Human Genome Editing Jason Onwumere Georgia State University Phil 3740 Biomedical Ethics Professor Lauren O’Dell December 10, 2024 Introduction Today we live in a forever evolving world. What was thought to have been impossible to achieve by scientists in the past, are now some of the things almost every person in the world interacts with on a daily basis. Things as complex as a phone or as simple as a toaster, at one point in time, were not even comprehensible within the capabilities of what science had achieved during the time. The newest example of this phenomenon happening in current times can be seen within the new and groundbreaking field of medicine known as human genome editing. This new technology can utilize several different techniques of DNA splicing such as CRISPR, Zinc Finger Nucleases (ZFNs), and Transcription Activator-Like Effector Nucleases (TALENs) to allow scientists to edit genetic information with precision and accuracy (Hildebrandt). The potential uses of this technology could be far greater than we could imagine. Currently, the main things this technology could be applied to include: eliminating genetic diseases and enhancing physical or cognitive traits. Despite its promises, human genome editing raises profound ethical questions. Any new advancement is a cause for scientists to slow down and really understand what it is they are doing. This leads to the main arguments against human genome editing concerning unintended consequences, lack of informed consent, and unequal justice and equity; as the main reasons that challenge the ethical justification for human genome editing. This essay argues that human genome editing, while revolutionary, is not ethically permissible due to these challenges. Unintended Consequences The first ethical justification against the use of human genome editing is that there is a risk of unintended consequences. Despite the precision of the technology and all the different techniques that have been developed to cut and reach more genetic information, there is a constant unknown variable for the potential for off-target effects. Off-target effects are unintended genetic alterations that can cause significant harm to a person's quality of health or general health and well-being. Yasar Elcin from the Turkish Biology Journal wrote that there is ”inadequate testing and rapid advancements in CRISPR technology may lead to unforeseen health complications which violate the medical ethics principle of non-maleficence” (Ayanoğlu). These off-target effects could result in harmful mutations, compromising patient safety that could be seen in present or future generations (Jacintoz) . These unintended changes can harm a person's health or well-being, either immediately or across generations. This risk directly violates the principle of non-maleficence, which requires healthcare professionals and researchers to avoid causing harm. At the same time, the potential of off-target effects also fails to uphold beneficence, the obligation to act in ways that promote the well-being of individuals and society. If genome editing unintentionally causes new diseases or worsens existing health conditions, it would contradict the core ethical obligation to maintain beneficence and non-maleficence for all. By risking harm in ways that outweigh the benefit, genome editing technologies fail to ethically justify their use under the guiding principles of medicine. Moreover, the speed of scientific advancements often outpaces the establishment of ethical frameworks. Without a comprehensive understanding of all possible outcomes, genome editing experiments risk creating a situation where consequences are irreversible. There is currently no system to rectify or reverse the outcomes of genetic editing gone wrong, which raises concerns about the danger of playing with the fundamental building blocks of life that could potentially become permanent within the root of human genetic information without a safety net. These aspects further emphasize why the potential for unintended consequences cannot be ignored. Informed Consent The second ethical justification against the use of human genome editing is there is the inability to obtain informed consent from those most affected by genome editing... future generations. Altering the genetic code of an embryo has permanent implications for the individual who will live with these changes, yet that individual cannot consent to the procedure. From the point of the first embryo who arrived with the modifications to their genome and the generation to follow, all would not have to live with a certain change to their genetic information, which could not be the case if they had consented “no” to a change. Having to think about that from the perspective of a person who may be affected arises a feeling of a loss of autonomy and a violation of what one feels is morally and ethically correct. This is supported by Clara Hildebrandt, and Jonathan Marron who wrote that “genome editing fundamentally challenges the autonomy of future individuals, as their genetic makeup is predetermined without their input” (Hildebrandt). Because of this, there needs to be a greater effort to establish a framework to work under that considers the rights and autonomy of future generations when discussing genetic modifications. This, however, is not possible at the moment since there is currently no way to communicate to the future to get full consent to make genetic changes. By proceeding with genome editing, society risks infringing on the autonomy of individuals in future generations who are affected by it, which would be a major violation of the medical ethics based on Kantian principles on the largest scale ever seen if it were to come to the worst case scenario of human genome editing. In addition to the ethical challenge of obtaining consent from future generations, there is a significant issue with the informed consent of current participants. Given the complexity of genome editing, patients or their families might not fully understand the risks and long-term implications of the procedures they consent to (Hildebrandt). This raises questions about whether consent is genuinely informed or merely assumed. The situation becomes even more extreme in cases involving vulnerable populations, such as children, individuals from low socioeconomic backgrounds, or those with limited educational resources. These individuals might lack the capacity or access to resources necessary to make well-informed decisions about their participation in genome editing experiments. Justice and Equity The last ethical justification against the use of human genome editing is the potential to create a greater lack of justice and equity, not only in healthcare but even as far as creating a whole new social class. This is all derived from the socioeconomic stratification that occurs within healthcare. It will be an expensive procedure for anyone to get done based on the current status of the price stratification of other simpler drugs for things such as diabetes and asthma. This is pointed out by Clara and Jonathan in their article when they say, “The high cost of genome editing technologies like CRISPR may limit access to the wealthy, creating a form of genetic classism” (Hildebrandt). Financial barriers to accessing genome editing tools could restrict their availability to underprivileged populations, which can further widen healthcare disparities (Ayanoğlu). Without proper and specific regulation, the benefits of genome editing could be monopolized by those with greater resources and intent to profit or benefit greatly from it, leaving less affluent groups at a disadvantage. This inequity contradicts the ethical principles of justice and fairness, which demand that calls for advancements be accessible to all individuals regardless of socioeconomic status to protect the ethical principles of medicine. If genome editing extends beyond medical treatments into enhancements for intelligence, physical abilities, or even appearance, it could lead to a society where those who can afford enhancements gain significant advantages over those who cannot. This "genetic divide" would not only widen existing socioeconomic gaps but could also result in new forms of discrimination. People with unedited genomes might face stigmatization, reduced opportunities, or outright exclusion in certain spheres of society. Such disparities would undermine the ethical principle of justice, which demands fairness and equity in the distribution of healthcare advancements. To address these concerns, it is important to establish global regulations and frameworks that prioritize equitable access to genome editing technologies. Without such measures, genome editing risks becoming a tool for perpetuating privilege rather than a means of advancing human health and well-being for all. These regulations must also include strict oversight to prevent the commercialization of genetic modifications for enhancements, ensuring that advancements focus on therapeutic benefits and not further social stratification. Counterargument: The Potential to Treat Genetic Disorders Supporters of human genome editing argue that its potential to treat genetic disorders outweighs its ethical challenges. The ability for it to make an immediate impact in the many lives of those affected by such diseases is very powerful. CRISPR is most known currently for the current work that is being done to eliminate hereditary diseases like cystic fibrosis and sickle cell anemia in entire bloodlines (Uddin). There is even a therapeutic potential use to use CRISPR for advancements in therapeutic applications as well (Uddin). The overall presence of human genome technology without a doubt would improve the quality of life for millions and possibly for billions in the future too. However, these benefits must be weighed against ethical concerns. While genome editing could indeed lead to significant medical breakthroughs, its potential risks and moral implications cannot be ignored. If billions of people are fundamentally affected at the core by an intentional violation of multiple fundamental ethical principles of medicine, then how credible is it of a framework to further enforce in other aspects of medicine that affect fewer people? The ability to do something does not necessarily mean we ought to do it. Ethical progress must match the speed of technological progress (or in most cases vice versa) to ensure that advancements do not come at the expense of fundamental moral principles. Conclusion Human genome editing represents a double-edged sword: a tool with the potential to eradicate genetic diseases and revolutionize medicine but also a technology riddled with ethical dilemmas, with no direct answers, given the resources we have in the current time and the unimaginable use that could be derived from it that ultimately could end the world in the most extreme case of its use. The risks of unintended consequences, the violation of informed consent, and the lack of justice and equity render genome editing ethically impermissible. While there is simply no answer to these major red flags yet, the investment into more research continues unregulated at an unprecedented rate. Hopefully, it is because it is pivoting... The technology of genome editing is not entirely bad. While I am against “human” genome editing entirely, agriculture is fair game. Genome editing in agriculture can be used to enhance crop resilience and nutrition (Sagar Kafle). This can help relieve other problems we are facing today, such as world hunger, without putting any ethical principles at risk of being irreversibly violated. This would be the best case forward while also upholding medical ethics and the Kantian principles that support it. References AYANOĞLU, F. B., ELÇİN, A. E., & ELÇİN, Y. M. (2020). Bioethical issues in genome editing by CRISPR-Cas9 technology. TURKISH JOURNAL of BIOLOGY, 44(2), 110–120. https://doi.org/10.3906/biy-1912-52 Cahn, N. (2021, April 9). CRISPR Parents and Informed Consent. Ssrn.com. https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=3823488 Hildebrandt, C. C., & Marron, J. M. (2018). Justice in CRISPR/Cas9 Research and Clinical Applications. AMA Journal of Ethics, 20(9), 826–833. https://doi.org/10.1001/amajethics.2018.826. Jacinto, F. V., Link, W., & Ferreira, B. I. (2020). CRISPR/Cas9‐mediated genome editing: From basic research to translational medicine. Journal of Cellular and Molecular Medicine, 24(7), 3766–3778. https://doi.org/10.1111/jcmm.14916 Khan, S., Mahmood, M. S., Rahman, S. ur, Zafar, H., Sultan Habibullah, khan, Z., & Ahmad, A. (2018). CRISPR/Cas9: the Jedi against the dark empire of diseases. Journal of Liu, Y., Zou, R. S., He, S., Yuta Nihongaki, Li, X., Razavi, S., Wu, B., & Ha, T. (2020). Very fast CRISPR on demand. Science, 368(6496), 1265–1269. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.aay8204 Sagar Kafle. (2022). CRISPR/CAS9: A new paradigm for crop improvement revolutionizing agriculture. Journal of Agriculture and Food Research, 11, 100484–100484. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jafr.2022.100484 Uddin, F., Rudin, C. M., & Sen, T. (2020). CRISPR Gene Therapy: Applications, Limitations, and Implications for the Future. Frontiers in Oncology, 10. https://doi.org/10.3389/fonc.2020.01387