Faust 1 In 1973, Alasdair MacIntyre wrote “the theorist of ideology as we have known him from Marx to the Frankfurt School, has always been someone who identified ideological contamination in others rather than in himself. … But, on the view which I am advancing, we have to discover the distortions of ideology first of all in ourselves and learn to live with them, at the same time that we learn, through self-conscious awareness, to avoid being their victims.” Late-capitalist society overemphasizes the results-based practice over the inquiry-based theory; a symptom of this fetishization of practical over the theoretical is being felt in humanities departments across the United States and the United Kingdom. As such, the relationship between theory and practice entails an appreciation of both prongs; undercutting one, at best, derails appreciation of the other; at worst, serves an ideological agenda. In this paper, I will argue that the neoliberal assault on the idea of university entails the latter proposition. I will begin by laying the groundwork for the MacIntyrean definitions of and interrelation between practice and theory. Then, I will analyse the rhetoric of cost-cutting measures being imposed upon the academy, with a special emphasis on drawing out correlations with capitalist ideology. I will then argue that this subtle attack upon the idea of university serves to disable, dismantle, and destroy effective critique of the prevailing hegemony. I will then conclude with a possible prognosis for the situation along MacIntyrean framework of practice based upon sacramental logic. A definition of MacIntyrean practice is given by MacIntyre himself: “Any coherent and complex form of socially established cooperative human activity through which goods internal to that form of activity are realised in the course of trying to achieve those standards of excellence which are appropriate to, and partially definitive of that form of activity, with the result that human powers to achieve excellence, and human conceptions to the ends and goods involved, are systematically extended.” MacIntyrean practice is not simply going forth and acting in a rote or Faust 2 instrumental manner. Rather, such practice is principled activity that can be evaluated according to a particular set of rules and standards. Accordingly, there are two kinds of goods that may result from human activity: the external, individual goods of property and possession, and the internal, social goods that enrich the entire community. Virtues, to MacIntyre, are those qualities that allow us to obtain these internal goods, and as such, they become part of the narrative of the self that sustains us on the quest for our ultimate end – the good life. Practice, in short, is the living articulation of values within a community. The notion of theory is somewhat harder to pin down, though the notion of tradition provides a good deal of help. Given the definition of a practice within the MacIntyrean framework, a theory can best be understood as articulating some systematic way of understanding a particular practice or particular sets of practices. Theory articulates and sets the boundaries of practice; the conversation between the two is necessarily dialectic. Taking a slight Humean aside, then, one might almost argue that a theory is a set of reasons that attempts to channel the passions toward practices. How, then, do theories come about? Recall that, for MacIntyre, the narrative aspect of the person is essential, as it provides the individual with a coherent notion the self during the pursuit of the good life. Because of the necessity and ubiquity of personal narratives in living the individual life, the narrative function of personality also serves as the prototypical model for theories of the non-personal, i.e., the internal goods within a practice. Since narratives and the achievement of internal goods are not the work of isolated individuals, the social and historical figures prominently in their formulation and articulation. Within the MacIntyrean framework, traditions supply and sustain the historical context to the virtues, as well as the theories that interrelate and influence the practices that are informed by them. According to MacIntyre, a “living tradition […] is an historically extended, socially embodied argument, and an argument Faust 3 precisely in part about the goods which constitute that tradition.” Tradition can thus be seen as providing a mooring for the theories as well as the related practices that cultivate them. Theory can, in turn, be seen as the analytic of the value of practices within the parameters of a tradition. At this point, it seems that theory and practice are mediated through the lens of a tradition. However, this account seems somewhat impoverished. Is not theory a more powerful concept than simply the articulation or dialectical companion of practice? Is there not room for metatheory, the theory that articulates and analyses the historical moors of the analytics of value within a tradition? For MacIntyre, a tradition, when vital, is not just a series of arguments, but also a continuity of conflict – differing theories within the tradition will compete with each and keep that tradition alive within that tradition’s parameters. As such, there is a sense of dynamism at work within every tradition, at least until the tradition dies down due to the failure of its interlocutors to exercise its relevant virtues. I take a “dying tradition” to mean one that can no longer supply or sustain the relevant theories that empower and invigorate its own dialogues, practices, and their associated virtues. Further, then, implicit within a dying tradition is the idea that practices themselves can no longer supply the necessary points of genesis for new theories, that the relations are insufficient to generate dialogue on their inherent virtues. Therefore, a tradition dies when its practices can no longer resuscitate theory within a tradition. However, the notion of a theory is not articulated exclusively through practices; the nonMacIntyrean-practice activities of the everyday also play a role in forming notions of theory. One of the most common aims of theory is formulating a narrative function for the community or society, rather like what MacIntyrean traditions seeks to do. However, the major difference between the overarching social theory and the MacIntyrean tradition is the completeness of the account they give of the good life and the path toward attaining it. At the risk of sounding too Faust 4 Lyotardian, within the notion of theory resides the possibility of metanarrative. For my purposes, this term will be used as shorthand for a set of theories that provide a narrative applied to the social whole that may be contained within, but are not identical with, a particular tradition. While the MacIntyrean tradition holds that exercise of the relevant virtues continues an as-of-yet unfinished narrative, the metanarrative supplies a constructive or pseudo-completeness of its constitutive theories to drive itself. The power of the metanarrative derives from its seeming cohesion of theories or a theory. Simply, there is a kernel of narrative and explanatory potential possessed within the possibility of theory that resides within the gap between practice and tradition – something that the MacIntyrean framework cannot adequately account for. As such, I argue that the interaction between theory and practice, as well as narrative and tradition, is woven through with ideology. Because of the role that ideology plays in uniting these aspects of MacIntyrean thought, the central issue in any split between theory and practice is one primarily of ideology. Here, ideology will be used within the sense of Louis Althusser’s “Ideological State Apparatuses”: that is, ideology is the productive intellectual driving force behind particular social institutions, as well as the content provider for those institutions to reproduce its notions of reality. Under this working definition of ideology, such social institutions are differentiated only as to the degree of explicit or implicit obedience to the ideological party line. The ideological state apparatuses provide the boundaries and standards for evaluation by shaping our tastes and preferences and by setting the ends and goods toward which we act by performing the practices. Further, they provide the notions of analysis by which theories might be formulated and evaluated. In short, they form and mold a tradition through their own prisms of analysis, by which subjects can formulate their own narratives. Indeed, an additional feature of Althusser’s conception of Faust 5 ideology – a subject’s formation through interpellation – corresponds to the lived experiences of subjects, especially if one sees ideology as working within the historical and cultural parameters that have thus been argued for. In effect, the most pernicious aspect of the ideological is how it hides in plain sight; how it constructs and defines the mental blocks and perceptions of the everyday; how it erects the intuitions that become the fixtures experience; and most distressingly, how it seamlessly integrates itself into the social fabric. Indeed, it can even appear to become its own antithesis: think of the “post-ideological” age of the post-World-War-II era, or more recently, of the much vaunted and the thoroughly discredited “End of History”. Because of this effect, our working definition of ideology can be further defined as the “common sense of the contemporary.” The account presented in this paper is not meant to impugn or indict the MacIntyrean framework. Rather, the claim is that MacIntyre’s concepts of practice, narrative, and tradition only capture a few aspects of the larger ideological whole. The quest for the good life in MacIntyre is predicated upon one’s ability to reach the values that enrich the entire community, that is, the virtues. The effect of ideology, however, is to block or alter that quest through the replacement of non-ideologically-approved ends with its own sanctioned ends. The space that the MacIntyrean tradition preserves for the continuation of its conversation is given a synthetic ending such that inquiry stops dead in its tracks, and becomes stale and stagnant. Ideology cuts off the possibility of personal and social development within not just a single tradition, but within every tradition. What, then are the dangers of theory to ideology, if any? If ideology is so pervasive, then how can theory provide a threat? For all its power, ideology is nonetheless historical – its success depends not only on the relation of theory, but also tradition, practice, and especially narrative. Faust 6 Theory qua theory contains a notion of demarcation. While a demarcation is not necessarily sharply defined, its simple existence hypothesizes, or at least concedes, alternatives. That is, if a theory is intrinsically tied to and supportive of practices, and that practices are historically situated within a tradition, then there necessarily must be some other theory that contains within it the possibility of alternatives, with its own constitutive, associative practices. Theory, by its very nature, though also supported by the notions of narrative, practice, and traditions, can easily be deconstructed, recombined, shared, flipped, chopped, and applied across various traditions. Theory, then, is the currency of possibilities, of meaningful proliferation of difference; contra ideology, which works to mask or gloss over the fractitious abundance of theories and traditions that will exist within any community or society. Because of this plethora of possibility, theory is the only refuge for revolutionary potential against ideology. The question then becomes, how does one see the affects of ideology in its most nakedly perceptive form, such that one cannot but help to see it’s the logic of its distortions? Rhetoric is indicative of the practical logic of an ideology, as it is the pure enactment of the ideological theories presented in an ingratiating sort of sophistry. In an almost ironic sense, rhetoric becomes its own practice in that it reveals the working ideological virtues at play in a society. More specifically, it is heavily reliant upon the heuristics, social norms, and everyday notions of those to whom it is addressed, rendering it a tool for recruitment, reinforcement, and restriction. The concept of reification, of making the abstract into concrete, becomes relevant, such that repetition and invocation of these rhetorical concepts solidify them into the building blocks of social reality. These basic constituents pieces can be arranged in innumerable forms and shapes, like a sort of cultural bricolage. Because the particular arrangements elucidate their own meanings, coupled with the earlier observation that the narrative conception of personality Faust 7 provides the basis for theory, metanarrative, and ideology, cultural bricolage enables its own form of hermeneutic self-interpretation. Therefore, cultural hermeneutics are required in order to reveal the ideological undercurrent prevalent within the culture at large. At this point, we are now prepared to examine the statements calling for the end of support for the humanities in postsecondary education as symptomatic of a late-capitalist ideology. Peter Cohan suggested in Forbes last year that: “Departments that are profitable and likely to remain so would stick around. Those that are not and would not, get cut.” Implicit within this statement is the notion of university as an all-too-literal market of ideas; that departments must be structured around a model of valuation through revenue production. Only then, so the argument goes, will the value of the enterprise be affirmed and considered worthwhile. No mention is given, of course, to the fact that the departments that are already best equipped to fit these evaluative criteria – science, technology, applied mathematics, engineering, finance – will be perennially most worthy of overall university support. Profitability, then, is the end to which an educational provider is to be valued. Within this notion of postsecondary education are several sub-notions that are never elucidated but still-present, that are not adequately argued for. Within the prevailing ideological culture, however, the purpose of higher education is higher marketability, which carries the expectation and correlation of more earning power. As such, Cohan is advocating that postsecondary institutions both reify and interpellate its students as profit-seeking subjects within a profit-maximizing culture. Not all critiques of liberal arts-based postsecondary education are so blatantly capitalistic. Walter Russell Mead writes in The American Interest that “rather than making vocational education more like higher ed, traditional colleges should be taking their cues from these successful certificate programs.” At first glance, this statement seems perfectly rational – Faust 8 shouldn’t people receive the skills that they are supposed to be paying for? However, this begs the question: are universities like vocational programs? Should they be? Would university be better if one received vocational skills? Within this statement, then, the notion of instrumentality is also present, though it is less dependent on making abstract concepts concrete through interpellation. Instead, its focus is on reaffirming and reproducing the concrete by limiting the purview of post-secondary education into as narrowly tailored and specialised an endeavor as possible. Despite this seeming difference, the underlying concept is still the same: that the cost associated with a post-secondary education is only justifiable such that the economic benefits (and only those such benefits) to the student outweigh those costs. What is absent from this concept of university is the notion of incompleteness, intellectual variety, and openness, let alone the exchange and analysis of traditions and their respective conversations. Even if a university seeks to work against this constant and omnipresent mindset, the overarching ideological mechanisms create stresses that often cannot be resisted. In the United Kingdom, the government imposed massive cuts to education funding for universities in 2010, a reduction of 40% to be spread over four years. At the time, the Treasury issued a statement that the Department for Business, Innovation and Skills, which oversees higher education, will “continue to fund teaching for science, technology, engineering and mathematics (STEM) subjects.” No mention was given of other subjects, however. As a result of this great reduction in support across the board, except for the most lucrative disciplines, a student entrepreneur writes in The Guardian: “with universities now having to commercialise their intellectual property out of financial necessity rather than choice, there will now be much more focus on exploiting their own innovations; greater emphasis on extracting as much value as they can from their academic learning.” As a result, because of the prevailing ideological forces at work, the university is Faust 9 being forced to abandon its traditional role as inculcator of knowledge, and to mold itself into an institution suspiciously similar to a profit-seeking corporation. Further, the student becomes both a customer/consumer, purchasing services in the form of skills that can be used for profitmaking, as well as subjects conditioned to view the world as composed of relationships between sellers and purchasers. This state of affairs, then, is the modern university as Althusserian ideological state apparatus within capitalist hegemony. The proliferation and reproduction of ideology within such a university is structured along the lines of what Herbert Marcuse called one-dimensional society. In such a society, ideological state apparatuses are “the technological controls [which] appear to be the very embodiment of Reason for the benefit of all social groups and interests – to such an extent that all contradiction seems irrational and all counteraction impossible”. Universities cast in the image of the ideological become the mass production and distribution systems that “blunt the individuals’ recognition that it contains no facts which do not communicate the repressive power of the whole”. As such, these institutions become the engines in which the pure instrumentalisation of (ideologically-approved) knowledge is paramount. MacIntyrean practice can still be present within such a society; however, the virtues inherent within them are simply those that inculcate the individual as a singular cog within the ideological mechanism. Theory exists only in the sense of economisation and reinforcement of the practices that already exist. Tradition effectively remains silent, as there is no longer either a conversation or interlocutors. I earlier stated that theory contains within it the kernel of metanarrative, such that theory is the possibility of proliferation of difference. The sources from which theory might arise are both the MacIntyrean practice and the everyday practice. Traditionally, however, the university is the only place such that traditions or ideologies cannot simply prevail unfettered, but rather, are Faust 10 analysed and examined and compared and contrasted within itself as well as against other traditions. Even within the modern research-oriented university, one is hard-pressed to find students that have never considered or encountered what are colloquially referred to as “the big questions”. The university, then, is an end-enabler: it is a space within a tradition wherein the student may be allowed to find herself within her or another tradition; to construct her own narrative; to engage in the associated practices; and to cultivate those virtues such that the good life might be accomplished both for her and for others. Within university, practice and theory are always in tension, that is, preparing a student for taking on a social role, and inculcate the rational autonomy to think for themselves. To that end, the dialectical relation is laid bare so as to reveal the inner workings of a tradition, and to allow for theoretical difference to emerge. This tension is at the very heart of the quest for the good life, and what empowers the quest toward it. Since the university provides space for both the self-analysis within one’s tradition and the possibility of difference, the university provides a threat to ideological supremacy. As such, while all institutions of education attempt to maintain a constant dialogue between theory and practice, the increasingly looming threat is one of instrumentalisation brought on by capitalist ideology. This emphasis on the practical and the diminishing of the theoretical cleaves the two from each other. As such, the very idea of university is split in two, leaving it both a mausoleum of silent tradition, and a factory of instrumentality toward a merely ideological end. What, then, might be done to preserve the idea of university, such that the capitalist ideology might not ossify all traditions? Within MacIntyrean thought, practices have a sacramental logic within them, one that defies the merely instrumental or managerial. Here I take “sacramental logic” to mean a systematics of understanding and practice based upon the preservation of the noumenous value of virtue – that is, the act of preserving a virtue-in-itself. By “noumenous,” I Faust 11 borrow the Kantian notion of the positive noumenal of an “intellectual intuition”; that is, the virtue of university is in its intellectual predisposition toward the notion of virtue and its special role in enabling the good life. What seems to be vital to understanding sacramental logic is the notion of value as indeterminacy; a positive void upon which there can be nothing equivalent or imposed, but from which everything can be derived. Already, there is within the concept of the university this notion of value from space creation. The Authentica habita, or Privilegium scholasticum, written in the twelfth century for the University of Bologna, offered these protections for its students and scholars: - Similar immunities and freedoms as those held by the clergy, provided they conformed to certain attributes, such as clerical dress Freedom of movement and travel for the purposes of study Immunity from the right of reprisal; and The right to be tried by their masters, or the Bishops court, rather than local civil courts These protections articulate a framework for providing the space to analyse traditions while suspending the common-sensical – that is, the key precondition for any serious mode of inquiry. As such, perhaps a closing-off of the university is the only way to save it from being ravaged by capital: its space must be preserved for the analysis of one’s own traditions alongside others, for enabling the construction of one’s own narrative, as well as the proliferation of the theories for practice that enable the virtues to take hold within practice. More importantly, university as such can provide its students with the intellectual tools needed to see through the illusions of the age, as embodied in its ideologies, and provide alternatives through the generation of theory. Therefore, if university is understood through a sacramental logic, it can become MacIntyre’s view of the ideal university within Three Rival Versions of Moral Enquiry: “a place of constrained disagreement, of imposed participation in conflict, in which the central responsibility of higher education would be to initiate students into conflict.”