Abstracts: Robert Kurzban: "Why everyone (else) is a hypocrite". In this talk, I will argue that the key to understanding our behavioral inconsistencies lies in understanding the mind's design. The human mind consists of many specialized units designed by the process of evolution by natural selection. While these modules sometimes work together seamlessly, they don't always, resulting in impossibly contradictory beliefs, vacillations between patience and impulsiveness, violations of our supposed moral principles, and overinflated views of ourselves. This modular, evolutionary psychological view of the mind undermines deeply held intuitions about ourselves, as well as a range of scientific theories that require a "self" with consistent beliefs and preferences. Modularity suggests that there is no "I." Instead, each of us is a contentious "we"--a collection of discrete but interacting systems whose constant conflicts shape our interactions with one another and our experience of the world. Edmund Henden: “Addiction, Bias and Autonomy”. What is it about addiction that impairs addicts’ autonomy and how can such impairment be explained? According to a standard philosophical account what addictive behavior lacks which, were it present, would make this behavior autonmous, is a certain form of “self-governance”. In this talk, I consider three versions of this account (synchronic, historical and diachronic), all of which I argue fail to explain the autonomy impairment characteristic of addicts. The reason they fail, however, is not that addicts are in fact fully autonomous (as some have claimed), but that these accounts rest on an insufficient conception of autonomy. One issue that has received surprisingly little philosophical consideration concerns the role of attention in autonomous behavior. This is a relevant issue because there is empirical evidence suggesting that addicts’ decisional capacity is impaired primarily because it is affected by drug-related attentional bias. I propose an explanation of why and how such bias might be thought to undermine addicts’ autonomy that does not rule out that many addicts can be “self-governing” agents. Justyna Klingemann: “The Congruence between Lay and professional Concepts of Alcohol Addiction". The issue of a congruence between lay and professional concepts of alcohol addiction is explored on the basis of the Polish qualitative data. The presented study identifies and categorizes concepts of addiction among treated and non-treated former alcohol dependents, and their function in the process of recovery from addiction within the post-communist treatment system dominated by the Minnesota model. Methods: This qualitative study is based on a media recruited sample of 29 former alcohol dependents (ICD-10) in Warsaw/Poland 2006/2007. They reported a recovery time of at least 2 years. In-depth interviews were analyzed according to the PCI method using Atlas.ti software. The applied triangulation procedures ensure reliability and validity of the data collected and the analysis of the narrative accounts. Results: The results of the study show that professional concepts of addiction reconstructed on the basis of narratives from treated respondents resemble the disease model of addiction. A first category of lay concepts of self-changers adopt a medical–moral model of 1 dependence including strong will as a key element of the successful recovery. A second category describes dependence as a symptom of maladaptive social functioning and recovery as a process of understanding one’s role in society and fulfilling social expectations. While self-changers relied on one of these lay concepts, treated respondents were confronted with a conflict between lay and professional definition of dependence. Conclusions: It is argued that lack of recognition of lay concepts of addiction by treatment providers may weaken help-seeking and increase drop-out rates. Moreover, the disease model implies the stability of the status of the alcoholic – which potentially affects the individual’s sense of autonomy and – consequently - weakens his/her chances to reach the stage of stable recovery. Carl Hart: "Ask the wrong question, get the wrong answer". If you ask the wrong question, be prepared to get the wrong answer. Whether addiction is a disease or a matter of choice is not a question that is even important. There are cases in which addiction falls under both classifications. While the vast majority of users do so without endangering their safely, many people struggle to control their intake of various substances, which have disrupted their ability to function.The better question is how do we best treat drug addiction? In recent years a disturbingly narrow focus on addiction as a biologically based disease has evolved, even though there are extremely limited data to support this view. As a result, efforts to develop treatments for drug addiction have overwhelmingly concentrated on searching for medications that correct some nebulous underlying biological deficit to the exclusion of addressing other important contributing factors such as co-morbid psychiatric disorders and the lack of better alternatives to drugs. The more I studied actual drug use in people, the more I became convinced that it was a behavior that was amenable to change like any other. So why did it seem so intractable in poor neighborhoods? A key problem is that poor people actually have few “competing reinforcers.” Crack or any other drug isn’t really all that overwhelmingly good or powerfully reinforcing: it gained the popularity that it achieved in the ‘hood (far less than advertised) because there weren’t that many other affordable sources of pleasure and purpose and because many of the people at the highest risk had other pre-existing mental illnesses that affected their choices. While drug use rates are similar across classes, addiction — like most other illnesses — is not an equal-opportunity disorder. Like cancer and heart disease, it disproportionately affects the poor, who have far less access to healthy diets and consistent medical care. In a series of experiments, my colleagues and I began investigating some of these questions. In one study, we gave methamphetamine addicts a choice between taking a big hit of methamphetamine (50 mg.) or five dollars in cash. They took the drug on about half of the opportunities. But when we increased the amount of money to twenty dollars, they almost never chose the drug. We had gotten similar results with crack cocaine addicts in an earlier study. This told me that the addictive potential of methamphetamine or crack was not what had been previously claimed; their addictiveness wasn’t extraordinary. Our results also demonstrated that addicts can and do make rational decisions and this information could be used to inform treatment development efforts.Treatments based on providing alternatives to drugs have shown repeatedly that they can be effective in changing addictive behavior. This kind of treatment is called “contingency management.” The idea comes from basic behaviorism: our actions are governed to a large extent by what we are rewarded for in our 2 environment. These cause-and-effect relationships where a reward is dependent (contingent) upon the person either doing or (in the case of drugs) not doing a particular behavior can be used to help change all types of habits. Contingency management is arguably the most successful substance abuse treatment strategy, despite the fact that it does not purport to correct some neural deficit. The lesson here is that we should be less preoccupied with characterizing addiction and more focused on what treatments work. Louis Charland: "Loss of Control and Disease in Addiction: Five Fallacies". The hypothesis that repeated use of addictive substances may result in ‘loss of control’ and that it is appropriate to call the ensuing syndrome a ‘disease’ at this stage of scientific research, is often met with strong – sometimes vehement – disproval and denial. Indeed, many philosophers, scientists, politicians, and members of the general public, insist that addicts ultimately always have the ‘free will’ to choose their destiny no matter how dire the circumstances. I argue that there are five pervasive fallacies that tend to undermine and stifle productive debate in this area. These are: False Dichotomy, Overgeneralization, Essentialism, Intellectualization, and Scientific Opportunism. Ironically, philosophers, who should be leaders in detecting fallacies in reasoning, are often among the culprits in these disputes. Jørgen Bramnes: “What is the neurobiological knowledge of addiction, and what has this knowledge contributed to understanding the phenomenon?” It is popular among scientists to speak of the neurological correlates of human or psychological phenomena. Implicit to such understanding is the assumption that neurobiology has made only minor contributions to understanding the addiction phenomena. Neurobiology is reduced to reflections on “what we already know”. In this talk, therefore, I will show that the neurobiological model is neither unidimensional, nor too general, or in contradiction with other, more dynamic or complex models. There are numerous examples of how neurobiological knowledge may enhance our understanding of psychological phenomena, and expand on these. In short, neurobiological research shows that intoxication or euphoria on the one end, and addiction/prioritizing on the other end are two separate, and parallel mental processes, mediated by different neurotransmitter-systems. Through dysregulation of these systems we have observed how people may progress from seeking euphoria to seeking normality, to avoid anhedonia. Situationally dependent “cue craving” is important to this process. In this talk I will discuss how this knowledge has prompted development of new medicines, as well as greater understanding of the relationship between substance use and mental illness. I will also discuss the current debate in the wake of these discoveries, and comment on some of the most serious critiques. Hanna Pickard & Serge Ahmed: "Addiction, Choice, Foresight". The puzzle of addiction derives from the fact of persistent use in the face of knowledge of negative consequences. We argue that the orthodox view of addiction as a neurobiological disease of compulsion solves this puzzle, but is undermined by a range of philosophical concerns and empirical data that taken together suggest that addicts have choice over their drug 3 and alcohol consumption. We propose an alternative solution to the puzzle which draws on the real-world psycho-socio-economic context in which chronic addicts typically live, but also raises a new puzzle about the values expressed by addictive choices. We explore this puzzle by considering the extent to which addicts lack concern for their future, whether for rational reasons or due to cognitive impairments, but respond positively to present, and especially social, reward. Peter Railton: "Two kinds of failure to learn in desire". I have elsewhere presented a model of desire as a compound state involving affective regulation of motivation via a positively-valenced representation. This state primes the individual for learning as well as action. This compound nature suggests two broad ways in which desires can fail to learn. There can be dysregulation and failure of feedback in affect--for example, in affective disorders like depression and mania--and there can be regulatory failures when affective representations cease to exercise effective control of motivation. Addiction and certain other forms of compulsive motivation appear to be examples of the second type of failure. 4