Kantian Robotics: Building a Robot to Understand Kant’s Transcendental Turn The Second Asia-Pacific Computing and Philosophy Conference, AP-CAP 2005 January 7 - 9, 2005, Novotel Hotel, Siam Square, Bangkok, Thailand 4/10/2015 ©Lawrence M. Hinman 1 Overview • Understanding the Transcendental Turn • Building the Robot • Transcendental Aesthetic: space and time • Transcendental Analytic: categories of the understanding • Conclusion 4/10/2015 ©Lawrence M. Hinman 2 Understanding the Transcendental Turn • Kant tries to demonstrate that there are certain structures of the mind that are necessary conditions of the possibility of any human experience whatsoever. • The challenge: to help students to understand the way in which these are prior to experience and constitutive of all possible experiences. • They are subjective (coming from the subject) and objective (conditions of the possibility of any objects whatsoever). 4/10/2015 ©Lawrence M. Hinman 3 The Copernican Revolution and the Transcendental Turn • Copernicus: from geocentric to heliocentric view of the cosmos • Kant: • To see that the motion that apparently is coming from the sun is actually coming from the rotation of the earth • More generally: some things that seem to belong to the object are actually coming from the subject. 4/10/2015 ©Lawrence M. Hinman 4 The Ptolemaic Cosmos In Ptolemy’s worldview, the earth is the center of the universe and everything else (including the sun) revolves around it. This put human beings at the center of the cosmos. 4/10/2015 ©Lawrence M. Hinman 5 The Copernican Universe In Copernicus’ view of the cosmos, the sun becomes the center of the universe and the planets revolve around it in a way roughly equivalent to our contemporary view. Human beings are no longer at the center of the cosmos, and this is the standard interpretation of the Copernican Revolution. 4/10/2015 ©Lawrence M. Hinman 6 Kant’s Copernican Universe Kant’s crucial insight was that he understood that the movement that appeared to be in the sun actually came from the earth’s rotation. This led to Kant’s crucial insight that motion and other characteristics that appear to be in the object may actually becoming from the perceiving subject. 4/10/2015 ©Lawrence M. Hinman 7 The Assignment Class assignment: • build a robot—whom we will call “Immanuel”--that moves around an area and collects information, a more primitive version of the unmanned Rovers that explore the moon’s surface. • Immanuel does not have to manipulate its environment. 4/10/2015 ©Lawrence M. Hinman 8 Building the Robot • Imagine a computer without a keyboard, screen, mouse, printer or network connection. Nothing could go in or out • Epistemological solipsism • Psychological autism • The issue: getting data in and out: • First critique: the input problem • Second critique: the output problem 4/10/2015 ©Lawrence M. Hinman 9 Sensing the Environment • Immanuel must have some way of sensing his external environment. • Begin with a typically human mode of sensing that environment: vision. • Let’s begin to construct Immanuel’s I/O system by adding a camera 4/10/2015 ©Lawrence M. Hinman 10 Incoming data The key to understanding Kant is to understand how much the mind has to add to the above photos in advance (that is, a priori) if they are to be meaningful. 4/10/2015 ©Lawrence M. Hinman 11 Adding temporal/date tags The first step in this process is to assign some kind of time stamp to these images. At the very least, a sequential (“before” and “after”) stamp; ultimately, as Immanuel gets more perceptions and eventually has to communicate with others (David, Georg, Gottfried, Johann, and others), he has to stamp these in a way that has intersubjective validity. 4/10/2015 ©Lawrence M. Hinman 12 Spatial Tags Each image has to be tagged for spatial location. The location tagging will vary in level of sophistication, depending on whether Immanuel is mobile and whether he has to communicate with others. The simplest schema is where Immanuel is not mobile, but the fixed center of his universe. If Immanuel can move, the there must be some scale of spatial reference (here the issue of absolute space lurks in the background) in which objects can be located in some objective (i.e., not Immanuel-relative) way. 4/10/2015 ©Lawrence M. Hinman 13 Categories of the Understanding • Incoming data are in fact much less coherent than the everyday pictures suggest. • In fact, we have given this computer data much more coherence than its original format—ultimately, a series of ones and zeros—would suggest. • The important point, both pedagogically and philosophically, for students to realize is how incredibly raw this incoming visual data actually is. 4/10/2015 ©Lawrence M. Hinman 14 Incoming data, 1 Incoming visual data might initially look like this. 4/10/2015 ©Lawrence M. Hinman 15 Incoming data, 2 Then as the categories of the understanding are applied to it, it starts to look more like this…. 4/10/2015 ©Lawrence M. Hinman 16 Incoming data, 3 …and then like this. 4/10/2015 ©Lawrence M. Hinman 17 Kant, Helmholtz, and Seurat Interestingly, Seurat’s painting technique (called “pointilism”) comes directly from Kant via Helmholtz, who elaborated Kant’s ideas for physics and optics. Seurat wanted to mix the colors optically in the viewer’s eyes rather than physically on the canvas in order to make them more vibrant. 4/10/2015 ©Lawrence M. Hinman 18 A nutty problem The challenge is to recognize the same object AS the same despite changing perspectives. 4/10/2015 ©Lawrence M. Hinman 19 The Concept of a Physical Object • The first step in in process of making sense of this incoming data—William James’ “blooming, buzzing confusion”—is to organize it in terms of discrete objects. • The Kantian point is that the concept of a physical object is not something that we derive from experience—à la Hume—but something that we have to impose in advance to make any sense out of this incoming sense data. 4/10/2015 ©Lawrence M. Hinman 20 Noumenal-Phenomenal World The thing-in-itself Unknowable Possible realm of freedom Morality 4/10/2015 The thing-as known Structured by human understanding Domain of scientific knowledge Cause-and-effect ©Lawrence M. Hinman 21 Kant and Nietzsche • Building the robot helps us to see a principal point of which Kant and Nietzsche diverge. • Both Kant and Nietzsche would agree that incoming sense experience is a series of radically different data. • Kant says that sameness and objectivity come from the necessary structures that the mind imposes on experience, the a priori forms of intuition and the categories of the understanding. • Nietzsche claims that the continuity we appear to find in experience is fundamentally a metaphor, carrying over one thing onto another that 4/10/2015 ©Lawrence M. Hinman 22 Conclusion Two unresolved questions: • Kant’s challenge: if you were in the position of the robot, how could you figure out the necessary limits of your own ability to know? • The second critique: if such a robot could act freely, what laws should constrain its actions? 4/10/2015 ©Lawrence M. Hinman 23