Berkeley, Perceptual Relativity, and the primary/secondary quality contrast; Hylas redux. I. Color as a secondary quality Unlike others I find Berkeley’s view (as Philonous) in the first of the Three Dialogues Between Hylas and Philonous (hereafter TD) 1 convincing; that perceptual relativity (PR) examples suggest that no standard exists (or even makes sense) to determine the inherent 2 colors of objects. But unlike Berkeley, I think the most this shows is that colors are Weakly Mind-Dependent (WMD). By that I mean that though objects can have color, what color they have is essentially relative to the nature of observers and lighting conditions. Strong mind-dependence (SMD)—Berkeley’s view—claims that colors can’t exist unless perceived, 3 1 George Berkeley, Three Dialogues between Hylas and Philonous, (1734 ed.) in Works vol. 2 ed. A.A. Luce and T.E Jessop, (Thomas Nelson and Sons, 1949). Page numbers in the text. 2 A color is inherent for an object if some change in the object is necessary for a change in its color. 3 Paul Boghossian, writes: “Finally, there is the question whether some things we are prepared to believe in – say, colors – exist only in some mind-dependent sense. There are two possible thoughts here; one is that colors are attributes precisely of minds, and the other is that, although they are the attributes of external objects, nothing could have them unless there are minds.” “Seeking the Real”, Philosophical Studies 108 (12), (2002) 223-238). I would make this “thought” weaker. Objects could have colors and shapes even if there were no minds, but reference to what would be perceived under certain conditions is essential to ascribing colors to objects. Weak mind-dependence what I’ve called in the past “perspectivalism”, and others “relationalism,” or “relativism” (differences exist between the last two) is supported by the findings of color science. 4 Relativism is consistent with the view that “outward objects” (Berkeley’s phrase) have color—a view to be distinguished from color eliminativists (e.g., Galileo, Descartes, Gassendi,)—a position Hylas I believe could have taken. 5 WMD claims the following about color; (1) Perceived colors vary with respect to a variety of circumstances e including essential reference to visual systems of perceivers, (2) There’s no fact of the matter as to an object’s mindindependent or “inherent” color. In The Principles of Human Knowledge (PHK) sec.15 Berkeley famously notes that at most PR examples entail that we don’t know the true extension or color of “an outward object,” not that there isn’t any. That there can’t be has allegedly been established by prior considerations on the nature of sensible objects. One consideration, discussed below, is that we can’t perceive shape sans some quality like color already shown to be SMD. However I accept Georges Dicker’s claim, following 4 5 See C.L. Hardin, Color for Philosophers, (Hackett, 1998) Joshua Cohen *** makes a distinction between relationalism and relativism.(The Red and the Real ) For my purposes that distinction is not crucial. Both relationalism and (relativism) are “ecumenical” (Cohen); meaning roughly and at a minimum that there is no standard, beyond stipulation, for determining the “intrinsic” color of an object, one it would have independent of the environment and visual system of perceivers. Jonathan Dancy (fn 15) that when he wrote TD Berkeley believed more proof was needed that colors can’t exist unperceived. 6 In TD1 Philonous says about color: Even our own eyes do not always represent objects to us after the same manner. In the jaundice 7everyone knows that all things seem yellow. Is it not therefore highly probable that those animals in whose eyes we discern a very different texture from that of ours, and whose bodies abound with different humours, do not see the same colors in every object that we do not see the same colors in every object that we do. From all which, should it not seem to follow that all colors are equally apparent and that none of those which we perceive are really inherent in any outward object.(TD1 Turbayne 124 (my emphasis). 8 Berkeley notes also the problem of whether visual acuteness directly tracks real color. Philonous., assuming for the sake of argument that objects seen through microscopes 6 Dicker argues that by the time of TD Berkeley thinks he needs arguments for Strong Mind-Dependence than in PHk; hence the detailed use of PR in TD1. See Georges Dicker, Berkley’s Idealism, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2011), 104, Also George Berkeley, A Treatise Concerning The Principles of Human Knowledge, ed. Jonathan Dancy, (Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1998), 201-202, n.45. 7 Berkeley was evidently wrong in thinking things looked yellow to people with jaundice. 8 In PHK 14 Berkeley as well gives a number of PR examples applicable to both “secondary” and “primary qualities.” The point again is that PR examples, if they show tastes and colors are SMD, equally he thinks show extension and motion are SMD. are numerically identical with originals seen with the naked eye, puzzles Hylas by suggesting that: The colors, therefore, by it [the microscope] perceived are more genuine and real then those perceived otherwise. (TD1 124) 9 Similarly, C. L. Hardin in his book Color for Philosophers10 asks us to consider, among a number of examples, a Seurat painting from various distances and then describe its real color. In any case Berkeley evidently thinks a true, that is, mindindependent color of an object would be intrinsic to the object, a property independent of perceptual circumstances, and no such standard exists. Tom Stoneham writes, Berkeley does not deny that when we judge something is cobalt or teal or whatever, our judgment is answerable to how the thing would look to suitable observers in suitable viewing conditions . . .What he wants to point out is that we cannot give an objective justification of the choice of these conditions as being the ones in which the ‘true colors’ are revealed, where true means 9 In the New Theory of Vision Berkeley apparently denies the microscope gives greater acuity since the number of minimua visibilia must be the same in what’s seen through the microscope and what’s seen unaided. We have, he thinks, simply a new object of vision. He also thinks what we see through the microscope, having no associative connections with tactile experience lacks practical importance. Thus we have “only the empty amusement of seeing,” Turbayne ed., of The New Theory of Vision, (sec 86) p. 62. See also Catherine Wilson, The Invisible World, (Princeton, Princeton University Press, 1995), 244-248. 10 (Indianapolis, Hackett, 1986). Also “A Spectral Reflectance Doth Not a Color Make” The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 100, No. 4 (Apr., 2003), 191-202. mind-independent. 11 What about so-called “normal” perceivers, and “standard” illuminants? Hardin asks the following: So should not color realists [objects have inherent non-mind-dependent color] not only claim that there are viewing conditions that are veridical, but be prepared to specify which ones are veridical, or at least tell us how we could in principle recognize such conditions when we encounter them?12 Hardin’s view is that the very notion of meeting that challenge is absurd. And though color science has advanced since Berkeley’s time, his own examples of PR (above) convinces Hylas, that . . .” there is no such thing as color really inhering in external bodies . . .” 13 Of course that still allows, as Stoneham and Hardin note, a viable notion 11 Tom Stoneham ***(reference?) 12 Hardin, JP, 194. Here is a partial list of reasons for denying inherent color to bodies. Things appear differently colored depending on background color. The existence of “metameric failure.” For example, (1) color samples seen to match in one light source fail to match in another. (2) Samples match in color when viewed from one angle, but fail to match when viewed from another. (3) Color vision for physiological reasons varies among observers even under “normal conditions.” Therefore two observers under identical lighting conditions have different color sensations. And obviously socalled typical conditions, like viewing in daylight (or “north day-light”) can’t apply to judging the colors of stars, or the moon. Though far from being an expert I am convinced that “ecumenism” (Jonathan Cohen) is correct, that a given object may possess at a given time an infinite number of colors though each is indexed to a particular set of circumstances, and that the difference between “real” and “apparent” color is ultimately conventional. 13 It’s interesting that Berkeley puts in the mouth of Hylas an extra argument against the claim that “outward objects” are colored; it would require action at a distance to of “typical” viewing conditions, where “typical,” as opposed to some uses of “normal,” is thoroughly pragmatic. What doesn’t follow is color eliminativism, or, alternatively SMD. Berkeley of course is not ultimately a color eliminativist. There are no colors on “outward objects” since he thinks ultimately there are no “outward (mind-independent) objects.” But that conclusion comes later in the Dialogues supported in part by the claim, based on PR examples, that colors are SMD. 14 Yet we suggest for Hylas another option exists, a perspectivalist, relativist or relationalist view of color perception.15 Jonathan Cohen outlines relationalism. as follows: What the relationalist proposes, then, is that colors are not (as the physicalist maintains) subject- and condition-independent properties of their bearers, but relational properties that are constituted in terms perceive them. Therefore Hylas proposes that [“light and colors ”] “in themselves are the motions and configurations of certain insensible particles of matter.” (TD 11 Turbayne, 126. This opens Hylas to analogous semantic objections to identifying sounds with sound waves. 14 Again, in PHK establishing SMD for sensible qualities doesn’t depend on PR examples. See Barry Stroud, “Locke v Berkeley on Primary Qualities,” Philosophy 55, (1980) for a good discussion. 15 Such theories have been around for a while; recently as a response to Hardin’s eliminativism. For example, Jonathan Cohen, “it’s Not Easy Being Green: Hardin and Color Relationalism,” In Jonathan Cohen & Mohan Matthen (eds.), Color Ontology and Color Science. Boston, MIT Press, 2010. Cohen develops the position in The Red and the Real, (op. cit.) and as mentioned contrasts relationalism with relativism though I don’t discuss the distinction. of relations to subjects and viewing conditions. . . This view does justice to the facts about perceptual variation, and it does so without requiring either unmotivated choices between variants or unjustified optimism that there is some unknown (or unknowable) fact that could motivate such a choice. 16 A radical relativism (or relationalism) presumably could associate every sighted being in a specific set of environmental and internal conditions with what colors she sees in those conditions. Certainly impractical, but the thought again is material objects do have colors, but always indexed to some set of perceptual conditions. What’s required is a pragmatic definition of normal (or better typical) conditions specifiable without begging the question. 17 We would rule out varieties of red-green color-blindness, for example. 18 But (following Hardin) there are evidently However, like relativism relationalism expresses the view that notions of normal viewers and standard viewing conditions are conventional. 17 For a good discussion along these lines, see Margaret Atherton, “How Berkeley Can Maintain That Snow is White?” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Vol. 67, No. 1 (Jul., 2003), pp. 101-113, Atherton writes: Berkeley [gives] us a method for determining the true colors of things: they are not the ones we constantly and unchangingly perceive, rather they are the ones that vary in a regular and predictable manner. The true color of an object should not be conceptualized as something that exists permanently like a Munsell chip, rather the true color of an object is in point of fact a family of colors, each of which can be reliably anticipated in appropriate circumstances. The snow that is brilliant white against a black background can be reliably anticipated to be yellowish under an incandescent light bulb and purply at twilight.” (Atherton p. ***) 18 For example, the condition called “protanomaly” “[In this condition people] are less able to discriminate colors, and they do not see mixed lights as having the same cases where two subjects, both considered statistically “normal”, but one a statistical outlier, disagree whether two green patches are hue-identical. 19 Here again we relativize perceived color to majority and minority normal perceivers. We might, for instance, be interested in genetic and/or neurological differences in majority and minority normals. What is important again is that relativizing color ascriptions permits saying, against either eliminativists, or those who think colors are SMD, that outward objects have color. Hylas could, in principle, have taken this option I think while accepting that PR examples show no fact of the matter about an object’s inherent color. 2. PR and Shape PR examples about color convince Hylas that, as he says, all colors are “equally apparent; and that there is no such thing as color really inhering in external bodies, . . . (TD1 186) 20 Philonous notes that comparable PR examples can given for perceived shape, or any of the qualities Hylas calls “primary.” qualities, those some “philosophers” hold “really exist in bodies.” Though accepting that SMD applies to colors, Hylas mentions what he takes to be the current (“philosophers”) view, that so- colors as normal observers. They also suffer from a darkening of the red end of the spectrum.” Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2008 Edition). 19 For details see Hardin, Color For Philosophers, 76-83. Summarizing his discussion Hardin contends that the choice of unique green is a practical matter. 20 Hylas in this passage then suggests colors are “altogether in the light,” a suggestion that suffers the same semantic objection Philonous made to identifying sounds with sound waves. called primary qualities (“extension, figure, solidity, gravity, motion, and rest,”) are held to “exist really in bodies.” He adds that he’s “thoroughly convinced of its truth.” (Works II 187-188) But after Berkeley offers some PR cases, particularly about shape and motion, Hylas, rightly or wrongly accepts that shape like color is SMD, though reserving the right to later change his mind. 21 My interest, however, is when the discussion later turns toward whether, as Hylas suggests, a distinction can be made between “ absolute and sensible extension,” the latter which Hylas (under some pressure) is willing to call “extension in general or motion in general.” When Philonous expresses astonishment about whether one can “frame” an abstract idea of extension sans any sensible quality, Hylas remarks: What! Is it not an easy matter, to consider extension and motion by themselves, abstracted from all other sensible qualities? Pray how do the mathematicians treat of them? Philonous’s response echoes one Berkeley makes in his The Introduction to The Principles of Human Knowledge (PHKI), Geometers, for example, can pay attention or selectively attend to the linearity of a polygon’s line segments for the purposes of proof, ignoring its other properties. Berkeley writes: Thus, when I demonstrate any proposition concerning triangles it is to be supposed that I have in view the universal idea of a triangle, which ought not to be understood as if I can frame an idea which was neither equilateral nor scaleon, nor equicrural, but only that 21 Controversies exist about Philonous’s examples but I choose to take the discussion in another direction. Moreover, we should think of Philonous’s argument here as a conditional: if Hylas thinks PR examples show that colors are SMD, then he should think from analogous examples, that perceived shapes are SMD. the particular triangle I consider, whether of this or that sort it matters not, does equally stand for and represent all rectilinear triangles whatsoever, and is in that sense universal. All of which seems very plain and not to include any difficulty in it. (my emphasis, (PHK I Works II, sec 15, 33-34) This he takes to be legitimate abstraction. It doesn’t follow that mathematicians or anyone can frame an idea of extension (or motion) in general. 22 I propose to contrast Philonous’s answer with an alternative, and argue for the following. (1) A distinction, Berkeley would have accepted, should be made between abstraction as selective attention and idealization. Idealizations, borrowing a phrase from Michael Weisberg, are “intentional fictions;” Neither sensible objects nor Platonic forms23 they are rather a certain way of treating sensible objects. Conceiving primary qualities as idealizations. I argue below, dissolves certain issues Berkeley raises; for example, whether particular shapes can be conceived apart from sensible qualities, or how sensible ideas can resemble objects in principle unperceivable. The reason to treat primary qualities—I’ll mostly consider shape—as idealizations, concerns their role in explanations. Following Michael Jacovides, I list some salient characteristics of primary qualities he finds in Boyle and Locke. 1. Primary qualities are explanatory; secondary qualities are not deeply explanatory. 2. Ideas of primary qualities resemble something in bodies; ideas of secondary 22 The example, which I think misplaced, occurs in a discussion of how in a world of particulars language can have general terms. 23 “Three Kinds of Idealizations,” The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. CIV, number 12, (2007), 639. qualities do not. 3. Primary qualities are not dispositions; secondary qualities are dispositions to produce ideas in us. 4. The genera of primary qualities are inseparable from bodies; the genera of secondary qualities are separable. 5. Primary qualities belong to bodies as they are in themselves; secondary qualities do not. 24 For my purposes 1, and 4, are crucial in understanding what makes a quality primary. Put simply, the inseparable properties of bodies—those they must possess to be material bodies—allegedly at bottom explain all other phenomena both mechanical and mental. Boyle writes: Whether these accidents may not be conveniently enough be called the moods or primary affections of bodies to distinguish them from those less simple qualities (as colors tastes and odors) that belong to bodies upon their account, or whether, with the Epicureans, they may not be called the conjuncts of the smallest parts of matter I shall not now stay to consider . . .25 (my italics). We should at this point distinguish two types of mechanical explanation, (1) Mechanical explanations of physical phenomena, particularly motion, (e.g., Galileo, Newton), and (2) Explanatory projects that ultimately aim to explain everything, 24 Michael Jacovides, “Locke’s Distinctions between Primary and Secondary Qualities,” in Lex Newman ed. The Cambridge Companion to Locke’s Essay Concerning Human Understanding, (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2007). 25 Robert Boyle, “The Origins and Forms of Qualities According to the Corpuscular Philosophy,” (1666, Oxford), in Selected Papers, ed., M. A. Stewart, (Indianapolis, Hackett, 1991), 21. including mental phenomena, in terms of invisible corpuscles or atoms. (e.g., Galileo, [in the Assayer] Boyle, perhaps Locke, 26 Gassendi.) The first type interests me somewhat more in assessing Berkeley’s discussion of primary qualities in TD1 since had no quarrel with the mathematical explanations of motion by, say, Galileo or Newton. 27 In Galileo’s, Two New Sciences, discussing inclined plane experiments for determining the law of free-fall, Sagredo, an interlocutor, remarks on the proposed “postulate” that whatever a plane’s inclination, the moving ball’s degree of speed [velocity] depends only on vertical distance from the ground, He notes the assumption that “the planes are quite solid and smooth, and that the movable is of a perfectly 26 Michael Ayers in his paper, “Primary and Secondary Qualities in Locke’s Essay,” (Primary and Secondary Qualities, ed. Nolan, 139-40) contends that Locke can be seen as making a reasonable distinction between primary and secondary qualities that doesn’t simply articulate the corpuscular program. Ayers notes about the perceived non-minded world that: "Round things normally and understandably roll as square things do not.” See Primary and Secondary Qualities, ed. L. Nolan, (Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2011), 139-40. Fundamentally the same point is made by Edwin Mann, “Locke’s Distinction between Primary Primary Qualities and Secondary Primary Qualities,” in Primary and Secondary Qualities, ed. Nolan, op. cit., 158-189. But even here, I suggest, ordinary working folk in the seventeenth century, (carpenters, surveyors) would certainly use the idealizations of Euclidean geometry. And there remains the problem of explaining apparent action at a distance, (gravity magnetism etc). 27 Although Berkeley allows the use of the term “cause” in such explanations, the term doesn’t refer to efficient causes. Only volitions, he consistently claims, can be strict or efficient causes. round shape.”28 Onora O’Neil about a different subject well expresses the difference between abstraction (as Berkeley conceives it PHKI) and idealization. Abstraction, taken straightforwardly, is a matter of bracketing, but not denying, predicates that are true of the matter under discussion. . . Idealization is another matter: it can easily lead to falsehood. An assumption, and derivatively a theory, idealizes when it ascribes predicates often seen as enhanced, ‘ideal’ predicates that are false of the case in hand, and so denies predicates that are true of that case. 29 “Galilean idealizations” 30 play an important role in a number of mathematically expressed natural laws, e.g., the law of free fall, or Newton’s law of 28 Galileo, Galilei, Two New Sciences, (1638), trans. Stillman Drake, (Madison, University of Wisconsin Press, 1974), 162). See also Ernan McMullin, “Galilean Idealization,” in Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 16, 3, (1985), 247273. Another example making use of Galilean idealization is Another well known example of the use of idealization in physics is in Boyle’s Gas Law: “Given any x and any y, if all the molecules in y are perfectly elastic and spherical, possess equal masses and volumes, have negligible size, and exert no forces on one another except during collisions, then if x is a gas and y is a given mass of x which is trapped in a vessel of variable size and the temperature of y is kept constant, then any decrease of the volume of y increases the pressure of y proportionally, and vice versa.” [Wikepedia] 29 Onora O’Neill, Towards Justice and Virtue, (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, ( 1996), 40-41. 30 The term is Ernan McMullins’. See the discussion in Andrew Wayne, “Expanding the Scope of Explanatory Idealization,” Proceedings of the Philosophy of Science Association, Vol. 78, No. 5, Part I, 830-842. gravity. 31 They allow the application of Euclidean geometry to mechanical problems, a point about which Berkeley was certainly cognizant. Here are three passages from his treatise on mechanics, De Motu (DM) [1721, somewhat revised 1752, Luce and Jessop Vol. IV.] Mechanical Principles and universal laws of motions or of nature, happily discoveries of the last century, treated and applied by the aid of geometry, have shown a remarkable light upon philosophy.” (DM 41). In physics sense and experience which reach only to apparent effects holds sway; in mechanics the abstract notions of mathematicians are admitted. In first philosophy or metaphysics we are concerned with incorporeal things, with causes truth and the existence of things. (DM 71, my italics.) 32 In Dm 39 he writes: And just as geometers for the sake of their art make use of many devices which they themselves cannot describe nor find in the nature of things, even so the mechanician makes use of certain abstract and general terms, imagining in bodies force, action, 31 Galilean idealizations are thought of as limiting cases; although we don’t have perfect vacuums, frictionless surfaces, or perfect spheres we think of such states as limits we approximate to by eliminating “material hindrances” (Wayne, 832). Not all idealizations in physics have this character. 32 Berkeley is discussing collision phenomena. He contends the debate about whether motion in one object ceases, and another begins “de novo “ in the second, or the numerically same motion maintains itself throughout, is spurious. attraction, solicitation, etc. which are of first utility for theories and formulations, as also for computations about motion, even if in the truth of things, and in bodies actually existing, they would be looked for in vain, just like geometers’ fictions made by mathematical abstraction. (my italics) It’s not entirely clear what Berkeley means by “mathematical abstraction ” but I suggest that the best interpretation is “idealization.” treating planetary orbits as ellipses is a simple example. 33 Idealization for Berkeley then is a legitimate form of abstraction, but distinct from abstraction as selective attention. In the latter one pays attention, for generalizing purposes, to a real property of an object and ignoring others, attending, for example, to just the shape of a triangle, the color of a ball, or the humanity of Peter. It’s likely an exaggeration to say that all early modern philosophers have as a conceptual requirement for primary qualities that they function in mathematical explanations.34 But that way of conceiving them has some attraction since an obvious question is why perceived shape has more primaryness than color or taste? With respect to sensible shape, as Berkeley and others noted, PR examples apply to them as 33 Another possibility is that he’s thinking of Euclidean figures themselves as abstractions. 34 This point is made by Antonia LoLordo in “Gassendi and the Seventeenth-Century Atomists on Primary and Secondary Qualities.” Primary and Secondary Qualities; the Historical and Ongoing Debate, ed. Lawrence Nolan, (Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2011), 63, fn 5. to colors. A plausible, and at least partial answer for the primacy of shape is that shape, as idealized, not color, plays a fundamental explanatory role in Galilean/Newtonian accounts of motion, and (at least as a research project) in explanation of all physical phenomena in terms of atoms or corpuscles. In any event at the point in Dialogue1 after Hylas notes about “absolute extension” that mathematicians treat of extension sans sensible qualities, he might have gone on as follows. (H) “Shape, for example, a Euclidean circle or sphere, is an idealization of sensible objects, but not itself a sensible object. It’s meaningless to ask for its color, taste, smell, or tactile qualities. A Euclidean circle obviously has shape. After all, it’s a circle, but that shape is stipulated—a matter of convention—not observed. In fact, your own view, Philonous/Berkeley, of sensible extension implies that a Euclidean sphere can’t exist since its circumference and diameter are incommensurable. And as for frictionless planes or perfect spheres how would you know you’ve discovered them without making use of the very law of free-fall you’re trying to establish.” There’s nothing in this line of thought that should worry Philonous. In Berkeley’s own reading of mathematical tracts on optics, astronomy and whatever version of Euclid he studied 35 he would treat postulates and theorems as about 35 For an account of Euclid translations in the period see Stefan Storrie (forthcoming 2012). (I thank him for email discussion). Storrie speculates that Berkeley might have been influenced by Isaac Barrow’s view that Euclidean objects, right lines, circles, etc. can be constructed by “generative motion” (p. 24) But, as Storrie notes, Isaac Barrow claims that no sensible line or circle is guaranteed to be Euclidean. Barrow in fact writes: “But for the line to be “perfectly right‟ we must conceive of the sensible right idealized diagrams, rather than about the drawn figures. Idealization in this case means stipulating the diagrams meet the Euclidean postulates, for example that there can’t be a two-sided polygon. I mentioned above that idealizing perceived shapes for mathematical treatment solves some problems Philonous raises in TD1. One was whether sensible extension must always have some sensory properties, visual, tactile etc. If so, Hylas has a difficulty, since having already accepted that color is SMD, he seems committed to saying the same about shape. But he might have suggested that the notion that idealized shapes possess sensible qualities is meaningless. Moreover, we no longer have the so-called “resemblance” problem; i.e., how can ideas of sense resemble anything not in principle perceivable? However, Euclidean circles obviously resemble perceived circles. Apropos here is the following selection from a dialogue of Leibniz between A (presumably Leibniz), and an interlocutor B, about geometric constructions. B notes the importance of “contemplating constructed figures accurately.” A: True, but we must recognize that these figures must also be regarded as characters, [symbols] for the circle described on paper is not a true circle and need not be; it is enough that we take it for a circle. B: Nevertheless it has a certain similarity to the circle, and this is surely not arbitrary. line as having no „roughness‟ or „exorbitances‟ by an act of reason rather than sense. In this way geometrical objects are not sensible but objects of reason” The Usefulness of Mathematical Learning Explained and Demonstrated, (1683) tr. Kirkby, (London, 1734), 75. A: Granted; therefore figures are the most useful of characters. 36 (my italics) Galilean idealizations are introduced to permit mathematical treatment. The laws of motion require idealizations of both objects and conditions. They are limiting cases that often can’t exist in principle. (e.g., absolute zero, a perfect vacuum, Newton’s point masses, etc.) Explanations making use of Galilean idealizations are strictly false, since they don’t precisely predict the phenomena. 37 But as Leibniz noted these idealizations resemble sensible objects. What about the project of causally explaining at least all mechanical phenomena (leaving out now mental phenomena) in terms of atoms or corpuscles? Here as well, idealized objects, for example, in the kinetic theory of gasses, were often involved.38 I note in passing that the question whether the molecules postulated by the theory exist at all is distinct 39 from the question whether they exist as Galilean idealizations, point masses undergoing perfectly elastic collisions. The answer to that 36 Leibniz, “Dialogue on the Connection between Things and Words” (August, 1677), in Philosophic Papers and Letters, Vol. 2, Ed. Leroy E. Loemker, (Chicago, Chicago University Press, 1969), 184. 37 Nancy Cartwright, in How the Laws of Physics Lie, (Clarendon Press, 1999), develops the theme that idealizations make explanations in physics, though useful, strictly false. 38 Boyle (1662) and others discovered the law named after him, that the pressure and volume of a gas were inversely proportional at a fixed temperature; The law was derived later from the a theory which presupposed molecules (considered as point masses) moving randomly in a closed container. 39 Issues about the existence of theoretical entities, exemplified by the kinetic theory of gasses, produced a large (and continuing) literature I fortunately needn’t discuss. clearly is ‘no.’ However, as limiting cases, they certainly resemble members of the sequence of cases they limit. In “The Excellency of the Mechanical Hypothesis,” Boyle, in recommending “the Corpuscular Principles, ” writes in part: For a figure of the portion of matter may either be one of the five regular solids treated of by geometricians, or some determinate species of solid figures. As that of a cone, cylinder, &c., [also irregular shapes] . . . And as the figure so the motion of one of these particulars . . . as (besides straight) circular, elliptical, parabolical, hyperbolical, and I know not how many others . . . (Boyle’s italics). 40 Again, Berkeley wouldn’t countenance the actual existence of a Euclidean regular solid, or perfectly elliptical motion. But as Leibniz noted their actual existence doesn’t matter. These are Galilean idealizations, limiting cases, ultimately useful in a mathematized mechanics. Perceptual relativity examples are obviously irrelevant to whether they are mind-dependent. 40 Boyle, Selected Philosophical Papers, 141.