CSE 20 DISCRETE MATH Prof. Shachar Lovett http://cseweb.ucsd.edu/classes/wi15/cse20-a/ Clicker frequency: CA Todays topics • Boolean logic: quantifiers • Paradoxes • Sections 3.2-3.4 in Jenkyns, Stephenson Quantifiers • Universal: ο’ • Existential: ο€ • Example: ο’x,y ο€ z, x-y=z • The universe where inputs live is important • Our example is: • True if x,y,z are integers • False if x,y,z are positive integers Some examples • “For all even numbers x and y, the sum of x and y is also even.” ≡ • ∀π₯, π¦ ∈ πΈ, π₯ + π¦ ∈ πΈ • “There exists an integer g such that g is greater than 5.” ≡ • ∃π ∈ π π . π‘. π > 5 We’re going to focus on: • “Nested” quantifiers/more than one quantifier • General strategy for proving (or disproving) quantified statements Which picture represents the predicate? (Predicate Love(x,y) means “x loves y”, denoted by arrow from x to y) • A. B. D. None/more/other C. Which picture represents the predicate? (Predicate Love(x,y) means “x loves y”, denoted by arrow from x to y) ο A. B. D. None/more/other C. Proof strategies overview (more coming later) • For a universally quantified (“for all”) statement: • To prove it: • direct proof, generalization from the generic particular (construction), mathematical induction • To disprove it: • Provide a single counterexample • For an existentially quantified (“there exists”) statement: • To prove it: • Provide a single example • To disprove it: • State the correct version as a universally quantified statement (“For all x, not P(x)”) then prove it using above methods What is the correct negation of the predicate? (Predicate Love(x,y) means “x loves y”) • ∀π∃π . πΏππ£π(π, π ) A. By counterexample: show there is a person who B. C. D. E. loves everyone By counterexample: Show there is a person who loves no one By counterexample: Show there is a person who nobody loves By counterexample: Show there is a person who everyone loves Other/more/none What is the correct negation of the predicate? (Predicate Love(x,y) means “x loves y”) • ∃π ∀π. πΏππ£π(π, π ) A. ∀π ∀π. ~πΏππ£π π, π B. ∀π ∃π. ~πΏππ£π(π, π ) C. ∃π ∀π. ~πΏππ£π π, π D. ∀π ∃π. ~πΏππ£π(π , π) E. Other/more/none Black swans “All swans are white” I lived 100 years. All the swans I saw in my lifetime are white. Is this enough for the predicate to be true? A. Yes B. No Black swans “All swans are white” I lived 101 years. I saw one black swan in all this time. Is this enough for the predicate to be false? A. Yes B. No Paradoxes • Lets have some fun with paradoxes • They actually have deep mathematical meaning • They came up when mathematicians and philosophers tried to understand some “corner cases” in math and logic Is this sentence true? “This sentence is true” A. True B. False Is this sentence true? “This sentence is false” A. True B. False Liar’s Paradox “This sentence is false” • This has been perplexing people since at least the Greeks in 4th century BCE (2300 years!) • What are some key features of this that make it a paradox? Grandparent Paradox (Time Travel Paradox) • You travel back in time and prevent one pair of your biological grandparents from ever meeting each other (assume this prevents your birth). • Now who will go back in time to prevent your grandparents from meeting? • Pop culture version: Pinocchio’s Paradox The Barber • A certain town has only one barber (a man). Every man in the town is clean-shaven. For each man m in the town, the barber shaves m if and only if m does not shave himself. • Question: Does the barber shave himself? a) YES b) NO c) Not enough information d) Other List Organization Question (aka Russell’s paradox) • Suppose you have many lists and some of your lists are lists of lists (to help you organize your lists), and some lists even include themselves. • You make a list of all lists that do not include themselves, called NON-DANGER-LIST. • Question: • Should NON-DANGER-LIST include itself? a) b) c) d) YES NO Not enough information Other Next class • Simplification rules • Implications and common mistakes using them • Read sections 3.2-3.4 in Jenkyns, Stephenson