of Milosevic to seriously, consciously, and objectively weigh the costs and benefits of his actions, which would have resulted in a rational decisions making process, was limited. However, one should not conclude from this that Milosevic was completely irrational, some kind of ‘mad man’. His great tactical skills ensured his survival for over a decade. However, the limitations to his decision making process clearly decreased his responsiveness to sanction threats. He failed to foresee that he would eventually lose power, be arrested and extradited to The Hague. However, he clearly preferred to either ‘have it all’ or ‘lose everything’. The events which finally led to his downfall – the ethnic cleansing in Kosovo, the rigging of elections – seemed to Milosevic to be the only choice to maintain his hold on power. As such, the loss aversion-effect, together with his gambler’s mentality, seems to have led to a certain kind of ‘no way back’-calculation. In Kosovo, in Milosevic’s eyes at least, his power was at stake. Giving in to either ICTY sanction threats or coercive diplomacy by the West would have almost certainly led to his loss of power and being shunned by his peers. And indeed, his ultimate failure to hold on to Kosovo was a significant factor which contributed to his downfall, his arrest, and finally his extradition to The Hague. 122 Ibid., 174-175. Ibid., 175. 124 Anthony Borden, ‘Milosevic Rages Against the West’, Institute for War & Peace Reporting, (15 February 2002), available online at: http://iwpr.net/report-news/milosevic-rages-against-west (10 October 2013). 123 76 §2.2.2 Milosevic’s motivation What drove Milosevic to destabilize the Balkans? Why did he incite the murder of thousands? Why did he implement the ethnic cleansing operations which led to mass atrocities? Most biographies of Slobodan Milosevic try to answer these questions by concluding that the prime motivator for Milosevic was the pure acquirement of power. In this paragraph I will analyze this conclusion and also try to present a counter-argument, namely that Milosevic did in part believe in his nationalist rhetoric and implemented his policies according to the nationalist Serbian ideology. Carla del Ponte, Prosecutor for the ICTY from August 1999 to January 2008, has stated that “everything with […] Milosevic was an instrument in the service of his quest for power”.125 It is David Rieff’s contention that, he “cannot be said to have had core beliefs – core beliefs other than in himself, that is”.126 This conviction, that Milosevic was basically only really interested in power, is a widely held notion about Milosevic. Even Slobodan’s wife, has said that he is not really interested in ideology, and would not exactly die for an idea.127 Those who support this view argue that Milosevic cynically manipulated Serbian nationalism, fashioning himself as a defender of Serbian nationalist interests, and its supporters in the 1980s and used them to push aside his enemies and increase his hold on power. Similarly, his support for the Bosnian Serbs and the Croatian Serbs did not stem from a genuine concern for their well-being, but rather from the wish to create a Greater Serbia under his control. When the Bosnian Serbs increasingly went out of control and when supporting them did not longer suit Milosevic’s personal interests, he cynically abandoned them at Dayton, forcing them to give up Sarajevo, which was entirely against the Bosnian Serbs’ own wishes. As soon as the Croatian Operation Storm began, he abandoned the Croatian Serbs, leaving them to their faith.128 In Kosovo, Milosevic did the same. When pressured hard enough he abandoned the Kosovar Serbs, leaving them vulnerable to retaliatory mass murders. Even though he portrayed himself as the only true defender of the Serbs, his actions did not fit this rhetoric. The sanctions that were the result of his actions in Croatia and Bosnia, together with his own economic policies, destroyed the Serbian economy, leaving many Serbs hungry, and caused a rampant inflation. Nor did Milosevic do much to help the thousands of Bosnian, Croatian and Kosovar Serbs which fled to Serbia during the various conflicts.129 If Milosevic’s values would have to be described, then, the only real values that he seemed to hold were his own self-interest, which was best served by power – which he valued most –, and the wellbeing of his family – his wife and his children. There seem to have been very few moral norms which moderated his behavior. He went over the backs of his friends, his ethnic brethren, and especially the 125 Carla del Ponte, Opening arguments by the Prosecutor, (12 February 2002), available online at: http://www.icty.org/x/cases/slobodan_milosevic/trans/en/020212IT.htm (10 October 2013) p. 9. 126 David Rieff, ‘Milosevic in Retrospect: An Essay’, Virginia Quarterly Review 82:1 (2006) 8-17, 9. 127 She claimed that she would die in defense of her ideology, although the ideology in her case, would of course be communism. 128 Rieff, ‘Milosevic in Retrospect’, 11. 129 Sell, ‘A Political Biography’, 16-17. 77 non-Serbs, to further his goals. The love and affection for his wife have been described above. Her influence on his decisions was enormous. According to Crnbornja, “more often than not Milosevic carried out her wishes and designs, even if it went against his better judgment and the council of his advisers”.130 He valued her opinions, and was constantly serving to her needs. Especially after Dayton, when Milosevic felt betrayed by the United States, Mirjana’s influence grew exponentially.131 Therefore, it is essential to recognize the influence of Mira when Milosevic’s motivation is analyzed. Moreover, the protection of his family was an important value for Milosevic. When the Serbian police set out to arrest him in 2001, he only agreed to surrender after receiving guarantees that his family would be protected and demanded guarantees that he would not be extradited to the ICTY. These two demands seem to sum up his most important values, his own self-interest and the well-being of his family. At times, however, Milosevic did seem to believe in the nationalism he propagated.132 This phenomenon – wherein someone who belies the world, in the end also belies himself – was described earlier in the analytical framework. The propaganda that someone disseminates, invariably effects the one who spreads it as well. He was convinced that the Serbian people were once again singled out for victimization by the world community, just as they had become victims of Ottoman repression after the 1389 battle of Kosovo Polje and of Croatian persecution during the Second World War. Moreover, he often accused the Western world of treating him unfairly. Especially after Dayton, he was disillusioned and genuinely felt betrayed when the United States lifted only part of the sanctions against Serbia – even though the gradual lifting of sanctions was agreed to in the Dayton peace accords. Other observers also note that, although Milosevic is not a committed ideologue, he “creates a core personality for himself and then shapes his own perception of the world to fit that personality”, meaning that he does actually believe in his lies.133 Defying outside powers to protect himself, and according to his rhetoric also the Serbs, might therefore have been to some extent motivated by elements of Serbian nationalism. The failure of the ICTY’s sanction threats to motivate Milosevic can also in part be explained by pointing to the differences between intrinsic and extrinsic motivation. Milosevic would have preferred to act on his intrinsic values. Thus, the course of action which he would have preferred would have resulted in the increase or holding on to power. When the ICTY was erected, it was hoped that it would be able to effectively deter future violations of human rights. However, in Milosevic’s mind, it functioned as an extrinsic motivator. To some extent, this was because Milosevic did not share the values espoused by the Tribunal. In Milosevic’s perception, it was an anti-Serb court, which was erected to punish the Serbs for trying to fight domestic terrorism and preserve their human rights. He was thus not 130 Introduction by Mihailo Crnobrnja, in: Djukic, Milosevic and Markovic, xi. Sell, ‘A Political Biography’, 22. 132 For one commentator who was convinced of Milosevic’s nationalism, see: Aleksa Djilas, ‘A profile of Slobodan Milosevic’, Foreign Affairs 72:3 (1993) 81-96. However, this account clearly stems from 1993. For example, according to Djilas, Milosevic is a “man who can be trusted […] because he is scared”. See: Ibid., 95. 133 Sell, The Destruction of Yugoslavia, 173. However, personality psychologists would denounce the idea that a man can ‘create’ a core personality for himself. Rather, these are influence by nature and nurture, and cannot be changed much after childhood. See §1.1.3 above. 131 78 able to identify with the Tribunal’s values. This means that when he would have acted on the Tribunal’s demands, the “perceived locus of causality” would have been outside himself, which people usually try to avoid.134 Acting on his intrinsic motivation (i.e. acting to hold on to power), while accepting the Tribunal’s extrinsic motivation (i.e. stop committing crimes), was in Milosevic’s eyes impossible. In conclusion Milosevic’s motivation and core values can be summed up by saying that he was mostly concerned with the acquirement or maintenance of power. To this, it can be added that he was also greatly influenced by his wife Mira Markovic, and that he was to some extent informed by notions of Serbian nationalism. The ICTY’s legal sanction threats were acting as an extrinsic motivator, which would have barred Milosevic’s pursuit of his prime motivation. This can explain to some extent the ICTY’s failure to deter Milosevic. 134 See §1.1.2. 79 §2.2.3 The personality of Slobodan Milosevic The personality of Milosevic was a multi-faceted phenomenon, which seemed to change over time and per situation. Milosevic could be a hospitable, humorous host for international negotiators, and the following day hostile and uncompromising to his enemies. However, according to the definition of personality given by Larsen and Buss, a personality is a set of traits which are relatively stable over time.135 Thus, when describing Milosevic’s personality, it is important to focus on those traits that seem to be stable elements of it. Warren Zimmerman, the last American ambassador to Yugoslavia and top diplomat during the Bosnian wars, has offered a helpful tool in analyzing the various behaviors of Milosevic. He suggested, only partly in jest, that there are in fact two Milosevic’s which come out under different circumstances and in different social contexts: one who is “hard-line and belligerent”, and another who is “affable and always looking for reasonable solutions”.136 The second Milosevic usually came out when he was dealing with foreigners. On his various trips as a banking professional to the United States, he showed himself to be friendly, open to American culture, and a good table guest. Men like David Rockefeller, who he befriended on one of his trips, would never have guessed that this was the man who was to become known as the ‘Butcher of the Balkans’.137 When foreign negotiators came to his office to convince him of yet another peace deal, he was almost always friendly, open to their ideas and seemed to have the time for hours of conversation.138 He would tell them what they wanted to hear, sending them back home feeling like they had achieved something. But, as many diplomats soon found out, he was not to be trusted. Zimmerman even called him “the slickest con man in the Balkans”.139 Louis Sell also, commented that he had an “endless capacity for mischief” and that “one of the few constants in Milosevic’s personality is his mendacity.”140 Richard Holbrooke, chief architect of Dayton, used to say, “I felt like washing my hands every time I came out of a meeting with the man.” 141 Nevertheless, Milosevic was able to manipulate his discussion partners into believing him. Very few negotiators felt they were dealing with someone who was to be held accountable for war crimes. The ‘First Milosevic’ would only come out whenever he was dealing with those below him. He could coldly depose of his friends. For example, even an appeal to their decades-old friendship could not save Ivan Stambolic when Milosevic pushed him aside on the 8th Party Congress, in 1989. During 135 Randy J. Larsen and David M. Buss, Personality Psychology: Domains of Knowledge About Human Nature (4th Edition, New York: McGraw Hill, 2010) 4. 136 Warren Zimmerman, Origins of a Catastrophe (New York: Random House, 1996) 118. Quoted in Sell, ‘A Political Biography’, 22. 137 LeBor, Milosevic, 68. 138 An anecdote that is often quoted, is the following: “Last March [1999], as NATO was preparing to unleash a massive air campaign against Yugoslavia and Serbian authorities were poised to empty the province of hundreds of thousands of Albanians, Slobodan Milosevic began phoning his old chums from high school, asking them to drop by. I’m bored, he explained.” Silber, ‘Milosevic Family Values’, 23. 139 Quoted in: Djilas, ‘A Profile of Slobodan Milosevic’, 95. 140 Sell, ‘A Political Biography’, 12, 23. 141 Quoted in: Ignatieff, Virtual War, 49. 80 his time as head of the Belgrade city organization, he was known as ‘Little Lenin’, for barking out orders against his inferiors while striding around his office. Equally, during the Dayton peace negotiations it was noticed that he was extremely belligerent towards the Bosnian Serb delegate Momhilo Krajisnik, denying him use of the single available telephone and treating him very disrespectful in general.142 These characteristics were also noticed by some of his class mates in college, where he was said to be condescending to his inferiors and a “toady” to those above him. After Dayton, and especially after the NATO bombing of 1999 and his extradition to The Hague in 2001, Milosevic increasingly turned his belligerence towards the West, and especially against the U.S. His behavior before the ICTY was defiant. The first address he made immediately called the Court “illegal”, “criminal” and an instrument of neocolonial policy by the United States.143 Finally, he seemed cold and indifferent to the victims of the wars in the former Yugoslavia. This was the other Milosevic. The Milosevic which foreign diplomats rarely saw, but which was an unmistakable part of Milosevic’s personality. Jerrold M. Post explains the ‘evil side’ of Milosevic’s personality by looking at his family history. Post emphasizes the fact that both his mother and his father committed suicide during his young adulthood (his father shortly after graduating from college, his mother while he was in his early 30s). A favorite uncle, a military intelligence officer, similarly committed suicide while Milosevic was still young.144 The prominence of suicide in Slobodan’s family led to some cruel jokes and wishful thinking among his opponents – hoping that when he faced adversity, he would also commit suicide.145 However, instead of internalizing his issues (which is common with people who commit suicide146), Milosevic seemed to externalize his issues when in crisis situations, “identify[ing] enemies as the cause of his problems, and lash out at them”.147 With this method of self-deception, he was able to assume a thin veneer of self-confidence.148 Indeed, in an interview with Milosevic featured in the excellent documentary Death of Yugoslavia which Laura Silber and Alan Little made for the BBC, he seems laidback and confident, completely convinced of his self-righteousness.149 Milosevic displayed the same attitude while in Court. But both Sell and Post comment that under this layer of self-confidence, rests a wounded soul. When his world falls apart, and his wall of self-deception crumbles down, he becomes 142 LeBor, Milosevic, 325-327. Slobodan Milosevic, Opening Arguments, (14-15 February 2002), online available at: http://www.icty.org/x/cases/slobodan_milosevic/trans/en/020214IT.htm (11 October 2013) pp. 246-319. For Milosevic’s behavior in court in general, see: Post and Panis, ‘Tyranny on Trial’. 144 Jerrold M. Post, Leaders and their Followers in a Dangerous World: The Psychology of Political Behavior (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2004) 179-180. 145 Sell, ‘A Political Biography’, 20. 146 See, for example: Kevin A. Yoder, Dan R. Hoyt, and Les B. Whitbeck, ‘Suicidal Behavior Among Homeless and Runaway Adolescents’, Journal of Youth and Adolescence 27:6 (1998) 753-771. 147 Post, Leaders and their Followers, 180. 148 Daniel Goleman, Vital Lies, Simple Truths: The psychology of self-deception (New York: Simon & Schuster, 1996). 149 See also the accompanying book: Laura Silber and Alan Little, The Death of Yugoslavia (London: Penguin Books, 1996). 143 81 emotionally unstable, almost out of control.150 According to this view, therefore, the self-confident man Milosevic appears to be, is nothing more than a show. When Milosevic’s personality would have to be described according to the Big Five, I would suggest the following rating: medium on Extraversion, high on Agreeableness, low on Conscientiousness, low on Emotional Stability, and medium on Openness to Experience.151 Yet, it must be emphasized that this rating is highly speculative, since it is not based on a clinical observation or any sort of scientifically passable personality evaluation. Moreover, since Milosevic had such a multifaceted personality – for example being at one time very outgoing, while at other times being something of a loner and a recluse – it is hard to get a consistent image of his personality traits. What is interesting here, however, is the apparent applicability of the Dark Triad of personality types (narcissism, Machiavellianism, and (subclinical) psychopathy). Their definition, as given in the analytical framework,152 matches much of the description of Milosevic’s behavior and personality as it was laid out in this paragraph. Although Milosevic cannot be called a clinical psychopath,153 he most definitely displayed traits consistent with this personality type. The way in which Milosevic treated people – apart from his direct family – was characterized by the interpersonal exploitation which forms a core part of (subclinical) psychopathy and Machiavellianism. Furthermore, the low empathy and little remorse which Milosevic displayed towards the victims of his policies – he remarked that he had a “clean conscience” about what happened in Yugoslavia – are key elements of psychopathy. Machiavellianism can also be seen in Milosevic’s deception and disregard of others: Warren Zimmerman had a reason when he called him “the slickest con man in the Balkans”. Finally, Milosevic seemed to be something of a narcissist. His sensitivity to criticism by anyone but his wife and the way in which he fashioned himself as a Serb national hero – linking himself to the heroic Prince Lazar of Kosovo Polje – are behavioral characteristics which are indicative of a narcissist personality. As such, as was already predicted in the analytical framework, Zimmerman’s ‘evil’ Slobodan Milosevic seemed to have been a good example of how the Dark Triad is applicable to authoritarian personalities. In conclusion The personality of Slobodan Milosevic had many facets, which suggests that there were two Milosevic’s, a ‘good Milosevic’ and a ‘bad Milosevic’. Foreign diplomats mostly saw the ‘good Milosevic’, while his victims mostly remember him as the ‘bad Milosevic’. His bad side is often explained by looking at this family past, which is marked by drama and suicide. However, Milosevic externalizes his issues, which can be clearly seen in his tantrums against the West and his behavior in court. The way he acted Post, Leaders and their Followers, 179-180; Sell, ‘A Political Biography’, 20. One might note that the low scores on Agreeableness and Openness to Experience predict prejudicial behavior. See §1.1.3 above. 152 For the description and definitions of the personality traits associated with the Dark Triad, see §1.1.3, at p. 19. 153 The fact that, as far as I know, he has not been clinically diagnosed with this mental illness, is reason enough for this. 150 151 82 towards other people shows indications of narcissism, Machiavellianism, and (subclinical) psychopathy, which seems to be typical of authoritarian leaders. Because of Milosevic’s complex personality, however, it is hard to give a clear, one-sided explanation of his personality. 83 §2.3 Slobodan Milosevic and the International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia In the previous paragraph Milosevic’s rationality, motivation, and personality were explored. As such, an attempt was made to understand ‘the man’ Milosevic. In this paragraph the relationship between ‘the court and the criminal’ will be analyzed. To do this, this paragraph will first feature a brief description of the ICTY’s establishment, its goals, and its operation. Second, Milosevic’s legal responsibility for crimes committed during the Yugoslav wars will be discussed. Third, it will explore the factors relevant to explaining the workings of the (potential) deterrent effect of the ICTY’s legal sanction threats issued against Milosevic. The fourth section will scrutinize the way in which the ICTY’s perceived legitimacy affected Milosevic’s reaction towards it. The fifth and last section considers how extralegal sanction threats, emanating both from the social environment and Milosevic’s self-disapproval, impacted Milosevic’s criminal decision making process. §2.3.1 The International Criminal Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia In May 1993, at a time when the conflict in the former Yugoslavia was at a high point, when various international diplomatic efforts to put an end to the brutal fighting had failed, the United Nations Security Council responded with a measure which had never been seen before. With the adoption of Resolution 827, it established under Chapter VII of the Charter of the United Nations an international tribunal, which had to try suspected war criminals in an ongoing conflict situation. The Tribunal would have to build on the precedents set by the international military tribunals established after the Second World War, the International Military Tribunal in Nuremberg – which tried war criminals from Nazi Germany – and the International Military Tribunal for the Far East in Tokyo – which held Japanese war criminals accountable.154 The International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia, as the Tribunal came to be known, was thus part of the effort of the international community to end the violence in and restore peace to the former Yugoslavia. With a comprehensive mandate, it was hoped that it would be able to contribute to these efforts. The mandate was fourfold. First, it would have to bring to justice individuals who were responsible for international humanitarian law violations. Second, the Tribunal would have to ensure that the victims of these violations received justice. Third, it had to halt such crimes in the future, not only in the former Yugoslavia, but in the wider world. And finally, it would have to restore peace to the conflict zone and promote healing.155 The evaluation of these goals, For the Nuremberg and Tokyo trial, see, inter alia: Erik A. Andersen, ‘The International Military Tribunals in Nuremberg and Tokyo. Epoch-making and standard-setting, yet with different effects’, in: Cedric Ryngaert (ed.), The Effectiveness of Transitional Justice (Antwerp: Intersentia, 2009) 3-26; Christoph Burchard, ‘The Nuremberg Trial and its Impact on Germany’, Journal of International Criminal Justice 4:4 (2006) 800-829; Robert W. Cooper, The Nuremberg Trial (London: Faber & Faber, 2011); Yuma Totani, The Tokyo War Crimes Trial: The Pursuit of Justice in the Wake of World War II (Cambridge: Harvard University Asia Center, 2009). 155 Gary Feinberg, ‘The International Criminal Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia: The Establishment and Evaluation of a Unique Concept in International Justice Administration’, War Crimes, Genocide, and Crimes Against Humanity 2 (2006) 87-113, 88-89. 154 84 especially on the basis of empirical evidence, has created a mixed judgment of its functioning. 156 Yet, the window of opportunity to do something about this seems to have closed. In effect since 1993, the ICTY is supposed to end its operations in 2014. The Tribunal is structured into three Trial Chambers, one Appeals Chamber, an autonomous and independent Prosecutorial Office, and a Registry for administrative affairs. Its judges, prosecutors and staff are international, with over 80 countries having been represented since its establishment.157 The Tribunal’s jurisdiction covers four types of crimes – grave breaches of the 1949 Geneva Convention, violations of the rules or customs of war, genocide, and crimes against humanity – which have to be committed by natural persons in the former Yugoslavia since 1991.158 It tries its suspects on a combination of common and civil law, using both adversarial and inquisitorial legal systems. Indictments, such as the one against Slobodan Milosevic in May 1999, are issued on the basis of an investigation by the Prosecutor’s Office. Although it has large legal powers – it has, for example, superior authority over any national proceedings and is allowed to retrieve national cases when it is of the opinion that justice is not being served159 –, the Tribunal is dependent on the cooperation of states for some of its core functions. Probably the most essential of these core functions for which it is dependent on state cooperation, is the apprehension of its suspects. Obviously, without the enforcement of its arrest warrants, no trials can take place (it cannot try suspects in absentia). In this sense, the Tribunal does not have any law enforcement powers. In its first years of existence, the problems with securing the apprehension and extradition of suspects was a major factor impeding its successful functioning. The examples of Ratko Mladic and Radovan Karadzic, who were able to evade arrest for over 10 years, has already been noted. Yet, by 2012, every single one of the ICTY’s 161 indictees had For a positive evaluation, see: Carla Del Ponte, Madame Prosecutor: Confrontations with Humanity’s Worst Criminals and the Culture of Impunity (New York: Other Press, 2008); Feinberg, ‘Unique Concept’, 106-109. More mixed views are found in: Donna E. Arzt, ´Views on the Ground: The Local Perception of International Criminal Tribunals in the Former Yugoslavia and Sierra Leone’, Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science 603:1 (2006) 226-239, 235-236; Janine Natalya Clark, ‘The Limits of Retributive Justice: Findings of an Empirical Study in Bosnia and Herzegovina’, Journal of International Criminal Justice 7:2 (2009) 463-487, 486-487; Sanja K. Ivkovic and John Hagan, Reclaiming justice: the international Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia and the local courts (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011) 152-166; Mirko Klarin, ‘The Impact of the ICTY Trials on Public Opinion in the Former Yugoslavia’, Journal of International Criminal Justice 7:1 (2009) 89-96, 95-96; Sabrina P. Ramet, ‘The ICTY – Controversies, Successes, Failures, Lessons’, Southeastern Europe 36:1 (2012) 1-9, 8. Outspokenly negative is: Robert M. Hayden, ‘Biased “Justice:” Humanrightsism and the International Criminal Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia’, Cleveland State Law Review 47:4 (2000) 549-573, 552-568. Slobodan Milosevic of course made himself infamous with his negative opinions about the Tribunal. See: Slobodan Milosevic, ‘Is Slobodan Milosevic Guilty of War Crimes? Con’, International Debates 1:5 (2003) 141-159. 157 Feinberg, ‘Unique Concept’, 96. 158 As such, it cannot try organizations or states. Ivkovic and Hagan, Reclaiming justice, 31-32. 159 Feinberg, ‘Unique Concept’, 89-90. According to William W. Burke-White, this led to unwillingness with national courts to take on cases of international crimes. Since there was no clear guidance of when and why cases would be taken over, they did not see the feasibility of it. See: William W. Burke-White, ‘The domestic influence of international criminal tribunals: The International Criminal Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia and the creation of the State Court of Bosnia & Herzegovina’, Columbia Journal of International Law 46:2 (2008) 278-350, 312. 156 85 been arrested.160 Other features for which it is dependent on states and NGO’s are the collection of evidence, the protection of its officials, the interviewing of victims, and its funding. Because states have often been either unwilling or unable to cooperate with the ICTY, despite their obligation under Security Council Resolution to do so, this dependence has significantly detracted from its powers. In conclusion The ICTY was established by Security Council Resolution as a unique concept in international law. Although it has large legal powers and an impressive mandate, it is still dependent on states and NGO’s for some of its core functions, such as the apprehension of its suspects. This dependence on politics, together with its erstwhile failure to have its indictees apprehended and some other shortcomings has generated some controversies, which will be explored in further detail below, when the Tribunal’s deterrence capabilities and legitimacy are analyzed. These shortcomings can go a long way in explaining why Slobodan Milosevic was not deterred from committing international crimes by the international legal proceedings against war criminals before the ICTY. First, however, it is necessary to examine why Milosevic was indicted by the ICTY and how his legal responsibility for crimes was structured by the Tribunal’s Prosecution. Alette Smeulers, Barbara Hola and Tom van den Berg, ‘Sixty-Five Years of International Criminal Justice: The Facts and Figures’, International Criminal Law Review 13:1 (2013) 7-41, 19. 160 86 §2.3.2 Milosevic’s legal responsibility for crimes committed during the Yugoslav wars As was discussed above, the exact involvement of Milosevic in the crimes committed during the wars which followed the break-up of Yugoslavia remains a topic of historical debate. The reasons for this have been outlined above. In this section, it is Milosevic’s legal liability for these crimes which is discussed. The indictment, as it was first issued by the ICTY in May 1999, accused Milosevic (and four other top Serbian political figures) of individual criminal responsibility for “plann[ing], instagat[ing], order[ing], commit[ing] or otherwise aid[ing] and abett[ing] the planning, preparation or execution of” crimes against humanity and violation of the laws or customs of war in Kosovo.161 In the six months after his extradition in June 2001, indictments followed for Croatia and Bosnia.162 These accused Milosevic of individual criminal responsibility for war crimes, crimes against humanity, grave breaches of the Geneva Convention of 1949, and (complicity in) genocide.163 Interestingly, information about his possible involvement in international crimes committed in Croatia and Bosnia was already known to American intelligence services in 1992. However, legal prosecution of Milosevic was not deemed feasible until 1999, because the Americans thought him to be too important for the peace process in the former Yugoslavia.164 The accusations against Milosevic were based on his individual criminal responsibility for crimes committed in Bosnia, Croatia and Kosovo. Individual criminal responsibility is a legal concept which can be used on the basis of direct responsibility, command responsibility or complicity-based responsibility.165 These concepts have been widely used in trials of other suspects before the ICTY, and when Milosevic was put on the docket, they had been relatively well developed. Although it is not the place here to delve too deeply in the judicial nuances of these legal concepts, it is nonetheless important to explore on what basis the Tribunal accused Milosevic of war crimes, crimes against humanity, genocide and grave breaches of the Geneva Convention of 1949. Essentially, Milosevic was held responsible because of his position as President of the Serbian Republic and de facto leader of the federal structure of the Federal Republic of Yugoslavia, including its army and police force. The Yugoslav federal army, the JNA, committed multiple atrocities in the breakaway republics and acted often symbiotically with paramilitary forces and secessionists.166 Moreover, according to the ICTY’s Prosecutor, his support of and influence over the Bosnian and Krajina Serbs and various Serbian paramilitary groups, made him responsible for war crimes committed by these entities. These crimes ICTY, Indictment against Slobodan Milosevic et al. “Kosovo”, Case No. IT-99-37-PT, available online at: http://www.icty.org/x/cases/slobodan_milosevic/ind/en/mil-2ai011029e.htm (15 October 2013). 162 Cigar and Williams, Indictment at The Hague, 20. 163 ICTY, Indictment against Slobodan Milosevic “Kosovo, Croatia & Bosnia”, Case No. IT-02-54-T, available online at: http://www.icty.org/x/cases/slobodan_milosevic/ind/en/mil-ai040421-e.htm (15 October 2013). 164 Cigar and Williams, Indictment at The Hague, 19-20. In 1996, a group of experts united in the Bosnian Institute had a fully prepared case for indictment. It is notable that the Prosecutor’s eventual decision to indict Milosevic for crimes committed in Bosnia and Croatia, closely followed the reasoning outlined in this case. 165 Ibid., 37. 166 Ibid., 22. 161 87 included, inter alia, the siege of Vukovar, the shelling of Sarajevo, the execution of several thousand Muslim men in Srebrenica, and ethnic cleansing operations in Bosnia and Croatia in general. As was said before, Milosevic denied any involvement in the Bosnian and Croatian wars. Also, although the Serbian army and police were directly involved in Kosovo, he denied that ethnic cleansing took place in the region. Instead, he claimed, the Serbs were fighting domestic terrorism, citing multiple (terrorist) attacks by the Kosovo Liberation Army as proof. Milosevic furthermore denied any linkages to paramilitary groups operating in the conflict zone. In the BBC documentary The Death of Yugoslavia, he said: “There is no one who can believe what is mentioned as an organized genocide, even organized from Belgrade, even organized by me! It is really out of consideration!” 167 Moreover, Milosevic was reported to be convinced that he did not do anything wrong in Kosovo. 168 He emphasized that the Prosecutor could not come with any piece of evidence which showed him directly ordering war crimes, dismissing the Prosecutor’s accusations as an “ocean of lies”.169 Both the historic record, as well as his trial before the ICTY, however, have convincingly established that Milosevic actively supported, and in some cases helped to organize and plan, ethnic cleansing operations in the various conflict zones. Telephone intercepts, witness statements, and historical documents all testify to this.170 Milosevic might have genuinely thought that his support for Bosnian and Krajina Serbs or his operations in Kosovo could not lead to his criminal liability under international criminal law. However, under the case law developed by the ICTY, especially its interpretation of direct and command responsibility, even before he stepped up military activities in Kosovo, these activities are in and of itself enough for criminal liability.171 According to this case law, Milosevic would be directly responsible for crimes committed by forces under his control. Moreover, through his various positions in the state infrastructure, he had command responsibility for any crimes committed by federal forces because he did know or could have known of their existence. Even though he denied their existence, it can be said that he had imputed knowledge of the crimes, which means that he should have known of the crimes as he was the de facto commander-in-chief of these forces.172 As such, Milosevic’s contention that the Prosecutor had no case whatsoever because of its failure to present any direct evidence of him ordering the commission of war crimes, did not prevent him from being individually criminally responsible under international criminal law. 167 Quoted in: Ibid., 23. Sell, The Destruction of Yugoslavia, 174. 169 Quoted in Post and Panis, ‘Tyranny on Trial’, 831. 170 Armatta, ‘Historical Revelations’, 35-36; Glaurdic, ‘Telephone Intercepts’, 97-98; Sell, The Destruction of Yugoslavia, 318-328. 171 For a comprehensive list of relevant ICTY case law, see: Cigar and Williams, Indictment at The Hague, 3031, note 12. 172 Ibid., 65-145. 168 88 In conclusion Sadly, Milosevic died before the Trial Chamber could determine his guilt or innocence. In the end, his constant stalling, together with the complexity of the case brought against him, protracted his trial too much for any judgment to take place.173 Therefore, his legal responsibility for the atrocities which took place during the conflict in the former Yugoslavia can never be determined. History, however, will not be as mild, and his responsibility for much of these atrocities is now widely accepted among scholars. Therefore, it is still relevant to assess why the legal sanction threats issued by the ICTY did not deter him from the crimes outlined above. 173 Gideon Boas, The Milosevic Trial: Lessons for the Conduct of Complex International Criminal Proceedings (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007) 271-274. One of Milosevic’s judges, Iain Bonomy, argues that the adoption of the adversarial format for the proceedings at the ICTY. See: Iain Bonomy, ‘The Reality of conducting a War Crimes Trial’, Journal of International Criminal Justice 5:2 (2007) 348-359, 350. 89 §2.3.3 The factors influencing the deterrence capability of the ICTY The legal sanction threats emanating from the ICTY were supposed to deter possible perpetrators of international crimes. The Security Council believed an international tribunal would be able “to end such crimes” and would “contribute to the restoration and maintenance of peace”.174 As was noted in the previous chapter, criminologists have identified three main characteristics of legal sanction threats which are thought to be most relevant to their deterrent capability. These are their certainty, severity, and celerity. Although empirical research identified certainty as the most important variable, severity and celerity theoretically are equally important. Other phenomena which were analyzed as impacting possible deterrence were the experiential effect and risk sensitivity. In this section it will be studied how these factors applied to the relationship between the ICTY and Slobodan Milosevic. The ICTY’s legitimacy and the social context of extralegal sanction threats, which were equally influential for the Tribunal’s deterrent capability, will be studied in separate sections. When looking at the certainty of sanctions by the ICTY against someone who committed war crimes, crimes against humanity, grave breaches of the Geneva Convention, or genocide, the data is mixed. An optimistic account of the Tribunal’s proceedings could note that by 2012 it has a 100% clearance rate for its 161 suspects. Although some cases are still ongoing, such as those of Radovan Karadzic and Ratko Mladic, almost all indictments have been fulfilled. The others have been withdrawn due to death, withdrawn due to other reasons, or referred to national courts.175 Moreover, the Tribunal has a 81% conviction rate. All these numbers suggest a relatively successful record of the Tribunal’s proceeding. However, there are a few points which sketch a more negative image. First, it has been noted that the 161 cases the Tribunal has dealt with or is still dealing with, is only a small sample of the enormous amount of perpetrators of the crimes active in the conflict zone that fall under the Tribunal’s jurisdiction.176 As such, the selectivity of the Tribunal’s proceedings is a problematic factor impacting the certainty of its legal sanctions. Still, it could be argued that the ICTY’s main focus has been to punish those ‘most responsible’ for these crimes, leaving the ‘smaller fish’ to national courts.177 Even when the Tribunal is judged according to this stated objective, however, it must be said that it has failed to indict a large number of people who were seemingly quintessential in the break-up of Yugoslavia and the chaos that followed. Examples are Croatian president Franjo Tudjman – who is held responsible for crimes committed by Croatian forces during Operation Storm178 – and Borisav Jovic – President of the Security Council, ‘Resolution 827’. Smeulers et al., ‘Facts and Figures’, 19. 176 Christopher Mullins estimates that the amount of perpetrators who are held accountable for international crimes worldwide, cannot be much higher than 1%. See: Christopher W. Mullins, ‘Conflict victimization and post-conflict justice 1945-2008’, in: M. Cherif Bassiouni (ed.), The Pursuit of International Criminal Justice: A World Study on Conflicts, Victimization, and Post-Conflict Justice (Antwerp: Intersentia, 2010) 67-108. 177 Stephen Parmentier and Elmar Weitekamp, ‘Punishing Perpetrators or Seeking Truth for Victims: Serbian Opinions on Dealing with War Crimes’, International Criminal Law Review 13:1 (2013) 43-62, 62. 178 Victor Peskin and Mieczyslaw P. Boduszynski, ‘International Justice and Domestic Politics: Post-Tudjman Croatia and the International Criminal Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia’, Europe-Asia Studies 55:7 (2003) 1117-1142, 1124. 174 175 90 State Presidency of Yugoslavia from May 1990 to May 1991, who is according to himself responsible for the planning and preparation of war.179 The Tribunal’s relatively small number of cases, or in other words, its selectivity,180 – even for the higher-level perpetrators – is therefore clearly a factor which reflects negatively on the certainty of its legal sanctions. For Slobodan Milosevic’s decision making process, however, the objective certainty of legal sanctioning by the ICTY – although relevant – was less important than the way in which he perceived it. To understand this perceived certainty, it is important to note the context in which Milosevic committed his crimes. During the wars in Bosnia and Croatia, the period in which the Tribunal started to enter into force and started issuing legal sanction threats, there seems to have been no certainty of arrest whatsoever. The first Prosecutor of the ICTY, Richard Goldstone, was hesitant with speedy indictments of top government officials. The lack of investigation and arrest powers, which marked the ‘honeymoon years’ of the Tribunal,181 further minimized the perceived certainty of legal sanctions. Moreover, the international community clearly signaled that they thought Milosevic was an essential figure for any peace efforts in the former Yugoslavia. But even when Louise Arbour, the ICTY’s new Prosecutor started in 1996 to actively pressure states to comply with arrest warrants, and convinced Western governments to make economic aid to the region contingent on the arrest and extradition to The Hague of those the ICTY indicted, some top ranking indictees remained at large. Men like Karadzic and Mladic, with whom Milosevic had frequent contact, seemed to be uncatchable.182 This must have convinced Milosevic that, as long as he maintained his hold on power, he would be able to evade arrest even when he would be indicted. This played a significant role in the failure of the ICTY to deter Milosevic from ordering more mass atrocities. A similar analysis seems to be applicable to the severity of the legal sanction threats of the Tribunal. The Tribunal’s judges certainly considered general deterrence an important factor in determining the length of the prison sentence meted out to those they convicted.183 The sentencing at the ICTY accordingly seems to have been harsh compared to national courts in Western democracies, with an average of 15.9 years imprisonment.184 Yet this is not the way it was perceived in the former Yugoslavia. In multiple surveys, there seems to have been a consensus that the Tribunal was sentencing its suspects too leniently. To some extent, this was because of the fact that the ICTY is not allowed to apply the death penalty: a significant minority of victims thought the only appropriate sentence for those Ramet, ‘Controversies, Successes, Failures, Lessons’, 5. Mark A. Drumbl, Atrocity, Punishment and International Law (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007) 169-170. 181 Ivkovic and Hagan, Reclaiming Justice, 3-4. 182 Drumbl, Atrocity, Punishment, 170. 183 Ivkovic and Hagan, Reclaiming Justice, 14. For the influence of this kind of goal-setting on sentence severity in supranational criminal courts, see: Roelof Haveman, ‘Supranational Expectations of a Punitive Approach’, in: Roelof Haveman and Olaoluwa Olusanya (eds.), Sentencing and Sanctioning in Supranational Criminal Law (Antwerp: Intersentia, 2006) 145-160, 146-148. 184 Smeulers, ‘Facts and Figures’, 21-24. 179 180 91 responsible for mass atrocities would have been death.185 But even those who were against the use of the death penalty thought the prison sentences should have been longer.186 This belief, that the sentences being meted out did not stand in relation to the severity of the crimes committed, translated into a low perceived severity of the legal sanctions issued by the ICTY. Although it is hard to say what Milosevic’s exact opinion was about the severity of the Tribunal’s legal sanctions, it is reasonable to assume that his opinion would have conformed to this dominant narrative. This low perceived severity could hardly have posed as a significant factor in Milosevic’s decision making process. The previously mentioned reluctance of the first Prosecutor to seriously engage in indictments of top leaders responsible for the atrocities in the former Yugoslavia, combined with the difficulties the Tribunal was facing in apprehending its suspects, greatly increased the amount of time between the committal of crimes and the legal sanction and thus decreased the swiftness of legal sanctions in the former Yugoslavia, especially for the ‘bigger fish’. To a considerable extent, this was a prosecution strategy. Both Goldstone and Arbour wished to slowly build up cases against the higher leadership by trying the lower-ranking perpetrators, thus building up a juridical record and ensuring the creation of a hefty case law.187 Therefore, although American intelligence services already had evidence implicating Milosevic in war crimes in 1992, his indictment followed only in 1999, and at that time only for crimes committed in Kosovo. The first step towards a legal sanction, in this case his arrest, extradition, and detention, only followed two years later, in 2001. This sequence of events led to a low perceived celerity, which decreased the deterrent effect of ICTY legal sanction threats even more. The ‘objective’ data paint a similar picture: there was an average time lapse of 3.6 years between an indictment and the start of a trial.188 When the trial started, a combination of shortcomings of the adversarial model and the complexity of the case material, ensured lengthy proceedings. After the trial started, the Tribunal needed an average of 1.9 years to produce a judgment.189 For Slobodan Milosevic this was even longer. After five years on the docket, Milosevic died before he could receive any sort of sentencing at all. While he did spend these years in prison, it can be said that Milosevic never received an actual legal sanction for the crimes he committed. Something else which seemed to have played a role in the failure of deterring Milosevic, is the experiential effect. As was stated in the analytical framework, the experiential effect holds that (potential) offenders learn from their own experiences with the criminal justice system, and also update their perception of the legal sanction threat by looking at what happens to their peers. Clearly, this experiential effect must have minimized Milosevic’s perception of the threat of the ICTY even more. In 185 This was the opinion of at least 25 percent of the respondents. See: Ivkovic and Hagan, Reclaiming Justice, 19. 186 Ibid. Clark similarly finds that especially Bosniak victim groups “expressed anger and disappointment with the prison sentences handed down by the ICTY”. See: Clark, ‘The Limits of Retributive Justice’, 471. 187 Minna Schrag, ‘Lessons Learned from the ICTY Experience’, Journal of International Criminal Justice 2:2 (2004) 427-434, 430-432. 188 Smeulers et al., ‘Facts and Figures’, 18. 189 Ibid. 92 his own experience, the ICTY would never indict him, since he had gotten a ‘get out of jail free’-card from Richard Holbrooke at Dayton for the criminal acts he had committed in Bosnia and Croatia from 1991 to 1995.190 When he started considering crimes in Kosovo, in his perception, there was no reason to believe that the international community would hold him accountable this time. Milosevic could draw the same conclusion when he looked at the experience with the international criminal justice system of his peers. Although the ICTY, together with the ICTR, was hailed as bringing to an end the ‘culture of impunity’, the empirical reality was definitely different. Many of those who had enough power to do so, were still able to defy legal accountability.191 In this case, it is interesting to note the link between Saddam Hussein, at that time the dictator of Iraq, and Slobodan Milosevic. Apart from their apparent competition for the title of ‘the worst villain of the 1990s’, they seemed to have learned from each other’s experiences. There is some information that Milosevic drew conclusions about the persistence and commitment of the international community from the fact that Saddam got away with his war against Kuwait (First Gulf War, 1990-1991) and his defiance of the world.192 Closer at home, Milosevic seems to have learned from the experiences of Radovan Karadzic and Ratko Mladic, who, even though they were indicted relatively early by the ICTY, were able to remain at large for years. The fact that the previously mentioned Tudjman and Josic, men who were in similar positions as Milosevic, were not indicted by the Tribunal, must have equally told Milosevic that he would be able to remain out of the Tribunal’s reach. In the end, of course, Milosevic did have to defend himself in court. Apparently, his perception of his chances of legal sanctioning by the ICTY, was misinformed by his own and others’ experiences. However, the experiential effect in this case seems to have minimized Milosevic’s perceived certainty of legal sanctions. As a final point, the criminological phenomenon of risk sensitivity is clearly applicable to the way in which Slobodan Milosevic reacted to the legal sanction threats issued by the ICTY. He tried to minimize any evidence against him about his involvement with the wars in Bosnia and Croatia. For example, most of his orders were given orally and he was keen on not leaving any documentary evidence behind. Moreover, he used proxies – Bosnian and Croatian Serbs, Serbian paramilitary groups – to fulfill his strategic goals of an ethnically pure Greater Serbia.193 In this way, whenever he was confronted with the atrocities taking place, he would be able to parry by stating that his hands were clean. Milosevic even seemed to be proud of this: when in court, he regularly accused the Prosecutor of not being able to present a ‘single piece of evidence’ against him. The risk sensitivity Milosevic thus displayed, puts him Rieff, ‘Milosevic in Retrospect’, 12. A similar point was made in 2000 by Geoffrey Robertson. See: Geoffrey Robertson, Crimes against Humanity: The Struggle for Global Justice (London: Penguin Books, 2000). 192 Saddam Hussein also seems to have learned from Milosevic. After Saddam was arrested by American forces following his downfall in 2003, his behavior in court mirrored closely that of Milosevic. See: Post and Panis, ‘Tyranny on Trial’, 833-836. 193 See, for example: Ruth Jamieson and Kieran McEvoy, ‘State Crime by Proxy and Juridical Othering’, The British Journal of Criminology 45:4 (2005) 504-527, 506; James Ron, ‘Territoriality and Plausible Deniability: Serbian Paramilitaries in the Bosnian War’, in: Bruce B. Campbell and Arthur D. Brenner, Death Squads in Global Perspective: Murder with Deniability (New York: St. Martin’s Press, 2000) 287-312. 190 191 93 squarely into the group offenders which are among the hardest to deter. Because he thought he would be able to maintain beyond the reach of the ICTY, the potential ‘cost’ of the Tribunal’s legal sanction threat, was significantly downplayed. In conclusion In all these ways – the low perceived certainty, severity and celerity, together with the experiential effect and Milosevic’s risk sensitivity – the potential disincentive the ICTY could form in Milosevic’s criminal decision making process, was minimized. This effect was exacerbated by the fact that Milosevic did not consider the Tribunal to be a legitimate institution. Therefore, the next section will study the ICTY’s perceived legitimacy. 94 §2.3.4 The social context and extralegal sanction threats In the analytical framework, it was mentioned that it has been shown that the threat of extralegal sanctions is often more important than legal sanction threats in influencing our behavior. These extralegal sanctions can take the form of self-disapproval and social censure. Therefore, the formation of these threats is formed by the social environment as well as the person’s self-identity. When studying the extralegal sanction environment in the former Yugoslavia, then, it is relevant to note that first of all, within the former Yugoslavia, the destabilization which followed the disintegration of the federal state – and especially the frequent episodes of savage violence – led to a culture in which the use of force, and the use of ethnic cleansing, became a well-accepted and even encouraged practice. Moreover, within political circles, any moral norms which might have moderated policies against other ethnic groups, seemed to have disappeared. During the 1990s the political elite criminalized: corruption and large scale plundering of the Serbian economy created a new elite which was dependent on Milosevic for their economic power and were thankful for the opportunities his wars created. This inversion of morality led to a situation in which any threat of extralegal sanctions coming from the social environment – such as shaming or (political) exclusion – for the committing of crimes against humanity etc. disappeared. A quote from Serbia’s Minister of Defense at the time, General Tomislav Simovic, alludes to the social context in which these crimes took place and the general acceptance of them as part of Serbia’s national goals: As far as I know the aforementioned ‘Arkan’ [commander of a prominent Serbian paramilitary group operating in Bosnia and Croatia] is acting with the direct blessing of the [Republic of] Serbia government in the areas of Slavonija, Western Srijem, and Baranja. It is also known that they are not the only volunteers [there]. I would not differentiate between criminals and patriots, but rather between those who contribute to the interests of their nation and those who do not, and one knows where criminals fit in.194 The inclusion of people like Arkan’s Tigers, responsible for some of the worst atrocities committed during the Yugoslav wars, into the community of ‘patriots’, clearly shows an inversion of morality in which crimes are not something to be ashamed of, but rather something to be hailed as patriotism. Since it can be said that the social context demanded the fulfillment of group goals, essentially the ethnic cleansing of Greater Serbia, extralegal sanctions for mass atrocities were not to be expected.195 194 Quoted in: Cigar and Williams, Indictment at The Hague, 68-69. According to Emily Shaw, the bombing of Serbia, especially of civilian targets there, caused a rising threat perception among the Serbs, which bonded them together against NATO. Even opposition figures, who had demonstrated en masse against Milosevic in the 1996-1997 protests, suddenly rallied around Milosevic as they collectively defied NATO. The identification of the ICTY with NATO, subsequently increased opposition against international criminal law. See: Shaw, ‘The Role of Social Identity’, 11-22. However, to some extent, the indictments against Milosevic did seem to delegitimize Milosevic as a political player. It stigmatized him as a criminal which detracted from his political support. Still, not too much weight should be given to these 195 95 For Milosevic, the absence of self-disapproval exacerbated this situation. This self-disapproval was defined earlier as “the internal dissonance from having violated an internalized behavioral norm”.196 Above, Milosevic’s behavioral norms were described as being strongly guided by his pursuit of power, one of his most important values. In the theory of extralegal sanctions, therefore, self-disapproval could have taken place when Milosevic would have endangered his pursuit of power. Milosevic, who knew that his rise to power had been kick-started by playing up Serbian nationalist themes in Kosovo Polje in April 1987, saw the dominance of Kosovo by the Serbian government as crucial for his hold on power. Therefore, self-disapproval, as well as (at least in his eyes) social disapproval, would have occurred when he would not have initiated military operations (culminating in the ethnic cleansing of Operation Horseshoe) in Kosovo in 1998. The social and personal context therefore deterred Milosevic from not committing or ordering mass atrocities in Bosnia, Croatia, and Kosovo. The reliance on extralegal sanctions for controlling criminal behavior, was even greater in the former Yugoslavia because of the malfunctioning of local judicial systems. The perceived absence of legal sanctioning threats emanating from properly functioning sanctioning institutions, increased the relative importance of extralegal sanction threats. During the 1990s, the legal sanctioning institutions were criticized by experts “for their lack of independence, incompetence and corruption”.197 They were either unable or unwilling to prosecute war criminals, especially when these criminals were members of the region’s dominant ethnic group. Therefore, during the 1990s, the region lacked a rule of law.198 It was only long after the war, around 2003, that residents of the former Yugoslavia started to regain trust in local legal sanctioning institutions.199 But during the 1990s, the lack of trust in the local judiciary system, decreased the possibility of legal deterrence and increased the importance of extralegal sanction threats. Sadly enough, however as was shown above, these extralegal sanction threats formed not against committing mass atrocities, but rather against not committing these crimes. In conclusion Although extralegal sanction threats can act as important behavioral constraints, for example in controlling criminal behavior, in the former Yugoslavia, the social context which issued these extralegal sanction threats was characterized by an inversion of morality. Therefore, the extralegal sanction threats did not form against committing atrocities which furthered group goals, but rather against not committing these atrocities. Moreover, Milosevic´s own norms and values, which were mainly focused on holding onto power, were violated in his eyes if he would not have adopted policies of ethnic arguments, since the population in general did not necessarily believe the ICTY was a legitimate institution itself and was capable of delegitimizing their leaders. The quote by Kostunica below further illustrates this. 196 Daniel S. Nagin and Greg Pogarsky, ‘Integrating Celerity, Impulsivity, and Extralegal Sanctions into a Model of General Deterrence: Theory and Evidence’, Criminology 39:4 (2001) 865-892, 869. 197 Ivkovic and Hagan, Reclaiming Justice, 20. 198 Ibid., 170. 199 Ibid. 96 cleansing which he saw as necessary for holding onto power. The social context and Milosevic´s individual characteristics created a situation in which extralegal sanction threats caused, rather than prevented crime. 97 §2.3.5 The legitimacy of the ICTY Antonio Cassese, the first President of the ICTY, in his study on the legitimacy of international tribunals, concluded that the ICTY had a positive track record in this aspect.200 At first, the residents of the former Yugoslavia seemed to agree. Especially among victims, there was a positive vibe surrounding the establishment of the institution, and many had positive expectations of it.201 Many of the Serbs, however, with Milosevic as one of them, disputed the Tribunal’s legitimacy. During the ICTY’s first trial, against Dusan Tadic for crimes committed in Prijedor,202 there was a dispute between the defendant and the Prosecutor over the legitimacy of the ICTY’s establishment.203 The establishment was contested because, in Tadic’s view, the Security Council did not have the authority to establish international tribunals with jurisdiction over residents of independent countries. As such, it was not “established by law”.204 Although the legality of the Tribunal’s establishment was confirmed by subsequent rulings, this was a first clear challenge to the Tribunal’s legitimacy. When the Tribunal started to become a fully functioning institution, the positive attitude which surrounded its establishment soon faded away. One of the most damaging narratives for the ICTY which became dominant in post-war Yugoslavia, among Serbs as well as Croats, was that the Tribunal was strongly biased against their own ethnic group.205 In part, this was because of the fact that there were no clear winners after the Dayton peace accords. As such, the Tribunal became a kind of arbiter, whose decisions were seen to establish the ‘winners’ and the ‘losers’ of the wars.206 Moreover, the fact that the post-war governments did not accept that their ethnic group were both victims as well as perpetrators, denying that they also had committed international crimes, complicated the acceptance of any indictments against members of their own group.207 The almost complete absence of outreach by the ICTY in the 1990s moreover – the Outreach programme was not established until 1999 –, gave post-war governments the opportunity to influence their constituency’s opinions about the ICTY.208 For example, a 2006 survey indicated that a majority Antonio Cassese, ‘The Legitimacy of International Criminal Tribunals and the Current Prospects of International Criminal Justice’, Leiden Journal of International Law 25 (2012) 491-501, 492-493. 201 Ivkovkic and Hagan, Reclaiming Justice, 159. 202 ICTY, Tadic. “Prijedor”, Case No. IT-94-1, available online at: http://www.icty.org/case/tadic/4#ind (17 October 2013). 203 Mia Swart, ‘Tadic Revisited: Some Critical Comments on the Legacy and the Legitimacy of the ICTY’, Goettingen Journal of International Law 3:3 (2011) 985-1010, 987-988. 204 Ibid., 996. 205 Miklos Biro et al., ‘Attitudes towards justice and social reconstruction in Bosnia and Herzegovina and Croatia’, in: Eric Stover and Harvey M. Weinstein (eds.), My neighbor, my enemy: justice and community after mass atrocity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004) 183-205, 193; Bojan Tonkic, ‘Serbia: Milosevic Trial Grips Nation’, Institute for War and Peace Reporting Balkan Crisis Report #318, (15 February 2002), available online at: http://iwpr.net/report-news/serbia-milosevic-trial-grips-nation (18 October 2013). 206 Ivkovic and Hagan, Reclaiming Justice, 160. 207 Nenad Dimitrijevic, ‘Serbia after the criminal past: what went wrong and what should be done’, International Journal of Transitional Justice 2:1 (2008) 5-22, 11. 208 Janine Natalya Clark, ‘International War Crimes Tribunals and the Challenge of Outreach’, International Criminal Law Review 9:1 (2009) 99-116, 100-106. 200 98 of Serbs still rejected the idea that crimes took place in Srebrenica or Sarajevo.209 Moreover, perceptions of partiality and characterizations of the Tribunal as victor’s justice, decreased the perceived legitimacy of the ICTY. The Tribunal’s decisions – be it its indictments, its acquittals or its convictions – therefore became a zero-sum game, in which any decision which was perceived positively by one ethnic group was perceived negatively by the other ethnic group.210 This reinforced the already salient feelings of victimization amongst the Serbs, and thus confirmed the dominant narrative that the Tribunal was set up to punish the Serbs.211 Arguments like these are sometimes echoed in the opinions of Western scholars. Defendant’s attorneys, also, have complained of unfair treatment by the ICTY compared with the Prosecution.212 The question of the legitimacy of establishing an international tribunal by Security Council Resolution was already debated during the negotiations over Resolution 827.213 Moreover, some commentators have labeled the whole Tribunal as victor’s justice.214 Noting the fact that during the Milosevic trial, both Prosecutor Louise Arbour and presiding judge Richard May were from NATO countries which had gone to war against Milosevic’s Serbia, David Rieff concludes that, “if the ICTY’s is not victors’ justice, the term has no meaning”.215 As such, because the Tribunal was perceived – by the Serbs and Croats especially – to be discriminatory, to not treat its suspects fairly, and to not be impartial, the Tribunal could not conform to Tyler’s procedural justice model.216 The legitimacy of the ICTY always seemed to be especially important to Milosevic. From the beginning of the ICTY’s operations, he claimed that the Tribunal was established unlawfully, claiming that, according to its charters, the United Nations was not allowed to set up an international tribunal. This focus on legitimacy is something which was important to Milosevic throughout his political career.217 Like those around him, he felt that the ICTY was set up to punish the Serbs. With this, he followed the dominant narrative. Although it is true that he was to a large extent himself responsible for constructing this narrative, constantly denying the ICTY’s legitimacy and using his control over the media to propagate this view, it is interesting to note that when he was arrested for abuse of power and corruption, Vojislav Kostunica, Serbia’s new president, was at first reluctant to hand him over to The Hague. Kostunica, the man who brought down Milosevic and was hailed by the West as the first true Belgrade Center for Human Rights, ‘Public opinion in Serbia: Views on domestic war crimes, judicial authorities and the Hague tribunal’, OSCE, (2006), available online at: http://www.osce.org/serbia/24241 (17 October 2013). 210 Stuart Ford, ‘A Social Psychology Model of the Perceived Legitimacy of International Criminal Courts: Implications for the Success of Transitional Justice Mechanisms’, Vanderbilt Journal of Transnational Law 45:2 (2012) 405-476, 440, 461. 211 Ivkovic and Hagan, Reclaiming Justice, 160-163. 212 For an overview of the complaints by defendant attorneys, see: Mark S. Ellis, ‘Achieving Justice before the International War Crimes Tribunal: Challenges for the Defense Counsel’, Duke Journal of Comparative and International Law 7:2 (1997) 519-538, 522-536. 213 Swart, ‘Tadic Revisited’, 995. 214 Hayden, ‘Humanrightsism’, 568-569; Rieff, ‘Milosevic in Retrospect’, 14-15. Hayden also questions the Tribunal’s impartiality, because of its failure to criminalize the cluster bombing of Nis by NATO warplanes. 215 Rieff, ‘Milosevic in Retrospect’, 14-15. 216 See §1.2.2. 217 Jakovljevic, ‘From Mastermind to Body Artist’, 55. 209 99 democratically elected president of post-war Serbia, thought the ICTY was an anti-Serbian institution and preferred to try Milosevic in Serbia.218 Thus, the conviction that the Tribunal was unfair to Serbs was not only held by indoctrinated masses or those indicted for war crimes. Milosevic consistently showed his disregard for the Tribunal’s proceedings while in the docket. He was able to portray his trial as a trial against the Serb nation; his rants against the Tribunal have been alluded to previously. It is also clear that Milosevic did not feel like his social status was respected by the Tribunal. As President of Serbia, he felt that he should not be tried by a distant court in The Hague. The Tribunal’s suspicions of him damaged his position as a key international player and his subsequent reputation as a ‘Peacemaker’, especially when the ICTY issued indictments against him in May 1999. This is another factor which, according to Tyler’s procedural justice model, impacted the ICTY’s perceived legitimacy in a negative way. The fact that Slobodan Milosevic did not view the ICTY as a legitimate institution which would be able to try war crimes in the region fairly and impartially, had important consequences for his behavior. As was noted earlier, when someone does not see a court as legitimate, it will not form a “right and proper restriction of behavior”.219 Therefore, this low perceived legitimacy has some explanatory power in understanding why Milosevic did not seem to be bothered by the legal sanction threats that were emanating from the ICTY. When the Tribunal started issuing indictments against men like Mladic and Karadzic, and after the Tribunal had convicted its first suspects, Milosevic did not feel any reason to comply with the Tribunal’s decisions – namely that war crimes, crimes against humanity, and genocide were completely unacceptable and that individual leaders could be he held criminally responsible for these crimes. As such, the ICTY was not able to restrict Milosevic’s behavior. Moreover, a low perceived legitimacy leads to problems with accepting unfavorable outcomes of the court’s decisions. The fact that the Tribunal convicted multiple Serbs of war crimes in Croatia, Bosnia, and Kosovo, was perceived by Milosevic as a condemnation of the entire Serbian nation. If he would have perceived the Tribunal as a legitimate sanctioning institution, he might have accepted the idea that Serbs were both perpetrators and victims, and that Serbs had indeed committed multiple international crimes during the Yugoslav wars. Because many Serbs did not perceive the ICTY to be a legitimate institution, the certainty of the ICTY’s legal sanction threat decreased. The Tribunal was unable to secure cooperation by the authorities in Serbia, which was necessary for the effective execution of its mandate. The decreased certainty in turn lowered the perception of the ICTY’s legitimacy. Since for a long time the ICTY could not try those held most responsible for the crimes committed in the former Yugoslavia, a large share of the population Sell, The Death of Yugoslavia, 355; Emily Shaw, ‘The Role of Social Identity in Resistance to International Criminal Law: The Case of Serbia and the ICTY’, Berkeley Program in Soviet and Post-Soviet Studies Working Paper Series (2003) 3-31, 8. 219 Dawn L. Rothe and Christopher W. Mullins, ‘Beyond the Juristic Orientation of International Criminal Justice: The Relevance of Criminological Insight to International Criminal Law and its Control: A Commentary’, International Criminal Law Review 10:1 (2010) 97-110, 103. 218 100 saw it as an ineffective institution, which detracted from its legitimacy. In this way, the perceived legitimacy and perceived certainty interacted with each other. In conclusion In the analytical framework, it was noted that legitimacy can powerfully influence someone’s behavior. The fact that Slobodan Milosevic, and many other residents of the former Yugoslavia, did not see the ICTY as a legitimate sanctioning institution, undermined the influence the Tribunal could potentially have had on moderating Milosevic’s behavior. Because the Tribunal’s actions were perceived to be procedurally unfair, discriminatory against his own ethnic group, and disrespectful of his social position, the ICTY was not seen by Milosevic as a right and proper restriction on his behavior. 101 §2.4 Summarizing the findings of this chapter The chaos and conflict that broke out on the territory of the former Yugoslavia after its disintegration in 1991, was marked by exceptional savagery and barbarism. Many atrocities were committed by all sides. With the establishment of the ICTY in 1993, the international community hoped to be able to deter future violations of international human rights law. At least in the case of Slobodan Milosevic, this hope proved to be futile. He did not change his policies in Croatia and Bosnia and some of the war’s worst crimes, such as the Srebrenica massacre of 1995 were committed well after the Tribunal was established. Moreover, although the Tribunal was clear about its intentions to hold those most responsible for international crimes accountable, Milosevic initiated ethnic cleansing operations in Kosovo in 1999, even after he was indicted. This chapter has attempted to explain why the legal sanction threats issued by the ICTY failed in deterring future atrocities in the former Yugoslavia. It did so by first looking at Milosevic’s life, his rationality, motivation, and personality, concluding that various factors contributed to the deterrence failure. It was noticed that there seemed to have been a ‘no way back’-effect at play. In many ways, Milosevic needed the crimes to maintain the thing he valued most, power. Because Milosevic had staked so much of his political fortunes on holding on to Kosovo, on defending Serbian nationalist interests and creating an ethnically pure Greater Serbia, any obvious and clear forsaking of these goals, would surely lead to the eroding of his political support. This became clear when he gave in to NATO bombing and lost Kosovo. Soon, he lost power and was extradited to The Hague. Thus, the combined phenomena of loss aversion and the power of Milosevic’s prime value, power, problematized the possible ICTY deterrence. On Milosevic’s personality, it was found that there might have been two Milosevic’s, a good and a bad one. The bad one seemed to closely conform to the Dark Triad of personality. Second, this chapter looked at the relationship between the court and the criminal. It studied the certainty, severity, and celerity of the Tribunal’s legal sanctions, concluding that all three were perceived by Milosevic as being rather low. Combined with Milosevic’s experiences with the ICTY – remaining immune from prosecution, while his friends – who were indicted – remained beyond the Tribunal’s reach for a long time – and his risk sensitivity, this decreased the relevance of the disincentive the Tribunal’s threats could deliver. This paragraph then looked at how Milosevic perceived the ICTY’s legitimacy and the environment in which extralegal sanction threats were formed. It found that Milosevic strongly contested the ICTY’s legitimacy, seeing it as victor’s justice, set up to punish him – and with him the Serbs –, while, in his view, the Serbs were the victims, not the aggressors. Moreover, he contested the establishment and impartiality of the Tribunal. Lastly, looking at the environment in which extralegal sanction threats were formed, it was concluded that the inversion of morality in the former Yugoslavia – leading to the labeling of the perpetrators of mass atrocities as ‘patriots’ – and the criminalization of the state elite in Serbia, caused extralegal sanction threats to form against not committing the crime. Milosevic’s internalized behavioral norms, which were mainly concerned with 102 the acquirement of and holding on to power, furthermore prevented self-disapproval to occur when he conducted policies which he knew would lead to severe crimes being committed. All these factors together, present a multi-causal explanation for why the ICTY failed to deter Slobodan Milosevic from committing, ordering, or aiding and abetting the commission of mass atrocities. 103 Chapter 3: Joseph Kony and the International Criminal Court The civil war between Joseph Kony’s Lord’s Resistance Army (LRA) and the Ugandan government has plagued Northern Uganda and its neighbors for the last 25 years, taking the lives of tens of thousands of civilians and causing the misery of more than a million people. Joseph Kony and his Lord’s Resistance Army (LRA) have captured the fantasies of many, especially after the YouTube-hit “Kony 2012” gave the rebel leader the status of a super villain. Usually, reference is made to his brutal, apparently religiously inspired campaign of violence, the mutilations and the abduction of sixty to eighty thousand children, who are used as sex-slaves and forced to commit atrocities. Furthermore, it is often noted that he is being searched for crimes against humanity by the International Criminal Court (ICC) in The Hague.1 When the ICC was established back in 2002, it was hoped that it would be able to deter future atrocities by building on the legacy of international prosecution set by the International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia and the International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda, and by prosecuting perpetrators of serious crimes itself. This chapter will analyze the way in which Joseph Kony responded to the legal sanction threat issued by the International Criminal Court. To do so, it will first set the context by giving an overview of the conflict in Northern Uganda and the role Joseph Kony played in it.2 Next, an attempt will be made to better understand ‘the man’ Joseph Kony, by looking at his rationality, his motivation, and his personality, and the way they affected his response to the International Criminal Court. The next paragraph will then further scrutinize the interaction between Kony and the ICC. After describing the establishment, structure, and functioning of the Court and setting out Kony’s legal responsibility, the factors influencing the deterrence capability of the ICC vis-á-vis Joseph Kony are analyzed. To give more depth to this analysis, this chapter will further look at the social context in which Kony committed his crimes and the way in which extralegal sanction threats emanating from it affected his decision making process. The chapter will conclude by summarizing its findings. §3.1 Joseph Kony and the conflict in Northern Uganda As is the case for many post-colonial wars in Africa, the root causes for the conflict in Northern Uganda can be traced back to policies adopted during the colonial rule of the 19 th and the first half of the 20th century. Uganda had been colonized by the British Empire, whose rule brought an end to the many local wars caused by the ivory trade and the involvement of Nubi soldiers who were sent to the region to secure it for the Egyptian Khedive. The almost sixty years of colonial rule were marked by relative peace See, for example: Jeffrey Gettleman, ‘In Vast Jungle, U.S. Troops Aid in Search for Kony’, The New York Times, (27 November 2013), available online at: http://www.nytimes.com/2012/04/30/world/africa/konytracked-by-us-forces-in-central-africa.html?ref=josephkony&_r=0 (2 December 2013). 2 In many ways, Joseph Kony’s life and the activities of the LRA coincide. Joseph Kony was a central and indispensable element of the LRA. Therefore, when the conflict overview discusses the activities and history of the LRA, it can be seen as coincident with that of Joseph Kony. 1 104 and stability.3 As a way of governing the region, the British organized its inhabitants into different tribes, such as the Acholi, of which Joseph Kony is a member. The creation of tribes divided Uganda along ethnic lines, which later created a social context conducive to ethnic violence. The colonial masters also exacerbated long-standing regional divisions in Uganda. By prioritizing economic and political development in the mostly Bantu-speaking south, the Lwo-speaking north was ignored, used as a source for labor reserves or recruits for the army.4 This created a deep rift between the northern and southern parts of Uganda and put them on different roads of development.5 Quickly after Uganda had gained its independence in 1962, Milton Obote, the country’s first Prime Minister who came from Northern Uganda, used the northern-dominated army – most of whom were from the Acholi tribe – to abolish the constitution and establish dictatorial rule.6 Obote did not shirk from using violence and repression to consolidate his hold on power, but his successor, Idi Amin Dada,7 who overthrew Obote’s government in 1971, was even worse. Amin’s power base was in the north, but he immediately set out to court the economic center of power in the south. To do so, he sent many Lwo-speaking army recruits back to the barracks in the north, where they were massacred.8 In addition, his reign of terror mainly targeted Acholi and Langi, another tribe from the north.9 Amin’s ruthless dictatorship caused many Acholi to flee Uganda, some of them regrouping across the border to form the Uganda National Liberation Army (UNLA). When Amin invaded Tanzania in 1978, the Tanzanian President Julius Nyerere decided to respond in kind. In 1979, together with the UNLA, Tanzania invaded Uganda and removed Amin from power.10 After elections in 1980 which were widely considered to be rigged, Obote came back to power. In the south, which was once again facing a northern president, a large number of insurgencies came up, one of them the National Resistance Army (NRA) of Yoweri Museveni.11 The ensuing conflict between Museveni and Obote was fought largely along ethnic lines: the Bantu-speaking people from the south who made up the NRA, fought against Obote’s Tim Allen, Trial Justice: The International Criminal Court and the Lord’s Resistance Army (London: Zed Books, 2006) 25-27. 4 Janine Natalya Clark, ‘The ICC, Uganda and the LRA: Re-Framing the Debate’, African Studies 69:1 (2010) 141-160, 142. Clark states that the people in the north were speakers of the Nilotic languages. However, the people in North Uganda are usually referred to as Lwo-speakers. Dominant in Northern Uganda, Lwo is a subgroup of the Nilotic language group. See: Doris Payne, ‘The Nilotic Language Family’, (June 2002), available online at: http://pages.uoregon.edu/dlpayne/Nilotic/NiloticFamily.htm (2 December 2013). 5 Usually, when speaking of Northern Uganda, what is meant are the regions north of Lake Kyoga. The LRA was mostly active in ‘Acholiland’, an area consisting of Gulu, Kitgum, and Pader districts. 6 Kenneth A. Rodman and Petie Booth, ‘Manipulated Commitments: The International Criminal Court in Uganda’, Human Rights Quarterly 35:2 (2013) 271-303, 278; Joanna R. Quinn, ‘Getting to Peace? Negotiating with the LRA in Northern Uganda’, Human Rights Review 10:1 (2009) 55-71, 55. 7 To give an idea of Amin’s inflated sense of self-importance: he referred to himself as His Excellency President for Life, Field Marshal Alhaji Dr. Idi Amin Dada, holder of the Victoria’s Cross, the Distinguished Service Order, and the Military Cross, Conqueror of the British Empire. See: Patrick Keatly, ‘Obituary: Idi Amin’, The Guardian, (18 August 2003), available online at: http://www.theguardian.com/news/2003/aug/18/guardianobituaries (2 December 2013). 8 Allen, Trial Justice, 28. 9 Quinn, ‘Negotiating with the LRA’, 55. 10 Allen, Trial Justice, 28-29. 11 Rodman and Booth, ‘Manipulated Commitments’, 278. 3 105 mostly Lwo-speaking northern army.12 The fighting concentrated in the so-called Luwero Triangle, a region just north of the nation’s capital Kampala. Here, in 1981, Obote carried out Operation Bonanza, using his army’s Acholi to conduct large-scale massacres against civilians, which left between 300.000 and 500.000 people dead.13 Although in 1985 an Acholi general called Tito Okello toppled Obote’s dictatorship and tried to stop the NRA insurgency by giving in to some of its demands, Museveni’s NRA still marched on Kampala, taking it in January 1986.14 Museveni immediately conducted retaliatory massacres against the Lwo-speakers, thus setting the stage for new insurgencies, this time mostly from the north.15 Thus, the civil war in Northern Uganda to which this paragraph now turns, “is rooted in a long-standing political, economic, and ethnic divide”.16 The early years of Kony’s insurgency, 1986-1994 Shortly after Museveni’s overthrow of the Okello regime, a man named Joseph Kony would enter the annals of Uganda’s history. Born in 1961, in a small village in Gulu district called Odek, he was an ethnic Acholi and a resident of Acholiland.17 Little is known about his father, a man named Luizi Obol, although some information indicates that he was a catechist who had seventeen children by three different wives. Luizi probably served in the King’s African Rifles, the colonial British army active in the Second World War, before going back to Odek to raise cattle.18 Even less is known about Kony’s mother, who goes by the name of Nora.19 In any way, Kony does not seem to have had a particularly close connection to either his mother or his father. Kony’s family was somewhat exceptional. It was shunned by the rest of the village – both out of respect and fear – because one of Kony’s many brothers was a witchdoctor, which gave the family a special place in the village’s social fabric.20 Witchdoctors like Kony’s brother played – and to a large extent still play – an important role in Acholiland, as in many other segments of East African society, for their supposed ability to communicate with the spirit world.21 Matthew Green, The Wizard of the Nile: The Hunt for Africa’s Most Wanted (London: Portobello Books, 2008) 74. 13 Quinn, ‘Negotiating with the LRA’, 56. 14 Aili Mari Tripp, Museveni’s Uganda: Paradoxies of Power in a Hybrid Regime (Boulder: Lynne Rienner Publishers, 2010) 151-152. According to Tim Allen and Koen Vlassenroot, this move on Kampala despite Okello’s attempt at negotiations is evidence for the Acholi that Museveni cannot be trusted. See: Tim Allen and Koen Vlassenroot, ‘Introduction’, in: Tim Allen and Koen Vlassenroot (eds.), The Lord’s Resistance Army: Myth and Reality (London: Zed Books, 2010) 1-21, 7. 15 Adam Branch, ‘Uganda’s Civil War and the Politics of ICC Intervention’, Ethics and International Affairs 21:2 (2007) 179-198, 180; Clark, ‘Re-Framing the Debate’, 142; Sverker Finnström, ‘An African hell of colonial imagination? The Lord’s Resistance Army in Uganda: another story’, in: Tim Allen and Koen Vlassenroot (eds.), The Lord’s Resistance Army: Myth and Reality (London: Zed Books, 2010) 74-89, 77-78. 16 Christopher Blattman, ‘From Violence to Voting: War and Political Participation in Uganda’, American Political Science Review 103:2 (2009) 231-247, 232. 17 Ruddy Doom and Koen Vlassenroot, ‘Kony’s message: a new Koine? The Lord’s Resistance Army in northern Uganda’, African Affairs 98:390 (1999) 5-36, 20. 18 Matthew Green notes that this amount of wives and children is not an exceptional number in Acholiland. See: Green, The Wizard of the Nile, 35, 121. 19 Ibid., 215. 20 Doom and Vlassenroot, ‘Kony’s Message’, 20. 21 Ibid., 20-21 12 106 Many Acholi have a firm belief in an all-consuming presence of a large amount of different spirits (jogi), which are involved in almost all aspects of life. Evil spirits, or cen, are responsible for causing negative events, while good jogi are associated with more positive events.22 The spiritual world has furthermore been syncretized with religions brought by the colonizers. Christianity and Islam have informed the traditional religions in Acholiland and have had a lasting effect on the way in which Acholi understand the world. One of the most prominent examples of this is the inclusion of the Christian Holy Spirit, or Tipu maleng, in the spiritual world.23 However, such spiritual worldviews coexist with more ‘modern’ ones.24 For example, many Ugandans will still seek medical help for diseases, but someone “may still want to know why her child died and not her neighbour’s”.25 Mediums like Kony’s brother, called ajwaki’s or nebi, are believed to be able to interpret the will of the spirits, help people in pleasing them, and sometimes even heal the sick, giving them an important and powerful role in Acholi society.26 It is not surprising, therefore, that the world of ajwaki appealed to Kony. As a kid, Kony was already special. He was usually reluctant to join in kids’ fights – he claimed not see the use of fighting – and was renowned for his oratory skills and dance moves.27 According to Kony himself, he was called by the spirits somewhere in his teenage years. They forced him to drop out of school and start healing people. When he was in his twenties, and he witnessed the rise of Museveni, these spirits called on him to fight the government.28 However, he was definitely not the first Ugandan, nor the first Acholi to do so. The first years of Museveni’s rule actually appeared to bring back a sense of normality to Uganda. After Amin’s brutal terror and the civil war under Obote – both accompanied by severe economic disasters and civilian suffering – the economic boom of the late 1980s and his apparent openmindedness made Museveni look like a godsend to many Ugandans, especially to those in the south.29 Numerous Ugandans in the north thought differently, however. Museveni’s dictatorial rule –he quickly abolished multi-party elections after gaining power – sparked as many as 27 armed insurgencies, the most devastating of which took place in the north.30 Already in 1986, the persecution of Acholi and Langi in Northern Uganda by Museveni’s NRA – to some extent as retaliation for the Luwero massacres – was reason for the Ugandan People’s Democratic Army (UPDA) to wage a conventional insurgency against the government in Kampala. This insurgency ended in a negotiated settlement between the NRA 22 Green, The Wizard of the Nile, 36-39. Allen, Trial Justice, 31. 24 Doom and Vlassenroot, ‘Kony’s Message’, 17. 25 Allen, Trial Justice, 31. See also: Green, The Wizard of the Nile, 37. 26 Doom and Vlassenroot, ‘Kony’s Message’, 17. 27 Green, The Wizard of the Nile, 35. 28 Ibid., 36. 29 Blattman, ‘From Violence to Voting’, 232 30 Quinn, ‘Negotiating with the LRA’, 56. She gets this number from: Zachary Lomo and Lucy Hovil, Behind the Violence: Causes, Consequences and the Search for Solutions to the War in Northern Uganda, Refugee Law Project Working Paper no. 11, (February 2004), available online at: http://www.issafrica.org/uploads/Mono99.pdf (2 December 2013). 23 107 and the UPDA in 1988, which offered UPDA-fighters amnesty in return for surrender.31 Yet, the secular UPDA was less influential in Northern Uganda than violent spiritual movements led by ajwaki’s. Numerous people declared themselves to be witchdoctors, their popularity fed by the insecurity and upheaval that marked the 1980s in Northern Uganda.32 One of these ajwaki’s was Alice Auma ‘Lakwena’, who led the Holy Spirit Movement (HSM) in an unconventional guerrilla campaign against the government, which she considered ‘impure’.33 Alice, three years older than Kony, claimed she was possessed by multiple spirits, most notably ‘the Messenger’, or in Acholi: ‘Lakwena’.34 These spirits instructed her on which rituals had to be performed on fighters, but also gave advice on which targets needed to be attacked next. In a short time, she attracted a mass following in the north, holding prayer meetings at ‘yards’, where she anointed her followers with shea-butter oil, “promising that if they were pure, bullets would not penetrate them” (to be pure meant to refrain from alcohol, drugs, and sexual intercourse, among many other things).35 As such, the ‘spiritual order’ of the HSM served to regulate the group’s internal and external behavior and advance group cohesion and discipline.36In 1987, Alice’s HSM moved on Kampala. In the last week of October, however, the NRA was able to stop her in a battle near Jinja. Alice was wounded, but escaped.37 Both the UPDA and, primarily, Alice’s HSM are crucial for understanding Kony’s Lord’s Resistance Army, especially for its formative years.38 At the time Kony started fighting, he was but a small pawn compared to Alice and the UPDA. Matthew Green, one of the few Western people to have spoken to Kony, reports the following story about the moment Kony decided to take up (spiritual) arms against the government “One day, Kony summoned his neighbours to the family homestead. ‘He gathered people to tell them that he had received a new spirit, the Holy Spirit, which had come to him, so that he could go and fight to overthrow the government. […] His voice was coming from his mouth, but it was not his normal voice.’”39 Kony seems to have tried to profit from the HSM’s immense popularity in Acholiland. In various ways he linked his LRA to the HSM. For example, Kony claimed to be possessed by the same ‘Lakwena’ as Blattman, ‘From Violence to Voting’, 15-16. Allen, Trial Justice, 33. 33 The HSM is sometimes called the ‘Holy Spirit Mobile Forces’. For more on Alice Lawkena, see: Heike Behrend, Alice Lakwena and the Holy Spirits: War in Northern Uganda, 1985-97 (Kampala: Fountain Publishers, 1999); Tim Allen, ‘Understanding Alice: Uganda’s Holy Spirit Movement in context’, Africa 61:3 (1991) 370-399. 34 Supposedly, “Lawkena is the spirit of an Italian who died during the First World War.” See: Doom and Vlassenroot, ‘Kony’s Message’, 16. 35 Allen, Trial Justice, 35. 36 Kristof Titeca, ‘The spiritual order of the LRA’, in: Tim Allen and Koen Vlassenroot (eds.), The Lord’s Resistance Army: Myth and Reality (London: Zed Books, 2010) 59-73, 62-71. 37 Allen, ‘Understanding Alice’, 373. 38 Finnström, ‘Another story’, 77. 39 Green, The Wizard of the Nile, 39-40. 31 32 108 Alice, who granted him similar powers. It was also suggested that Alice and Kony were related by blood, with some claiming that Alice was a cousin of Kony.40 Moreover, Alice and Kony shared a similar message: they preached that Acholi society had to be purified of evil influences, which required the overthrow of Museveni’s ‘impure’ government and the moral rejuvenation of the Acholi, if needed by violence.41 Kony added to this that the Ten Commandments should be considered as a guide for governing a post-Museveni country.42 Kony’s similarities with the immensely popular HSM lent him some popular support in his first days as a rebel, although this support was still considerably less than the support Alice had commanded.43 To improve this situation, Kony even tried to ally himself to Alice, but he was turned down, because Alice saw him as an ‘evil’ ajwaki.44 Still, by early 1988, when both the UPDA and the HSM had been defeated, Kony was effectively the only important Acholi insurgency remaining. Defeated UPDA- and HSM-rebels, who did not want to accept the government’s demands, flocked to Kony, strengthening the LRA with experienced guerilla fighters.45 Indeed, one of the UPDA’s most effective commanders, Odong Latek, joined the LRA and helped Kony train his fighters in guerrilla tactics, significantly increasing the group’s military capabilities.46 During the LRA’s first years, its operations mostly consisted of small-scale guerilla actions against NRA-targets. The brutality which would mark the group’s later actions, was still absent in these days. Two things changed this. The first was that Museveni tried to cover up the problems in the north, a symptom of which was the appointment of the controversial and seemingly powerless Betty Bigombe as Minister of State for Pacification of the Northern Uganda.47 The second was that, to quell the insurgency, Kampala initiated Operation North, in 1991. During this operation, the government formed so-called ‘Arrow Groups’, lightly armed Acholi self-defense militias which had to defend the civilian population from violence perpetrated by the LRA.48 The apparent betrayal of the Acholi angered Kony, and he retaliated by stepping up violence against civilians, who were now considered to be ‘impure’ as well.49 People suspected of collaborating with the government were punished with brutal mutilations: anyone who talked to the government, had their lips cut off; owning a bike – associated with its use to Ruddy Doom and Vlassenroot clearly state that Alice is Kony’s cousin. See: Doom and Vlassenroot, ‘Kony’s Message’, 20. Later research, however, contradict this claim. Green, who has seen some family trees of Kony, concludes that there seems to be some sort of familial relation, which is hard to pin down. Green, The Wizard of the Nile, 79. Allen confirms the haziness of the relation, but suggests that “Alice and Kony share a grandfather on their mothers’ side”. Allen, Trial Justice, 37. 41 Doom and Vlassenroot, ‘Kony’s Message’, 22. 42 Allen, Trial Justice, 43. 43 Doom and Vlassenroot, ‘Kony’s Message’, 23. 44 Allen, Trial Justice, 38-39. 45 Blattman, ‘From Violence to Voting’, 232. 46 Rodman and Booth, ‘Manipulated Commitments’, 279. 47 Allen and Vlassenroot, ‘Introduction’, 11. 48 Rodman and Booth, ‘Manipulated Commitments, 279-280. 49 Branch, ‘The Politics of ICC Intervention’, 180; Philipp Kastner, International Criminal Justice in bello?: The ICC between Law and Politics in Darfur and Northern Uganda (Leiden: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, 2012) 21; Rodman and Booth, ‘Manipulated Commitments’, 279-280. 40 109 inform the government of LRA attacks – resulted in the chopping off of legs, etc.50 Moreover, the LRA, lacking significant voluntary support, started using large-scale abduction as a means of recruitment. Kony’s fighters abducted scores of children, men and women, using them as fighters, sex slaves, but sometimes also as short-term porters.51 These abductees were often forced to commit atrocities, undergoing initial rites such as the killing their own parents or fellow abductees to harden them and make them irrevocably part of the LRA.52 At the same time, the government’s NRA was also implicated in crimes against civilians. Acholi suspected of involvement with the insurgency were massacred by government forces and innocent civilians were arbitrarily tortured, beaten, raped, and killed.53 Peace talks, continued violence, and forced displacement, 1994-2000 During this escalation of violence, Betty Bigombe tried to start negotiations between Kampala and the LRA. She generally abstained from violent policies, instead “keeping a certain distance from all interest groups”, while she remained “willing to talk to anyone”.54 This position seemed to pay off, and between 1988 and 1996 various peace accords, limited in scope, were attempted.55 In 1993-1994, Bigombe came very close to reaching a negotiated settlement. There was a mood of reconciliation in Northern Uganda. LRA fighters were able to visit several Northern Ugandan towns, and were seen fraternizing with NRA soldiers.56 Even though the peace talks were very promising and a ceasefire was reached, in the end, the talks backfired. In January 1994, Museveni ordered an ultimatum, demanding that the rebels lay down their weapons unconditionally within a week.57 Kony was furious. He called Bigombe on his satellite phone, and said: “Unless we demonstrate to people that we are still here, the government will never accept peace talks. I’m going to do things that will shock the world.”58 Why did the 1994 peace talks, which seemed to have such a good chance of success, fail? Both Museveni and Kony are to blame. Museveni was never really interested in a negotiated settlement, preferring a military solution instead. The army, increasingly important as a bastion of support for Museveni’s rule, needed to be kept busy, and the fight against the ‘brutal’ and ‘savage’ LRA legitimized his authoritarian rule.59 At the same time, 50 Green, The Wizard of the Nile, 171. Blattman, ‘From Violence to Voting’, 233-235. See also: Allen, Trial Justice, 60-66; Phuom Pham, Patrick Vinck, and Eric Stover, ‘The Lord’s Resistance Army and forced conscription in Northern Uganda’, Human Rights Quarterly 30:2 (2008) 404-411. 52 For the various phases the LRA abductees are forced to go through in their transformation from child to fighter, see: Opis Oloya, Child to Soldier: Stories from Joseph Kony’s Lord’s Resistance Army (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2013) 78-95. 53 Branch, ‘The Politics of ICC Intervention’, 181. 54 Allen and Vlassenroot, ‘Introduction’, 11. 55 Quinn, ´Negotiating with the LRA´, 59, 56 Allen, Trial Justice, 48. 57 Kastner, The ICC between Law and Politics, 21-22; Rodman and Booth, ‘Manipulated Commitments’, 281. 58 Green, The Wizard of the Nile, 173. See also: Doom and Vlassenroot, ‘Kony’s Message’, 25. 59 Allen and Vlassenroot, ‘Introduction’, 12; Branch, ‘The Politics of ICC Intervention’, 185; International Crisis Group, A Strategy for Ending Northern Uganda’s Crisis, Africa Briefing No. 35, (11 January 2006), available online at: http://www.crisisgroup.org/~/media/Files/africa/horn-ofafrica/uganda/B035%20A%20Strategy%20for%20Ending%20Northern%20Ugandas%20Crisis.pdf (2 December 2013) 12; Andrew Mwenda, ´Uganda´s politics of foreign aid and violent conflict: the political uses of the LRA 51 110 Kony also opted for the maximization of his gains. This meant continued abductions and violence for self-sustainment. He was rather lackluster about peace talks: the very reason Museveni had issued the ultimatum was that Kony had asked for a few months of postponement before signing the peace agreement.60 Museveni suspected that Kony would use the time to prepare and rearm for more insurgency operations. There may have been some truth in this suspicion. In the first half of the 1990s, Sudan was emerging as a major spoiler in the Northern Ugandan peace process. The Sudan-Uganda border area was increasingly a region in which the country’s respective governments waged a proxy war against each other.61 The government of President Omar al-Bashir in Khartoum was waging a counterinsurgency campaign in South Sudan. To destabilize the Sudanese government, Museveni supported the main rebel group there, called the Sudanese People’s Liberation Army (SPLA).62 At the same time, Khartoum used various proxy militias – one of them the LRA – to fight the SPLA.63 Kony agreed to fight the SPLA, and Khartoum gave him refuge from Uganda’s government troops in South Sudan in return, as well as large amounts of weapons and money.64 There is some evidence that during the 1994 peace talks the LRA was reorganizing itself in South Sudan, being resupplied by Khartoum, in this way acquiring the means to “shock the world” as Kony had promised Bigombe.65 The period after 1994 saw some of the LRA’s worst crimes. For example, in April/May 1995, LRA fighters attacked a village called Atiak, where they murdered hundreds of villagers and burned their homes. The victims – including women and children, even some babies – were mostly clubbed or chopped to death.66 The LRA also stepped up its campaign of abductions. In one incident, some 160 young girls, were abducted from St. Mary’s College in Aboke, located in Lira district.67 In both instances, despite the fact that they were close by, government forces were either too late or unwilling rebellion’, in: Tim Allen and Koen Vlassenroot (eds.), The Lord’s Resistance Army: Myth and Reality (London: Zed Books, 2010) 45-58, 51. 60 Allen, Trial Justice, 49. 61 Congo was also involved in this proxy warfare. See: Gerard Prunier, ‘Rebel movements and proxy warfare: Uganda, Sudan and the Congo (1986-1999)’, African Affairs 103:412 (2004) 359-383. 62 Allen and Vlassenroot, ‘Introduction’, 12; Kastner, The ICC between Law and Politics, 19. 63 Cecily G. Brewer, ‘Peril by Proxy: Negotiating Conflict in East Africa’, International Negotiation 16:1 (2011) 137-167, 145-147. 64 Global politics were to some extent responsible for these more regional considerations. According to Mwenda, “[t]he Cold War ended in 1990, and this shifted US geostrategic concerns from the threat of communism to the spread of Islamic extremism. [After Omar al-Bashir took power in Sudan, the US] responded by labeling the [Islamic] regime in Khartoum a threat, and thus began to finance the rebel [SPLA]. Uganda became the conduit of this assistance. In retaliation, Sudan began to support the LRA[.]” See: Mwenda, ‘Uganda’s politics of foreign aid’, 49. 65 Green, The Wizard of the Nile, 174-176. 66 Allen and Vlassenroot, ‘Introduction’, 12. 67 The LRA’s apparent focus on abducting children, turning them into child soldiers and sex slaves, seems particularly abhorrent. Yet, according to Allen, this must not be overemphasized. Children do not make up the majority of the people abducted by the LRA (although they do make up the majority of the people ‘kept’). Moreover, the abduction of children is a strategic choice. Not only does this terrorize the community, the children are seen as ‘blank spaces’, who can be raised according to the LRA norms and values and who are not yet contaminated by ‘impure’ Acholi practices. See: Allen, Trial Justice, 60-66. 111 to react.68 In 1996, in reaction to this campaign of increased violence, the Ugandan People’s Defense Forces (UPDF, the NRA’s new name according to the 1995 constitution) initiated a policy of systematic concentration of the supposedly hostile population in Northern Uganda. 69 Inhabitants of the rural areas were forced to migrate towards mass camps for so-called Internally Displaced Persons (IDP’s). Those who did not want to migrate, were forced to, in “a campaign of murder, intimidation, and the bombing and burning of entire villages”.70 Soon, the number of people in the IDP camps numbered close to 1.5 million and at some point almost 90 percent of the population of Northern Uganda was stuck in the camps.71 Ostensibly, these forced displacements were meant to protect the civilians from abductions and attacks by the LRA, but in many ways the civilians’ living conditions only worsened. The IDP camps were poorly sanitized, causing a large number of diseases, and there was little food, although large operations by aid agencies such as the World Food Programme relieved these conditions somewhat.72 In the 2000s, a thousand people died every week from conflict-related disease and malnutrition.73 Moreover, the UPDF and local defense groups were unable to protect the civilians in the camps from LRA attacks.74 For example, a camp of 15.000 IDP’s would be protected by about 14 soldiers, who lived in the middle of the camp, raising the question of who was supposed to protect who.75 The deteriorated security situation led to the phenomenon of ‘night commuting’. Every day large groups of children walked miles to congregate at a safe place in order to protect themselves from abduction.76 The UPDF, failing to protect the civilians from the LRA, has in fact itself been implicated in large-scale abuses of civilians in the camps. Beatings, torture, rape, and want-on killings were perpetrated on a daily basis, further intensifying the suffering of the people in the camps.77 During almost the entire 1990s, the international political response to the violence and suffering taking place in Northern Uganda, remained minimal. This had much to do with the fact that Museveni succeeded in keeping the disaster in the north beyond the international community’s view, acting like Allen and Vlassenroot, ‘Introduction’, 12. Mwenda, ‘Uganda’s politics of foreign aid’, 46. 70 Branch, ‘The Politics of ICC Intervention’, 181. 71 Allen, Trial Justice, 53; Clark, ‘Re-Framing the Debate’, 142. 72 It has been argued that the policy of the aid agencies – feeding the people in the camps but not doing anything about the causes of their suffering, namely the forced concentration into large unprotected and undersupplied IDP camps – to some extent only worsened the situation, institutionalizing the camps and helping Museveni to maintain the status quo. Chris Dolan, for example, has stated: “Like doctors in a torture situation, they appear to be there to ease the suffering of victims, but in reality they enable the process to be prolonged by keeping the victim alive for further abuses.” Quoted in: Green, The Wizard of the Nile, 91. See also: Chris Dolan, Understanding War and Its Continuation: The Case of Northern Uganda (London: Development Studies Institute, London School of Economics, 2005); Mwenda, ‘Uganda’s politics of foreign aid’, 55-56. 73 Nick Grono and Adam O’Brien, ‘Justice in Conflict? The ICC and Peace Processes’, in: Nicholas Waddell and Phil Clark (eds.), Courting Conflict? Justice, Peace and the ICC in Africa, (London: Royal African Society, 2008) 13-20, 14-15. 74 Branch, ‘The Politics of ICC Intervention’, 181. 75 Mwenda, ‘Uganda’s politics of foreign aid’, 55. 76 Green, The Wizard of the Nile, 89; Quinn, ‘Negotiating with the LRA’, 57. 77 Branch, ‘The Politics of ICC Intervention’, 181. 68 69 112 the LRA was everything but defeated.78 When Museveni accepted demands in May 1987 from the International Monetary Fund (IMF) to conduct Western-styled market reforms in Uganda, large amounts of foreign aid from Western donors were made available. In Southern Uganda, this led to a quick economic recovery.79 Moreover, Museveni looked like a good example of the new generation of African presidents: his apparent open-mindedness – he was talking about solutions to AIDS while the subject was still a big taboo in the rest of Africa80 - and regular exhortations to African leaders who refused to give up power, made him look like the ideal partner for the West.81 While its neighbors Rwanda and the Democratic Republic of Congo (DRC) were plagued by political upheaval and large-scale violence,82 and Sudan increasingly became – in American words – a “state-sponsor of terrorism”, Museveni’s Uganda looked like a bastion of peace and stability. All these factors made Museveni something of a ‘Darling of the West’. In the words of one observer, he became “arguably the most influential head of state in sub-Saharan Africa after Nelson Mandela”.83 However, this idolization of Museveni caused the crisis in the north to be all but forgotten, if not ignored. News reports issued around the turn of the millennium often called the situation in Northern Uganda “the most forgotten crisis in the world”.84 Amnesty, further counter-insurgency operations, and ICC involvement, 2000-2006 The failure of Museveni to defeat the LRA militarily and the absence of international involvement led to more regional peace initiatives. After Bigombe’s failed peace talks in 1994, the Acholi Religious Leaders Peace Initiative (ARLPI), an organization of tribal elders and religious leaders supposedly representing the victims of the war, pleaded for the abandonment of the military option in favor of traditional reconciliation. In 2000, the ARLPI succeeded in getting the government to enact an Amnesty Law, overcoming significant opposition from Museveni.85 Granted overwhelming popular support by the Acholi community, the Amnesty Law would allow anyone who renounced violence and abandon the LRA – regardless of rank or crimes committed – to return to his or her community without having to fear criminal prosecution.86 Anyone who accepted the terms, would receive an ‘amnesty package’, Oliver Furley, ‘Uganda: The Struggle for Peace’, in: Oliver Furley and Roy May (eds.), Ending Africa’s Wars: Progressing to Peace (Aldershot: Ashgate Publishing Ltd., 2006) 116-133, 120-121. 79 Mwenda, ´Uganda´s politics of foreign aid’, 46-47. 80 Furley, ‘Uganda: The Struggle for Peace’, 130-131. 81 Sandrine Perrot, ‘Northern Uganda: a ‘forgotten conflict’, again? The impact of the internationalization of the resolution process’, in: Tim Allen and Koen Vlassenroot, The Lord’s Resistance Army: Myth and Reality (London: Zed Books, 2010) 187-204, 191. 82 In the end, it turned out that Museveni was as deeply involved in the exploitation of the DRC as his neighbors. See: Filip Reyntjens, The Great African War: Congo and Regional Geopolitics, 1996-2006 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010). 83 Green, The Wizard of the Nile, 85-86. 84 Furley, ‘Uganda: The Struggle for Peace’, 118. 85 Kasaija Phillip Apuuli, ‘Peace over Justice: The Acholi Religious Leaders Peace Initiative (ARLPI) vs. the International Criminal Court (ICC) in Northern Uganda’, Studies in Ethnicity and Nationalism 11:1 (2011) 116129, 121-122. 86 Branch, ‘The Politics of ICC Intervention’, 184; Clark, ‘Re-Framing the Debate’, 145; Katherine Southwick, ‘Investigating War in Northern Uganda: Dilemmas for the International Criminal Court’, Yale Journal of International Affairs 1 (2005) 105-119, 109. 78 113 consisting of some money and other things that would help the reintegration of the former fighter.87 First, however, they would have to go through a traditional reconciliation ceremony, called mato oput, which involves rituals such as stepping on eggs – signifying a fresh start –, consumption of a bitter tasting root, the confession of guilt and the paying of compensation, presided over by elders and chiefs.88 The Amnesty Commission, responsible for overseeing the execution of the Amnesty Law, produced some results: tens of thousands of former rebel fighters have accepted the amnesty since 2000, although these included only a few top commanders.89 Still, problems remain. One of these is the fact that Kony has threatened his fighters with retaliation if they turn themselves over to the Amnesty Commission, because the amnesty forms a threat to the cohesion and internal discipline of the LRA. The threat of violence has deterred some fighters from defecting.90 Also, the Ugandan government has been accused of recruiting former abductees into the UPDF’s 105th battalion, making use of their military skills.91 In addition, as was noted earlier, Museveni strongly opposed the Amnesty Law. In his eyes, military operations remained the only viable option to fight the LRA.92 Once again, it turned out that Museveni did not have any real interest in a peaceful resolution of the conflict. To quote Ugandan journalist Andrew Mwenda, “What does he lose [with the war in the north]?”93 In March 2002, Museveni initiated Operation Iron Fist, a large-scale military operation, which involved over ten thousand troops. Iron Fist would have to defeat the LRA once and for all. Several factors coincided to give this operation a good chance of success. First, in the late 1990s international pressure on Sudan greatly increased, eventually causing Khartoum to officially end its support of the LRA. In 1999, the American Carter Center managed to bring about the Nairobi agreement between Kampala and Khartoum, which stipulated that they would both cease their support for proxy militias in each other’s countries.94 Although both governments did not actually alter their respective policies of proxy warfare substantially, the agreement opened the door for Museveni to gain Sudanese agreement to pursue the LRA into its territory during Operation Iron Fist, thus denying the LRA refuge.95 An important reason for Khartoum 87 Allen, Trial Justice, 125. According to Allen, the ‘traditional’ Acholi process of mato oput is different from the ceremony adapted to ‘forgive’ former LRA fighters and abductees. For example, it did not include the stepping on eggs, a ceremony apart called nyono tong gweno, which was used in other circumstances. In addition, the process of mato oput has its own pragmatic and moral problems. See: Allen, Trial Justice, 130-131, 160-168. See also: Steven C. Roach, ‘Multilayered Justice in Northern Uganda: ICC Intervention and Local Procedures of Accountability’, International Criminal Law Review 13:1 (2013) 249-268, 251-258. 89 Michael Otim and Marieke Wierda, ‘Justice at Juba: International Obligations and Local Demands in Northern Uganda’, in: Nicholas Waddell and Phil Clark (eds.), Courting Conflict? Justice, Peace and the ICC in Africa, (London: Royal African Society, 2008) 21-28, 22. See also: Tim Allen and Mareike Schomerus, A hard homecoming. Lessons learned from the reception centre process in Northern Uganda – and independent study, Management Systems International, (15 August 2006), available online at: http://pdf.usaid.gov/pdf_docs/PNADI241.pdf (2 December 2013). 90 Blattman, ‘From Violence to Voting’, 234. 91 Allen, Trial Justice, 77-78. 92 Kastner, The ICC Between Law and Politics, 22-23. 93 Green, The Wizard of the Nile, 119. 94 Brewer, ‘Peril by Proxy’, 148-149. 95 Kastner, The ICC Between Law and Politics, 23-24. 88 114 to move from spoiler to facilitator, was that it hoped to end its international isolation resulting from its alleged support of terrorism. The fight against terrorism gained increased international importance after Jihadi terrorists attacked the United States with several suicide operations on 11 September 2001 and the administration of George W. Bush declared “war on terror” shortly after.96 The LRA was included on the USA Patriot Act Terrorist Exclusion List, which provided the rationale to significantly increase U.S. support for Kampala. During Operation Iron Fist, the U.S. even provided logistical support and military advisers to the UPDF.97 Together with the support of Khartoum, the U.S. support for Operation Iron Fist made it one of the strongest military measures taken against the LRA to date. But, although it dealt a heavy blow to the LRA and UPDF troops came very close to capturing Kony, the operation did not succeed in defeating the LRA.98 The operation did lead to an increase in human rights abuses against civilians by both the LRA and the UPDF, however.99 Kony was both angered and frightened by the UPDF’s Operation Iron Fist. During the initial phases of the government action, Kony disappeared into the Imatong Mountains near the Sudan-Uganda border, from where he could conduct an excellent defense due to the area’s ruggedness and inaccessibility.100 From there, he planned the ‘counter-punch’ against the government. Once again, Kony retaliated mostly against civilians. By conducting incursions into Northern Uganda – committing massacres, mutilations, and abductions along the way – the LRA terrorized civilians living in the SudanUganda border area. Over 850 attacks were reported in this period.101 In one, not unusual case, the LRA attacked the town of Kitgum, where forty-eight people were hacked to death on 25 July 2002, with babies being flung against trees.102 Two years later, on 21 February 2004, Kony directed his fighters against Barlonya camp, where some two hundred unarmed people were killed.103 The return of the LRA to Northern Uganda as a result of Operation Iron Fist, led some Northern Ugandans to accuse the government of stirring up the hornet’s nest of the LRA.104 At the same time, to protect itself from the furious UPDF attacks, the LRA moved its most important bases north of the Sudanese ‘Red Line’, the northernmost point of deployment for UPDF troops under the agreement between Kampala and 96 Allen, Trial Justice, 51. Allen and Vlassenroot, ‘Introduction’, 14. 98 Furley, ‘Uganda: Progressing to Peace’, 116. 99 Human Rights Watch, Uprooted and Forgotten, 14-36. 100 Green, The Wizard of the Nile, 147; International Crisis Group, Northern Uganda: Understanding and Solving the Conflict, Africa Report No. 77, (14 April 2004), available online at: http://www.crisisgroup.org/~/media/Files/africa/horn-ofafrica/uganda/Northern%20Uganda%20Understanding%20and%20Solving%20the%20Conflict.pdf (2 December 2013) 7. 101 Matthew Brubacher, ‘The ICC investigation of the Lord’s Resistance Army: an insider’s view’, in: Tim Allen and Koen Vlassenroot, The Lord’s Resistance Army: Myth and Reality (London: Zed Books, 2010) 262-277, 270. 102 Payam Akhavan, ‘The Lord’s Resistance Army Case: Uganda’s Submission of the First State Referral to the International Criminal Court’, The American Journal of International Law 99:2 (2005) 403-421, 408-409. 103 Allen, Trial Justice, 3. 104 Human Rights Watch, Uprooted and Forgotten: Impunity and Human Rights Abuses in Northern Uganda, (20 September 2005), available online at: http://www.hrw.org/sites/default/files/reports/uganda0905.pdf (2 December 2013) 9-10. 97 115 Khartoum.105 In the end, despite the fact that he was now branded as a terrorist by the U.S., Kony managed to maintain the LRA’s operational capability from his hide-out in the Imatong Mountains, mostly because of continued support from Omar al-Bashir’s government and a stepped-up abduction effort to replenish its ranks.106 In the same year that Kony had to defend himself from Operation Iron Fist, a development in international law created an institution which would have a significant impact on the situation in Northern Uganda. On 1 July 2002 the Rome Statute entered into force, which gave the International Criminal Court (ICC) the mandate to start its operations.107 The ICC quickly recognized the situation in Northern Uganda as a potential case for investigation, since it seemed obvious to everyone that crimes falling within the Court’s jurisdiction had been committed in the conflict.108 In December 2003, the Ugandan government decided to refer the situation in Northern Uganda to the jurisdiction of the ICC, declaring: Having exhausted every other means of bringing an end to this terrible suffering, the Republic of Uganda now turns to the newly established ICC and its promise of global justice. Uganda pledges its full cooperation to the Prosecutor in the investigation and prosecution of LRA crimes, achievement of which is vital not only for the future progress of the nation, but also for the suppression of the most serious crimes of concern to the international community as a whole. 109 The ICC was happy to accept the referral, seeing it as a chance to prove its viability and effectiveness as a new institution of international law.110 In January 2004, the referral was made public at a joint press conference in London by Museveni and the ICC Chief Prosecutor, Luis Moreno-Ocampo, who declared to accept this ‘situation concerning the Lord’s Resistance Army’.111 The joint press conference and the initial naming of the investigation aroused suspicion about the ICC’s alleged partiality. It seemed that the ICC was only investigating crimes committed by the LRA, leaving the UPDF out of the investigation. Many questioned Museveni’s motives for referring the situation to the ICC.112 He was accused of instrumentalizing the ICC, using it to frustrate the efforts of the Amnesty Commission.113 The ICC, moreover, was suspected of partiality, because of its dependence Brubacher, ‘An Insider’s View’, 270. Akhavan, ‘First State Referral’, 409. 107 The creation of the ICC, its legal regime and the Court’s peculiarities will be discussed further below, in §3.3.1. 108 Akhavan, ‘First State Referral’, 404; Allen, Trial Justice, 82-83; Brubacher, ‘An Insider’s View’, 268-269. 109 Quoted in: Branch, ‘The Politics of ICC Intervention’, 182-183. 110 Akhavan, ‘The First State Referral’, 404-406. 111 Allen, Trial Justice, 82. 112 See, inter alia, Phil Clark, ‘Law, Politics and Pragmatism: The ICC and Case Selection in the Democratic Republic of Congo and Uganda’, in: Nicholas Waddell and Phil Clark (eds.), Courting Conflict? Justice, Peace and the ICC in Africa, (London: Royal African Society, 2008) 37-45, 42-43; Rodman and Booth, ‘Manipulated Commitments’, 284-286. 113 Clark, ‘The ICC and Case Selection’, 42; Roach, ‘Multilayered Justice’, 187. 105 106 116 on the Ugandan government.114 When the Court issued its first indictments, which were initially issued under seal on 8 July 2005 but were unsealed on 13 October 2005,115 these suspicions were amplified. The first five arrest warrants, the only ones issued so far for the conflict, all targeted members of the LRA leadership.116 Although the ICC Prosecutor’s Office has repeatedly stressed that it investigates all parties to the conflict, it could not properly defend itself for its seeming lack of attention for the crimes committed by the UPDF.117 Multiple observers have argued that the forced displacement of more than a million Northern Ugandans into IDP camps constituted a war crime under the Rome Statute.118 However, it is clear that the ICC’s dependence on the Ugandan government is too great to risk indicting government agents. Ugandan officials have stated multiple times that any accusations against UPDF soldiers would result in the withdrawal of the Ugandan government from the international justice process.119 At the time of writing, the ICC has still only issued warrants against the LRA; none have been issued against the UPDF or members of the Ugandan government.120 As was intended by Museveni, the involvement of the ICC in the Northern Ugandan civil war resulted in a great increase of international attention for the conflict.121 It was hoped that the ICC could contribute to ending the war by putting pressure on Sudan to stop supporting the LRA and by decapitating the LRA, so that the rest of the LRA as an organization would wither and die.122 Moreover, some expected that Kampala would see the increased international scrutiny as a warning against relying too heavily on the military option. The first objective was to a large extent reached. Sudan increasingly cooperated with the Ugandan government in denying safe havens to the LRA and it cut most of its funding for the rebel group.123 The second and third objective have thus far not been reached, however. The LRA, although diminished in size and capabilities, is still a functioning rebel group, and Kony remains at large. In addition, there is no reason to believe that Museveni saw the referral as a reason to more actively pursue peace negotiations. Rather, the criminalization of the LRA legitimized more military operations, which were now labeled as ‘international law enforcement’.124 In May 2004, soon after the ICC opened its investigations, the UPDF initiated Operation Iron Fist II, another immense military operation targeting the LRA in South Sudan.125 Otim and Wierda, ‘Justice at Juba’, 22. Brubacher, ‘An Insider’s View’, 275; Manisuli Ssenyonjo, ‘The International Criminal Court and the Lord’s Resistance Army Leaders: Prosecution or Amnesty?’, International Criminal Law Review 7:2-3 (2007) 361-389, 366-367. 116 Allen, Trial Justice, 182-185. 117 Clark, ‘The ICC and Case Selection’, 42-43. 118 Branch, ‘The Politics of ICC Intervention’, 181; Clark, ‘The ICC and Case Selection’, 43. 119 Ibid. 120 International Criminal Court, ‘Situation in Uganda’, available online at: http://www.icccpi.int/EN_Menus/ICC/Situations%20and%20Cases/Situations/Situation%20ICC%200204/Pages/situation%20i ndex.aspx (2 December 2013). 121 Akhavan, ‘First State Referral’, 404. 122 Branch, ‘The Politics of ICC Intervention’, 183. 123 The ICC indictment of Sudanese President Omar al-Bashir complicated this matter, however. 124 Booth and Rodman, ‘Manipulated Commitments’, 296-303; Branch, ‘The Politics of ICC Intervention’, 183. 125 Brubacher, ‘An Insider’s View’, 270. 114 115 117 Juba peace talks, the LRA’s flight from Uganda and further international involvement, 2006-today The two Iron Fist operations, together with expanded international attention and the loss of its ally in Sudan, greatly increased the international pressure on the LRA. Kony was desperate.126 To augment his survival chances, he decided to move the LRA’s base of operations to the DRC and simultaneously increase its commitment to peace talks. In September 2005, the first group of LRA fighters led by Kony’s second-in-command Vincent Otti crossed the Nile and moved into the Garamba National Park in the DRC Haut Uele province, where the density of the bush made effective government supervision almost impossible.127 After Kony had joined him in early 2006, the LRA concluded that peace talks with Kampala negotiated by the government of South Sudan128 would now be its best option.129 As was the case with Bigombe’s peace talks in 1994, the Juba peace talks looked like they could finally bring the war to an end. The negotiators, headed by Vice-President of South Sudan Riek Machar, succeeded in bringing about a Cessation of Hostilities Agreement in August 2006.130 Between 2006 and 2008 the talks resumed, and some peace finally returned to Northern Uganda. One of the biggest issues at the table was the outstanding ICC arrest warrant. Kony demanded that an amnesty would be part of any negotiated agreement between him and Kampala.131 The Ugandan government, however, including President Museveni in the early days of the Juba peace talks, remained ambiguous at this point. Some officials suggested that the Ugandan government would retrieve its ICC referral if Kony signed a peace agreement and would extend amnesty under the 2000 Amnesty Law.132 At the same time, however, Museveni showed signs that Kony might be arrested after all: he signified that LRA leaders indicted by the ICC would be exempt from the Amnesty Law.133 The ICC Prosecutor was especially fervent in its refusal to accept any sort of amnesty for Kony. Luis Moreno-Ocampo has called Kony’s demands “extortion and blackmail” and emphasized the Ugandan government’s duty and Akhavan, ‘First State Referral’, 419. Brubacher, ‘An Insider’s View’, 274; Ssenyonjo, ‘Prosecution or Amnesty?’, 363. 128 The Sudanese government in Khartoum and the SPLA signed a Comprehensive Peace Agreement (CAP) in January 2005, formally ending the north-south Sudanese civil war. One of the many provisions was the creation of a separate Government of South Sudan, headed by the former SPLA rebels, with its capital in Juba. See: Ronald R. Atkinson, ‘‘The realists in Juba’? An analysis of the Juba peace talks’, in: Tim Allen and Koen Vlassenroot, The Lord’s Resistance Army: Myth and Reality (London: Zed Books, 2010) 205-222, 207. In 2011, as was agreed to in the CAP, South Sudan held a referendum to vote on its potential secession, which would turn it into a sovereign state, independent from Khartoum. The South Sudanese voted for this independence in January 2011. See: United Nations News Centre, ‘UN welcomes South Sudan as 193rd Member State’, (14 July 2011), available online at: http://www.un.org/apps/news/story.asp?NewsID=39034&Cr=South+Sudan&Cr1=#.UnvpIPkrdBk (2 December 2013). It is clear that the changed regional dynamics which were a result of the CAP, gave a significant impetus to the Juba peace talks: Khartoum’s rationale for supporting the LRA had now largely disappeared and the LRA’s former enemies, the SPLA, were now in power in South Sudan. See: Otim and Wierda, ‘Justice at Juba’, 22-23. 129 Atkinson, ‘Juba Peace Talks’, 211; Kastner, The ICC between Law and Politics, 24. 130 Otim and Wierda, ‘Justice at Juba’, 21; Ssenyonjo, ‘Prosecution or Amnesty?’, 368-369. 131 Otim and Wierda, ‘Justice at Juba’, 21. 132 Ibid., 23; Quinn, ‘Negotiating with the LRA’, 66; Ssenyonjo, ‘Prosecution or Amnesty?’, 363-364, 371-372. 133 Akhavan, ‘First State Referral’, 410. 126 127 118 responsibility to uphold the law.134 Furthermore, the ICC Prosecutor’s Office suspected Kony of using the Juba peace talks to regroup and rearm.135 Outside observers have noted the impossible position in which the ICC’s refusal to accept the inclusion of an amnesty in a peace agreement put Kony and the other indicted rebel commanders. To cite a statement that is often quoted: “Obviously, nobody can convince the leaders of a rebel movement to come to the negotiating table and at the same time tell them that they will appear in courts to be prosecuted.”136 In the end, Kony decided that his fate was too unclear, and retreated from the peace talks in November 2008, citing the lack of clarity about the ICC warrants as the main reason. This decision followed a leadership struggle between Joseph Kony and Vincent Otti, supposedly over the negotiation strategy in Juba. The struggle ended in October 2007 with Otti’s execution by rebels loyal to Kony.137 By then, the LRA had firmly established itself in the DRC. By 2007, it also spread to the Central African Republic, maintaining a strong presence in regions where the countries’ respective governments had limited control. Although seriously weakened by the Iron Fist operations, the LRA was still able to terrorize citizens. Once again, large-scale abductions took place, giving the LRA access to fresh recruits. After a particularly brutal episode of violence in September 2008 and an intensification of U.S. pressure, the President of the DRC, Joseph Kabila, approvedmilitary operations by Ugandan troops against the LRA in Congo.138 In the beginning of December 2008, with U.S. support in logistics, planning, and intelligence, the UPDF, in cooperation with Congolese and SPLA troops – as well as forces from the U.N. Mission in Congo, the Mission de l’Organisation des Nations Unies en RD Congo (MONUC) – initiated Operation Lightning Thunder.139 However, the operation quickly ran into problems, and the LRA soon retaliated, by killing, maiming, and abducting hundreds of civilians in Congo and South Sudan in the 2008 Christmas Massacres. According to Human Rights Watch, at least 815 Congolese civilians and 50 Sudanese civilians lost their lives in this massacre.140 Thus, despite increased pressure, Joseph Kony and his LRA still seemed anything but defeated. Luis Moreno-Ocampo, ‘The Role of the International Community in Assisting the International Criminal Court to Secure Justice and Accountability’, in: René Provost and Payam Akhavan (eds.), Confronting Genocide (Berlin: Springer, 2011) 279-289, 288. 135 Brubacher, ‘An Insider’s View’, 275-277. 136 Cited in: Allen, Trial Justice, 85-86. Indeed, Michael P. Scharf thinks it is unrealistic that leaders involved in conflicts will accept a negotiated peace agreement if they face the risk of arrest and imprisonment after that. See: Michael P. Scharf, ‘The Amnesty Exception to the Jurisdiction of the International Criminal Court’, Cornell International Law Journal 32 (1999) 507-527, 508. On the other hand, various proponents of international criminal justice stress that a durable peace cannot be achieved without justice. See, for example: Payam Akhavan, ‘The Rise, and Fall, and Rise of International Criminal Justice’, Journal of International Criminal Justice 11:3 (2013) 527-536, 532-534; Janine Natalya Clark, ‘Peace, Justice and the International Criminal Court: Limitations and Possibilities’, Journal of International Criminal Justice 9:3 (2011) 521-545, 543-544. 137 Clark, ‘The ICC and Case Selection’, 45, note 18; Green, The Wizard of the Nile, 184-186. 138 Human Rights Watch, The Christmas Massacres: The LRM/A attacks on civilians in northern Congo, (16 February 2009), available online at: http://www.hrw.org/sites/default/files/reports/drc0209web_0.pdf (2 December 2013) 28. 139 Human Rights Watch, The Christmas Massacres, 28; Perrot, ‘Impact of the internationalization’, 201.. 140 Human Rights Watch, The Christmas Massacres, 29. See also: Ibid., 55-60. 134 119 As was noted earlier, the ICC intervention did succeed in generating much-needed international attention for the conflict, finally giving it the attention it deserved.141 Forces from MONUC were regularly employed against suspected LRA hide-outs and entered into an agreement with the ICC to assist in the execution of the international arrest warrants.142 The United States, despite initial protests against the legitimacy of the ICC, cooperated with the Ugandan government in its fight against the LRA as part of its “war on terror”. An American military intelligence unit was deployed to Uganda, from where it assisted the Ugandan military in Operation Lightning Thunder.143 In addition, the U.S. State Department provided Kampala with $1.2 million to operate two helicopters, part of a counter-LRA program adopted by the American Congress in 2010, which also provided funds for programs encouraging LRA fighters to defect.144 In October 2011, U.S. President Barack Obama decided to send one hundred American Special Forces to the region, where they would assist in training Ugandan troops and also in fighting the LRA on the front lines.145 Lastly, a contingent of 5.000 African Union soldiers, with the mission to eliminate the LRA, was deployed to the Central African Republic.146 At the time of writing, however, Joseph Kony remains at large. In April 2013, the hunt for Joseph Kony, who is believed to be hiding somewhere in the Central African Republic, was temporarily halted because of political upheaval in the CAR caused by a rebel coup.147 In the most recent development, the new interim President of the CAR, Michel Djotodia, claimed that Kony was ready to surrender. Whether this is true remains to be seen: many LRA experts, as well as the U.S. State Department remain skeptical. 148 Although Kony is being chased closely, his still functioning LRA remains a threat to peace in the region and civilians in the area.149 Clark, ‘Re-Framing the Debate’, 141-142. Brubacher, ‘An Insider’s View’, 276. 143 Michael Gerson, ‘The worthy mission to get Joseph Kony’, The Washington Post, (17 October 2011), available online at: http://articles.washingtonpost.com/2011-10-17/opinions/35276891_1_lra-joseph-konyspecial-operations-forces (2 December 2013). 144 Starting in 2010, Shannon Sedgwick Davis, an American philanthropist also recruited a private military company to train Ugandan forces, even before the October 2011 decision to send in U.S. Special Forces. Elizabeth Rubin, ‘How a Texas Philantropist Helped Fund the Hunt for Joseph Kony’, The New Yorker, (21 October 2013), available online at: http://www.newyorker.com/online/blogs/newsdesk/2013/10/how-a-texasphilanthropist-funded-the-hunt-for-joseph-kony.html?printable=true&currentPage=all#ixzz2ijfnrFzo (2 December 2013). 145 Gerson, ‘The worthy mission’. 146 This force is called the Regional Cooperation Initiative for the Elimination of the LRA. See: Conal Urquhart, ‘Joseph Kony: African Union brigade to hunt down LRA leader’, The Guardian, (24 March 2012), available online at: http://www.theguardian.com/world/2012/mar/24/joseph-kony-african-union-brigade (2 December 2013). 147 Sudarsan Raghavan and Craig Whitlock, ‘Hunt for Joseph Kony, elusive African warlord, is halted’, The Washington Post, (3 April 2013), available online at: http://articles.washingtonpost.com/2013-0403/world/38238379_1_central-african-republic-lra-dominic-ongwen (2 December 2013). 148 J. Dana Stuster, ‘Don’t Believe the Hype: Joseph Kony Isn’t About to Surrender’, Foreign Policy, (21 November 2013), available online at: http://blog.foreignpolicy.com/posts/2013/11/21/dont_believe_the_hype_joseph_kony_isnt_about_to_surrender (2 December 2013). 149 Mark Tran, ‘Joseph Kony cannot be swept under the carpet, warns DRC priest turned activist’, The Guardian, (6 November 2013), http://www.theguardian.com/global-development/2013/nov/06/joseph-kony-drc-abbebenoit-kinalegu (2 December 2013). 141 142 120 In conclusion The rule of Yoweri Museveni has been powerfully challenged in Northern Uganda by Joseph Kony’s Lord’s Resistance Army. Kony was central to this group, a spiritual guide, military leader and its almost completely undisputed master. Supported by Sudan, the rebel group conducted a brutal campaign of terror during the 1990s, while the Ugandan army reacted with a series of counterinsurgency campaigns. The UPDF forced the people of Acholiland into IDP camps, where they were left unprotected and underfed as victims to LRA and UPDF atrocities. The international response to the savage civil war in the north was minimal until the International Criminal Court intervened in Uganda and issued arrest warrants against the LRA’s commanders. Although the military pressure on the LRA greatly increased, Joseph Kony has been able to escape the authorities and continue his campaign of terror. 121 §3.2 Joseph Kony, “messianic madman”, “freedom fighter”, “devil” Joseph Kony was a central figure in the conflict in Northern Uganda. His spiritual authority and leadership of the LRA were quintessential for its campaign of mass violence. Often, he is seen as a completely irrational devil, unwilling to come to peace with the government in Kampala, and a betrayer of his own Acholi people. However, some scholars, like Sverker Finnström, remain convinced that the craziness of his movement is overemphasized and he should rather be seen as an effective insurgency leader fighting against Museveni’s authoritarian rule. In this paragraph, the focus will be on understanding Joseph Kony ‘the man’. Although little is known about the man behind the phenomenon, there are some things that are known. Furthermore, much can be inferred from his actions and the way he reacts to threats. By using the data that is available, this paragraph will try to paint a picture of Joseph Kony’s rationality, his motivation, and his personality. §3.2.1 A bunch of lunatics led by a psychopath? Joseph Kony’s rationality Joseph Kony’s Lord’s Resistance Army has often been described as an erratic group of brainwashed psychopaths, ‘rebels without a cause’, who have no clearly articulated political goals except for the overthrow of the Museveni government and the rule of Uganda according to the biblical Ten Commandments.150 By extension, Joseph Kony is seen as a lunatic, a ‘psychopath’, devoid of any mental capacity and concerned about nothing but his own survival.151 However, although the crimes committed by Kony – such as the large-scale use of child soldiers and the massacre and mutilation of thousands of the people he supposedly fights for – do indeed seem to defy comprehension, it is important to understand that the characterization of the LRA – and by extension Joseph Kony – as fundamentally irrational has important implications, both in discourse and in politics. Finnström points to the fact that Western media accounts of the conflict overemphasize its irrational aspects, using the spectacular and bizarre elements of the conflict to construe a “hell of colonial imagination”, structuring it as just another round of incomprehensible primordial African violence.152 As such, the emphasis on the craziness of one man, makes it easier for the media to preclude any efforts necessary for a deeper understanding of the war’s deeper causes.153 Moreover, it has been argued that the Ugandan government has deliberately misconstrued the conflict as a fundamentally irrational endeavor of one unstable individual, who does not have any serious political agenda, in order to marginalize the north and ignore any efforts that aim Finnström, ‘Another story’, 75. Green, The Wizard of the Nile, 19. Payam Akhavan quotes comments on an article by BBC journalist Will Ross: “[Kony’s] refusal for years to accept olive branches and huge concessions including total amnesty (which has been on the table at least since the Carter Centre’s efforts in 2000) indicate his mental incapacity.” See: Akhavan, ‘First State Referral’, 419. Another observer adds that Kony “has created an aura for himself and his organization of deliberate irrationality and obscurantism”. Quoted in: Finnström, ‘Another story’, 81. 152 Finnström, ‘Another story’, 74-75. See also: Branch, ‘The Politics of ICC Intervention’, 182. 153 Green, The Wizard of the Nile, 312. Finnström criticizes Green as one of the authors who too explicitly link their journeys through Africa with the adventures of colonists like Henry Morton Stanley. See: Finnström, ‘Another Story’, 74. See also: Mwenda, ‘Uganda’s politics of foreign aid’, 50-51. 150 151 122 to end the violence with serious structural political, economic, or social change which would redress the Acholi claims of discrimination.154 The LRA has been engaged in politics, however. It has published various manifestos with political grievances and has not been above using the ballot box to achieve its aims – it declared a ceasefire during the 1996 Ugandan elections, for example.155 Still, it is hard to find any rationality in the acts of Joseph Kony: forcing abducted children to kill their parents, to cut off lips and amputate limbs of civilians, would not pose as particularly ‘rational’ in any sane man’s mind. It is not the intention of this study to construe the acts of Kony as a rational campaign pursuing rational ends. That being said, to portray Kony as being unable to make any sorts of rational decision, or to see him as a ‘messianic mad man’156 mentally incapable of doing so, would be a mistake. There are certainly some elements of his pattern of conduct which necessitated rational planning, some actions which are proof of his capacity to engage in a somewhat normal decision making process. Examples of this are outlined below. At the same time, like any other human’s decision making process, it was misdirected by computational difficulties and cognitive fallacies, significantly impacted by his individual traits – thoroughly described in §3.2.3, which describes Kony’s personality – and circumscribed by emotions. A first example of Joseph Kony’s capacity to engage in human (bounded/instrumental) rationality, is the use of what is sometimes mentioned as proof of his fundamental irrationality, namely the LRA’s spiritual order. Although stories of his claim to be possessed by spirits might make him sound insane, it has already been noted above that the use of this spiritual order has various rational advantages. It regulates the internal and external behavior of the LRA fighters – serving as a guide for both their own conduct and their relations with the outside world – and serves their need for a legitimizing framework in which to live.157 The fact that many NRA/UPDF soldiers – not necessarily known as particularly irrational – believe in most facets of the LRA’s spiritual order serves to put the LRA’s spiritual order in its wider, East African context.158 Moreover, Kony takes pains to educate ‘his’ children, recruiting teachers to learn them about the bible and about other revolutionaries.159 These organizational efforts have furthermore affected the LRA’s military organization. The rebel group uses a strict military hierarchy: it is organized into brigades – which in 2008 were called Stockree, Gilva, Sinia, Trinkle, and Finnström, ‘Another story’, 75. Government officials as well as NGO’s have gone so far as to deny the existence of LRA political manifestos, even though the wider public was certainly aware of them. Some Acholi who were suspected of having copies have been imprisoned. Ibid., 84-86. 155 Allen, Trial Justice, 43-44, 50; Green, The Wizard of the Nile, 56. 156 This term is used by Matthew Green, as part of the subtext of his front cover. The full subtext of his book title is: “A bloody conflict, a messianic madman, an army of child soldiers”. 157 Titeca, ‘Spiritual Order’, 62-71. 158 Ronald Iya, ‘Encountering Kony: a Madi perspective’, in: Tim Allen and Koen Vlassenroot, The Lord’s Resistance Army: Myth and Reality (London: Zed Books, 2010) 177-184, 183. In his autobiography, Museveni has tried hard to fashion the fight against the LRA as a battle between his ‘modern’, ‘rational’ army and the ‘primitive’, ‘irrational’ rebels, who used “mysticism instead of science”. See: Yoweri K. Museveni, Sowing the Mustard Seed: The struggle from freedom and democracy in Uganda (London: Macmillan, 1997) 115, 116, 173. 159 Green, The Wizard of the Nile, 186. 154 123 Control Altar – and uses military ranks – such as Brigade General and Lieutenant – to indicate the fighters’ standing.160 Second, to describe Kony’s insurgency as wholly indiscriminate would not correspond with reality. The use of child soldiers seems a beneficial strategic choice which has caused their large-scale use throughout Africa and other parts of the world – Museveni’s NRA, for example, also used child soldiers in its rebel years. The central reason for this is that they are a tabula rasa which can easily be filled with the teachings of their new leaders and they are more conducive to military discipline.161 This (‘relative’) rationality in target selection can also be seen in Kony’s violence against civilians. As horrifying as it usually was, it always had a rationale – massacres were often retaliatory, mutilations were mostly against (suspected) government collaborators.162 Or, as Kony said: “If you lie about us we will cut your lips off, if you run from us we will cut your legs off.”163 As was discussed above, UPDF soldiers were equally engaged in retaliatory massacres and abuses of civilians. The point here is that although the violence was exceptionally brutal, and the spiritual order seemingly spectacular, when put in context, they are not exceptional in and of themselves. A factor which seems to have been important in Kony’s criminal decision making process, is the presence of computational difficulties in conjunction with cognitive biases. Kony has spent the last 25 years living in the bush, usually in remote areas without access to modern ICT- and/or telecommunications facilities. The bits of information Kony did receive were only pieces to a puzzle of which Kony was unable to get the full picture. This was also applicable to the information he received about the ICC. Although he was aware of the fact that men in The Hague were now after him, he was not fully informed about the exact processes and workings of the Court, at one point identifying Museveni as the prime director of the ICC.164 The lack of information made the effects of cognitive biases more severe, as the information pool from which he selected the pieces used for his decision making process would have been smaller and less reliable. Moreover, loss aversion – the overrating of the significance of a loss – has some explanatory power here. The cost of losing the power he had acquired – his social standing in the group, but also the control over an organization that he had built up over decades – would have loomed relatively large to any small benefits gained by accepting amnesty or any other negotiated settlement which would not leave him with some significant power. Thus, Control Altar is seen as the group’s leadership brigade. The names of the brigades come from: Green, The Wizard of the Nile, 142. It is unclear if the LRA still uses five distinct battalions. This can be more or less, depending on the numbers of fighters and the geographic spread of the rebel group. 161 See for example: Peter Eichstaedt First kill your family – Child soldiers of Uganda and the Lord’s Resistance Army (Chicago: Lawrence Hill Books, 2009); Alcinda Honwana, Child Soldiers in Africa (Philadelphia: University Press of Pennsylvania, 2011); Oloya, Child to Soldier; Pham et al., ‘Forced Conscription in Northern Uganda’. 162 Allen, Trial Justice, 42. 163 Finnström, ‘Another story’, 90. Photo subscript. 164 Iya, ‘A Madi perspective’, 181; Mareike Schomerus, ‘‘A terrorist person is not a person like me’: an interview with Joseph Kony’, in: Tim Allen and Koen Vlassenroot, The Lord’s Resistance Army: Myth and Reality (London: Zed Books, 2010) 113-131, 127. See also: Green, The Wizard of the Nile, 234-235. 160 124 Kony’s refusal to give in to the ICC’s legal sanctioning threat can be explained to some extent by looking at his limited information pool and the effect of cognitive biases.165 Kony’s unreliable affective mood was sometimes responsible for circumscribing his decision making process. Kony could become angry very quickly, which often resulted in the use of extreme violence against the targets of his rage, which usually were civilians. When, in 1991, some Acholi created the so-called Arrow Groups, Kony felt betrayed, and lashed out increasingly at civilians. Similarly, as the 1994 peace talks broke down, he called Betty Bigombe in anger, and vowed to “shock the world”. Although the 2002-2005 Iron Fist operations significantly weakened the LRA’s military capacities, they above all enraged Kony, prompting him to order his fighters to re-enter Northern Uganda and retaliate against the civilian population.166 This is why Father Carlos of the Acholi Religious Leaders Peace Initiative stated: He may be laughing with you and very cordial, saying that he really wants peace, but the next minute he’s very angry and shouting and making threats and saying he’s going to give orders to kill everybody.167 Kony’s emotional states thus seems to have impacted his criminal decision making process, causing him to lash out with atrocities when he felt betrayed or was angry. These severe emotional states made acquiescing to the demands of an International Criminal Court harder to consider. In conclusion The irrational elements of Kony’s insurgency, a central element in the discourse about the conflict in Northern Uganda, have probably been overemphasized. There are certainly aspects to his activities that betray some amount of rationality, examples of which are the military and spiritual organization of his rebel group and the selection of targets. Yet, 25 years in the bush have certainly limited Kony’s information pool, exacerbating the effects of cognitive biases.168 This does not necessarily suggest that a ‘fully rational person’ would have given in to the ICC’s demands. For all of these examples, see above, §3.1. 167 Green, The Wizard of the Nile, 19. 168 But even when a rational cost-benefit analysis would be applied to Kony’s persistence of violence after having been indicted by the ICC, the continuation of violence should not be surprising. The refusal to withdraw the arrest warrants meant that Kony’s only viable nonviolent exit strategy had been closed off. Thus, there was no way back from the path of violence. See, for example, Adam Branch, ‘International justice, local injustice: the International Criminal Court in northern Uganda’, Dissent 51:3 (2004) 22-29, 23. 165 166 125 §3.2.2 Mony me ngom and mony me polo: Kony’s motivation What motivated Joseph Kony during his murderous campaign in East Africa? What did he try to achieve and with what purpose? As was noted in the previous section, it is often said that the LRA does not have any political agenda, apart from replacing Museveni’s government by one based on the Ten Commandments. Also, it was noted that the denial of the existence of an LRA political agenda has its own political uses, which leads to a misconstruction of reality. In this section Kony’s motivation is studied more closely. It is assumed here, that Kony’s insurgency campaign has both rational, ‘earthly’ aspects, and – at least in Western eyes – irrational, or ‘spiritual’ aspects. This simultaneous existence of both secular and religious aspects in Kony’s campaign, is reflected in the Acholi perspective, which looks at the LRA as both an ‘earthly army’ (mony me ngom) and a ‘heavenly army’ (mony me polo). This section therefore studies Kony’s motivation by using parts of Finnström’s framework, which sees “the ‘earthly’ and ‘heavenly’ aspects of the insurgency campaign as parallel intertwined aspects of the same fragmented war reality”, which differ in salience depending on the time period and the situation.169 Kony’s spirituality played a key role in his motivation. One of the most often cited examples of Kony’s spiritual motivation is his stated desire to rule Uganda according to the Ten Commandments. Moreover, it has been reported that he teaches abducted children from the Bible and has justified his killing campaigns by citing biblical messages from which it would follow that “God is a killer”.170 This has led some to typify Kony as a Christian fundamentalist. However, Kony’s spiritual world merges traditional Acholi – and wider East-African – beliefs with Christian and Islamic motifs. His claims to be communicating with the spirit world – in his capacity as an ajwaki – are consistent with longer-held Acholi spirituality, while he has expressed his Islamic inspiration by fasting on Fridays or threatening pig farmers with death.171 As such, to see Kony as being mainly motivated by a fundamentalist version of Christianity would definitely be incorrect – he even explicitly denied being one in one of the rare interviews with him: “[W]e are [not] fundamental as Museveni said”.172 It has already been described above how the spiritual order of the LRA serves to regulate the internal and external behavior of its members. It would therefore be more concise to describe Kony’s spiritual world as an eclectic mix of regional belief systems which have fused into an ideology legitimizing the opposition against the government in Kampala, casting it as a fight against the ‘impure’.173 When Kony suspected the civilian population of collaborating with this impure government, they became part of this ‘impure’ out-group as well, which made atrocities against civilians a regular and – in Kony’s eyes – perfectly justifiable act. Although Kony has cast his insurgency as a spiritual struggle to rid the world of impurity, he also often emphasized his secular demands. It is hard to imagine that Kony’s representatives would be able to seriously negotiate with the Ugandan government at the Juba peace talks for two years and come Finnström, ‘Another story’, 77. Green, The Wizard of the Nile, 133. 171 According to mainstream Islamic belief, pigs are haram (impure). 172 Schomerus, ‘Interview with Joseph Kony’, 123. 173 Titeca, ‘The spiritual order’, 66. 169 170 126 very close to a negotiated end to the insurgency, if they were only informed by spiritual motivations such as the introduction of the Ten Commandments as a guiding document of the Ugandan government.174 Kony’s demands focus on an end to the perceived discrimination of Northern Uganda by the south – a feeling prevalent amongst many northerners – and Museveni’s authoritarian leadership style.175 In some of the LRA pamphlets, it has been stated that the development of Uganda has excluded Northern Uganda both economically and politically and that the Kampala government has systematically violated the human rights of its inhabitants. Museveni’s authoritarianism – expressed in such events as the intimidation of opposition politicians and the arrest and trial of Museveni’s opponent Kizza Besigye on allegations of conspiring with the LRA176 - has led the LRA to call for new multiparty elections (the fact that the LRA itself has long ignored such notions as democracy and respect for human rights is conveniently forgotten).177 The observation that Kony in fact has articulated a political agenda leads to the question of why he and the other rebel commanders have not accepted the amnesty offer resulting from the 2000 Amnesty Law, nor concluded peace in the various peace talks with the Ugandan government between 1988 and 2008. It is indeed striking that Kony has not accepted the amnesty, not even in the LRA’s weakest moments. Rather, he threatened his fighters with severe punishment if they would accept the amnesty. So why is Kony so hostile to the 2000 Amnesty Law? Answering this question can give us some insight into Kony’s central motivations and to some extent into his values. Various answers have been suggested. Some have argued that Kony’s hostility shows his lack of willingness to achieve peace, sometimes even calling him mentally incapable because of the fact that he refused to accept so many peace offerings.178 One could also point to the lowering of Kony’s social status which would occur if Kony accepted the amnesty. Having spent decades in the bush amongst an army of fighters who worship him like a god, it is highly unlikely that he would see a normal life as just another Acholi as a positive alternative. A third reason for the refusal to accept amnesty might be his distrust of the government. In the not so distant history, the high-ranking rebel Mike Kilama, who – along with other rebel commanders – accepted a government amnesty offer, had subsequently died in unclear circumstances. For Kony, this remained a sensitive issue and he might have been afraid that he might end up in the same way. 179 It seems that during the Juba peace talks, the government’s ambiguity about the status of the ICC arrest warrants fed into this distrust. With the ICC often making clear that they would not respect an amnesty 174 However, Joanna R. Quinn, questions the representativeness of those who were negotiating on behalf of the LRA. This group of people, calling themselves the Lord’s Resistance Movement (LRM), consisted mostly of members of the Acholi diaspora instead of fighters from the bush. She doubts the group’s claim to have been negotiating on behalf of the LRA and to have been in frequent contact with the rebel group. See: Quinn, ‘Negotiating with the LRA’, 60. 175 Allen, Trial Justice, 43; Finnström, ‘Another story’, 82; Green, The Wizard of the Nile, 130-138, 300; Ssenyonjo, ‘Persecution or Amnesty?’, 362. 176 Mwenda, ‘Uganda’s politics of foreign aid’, 53-54. 177 Finnström, ‘Another story’, 81-82 178 Akhavan, ‘First State Referral’, 419. 179 Finnström, ‘Another story’, 79. 127 for ‘those most responsible’, Kony might have felt that accepting the peace process would have been tantamount to a surrender to the ICC. The final reason for Kony’s hostility towards the amnesty is linked to the distrust of the government and has to do with his denial of having done anything wrong. As was noted earlier, accepting the amnesty was linked to the process of mato oput, of which confession of guilt is a vital element. Therefore, accepting an amnesty would be synonymous with accepting guilt and being absolved of your crimes by the government. The problem here, then, was that Kony did not feel like he had done anything wrong. In his eyes, he and his LRA had only fought for the improvement of the fate of the Acholi. Thus, Kony felt that accepting an amnesty without any (talks on a) serious political process of transformation, would be commensurate with a capitulation.180 Having answered the question of why Kony did not accept amnesty from various viewpoints, what would be the best way to describe Kony’s values? It follows that one of Kony’s most important values is ensuring his own survival. The risk of betrayal by the government or being handed over to the ICC were important motivations for him to continue his insurgency. This can also explain his campaign of child abduction, since the regular input of fresh recruits was essential for the LRA’s continued operational capabilities. His own survival in this sense prevails over one of his other values, putting an end to the discrimination of the Ugandan north by the Ugandan south, which is one of the most important points of his political agenda. Although Kony does seem to care about the fate of the Acholi, ridding the world of everything impure is even more important. He justified his crimes by pointing to the perceived need to (violently) purify Acholi society. For Kony, the more important categorization was ‘pure’ and ‘impure’, instead of other, more ethnically oriented categorizations such as Lwo-speakers and Bantuspeakers. As such, the spiritual motivation seems to prevail over his political motivations. In this sense, a hierarchy of values emerges, in which his own survival comes first, the spiritual agenda comes second, and the political motivations come last. Another important value for Kony seems to be the acquirement of or the holding on to power. As might be expected, this study finds no evidence of any moral norms which preclude the use of violence (against civilians). The large-scale use of violence against innocent civilians is ‘morally acceptable’ to Kony and his LRA fighters. Moreover, Kony’s intrinsic motivators – his own survival, holding onto power, and the fate of the Acholi – are all at odds with giving into the extrinsic motivation of ICC demands. Since intrinsic motivation is more powerful than extrinsic motivation, this can also, to some extent, explain Kony’s apparent insusceptibility to the ICC’s legal sanction threats. In conclusion This section has tried to answer the question of what motivates Kony in his violent campaign throughout East Africa. It was suggested that Kony’s motivation comes both from spiritual and more earthly notions. While the LRA does indeed pursue a political agenda, Kony’s spiritual worldview, legitimizing 180 Ibid., 83-84. 128 the violence against civilians, seems to prevail. When Kony’s values would have to be described, one might note his need for survival and holding onto power, as well as his political struggle against Museveni’s government. In recent years, however, Kony’s main motivation seems to be the survival of himself and the LRA. Any other option has been closed off. Government forces from Uganda, South Sudan and the DRC, along with American Special Forces and U.N. and A.U. troops have chased him around Central Africa for multiple years now. The political manifestos the LRA once regularly published, are now increasingly rare. Marginalized and chased around, there is little chance that the group will ever be in the position again to issue demands at a negotiation table in Juba – or anywhere else, for that matter. This course of events clearly shows how some values can become more salient when the situation calls for it.181 The always present perceived importance of his own survival has now apparently established itself as the thing he values most. 181 See, for example: E. Tory Higgins, Beyond Pleasure and Pain: How Motivation Works (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011). 129 §3.2.3 “Somehow you believe”: Joseph Kony’s personality It is difficult to describe the personality of someone who is notorious for his opacity. Therefore, instead of pretending to give a definitive analysis of Kony’s personality, this section will describe some of his more remarkable traits, tendencies in his personality make-up which seem to be lasting and consistent. While doing so, it is necessary to distinguish between two very different images of Kony, namely the one he holds of himself and the one that many others hold of him.182 Kony likes to fashion himself as a freedom fighter, someone who fights for the protection of the Acholi people against the tyrannical government of Museveni.183 At the same time, his opponents see him as a dangerously psychotic criminal. People who have interacted with him on a daily basis are unsure of what they should think of him. This leads to one of his apparently consistent personality traits: his unpredictability. The quote from Father Carlos which was alluded to earlier is worth mentioning here. A tribal chief from Congo involved in the Juba peace process adds to this that “he was unpredictable, and could do anything”.184 Although Kony is mostly known for his violent outbursts and murderous sprees in Eastern Africa, one of his over sixty wives, who had escaped from the rebel group, had nothing bad to say about him, further illustrating the multiple faces of Kony’s personality.185 He was often described as a charismatic leader, with one former rebel noting that “Kony has a kind of invisible magic[,] [s]omehow you believe”.186 Another apparently lasting personality trait is his sensibility for betrayal, which usually resulted in the ordering of extremely brutal outbursts of LRA violence. For Kony, betrayal is widely defined. The failed peace talks of 1994 and 2006-2008, and the forming of Acholi self-defense groups as part of the 1991 Operation North, each resulted in large-scale campaigns of massacres, mutilations and abductions. When Vincent Otti, a long-time rebel commander and Kony’s second-in-command, questioned his negotiation policy at Juba, Kony had him executed for betrayal. Moreover, abductees who were captured while they tried to escape the LRA, were usually tortured or murdered for betraying Kony. In Kony’s own world, his cause is the only right one. The sensitivity for betrayal might have something to do with the decades of living in the bush in a reality that he controlled. In this reality, he is the spiritual leader with magical powers, the sole guarantor of Acholi well-being. In his own words, he is “a human being”, who has not committed any crimes. In this reality, he is not the perpetrator, but the victim.187 When he is ripped out of his own version of reality, he responds by viciously striking out at those whom he considers impure. 182 It must be noted that the reality on the ground has shown that these two images are not mutually exclusive. There are supporters of both extreme views, but there are also those who hold a more mixed image of Kony. See also: Green, The Wizard of the Nile, 316. 183 Schomerus, ‘Interview with Kony’, 129-131. 184 Iya, ‘A Madi perspective’, 181. 185 Green, The Wizard of the Nile, 288-289. 186 Ibid., 134. 187 In one of his rare interviews, with Mareike Schomerus, Kony claims that “we don’t kill people”, and that any claims of atrocities committed by the LRA is propaganda by Museveni. He concludes that “I am not a killer. I don’t kill people. I am a human being. I am a person, also.” See: Schomerus, ‘Interview with Joseph Kony’, 116117. 130 Rating Joseph Kony on the Big Five of personality traits is even harder to do than for Slobodan Milosevic. A possible rating could be: low on Extraversion, low on Agreeableness, low on Conscientiousness, low on Emotional Stability and low on Openness to Experience.188 As was expected in the analytical framework, the Dark Triad of personality types (narcissism, Machiavellianism, and (subclinical) psychopathy) also looks like a useful framework to typify Kony’s personality. Kony certainly displays behavioral tendencies that match the definition of subclinical psychopathy as it was laid out in the analytical framework.189 With thousands of victims, he has not once expressed remorse or shown any sign of empathy for his victims. The brainwashing of thousands of abductees, forcing them to commit atrocities and inducing extreme forms of Stockholm syndrome,190 would definitely count as interpersonal exploitation and manipulation. Machiavellianism, however, is not necessarily a strong element of Kony’s personality.191 There is little evidence for elaborate deceptive schemes or the deliberate betrayal of others. At the same time, Kony does come across as a narcissistic person.192 The status he acquired – as the leader of a group of rebels who idolize him –, his supposed magical powers and ability to communicate with the spirit world, have apparently led to an inflated sense of selfimportance and ideas of grandiosity. The fact that Kony seems to mostly live in his own world, and is highly sensitive to what he sees as betrayal, moreover points at am extreme sensitivity to criticism, another element of narcissism. As such, although Kony does not seem particularly characterized by Machiavellianism, he definitely does display traits of (subclinical) psychopathy and narcissism. In conclusion A few traits that seem to be lasting and consistent elements of Kony’s personality are his unpredictability, his charisma, his sensibility to betrayal, and his inability to cope with events that rip him out of his own reality. Still, it is almost impossible to give a definitive description of the personality of a man who is as mysterious as Kony. 188 As was the case with the previous case study, it has to be emphasized that this rating is highly speculative, since it is not based on a clinical observation or any sort of scientifically passable personality evaluation. 189 There, it was defined as a combination of “high impulsivity, callousness, interpersonal manipulation, exploitation, and stimulation-seeking, and by low empathy, anxiety, and remorse”. 190 Oloya, Child to Soldier, 69-74. 191 Machiavellianism is defined by interpersonal exploitation, manipulation, along with the deception and disregard of others. 192 Narcissism is defined as “an excessive sense of self-importance, ideas of grandiosity and an extreme sensitivity to criticism”. 131 §3.3 Joseph Kony and the International Criminal Court When the ICC intervened in Northern Uganda, a new dimension was added to the conflict. While it was hoped it could bring peace, the reception by ordinary Ugandans has been mixed. Kony did not seem to be bothered by the newly created permanent international court. The reasons behind this will be further explored in the sections below. To set the context, this paragraph will start out with a short description of the ICC’s mandate, structure, and its powers and shortcomings. Thereafter, the way in which Kony is held legally responsibility for crimes committed under the jurisdiction of the Court will be described. After this context has been given, the paragraph will move on to analyze the factors that influenced the ICC’s deterrent capability and the way in which this capability impacted Joseph Kony’s decision making process. §3.3.1 The International Criminal Court After the epoch-making international military tribunals of Nuremberg and Tokyo, the hope was expressed by many that a permanent international criminal court could be created by the international community. However, the political deadlock created by the Cold War long prevented the fulfillment of this dream. When the atrocities taking place in the former Yugoslavia and Rwanda gave rise to ad-hoc international criminal tribunals, this paved the way for a new wave of legal optimism. In July 1998, after lengthy negotiations, over a hundred states signed the Rome Statute, which would establish a permanent International Criminal Court.193 On 1 July 2002, after it was ratified by 60 state parties, the Rome Statute entered into force, thus creating the first treaty-based International Criminal Court (ICC) with a permanent jurisdiction.194 As of November 2013 the Rome Statute has been ratified by 122 countries.195 The Court’s mission is to punish those most responsible for “the most serious crimes of concern to the international community as a whole”. The Court has to “end impunity for the perpetrators of [the most serious] crimes and thus […] contribute to the prevention of such crimes”.196 As such, it “appeared to make the old universalist dream of lasting, if not perpetual, peace a reality”.197 193 For the story of the developments leading to the creation of the International Criminal Court, see: Dawn Rothe and Christopher W. Mullins, The International Criminal Court: Symbolic Gestures and the Generation of Global Social Control (Lexington: Lexington Books, 2006) 29-51. 194 Moreno-Ocampo, ‘The Role of the International Community’, 280; Volker Nerlich, ‘The International Criminal Court 2002-2010 – A view from the inside’, Criminal Law Forum 22:1-2 (2011) 199-214, 199. 195 International Criminal Court, ‘How Many Countries Have Ratified the Rome Statute?’, available online at: www.icc-cpi.int/en_menus/icc/about%20the%20court/frequently%20asked%20questions/Pages/4.aspx (2 December 2013). 196 International Criminal Court, Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court, (17 July 1998), available online at: www.icc-cpi.int/NR/rdonlyres/ADD16852-AEE9-4757-ABE79CDC7CF02886/283503/RomeStatutEng1.pdf (2 December 2013). The other Articles referred to in this piece can be found in the same document. 197 Mireille Delmas-Marty, ‘Ambiguities and Lacunae: The International Criminal Court Ten Years on’, Journal of International Criminal Justice 9:3 (2013) 553-561, 553. 132 The ICC is structured in a similar way as the ICTY. It has four different organs: the Presidency, the Office of the Prosecutor, the Registry, and separate judicial chambers.198 The Presidency is responsible for the administrative functions of the Court, and consists of three judges elected by their fellow judges for terms of three years. The current Presidency consists of the Justices Sang-Hyun Song, Sanji Mmasenono Monageng, and Cuno Tarfusser.199 The Office of the Prosecutor is an organ largely independent of the rest of the Court and is occupied with the investigation and prosecution of the cases referred to the jurisdiction of the ICC. After ten years of work, Chief Prosecutor Luis Moreno-Ocampo has recently handed over his function to Fatou Bensouda, who has filled the function since 15 June 2012 and will maintain it for a term of nine years.200 The Registry is responsible for the administrative and non-judicial functions of the ICC. As such, it conducts the Court’s Outreach work and houses elements occupied with activities aimed at the redress of victims, such as the ICC Victims Trust Fund.201 Although the non-judicial activities of the Court have struggled with funding problems,202 the important place that victims hold in the ICC’s Rome Statute is one of the novel contributions the Court brings to international criminal law.203 The separate judicial chambers include Pre-Trial, Trial, and Appeals Divisions. The Pre-Trial Chamber hears issues that are relevant to pre-judicial case processing, while the Trial and Appeals Divisions conduct the trials themselves. At the same time, the ICC is distinctly different from the ICTY in political terms. The ICC is an independent judicial body, unrelated to any other international organization. Its mandate comes from the Rome Statute, a treaty ratified by states themselves, unlike the ICTY, which was functioning with a mandate from the U.N. Security Council. An Assembly of States Parties conducts oversight and management, and is furthermore responsible for the Court’s financing. The description of the structure of the ICC largely follows: Christopher W. Mullins, ‘The International Criminal Court’, in: M. Cherif Bassiouni, The Pursuit of International Criminal Justice: A World Study on Conflicts, Victimization, and Post-Conflict Justice. Volume 1 (Antwerp: Intersentia, 2010) 399-421, 400-402. 199 International Criminal Court, ‘The Presidency’, available online at: http://www.icccpi.int/en_menus/icc/structure%20of%20the%20court/presidency/Pages/the%20presidency.aspx (2 December 2013). 200 International Criminal Court, ‘Office of the Prosecutor’, available online at: http://www.icccpi.int/en_menus/icc/structure%20of%20the%20court/office%20of%20the%20prosecutor/Pages/office%20of%2 0the%20prosecutor.aspx (2 December 2013). 201 See, inter alia: Janine Natalya Clark, ‘International War Crimes Tribunals and the Challenge of Outreach’, International Criminal Law Review 9:1 (2009) 99-116,112-115; Mariana Goetz, ‘The International Criminal Court and its Relevance to Affected Communities’, in: Nicholas Waddell and Phil Clark, Courting Conflict? Justice, Peace and the ICC in Africa (London: Royal African Society, 2008) 65-72, 65-71; Roach, ‘Multilayered Justice’, 260-264. 202 Goetz, ‘Relevance to Affected Communities’, 67; Jonathan O’Donohue, ‘Financing the International Criminal Court’, International Criminal Law Review 13:1 (2013) 269-296, 283; David Taylor, ‘Beyond the Courtroom: The objectives and experience of international trials at the grassroots’, Paper Presented at “Facing the Past: International Conference on the Effectiveness of Remedies for Grave Historical Injustices,” sponsored by the University of Utrecht, Hotel Karel V, Utrecht, the Netherlands, (27-28 May 2010) 15. 203 Marc Henzelin, Veijo Heiskanen, and Guénaël Mettraux, ‘Reparations to Victims before the International Criminal Court: Lessons from International Mass Claims Processes’, Criminal Law Forum 17:3 (2006) 317-344, 317-318. The relevant articles for victim participation and reparation in the Rome Statute are Articles 68, 75, and 79. 198 133 As set out in Article 5 of the Rome Statute, the Court has jurisdiction over a core set of international crimes, namely genocide, crimes against humanity, and war crimes. Also, it will be mandated to prosecute crimes of aggression, although at the time a definition of this crime has not yet been agreed upon.204 The jurisdiction of the Court, however, is limited in three important ways. First, according to Article 11 of the Rome Statute, it has jurisdiction only over crimes committed after the Statute entered into force, thus limiting its temporal jurisdiction to crimes committed after 1 July 2002. As will be discussed further below, this limitation has led to some problems in the Ugandan case. Second, the ICC’s jurisdiction is restricted in its geographical scope. Since the ICC is a treaty-based judicial mechanism, it only has jurisdiction over crimes committed in the territory of a state party. As such, it has nothing to say over countries that have not ratified the Rome Statute.205 This leaves some of the most powerful states in the world – amongst others the United States, China, India, and Russia – immune to any international legal repercussions for its actions.206 Third, the Court is restricted by the principle of complementarity. The Rome Statute does not lift the responsibility of national judiciaries to investigate and prosecute those most responsible for serious crimes.207 Nor does the ICC have the power to override national investigations like the ICTY could.208 As Article 17(1)(a) states, a case is inadmissible when it “is being investigated or prosecuted by a State which has jurisdiction over it”. Only when a domestic judiciary is genuinely unwilling or unable to carry out investigations or prosecutions, can the ICC’s jurisdiction be activated. As such, the Court is meant as a ‘court of last resort’.209 The exact workings of this system of complementarity, as regulated by Article 17, is hotly debated, especially with regards to the practice of self-referrals. This debate will be further explored when discussing the ICC’s legitimacy, in §3.3.5. There are various ‘triggering mechanisms’ that can activate the Court’s jurisdiction. The first and so far most often used is a self-referral by a state party. Under Article 14 (1), a “State Party may refer to the Prosecutor a situation in which one or more crimes within the jurisdiction of the Court appear to have been committed”. A self-referral leads to an investigation by the Office of the Prosecutor, in which it decides whether or not it is feasible to prosecute those responsible, based on the complementarity principle and the gravity of the crimes. Once the Prosecutor has decided that the case is indeed feasible, it has to bring it before a Pre-Trial Chamber, which makes the final decision regarding the admissibility of the case. If the Pre-Trial Chamber gives the go-ahead, the Prosecutor can continue its investigations and start issuing arrest warrants. It is important here to note that a self-referral brings 204 The state parties decided during a meeting in Kampala in 2010 to have a workable definition enter into force in 2017. See: Delmas-Marty, ‘Ambiguities and Lacunae’, 555-558. 205 This is lined out in Article 12. However, under Article 13 (b), the U.N. Security Council can refer situations to the Court’s jurisdiction under Chapter VII of the Charter of the United Nations. This is what happened in the cases of Sudan and Libya. 206 Darren Hawkins, ‘Power and Interest at the International Criminal Court’, SAIS Review 28:2 (2008) 107-119, 113-114. 207 Kastner, The ICC between Law and Politics, 57. 208 Clark, ‘Peace, Justice and the International Criminal Court’, 537. 209 Article 17 of the Rome Statute. See also: Akhavan, ‘The Rise, and Fall, and Rise’, 531. 134 a situation under the jurisdiction of the Court (as opposed to a single person or entity). By accepting self-referrals, the Court has opened investigations in Uganda, the DRC, the Central African Republic, Côte d’Ivoire, and Mali. The second way in which a case can be referred to the ICC is by way of the U.N. Security Council. Article 13 (b) authorizes the Security Council to issue a Chapter VII Resolution in which it refers a situation, usually in the territory of a non-state party, to the jurisdiction of the Court. Article 13 (b) has been utilized in March 2005 for the situation in Darfur, Sudan, and in February 2011 for the situation in Libya. The third, and final way the ICC can obtain jurisdiction over international crimes, is by using the proprio motu powers of the Prosecutor. Article 15 (1) gives the Office of the Prosecutor the power to open investigations on its own behalf, although in this context the approval of a Pre-Trial chamber is explicitly required. If the Pre-Trial chamber can be convinced that the state in question is either unwilling or unable to conduct domestic prosecutions, and the crimes are grave enough, the Prosecutor can obtain the permission to open its own investigations. 210 The Prosecutor’s proprio motu powers were used for the first time in its investigation into the situation in Kenya. 211 At the moment, the Office of the Prosecutor is also conducting preliminary investigations into alleged crimes committed in Honduras, Afghanistan, Korea, and Comoros, as well as Georgia, Guinea, Colombia, and Nigeria.212 All of these cases have made the years 2012-2013 the busiest years yet for the Court.213 In the selection of persons to be indicted for crimes under the ICC’s jurisdiction, the Office of the Prosecutor has so far chosen for a mixed prosecutorial strategy, in which it has targeted both highranking government officials – including some (former) heads of state – and rebel commanders, leading to a total of 25 arrest warrants.214 In the first ten years of investigating situations and prosecuting individuals, the ICC has been running into some problems, many of which are endemic to its design, while others are the result of unhappy choices made by the ICC itself. The first major problem the ICC is facing today, is securing the apprehension of its suspects. Because the ICC does not have its own police force, it lacks the enforcement capabilities necessary to fulfill its mandate.215 At the moment, 15 out of 25 suspects, including Joseph Kony, remain at large.216 Unlike the ICTY, the ICC is not mandated 210 An analysis of the proprio motu powers of the Prosecutor, and why they have not yet been used very often, can be found in: Kastner, The ICC between Law and Politics, 117-153. 211 Dov Jacobs, ‘The ICC authorizes first use of OTP proprio motu powers in Kenya: Opening a new Pandora’s Box of legal difficulties (and revisiting some old ones too…)’, The Netherlands School of Human Rights Research, (7 April 2010), available online at: http://invisiblecollege.weblog.leidenuniv.nl/2010/04/07/the-iccauthorizes-first-use-of-otp-prop/ (2 December 2013). 212 International Criminal Court, ‘Office of the Prosecutor’. 213 International Criminal Court, ‘ICC report to UN details busiest year yet, urges Security Council support’, (8 October 2013), available online at: http://www.icccpi.int/en_menus/icc/press%20and%20media/press%20releases/Pages/pr951.aspx (2 December 2013). 214 James Meernik, ‘Justice, Power and Peace: Conflicting Interests and the Apprehension of ICC Suspects’, International Criminal Law Review 13:1 (2013) 169-190, 190. For an overview, see: International Criminal Court, ‘All Cases’, available online at: www.icccpi.int/en_menus/icc/situations%20and%20cases/cases/Pages/cases%20index.aspx (2 December 2013). 215 Meernik, ‘Apprehension of ICC Suspects’, 169. 216 International Criminal Court, ‘All Cases’. 135 by the Security Council, and thus lacks a “supranational enforcement capacity to command state compliance”.217 The ICC is wholly dependent on the cooperation of states for assistance in the judicial process, including the arrest of suspects, the collection of evidence, the questioning of witnesses and non-judicial activities like outreach and victims’ assistance.218 To ensure this assistance, the ICC has often entered into cooperative relationships with governments of the states in which it is conducting investigations. This is also why the first Chief Prosecutor actively promoted self-referrals.219 Although such a cooperative relationship definitely seems preferable to an adversarial relationship – an example of which is the ICC’s relationship with the government of Sudan, which has actively challenged the Court and prevented any ICC staff from entering its territory220 -, it has its own downsides, which are mostly related to the risk of instrumentalization and perceived partiality. Some actions taken by the former Chief Prosecutor have further fuelled these allegations.221 Many of these problems can be seen in Uganda, as will be discussed in §3.3.5. The problems outlined above are mostly endemic to the ICC’s design, or as Volkert Nerlich calls it, an “in-built weakness”.222 In many ways, the Rome Statute is a compromise between two different ideals. On the one hand, it is a symptom of the drive for a transformation of world politics, a call for the ending of the ‘culture of impunity’, which had prevailed for so long after the transformative Nuremberg and Tokyo trials that followed the Second World War.223 On the other hand, the Rome Statute forces the Court to function in a political environment that is still very much dominated by the Realpolitik characteristic of the Westphalian state system.224 As such, the ICC and the Rome Statute are the children of a clash between what Delmas-Marty calls the ‘universalist model’ and the ‘sovereign model’.225 Any aspirations to a utopia of worldwide justice for everyone, will always be checked by the self-interested actors in the international state system. Or, as M. Cherif Bassiouni has argued: “The principal obstacles to the effectiveness of the ICC will always be Realpolitik and states’ interests.”226 Thus, the environment of global politics forces the ICC, despite its apparent reluctance to deviate from its legal underpinnings, to engage in political processes and make decisions that have a political impact. Kenneth A. Rodman, ‘Pacting the Law within Politics. Lessons from the International Criminal Court’s First Investigations’, Paper Presented at “Facing the Past: International Conference on the Effectiveness of Remedies for Grave Historical Injustices,” sponsored by the University of Utrecht, Hotel Karel V, Utrecht, the Netherlands, (27-28 May 2010) 2 See also: Clark, ‘Peace, Justice and the International Criminal Court’, 527. 218 Ibid., 529. 219 Claus Kress, ‘‘Self-Referrals’ and ‘Waivers of Complementarity’: Some Considerations in Law and Policy’, Journal of International Criminal Justice 2:4 (2004) 944-948, 944-945. 220 Angelo Izama, ‘Accomplice to Impunity? Rethinking the Political Strategy of the International Criminal Court in Central Africa’, SAIS Review 29:2 (2009) 51-60, 51-52; Lydia A. Nkansah, ‘International Criminal Justice in Africa: Some Emerging Dynamics’, Journal of Politics and Law 4:2 (2011) 74-84, 77-78. 221 Clark, ‘Peace, Justice and the International Criminal Court’, 524. 222 Nerlich, ‘A View from the Inside’, 214. 223 Michael Struett, ‘The Meaning of the International Criminal Court’, Peace Review 16:3 (2004) 317-321, 319. 224 Rodman, ‘Pacting the Law’, 2. 225 Delmas-Marty, ‘Ambiguities and Lacunae’, 554. 226 M.Cherif Bassiouni, ‘The ICC – Quo vadis?’, Journal of International Criminal Justice 4:3 (2006) 421-427, 426. 217 136 In conclusion The ICC was established as a result of the legal optimism that flourished after the creation of the ICTY and the ICTR. The founding Rome Statute has been ratified by over a hundred countries and the Court – structured into a Presidency, Office of the Prosecutor, judicial chambers, and Registry – has experienced all three triggering mechanisms: it has accepted self-referrals, referrals by the Security Council, and used the Prosecutor’s proprio motu powers. While investigating cases and prosecuting alleged war criminals, the Court has run into problems – inter alia the apprehension of suspects, state dependency, and perceived partiality – that are mostly endemic to its design. Despite these persisting problems, the ICC has made some important progress in recent years. It has both convicted and acquitted its first suspect, produced a large number of arrest warrants, and has had some successes in securing the arrest of other indictees. Moreover, the two Security Council referrals appear to signal increasing support for the ICC amongst the Council’s five permanent members. 137 §3.3.2 Kony’s legal responsibility for crimes committed in Northern Uganda On 16 December 2003, Uganda used Articles 13(a) and 14 of the Rome Statute to refer the ‘situation regarding the Lord’s Resistance Army’ to the Prosecutor of the International Criminal Court, thus granting to the Court jurisdiction over crimes committed (in principle) by both parties in the conflict.227 After making the acceptance of the referral known on a press conference in London on 29 January 2004, the Prosecutor notified states parties on 21 June that sufficient evidence existed to proceed with an investigation.228 This investigation resulted in the issuing of arrest warrants against five LRA commanders, namely Joseph Kony, Vincent Otti, Okot Odhiambo, Dominic Ongwen, and Raska Lukwiya, which were made public on 13 October 2005.229 After reports came in that Raska Lukwiya had been killed in fights with government forces on 12 August 2006, the Pre-Trial Chamber terminated the outstanding arrest warrant on 11 July 2007.230 Although many observers have reported the death of Vincent Otti in November 2007, as of November 2013 the warrant against him remains outstanding.231 In this section, the focus will be on the warrant against Joseph Kony and the way in which his legal responsibility is construed. In the arrest warrant, Joseph Kony is accused of individual criminal responsibility232 for twelve counts of crimes against humanity – including murder, enslavement, sexual enslavement, rape, and inhumane acts of inflicting serious bodily injury and suffering. 233 Also he is held responsible for twenty-one counts of war crimes – including murder, cruel treatment of civilians, intentionally directing an attack against a civilian population, pillaging, inducing rape, and forced enlistment of children.234 Together with the other LRA commanders indicted by the ICC, Joseph Kony is accused of “more than 2.200 killings and 3.200 abductions in over 820 attacks”.235 Kony’s individual criminal responsibility is more direct and more easily constructed than in the case against Slobodan Milosevic. Its apparent simplicity made the case against the LRA seem like a promising first for the ICC.236 Although Kony has often denied committing any crimes, 237 it seemed clear to everyone that crimes had indeed been committed by the LRA, and that Joseph Kony was Akhavan, ‘First State Referral’, 403; Ssenyonjo, ‘Prosecution or Amnesty?’, 365. Allen, Trial Justice, 82, 85. 229 Ibid., 182-185; Clark, ‘Re-Framing the Debate’, 141. 230 Ssenyonjo, ‘Prosecution or Amnesty?’, 366. 231 See: International Criminal Court, The Prosecutor v. Joseph Kony, Vincent Otti, Okot Odhiambo and Dominic Ongwen, Case No. ICC-02/04-01/05, available online at: http://www.icccpi.int/en_menus/icc/situations%20and%20cases/situations/situation%20icc%200204/related%20cases/icc%200 204%200105/Pages/uganda.aspx (2 December 2013). 232 Individual criminal responsibility is defined in Article 25 of the Rome Statute and is used in a similar way as in the indictment against Slobodan Milosevic. For more on this, see §2.3.2. 233 These are punishable under Article 7(1)(a), Article 7(1)(c), Article 7(1)(g), and Article 7(1)(k) of the Rome Statute. 234 These are punishable under Article 8(2)(c)(i), Article 8(2)(e)(i), Article 8(2)(e)(v), Article 8(2)(e)(vi), and Article 8(2)(e)(vii) of the Rome Statute. 235 Quinn, ‘Negotiating with the LRA’, 65. 236 Akhavan, ‘First State Referral’, 403-405. 237 He has either denied that killing civilians is a crime – according to him, killing impure people is not a crime –, or has denied committing any crimes at all – claiming that any accusations are propaganda by Museveni. See: Schomerus, ‘Interview with Joseph Kony’, 116-117. 227 228 138 individually responsible for them.238 As the leader of a rebel group implicated in the most horrendous of crimes – massacres, mutilations, and the enlistment of children to commit atrocities – it is hardly possible to disagree with the prosecution of Joseph Kony. Moreover, the crimes perpetrated by the LRA seem to be part of a widespread, systematic campaign, further justifying holding Joseph Kony individually responsible as the group’s leader.239 Although Joseph Kony has been implicated in crimes committed as far back as 1988, the ICC in principle has jurisdiction only over crimes committed after 1 September 2002, the date the Rome Statute entered into force for Uganda. However, because Uganda submitted a declaration under Articles 11(2) and 12(3) of the Rome Statute, the Court’s jurisdiction is extended to 1 July 2002, the day the Rome Statute entered into force.240 This still leaves out some of the worst massacres the LRA conducted, including the one in Atiak described earlier. Some observers have argued that the prosecution of Joseph Kony before the ICC, with its limited temporal jurisdiction, runs the risk of ignoring the victims of these crimes.241 At the same time, the temporal jurisdiction still includes enough crimes to put the LRA commanders away for a long time, as the large amount of accusations in the ICC’s arrest warrants illustrates.242 The atrocities for which Joseph Kony is allegedly responsible fall for the largest part within the geographical scope of the ICC’s jurisdiction. Joseph Kony is a Ugandan national who committed crimes mostly in Uganda, the DRC, and the Central African Republic, all states parties to the ICC. Some discussion exists as to the applicability of the ICC’s jurisdiction for crimes committed by the LRA in south Sudan during the LRA’s stay there. Sudan is not a state party and therefore the ICC does not have jurisdiction there. Although the U.N. Security Council has referred the situation in Darfur to the ICC, thus giving the ICC jurisdiction over crimes committed in parts of Sudan, this referral only extends to the situation in Darfur, leaving out south Sudan. In conclusion It is clear that Joseph Kony can be prosecuted for individual criminal responsibility for serious international crimes. Although the limited temporal and geographical jurisdiction of the ICC causes some problems – especially with regards to the redress of victims – the ICC should have no problem to put Kony away for a long time. Branch, ‘Local Injustice’, 23. Ssenyonjo, ‘Prosecution or Amnesty?’, 362-363. 240 Akhavan, ‘First State Referral’, 412. 241 Clark, ‘Peace, Justice and the International Criminal Court’, 525; Goetz, ‘Relevance to Affected Communities’, 69. 242 Branch, ‘The Politics of ICC Intervention’, 180. 238 239 139 §3.3.3 Factors influencing the deterrence capability of the ICC The International Criminal Court has as its explicit mandate, that it should prevent the most serious crimes of concern to the international community by punishing those most responsible for them.243 By posing a serious threat of prosecution to those who consider committing crimes, it was hoped that the deterrent effect of the ICC would be powerful enough to dissuade more crimes from occurring. Accordingly, when the ICC intervened in the situation in Northern Uganda, it claimed that it could help to end the conflict by isolating and neutralizing the LRA’s top commanders. 244 In the analytical framework, it was explained how the deterrent effect of legal sanction threats could best be assessed. In this section, this framework will be applied to scrutinize the potential deterrent effect the ICC could have on Joseph Kony. To do this, this section will analyze the certainty, severity, and celerity of the legal sanction threat and make some observations as to how the experiential effect and Kony’s risk sensitivity affected this potential deterrent effect. The way in which it was affected by extralegal sanction threats and the ICC’s perceived legitimacy, will be studied in §3.3.4 and §3.3.5, respectively. It must be said that, because the ICC has clearly failed to deter Kony from committing any further crimes, this section will mostly be occupied with the explanation of how the deterrent effect of the ICC was either not enough for or incapable of stopping Joseph Kony. To start with the certainty of the legal sanction threat issued by the ICC, it can be said that the objective certainty is rather low. So far, the ICC has only issued arrest warrants for 25 persons, of whom it has secured the arrest of only 15, a little more than a half. It has only convicted one suspect, while another has been acquitted. Moreover, the enormous amount of perpetrators left unprosecuted, has caused the persistence of what Janine-Natalya Clark has called an ‘impunity gap’.245 Mostly, the small amount of persons indicted and trials finished is due to capacity constraints – for example, the ICC can only manage two to three cases a year.246 However, the ICC has also been accused of selective justice, since it has so far mostly refused to indict officials and/or persons belonging to the state on which it depends for cooperation.247 But even the ones who do get indicted, face a small chance of apprehension. Indeed, in a discussion of the relevant interests of the ICC, the indicted suspects, and the international community, James Meernik predicts that the most likely outcome of ICC indictments, at least initially, 243 As was mentioned earlier, the Preamble to the Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court states that it has “to put an end to impunity for the perpetrators of these crimes and thus to contribute to the prevention of such crimes.” 244 Clark, ‘The ICC and Case Selection’, 42. 245 Clark, ‘Peace, Justice and the International Criminal Court’, 535. See also: Christopher W. Mullins and Dawn L. Rothe, ‘The Ability of the International Criminal Court to Deter Violations of International Criminal Law: A Theoretical Assessment’, International Criminal Law Review 10:5 (2010) 771-786, 780-781. 246 Akhavan, ‘The Rise, and Fall, and Rise’, 531; Clark, ‘Peace, Justice and the International Criminal Court’, 526. 247 Clark, ‘The ICC and Case Selection’, 44. 140 will be a stalemate, in which neither the suspected war criminals, nor the international community are willing to make justice happen by letting a trial take place.248 It is likely that Joseph Kony does not perceive the certainty of the legal sanction threat made against him to be higher than it actually is. In fact, it is probable that he will perceive it to be even lower. First of all, it must be noted that in the first few years of the existence of the International Criminal Court, up to the time that arrest warrants were issued, there seems to have been an ‘awareness problem’. It was only after the Court demanded his arrest that Kony started to try and collect information about the institution in The Hague.249 Once he did become aware of it, his reaction appears to have been somewhat ambiguous, as is illustrated by someone who participated with him in a subsidiary of the Juba peace talks: “[H]e [Kony] raised the issue of the ICC. At first he said that he did not fear it, because the ICC would do nothing to him. Then he said he would not sign until the indictment was lifted.”250 The fact that the world was now after Kony, definitely increased the international pressure on him. But after the years went by and it turned out that he was able to defy apprehension by adapting some of its tactics and changing its geographical focus (Kony has now been at large for over eight years), the perceived certainty of eventually being sanctioned by the ICC has been downgraded significantly. As will be discussed further below, the consequences of the experiential effect and Kony’s risk sensitivity amplified this. The severity of the ICC’s legal sanction threat is comparable to that of the ICTY. It cannot impose the death penalty and Thomas Lubanga, the one suspect it has convicted so far, received a meager sentence of 14 years for conscripting child soldiers.251 The way in which the severity of the legal sanction threat is perceived is influenced by the fact that the situations the ICC has involved itself in so far are marked by a particular brutality – the case against Joseph Kony is no exception here. (This is no surprise, since the ICC can only prosecute cases which are of sufficient gravity.) In these situations, the price of failure is already much higher than any punishment the ICC can deliver. Those who fail namely have to often face torture and/or death. In these circumstances, the Court can hardly add a significantly severe threat of punishment.252 Indeed, Julian Ku and Jide Nzelibe have argued that African coup plotters – who, according to Ku and Nzelibe, are likely to violate international humanitarian law – are more likely Meernik, ‘Apprehension of ICC suspects’, 187. It is relevant to note here that Meernik estimates the chance that the international community will engage in securing the apprehension of a rebel leader to be bigger than it is for government officials. See: Ibid., 187-188. 249 Green, The Wizard of the Nile, 234-235. 250 Iya, ‘A Madi perspective’, 182-183. 251 Alette Smeulers, Barbara Hola and Tom van den Berg, ‘Sixty-Five Years of International Criminal Justice: The Facts and Figures’, International Criminal Law Review 13:1 (2013) 7-41, 24. Because the time Lubanga has spent in ICC custody (he was transferred to The Hague on 16 March 2006) will be deducted from his sentence, he will be released after 8 years, meaning he will be free again in 2020. See: International Criminal Court, The Prosecutor v. Thomas Lubanga Dyilo, Case No. ICC-01/03-01/06, available online at: http://www.icccpi.int/en_menus/icc/situations%20and%20cases/situations/situation%20icc%200104/related%20cases/icc%200 104%200106/Pages/democratic%20republic%20of%20the%20congo.aspx (2 December2013). 252 Meernik, ‘Apprehension of ICC suspects’, 178. 248 141 to face sanctions by domestic institutions – either legally or extralegally – than to be convicted by the ICC. Furthermore, these sanctions are likely to be much more severe, because, for example, the ICC cannot impose the death penalty. Thus, Ku and Nzelibe conclude, the limited certainty and severity of ICC sanction threats are unlikely to pose much of an additional deterrent to potential violators. 253 The low perceived severity of ICC punishment compared to other sanctions offenders might be facing, appears to be the exact reason why Bosco ‘The Terminator’ Ntaganda surrendered himself to the American embassy in March this year, asking to be handed over to the ICC, which had an outstanding arrest warrant against him. After he lost a battle for the leadership of his M23 rebel group, he preferred a lavish cell in The Hague over a sure death by his former rebel comrades.254 A similar analysis would be applicable for Joseph Kony. It is unlikely that, after having lived for over 25 years in the bush with the past few years fighting a constant struggle for survival, he will perceive a prison sentence to be a particularly severe sanction for criminal behavior.255 However, punishment by the ICC might pose some significant immaterial costs for Kony. If apprehended and subsequently convicted, he would lose his power and position as the commander of the LRA. Joseph Kony might therefore perceive the ICC sanction threat as reasonably severe. As was noted in the first chapter, the fact that most legal punishment only comes after a lengthy process of indictment, arrest, trials and appeals, makes the criminal justice system unsuited to exploit human’s (instrumental/bounded) rationality.256 The lack of effective disincentives for the crime in situ, makes the criminal justice system unable to counter its (usually) immediate incentives. The gap in time between the crime and its punishment has been even larger for the ICC than for most domestic legal systems.257 The lack of capacity, together with budgetary constraints limits the number of cases the Court can handle at one time.258 For Thomas Lubanga, almost ten years elapsed before he was punished for the crimes he committed.259 This long lapse of time between crime and punishment would mean that the ICC is even less suited to pose as an effective deterrent. It does not seem that the distant threat of being prosecuted by a far-away Court, especially given the long lasting culture of impunity, will be Julian Ku and Jide Nzelibe, ‘Do International Criminal Tribunals Deter or Exacerbate Humanitarian Atrocities?’, Washington University Law Review 84:4 (2006) 777-834, 831-833. 254 Joseph Hammond, ‘M23’s Congo Cadres: The Rebel Movement with a Taste for Local Politics’, Think Africa Press, (23 October 2013), available online at: http://thinkafricapress.com/drc/m23-cadres-key-grip-power (2 December 2013); Stewart McCartney, ‘Despite M23 Defeat, Militias Still Threat to Congo’, Institute for War and Peace Reporting, (20 November 2013), available online at: http://iwpr.net/report-news/despite-m23-defeatmilitias-still-threat-congo (2 December 2013). 255 Ssenyonjo, ‘Prosecution or Amnesty?’, 371. 256 Raymond Paternoster notes that this is because the criminal justice system has other imperatives – justice must be served and justice frequently takes time – which inhibit it to properly exploit human rationality. See: Raymond Paternoster, ‘How Much Do We Really Know About Criminal Deterrence’, The Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology 100:3 (2010) 765-823, 821. 257 Smeulers et al., ‘Facts and Figures’, 16-18. 258 Mullins and Rothe, ‘The Ability’, 780-781. 259 Lubanga was convicted for the crimes he committed between September 2002 and August 2003. Lubanga has been implicated in crimes before that, but the limit to the ICC’s temporal jurisdiction means that the Court does not have jurisdiction over these crimes. It can therefore be said that the time between the crimes and the punishment is even longer. 253 142 perceived as a strong disincentive by future offenders. Joseph Kony has been committing grave human rights abuses for over twenty years, and although the international community is now significantly involved in the efforts to catch him, his streak of impunity endures. Thus, at the time that Joseph Kony decided whether or not to continue committing crimes, the perceived celerity of punishment must have been low. The experiential effect contributed to the low perceived certainty and celerity. The information Joseph Kony received from his own experience with the (international) criminal justice system, as well as the information he received from the experiences of his peers, mostly caused Kony to downgrade his perception of the certainty and celerity of the legal sanction threat issued by the ICC. First, Kony was able to commit crimes without any serious international legal sanction threat for almost fifteen years (from 1988 to 2002) before the ICC was established and it was in theory able to exercise jurisdiction over crimes he would commit. In fact, in 2000 he was offered an amnesty for his crimes. Even after the Court indicted him, he successfully evaded arrest and remains at large, even up to this day. Therefore, his own experience with the (international) criminal justice system, does not point at a particularly high chance of being sanctioned for his actions. Neither does the information coming from his peers, although there is some reason to believe that he was aware of international successes in the international prosecution of African war criminals, in particular the prosecution of Charles Taylor, the former President of Nigeria who was accused of and subsequently arrested and convicted for crimes committed during the civil war in Sierra Leone.260 Although this information would have been a reason to upgrade his certainty perception, the experiences of his more direct peers were more congruent with his own. There have been no trials for other LRA commanders. Like Kony, they were initially offered amnesty and have been able to evade arrest after the ICC indictment. It is reasonable to assume that Kony perceived the experiences of his more direct peers261 to be more reliable and comparable to his situation and that they thus exerted a stronger influence on Kony. Therefore, the overall impact of the experiential effect seems to be a downgrade in the perceived certainty and celerity of the international legal sanction threat. The fact that Kony has been able to evade apprehension for more than eight years, even though the international effort to arrest Africa’s most wanted have greatly increased in recent years, points at the high extent to which Kony is risk sensitive. There are many examples of Kony adapting his tactics to decrease the chance of detection and/or apprehension. During the 1990s he situated his bases in South Sudan, beyond the reach of the Ugandan government troops. When Operation Iron Fist was launched by the UPDF in 2002, and the Ugandan army was allowed to operate in South Sudan up to the ‘Red Line’, Kony moved the LRA bases further north beyond the reach of the UPDF, while he himself went 260 Green, The Wizard of the Nile, 233. The President of Sudan, Omar al-Bashir, could also be counted among his more direct peers, since Bashir gave the LRA significant support during the civil war in South Sudan. Bashir, also, has been able to evade arrest since his ICC indictment, and has been able to defy the ICC with impunity. 261 143 in hiding in the largely inaccessible Imatong Mountains. Following the referral of the situation in Northern Uganda to the ICC, Operation Iron Fist II was launched. At this point, pressure on Kony greatly increased, both because of the seeming lack of support coming from Khartoum and the now increased international efforts to stop him. Kony responded by once again relocating the LRA. Between September 2005 and early 2006, the LRA moved to the border region of the Central African Republic and the Democratic Republic of Congo, where the LRA now remains.262 In the CAR and DRC, Kony has deliberately been operating in areas like the Garamba National Park, where government presence is minimal. Thus, risk sensitivity – defined in the Analytical Framework as “the extent to which the offender is aware of the risk of being caught and takes measures to minimize this risk”263 – is a trait that seems highly applicable to Joseph Kony. In conclusion To conclude, it seems that the ICC was unable to form a credible sanction threat in Kony’s eyes. Although it might be argued that his perception of the severity of the ICC’s sanction threat was reasonably high, Kony’s low perception of its certainty and celerity were responsible for significantly detracting from the deterrent effect of the ICC’s sanction threat. The experiential effect – Kony’s own experience and the experience of his more direct peers – furthermore point to a lowering of the sanction threat’s credibility. Lastly, Kony’s actions betray a high risk sensitivity. Thus, although Kony might have been deterrable, actually deterring him was and remains a significant task, a task the ICC is, at least to this point, unable to complete. On the website of the LRA Crisis Tracker, designed by the NGO’s Invisible Children – known for its Kony 2012 campaign – and The Resolve, the reports of the rebel group’s current activity are visualized. See: Invisible Children and The Resolve, ‘LRA Crisis Tracker’, (2 December 2013), available online at: http://www.lracrisistracker.com/ (2 December 2013). 263 This definition was given in §1.2.1. See also: Jacobs, ‘Deterrence and Deterrability’, 422-423 262 144 §3.3.4 Extralegal sanction threats The social context in which Joseph Kony committed his atrocities – the context in which extralegal sanction threats were issued that could have a powerful effect on Kony’s decision making process – was for the most part made up of two different environments, Northern Uganda (mostly Acholiland) and the LRA rebel group.264 The inhabitants of Acholiland were rather ambivalent in their attitudes towards the LRA. Many Acholi had enough of Kony’s violence, his brutal attacks and abductions of their children.265 Clearly, the rebels had to take the majority of the blame for their predicament. At the same time, part of the blame was also attributed to the government in Kampala. A large segment of Acholi society felt that Northern Uganda was marginalized by Museveni. This sentiment was reflected in the outcome of the 1996, 2001, and 2006 presidential elections. In 1996 and 2001, fewer than 10 percent of the voters in Northern Uganda supported Museveni, while in 2006 only 16 percent did so.266 Evidently, the northerners were vehemently negative about the way in which they were being treated by the Kampala government. Many Acholi felt that the UPDF’s policy of forced displacement was meant to neutralize the north politically, with some even accusing of Museveni of trying to commit genocide against them. 267 With such a large share of the Acholi opposed to Museveni, it is understandable that at least some sympathy existed for Kony and his rebel movement, even if they were unhappy about his methods.268 As such, it can be said that the inhabitants of Acholiland were not so much supportive of Kony and the LRA, as they were opposed to Museveni.269 Also, it must not be forgotten that a majority of the LRA fighters were abducted as a child and had been forced to commit atrocities. Many people felt that these children were not perpetrators, but victims, and, although brainwashed, remained ‘their children’. 270 These sentiments were manifestly expressed in the widespread support for the 2000 Amnesty Law. In short, the inhabitants of Acholiland displayed an ambivalent attitude towards Kony and the LRA, and therefore, extralegal sanction threats were not issued with as much force as might be expected from a community terrorized for decades. It is acknowledged that ‘the social context’ is not some homogenous set of people. The many different actors who made up the Acholi society were not of one mind. Some hated Kony, some were ambivalent, others were supportive of his cause, but opposed to his methods, while many others fell somewhere in between. Nor were the LRA fighters were all of one mind. Even though they lived in a hierarchical rebel group with a strict disciplinarian and spiritual order, which made them more homogenous than Acholi society in general, some fighters were completely entranced by the group’s cause – becoming enthusiastic killers and effective soldiers – while others were mostly homesick, tried to exclude themselves from the atrocities and often tried to escape. 265 This was already so in 1997. See: Robert Gersony, The Anguish of Northern Uganda: Results of a field-based assessment of the civil conflicts in Northern Uganda (Kampala: USAID Mission, 1997) 59. Christopher Blattman similarly argues that the overwhelming majority of the Acholi did not support Kony. See: Blattman, ‘From Violence to Voting’, 235. 266 Finnström, ‘Another story’, 78-79. 267 Green, The Wizard of the Nile, 118-119. 268 Still, some Acholi saw Kony as a ‘freedom fighter’. In their view, the violence could be legitimized, since “when you can do nothing” in a conventional manner to solve your problems, only violence remains. See: Finnström, ‘Another story’, 83. 269 Ibid., 78-79. 270 Green, The Wizard of the Nile, 96-97. 264 145 The other social environment in which Kony operated was the LRA. It is often noted that this group bears similarities to a cult. Its fighters are abducted, brainwashed, and forced to commit atrocities. Kony has great spiritual authority over his fighters and his violent means of submission have deterred many fighters from running away.271 Apart from versions of Stockholm syndrome, the apparently incomprehensible loyalty of the abductees is fostered by an elaborate initiation process. Indeed, Opis Oloya describes the process through which the LRA recruits are transformed into LRA members, undergoing various initiating rituals, such as witnessing or participating in the killing of innocent civilians. Usually these rituals, although not clearly structured, include components like Lwoko wii Cibilan (washing the civilian mind), Neko Dano (killing a person), and Pwonyo Mony (military training).272 These abductees are transformed from innocent civilians into killing machines by a brutal regime and the encouragement of violence. During the training, killing is deliberately trivialized, and even encouraged by promoting those fighters who participate in the worst atrocities.273 Moreover, it has been reported that life in the LRA camps is strictly hierarchical and that minor transgressions are punished by severe beatings and sometimes even killings.274 Therefore, it seems highly unlikely that LRA fighters would sanction (what is defined by the ICC as) criminal behavior by using extralegal punishments such as shaming and embarrassment. It is rather more likely that the opposite is true: LRA fighters are punished for trying to withdraw themselves from or refusing to participate in killing activities. If Kony would give in to the ICC’s demands, stop his violence and turn himself over for judgment in The Hague, he would so completely abandon all the values he once professed to his peers that he would most likely be completely shunned by them. Thus, the social context of the LRA in fact issues extralegal sanction threats which do not deter violence, but deter non-violence. Although indicting leaders of violent groups can sometimes create pressure coming from within the group by stigmatizing and delegitimizing its leader – which, to some extent, happened with Slobodan Milosevic –, in the context of the LRA this is contestable “given the composition of the LRA, which is made up in great part of those conscripted as children who fear Kony’s threats of violence and spiritual authority”.275 As was mentioned in the first chapter, the importance of extralegal sanction threats can be increased in contexts in which the rule of law is lacking and the trust in formal sanctioning institutions is generally low. Although such a situation is often applicable to contexts in which mass atrocities take place, multiple observers have noted that Uganda has a proudly independent and efficient judicial Akhavan, ‘First State Referral’, 407-408. Akhavan refers here to a 2001 report on Northern Uganda by the UN High Commissioner for Human Rights. 272 See: Oloya, Child to Soldier, 78-95. 273 Allen, Trial Justice, 141. 274 Akhavan, ‘First State Referral’, 408. 275 Branch, ‘The Politics of ICC Intervention’, 183. 271 146 institution.276 However, Uganda’s judiciary does not seem to be able to effectively adjudicate crimes committed by high-ranking government officials, let alone crimes committed by rebel forces such as the LRA.277 A certain culture of impunity thus persists here. It is unlikely that the domestic courts are able to exercise much of a rule of law in the context of the rebel camps in the bush, although there is no specific reason to believe that Kony does not trust the Ugandan judiciary or sees it as illegitimate – which is the case for his perception of the ICC, which he does not trust and sees as an illegitimate extension of Museveni’s war against him. Still, the absence of any functioning judicial institution in the context of the LRA camps in the bush, increases the importance of extralegal sanction threats to regulate deviant behavior. Since deviant behavior is defined in this context as the refusal to participate in serious crimes, the social context is actually working against the prevention of criminal behavior. In conclusion The ambivalent attitude in Northern Uganda with regards to the LRA and Joseph Kony – with some condemning his struggle as brutally criminal, others agreeing with his ultimate goal while condemning his methods, and still others praising him as a freedom fighter – decreased the power of the extralegal sanction threats that could have been issued by this social environment. In the social context of the LRA, this situation was even worse. The lack of a functioning judicial institution which could have punished criminal behavior by the rebel group, increased the reliance on extralegal sanctions to regulate deviant behavior. Yet, because deviant behavior in this context was defined as the refusal to participate in crimes, the social environment here was issuing extralegal sanction threats that actually worked against the prevention of mass atrocities. This argument is usually made in the context of the admissibility challenge to the ICC’s jurisdiction in the Ugandan situation. See: Clark, ‘Re-Framing the Debate’, 143-144; Kastner, The ICC between Law and Politics, 48-52, 60-67; Ssenyonjo, ‘Prosecution or Amnesty?’, 368. 277 For example, a recent report by Human Rights Watch finds a persistent failure to prosecute high-level corruption in Uganda. See: Human Rights Watch, “Letting the Big Fish Swim”: Failures to Prosecute HighLevel Corruption in Uganda, (21 October 2013), available online at: http://www.hrw.org/sites/default/files/reports/uganda1013_ForUpload_0.pdf (2 December 2013). Of course, there are some problems in the judiciary’s exercise of jurisdiction over former LRA fighters and/or commanders, since the Amnesty Law of 2000 gives them an amnesty if they surrender voluntarily. 276 147 §3.3.5 Legitimacy of the ICC The impact of the ICC on Joseph Kony’s criminal decision making process was affected by the legitimacy of the Court, about which there has been some vigorous debate. To analyze this debate, it is useful to distinguish between two different views on legitimacy. The first, which would see the legitimacy of an international criminal tribunal as defined by a firm legal basis and fair proceedings during its trials, might judge the ICC to be more legitimate than the ICTY. The ICC’s jurisdiction does not come from a Resolution by the Security Council, but rather from a signed treaty that has been ratified by Uganda itself.278 In first instance, the Court does not have jurisdiction in those states that have refused to acknowledge it. As such, it would be hard to claim that the ICC’s exercise of its jurisdiction in Uganda is illegitimate from a legal standpoint.279 The admissibility of the Ugandan case before the ICC, however, has been doubted by some scholars. According to the complementarity principle, for the ICC to assume jurisdiction, the national judiciary has to be either unwilling or unable to prosecute crimes articulated in the Rome Statute. Neither seemed to apply to the Ugandan judiciary. It seems that the only reason why Joseph Kony could not be tried by Uganda was the UPDF’s inability to apprehend him. This observation raises some questions with regard to the motives behind the acceptance of the case by the ICC. 280 Although the ICC was probably motivated mostly by actual concern for the bringing of justice to those responsible for atrocities in Northern Uganda, institutional interests also definitely played a role. The ICC was eager to establish its institutional legitimacy by accepting its first case. The situation in Northern Uganda, where it seemed clear that horrendous atrocities had been committed on a large scale and as part of a systematic policy, thus looked like a promising first. The more important view on legitimacy for this study, however, is the way in which the legitimacy of the ICC was perceived by its audience in Northern Uganda, especially by Kony. The ICC intervention in the situation in Northern Uganda was highly controversial, and was sometimes met with outright hostility by the affected community. Many Acholi questioned the motivations of Yoweri Museveni for referring the situation to the ICC. They saw the move as another step towards marginalizing the north, doubted Museveni’s desire for ‘justice’, and were angered by the fact that the ICC referral seemed to run roughshod over local demands, which asked for an end to the conflict by a combination of amnesty and traditional reconciliation processes.281 One of the most often-cited reports, written by the Kampala-based Refugee Law Project, clearly stated the demands of this group of people: 278 Still, Adam Branch criticizes the fact that the ICC is not democratically accountable to the victims of mass atrocities. See: Branch, ‘The Politics of ICC Intervention’, 193-194. 279 See also: Margaret M. DeGuzman, ‘Gravity and the Legitimacy of the International Criminal Court’, Fordham International Law Journal 32:5 (2008) 1400-1465 280 Clark, ‘Re-Framing the Debate’, 143-144; Kastner, The ICC between Law and Politics, 57-67; Roach, ‘Multilayered Justice’, 186-188. 281 Adam Branch and Katherine Southwick have argued most forcefully for this point. See: Branch, ‘Local Injustice’, 25-26; Branch, ‘The Politics of ICC Intervention’, 182-190; Southwick, ‘Investigating War’, 105-119. For counterpoints, cf: Clark, ‘Peace, Justice and the International Criminal Court’, 543-544; Ssenyonjo, ‘Prosecution or Amnesty?’, 384-389. 148 Peace First, Justice Later.282 Similarly, the Acholi Religious Leaders Peace Initiative was worried about the effect the ICC intervention would have on the peace process.283 In the opinion of this group, the Acholi themselves had clearly stated their support for the Amnesty Law of 2000 and furthermore preferred their own version of justice – the earlier described mato oput ceremony – which emphasized restorative justice over the ICC-delivered retributive justice. Although the ICC Prosecutor reached out to these people by inviting them to The Hague in March/April 2005 – leading to a joint statement by Moreno-Ocampo and Acholi leaders that they would cooperate on the issue284 -, the exact way in which the problem would be resolved remained a point of contention.285 On one hand, the Acholi did seem to profess support for the ICC trial of those most responsible for the serious crimes committed in Northern Uganda. Multiple opinion polls concluded that a large share of the Acholi were not ready to extend forgiveness to the LRA leaders.286 On the other hand, research by Otim and Wierda has shown that victim views are complex and changing over time. For example, a 2005 opinion poll suggested that a majority of the victims preferred hard – military, retributive – measures over soft – amnesty, restorative – measures to deal with the LRA, while a 2007 poll showed that these statistics were reversed.287 As such, it is hard to say something conclusive about the views of the wider Acholi population on the ICC intervention. This has a lot to do with the population’s ambivalent view on the LRA itself, which has been handled in greater detail in §3.3.4. In any way, the ICC did not receive the welcome in Uganda that it might have expected or wished for. Apart from the peace vs. justice debate outlined above, this was caused to a large extent by the perceived partiality emanating from the ICC’s cooperation with Museveni’s government. The stage was already set for this perception in January 2004. The press conference in London – in which the ICC Prosecutor and Museveni jointly announced that the Prosecutor accepted the ‘situation regarding the LRA’ –, gave rise to suspicions that the ICC would only investigate crimes committed by the LRA and, because of dependence on the Ugandan government, would ignore crimes committed by the UPDF. Apart from massacres and lootings in the context of the counter-insurgency campaign, the forceful displacement by the UPDF of a large share of the Acholi population into the poorly protected IDP camps, with abhorrent living conditions, perhaps caused even more suffering than the LRA attacks. This campaign of forceful displacement of over a million people moreover clearly falls under the jurisdiction 282 Lucy Hovil and Joanna R. Quinn, Peace First, Justice Later: Traditional Justice in Northern Uganda, Refugee Law Project Working Paper No. 17, (July 2005), available online at: http://www.refugeelawproject.org/working_papers/RLP.WP17.pdf (2 December 2013). 283 Apuuli, ‘ARLPI’, 122-125. 284 International Criminal Court, ‘ICC – Joint Statement by ICC Chief Prosecutor and the visiting Delegation of Lango, Acholi, Iteso and Madi Community Leaders from Northern Uganda’, ICC Press Release, (16 April 2005), available online at: http://www.icccpi.int/en_menus/icc/situations%20and%20cases/situations/situation%20icc%200204/press%20releases/Pages/jo int%20statement%20by%20icc%20chief%20prosecutor%20and%20the%20visiting%20delegation%20of%20lan go%20ach.aspx (2 December 2013). 285 Kastner, The ICC between Law and Polities, 56. 286 Allen, Trial Justice, 147-148; Roach, ‘Multilayered Justice’, 254-255. 287 Otim and Wierda, ‘Juba peace talks’, 26. 149 of the ICC: Articles 7(1)(e) and7(2)(d) of the Rome Statute brand such a policy a crime against humanity. The ICC Prosecutor has defended its decision not to issue warrants of arrest against those responsible for these crimes on the grounds of gravity, claiming that the LRA crimes are far more grave than any of those committed by UPDF troops.288 Many independent observers have noted that the Prosecutor’s decision on the basis of gravity is unconvincing, pointing instead to the ICC’s dependence on the government of Uganda for assistance in its proceedings.289 Also, it has been stressed that the Prosecutor’s decision is hardly explainable to the victims of the UPDF crimes.290 Therefore, even if the decision by the Prosecutor not to prosecute UPDF crimes can be justified on legal grounds, the failure to do so has powerfully degraded the impartiality and legitimacy of the ICC in the eyes of the Acholi population. Joseph Kony’s perception of the ICC’s legitimacy seems to be affected by similar ideas about the judicial institution’s partiality. Kony has stated that the ICC is simply an instrument of Museveni’s battle against him and his LRA.291 In Kony’s mind, the sometimes highly visible connection of the ICC with government troops – ICC investigators have reportedly travelled in government vehicles and have been escorted by UPDF troops during their activities292 - has made the Court synonymous with Museveni’s government and thus clearly biased against him. Lately, the increased effort by the international community to apprehend him in order to execute the Court’s arrest warrants, has further exacerbated this. Because the ICC in this sense is the enemy – the power responsible for his predicament, forcing him to constantly be on the run – there is little chance that Kony will perceive the ICC to be legitimate and thus a rightful restriction of his behavior. Indeed, Tyler’s theory of procedural justice as a basis of legitimacy, which was described in the first chapter, predicts this.293 In Kony’s perception, the ICC’s one-sided arrest warrants – all aimed at Acholi – are unfair and discriminatory, and do not respect his social status. As such, Kony’s perception of the ICC as an illegitimate court, is to some extent explained by the ICC’s perceived procedural unfairness. One more factor that has unfavorably impacted the Court’s legitimacy is its physical remoteness and the perceived imposition of Western justice models.294 For many Acholi, the ICC’s trials are seen as a “foreign and remote process”, which has little impact on the people’s daily lives.295 This recalls the Clark, ‘The ICC and Case Selection’, 43; Ssenyonjo,’Prosecution or Amnesty?’, 365. Yet, Akhavan stresses that the ICC, as an independent judicial institution, should not concern itself with issues such as reconciliation. In his view, the ICC’s impartiality would be tarnished even more if it were to accuse and convict persons without sufficient evidence only to ‘spread the blame’. See: Akhavan, ‘Rise, and Fall, and Rise’, 533. 289 Clark, ‘The ICC and Case Selection’, 44; Otim and Wierda, ‘Juba peace talks’, 22. 290 Clark, ‘Peace, Justice and the International Criminal Court’, 524-525, 529. 291 Schomerus, ‘Interview with Kony’, 127-129. 292 Allen, Trial Justice, 97. 293 See: Tom R. Tyler, ‘Procedural Justice, Legitimacy, and the Effective Rule of Law’, Crime and Justice 30 (2003) 284-357; Tom R. Tyler, ‘Psychological Perspectives on Legitimacy and Legitimation’, Annual Review of Psychology 57 (2006) 375-400. For more, see: §1.2.3. 294 Clark, ‘Peace, Justice and the International Criminal Court’, 532-534; Otim and Wiarda, ‘Juba peace talks’, 22. 295 Goetz, ‘Relevance to Affected Communities’, 68, 70-71. 288 150 old aphorism that ‘justice has to be seen to be done’. Although Outreach work has significantly improved since the days of the ICTY’s inception, the ICC has still been accused of spending too little efforts on explaining its decisions to the Ugandan population, thus doing little to counter the narratives of partial justice.296 The perceived imposition of a Western model of criminal justice, has further led to a questioning of the cultural relevance of the ICC to Africa, since it is largely seen as an embodiment of Western values.297 Its focus on Africa, a symptom of which is the fact that the Court has so far only issued arrest warrants against African persons, has exacerbated these sentiments.298 Furthermore, the high financial costs of the Court has sparked some outrage, with some people in the IDP camps clamoring that millions are spent on a far-away court, while the Acholi were starving in the camps.299 This (physical and emotional) remoteness of the ICC judicial process has also had an impact on the way 296 Ibid., 66-67. Graeme Simpson, ‘One among Many: The ICC as a Tool of Justice during Transition’, in: Nicholas Waddell and Phil Clark, Courting Conflict? Justice, Peace and the ICC in Africa (London: Royal African Society, 2008) 73-80, 77 298 That the ICC seems to exclusively focus itself on the African continent has been one of the major accusations leveled against it by African leaders. It is a sensitive suspect among many African leaders, especially in the context of the West’s colonial history. See: Nicholas Waddell and Phil Clark, ‘Introduction’, in: Nicholas Waddell and Phil Clark, Courting Conflict? Justice, Peace and the ICC in Africa (London: Royal African Society, 2008) 7-12, 8-9. The Sudanese president Omar al-Bashir was one of the first to liken the ICC’s intervention in his country as a neo-colonial breach of his country’s sovereignty. As a reward, the African Union declared in July 2009 that it would no longer assist the ICC in apprehending Sudanese suspects. See: Clark, ‘Peace, Justice and the International Criminal Court’, 524; Nkansah, ‘Emerging Dynamics’, 76; Kenneth A. Rodman, ‘Darfur and the Limits of Legal Deterrence’, Human Rights Quarterly 30:3 (2008) 529-560, 543; Dawn L. Rothe and Christopher W. Mullins, ‘Beyond the Juristic Orientation of International Criminal Justice: The Relevance of Criminological Insight to International Criminal Law and its Control. A Commentary’, International Criminal Law Review 10:1 (2010) 97110, 105. This argument has recently gained more traction with the Kenyan opposition to the ICC’s case against the country’s President Uhuru Kenyatta and Vice-President William Rutto. In October 2013, the African Union convened a special meeting to discuss a possible retreat by the organization from the Rome Statute, which the Kenyan parliament had already voted for. Eventually, the African Union decided not to do so, instead issuing a declaration that called upon the Court to cease its prosecutions and investigations against sitting heads of state. See: Benjamin Minegar, ‘Africa leaders should be immune from ICC prosecution: AU’, Jurist, (13 October 2013), available online at: http://jurist.org/paperchase/2013/10/africa-leaders-should-be-immune-from-icc-prosecutionau.php (2 December 2013); Manisuli Ssenyonjo, ‘The Rise of the African Union Opposition to the International Criminal Court’s Investigations and Prosecution of African Leaders’, International Criminal Law Review 13:2 (2013) 385-428. Understandably, the ICC has not been particularly accepting of such declarations and challenges to its legitimacy. However, according to Tomas Zak, it is losing the public perception battle, and seems to be unable to counter the narratives that it is a neocolonial and imperial institution intent on the removal of African leaders who are not favored by the West. See: Tomas Zak, ‘Kenyatta in Court’, Think Africa Press, (12 November 2013), available online at: http://thinkafricapress.com/kenya/manipulation-and-misinformation-kenyatta-and-iccquestion (2 December 2013). Interestingly, the social psychological model of perceived legitimacy put forward by Stuart Ford, seems particularly applicable in this context. This model suggests that the perceived legitimacy of international criminal justice institutions are mostly determined by whom they indict. For example, Moses Chelang’a has observed that the opinion that African leaders have of the ICC, “seems to depend on whether it is they or their opponents who face charges”. Quoted in: Bernard Momanyi, ‘Ugandan Leader Lashes Out at ICC’, Institute for War and Peace Reporting (20 April 2013), available online at: http://iwpr.net/report-news/ugandanleader-lashes-out-icc (2 December 2013). To conclude, it is clear that the ICC is facing a serious challenge to its legitimacy because of its apparently exclusive focus on the African continent. At the moment, there is little reason to believe that this will soon change. However, as long as the ICC does not give more attention to these arguments, neither will the opinions of many Africans who believe that the ICC is just another imperialist institution created by the West to punish African leaders. 299 Green, The Wizard of the Nile, 85. See also: David Wippman, ‘The Costs of International Justice’, The American Journal of International Law 100:4 (2006) 861-881. 297 151 in which Kony perceived the Court’s legitimacy. Apart from the increased effort to apprehend him, Kony has come in little contact with the Court, for a long time feeding his feeling that he had nothing to be afraid of. It turned out that the low perceived legitimacy which troubled the ICC’s legal sanction threat in Northern Uganda, was and is interrelated with the certainty of this sanction threat. As was noted earlier, a low certainty of arrest decreases the court’s legitimacy.300 Indeed, had the Court been more successful in securing the arrest of all of its suspects, the Court’s effectiveness in removing spoilers to an effective peace process might have been perceived very differently. Moreover, the low perceived legitimacy caused the certainty of the legal sanction threat to decrease. Because of the ambivalent attitude of the population towards the Museveni government and the ICC, many people were still willing to assist the LRA. There have been multiple reports of villagers providing the LRA with food and medicine. High ranking negotiators were similarly reluctant to assist the ICC in arresting its suspects.301 People like Riek Machar, leader of the Juba peace talks, had various meetings with Kony. However, he refused to be accompanied by soldiers who could arrest him, citing the prevalence of peace over justice as his motivation. At one point, Machar even supplied the LRA with $20.000 to buy food and medicine.302 The unwillingness of much of the Acholi population to assist in the ICC’s efforts to arrest LRA soldiers, caused by their low perception of the ICC’s legitimacy, therefore caused the certainty of the ICC’s legal sanction threat to decrease accordingly. Thus, the perceptions of the legitimacy and certainty of the ICC’s legal sanction threat interacted and reinforced each other, facilitating Kony’s decision to ignore the threat even more. In conclusion The ICC’s legitimacy from a legal standpoint, although somewhat tarnished by doubts about admissibility in the Ugandan case, seems to be powerfully established. The ICC’s procedural fairness, especially in the eyes of Kony, is much less secure, however. Because there is a perception among many Acholi, including Kony, that the ICC is biased in favor of Museveni’s government, the Court has run into troubles with its activities in Uganda. The highly emotional peace vs. justice debates resulting from the ICC’s alleged spoiling of the peace process and the remoteness of a foreign-based and culturally alien criminal court are exacerbating these troubles. These troubles have led to a low perceived legitimacy of the ICC in Northern Uganda, and by Kony in particular. The low perceived legitimacy has in turn lowered the certainty of the ICC’s legal sanction threat. See: Dawn L. Rothe and Victoria E. Collins, ‘The International Criminal Court: A Pipe Dream to End Impunity?’, International Criminal Law Review 13:1 (2013) 191-209, 196-197. 301 Green, The Wizard of the Nile, 232. 302 Ibid. 300 152 §3.4 Summarizing the findings of this chapter Joseph Kony was a central – if not the central – actor in the conflict that has devastated Northern Uganda for over two decades. His rebel group, the Lord’s Resistance Army, has been responsible for mass abductions of children, mutilations and massacres. Meanwhile, the Ugandan President Yoweri Museveni’s Uganda’s People Defense Force has waged a brutal counterinsurgency campaign in an attempt to destroy the LRA. By forcibly displacing over a million inhabitants of Northern Uganda into IDP camps, the UPDF has made the life of Northern Ugandans even more miserable. With help from Sudan, Kony was able for a long time to easily defend himself from the UPDF campaigns. After the Ugandan government referred the situation to the jurisdiction of the newly established International Criminal Court, however, international pressure greatly increased, causing the LRA to move its area of operations to the DRC and CAR. But the ICC was unable to deter Kony from more violence. Although diminished in size and capability, the LRA remains in the DRC and CAR, regularly committing crimes. This chapter has studied the way in which the ICC influenced Kony’s decision making, trying to answer the question of why the ICC was unable to deter Kony. It started out by assessing Kony’s rationality, motivation, and personality, all factors that have to be factored in when looking at Kony’s reaction the ICC legal sanction threat. It was concluded that Kony’s apparent irrationality might be overstated, and it was stressed that Kony’s handling of the LRA, including its spiritual and military order, betray at least some rational aspects. Kony’s motivation has been studied through Finnström’s looking glass, who stresses that the LRA has both spiritual and earthly motivations. The group definitely has political motivations, despite the government’s persistent refusal to acknowledge it. This refusal can be seen as a deliberate attempt to portray the LRA as a bunch of lunatics led by a psychopath, so that the government does not have to take its demands seriously. At the same time, Kony’s main value seems to be his own survival, and the acquirement of or holding onto power. Joseph Kony’s personality was much harder to assess. By pointing at Kony’s unpredictability, charisma, sensibility for betrayal, and his difficulty with coping with unfamiliar events, a sketch of Kony’s personality was nevertheless given. Next, the interaction between Joseph Kony and the ICC was studied. After describing the ICC and Kony’s legal responsibility, the analysis of factors impacting the ICC’s perceived deterrence capability, resulted in the conclusion that Joseph Kony must have perceived the legal sanction threat as having low certainty, reasonable severity, and low celerity. The experiential effect and Kony’s risk sensitivity exacerbated these effects, eventually leading to a perception that the ICC sanction threat was rather incredible. While extralegal sanction threats could have compensated for this, the social contexts – Acholi society and the LRA – in which Kony operated were rather lackluster about issuing extralegal sanction threats to Kony. In the context of the LRA, extralegal sanction threats instead formed against not committing crimes. The ICC has moreover been running into troubles with the public perception battle about its legitimacy. Its alleged partiality in the Ugandan case has significantly detracted from its legitimacy, both in the eyes of many Acholi and in Kony’s eyes. 153 All these factors play a role in explaining why Joseph Kony was not deterred from committing crimes and why the International Criminal Court was unable to prevent further violence after it accepted the situation in Northern Uganda. As such, Kony’s reaction to the ICC can be best described as indifference. 154 Conclusion This contribution has studied the potential deterrent effects of the legal sanction threat delivered by international criminal courts and tribunals through an actor-centric perspective. In this section, the results of this study will be brought together and the findings from the two case study’s – that of Slobodan Milosevic and that of Joseph Kony – will be analyzed and compared, in order to get a clearer idea of the effects of international legal sanction threats, both on government agents and on members of militias.1 The effects of the legal sanction threats and the way Milosevic and Kony reacted to them bore some similarities, although they also quite often varied. This gives substance to one of the statements made in the analytical framework, namely that it is important to realize that the effects of legal sanction threats are not the same for everyone, as they are affected by individual differences in their rationality, motivation, and personality. This section will close by putting the findings in context, looking at some problems for the hoped-for deterrence by international criminal tribunals, and, finally, recommending a way forward. The conflicts in Northern Uganda and the former Yugoslavia were extremely brutal, with hundreds of thousands innocent civilians being massacred, mutilated, and suffering in other ways, on a daily basis for years. While the conflicts in the former Yugoslavia were mostly dominated by ethnic struggles with relatively large-scale rather conventional battles taking places, the conflict in Northern Uganda is characterized by an insurgency in an underdeveloped region led by a spiritual medium using guerilla tactics against anyone found to be ‘impure’. In both conflicts, it looks as all sides can be held responsible for gruesome crimes, although some men stand out as being most responsible. Both Slobodan Milosevic and Joseph Kony were allegedly responsible for an enormous amount of crimes, involving thousands of victims. Although neither Milosevic nor Kony have been found guilty in court, it is widely accepted historically that these men were among those most responsible for the atrocities in the former Yugoslavia and Northern Uganda, the Democratic Republic of Congo and the Central African Republic. Their involvement in the atrocities differed, however and this also led to a different construction of their legal responsibility, as was set out in §2.3.2 and §3.3.2. Joseph Kony was a militia leader quite directly involved in the slaughter and mutilation of civilians. The abducted children became ‘his’ children, and he took part in educating – i.e. brainwashing – them. Milosevic, on the other hand, was more indirectly responsible – at least in a legal sense – for the atrocities committed by Bosnian and Croatian Serbs as well as Serbian paramilitary groups. He never supervised atrocities or directly participated in them – he just gave the orders. In both conflicts, the international community’s response was at first marked by a general unwillingness to become too deeply involved, symptoms of which were the hopes pinned on the International Criminal Tribunal of the former Yugoslavia and the International Criminal Court. The 1 The reader is referred to the tables at the end of the first chapter for the relevant theories that are used in the assessment of the case studies. 155 violence only ended, however, after the international community supported more powerful responses and geopolitical concerns shifted: in the former Yugoslavia, Milosevic was stopped by the use of a largescale air campaign; in Northern Uganda, Joseph Kony was driven out of Northern Uganda when Sudanese aid largely ceased, and the Ugandan army – assisted by American Special Forces and peacekeepers from the U.N. and African Union – was able to operate across borders more effectively. The savagery that was the result of the actions of Milosevic and Kony makes it somewhat irresistible to see them as ‘Butchers’ and ‘Messianic Mad Men’, whose acts defy rational understanding and who must therefore be irrational actors. And indeed, they both played on seemingly irrational elements in their respective societies to increase their authority and garner support. Milosevic made use of the nationalistic tendencies and feelings of victimhood amongst the Serbian population in the former Yugoslavia, while Kony emphasized his ability to communicate with the spirit world and professed a willingness to rid the world of the ‘impure’. But such notions are not entirely helpful for a deeper understanding of Milosevic and Kony. The political uses of overemphasizing the actors’ irrationality should not be forgotten here. Especially in the case of Kony and his LRA, journalists and government agents – amongst others the country’s president Yoweri Museveni – have portrayed the LRA as a ‘bunch of fundamentally irrational lunatics led by a psychopath’ in order to preclude a deeper understanding of the conflict and marginalize the group’s political wishes. The actions of Kony and Milosevic definitely had ‘rational’ elements, reminding of the observation in the first chapter that rationality is not defined by its substance, but rather by its consistency. That being said, Kony’s and Milosevic’s decision making process were still affected by computational difficulties, cognitive biases, emotions and individual differences, perhaps a bit more than for ‘normal’ state leaders familiar to Western countries. Both men were emotionally unstable and their limited information pool – Milosevic was surrounded by yes-men and Kony’s time in the bush for a large part precluded access to information – worsened the effects of computational difficulties and cognitive biases. As such, Kony and Milosevic mostly conformed to the bounded rationality model presented in the analytical framework. While studying Kony’s and Milosevic’s motivation, it is striking that both men were concerned with a mix of selfish motives and (at least rhetorically) concern for the well-being of their own ethnic group. It must be stressed that what both men seemed to value most was their own survival and the acquirement or maintenance of power. With little moral norms to regulate this pursuit, this value was usually most salient and sometimes got in the way of their other motivations, such as when Milosevic abandoned the Bosnian and Croatian Serbs during the Dayton peace process. But Kony and Milosevic also greatly differed in important aspects of their motivation, and not only in substance. For example, Milosevic’s wife, Mirjana Markovic, was hugely influential in the construction of Milosevic’s motivation. Keeping her, and his family, happy was a central value for Milosevic. Moreover, Kony’s ideological agenda was mostly concerned with the purification of Acholi society. The eradication of everything impure – basically almost anything opposed to him – was an important element of Kony’s motivation. Kony’s political agenda seems to be more consistent than was the case with Milosevic, 156 however. The overthrow of Museveni’s government has been propagated for 25 years now, while Milosevic seemed to adjust his political demands to what suited him best. Kony’s and Milosevic’s personalities are also somewhat alike and at the same time hugely different. Observers noted that Milosevic and Kony were somehow hugely charismatic, with Milosevic being beloved by many Serbs and Kony being idolized by the LRA members. Moreover, both men were easily angered, and struck out viciously when seriously confronted. Kony’s promise to Betty Bigombe to “shock the world” after the failed 1994 peace negotiations was the prelude to a Sudanese-supported campaign of increased violence and abductions. Milosevic was rather unscrupulous with his enemies, and although he usually did not maim or kill them like Kony did, he made sure they were made politically and socially dead. Yet, at the same time, Milosevic was much more of a jovial host than Kony, who was usually unwilling to receive journalists and hostile to outsiders. This was probably caused by the sophistication that comes with being a political animal like Milosevic, while Kony has been living in the bush for decades. Moreover, Milosevic and Kony differed in the applicability of the Dark Triad of personality types. While Milosevic clearly looked like a narcissist, Machiavellist, and (subclinical) psychopath, the same cannot be said for Kony. Kony, although somewhat narcissistic and often seen as a psychopath, does not look like much of a Machiavellist. The individual differences have some important explanatory power in understanding the ways in which Kony and Milosevic differed in their reactions to the international legal sanction threat. This legal sanction threat can be broken down by looking at its certainty, severity, and celerity. With regards to certainty, both the ICTY and the ICC have had – or are still having – significant problems with the apprehension of its suspects. Neither possesses its own police force, and the assistance of the international community was and is not always as straightforward as needed. Although the ICTY has now secured the arrest of all of its suspects, the enormous amount of perpetrators left unpunished does not bode well for its certainty. This has to do with capacity and budgetary constraints which also mark the ICC’s operations. These constraints limit the number of suspects that can be prosecuted and increase the risk of selective justice. Thus, the perceived certainty, which criminologists have identified as a crucial element of the legal sanction threat, was low. While the legal sanction threat’s severity might have been relatively high – mostly because of the damage a conviction might cause to a person’s social status – this does not seem to have had a particularly significant effect on either Milosevic or Kony.2 The fact that it usually took a long time for the ICTY and ICC to prosecute and punish its suspects, furthermore led to a low perceived celerity. Moreover, the negative effects of the factors described above, were exacerbated by the experiential effect and the men’s risk sensitivity. The fact that both Milosevic and Kony were able for a long time to get away with their crimes , with Milosevic at one time being hailed as a peacemaker and 2 It could be mentioned that this was to some extent expected, since criminologists have usually found that the severity of the legal sanction threat does not increase its deterrent effect. 157 Kony being offered an amnesty, decreased the deterrent effects of the ICTY’s and ICC’s sanction threat. Their peers had similar experiences: Milosevic’s peers – notably Karadzic and Mladic – were not seriously threatened with international prosecution, while Kony’s direct peers were, like him, able to evade arrest and had similar experiences with the criminal justice system before they were being threatened with international prosecution. Milosevic and Kony were also clearly risk sensitive, although it was expressed in different ways. Milosevic tried to decrease the chance of detection by making sure that no documentary trail remained which could clearly link him to the atrocities taking place, and by using the Serbian government apparatus to decrease the chance of being apprehended. Kony on the other hand, showed his risk sensitivity by constantly adapting his tactics and hiding in places that were known for their inaccessibility and low government control. At the same time, the social contexts in which Milosevic and Kony committed their crimes were usually rather lackluster about issuing extralegal sanction threats against committing serious crimes. This was the case both for the circles in which the men operated and the wider society in which they lived. The support for Milosevic’s ideological goals, such as the creation of an ethnically pure Greater Serbia, caused a somewhat perverted morality, which did not disapprove of the ethnic cleansings taking place in Croatia, Bosnia or Kosovo. With regards to Acholiland, the society in which Kony operated most of the time, it can be said that the region for the most part does not so much support Kony as it disapproves of his rival, Museveni. The lack (of force) of the extralegal sanction threats was even more pronounced in the more direct social context. Kony’s LRA was almost completely subjugated to his rule and most of the rebels were afraid to challenge him. The same can be said of Milosevic’s political allies, who were mostly yes-men. Yet, Milosevic did in fact often receive advice that ran counter to his support for the ethnic cleansing operations in Kosovo, Bosnia, and Croatia. Still, the social context in general did not issue extralegal sanction threats as firmly as might be expected, sometimes even leading to an inversion of morality which actually deterred Kony and Milosevic from not committing any (further) crimes. While a court that is perceived as legitimate can command a significant pool of support which can facilitate the acceptance of unfavorable decisions, and moreover can have a restrictive effect on people’s behavior, the ICTY and ICC, although eventually achieving performance legitimacy, did not achieve audience legitimacy. Nor did Milosevic and Kony perceive the court that prosecuted them as legitimate. Of course, it is hardly surprising that courts have a hard time to be perceived as legitimate by the people they prosecute. However, Tyler’s model of procedural legitimacy points to some important requirements to be perceived more positively. One of these requirements is that the court cannot be perceived as discriminatory. It was problematic, then, that Milosevic regularly accused the ICTY of discriminating against the Serbs and felt that the ICTY was only established by the international community to once again victimize the Serbian people. Kony, on the other hand, felt like the ICC was part of Museveni’s strategy to destroy him. The failure of the ICC to prosecute members of the Ugandan government or the armed forces, gave rise to allegations of partiality, which made Kony feel like the 158 ICC was biased against him. Both in the case of the ICTY and the ICC, these accusations of selective justice were exacerbated by the lack of an effective, properly funded Outreach programme. Because of this, the narratives of discrimination and bias were basically left unchallenged.3 Thus, the restrictive effect the ICTY and ICC could have had on Milosevic and Kony, was largely impeded by a negatively perceived legitimacy. The combination of factors described above offers a multi-causal explanation for why the ICTY and ICC were unable to meaningfully deter Milosevic and Kony from committing any (further) crimes. Although many hoped that these courts would significantly contribute to the ending of human rights violations and the bringing of peace, these hopes were soon shown to be false. In the end, as was explained in the analytical framework, the involvement of the ICTY and ICC was an insufficient obstacle to decrease, instead of increase Kony’s and Milosevic’s strength of commitment to their goals. As such, a certain ‘foot-in-the-door’-effect was created, in which only extremely strong obstacles can make the subject give up its goals. It can be said that the bombing of Serbia proper was such a strong obstacle, finally forcing Milosevic to surrender. Weaker interventions, like the ICTY and ICC delivered, only increase their strength of commitment. Still, one might argue that the involvement of these international legal institutions was better than nothing. The ICC still focused international attention on the conflict in Northern Uganda and the ICTY meant that at least some perpetrators were held accountable. Although the ICTY and ICC wellintentioned interventions indeed did deliver at least some positive change, the risk here is that the involvement of international legal institutions is seen as a panacea for ending the conflict. The ICTY and ICC gave the international community the feeling that it was at least doing something. At first, these courts were therefore a substitute for effective (military or diplomatic) intervention. The conflicts in the former Yugoslavia were only ended after the international community embarked on a path of coercive diplomacy, threatening with air strikes and a further increase in sanctions if the spoilers to the conflict did not give in to its demands. The ICC’s involvement in Northern Uganda did increase international attention for the conflict, although at first this was mostly expressed in the form of increased humanitarian assistance. As such, the limits of retributive justice – and not only to its preventative effect, but also with regards to other goals, such as its potential for bringing about reconciliation, establishing a historical record or individualizing guilt – must be acknowledged.4 3 This was especially so in the case of the ICTY, which in its first years did not have any Outreach programme. In the case of the ICC, this situation was somewhat better, although it remains to be seen if the Court’s activities, and most of all its lack of activities against the UPDF, can be properly explained in Northern Uganda. Moreover, there have been funding problems, which have limited the non-judicial activities of the ICC. 4 Janine Natalya Clark has done important work in this aspect. See, inter alia: Janine Natalya Clark, ‘The Limits of Retributive Justice: Findings of an Empirical Study in Bosnia and Herzegovina’, Journal of International Criminal Justice 7:2 (2009) 463-487; Janine Natalya Clark, ‘The ICC, Uganda and the LRA: Re-Framing the Debate’, African Studies 69:1 (2010) 141-160; Janine Natalya Clark, ‘Peace, Justice and the International Criminal Court: Limitations and Possibilities’, Journal of International Criminal Justice 9:3 (2011) 521-545. 159 The ICTY’s and ICC’s problems with effectively deterring the commitment of mass atrocities can to some extent be explained by looking at the problems as they were laid out in the chapters above. Despite these problems, many still believe in the idea that international criminal justice can contribute to ending conflicts while they are already taking place – one might point to the ICTY’s and ICC’s involvement, but also to the called-for referral of the Syrian conflict to the ICC. The statement by Amnesty International quoted in the introduction – “try asking senior Syrian officials with blood on their hands or the leaders of groups like ISIS and Jabhat al Nusra if they would feel confident in a dock at The Hague” – is characteristic of this belief. There are some logical problems with this thinking, however. Why would anyone in their right mind stop pursuing atrocities after a legal sanction threat if they have already committed them? How could a referral in the Syrian situation have a deterrent effects on the likes of Bashar al-Assad? It is highly unlikely that those who are already so far on what Ervin Staub calls the ‘continuum of destruction’,5 can be dissuaded from committing any further atrocities by a threat of international legal prosecution. Rather, such a threat would make them want to cling on to power even more, since this is the only thing that can prevent them from being captured and put in the docket. And, more often than not, clinging onto power means committing further atrocities. This was both the case with Milosevic in the former Yugoslavia, Kony in Africa, and now with Assad in Syria. According to Staub’s theory of the continuum of destruction and the strength of commitmenttheory, such people can only be stopped by a threat powerful enough to disrupt this continuum, forcing them to give up on their goals. An effective military intervention, or a serious coercive diplomatic effort might therefore be necessary in such cases to prevent further violence and protect the victims. It is striking that the realities of ten years of international criminal justice by the ICC seems to have made Payam Akhavan, who was referred to in the introduction of this piece as one of the ardent supporters of the preventive effect of international criminal justice, change his mind somewhat. In pieces ranging from 1998 to 2009,6 he regularly expressed faith in the potential of deterrence by the International Criminal Court, but in one of his more recent articles called ‘The Rise, and Fall, and Rise of International Criminal Justice’, he argues that it should be realized that international criminal tribunals cannot prevent violence, at least not on their own.7 In his words, “the ICC […] has been decoupled from more effective measures to halt ongoing atrocities” and “we [should not] plac[e] a burden on international criminal justice that it cannot bear, by making it a substitute for, rather than a complement to, preventive action”.8 This 5 Ervin Staub, The Roots of Evil: The Origins of Genocide and Other Group Violence (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989) 17-18. 6 He argued most powerfully for this stance in: Payam Akhavan, ‘Justice in the Hague, peace in the former Yugoslavia?: A Commentary on the United Nations War Crimes Tribunal’, Human Rights Quarterly 20:4 (1998) 737-816; Payam Akhavan, ‘Beyond Impunity: Can International Criminal Justice Prevent Future Atrocities?’, The American Journal of International Law 95:1 (2001) 7-31Payam Akhavan, ‘Are International Criminal Tribunals a Disincentive to Peace?: Reconciling Judicial Romanticism with Political Realism’, Human Rights Quarterly 31:3 (2009) 624-654. 7 Payam Akhavan, ‘The Rise, and Fall, and Rise of International Criminal Justice’, Journal of International Criminal Justice 11:3 (2013) 527-536, 530. 8 Ibid. 160 contribution would like to close with a similar argument. The case studies have shown the complexities of preventing violence in a conflict situation through a psychological and criminological perspective. There is little reason to believe, however, that an increase in the capabilities of international criminal justice, which might solve some of these complexities, will do all that much to increase their deterrence capability. It is unrealistic to expect that the distant threat of international legal prosecution can deter militia leaders or government agents from committing serious crimes. An effective disruption of the continuum of destruction can only be achieved by an effective and powerful intervention, either militarily or diplomatically.9 The role of international criminal justice can then be played out after the violence has been halted. 9 The intervention of peacekeepers and the presence of military troops will also increase the chance of suspects being apprehended. French troops, for example, have recently been playing an important role in the arrest of ICC suspects in African countries. 161 Literature used Articles Akhavan, Payam, ‘Justice in the Hague, peace in the former Yugoslavia?: A Commentary on the United Nations War Crimes Tribunal’, Human Rights Quarterly 20:4 (1998) 737-816. Akhavan, Payam, ‘Beyond Impunity: Can International Criminal Justice Prevent Future Atrocities?’, The American Journal of International Law 95:1 (2001) 7-31. Akhavan, Payam, ‘The Lord’s Resistance Army Case: Uganda’s Submission of the First State Referral to the International Criminal Court’, The American Journal of International Law 99:2 (2005) 403-421. Akhavan, Payam, ‘Are International Criminal Tribunals a Disincentive to Peace?: Reconciling Judicial Romanticism with Political Realism’, Human Rights Quarterly 31:3 (2009) 624-654. Akhavan, Payam, ‘The Rise, and Fall, and Rise of International Criminal Justice’, Journal of International Criminal Justice 11:3 (2013) 527-536. Allen, Tim, ‘Understanding Alice: Uganda’s Holy Spirit Movement in context’, Africa 61:3 (1991) 370-399. Alvarez, Alex, ‘Militias and genocide’, War Crimes, Genocide, & Crimes against Humanity 2 (2006) 1-33. Apel, Robert, ‘Sanctions, Perceptions and Crime: Implications for Criminal Deterrence’, Journal of Quantitative Criminology 29:1 (2012) 67-101. Apuuli, Kasaija Phillip, ‘Peace over Justice: The Acholi Religious Leaders Peace Initiative (ARLPI) vs. the International Criminal Court (ICC) in Northern Uganda’, Studies in Ethnicity and Nationalism 11:1 (2011) 116-129. Armatta, Judith, ‘Historical Revelations from the Milosevic Trial’, Southeastern Europe 36:1 (2012) 10-38. Arzt, Donna E., ´Views on the Ground: The Local Perception of International Criminal Tribunals in the Former Yugoslavia and Sierra Leone’, Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science 603:1 (2006) 226-239. Barria, Lilian A. and Steven D. Roper, ‘How Effective are International Criminal Tribunals? An Analysis of the ICTY and the ICTR’, The International Journal of Human Rights 9:3 (2005) 349-368. Bassiouni, M.Cherif, ‘The ICC – Quo vadis?’, Journal of International Criminal Justice 4:3 (2006) 421-427. Bhavnani, Ravi, ‘Ethnic Norms and Interethnic Violence: Accounting for Mass Participation in the Rwandan Genocide’, Journal of Peace Research 43:6 (2006) 651-669. Blattman, Christopher, ‘From Violence to Voting: War and Political Participation in Uganda’, American Political Science Review 103:2 (2009) 231-247. Bonanno, Anna, ‘The Economic Analysis of Offender’s Choice: Old and New Insights’, Rivista Internazionale di Scienze Economiche e Commerciali 53:2 (2006) 193-224. Bonomy, Iain, ‘The Reality of conducting a War Crimes Trial’, Journal of International Criminal Justice 5:2 (2007) 348-359. Bottoms, Anthony and Justice Tankebe, ‘Beyond Procedural Justice: A Dialogic Approach to Legitimacy in Criminal Justice’, Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology 102:1 (2012) 119170. Bouffard, Jeffrey A., ‘The Influence of Emotion on Rational Decision Making in Sexual Aggression’, Journal of Criminal Justice 30:2 (2002) 121-134. Bozic-Roberson, Agneza, ‘Words Before the War: Milosevic’s Use of Mass Media and Rhetoric to Provoke Ethnopolitical Conflict in Former Yugoslavia’, East European Quarterly 38:4 (2005) 395-408. Branch, Adam, ‘International justice, local injustice: the International Criminal Court in northern Uganda’, Dissent 51:3 (2004) 22-29. Branch, Adam, ‘Uganda’s Civil War and the Politics of ICC Intervention’, Ethics and International Affairs 21:2 (2007) 179-198. Brewer, Cecily G., ‘Peril by Proxy: Negotiating Conflict in East Africa’, International Negotiation 162 16:1 (2011) 137-167. Burchard, Christoph, ‘The Nuremberg Trial and its Impact on Germany’, Journal of International Criminal Justice 4:4 (2006) 800-829. Burke-White, William W., ‘The domestic influence of international criminal tribunals: The International Criminal Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia and the creation of the State Court of Bosnia & Herzegovina’, Columbia Journal of International Law 46:2 (2008) 278-350. Caprara, Gian V. et al., ‘Personality and Politics: Values, Traits, and Political Choice’, Political Psychology 27:1 (2006) 1-28. Cassese, Antonio, ‘The Legitimacy of International Criminal Tribunals and the Current Prospects of International Criminal Justice’, Leiden Journal of International Law 25:2 (2012) 491-501. Castillo, Pablo, ‘Rethinking Deterrence: The International Criminal Court in Sudan’, UNISCI Discussion Papers 13 (2007) 167-184. Clark, Janine Natalya, ‘International War Crimes Tribunals and the Challenge of Outreach’, International Criminal Law Review 9:1 (2009) 99-116. Clark, Janine Natalya, ‘The Limits of Retributive Justice: Findings of an Empirical Study in Bosnia and Herzegovina’, Journal of International Criminal Justice 7:2 (2009) 463-487. Clark, Janine Natalya, ‘The ICC, Uganda and the LRA: Re-Framing the Debate’, African Studies 69:1 (2010) 141-160. Clark, Janine Natalya, ‘Peace, Justice and the International Criminal Court: Limitations and Possibilities’, Journal of International Criminal Justice 9:3 (2011) 521-545. DeGuzman, Margaret M., ‘Gravity and the Legitimacy of the International Criminal Court’, Fordham International Law Journal 32:5 (2008) 1400-1465. Delmas-Marty, Mireille, ‘Ambiguities and Lacunae: The International Criminal Court Ten Years on’, Journal of International Criminal Justice 9:3 (2013) 553-561. Dimitrijevic, Nenad, ‘Serbia after the criminal past: what went wrong and what should be done’, International Journal of Transitional Justice 2:1 (2008) 5-22. Djilas, Aleksa, ‘A profile of Slobodan Milosevic’, Foreign Affairs 72:3 (1993) 81-96. Doom, Ruddy and Koen Vlassenroot, ‘Kony’s message: a new Koine? The Lord’s Resistance Army in northern Uganda’, African Affairs 98:390 (1999) 5-36. Ellis, Mark S., ‘Achieving Justice before the International War Crimes Tribunal: Challenges for the Defense Counsel’, Duke Journal of Comparative and International Law 7:2 (1997) 519-538. Erbeznick, Katherine, ‘Money Can’t Buy You Law: The Effects of Foreign Aid on the Rule of Law in Developing Countries’, Indiana Journal of Global Legal Studies 18:2 (2011) 873-900. Farer, Tom J., ‘Restraining the Barbarians: Can International Criminal Law Help?’, Human Rights Quarterly 22:1 (2000) 90-117. Feinberg, Gary, ‘The International Criminal Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia: The Establishment and Evaluation of a Unique Concept in International Justice Administration’, War Crimes, Genocide, and Crimes Against Humanity 2 (2006) 87-113. Ford, Stuart, ‘A Social Psychology Model of the Perceived Legitimacy of International Criminal Courts: Implications for the Success of Transitional Justice Mechanisms’, Vanderbilt Journal of Transnational Law 45:2 (2012) 405-476. Gerber, Alan S. et al., ‘The Big Five Personality Traits in the Political Arena’, Annual Review of Political Science 14 (2011) 265-287. Glasius, Marlies, ‘Too much law, not enough justice? The dominant role of the legal discourse in transitional justice’, Paper Presented at the Conference “Making Peace and Justice: Images, Histories, Memories”, 22 March 2013, Ottone, Utrecht, NL. Glaurdic, Josip, ‘Inside the Serbian War Machine: The Milosevic Telephone Intercepts’, East European Politics and Societies 23:1 (2009) 86-104. Greifeneder, Raifer, Herbert Bless, and Michel Tuan Pham, ‘When Do People Rely on Affective and Cognitive Feelings in Judgment?: A Review’, Personality and Social Psychological Review 15:2 (2010) 107-141. Hardy, Sam A. and Gustavo Carlo, ‘Identity as a Source of Moral Motivation’, Human Development 48:4 (2005) 232-256. Hawkins, Darren, ‘Power and Interest at the International Criminal Court’, SAIS Review 28:2 (2008) 107-119. 163 Hayden, Robert M., ‘Biased “Justice:” Humanrightsism and the International Criminal Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia’, Cleveland State Law Review 47:4 (2000) 549-573. Hegtvedt, Karen A. and Cathryn Johnson, ‘Power and Justice: Towards an Understanding of Legitimacy’, American Behavioral Scientist 53:3 (2009) 376-399. Henzelin, Marc, Veijo Heiskanen and Guénaël Mettraux, ‘Reparations to Victims before the International Criminal Court: Lessons from International Mass Claims Processes’, Criminal Law Forum 17:3 (2006) 317-344. Higgins, E. Tory, ‘Value from hedonic experience and engagement’, Psychological Review 113:3 (2006) 439–460. Hodson, Gordon, Sarah M. Hogg, and Cara C. Macinnis, ´The Role of “Dark Personalities” (Narcissism, Machiavellianism, Psychopathy), Big Five Personality Factors, and Ideology in Explaining Prejudice’, Journal of Research in Personality 43:4 (2009) 686-690. Holtermann, J. von H., ‘A “Slice of Cheese” – a Deterrence-Based Argument for the International Criminal Court’, Human Rights Review 11:3 (September 2010) 289-315. Horney, Julie and Ineke H. Marshall, ‘Risk Perceptions Among Serious Offenders: The Role of Crime and Punishment’, Criminology 30:4 (1992) 575-594. Iyengar, Sheena S., and Mark R. Lepper, ‘Rethinking the value of choice: A cultural perspective on intrinsic motivation’, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 76:3 (1999) 349–366. Izama, Angelo, ‘Accomplice to Impunity? Rethinking the Political Strategy of the International Criminal Court in Central Africa’, SAIS Review 29:2 (2009) 51-60. Jackson, Jonathan et al., ‘Why Do People Comply with the Law?: Legitimacy and the Influence of Legal Institutions’, British Journal of Criminology 52:6 (2012) 1051-1071. Jacobs, Bruce A., ‘Deterrence and Deterrability’, Criminology 48:2 (2010) 417-441. Jamieson, R. and K. McEvoy, ‘State Crime by Proxy and Juridical Othering’, The British Journal of Criminology 45:4 (2005) 504-527 Jakovljevic, Branislav, ‘From Mastermind to Body Artist: Political Performances of Slobodan Milosevic’, The Drama Review 52:1 (2008) 51-74. Kahneman, Daniel, Jack L. Knetsch and Richard H. Thaler, ‘Experimental Tests of the Endowment Effect and the Coase Theorem’, Journal of Political Economy 98:6 (1990) 1325-1348. Kalter, Frank and Clemens Kroneberg, ‘Rational Choice Theory and Empirical Research: Methodological and Theoretical Contributions in Europe’, Annual Review of Sociology 38 (2012) 73-92. Kim, Hunjoon and Kathryn Sikkink, ‘Explaining the Deterrent Effect of Human RIghts Prosecutions for Transitional Countries’, International Studies Quarterly 54:4 (2010) 939-963. Klarin, Mirko, ‘The Impact of the ICTY Trials on Public Opinion in the Former Yugoslavia’, Journal of International Criminal Justice 7:1 (2009) 89-96. Kleck, Gary et al., ‘The Missing Link in General Deterrence Research’, Criminology 43:3 (2005) 623660. Kress, Claus, ‘‘Self-Referrals’ and ‘Waivers of Complementarity’: Some Considerations in Law and Policy’, Journal of International Criminal Justice 2:4 (2004) 944-948. Kroneberg, Clemens, Isolde Heintze, and Guido Mehlkop, ‘The Interplay of Moral Norms and Instrumental Incentives in Crime Causation’, Criminology 48:1 (2010) 259-294. Ku, Julian and Jide Nzelibe, ‘Do International Criminal Tribunals Deter or Exacerbate Humanitarian Atrocities?’, Washington University Law Review 84:4 (2006) 777-834. Llolos, John J., ‘Justice for Tyrants: International Criminal Court Warrants for Gaddafi Regime Crimes’, Boston College International & Comparative Law Review 35:2 (2012) 589-602. Loewenstein, George, ‘Out of Control: Visceral Influences on Behavior’, Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 65:3 (1996) 272-292. Loewenstein, George, Daniel Nagin and Raymond Paternoster, ‘The Effect of Sexual Arousal on Expectations of Sexual Forcefulness’, Journal of Research in Crime and Delinquency 34:4 (1997) 443-473. Lyon, Charlie, ‘Operation Allied Force: A Lesson on Strategy, Risk, and Tactical Execution’, Comparative Strategy 20:1 (2001) 57-75. Markusen, Eric, ‘The Genocidal Mentality at the Dawn of the Twenty-First Century’, The Aegis Review on Genocide 1:1 (2003) 11-14. 164 Maslow, Abraham, ‘A Theory of Human Motivation’, Psychological Review 50:4 (1943) 370-396. Meernik, James, ‘Justice, Power and Peace: Conflicting Interests and the Apprehension of ICC Suspects’, International Criminal Law Review 13:1 (2013) 169-190. Mendes, Silvia M. and Michael D. McDonald, ‘Putting Severity Back in the Deterrence Package’, Policy Studies Journal 29:4 (2001) 588-610. Mennecke, Martin, ‘Punishing Genocidaires: A Deterrent Effect or Not?’, Human Rights Review 8:4 (2007) 319-339. Miller, Timothy R., ‘The Psychotherapeutic Utility of the Five-Factor Model of Personality: A Clinician’s Experience’, Journal of Personality Assessment 57:3 (1991) 415-433. Milosevic, Slobodan, ‘Is Slobodan Milosevic Guilty of War Crimes? Con’, International Debates 1:5 (2003). Mullins, Christopher W. and Dawn L. Rothe, ‘The Ability of the International Criminal Court to Deter Violations of International Criminal Law: A Theoretical Assessment’, International Criminal Law Review 10:5 (2010) 771-786. Nagin, Daniel S. and Raymond Paternoster, ‘Enduring Individual Differences and Rational Choice Theories of Crime’, Law and Society Review 27:3 (1993) 467-496. Nagin, Daniel S. and Greg Pogarsky, ‘Integrating Celerity, Impulsivity, and Extralegal Sanctions into a Model of General Deterrence: Theory and Evidence’, Criminology 39:4 (2001) 865-892. Nickerson, Raymond S., ‘Confirmation Bias: A Ubiquitous Phenomenon in Many Guises’, Review of General Psychology 2:2 (1998) 175-220. Nkansah, Lydia A., ‘International Criminal Justice in Africa: Some Emerging Dynamics’, Journal of Politics and Law 4:2 (2011) 74-84. O’Donohue, Jonathan, ‘Financing the International Criminal Court’, International Criminal Law Review 13:1 (2013) 269-296. Pappas, Takis S., ‘Shared culture, individual strategy and collective action: explaining Slobodan Milosevic’s charismatic rise to power’, Southeast European and Black Sea Studies 5:2 (2006) 191-211. Parmentier, Stephen and Elmar Weitekamp, ‘Punishing Perpetrators or Seeking Truth for Victims: Serbian Opinions on Dealing with War Crimes’, International Criminal Law Review 13:1 (2013) 43-62. Paternoster, Raymond, ‘How Much Do We Really Know About Criminal Deterrence?’, The Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology 100:3 (2010) 765-823. Paunonen, Sampo V. and Michael C. Ashton, ‘Big Five Predictors of Academic Achievement’, Journal of Research in Personality and Social Psychology 81:3 (2001) 524-539. Peskin, Victor and Mieczyslaw P. Boduszynski, ‘International Justice and Domestic Politics: PostTudjman Croatia and the International Criminal Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia’, EuropeAsia Studies 55:7 (2003) 1117-1142. Pham, Phuom, Patrick Vinck, and Eric Stover, ‘The Lord’s Resistance Army and forced conscription in Northern Uganda’, Human Rights Quarterly 30:2 (2008) 404-411. Pogarsky, Greg, ‘Identifying “Deterrable” Offenders: Implications for Research on Deterrence’, Justice Quarterly 19:3 (2002) 431-452. Pogarsky, Greg, ‘Deterrence and Individual Differences Among Convicted Offenders’, Journal of Quantitative Criminology 23:1 (2007) 59-74. Post, Jerrold M. and Lara K. Panis, ‘Tyranny on Trial: Personality and Courtroom Conduct of Defendants Slobodan Milosevic and Saddam Hussein’, Cornell International Law Journal 38 (2005) 823-836. Prunier, Gerard, ‘Rebel movements and proxy warfare: Uganda, Sudan and the Congo (1986-1999)’, African Affairs 103:412 (2004) 359-383. Quinn, Joanna R., ‘Getting to Peace? Negotiating with the LRA in Northern Uganda’, Human Rights Review 10:1 (2009) 55-71. Ramet, Sabrina P., ‘Review Essay: In search of the ‘real’ Milosevic: new books about the rise and fall of Serbia’s strongman’, Journal of Human Rights 2:3 (2003) 455-466. Ramet, Sabrina P., ‘The ICTY – Controversies, Successes, Failures, Lessons’, Southeastern Europe 36:1 (2012) 1-9. Redlawsk, David P., ‘Hot Cognition or Cool Consideration? Testing the Effects of Motivated 165 Reasoning on Political Decision Making’, Journal of Politics 64:4 (2002) 1021-1044. Rieff, David, ‘Milosevic in Retrospect: An Essay’, Virginia Quarterly Review 82:1 (2006) 8-17 Roach, Steven C., ‘Multilayered Justice in Northern Uganda: ICC Intervention and Local Procedures of Accountability’, International Criminal Law Review 13:1 (2013) 249-268. Robinson, Lucy J. et al., ‘Effects of Intrinsic and Extrinsic Motivation on Attention and Memory’, Acta Psychologica 141:2 (2012) 243-249. Roberts, Andrew, ‘Raving Mad Monster’, Newsweek 158:10 (2011) 41. Robinson, Piers, ‘Misperception in foreign policy making: Operation ‘deliberate force’ and the ending of war in Bosnia’, Civil Wars 4:4 (2001) 115-126. Rodman, Kenneth A., ‘Darfur and the Limits of Legal Deterrence’, Human Rights Quarterly 30:3 (2008) 529-560. Rodman, Kenneth A., ‘Pacting the Law within Politics. Lessons from the International Criminal Court’s First Investigations’, Paper Presented at “Facing the Past: International Conference on the Effectiveness of Remedies for Grave Historical Injustices,” sponsored by the University of Utrecht, Hotel Karel V, Utrecht, the Netherlands, (27-28 May 2010). Rodman, Kenneth A. and Petie Booth, ‘Manipulated Commitments: The International Criminal Court in Uganda’, Human Rights Quarterly 35:2 (2013) 271-303. Ron, James, ‘Territoriality and Plausible Deniability: Serbian Paramilitaries in the Bosnian War’, in: Bruce B. Campbell and Arthur D. Brenner, Death Squads in Global Perspective: Murder with Deniability (New York: St. Martin’s Press, 2000) 287-312. Rothe, Dawn L. and Victoria E. Collins, ‘The International Criminal Court: A Pipe Dream to End Impunity?’, International Criminal Law Review 13:1 (2013) 191-209. Rothe, Dawn L. and Christopher W. Mullins, ‘Beyond the Juristic Orientation of International Criminal Justice: The Relevance of Criminological Insight to International Criminal Law and its Control: A Commentary’, International Criminal Law Review 10:1 (2010) 97-110. Ryan, R.M. and E.L. Deci, ‘Intrinsic and Extrinsic Motivations: Classic Definitions and New Directions’, Contemporary Educational Psychology 25:1 (2000) 54-67. Scharf, Michael P., ‘The Amnesty Exception to the Jurisdiction of the International Criminal Court’, Cornell International Law Journal 32 (1999) 507-527. Schrag, Minna, ‘Lessons Learned from the ICTY Experience’, Journal of International Criminal Justice 2:2 (2004) 427-434. Sell, Louis, ‘Slobodan Milosevic: A Political Biography’, Problems of Post-Communism 46:6 (1999) 12-28. Shafir, Eldar and Robyn A. LeBoeuf, ‘Rationality’, Annual Review of Psychology 53 (2002) 491-517. Shaw, Emily, ‘The Role of Social Identity in Resistance to International Criminal Law: The Case of Serbia and the ICTY’, Berkeley Program in Soviet and Post-Soviet Studies Working Paper Series (2003) 3-31. Sibley, Chris G. and John Duckitt, ‘Personality and Prejudice: A Meta-Analysis and Theoretical Review’, Personality and Social Psychology Review 12:3 (2008) 248-279. Silber, Laura, ‘Milosevic Family Values’, New Republic 221:9 (1999) 23-28. Smeulers, Alette, Barbara Hola and Tom van den Berg, ‘Sixty-Five Years of International Criminal Justice: The Facts and Figures’, International Criminal Law Review 13:1 (2013) 7-41. Soutwhick, Katherine, ‘Investigating War in Northern Uganda: Dilemmas for the International Criminal Court’, Yale Journal of International Affairs 1 (2005) 105-119. Ssenyonjo, Manisuli, ‘The International Criminal Court and the Lord’s Resistance Army Leaders: Prosecution or Amnesty?’, International Criminal Law Review 7:2-3 (2007) 361-389. Ssenyonjo, Manisuli, ‘The Rise of the African Union Opposition to the International Criminal Court’s Investigations and Prosecution of African Leaders’, International Criminal Law Review 13:2 (2013) 385-428. Struett, Michael, ‘The Meaning of the International Criminal Court’, Peace Review 16:3 (2004) 317321. Sullivan, Stacy, ‘Milosevic’s Willing Executioners’, New Republic 220:19 (1999) 26-32. Swart, Mia, ‘Tadic Revisited: Some Critical Comments on the Legacy and the Legitimacy of the ICTY’, Goettingen Journal of International Law 3:3 (2011) 985-1010. Tanner, Samuel and Massimiliano Mulone, ‘Private Security and Armed Conflit: A Case Study of the 166 Scorpions during the Mass Killings in Former Yugoslavia’, The British Journal of Criminology 53:1 (2013) 41-58. Taylor, David, ‘Beyond the Courtroom: The objectives and experience of international trials at the grassroots’, Paper Presented at “Facing the Past: International Conference on the Effectiveness of Remedies for Grave Historical Injustices,” sponsored by the University of Utrecht, Hotel Karel V, Utrecht, the Netherlands (27-28 May 2010). Tittle, Charles R., Ekaterina V. Botchkovar, and Olena Antonaccio, ‘Criminal Contemplation, National Context, and Deterrence’, Journal of Quantitative Criminology 27:2 (2010) 225-249. Tversky, Amos and Daniel Kahneman, ‘Availability: A Heuristic for Judging Frequency and Probability’, Cognitive Psychology 5:2 (1973) 207-232. Tversky, Amos and Daniel Kahneman, ‘Rational Choice and the Framing of Decisions’, The Journal of Business 59:4 (1986) 251-278. Tversky, Amos and Daniel Kahneman, ‘Loss Aversion in Riskless Choice: A Reference-Dependent Model’, Quarterly Journal of Economics 106:4 (1991) 1039-1061. Tyler, Tom R., ‘Procedural Justice, Legitimacy, and the Effective Rule of Law’, Crime and Justice 30 (2003) 284-357. Tyler, Tom R., ‘Psychological Perspectives on Legitimacy and Legitimation’, Annual Review of Psychology 57 (2006) 375-400. Viki, G. Tendayi, Daniel Osgood, and Sabine Phillips, ‘Dehumanization and Self-Reported Proclivity to Torture Prisoners of War’, Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 49:3 (2013) 325328. Williams, Kirk R. and Richard A. Hawkins, ‘Perceptual Research on General Deterrence: A Critical Review’, Law and Society Review 20:4 (1986) 545-572. Wippman, David, ‘Atrocities, Deterrence, and the Limits of International Justice’, Fordham International Law Journal 23 (1999) 473-488. Wippman, David ‘The Costs of International Justice’, The American Journal of International Law 100:4 (2006) 861-881. Yoder, Kevin A., Dan R. Hoyt, and Les B. Whitbeck, ‘Suicidal Behavior Among Homeless and Runaway Adolescents’, Journal of Youth and Adolescence 27:6 (1998) 753-771. Zelditch, Morris, ‘Processes of Legitimation: Recent Developments and New Directions’, Social Psychology Quarterly 64:1 (2001) 4-17. Zelditch, Morris, ‘The Normative Regulation of Power’, Advances in Group Processes 20 (2003) 217-249. Books Allen, Tim, Trial Justice: The International Criminal Court and the Lord’s Resistance Army (London: Zed Books, 2006). Allison Graham T., Essence of Decision: Explaining the Cuban Missile Crisis (Boston: Little Brown, 1971). Andjelic, Bosnia-Herzegovina: The End of a Legacy (London: Frank Cass, 2003). Anzulovic, Branimir, Heavenly Serbia: From Myth to Genocide (New York: New York University Press, 1999). Arendt, Hannah, Eichmann in Jerusalem: A Report on the Banality of Evil (New York: Penguin Books, 2006 [1963]). Ashcraft, Mark H. and Gabriel A. Radvansky, Cognition (5th Edition; Upper Saddle River: Pearson, 2010). Behrend, Heike, Alice Lakwena and the Holy Spirits: War in Northern Uganda, 1985-97 (Kampala: Fountain Publishers, 1999). Bellamy, Alex J., Kosovo and International Society (New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2002). Boas, Gideon, The Milosevic Trial: Lessons for the Conduct of Complex International Criminal Proceedings (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007). Browning, Christopher R., Ordinary Men. Reserve Police Battalion 101 and the Final Solution in Poland (London: Vintage, 1992). Bujosevic, Dragan and Ivan Radovanovic, The Fall of Milosevic: The October 5th Revolution (New 167 York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2003). Cigar, Norman and Paul Williams, Indictment at The Hague: the Milosevic regime and crimes of the Balkan War (New York: New York University Press, 2002). Cohen, Lenard J., Serpent in the Bosom: the Rise and Fall of Slobodan Milosevic (Boulder: Westview Press, 2001). Cooper, Robert W., The Nuremberg Trial (London: Faber & Faber, 2011). Del Ponte, Carla, Madame Prosecutor: Confrontations with Humanity’s Worst Criminals and the Culture of Impunity (New York: Other Press, 2008). Djukic, Slavoljub, Milosevic and Markovic: A Lust for Power (Montreal & Kingston: McGill-Queen’s University Press, 2001). Dolan, Chris, Understanding War and Its Continuation: The Case of Northern Uganda (London: Development Studies Institute, London School of Economics, 2005). Drumbl, Mark A., Atrocity, Punishment and International Law (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007). Eichstaedt, Peter, First kill your family – Child soldiers of Uganda and the Lord’s Resistance Army (Chicago: Lawrence Hill Books, 2009). Filipovic, Zlata, Zlata’s Diary – A Child’s Life in Sarajevo (London: Puffin Books, 1995). Finlan, Alastair, The Collapse of Yugoslavia 1991-1999 (Oxford: Osprey Publishing, 2004). Gersony, Robert, The Anguish of Northern Uganda: Results of a field-based assessment of the civil conflicts in Northern Uganda (Kampala: USAID Mission, 1997). Goldhagen, Daniel J., Hitler’s Willing Executioners: Ordinary Germans and the Holocaust (London: Vintage, 1997). Goleman, Daniel, Vital Lies, Simple Truths: The psychology of self-deception (New York: Simon & Schuster, 1996) Gottfredson, Michael R. and Travis Hirschi, A General Theory of Crime (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1990). Gow, James, The Serbian project and its adversaries: a strategy of war crimes (London: C. Hurst, 2003). Green, Matthew, The Wizard of the Nile: The Hunt for Africa’s Most Wanted (London: Portobello Books, 2008). Higgins, E. Tory, Beyond Pleasure and Pain: How Motivation Works (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011). Honwana, Alcinda, Child Soldiers in Africa (Philadelphia: University Press of Pennsylvania, 2011). Ignatieff, Michael, Virtual War: Kosovo and Beyond (London: Chatto & Windus, 2000). Ivkovic, Sanja K. and John Hagan, Reclaiming justice: the international tribunal for the former Yugoslavia and the local courts (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011). Jackson, Robert and Georg Sørensen, Introduction to International Relations: Theories & Approaches (4th Edition; Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010). Kastner, Philipp, International Criminal Justice in bello?: The ICC between Law and Politics in Darfur and Northern Uganda (Leiden: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, 2012). Kelman, Herbert C. and V.Lee Hamilton, Crimes of Obedience: Toward a Social Psychology of Authority and Responsibility (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1989). Kershaw, Ian, Hitler: 1936-1945 (New York: W.W. Norton, 2000). Kissinger, Henry, White House Years (New York: Little, Brown and Company, 1979). Larsen, Randy J. and David M. Buss, Personality Psychology: Domains of Knowledge About Human Nature (4th Edition: New York: McGraw Hill, 2010). LeBor, Adam, Slobodan Milosevic: Biografie (Amsterdam: Uitgeverij Balans, 2002). Lilly, J. Robert, Francis T. Cullen, and Richard A. Ball, Criminological Theory: Context and Consequences (5th Edition; Thousand Oaks: Sage Publications, 2011). Listhaug, Ola, Sabrina P. Ramet, and Dragana Dulic (eds.), Civic and Uncivic Values: Serbia in the post-Milosevic era (Budapest and New York: Central European University Press, 2011). McCrae, Robert R. and Paul T. Costa, Personality in Adulthood (New York: Guilford Press, 1990). Milgram, Stanley, Obedience to Authority: An Experimental View (New York: Harper & Row, 1974). Museveni, Yoweri K., Sowing the Mustard Seed: The struggle from freedom and democracy in Uganda (London: Macmillan, 1997). 168 Oloya, Opis, Child to Soldier: Stories from Joseph Kony’s Lord’s Resistance Army (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2013). Pikis, Georghios M., The Rome Statute for the International Criminal Court. Analysis of the Statute, the Rules of Procedure and Evidence, the Regulations of the Court and Supplementary Instruments (Leiden: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, 2010). Post, Jerrold M., Leaders and their Followers in a Dangerous World: The Psychology of Political Behavior (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2004). Ramet, Sabrina P., Konrad Clewing, and Reneo Lukic (eds.), Croatia since Independence: War, Politics, Society, Foreign Relations (Munich: R. Oldenbourg, 2008). Raz, Joseph, Between Authority and Interpretation (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009). Reyntjens, Filip, The Great African War: Congo and Regional Geopolitics, 1996-2006 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010). Robertson, Geoffrey, Crimes against Humanity: The Struggle for Global Justice (London: Penguin Books, 2000). Rothe, Dawn and Christopher W. Mullins, The International Criminal Court: Symbolic Gestures and the Generation of Global Social Control (Lexington: Lexington Books, 2006). Sadock, Benjamin J. and Virginia A. Sadock, Kaplan & Sadock’s Synopsis of Psychiatry (10th Edition; Philadelphia: Lippincott Williams & Wilkins, 2007). Schrader, Charles R., The Muslim-Croat Civil War: A Military History, 1992-1994 (College Station: Texas A&M University Press, 2003). Sell, Louis, Slobodan Milosevic and the Destruction of Yugoslavia (Durham: Duke University Press, 2002). Service, Robert, Stalin: A Biography (Harvard: Harvard University Press, 2006). Silber, Laura and Alan Little, The Death of Yugoslavia (London: Penguin Books, 1996). Smeulers, Alette and Fred Grünfeld, International Crimes and Other Gross Human Rights Violations: A Multi- and Interdisciplinary Textbook (Leiden: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, 2011). Snyder, Jack, From Voting to Violence: Democratization and Nationalist Conflict (London: W.W. Norton & Company, 2000). Staub, Ervin, The Roots of Evil: The Origins of Genocide and Other Group Violence (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989). Stewart, Christopher S., Hunting the Tiger – the Fast Life and Violent Death of the Balkans most Dangerous Man (New York: Thomas Dunne Books, 2007). Thaler, Richard H. and Cass R. Sunstein, Nudge: Improving Decisions About Health, Wealth, and Happiness (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2008). Totani, Yuma, The Tokyo War Crimes Trial: The Pursuit of Justice in the Wake of World War II (Cambridge: Harvard University Asia Center, 2009). Tripp, Aili Mari, Museveni’s Uganda: Paradoxies of Power in a Hybrid Regime (Boulder: Lynne Rienner Publishers, 2010). Waller, James, Becoming Evil: How Ordinary People Commit Genocide and Mass Killing (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002). Weber, Max, Economy and Society (4th Edition; Berkely: University of California Press, 1978). Zimmerman, Warren, Origins of a Catastrophe (New York: Random House, 1996) Book chapters Allen, Tim and Koen Vlassenroot, ‘Introduction’, in: Tim Allen and Koen Vlassenroot (eds.), The Lord’s Resistance Army: Myth and Reality (London: Zed Books, 2010) 1-21. Alvarez, Alex, ‘Destructive Beliefs: Genocide and the Role of Ideology’, in: Alette Smeulers and Roelof Haveman (eds.), Supranational Criminology: Towards a Criminology of International Crimes (Antwerp: Intersentia, 2008) 213-231. Andersen, Erik A., ‘The International Military Tribunals in Nuremberg and Tokyo. Epoch-making and standard-setting, yet with different effects’, in: Cedric Ryngaert (ed.), The effectiveness of transitional justice (Antwerp: Intersentia, 2009) 3-26. Atkinson, Ronald R., ‘‘The realists in Juba’? An analysis of the Juba peace talks’, in: Tim Allen and 169 Koen Vlassenroot, The Lord’s Resistance Army: Myth and Reality (London: Zed Books, 2010) 205-222. Biro, Miklos et al., ‘Attitudes towards justice and social reconstruction in Bosnia and Herzegovina and Croatia’, in: Eric Stover and Harvey M. Weinstein (eds.), My neighbor, my enemy: justice and community after mass atrocity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004) 183-205. Brubacher, Matthew, ‘The ICC investigation of the Lord’s Resistance Army: an insider’s view’, in: Tim Allen and Koen Vlassenroot, The Lord’s Resistance Army: Myth and Reality (London: Zed Books, 2010) 262-277. Clark, Phil, ‘Law, Politics and Pragmatism: The ICC and Case Selection in the Democratic Republic of Congo and Uganda’, in: Nicholas Waddell and Phil Clark (eds.), Courting Conflict? Justice, Peace and the ICC in Africa, (London: Royal African Society, 2008) 37-45. Finnström, Sverker, ‘An African hell of colonial imagination? The Lord’s Resistance Army in Uganda: another story’, in: Tim Allen and Koen Vlassenroot (eds.), The Lord’s Resistance Army: Myth and Reality (London: Zed Books, 2010) 74-89. Friedrichs, David O., ‘Towards a Criminology of International Crimes: Producing a Conceptual and Contextual Framework’, in: Alette Smeulers and Roelof Haveman (eds.), Supranational Criminology: Towards a Criminology of International Crimes (Berlin: Springer, 2008) 29-49. Furley, Oliver, ‘Uganda: The Struggle for Peace’, in: Oliver Furley and Roy May (eds.), Ending Africa’s Wars: Progressing to Peace (Aldershot: Ashgate Publishing Ltd., 2006) 116-133. Goetz, Mariana, ‘The International Criminal Court and its Relevance to Affected Communities’, in: Nicholas Waddell and Phil Clark, Courting Conflict? Justice, Peace and the ICC in Africa (London: Royal African Society, 2008) 65-72. Grono, Nick and Adam O’Brien, ‘Justice in Conflict? The ICC and Peace Processes’, in: Nicholas Waddell and Phil Clark (eds.), Courting Conflict? Justice, Peace and the ICC in Africa, (London: Royal African Society, 2008) 13-20. Haveman, Roelof, ‘Supranational Expectations of a Punitive Approach’, in: Roelof Haveman and Olaoluwa Olusanya (eds.), Sentencing and Sanctioning in Supranational Criminal Law (Antwerp: Intersentia, 2006) 145-160. Haveman, Roelof and Alette Smeulers, ‘Criminology in a State of Denial – Towards a Criminology of International Crimes: Supranational Criminology’, in Alette Smeulers and Roelof Haveman (eds.), Supranational Criminology: Towards a Criminology of International Crimes (Berlin: Springer, 2008) 23-26. Iya, Ronald, ‘Encountering Kony: a Madi perspective’, in: Tim Allen and Koen Vlassenroot, The Lord’s Resistance Army: Myth and Reality (London: Zed Books, 2010) 177-184. King, Curtis S., ‘The Siege of Sarajevo, 1992-1995’, in: William G. Robertson and Lawrence A. Yates (eds.), Block by Block: The Challenges of Urban Operations (Fort Leavenworth, KA: U.S. Army Command and General Staff College Press, 2003) 235-290. Moreno-Ocampo, Luis, ‘The Role of the International Community in Assisting the International Criminal Court to Secure Justice and Accountability’, in: Raymond Provost and Payam Akhavan (eds.), Confronting Genocide (Berlin: Springer, 2011) 279-289. Mullins, Christopher W., ‘Conflict victimization and post-conflict justice 1945-2008’, in: M. Cherif Bassiouni (ed.), The Pursuit of International Criminal Justice: A World Study on Conflicts, Victimization, and Post-Conflict Justice (Antwerp: Intersentia, 2010) 67-108. Mullins, Christopher W., ‘The International Criminal Court’, in: M. Cherif Bassiouni, The Pursuit of International Criminal Justice: A World Study on Conflicts, Victimization, and Post-Conflict Justice. Volume 1 (Antwerp: Intersentia, 2010) 399-421. Mwenda, Andrew, ´Uganda´s politics of foreign aid and violent conflict: the political uses of the LRA rebellion’, in: Tim Allen and Koen Vlassenroot (eds.), The Lord’s Resistance Army: Myth and Reality (London: Zed Books, 2010) 45-58. Otim, Michael and Marieke Wierda, ‘Justice at Juba: International Obligations and Local Demands in Northern Uganda’, in: Nicholas Waddell and Phil Clark (eds.), Courting Conflict? Justice, Peace and the ICC in Africa, (London: Royal African Society, 2008) 21-28. Perrot, Sandrine, ‘Northern Uganda: a ‘forgotten conflict’, again? The impact of the 170 internationalization of the resolution process’, in: Tim Allen and Koen Vlassenroot, The Lord’s Resistance Army: Myth and Reality (London: Zed Books, 2010) 187-204. Pogarsky, Greg, ‘Deterrence and Decision Making: Research Questions and Theoretical Refinements’, in: Marvin D. Krohn et al. (eds.), Handbook on Crime and Deviance (Berlin: Springer, 2009) 241-258. Schomerus, Mareike, ‘‘A terrorist person is not a person like me’: an interview with Joseph Kony’, in: Tim Allen and Koen Vlassenroot, The Lord’s Resistance Army: Myth and Reality (London: Zed Books, 2010) 113-131. Simpson, Graeme, ‘One among Many: The ICC as a Tool of Justice during Transition’, in: Nicholas Waddell and Phil Clark, Courting Conflict? Justice, Peace and the ICC in Africa (London: Royal African Society, 2008) 73-80. Smeulers, Alette, ‘Perpetrators of International Crimes: Towards a Typology’, in: Alette Smeulers and Roelof Haveman (eds.), Supranational Criminology: Towards a Criminology of International Crimes (Antwerp: Intersentia, 2008) 233-265. Titeca, Kristof, ‘The spiritual order of the LRA’, in: Tim Allen and Koen Vlassenroot (eds.), The Lord’s Resistance Army: Myth and Reality (London: Zed Books, 2010) 59-73. Waddell, Nicholas and Phil Clark, ‘Introduction’, in: Nicholas Waddell and Phil Clark, Courting Conflict? Justice, Peace and the ICC in Africa (London: Royal African Society, 2008) 7-12. Online resources Allen, Tim and Mareike Schomerus, A hard homecoming. Lessons learned from the reception centre process in Northern Uganda – and independent study, Management Systems International, (15 August 2006), available online at: http://pdf.usaid.gov/pdf_docs/PNADI241.pdf Amnesty International, ‘Dozens of UN members urge immediate ICC referral of ‘desperate’ situation in Syria’, (14 January 2013), available online at: http://www.amnesty.org/en/news/dozens-un-members-urge-immediate-icc-referral-desperatesituation-syria-2013-01-14 Amnesty International, ‘The countries that support referring Syria to the International Criminal Court – and some absent ‘friends’’, (20 September 2013), available online at: http://www2.amnesty.org.uk/blogs/campaigns/syria-icc-international-criminal-court Belgrade Center for Human Rights, ‘Public opinion in Serbia: Views on domestic war crimes, judicial authorities and the Hague tribunal’, OSCE, (2006), available online at: http://www.osce.org/serbia/24241 Beaumont, Peter and Adam Gabbatt, ‘Ratko Mladic arrested, Serbian president confirms’, The Guardian, (26 May 2011), available online at: http://www.guardian.co.uk/world/2011/may/26/ratko-mladic-arrested-serbian-president Beayo, Mohammed Omar, ‘Following the Revolution, Militias Continue to Terrorize Libya’, AlMonitor, (27 June 2013), available online at: http://www.almonitor.com/pulse/tr/contents/articles/politics/2013/06/libya-militias-brute-forcebenghazi.html# Borden, Anthony, ‘Milosevic Rages Against the West’, Institute for War & Peace Reporting, (15 February 2002), available online at: http://iwpr.net/report-news/milosevic-rages-against-west Del Ponte, Carla, Opening arguments by the Prosecutor, (12 February 2002), available online at: http://www.icty.org/x/cases/slobodan_milosevic/trans/en/020212IT.htm Gerson, Michael, ‘The worthy mission to get Joseph Kony’, The Washington Post, (17 October 2011), available online at: http://articles.washingtonpost.com/2011-10-17/opinions/35276891_1_lrajoseph-kony-special-operations-forces Gettleman, Jeffrey, ‘In Vast Jungle, U.S. Troops Aid in Search for Kony’, The New York Times, (27 November 2013), available online at: http://www.nytimes.com/2012/04/30/world/africa/konytracked-by-us-forces-in-central-africa.html?ref=josephkony&_r=0 Hammond, Joseph, ‘M23’s Congo Cadres: The Rebel Movement with a Taste for Local Politics’, Think Africa Press, (23 October 2013), available online at: http://thinkafricapress.com/drc/m23-cadres-key-grip-power Hovil, Lucy and Joanna R. Quinn, Peace First, Justice Later: Traditional Justice in Northern 171 Uganda, Refugee Law Project Working Paper No. 17, (July 2005), available online at: http://www.refugeelawproject.org/working_papers/RLP.WP17.pdf Human Rights Watch, Uprooted and Forgotten: Impunity and Human Rights Abuses in Northern Uganda, (20 September 2005), available online at: http://www.hrw.org/sites/default/files/reports/uganda0905.pdf Human Rights Watch, The Christmas Massacres: The LRM/A attacks on civilians in northern Congo, (16 February 2009), available online at: http://www.hrw.org/sites/default/files/reports/drc0209web_0.pdf Human Rights Watch, A Long Way from Reconciliation, (19 November 2012), available online at: http://www.hrw.org/reports/2012/11/18/long-way-reconciliation Human Rights Watch, “Letting the Big Fish Swim”: Failures to Prosecute High-Level Corruption in Uganda, (21 October 2013), available online at: http://www.hrw.org/sites/default/files/reports/uganda1013_ForUpload_0.pdf International Criminal Court, ‘All Situations’, available online at: http://www.icccpi.int/en_menus/icc/situations%20and%20cases/situations/Pages/situations%20index.aspx International Criminal Court, ‘How Many Countries Have Ratified the Rome Statute?’, available online at: www.icccpi.int/en_menus/icc/about%20the%20court/frequently%20asked%20questions/Pages/4.aspx International Criminal Court, ‘ICC – Joint Statement by ICC Chief Prosecutor and the visiting Delegation of Lango, Acholi, Iteso and Madi Community Leaders from Northern Uganda’, ICC Press Release, (16 April 2005), available online at: http://www.icccpi.int/en_menus/icc/situations%20and%20cases/situations/situation%20icc%200204/press%2 0releases/Pages/joint%20statement%20by%20icc%20chief%20prosecutor%20and%20the%20 visiting%20delegation%20of%20lango%20ach.aspx International Criminal Court, ‘ICC report to UN details busiest year yet, urges Security Council support’, (8 October 2013), available online at: http://www.icccpi.int/en_menus/icc/press%20and%20media/press%20releases/Pages/pr951.aspx International Criminal Court, ‘Office of the Prosecutor’, available online at: http://www.icccpi.int/en_menus/icc/structure%20of%20the%20court/office%20of%20the%20prosecutor/Pag es/office%20of%20the%20prosecutor.aspx International Criminal Court, Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court, (17 July 1998), available online at: http://www.icc-cpi.int/NR/rdonlyres/ADD16852-AEE9-4757-ABE79CDC7CF02886/283503/RomeStatutEng1.pdf International Criminal Court, ‘Situation in Uganda’, available online at: http://www.icccpi.int/EN_Menus/ICC/Situations%20and%20Cases/Situations/Situation%20ICC%200204/Pa ges/situation%20index.aspx International Criminal Court, ‘The Presidency’, available online at: http://www.icccpi.int/en_menus/icc/structure%20of%20the%20court/presidency/Pages/the%20presidency.as px International Criminal Court, The Prosecutor v. Joseph Kony, Vincent Otti, Okot Odhiambo and Dominic Ongwen, Case No. ICC-02/04-01/05, available online at: http://www.icccpi.int/en_menus/icc/situations%20and%20cases/situations/situation%20icc%200204/related %20cases/icc%200204%200105/Pages/uganda.aspx International Criminal Court, The Prosecutor v. Omar Hassan Ahmad al-Bashir, Case No. ICC02/05-01/09, available online at: http://www.icccpi.int/en_menus/icc/situations%20and%20cases/situations/situation%20icc%200205/related %20cases/icc02050109/Pages/icc02050109.aspx International Criminal Court, The Prosecutor v. Thomas Lubanga Dyilo, Case No. ICC-01/0301/06, available online at: http://www.icccpi.int/en_menus/icc/situations%20and%20cases/situations/situation%20icc%200104/related %20cases/icc%200104%200106/Pages/democratic%20republic%20of%20the%20congo.aspx 172 International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia, Indictment against Slobodan Milosevic et al. “Kosovo”, Case No. IT-99-37-PT, available online at: http://www.icty.org/x/cases/slobodan_milosevic/ind/en/mil-2ai011029e.htm International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia, Indictment against Slobodan Milosevic “Kosovo, Croatia & Bosnia”, Case No. IT-02-54-T, available online at: http://www.icty.org/x/cases/slobodan_milosevic/ind/en/mil-ai040421-e.htm International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia, Tadic. “Prijedor”, Case No. IT-94-1, available online at: http://www.icty.org/case/tadic/4#ind International Crisis Group, Northern Uganda: Understanding and Solving the Conflict, Africa Report No. 77, (14 April 2004), available online at: http://www.crisisgroup.org/~/media/Files/africa/horn-ofafrica/uganda/Northern%20Uganda%20Understanding%20and%20Solving%20the%20Confli ct.pdf International Crisis Group, A Strategy for Ending Northern Uganda’s Crisis, Africa Briefing No. 35, (11 January 2006), available online at: http://www.crisisgroup.org/~/media/Files/africa/horn-ofAfrica/uganda/B035%20A%20Strategy%20for%20Ending%20Northern%20Ugandas%20Cris is.pdf Invisible Children and The Resolve, ‘LRA Crisis Tracker’, (2 December 2013), available online at: http://www.lracrisistracker.com/ Jacobs, Dov, ‘The ICC authorizes first use of OTP proprio motu powers in Kenya: Opening a new Pandora’s Box of legal difficulties (and revisiting some old ones too…)’, The Netherlands School of Human Rights Research, (7 April 2010), available online at: http://invisiblecollege.weblog.leidenuniv.nl/2010/04/07/the-icc-authorizes-first-use-of-otpprop/ Jivanda, Tomas, ‘Syria crisis: ‘Massive evidence’ implicates Bashar al-Assad in war crimes says UN’, The Independent, (2 December 2013), available online at: http://www.independent.co.uk/news/world/middle-east/massive-evidence-implicates-basharalassad-in-war-crimes-says-un-8978193.html Keatly, Patrick, ‘Obituary: Idi Amin’, The Guardian, (18 August 2003), available online at: http://www.theguardian.com/news/2003/aug/18/guardianobituaries Lomo, Zachary and Lucy Hovil, Behind the Violence: Causes, Consequences and the Search for Solutions to the War in Northern Uganda, Refugee Law Project Working Paper no. 11, (February 2004), available online at: http://www.issafrica.org/uploads/Mono99.pdf McCartney, Stewart, ‘Despite M23 Defeat, Militias Still Threat to Congo’, Institute for War and Peace Reporting, (20 November 2013), available online at: http://iwpr.net/reportnews/despite-m23-defeat-militias-still-threat-congo Milosevic, Slobodan, Opening Arguments, (14-15 February 2002), online available at: http://www.icty.org/x/cases/slobodan_milosevic/trans/en/020214IT.htm Minegar, Benjamin, ‘Africa leaders should be immune from ICC prosecution: AU’, Jurist, (13 October 2013), available online at: http://jurist.org/paperchase/2013/10/africa-leaders-shouldbe-immune-from-icc-prosecution-au.php Momanyi, Bernard, ‘Ugandan Leader Lashes Out at ICC’, Institute for War and Peace Reporting (20 April 2013), available online at: http://iwpr.net/report-news/ugandan-leader-lashes-out-icc Mroue, Bassem, ‘Watchdog: More than 120.000 killed in Syria war’, The Washington Times, (31 October 2013), available online at: http://www.washingtontimes.com/news/2013/oct/31/watchdog-more-120000-killed-syria-war/ Office of the High Commissioner for Human Rights, ‘Côte d’Ivoire: UN call for investigations into serious human rights abuses by traditional hunters’, (6 December 2013), available online at: http://www.ohchr.org/EN/NewsEvents/Pages/DisplayNews.aspx?NewsID=14071&LangID=E Oketch, Bill, ‘“Kony 2012” Campaign Too Late in North Uganda’, Institute for War and Peace Reporting, (20 March 2012), available online at: http://iwpr.net/report-news/kony-2012campaign-too-late-north-uganda Payne, Doris, ‘The Nilotic Language Family’, (June 2002), available online at: http://pages.uoregon.edu/dlpayne/Nilotic/NiloticFamily.htm 173 Raghavan, Sudarsan and Craig Whitlock, ‘Hunt for Joseph Kony, elusive African warlord, is halted’, The Washington Post, (3 April 2013), available online at: http://articles.washingtonpost.com/2013-04-03/world/38238379_1_central-african-republiclra-dominic-ongwen Rubin, Elizabeth, ‘How a Texas Philantropist Helped Fund the Hunt for Joseph Kony’, The New Yorker, (21 October 2013), available online at: http://www.newyorker.com/online/blogs/newsdesk/2013/10/how-a-texas-philanthropistfunded-the-hunt-for-joseph-kony.html?printable=true&currentPage=all#ixzz2ijfnrFzo Sands, Philippe, ‘Referring Syria to the International Criminal Court is a Justified Gamble’, The Guardian, (16 January 2013), available online at: http://www.guardian.co.uk/commentisfree/2013/jan/16/syria-international-criminal-courtjustified-gamble Serbian Academy of Arts and Sciences, ‘Memorandum 1986 (the Greater Serbian Ideology)’, (24 September 1986), available online at: http://www.trepca.net/english/2006/serbian_memorandum_1986/serbia_memorandum_1986.h tml Stuster, J. Dana, ‘Don’t Believe the Hype: Joseph Kony Isn’t About to Surrender’, Foreign Policy, (21 November 2013), available online at: http://blog.foreignpolicy.com/posts/2013/11/21/dont_believe_the_hype_joseph_kony_isnt_ab out_to_surrender Toncic, Bojan, ‘Serbia: Milosevic Trial Grips Nation’, Institute for War & Peace Reporting Crisis Report #318, (15 February 2002), available online at: http://iwpr.net/report-news/serbiamilosevic-trial-grips-nation Tran, Mark, ‘Joseph Kony cannot be swept under the carpet, warns DRC priest turned activist’, The Guardian, (6 November 2013), http://www.theguardian.com/globaldevelopment/2013/nov/06/joseph-kony-drc-abbe-benoit-kinalegu Tzortzi, Ellie, ‘Karadzic Arrested in Serbia, worked as doctor’, Reuters, (22 July 2008), available online at: http://www.reuters.com/article/2008/07/22/us-warcrimes-karadzicidUSL2196241820080722 United Nations News Centre, ‘UN welcomes South Sudan as 193rd Member State’, (14 July 2011), available online at: http://www.un.org/apps/news/story.asp?NewsID=39034&Cr=South+Sudan&Cr1=#.UnvpIPkr dBk United Nations Security Council, ‘Resolution 827 (1993), (25 May 1993), available online at: www.un.org/en/ga/search/view_doc.asp?symbol=S/RES/827(1993) United Nations Security Council, ‘Resolution 1593 (2005)’, (31 March 2005), available online at: http://www.un.org/en/ga/search/view_doc.asp?symbol=S/RES/1593(2005) United Nations Security Council, ‘Resolution 1970 (2011)’, (26 February 2011), available online at: http://www.un.org/en/ga/search/view_doc.asp?symbol=S/RES/1970(2011) Urquhart, Conal, ‘Joseph Kony: African Union brigade to hunt down LRA leader’, The Guardian, (24 March 2012), available online at: http://www.theguardian.com/world/2012/mar/24/josephkony-african-union-brigade Verini, James, ‘The Battle for South Kordofan’, Foreign Policy, (22 January 2013), available online at: http://www.foreignpolicy.com/articles/2013/01/22/the_battle_for_south_kordofan_sudan Wagner, Daniel and Giorgio Cafiero, ‘The Central African Republic’s Coming Genocide’, The Huffington Post, (3 December 2013), available online at: http://www.huffingtonpost.com/daniel-wagner/the-central-african-repub_2_b_4377563.html Zak, Tomas, ‘Kenyatta in Court’, Think Africa Press, (12 November 2013), available online at: http://thinkafricapress.com/kenya/manipulation-and-misinformation-kenyatta-and-icc-question 174