Ian Roberts igr20@cam.ac.uk Generate well-formed structural descriptions “create” trees/labelled bracketings More (X’) or less (PS-rules) abstract Can create infinite structures Movement rules: Don’t create structures but manipulate them Technically, they map phrase markers into other phrase markers Informally, constituents “move” from one place in the structure to another Head-movement, as in English subject-auxiliary inversion in questions: John can leave. Can John t leave? CP | C’ ru C Can TP ru NP John T’ ru T t VP | V win as in the English passive: The policeman arrested the student The student was arrested t TP ru NP ru T’ ru D N T The studentwas VP ru V NP arrested t The most important and interesting type of movement for various reasons. Moves (almost) any XP to the beginning of the sentence to form, in the simplest case, a question. (1) (2) (3) (4) (5) Which man will John see t ? -- object NP Who should John talk to t ? – indirect object NP (“preposition stranding”) To whom can John talk t ? – indirect object PP (“pied-piping”) How angry is Alex t ? -- AP What does John believe t ? – CP TP and VP do not undergo WHmovement “Echo-questions” show where the wh-phrase originates: Bill bought WHAT?! You talked to WHO?! CP ru C’ ru ru D N C TP Which man will ru NP NP T’ | N ru T John t VP ru V see NP t I wonder .. (1) which man John will see t ?-- object NP (2) who John talk should to t ? – indirect object NP (“preposition stranding”) (3) to whom John can talk t ? – indirect object PP (“pied-piping”) (4) how angry Alex is t ? -- AP (5) what John believes t ? – CP Just like direct questions except no subject-aux inversion. C must be empty here (no that/if/whether) Who t saw John? “vacuous movement”: CP ru NP C’ | ru N C TP Who ru NP t T’ ru T VP ru V saw NP John I wonder who t saw John ? *I wonder who did t t see John ? *I wonder who that/if t saw John ? *I wonder that/if who saw John ? C must always be empty in indirect subject questions like all other indirect questions. Movement to SpecC’ always, accompanied by a zero [+wh] C. (1) (2) (3) (4) (5) Which man did you say (that) John will see t? -- object NP Who did you say (that) John will talk to t ? – indirect object NP (“preposition stranding”) To whom did you say (that) John will talk t ? – indirect object PP (“pied-piping”) How angry did you say (that) Alex is t ?-AP What did you say (that) John believes t ? – CP Who did you say [ that Mary believes [ that John saw t ]] ? Who did you say [ that Mary believes [ that Fred knows [ that John saw t ]]] ? Who did you say [ that Mary believes [ that Fred knows [ that I asserted [ that John saw t ]]] ? .. and so on. The unbounded nature of WH-islands poses a problem for PS-rules/X’theory because PS-rules/X’-theory are local: they define little bits of the tree at a time, e.g. VP V CP How does VP “know” it’s part of a whdependency as in: Who did you say [ that Mary [VP believes [CP that John saw t ]] ? Either we complicate the PS-rules/X’-theory hugely (this can be and has been done) or we have two relatively simple rule types: PS-rules/X’-theory build structure (create phrase markers) Movement/transformational rules manipulate structure (map phrase markers into other phrase markers) WH-movement: Move a WH-phrase to the specifier of a [+wh] C. “NP-movement”: move the object to the subject position (passive) Head-movement: move T to C (subject-aux inversion) (The last two can be generalised; WHmovement is already in quite a general form here). (1) Although WH-movement is unbounded, it doesn’t apply just anywhere, but is subject to stringent locality conditions, cf.: my guitar, John’s cat – possessor NP in Spec of higher NP: NP1 ru NP2 N’1 | | N’2 N1 | cat N2 guitar John’s my And similarly for whose cat If you want to know whose cat you’re talking about: (1) Whose cat did you feed t ? – object NP *Whose did you feed [NP t cat ] ? – can’t apply WH-movement directly to the possessor, but must “pied-pipe” the whole object. (2) The Left Branch Constraint (LBC): WH-movement can’t apply to a left-branch, or to part of a left branch. So, whose can’t move on its own. Cf also: How angry is Alex t ? -- AP-movement *How is Alex [AP t angry ] ? – no movement just of Spec of AP. Sometimes a pronoun appears where a gap could be: John, I like (him). John, I like {him/t}. Pronouns don’t obey island constraints: *Whose did you say that you like [NP t cat ]? Whose cat did you say that you like t ? ?Who did you say that you like his cat ? Marginally (in English) a resumptive can link to a WH, but only in an island. The LBC is one of several constraints on WHmovement called “island constraints” (islands are things that are difficult move off). In general, WH-movement: Leaves a gap Is unbounded Obeys the LBC (and other island constraints) Recall the constituency test clefting: John wrote the book It was John that wrote the book. It leaves a gap *It was John that he wrote the letter. It can be unbounded It was John that Mary said that Bill thinks t wrote the letter. It obeys LBC: *It was John’s that I saw [NP t cat ]. We need movement rules alongside PSrules/X’-theory Three types of movement WH-movement involves unbounded dependency WH-movement leaves a gap, obeys LBC Clefting is a type of WH-movement (albeit a bit hidden)