Parapsychology A Handbook for the 21st Century Edited by Etzel Cardeña, John Palmer and David Marcusson-Clavertz McFarland & Company, Inc., Publishers Jefferson, North Carolina OceanofPDF.com LIBRARY OF CONGRESS CATALOGUING DATA ARE AVAILABLE BRITISH LIBRARY CATALOGUING DATA ARE AVAILABLE e-ISBN: 978-1-4766-2105-0 © 2015 Etzel Cardeña, John Palmer and David Marcusson-Clavertz. All rights reserved No part of this book may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying or recording, or by any information storage and retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publisher. Cover image © 2015 Petr Vaclavek/Dreamstime McFarland & Company, Inc., Publishers Box 611, Jefferson, North Carolina 28640 www.mcfarlandpub.com OceanofPDF.com The editors dedicate this volume to the memory of the SPR pioneers in the study of psi phenomena, including such luminaries as William James and Eleanor Sidgwick, and to two more recent pathbreakers, William Braud and Robert L. Morris. Etzel Cardeña also dedicates the book to his beloved, the perennially precious playful poet and psychologist Sophie Reijman, and to all beessies who are part of the unveiled reality. OceanofPDF.com Table of Contents Preface: Reintroduction Parapsychology (Etzel Cardeña, David Marcusson-Clavertz and John Palmer) Part One: Basic Concepts 1. An Overview of Modern Developments in Parapsychology (Nancy L. Zingrone, Carlos S. Alvarado and Gerd H. Hövelmann) 2. Parapsychology in Context: The Big Picture (Edward F. Kelly) 3. The Case Against Psi (Douglas M. Stokes) Part Two: Research Methods and Statistical Approaches 4. Experimental Methods in Anomalous Cognition and Anomalous Perturbation Research (John Palmer) 5. Research Methods with Spontaneous Case Studies (Emily Williams Kelly and Jim B. Tucker) 6. Macro-Psychokinesis: Methodological Concerns (Graham Watkins) 7. Statistical Guidelines for Empirical Studies (Patrizio E. Tressoldi and Jessica Utts) Part Three: Psychology and Psi 8. Psychological Concepts of Psi Function: A Review and Constructive Critique (Rex G. Stanford) 9. States, Traits, Cognitive Variables and Psi (Etzel Cardeña and David Marcusson-Clavertz) 10. Ariadne’s Thread: Meditation and Psi (Serena M. Roney-Dougal) Part Four: Biology and Psi 11. Psi and Biology: An Evolutionary Perspective (Richard S. Broughton) 12. Drugs and Psi Phenomena (David Luke) Part Five: Physics and Psi 13. Quantum Theory and Parapsychology (Brian Millar) 14. Physical Correlates of Psi (Adrian Ryan) Part Six: Psi Phenomena: Anomalous Cognition, Perturbation and Force 15. Explicit Anomalous Cognition: A Review of the Best Evidence in Ganzfeld, Forced Choice, Remote Viewing and Dream Studies (Johann Baptista, Max Derakhshani and Patrizio E. Tressoldi) 16. Implicit Anomalous Cognition (John Palmer) 17. Psi and Psychophysiology (Dean Radin and Alan Pierce) 18. Experimental Research on Distant Intention Phenomena (Stefan Schmidt) 19. Macro-Psychokinesis (Stephen E. Braude) 20. Micro-Psychokinesis (Mario Varvoglis and Peter A. Bancel) 21. Implicit Physical Psi: The Global Consciousness Project (Roger D. Nelson) 22. Experimenter Effects in Parapsychological Research (John Palmer and Brian Millar) Part Seven: Psi Phenomena: Research on Survival 23. Mental Mediumship (Julie Beischel and Nancy L. Zingrone) 24. Reincarnation: Field Studies and Theoretical Issues Today (Antonia Mills and Jim B. Tucker) 25. Ghosts and Poltergeists: An Eternal Enigma (Michaeleen Maher) 26. Electronic Voice Phenomena (Mark R. Leary and Tom Butler) Part Eight: Practical Applications 27. Psi in Everyday Life: Nonhuman and Human (Rupert Sheldrake) 28. Exceptional Experiences (ExE) in Clinical Psychology (Martina Belz and Wolfgang Fach) 29. Applied Psi (Paul H. Smith and Garret Moddel) Part Nine: To Sum It Up 30. On the Usefulness of Parapsychology for Science at Large (Gerd H. Hövelmann) 31. On Negative Capability and Parapsychology: Personal Reflections (Etzel Cardeña) About the Contributors List of Names and Terms OceanofPDF.com Preface Reintroducing Parapsychology ETZEL CARDEÑA, DAVID MARCUSSON-CLAVERTZ and JOHN PALMER The report of my death was an exaggeration.—Mark Twain, May 31, 1897 Parapsychology is the scientific study of ostensible parapsychological phenomena such as telepathy and psychokinesis (see below). As with the report of the death of the great ironist Mark Twain while he was alive, the reports about the demise of parapsychology (e.g., Hyman, 2010) have been greatly exaggerated. There are at least three good reasons why this is the case. First, reports of meaningful and extraordinary events such as Mark Twain’s dream that seemed to anticipate in detail the death of his brother (Kripal, 2014), or in which some individuals seem to have precise knowledge not attributable to their senses or logical reasoning (e.g., Lloyd Mayer, 2007) continue to occur and are widespread across the globe (Watt & Tierney, 2014). When one inquires, it is not unusual to have people mention that they seem to have extraordinary coincidences with someone close to them, or that they dreamed about an event that happened in the future but could not have been reasonably anticipated. Although some of these experiences may be the result of selective reporting or a bad estimate of probabilities, others can hardly be explained away as “mere coincidence,” even considering the law of large numbers and the occurrence of very unusual events just by chance (cf. Dyson, 2004; see also chapter 27, this volume). From its onset as a scientific discipline, parapsychology (or psychical research) considered “chance” as an alternative explanation and rejected it only after evaluating its probability (Holt, Simmonds-Moore, Luke, & French, 2012). It is thus not surprising that psi phenomena are seriously contemplated not only in science but also in art and culture at large (Cardeña, Iribas, & Reijman, 2012; chapter 30, this volume). Second, as most of the chapters in this volume attest, there are various parapsychology research paradigms (e.g., ganzfeld, dream, remote viewing, presentiment) that control for chance and support the existence of psi phenomena using the same criteria as those for mainstream topics. Even Richard Wiseman, a foremost critic of parapsychology, is on record stating that “by the standards of any other area of science … remote viewing is proven” (http://www.dailymail.co.uk/news/article-510762/Could-prooftheory-ALL-psychic.html). Third, although some parapsychology critics have been vociferous and often persecuted those who dare to conduct research in the area, previous surveys and a recent letter written by 100 academics show that many researchers have not been persuaded by their rhetoric (Cardeña, 2011, 2014). Furthermore, a number of recent books have taken these critics to task for their double standards and misrepresentation of the results of psi research (e.g., McLuhan, 2010; Storr, 2013). These arguments do not deny that the field faces considerable challenges including lack of funding and gaining greater acceptance as a topic of investigation (McClenon, 1982), but they reject an unjustified closure of phenomena that continue to interest both laypeople and scientists, and have important theoretical and practical implications. Although we are far from having a full understanding of psi phenomena or being able to provide a perfectly replicable experiment, there have been a number of empirical and theoretical advances in the last few decades, described in this book. What Is Parapsychology? To communicate and transact with the world, humans use a number of senses to gain information from it and muscles to act upon it. Commonly reported, however, are experiences of phenomena in which information or energy seems to have been apprehended or transferred without the operation of the known senses or logical inference, and these are usually referred to as psi phenomena (Bem & Honorton, 1994). Parapsychology is the scientific study of these phenomena, and it includes consideration of both common psychological explanations (e.g., inferential mistakes) as well as explanations in which mind may be a basic, irreducible aspect of reality (cf. Nagel, 2012) that may transcend the perceived limitations of the body (Sidgwick, 1932). Prospective research not only on psi but on near-death experiences (e.g., Parnia et al., 2014) suggests that the relation between the brain and the mind is far more complex than the usual “brain creates mind” dictum [chapter 2, this volume]. Traditionally, psi phenomena have been classified according to the ostensible source and direction of the communication. In telepathy, information appears to be received directly from another mind, such as sensing that a loved one is calling for help from a distance. In clairvoyance, information appears to be received from a distant event or object, such as sensing that there is a fire in another city in the absence of any news about it. In precognition information appears to be received from a future event, such as dreaming about a disaster that occurs later that same day. In retrocognition, a person may seem to know what occurred in the past without using the senses or logic, as in providing precise information about a crime that occurred earlier. It is worth mentioning that retrocognition and precognition are not orthogonal to clairvoyance or telepathy since an experience could be labeled as either precognitive–clairvoyant or precognitive–telepathic. It is common to group these categories as forms of extrasensory perception or ESP. In psychokinesis (PK) it appears that our minds have a direct energetic effect on matter, such as a watch stopping at the time of someone’s death. Parapsychology also includes the scientific study of the possibility of survival of consciousness after bodily death, such as apparent communication with a deceased person or memories of a past life. Some of these labels have been criticized for being burdened with theoretical assumptions about the underlying mechanism (May, Utts, & Spottiswoode, 1995; Palmer, 1992), and since there is debate as to the nature of psi, it may be advisable to use more neutral terms. For instance, the term “extrasensory perception” implies that there is a perceptual ability other than the usual senses at work, although there is reason to suppose that psi is not perceptual [e.g., chapters 9 and 14], so alternative terms have been offered. May and colleagues (1995) proposed instead of ESP the term anomalous cognition (AC) to refer to ostensible acquisition of information in ways that are currently unexplained, and the term anomalous perturbation (AP) to refer to ostensible influence of mind on matter in ways that are currently unexplained, but this term applies only to what has traditionally been called micro-PK (effects on microscopic systems, typically random number generators). The term does not seem applicable to what is traditionally labeled as macro-PK (effects visible to the naked eye, such as levitation of objects), for which we propose the neologism anomalous force (AF). Many of the authors in this volume, however, have used the terms for the standard subcategories of ESP: telepathy (AC when the source is another person’s mind), clairvoyance (AC when the source is an external object or event), and precognition (AC when the source is in the future). We use psi and anomalous mental phenomena1 interchangeably as neutral umbrella concepts that include AC, AP, and AF. Moreover, we make a distinction between explicit and implicit anomalous mental phenomena. In the case of explicit anomalous mental phenomena, individuals consciously intend to interact with other systems (e.g., attempting to retrieve information via telepathy). If the process is implicit there is no conscious awareness of the phenomenon occurring but individuals nonetheless respond to the information, for instance physiologically. Throughout its existence, parapsychology has often been discussed as an independent science or discipline, but it is more precise to think of it as a transdisciplinary topic that is relevant to a number of disciplines including psychology, anthropology, physics, biology, and the humanities. Although a major component of research in the area revolves around what we could call the “psi hypothesis,” namely that sentient beings are able to obtain information not mediated by the senses or reason, or act on matter directly independently of known physical mechanisms, there are works that leave that question aside and focus on, for instance, the sociocultural or aesthetic impact of ostensible parapsychological experiences or beliefs (e.g., Cardeña et al., 2012; Owen, 1990). In surveys of general samples and of academics, majorities have reported for decades that parapsychology is a legitimate scientific undertaking, and that psi phenomena is established or a likely possibility (http://en.wikademia.org/Surveys_of_academic_opinion_regarding_parapsy chology), with psychologists having been noticeably more skeptical than other disciplines (Wagner & Monnet, 1979). McClenon (1982) also found strong and widespread skepticism among Council members and section committee members of the American Association for the Advancement of Science, especially in sections that emphasize theory/philosophy or basic research as opposed to application. It is instructive that a skeptic of parapsychology has commented that “most psychologists could reasonably be described as uninformed skeptics—a minority could reasonably be described as prejudiced bigots—where the paranormal is concerned” (French, 2001, p. 7). And despite the notoriety of the professional magician and debunker “The Amazing Randi,” surveys have shown that the majority of magicians believe the phenomena to be valid or likely (Carter, 2012). There has also been a very vehement and at times aggressive set of critics of the psi hypothesis, some of whom have made a career out of their critiques (Cardeña, 2011; Zingrone, 2004). They have repeatedly stated that there is no empirical evidence for the psi hypothesis and/or that the hypothesis is by definition impossible and any attempt to test it is foolish if not outright dishonest. In this volume, we present a comprehensive survey of the field, including a chapter by a critic, so that readers can evaluate the evidence and arguments for and against psi and make up their own mind. We are by no means the first to attempt to give an empirically-based and comprehensive overview of the field at a particular point in time. Joseph Banks Rhine, the best-known psi researcher in the middle of the 20th century, and his associates provided a number of summaries of their extensive research work (e.g., Rhine, Pratt, Stuart, Smith, & Greenwood, 1940). There have also been later comprehensive synopses of the field by experts, including one directed to a general readership (Broughton, 1991) and a more technical one (Radin, 1997), both having the advantages and disadvantages of a single-authored work. A Comparison with the 1977 Handbook of Parapsychology The most direct precedent and inspiration for our work is the 1977 Handbook of Parapsychology, edited by Benjamin B. Wolman, with Laura A. Dale, Gertrude R. Schmeidler, and Montague Ullman as associate editors. Its 11 parts (history; research methods; perception, communication, and parapsychology; parapsychology and physical systems; parapsychology and altered states of consciousness; parapsychology and healing; survival of bodily death; parapsychology and other fields; parapsychological models and theories; soviet research in parapsychology; and suggested readings and glossary), comprising 36 chapters, was an attempt to provide a “state of the science” account, with many of the most eminent researchers and theoreticians as contributors. Although there is much overlap between the chapter topics in the 1977 Handbook and this volume, there are also some differences. In most cases, they reflect changes that have occurred in the field over the years. We will run through the most noteworthy differences in order as defined by the Table of Contents of the 1977 Handbook. The first difference is that the 1977 Handbook has no chapter on methodology for studying AF effects, and these were not addressed in the Experimental Psychokinesis chapter devoted to results. We see this as a simple oversight rather than being due to an increase in the amount of anomalous force (AF) research being conducted. It also may have something to do with the fact that at that time many parapsychologists felt that most AF effects (poltergeists being a notable exception) were fraudulent and did not want parapsychology to be identified with ostensible AF manifestations. This in turn may have been influenced by the considerable media attention devoted at the time to the psychic Uri Geller, whose AF exhibitions were widely (but not universally) considered to be fraudulent. On the other hand, the 1977 Handbook did include a chapter on paranormal photography, devoted primarily to the exploits of the psychic Ted Serios, so the oversight was not total. Although both volumes contain chapters on experimenter effects, Rhea White (1977) explicitly excluded discussion of experimenter psi, claiming a lack of space. This decision nonetheless speaks to her priorities and reflects the discomfort that most parapsychologists have always had with this topic as an explanation of psi effects in the laboratory. It is only in the 1980s, with the research on the checker effect [see chapter 22, this volume] that experimenter psi began to be reflected in the literature, and now it has become a virtual obsession with some. Another major difference in coverage, which is related to experimenter psi and may contribute to the growing interest in it, is the distinction made only in the current volume between implicit and explicit psi, with separate chapters devoted to each. Until the introduction of the psi-mediated response model in the 1970s, parapsychologists took it for granted that participants in laboratory studies had to intend to produce psi for it to occur. This has changed to such an extent that the three most prominent methodological paradigms in recent years—the Global Consciousness Project, the presentiment effect, and retroactive psi influence on psychological tasks [see chapters 16, 17, and 21]—all involve implicit psi. Although both volumes contain chapters on poltergeists and hauntings, the chapter in the 1977 Handbook by William Roll, entitled simply “Poltergeists,” had only one page devoted to the latter. To some extent this reflects his interests at the time, but we have noticed a drop-off in published poltergeist cases since 1977, offset by an increase in reports of haunting cases. A prime example is Roll himself, whose more recent investigations were of apparent hauntings (e.g., Roll, Maher, & Brown, 1992). In keeping with the upsurge of interest in popular culture in technology and electronics associated with the computer age, psi researchers in recent decades have shown a renewed interest in the role that physical energies might play in mediating psi effects, the prime example being the earth’s geomagnetic field. This interest is reflected by chapters in this volume on physical energies and psi and, to a lesser extent, electronic voice phenomena. The 1977 Handbook did not have chapters covering empirical research on these topics, although relevant theories were covered at some length in the chapter by C. T. K. Chari. At the time the 1977 Handbook was published there had been little research involving psychophysiological variables either as predictors or measures of psi. The terms DMILS and presentiment were not yet part of our vocabulary. Discussion of what little research there was consumed only five pages in a chapter entitled “Parapsychology, Biology, and Anpsi” by Robert L. Morris. Since then, psychophysiological variables have become extremely prominent in parapsychology, mostly as psi measures. Thus, in the current volume no less than three chapters are devoted to such research. A topic that was not nearly as known in 1977 as now is near-death experiences, which have received an inordinate amount of media attention. Besides their relevance to the study of consciousness in general, they have at times included accurate and corroborated reports of anomalous cognition (Greyson, 2014), and most recently a prospective study had one such report (Parnia et al., 2014) [see also chapter 6]. The previously discussed differences involve topics that are represented in the current volume but not in the original one. The final example is the opposite. It concerns DMILS research aimed specifically at curing some kind of physical disease or malady, in other words, psychic or spiritual healing. The 1977 Handbook contained a chapter on this topic, but the current volume does not, despite a huge upsurge in such research in recent decades. Nor is such research covered in the chapters devoted to psi and psychophysiology. The main reason for this omission is that this work has been published almost exclusively in alternative medicine or other medical journals rather than parapsychology journals. In practice, the domain of parapsychology is partly defined by what gets published in the specialized journals, and we followed that convention for our current volume. Advances in parapsychology since 1977 are also reflected by differences in the contents of chapters on a common topic present in both volumes. For example, the statistics chapter in the present volume devotes considerable attention to meta-analyses and Bayesian statistics. These topics are not covered at all in the statistics chapter of the 1977 Handbook because they were not on parapsychology’s (or mainstream psychology’s) radar screen even though Bayesian stats had been discussed earlier (e.g., Bakan, 1973). This comparison of the two volumes belies the claim of some critics (e.g., Hyman, 2010) that parapsychology is a field that has stagnated or even died. Because there is no space to reiterate the comprehensive reviews in the 1977 Handbook and developments since then, we have asked our contributors to briefly summarize the relevant previous sections from that book before focusing on developments in the last 40 years. Some Invalid Criticisms of Psi Research The scientific method demands a skeptical (i.e., open but critical) attitude toward both cherished and abhorred hypotheses. A discussion of alternative explanations and potential problems with previous studies or analyses is healthy and necessary in scientific discourse. We do not refer to that necessary aspect of science in what follows, but rather to a number of specific invalid criticisms of parapsychology. Some of these are outright false or very questionable despite being often repeated, especially in the echo chambers of some blogs and “skeptical” magazines (we strongly recommend that the seriously interested reader skip Wikipedia and these sources, which are often blatantly biased, and consult instead primary journal sources). We list here some of the most common ones along with an explanation of why they are unfounded: (a) Psi research is not scientific because it is not published in scientific, peer-reviewed journals. This is a false but not uncommon belief, despite the fact that it can be easily disproven. Despite the strong bias by some editors against the field, psi work has been published in major transdisciplinary journals such as Nature and Science, as well as in top-tier disciplinary journals such as American Psychologist, Behavioral and Brain Sciences, Psychological Bulletin, the Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, and Physics Letters. In addition, the major parapsychological journals still being published including the Journal of Parapsychology, the Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, and the Journal of Scientific Exploration have been peer-reviewed for decades, and have published failures to replicate and criticism of studies from both proponents and critics of the psi hypothesis. (b) The previous criticism at times has been paradoxically paired with this one: Psi research is not scientific by definition and should not be published in scientific, peer-reviewed journals. The catch-22 logic behind this statement is that psi research is not scientific because it is not published in peer-reviewed journals (false, but never mind that), while simultaneously maintaining that such research cannot be published because it is not scientific (see Cardeña, 2011, for various examples of this [il]logic). (c) Also related to the notion that parapsychology is unscientific is the assertion that psi research does not use the scientific method. In fact, since the founding of the Society for Psychical Research (SPR) in 1882, parapsychological research has strived for unbiased testing of the psi hypothesis through the scientific method, even though (as in other scientific fields) it has not always been applied properly. The SPR and other societies have included as members very eminent scientists (including various Nobel prizewinners) who have used the methodology and skills learned in their respective scientific disciplines to conduct their psi research (e.g., Cardeña, 2013). A perusal of any of the main parapsychology journals shows that the basic elements of the scientific method such as hypothesis testing, designs that seek to eliminate confounding variables, and statistical analysis typify research in this field, a fact that allowed the professional organization of parapsychology, the Parapsychological Association, to become an affiliate of the American Association for the Advancement of Sciences (AAAS) in 1969. Not only that, but some techniques now regularly used in mainstream disciplines such as meta-analysis and masked designs, were created or developed by psi researchers (Watt, 2005). (d) Another false assertion is that only individuals without a scientific background endorse psi. This is clearly not the case, given the number of past and present academy-based researchers who have done research in the field. More insidious is the sometimes implied notion that although these researchers may conduct themselves scientifically in their mainstream fields, they become unscientific when they conduct psi research. An example of this is the opprobrium that the eminent psychologist Daryl Bem received after he published a paper supportive of the psi hypothesis with, among others, Douglas Hofstadter referring to it as “a cutoff for craziness,” and David Helfand as “an assault on science and rationality” (http://www.nytimes.com/roomfordebate/2011/01/06/the-esp-study-whenscience-goes-psychic). A perverse link of this vicious circle is that whereas successful researchers in other areas are assumed to become unscientific once they endorse parapsychology, other researchers who opine on nonmainstream fields without becoming knowledgeable in them are not assumed to be unscientific even though they “fail to do their homework” in the words of Carl Sagan (1976, p. 2). It is very unlikely that those scientists would approve of colleagues in other fields judging their areas of expertise unless the latter had thoroughly studied the literature in that field, yet some critics of parapsychology seem to have no problem doing so. (e) A somewhat tangential but very popular point, especially among nonacademic critics of parapsychology, is that the “Randi prize,” a cash award created by a magician who has made a career out of exposing fraudulent performers, has never been awarded. Thus, some conclude from this that psi phenomena do not exist. Nonetheless, both psi proponents and critics have remarked that such a challenge has nothing to do with how science tests hypotheses, and the circumstances of awarding it are completely controlled by Randi, making the prize a publicity stunt rather than an impartial test (McLuhan, 2010). We should also mention that the vast amount of evidence covered in this volume refers to consistent results deviating from randomness—the kind of evidence often used in many other disciplines, including psychology, medicine, biology, and physics—rather than showing an exceptional ability on demand such as “reading a person’s mind” or making a table levitate. (f) Some in the general public whose only contact with science may be the popular press think that if one or a group of scientists opine something (for instance the notion that psi is a pseudoscience), then all scientists in that field surely must agree with that opinion. In reality, there are contentious disagreements among experts even on mainstream topics (Feyerabend, 1975), so there is no single scientist or even a group of them who can speak for all experts in a field. When a scientist makes a portentous statement such as the existence of psi would annul science or go against the “laws of nature,” there is a good reason to question whether all or even most scientists in the area would agree with the statement. For example, although ostensible precognitive abilities seem to go against the current folk understanding of physics, they do not prima facie contradict block models of time or backward causation, which are currently discussed within mainstream physics [see chapter 13]. Furthermore, the idea that science would disown relativity theory, for example, if psi were established as real to the satisfaction of currently skeptical mainstream scientists is ludicrous. As Braude (1986) has pointed out, parapsychology and these other theories are not mutually exclusive because they account for different domains of phenomena. (g) Another false notion is that only individuals with poor reasoning skills, cognitive biases, and/or mental disorders support the existence of psi phenomena. We have already mentioned that scientists of extraordinary intellect have endorsed psi, but there is a more general version of the criticism, namely that psi supporters in general have cognitive deficits and/or psychological problems. A number of studies (reviewed in Watt & Tierney, 2014; see also chapter 10) do not support this explanation. Of course, there are individuals with reasoning deficits or psychological problems who support psi, but there are also individuals with those problems who do not support psi. As for a general cognitive bias, the most relevant study to date used signal detection analysis and found that whereas psi supporters in general tend to report false positives in a relevant task, psi disbelievers show the opposite bias of reporting false negatives (Riekki, Lindeman, Aleneff, Halme, & Nuortimo, 2013, but see also Van Elk, 2013). Relevant to this finding is a study that showed that both psi-prone and psiagainst individuals tended to rate papers with results incongruent with their beliefs as being of poorer quality (Roe, 1999), a result consistent with research showing that people use differential criteria for conclusions they dislike than for those they prefer (Ditto & Lopez, 1992). This is further confounded by the replicated finding that in controlled psi studies “sheep” (those who believe in the reality of psi phenomena) tend to perform significantly better than “goats” (who do not believe in psi). Thus, the actual (conscious) experience of psi phenomena may partly depend on previous beliefs, and such phenomena may be evaluated in a biased way by both psi-supporters and psi-critics individuals. A true skeptic may be a very rare creature indeed. (h) Then there is the claim that psi critics have explained away the statistical evidence for psi. However, a parapsychology critic (who later retracted the paper from his own webpage), when confronted by a very knowledgeable statistician took the position that although he could not explain away favorable psi results, in principle a future argument could explain them away (Hyman, 1995). This argument is undoubtedly true, but it also applies to every single study and theory in mainstream science; any study could someday be refuted or better explained by a future theory. More recently it has been stated that if parapsychologists used Bayesian rather than frequentist statistical techniques, their results would evaporate. This argument is refuted in chapters 7 and 15 in this volume. (i) A not uncommon position taken by more knowledgeable critics is that even if most research and analyses in parapsychology are well conducted, psi requires exceptional evidence because it is an exceptional claim (e.g., French & Stone, 2014). There are a number of problems with such assertion. The first one is that it misrepresents what the coiner of the phrase meant. Contrary to the way it is usually interpreted, the agnostic author Marcello Truzzi (1978) coined it to declare that there is nothing unscientific about the psi hypothesis, but that “it is actually quite scientifically proper if all ordinary explanations for an established extraordinary event have been found inadequate” (p. 13). But even if we were to misconstrue Truzzi’s phrase, we would encounter the difficulties of having to determine what constitute “exceptional claims” (consider that many common phenomena such as electricity or airplane flying would have been considered exceptional if not impossible in the past). And there is the parallel problem of what would constitute “exceptional evidence,” a concept so flexible that it could be used to either keep changing the evidential goalpost permanently, or to propose such levels of evidence that would make it practically impossible to have evidence for the psi hypothesis no matter how much of it accumulated, as Wagenmakers, Wetzels, Boorsboom, and Van der Maas (2011) do. The artificially created “law” that the evidence for psi phenomena should follow some (unspecified or impossible to fulfill) higher criteria than the own research of the critics is a particular example of a more general practice in which some critics use a double standard by not applying the same standards of evidence that they seek to impose on parapsychology to other areas (see Zingrone, 2014). Palmer (1987) has shown that applying this version of the extraordinary proof criterion to publication of scientific research would lead to biases in the literature that would give an unfair advantage to ostensibly well-established theories, and it would greatly increase the likelihood of Type II errors (cf. Fiedler, Kutzner, & Krueger, 2012). (j) A more technical argument is that even though there is statistical evidence for psi phenomena it can be explained by what has been called the “file-drawer effect,” namely that only studies supporting psi tend to get published whereas failures to find evidence for psi are not submitted for publication [see chapter 3]. There are four main counterarguments to this assertion: first, parapsychology has actually been ahead of psychology and other fields in encouraging the publication of replication failures in its specialized journals. (By the way, the current realization that some “findings” cannot be replicated on demand or at all in a number of areas, cf. Schooler, 2011, shows that the problem is not unique to psi.) Second, considering the very small number of researchers in the field and the fact that most of them do not have independent means or receive research funding through the usual channels, it is very unlikely that they would spend considerable time and effort conducting a study and then not present it at least to their peers in their meetings, which ipso facto means that the results of their studies are retrievable by any conscientious researcher. Even a brief perusal of the parapsychology journals shows that failures to replicate have been published throughout the history of parapsychology. Moreover, as various chapters in this volume attest, although replication on demand has not been demonstrated for psi, neither has it been demonstrated for many accepted effects in mainstream psychology, and meta-analyses have confirmed the replicability of small effects in several psi research paradigms. Third, there is a reverse kind of file drawer effect, namely that of researchers not publishing or reporting studies supportive of psi, as chapter 27 in this volume describes (see also, for instance, Ertel & French, 2012). Fourth, meta-analyses of various psi areas, including at least one by a critic (Blackmore, 1980), have calculated the number of studies that would be needed to invalidate results supportive of psi, finding it to be a very unlikely explanation (see also Mossbridge, Tressoldi, & Utts, 2012; and chapter 16). (k) An extreme example of not playing the science game fairly is reporting fraudulent data. Here it is important to distinguish whether the source of the fraud is the participants or the researchers. In parapsychology, the strongest risk of fraud has been in the case of séances conducted by individuals who do this professionally. Throughout the history of parapsychology there have been individuals who engaged in these practices, but it bears mentioning that from the inception of the SPR parapsychologists have been instrumental in revealing such frauds (Gauld, 1968). Then there is the scientifically more dangerous possibility of a scientist being the perpetrator of the fraud. In the history of parapsychology there are two well-known cases [see chapter 3] that, it bears mentioning, were unveiled by other psi researchers. Moreover, the possibility of fraud exists in every field and parapsychology does not seem to stand out. Nonetheless, both psi critics and proponents agree that psi (and other types of) research would benefit from such good research practices as multi-site and multi-experimenter testing and a pre-registry of research designs and hypotheses. These practices would improve estimates of the file-drawer effect and reduce the likelihood of fraud and of misreporting the original hypotheses. (l) Finally, we should mention that it is not infrequent for critics to assume that mentioning an alternative explanation to the psi hypothesis, no matter how unfounded or unlikely, suffices to discount the latter. Already Hume and other philosophers had shown that all statements of knowledge are potentially false since circumstances in the future can change. Probably the most extreme exponent of arbitrary explanations to psi was C. E. M. Hansel, whose strategy was to assume that “trickery would be the only alternative explanation to ESP” in a well-conducted psi experiment showing high odds against chance, not withstanding the implausibility or lack of evidence for it (Hansel, 1989, p. 265). He concluded more generally that coming with a possible, no matter how implausible or trivial, counterexplanation for a psi effect would suffice to discredit the latter, an unfalsifiable line of reasoning that even the psi critic Hyman found indefensible (http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=McVY5ogi_q8). In other areas of science, it is expected that a critic who proposes an alternative explanation will carry out a new project or a reanalysis, but critics of parapsychology sometimes state an alternative explanation without testing it, or if they carry out a replication study and get results supportive of psi they change the criteria of success or propose ad hoc explanations (Carter, 2012; and chapter 28). A good example of a follow-up study showing that a skeptical explanation for a psi effect was not adequate is Palmer’s (1983) research in which results in a ganzfeld study could not be explained away by the potential accidental marking of target images. Previously, critics had proposed, but not tested, that hypothesis as an explanation for significant results (see Bierman, 1999, for another example refuting critics’ dismissal of ganzfeld results). Although psi critics seem especially vexed by the possibility that supportive psi results might be false positives, they do not consider the also very serious problem of not rejecting a null hypothesis when it should be rejected, or false negative findings (Fiedler et al. 2012). We have spent some time detailing what we consider to be unfair criticisms of parapsychology, but there are some with which we agree. First, although some inroads have been made in discussing ways to enhance the typically small effect sizes found in psi research—for example, selecting research participants considered more likely to produce psi in the lab and using psychophysiological indicators of psi instead of, or in addition to, introspective reports—parapsychology has not developed a reliable indicator of who is likely to perform consistently well in psi experiments. This contrasts with other research areas such as hypnosis, which took off mostly after the development of valid and reliable measures of hypnotic suggestibility (Cardeña, 2010). Second, although there has been in the past programmatic research of many years duration, as in the work of the Rhines and their associates (Rhine et al., 1940) and Honorton (e.g., Bem & Honorton, 1994; Honorton et al., 1990), the critique that often times the few psi researchers extant seem to jump to a new research strategy rather than pursue a systematic program of research (Wiseman, 2010) is not off-target. Third, especially considering the typical small effects found in psi research (but not unlike those found in, for example, social psychology, see Richard, Bond, & Stokes-Zoota, 2003), many studies in parapsychology are clearly underpowered (as are typically studies within neuroscience, see Button et al., 2013). Thus, developing collaborative, multi-site research should be a priority in the future, despite the scarce resources in this area. Fourth, although there have been attempts to discuss the place of psi phenomena within larger disciplines such as psychology (e.g., Cardeña, Lynn, & Krippner, 2014; Carpenter, 2012) and physics (Kaiser, 2011), the field clearly needs to become more integrated with more established disciplines. It has often been pointed out that terms such as parapsychology elicit in some a very negative reaction, and that we would do better by coining other terms with less baggage, which may be more theoretically neutral and have less of a bias against it. The current consideration of “anomalistic” (or “anomalous”) psychology as part of the elective curriculum in United Kingdom universities is a path-breaking example of normalization of this area. Fifth, up until a few years ago many psi studies were published exclusively as conference proceedings, mostly from the Parapsychological Association’s annual meetings, including some with rather striking results not published anywhere else. Although proposals to these meetings undergo peer-review, this process has been uneven and generally not as rigorous as that of journals, and has contributed to marginalize psi research since findings in most other scientific areas are not only reported as proceedings. Finally, although psi papers have been published in various mainstream journals, more research should be submitted to these forums and not only to specialized parapsychology journals so that researchers in other topics have the opportunity to acquaint themselves with research on this area. Summary of Chapters This handbook contains 31 chapters divided into 9 sections, and we have added cross references within square brackets [ ] in each chapter to lead the reader to related materials in other chapters. The first section sets up the stage for the remaining of this book. Following this chapter, Nancy L. Zingrone, Carlos S. Alvarado, and Gerd H. Hövelmann provide an overview of research trends in parapsychology since about 1977. Among the trends are the rise of anomalous or anomalistic psychology, which seeks to discuss psi experiences and beliefs from conventional psychological theories (although not necessarily discarding the hypothesis of psi phenomena), and the development of theories relating psi phenomena to contemporary physics. The rise and fall of various institutions, journals, and funding sources are also considered. Edward F. Kelly, in chapter 2, critically reviews the prevailing physicalist view in neuroscience. He discusses a number of observations in parapsychology and other fields that challenge this approach. In the next chapter, Douglas M. Stokes takes a critical stance against experimental parapsychology. He discusses the prevalence of scientific misconduct in mainstream research and in parapsychology before presenting a simulation in which a hypothetical distribution of experimenters designated as “filers” (who only publish studies with significant results), “non-filers,” and frauds is compared to that of a recent empirical meta-analysis. Stokes makes the case that the empirical data matches what would be expected if there is no psi and recommends parapsychologists to increase their use of pre-registrations of studies and of multiple experimenters and records to reduce the likelihood of biased file-drawers and scientific misconduct. The second section includes four chapters on research methods and statistical approaches. In chapter 4, John Palmer provides an introductory guide to experimental methods in AC and AP research. In addition to guidelines about eliminating alternative non-psi explanations, he discusses many of the choices that parapsychology researchers are confronted with, such as whether to present the target using telepathy, clairvoyance, or precognition paradigms, or whether to ask the participant to choose an alternative among a set of pre-given ones (forced-choice) or to freely report any impression that comes to mind (free-response). He also discusses how to select participants and prepare them for the experiment. In the next chapter, Emily Williams Kelly and Jim B. Tucker give an overview of methods to study spontaneous cases of psi, with the aims of understanding the meaning the experience has for the experient (experience-based) or testing the veridicality of the phenomenon (evidence-based). The types of cases they review include deathbed visions, synchronicity (meaningful “coincidences”), and mystical experiences. In chapter 6, Graham Watkins deals with methodological concerns when studying macro–PK (or AF). He discusses some of the most famous cases, including that of Ted Serios, who allegedly produced images on polaroid film through mental means, and Uri Geller, who allegedly bent objects like spoons through mental means. He also discusses the methods used when testing so-called “psi-wheels,” which have gained public interest lately. In their contribution, Patrizio E. Tressoldi and Jessica Utts present a guide on statistical approaches to answer quantitative research questions. They provide numerous recommendations on how to report descriptive statistics, handle outliers, conduct null hypothesis significance testing, measure effect-sizes, and analyze data with a Bayesian approach, among other statistical issues. The third section includes three chapters on psychology and psi. Rex G. Stanford, in chapter 8, examines two seminal frameworks, the psi-mediated instrumental response and the first sight models. Both models purport that organisms use psi, often implicitly, to serve adaptive or personal dispositions. Stanford scrutinizes the assumptions of each framework and evaluates their clarity and empirical support. In the following chapter, Etzel Cardeña and David Marcusson-Clavertz review the research on states, traits, and cognitive predictors of performance in psi tasks. They begin by clarifying some of the common conceptual confusions when studying alterations in consciousness before reviewing the association between psi performance and these alterations, as well as other common predictors such as extraversion and belief in psi. They also summarize common measures of psi experiences and beliefs. In chapter 10, Serena M. Roney-Dougal summarizes the research on meditation and psi, a topic that has reclaimed interest during the last decade. She reviews research that has focused on comparing psi performance of meditators and nonmeditators, noticing differences particularly between very long meditators and other meditators. The fourth section includes two chapters on biology and psi. Richard S. Broughton provides an evolutionary perspective and reports that since 1977 biology and parapsychology have moved closer to each other, especially with the emerging trend in using neurophysiological measures to detect AC. He examines the research on brain structures and psi and how they may be affected by environmental factors. In chapter 12, David Luke reviews empirical work on psychoactive substances and psi phenomena. His chapter integrates findings from fieldwork, surveys of psi beliefs, and laboratory parapsychology research. The fifth section contains two chapters on physics and psi. Brian Millar explains how knowledge from physics can help parapsychologists. He compares two frameworks that are frequently used in parapsychology, the observational theories and decision augmentation theory. The review will likely clarify the meaning of central physical constructs that psychologists might confuse with similar psychological terms (e.g., “feedback-loops” and “observation”). In chapter 14, Adrian Ryan summarizes research on physical correlates of psi. He shows how seasonal variation (e.g., higher psi performance in August compared to other months) might explain the association between psi performance and local sidereal time. He then proceeds to review the association between psi performance and geomagnetic activity as well as fluctuations in the magnetic field related to solar activity, and shows that the magnitude of the association is promisingly large. The sixth section contains 8 chapters that evaluate the evidence for psi phenomena across various research paradigms. Johann Baptista, Max Derakhshani, and Patrizio E. Tressoldi provide a comprehensive metaanalytic review of four dominant paradigms for testing explicit AC: ganzfeld (i.e., sensory homogenization), dreams, forced-choice tasks, and remote viewing. They also analyze a number of moderators, such as study quality and whether investigators recruited participants with particular characteristics or used a convenience sample. The authors provide guidelines to increase the likelihood of detecting a psi effect. Much like Stokes, they advise researchers to preregister their studies and make their data available to other investigators. John Palmer, in chapter 16, provides a literature review of implicit AC, which has increased in popularity in the last few decades when Stanford introduced a model that emphasizes the prevalence of implicit psi, and culminated with the widely debated publication of Bem (2011). Palmer distinguishes between research that falls under (a) Stanford’s model, (b) Bem’s experiment series, and (c) others, and reviews the evidence for each class. In the next chapter, Dean Radin and Alan Pierce summarize research on implicit anomalous physiological phenomena, such as the apparent ability to physiologically react to randomly selected arousing stimuli a few seconds before they are shown (presentiment or pre-stimulus response). This paradigm suggests that a large amount of psi activity occurs without conscious awareness. They also review research on whether changes in brain states, such as electroencephalograph (EEG) frequencies and eventrelated potentials, can be used to detect anomalous mental phenomena. In chapter 18, Stefan Schmidt evaluates research on a purported phenomenon known as direct mental interaction in living systems (DMILS). In these studies, participants are designated as agents or percipients and the former are asked to attempt to influence the physiology or behavior of the latter at a distance, typically in one of three ways: activate or calm the percipient, stare or not stare at the percipient, help or not help the percipient focus their attention on a certain object. Usually electrodermal activity (EDA) is measured in the percipients as a measure of arousal, but behavioral responses are common in the helping protocol. Schmidt summarizes metaanalyses of all three protocols. In the next chapter, Stephen E. Braude reviews research on macropsychokinesis (macro–PK, or AF). He begins by critically discussing the common distinction between micro-psychokinesis (micro–PK, or AP) and macro–PK, whether the concepts reflect qualitatively different phenomena or are in a continuum. He next argues against the most common critiques of eyewitness testimony, such as the human bias to “see” things that one is motivated to see. At the end, he presents a number of recent cases on macro–PK. Mario Varvoglis and Peter A. Bancel review in chapter 20 evidence for micro–PK (or AP). They address four central research questions: (a) is there a genuine psi effect?; (b) if so, is this effect attributable to receptive (AC) or expressive (AP) mechanisms?; (c) what are the psychological and physical moderators of this effect?; and (d) to what extent is the effect replicable across experimenters? In chapter 21, Roger D. Nelson presents research on implicit anomalous physical phenomena. Research in this domain investigates whether individuals can influence physical systems (e.g., random number generators, RNGs) by mental means even if there is no conscious intention of doing so. The Global Consciousness Project (GCP) has been evaluating whether the occurrence of events that engage people worldwide (e.g., the terrorist attacks on the 11th of September of 2001) are associated with deviations in the output of RNGs spread out across the globe. In the following chapter, John Palmer and Brian Millar deal with the observation that some researchers consistently get better results than others (experimenter effect). They focus on two main explanations of this effect: that experimenters differ in the ways they motivate participants or make them feel relaxed, confident, and so on (experimenter behavior hypothesis), or that experimenters differ in the ways they use their own psi abilities to influence the outcome (experimenter psi hypothesis). Palmer evaluates the evidence from the experimental literature and Millar discusses it in light of observational theories and decision augmentation theory. The seventh section contains four chapters on research on survival. Julie Beischel and Nancy L. Zingrone summarize research on mediumship, another topic that has regained interest during the last decade. They review the protocols of recent proof-oriented studies with various levels of masking and the findings of those studies. Process-oriented and qualitative research is also given attention, such as investigations of neural correlates of mediumship and the phenomenology of mediumship experience. Antonia Mills and Jim B. Tucker, in chapter 24, review research on cases suggestive of reincarnation. They present an example of a young boy who apparently remembered details of a past life as a war pilot. Although research on spontaneous cases like this faces many methodological challenges, this case report illustrates the remarkable richness of details in some of the correspondences between past-life memories and events. The authors report on general trends in spontaneous case data and discuss a variety of explanations, such as cryptomnesia (learning the information through normal means but then forgetting the source), fraud, psi, and reincarnation. In the following chapter, Michaeleen Maher reviews research on ghosts and poltergeists and compares the characteristics of people reporting them. She also summarizes the methods of investigation, such as the increasing trend of using various technological applications. As with other chapters, the evidence for diverse explanations is reviewed. Mark R. Leary and Tom Butler, in chapter 26, discuss research on anomalous voice-like sounds heard through electronic equipment (electronic voice phenomena). The chapter describes a number of methodological pitfalls to avoid mistaking, say, mundane radio interferences or physical sounds for anomalous voices. They also discuss research on the tendency for individuals to find meaningful patterns in random noise. They evaluate mundane and parapsychological hypotheses (AP and discarnate voices). The eighth section contains three chapters on practical applications. Rupert Sheldrake summarizes research on psi phenomena in everyday life. He reviews research on nonhuman animals such as dogs that seem to know when their owners are coming home. Dogs are not the only animal with psi abilities it seems, with similar observations being reported for parrots, cats, and horses. He then reviews research on anomalous mental phenomena in humans, such as the feeling of being stared at, and the experience of thinking about a person right before that person calls you on the phone. In chapter 28, Martina Belz and Wolfgang Fach discuss anomalous or exceptional experiences in clinical settings. They summarize their characteristics and the people who report them, focusing on specific phenomenology and the motives and goals of the person. Because some individuals who have these experiences feel confused and frightened about them, the authors describe how to best offer counseling to these individuals. In the following chapter, Paul H. Smith and Garret Moddel summarize potential practical applications of psi phenomena. They include the use of psi in the military (e.g., the well-known Star Gate project), finance and investing, criminal investigations, and archaeology. They also discuss a number of promising future mobile apps that may be just the beginning of a new research trend in parapsychology. The ninth section contains two chapters that offer an integrative summary of the field. In chapter 30, Gerd H. Hövelmann explains the usefulness of parapsychology for science at large. He makes a distinction between science as an “institutional phenomena” and as a “distinguished form of knowledge” and evaluates how parapsychology relates to these aspects of science. He next reviews several contributions from parapsychology to other fields, such as the pioneering of various statistical analyses and multiple contributions to psychology including research on dissociation. In the final chapter Etzel Cardeña gives his personal impression on patterns found throughout the volume in the context of the limitations of human knowledge. Note 1. Notice that the concept of anomalous phenomena (assumed to be consensually observable events) differs from that of anomalous experiences (subjective experiences that may or may not be consensually verifiable) (Cardeña, Lynn, & Krippner, 2014). References Bakan, D. (1973). On method. Toward a reconstruction of psychological investigation. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass. Bem, D. J., and Honorton, C. (1994). Does psi exist? Replicable evidence for an anomalous process of information transfer. Psychological Bulletin, 115, 4–18. Bierman, D. J. (1999). The PRL autoganzfeld revisited: Refuting the sound leakage hypothesis. Journal of Parapsychology, 63, 271–274. Blackmore, S. (1980). The extent of selective reporting in ESP ganzfeld studies. European Journal of Parapsychology, 3, 213–219. Braude, S. (1986). The limits of influence: Psychokinesis and the philosophy of science. New York, NY: Routledge and Kegan Paul. Broughton, R. S. (1991). Parapsychology: The controversial science. New York, NY: Ballantine Books. Button, K. S., Ioannidis, J. P. A., Mokrysz, C., Nosek, B. A., Flint, J., Robinson, E. S. J., and Munafò, M. R. (2013). Power failure: Why small sample size undermines the reliability of neuroscience. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 14, 365–376. Cardeña, E. (2010). Presidential address: A look at the potential future of parapsychology with help from a regression to the hypnotic past. Journal of Parapsychology, 74, 15–30. Cardeña, E. (2011). On wolverines and epistemological totalitarianism. Journal of Scientific Exploration, 25, 539–551. Cardeña, E. (2013). Eminent authors from other areas. Mindfield, 5, 83–90. Cardeña, E. (2014). A call for an open, informed, study of all aspects of consciousness. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, doi: 10.3389/fnhum.2014.00017 Cardeña, E., Iribas, A., and Reijman, S. (2012). Art and psi. Journal of Parapsychology, 76, 3–25. Cardeña, E., Lynn, S. J., and Krippner, S. (Eds.) (2014). Varieties of anomalous experience: Examining the scientific evidence (2nd ed.). Washington, D.C.: American Psychological Association. Carpenter, J. C. (2012). First sight: ESP and parapsychology in everyday life. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield. Carter, C. (2012). Science and psychic phenomena: The fall of the house of skeptics. Rochester, VT: Inner Traditions. Ditto, P. H. and Lopez, D. F. (1992). Motivated skepticism: Use of differential decision criteria for preferred and nonpreferred conclusions. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 63, 568–584. Dyson, F. (2014, March 25). One in a million. New York Review of Books. http://www.nybooks.com/articles/archives/2004/mar/25/one-in-a-million/ Ertel, S., and French, C. (2012). Debate: Are psi effects reproducible under watchful skeptical conditions? Mindfield, 4, 68–70. Feyerabend, P. K. (1975). Against method: Outline of an anarchistic theory of knowledge. London, UK: Verso. Fiedler, K., Kutzner, F., and Krueger, J. I. (2012). The long way from αerror control to validity proper: Problems with a short-sighted false-positive debate. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 7, 661–669. French, C. (2001). Weird science at Goldsmiths. The Skeptic 14 (1), 7–8. French, C., and Stone, A. (2014). Anomalistic psychology: Exploring paranormal belief & experience. Hampshire, UK: Palgrave Macmillan. Gauld, A. (1968). The founders of psychical research. New York, NY: Schoken. Greyson, B. (2014). Near-death experiences. In E. Cardeña, S. J. Lynn, and S. Krippner (Eds.), Varieties of anomalous experience: Examining the scientific evidence (2nd ed.) (pp. 333–367). Washington, D.C.: American Psychological Association. Hansel, C. E. M. (1989). The search for psychic power: ESP & parapsychology revisited. Buffalo, NY: Prometheus. Holt, N., Simmonds-Moore, Luke, D., and French, C. (2012). Anomalistic psychology. Basingstoke, UK: Palgrave Macmillan. Honorton, C., Berger, R., Varvoglis, M., Quant, M., Derr, P., Schechter, E., and Ferrari, D. (1990). Psi communication in the ganzfeld: Experiments with an automated testing system and comparison with a meta-analysis of earlier studies. Journal of Parapsychology, 54, 99–139. Hyman, R. (1995). Evaluation of program on anomalous mental phenomena. Retrieved July 14, 2014, from http://www.ics.uci.edu/~jutts/hyman.html Hyman, R. (2010) The demise of parapsychology, 1850–2009. The Skeptic, 22 (2), 17–20. Kaiser, D. (2011). How the hippies saved physics. Science, counterculture, and the quantum revival. New York, NY: Norton. Kripal, J. (2014). Visions of the impossible. How “fantastic“ stories unlock the nature of consciousness. Chronicle of Higher Education. Retrieved from http://chronicle.com/article/Embrace-the-Unexplained/145557/ Lloyd Mayer, E. (2007). Extraordinary knowing: Science, skepticism, and the inexplicable powers of the human mind. New York, NY: Bantam Books. May, E. C., Utts, J. M., and Spottiswoode, S. J. P. (1995). Decision augmentation theory: Toward a model of anomalous mental phenomena. Journal of Parapsychology, 59, 195–220. McClenon, J. (1982). A survey of elite scientists: Their attitudes toward ESP and parapsychology. Journal of Parapsychology, 46, 127–152. McLuhan, R. (2010). Randi’s prize: What sceptics say about the paranormal, why they are wrong, and why it matters. London, UK: Matador. Moody, R. (1975). Life after life. Atlanta, GA: Mockingbird Books. Mossbridge J., Tressoldi, P., and Utts, J. (2012). Predictive physiological anticipation preceding seemingly unpredictable stimuli: A meta-analysis. Frontiers in Psychology 3, 390. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2012.00390 Nagel, T. (2012). Mind and cosmos: Why the materialist neo-darwinian conception of nature is almost certainly false. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Owen, A. (1990). The darkened room: Women, power, and Spiritualism in late Victorian England. Philadelphia, PA: University of Pennsylvania Press. Palmer, J. (1983). Sensory contamination of free-response ESP targets: The greasy fingers hypothesis. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 77, 101–113. Palmer, J. (1987). Dulling Occam’s razor: The role of coherence in assessing scientific knowledge claims. European Journal of Parapsychology, 7, 73–82. Palmer, J. (1992). From survival to transcendence: Reflections on psi as anomalous. Journal of Parapsychology, 56, 229–254. Parnia, S., Spearpoint, K., de Vos, G., Fenwick, P., Goldberg, D., Yank, J., … Schoenfeld, E. R. (2014). AWARE—AWAreness during REsuscitation: A prospective study. Resuscitation. Radin, D. (1997). The conscious universe: The scientific truth of psychic phenomena. New York, NY: Harper Collins. Rhine, J. B., Pratt, J. G., Stuart, C. E., Smith, B. M., and Greenwood, J. A. (1940). Extra sensory perception after sixty years. A critical appraisal of the research in extra-sensory perception. Boston, MA: Bruce Humphries. Richard, F. D., Bond, C. F., Jr. , and Stokes-Zoota, J. J. (2003). One hundred years of social psychology quantitatively described. Review of General Psychology, 7, 331–363. Riekki, T., Lindeman, M., Aleneff, M., Halme, A., and Nuortimo, A. (2013). Paranormal and religious believers are more prone to illusory face perception than skeptics and non-believers. Applied Cognitive Psychology, 27, 150–155. Roe, C. A. (1999). Critical thinking and belief in the paranormal: A reevaluation. British Journal of Psychology, 90, 85–98. Roll, W. G., Maher, M. C., and Brown, B. (1992). An investigation of reported haunting occurrences in a Japanese restaurant in Georgia. Proceedings of Presented Papers. The Parapsychological Association 35th Annual Convention (pp. 151–168). Sagan, C. (1976). Letter on astrology. The Humanist, 36 (1), 2. Schooler, J. (2011). Unpublished results hide the decline effect. Nature, 470, 437. Sidgwick, Mrs. H. [E.H.]. (1932). The Society for Psychical Research: A short account of its history and work on the occasion of the Society’s jubilee, 1932. Proceedings of the Society for Psychical Research, 41, 1–26. Storr, W. (2013). The heretics: Adventures with the enemies of science. London, UK: Picador. Truzzi, M. (1978). On the extraordinary: An attempt at clarification. Zetetic Scholar, 1(1), 11–22. Van Elk, M. (2013). Paranormal believers are more prone to illusory agency detection than skeptics. Consciousness & Cognition 22, 1041–1046. Wagenmakers, E.-J., Wetzels, R., Boorsboom, D., and Van der Maas, H. L. J. (2011). Why psychologists must change the way they analyze their data: The case of psi: Comment on Bem (2011). Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 100, 426–432. Wagner, M. W., and Monnet, M. (1979). Attitudes of college professors toward extra-sensory perception. Zetetic Scholar, 5, 7–16. Watt, C. (2005). 2005 Presidential Address: Parapsychology’s contribution to psychology: A view from the front line. Journal of Parapsychology, 69, 215–232. Watt, C., and Tierney, (2014). Psi-related experiences. In E. Cardeña, S. J. Lynn, and S. Krippner (Eds.), (2014). Varieties of anomalous experience: Examining the scientific evidence (2nd ed.) (pp. 241–272). Washington, D.C.: American Psychological Association. Wiseman, R. (2010). “Heads I win, tails you lose”: How parapsychologists nullify null results. Skeptical Inquirer, 34 (1), http://www.csicop.org/si/show/heads_i_win_tails_you_loser_how_parapsyc hologists_nullify_null_results Wolman, B. J. (Ed.) (1977). Handbook of parapsychology. Orig. pub. Van Nostrand Reinhold; repr. 1986, Jefferson, NC: McFarland. Zingrone, N. (2004). Failing to go the distance. On critics and parapsychology. www.skepticalinvestigations.org/Examskeptics/Zingrone_critics.html. OceanofPDF.com Part One: Basic Concepts OceanofPDF.com CHAPTER 1 An Overview of Modern Developments in Parapsychology NANCY L. ZINGRONE, CARLOS S. ALVARADO and GERD H. HÖVELMANN In his chapter in Wolman’s (1977) Handbook of Parapsychology, the late John Beloff (1977) reviewed the history of parapsychology from its origins to the mid–1970s. As was usual, he placed the start of modern parapsychology with 18th-century Mesmerism and 19th-century Spiritualism. An “Heroic Age” (1882 to 1930) followed, consisting mainly of the work of the Society for Psychical Research. From there, Beloff covered work with mediums and psychics, the research program of J. B. Rhine and his associates (1930 to 1960), closing the chapter with a review of what was then the contemporary scene. Our temporal remit is also large (1977 to 2014) with space constraints that require a telegraphic treatment of the period at hand. Unlike Beloff, we do not conceive of our chapter as history per se, but rather as an overview of research and institutional trends. We return to earlier topics not covered by Beloff (1977) and overlap somewhat with his (1993) general history of parapsychology. We include various approaches that have influenced the content and direction of modern parapsychology such as anthropology, clinical psychology, and quantum mechanics as well as trends in education, funding, and the rise of new laboratories and other institutions. Phenomena not mentioned in the previous Handbook or not planned for the present one are mentioned briefly. Finally, we endeavor to venture beyond the narrow Anglo-American focus of the original Handbook. Because of the breadth of this review, we have dealt with our materials concisely, on occasion redirecting readers to other chapters in this volume for greater depth. We ask readers to remember that each study, event, development, or reference mentioned serves as an example of many more. To avoid repetition, we have used “e.g.,” “such as” and “among others” sparingly. However, when our list seems too brief, it is likely that the one we listed was chosen from among many. Furthermore, we have not dealt with validity, ambiguities, or opposing trends. Research Topics and Approaches Since 1977 general trends have emerged from the literature. It is safe to say that the emphasis has been on experimental studies of ESP and PK. Less well-examined—although not insignificant—have been single case studies and case collections of spontaneous phenomena, surveys of experiences, and investigations into psychological states/traits found among experients and high-scoring experimental participants. Archival research has been the least used methodology over the recent history of the field, although among the few studies that re-examined already published materials, meta-analyses on major experimental methodologies has been the most important. Over the last nearly 40 years, experiments have commonly involved unselected participants, not known to have special abilities, with some interesting exceptions including healers (Higuchi, Kotani, Higuchi, Minegishi, & Momose, 1999), psychics like Matthew Manning (Braud, Davis, & Wood, 1979) and Alex Tanous (Osis & McCormick, 1980), mediums (Beischel & Schwartz, 2007), and suspected poltergeist agents (Roll et al., 2012). In other research, samples have been selected on the likelihood of claiming specific experiences including readers of New Age publications (Alvarado & Zingrone, 1999), twins (Parker & Jensen, 2013), and performing arts students (Schlitz & Honorton, 1992). ESP Experiments Similar to the pre–1977 era, most experiments have focused on ESP. However, modern experiments have largely been conceptual or methodological extensions, or conceptual replication attempts. Few studies have used forced-choice methodology (Carpenter, 1983), while the majority have been free-response, such as those conducted with mediums (Kelly & Arcangel, 2011) or using the ganzfeld (Williams, 2011) or remote viewing methodologies [chapters 15, 23, and 29, this volume]. Many experiments have been conducted to explore such psychological correlates as moods (Carpenter, 1991), extraversion (Parra & Villanueva, 2003), experimenter effects (Schmeidler & Maher, 1981), and defense mechanisms (Watt & Morris, 1995). In particularly interesting work, Honorton (1997) explored ESP in relation to four participant characteristics: previous experience of spontaneous psi experiences; scores on the MyersBriggs Type Indicator, especially the Feeling/Perception scale; previous ESP testing experience; and previous practice of meditation [see chapter 10, this volume] or other mental disciplines. Another important research trend examined whether a psi-conducive state —especially an altered state—of consciousness influences experimental results. This notion has been studied in ganzfeld experiments (Bem & Honorton, 1994), in dream ESP studies (Sherwood, Dalton, Steinkamp, & Watt, 2000), by assessing hypnotizability and dissociation and their impact on ESP results (Marcusson-Clavertz & Cardeña, 2011), and through the correlation of EEG measurements with ESP tasks (McDonough, Don, & Warren, 2002) [see chapters 9 and 11, this volume]. The influence of physical variables on ESP results has also been a topic of research. Local geomagnetic activity (Haraldsson & Gissurarson, 1987), atmospheric electromagnetics (Houtkooper, Schienle, Stark, & Vaitl, 1999), Shannon entropy (May, Spottiswoode, & James, 1994), and local sidereal time (Spottiswoode, 1997) have all been examined [see chapter 14, this volume]. Also important has been the influence of psychological research methods. In one area of research, study participants were kept unaware they were being tested for ESP [see chapters 8 and 16, this volume]. Bem (2011) pioneered a line of research focusing on “anomalous retroactive influences on cognition and affect.” Other researchers embedded ESP tests in, among other contexts, tasks involving preference ratings of fractal images (Luke, Delanoy, & Sherwood, 2008), and perceptual switching of Necker cube images (Bierman, 2011). Also important across this period were experiments that employed psychophysiological measures as a test of unconscious ESP (Haraldsson, 1980; Radin, 2004; Tressoldi, Martinelli, Semenzato, & Cappato, 2011) [see chapter 17, this volume]. A significant overall effect was found in a recent meta-analysis of studies of predictive physiological anticipation using such measures as electrodermal activity, heart rate, and electroencephalographic activity (Mossbridge, Tressoldi, & Utts, 2012; for an exhaustive overview of physiological measures applied in parapsychology and other areas of anomalistics, see Ambach, 2012). Psychokinesis (PK) Experiments Although, similar to the previous period, PK was less frequently studied than ESP, important work has been conducted, the most notable of which used random number generators (Bösch, Steinkamp, & Boller, 2006; Jahn, Dunne, Nelson, Dobyns, & Bradish, 1997; Nelson 2013) [see chapter 21, this volume]. Potentially psychokinetic effects on target systems have been also explored in various areas of behavior and biology (Braud, 2003)— although in some experiments it is difficult to determine whether the effects were due to PK or ESP. The list of target systems has varied considerably, among them, cancer cells in mice (Bengston & Krinsley, 2003), hemolysis in human red blood cells (Braud, 1990), human electrodermal activity (Braud & Schlitz, 1983), outcomes in patients with bloodstream infection (Leibovici, 2001), and the growth or deterioration of vegetables (Minami, Usui, & Kokubo, 2014) [see chapter 18, this volume]. Other experiments have related PK scores to the lability of targets (Braud, 1980), geomagnetic field activity (Braud & Dennis, 1989), a relaxed mind-set (Debes & Morris, 1982), previous PK experiences (Gissurarson, 1990–1991), visual imagery strategies (Morris, Nanko, & Phillips, 1982), and neurophysiology (Roll et al., 2012). Out-of-Body Experiences (OBEs) Most modern out-of-body experience (OBE) research has been conducted through questionnaire studies of spontaneous experiences, guided largely by a psychological approach (Murray, 2009). For example, investigators related OBEs to reports of lucid dreams and imagery (Blackmore, 1982) and hallucinations (Parra, 2010), to scores on the five factor model of personality (Alvarado, Zingrone, & Dalton, 1998–1999), absorption (Irwin, 1980), and dissociation (Richards, 1991). More recent research has attempted to redefine the OBE in terms of the effect of neuropathology on body image (Blanke, Landis, Spinelli, & Seeck, 2004), and other proprioceptive disturbances (Braithwaite, Samson, Apperly, Broglia, & Hulleman, 2011). Only a few OBE experiments have been conducted since 1977. In one of these, attention was paid to psychophysiology (Osis & Mitchell, 1977). Two others focused on veridical perception and detection of the OBE state (Morris, Harary, Janis, Hartwell, & Roll, 1978; Osis & McCormick, 1980). Near-Death Experiences (NDEs) Although Moody (1975) was the first to call attention to near-death experiences (NDEs) in modern times, the scientific study of NDEs began with the work of such individuals as Greyson and Stevenson (1980), Ring (1980), and Sabom (1982). Their studies opened the way to later work that expanded our understanding of the content and circumstances of the NDE, as well as of its relation to physiological, psychological, and cultural variables (Hou, Huang, Prakash, & Chaudhury, 2013; Owens, Cook, & Stevenson, 1990; Van Lommel, Van Wees, Meyers, & Elfferich, 2001). Some NDE work has also been devoted to the important, but generally neglected, issue of veridicality (Ring & Lawrence, 1993). Mediumship The study of mental mediumship has re-emerged recently. Some studies have focused on veridicality (Beischel & Schwartz, 2007; Kelly & Arcangel, 2011), and others on psychological variables (Moreira-Almeida, Neto, & Cardeña, 2008; Roxburgh & Roe, 2011) and on psychophysiological and neurophysiological variables (Delorme et al., 2013; Peres, Moreira-Almeida, Caixeta, Leao, & Newberg, 2012) [see chapter 23, this volume]. In contrast, physical mediumship has rarely been investigated (but see Keen, Ellison, & Fontana, 1999; Nahm, 2014) [see chapter 19, this volume]. Other Phenomena Since 1977, only a few researchers have conducted single case studies or case collections of spontaneous phenomena, among them Hearne (1982), Novelletto (1980), Piccinini and Rinaldi (1990), and Stevenson (1992). The most common methodology used has been print-based or web-administered questionnaires. ESP experiences, OBEs, and apparitions have all been studied this way. Palmer’s (1979) survey has been the most influential of these. Other studies drew samples from Brazil (Machado, 2010) and Germany (Schmied-Knittel & Schetsche, 2005). Some studies have investigated the relation of psychic experiences to dream recall and lucid dreams (Alvarado & Zingrone, 2007–2008), cognitive and emotional empathy (Parra, 2013), dissociative experiences (Richards, 1991), positive schizotypy, complex partial epileptic-like signs, boundary thinness, and transliminality (Simmonds-Moore, 2009–2010). Schouten (1979, 1981, 1982) explored previously collected ESP experience case reports from different countries and eras in a search for commonalities. Schriever (1987) investigated the precognition experiences of a single individual over several decades. Apparition experiences that occurred around deathbeds (Osis & Haraldsson, 1997) and in other contexts (Haraldsson, 2012; Piccinni & Rinaldi, 1990) have also been studied. Maher and Hansen (1995) developed new ways to assess the features of hauntings. Gauld and Cornell’s (1979) exhaustive study of poltergeist and apparition case features provided the data for re-analyses of haunting apparitions (Alvarado & Zingrone, 1995; Biondi & Caratelli, 1993). New poltergeist case collections have appeared (Huesmann & Schriever, 1989), as well as analyses of cases based on such specific features as fire (Andrade, 1984), raps (Colvin, 2010), and water (Nichols, 2000). In the modern period, Stevenson continued to investigate children who claimed to remember previous lives, extending his analysis to birthmarks and birth defects thought to be related to the death of the previous personality (Stevenson, 1997). European and North American cases were also published in this period (e.g., Stevenson, 2003; see also Hassler, 2013). New in reincarnation research has been a shift from a primary emphasis on veridicality and other features to the psychological profile of children who report these experiences (Haraldsson, 2003). Several new researchers have also emerged in this area (Mills, 1988; Pasricha, 1990; Tucker & Keil, 2013) [see chapter 24, this volume]. Researchers have also focused on phenomena neglected prior to 1977. Cassoli (1979) documented several cases of psychic healing. More recently, Moga (2014) related the effectiveness of psychic healing to magnetic field activity. Zingrone, Alvarado, and Agee (2009) studied the relation of aura vision to other types of phenomena and to the psychological states/traits of aura viewers. Alvarado (1987) analyzed published cases of luminous phenomena. Joines, Baumann, and Kruth (2012) conducted experiments to detect an increase in photons while self-identified psychics and healers attempted to interact with equipment in a darkened room. Stevenson (1984) investigated xenoglossy cases. Colvin (2010) conducted a unique study in which raps were recorded and analyzed. Piccinini and Rinaldi (1990) investigated physical events reported around the death of a distant person such as falling objects and clocks stopping. Finally, Sherwood (2000) began a multi-method investigation of apparitions of black dogs. Scholarly Work: History, Religion and Other Disciplines Philosophy Among the philosophers in the field, Braude (1997, 2002) has clarified and criticized such concepts as synchronicity, the memory trace ideas of ESP, and physical models of psi. Others have argued that philosophical discussions of parapsychology enable us to evaluate the current paradigm and “form within an entirely naturalistic framework, … a conception of human life that is spiritually no less satisfying than any theology formulated in terms of some version of supernaturalism” (Griffin, 1997, p. 4). Steinkamp (2002) reminded us that the philosophy of mind has been important in both careful speculation about, and the analysis of phenomena and findings of the field. History Although many useful overviews of psychical research have appeared since 1977 (e.g., Beloff, 1993; Inglis, 1984), one of the first fine-grained scholarly histories appeared in 1980, emphasizing the work of J. B. Rhine and his associates (Mauskopf & McVaugh, 1980). Other histories of importance have been Biondi (1988) on Italy, Lachapelle (2011) on France, and Wolffram (2009) on Germany. These works provide insight into institutions, professionalization, and the rise and fall of research programs and research schools. Cultural historical work has also been done by Duplessis (2002), Gauger (1980), and Méheust (1999), among others. Lamont (2013) recently examined aspects of the acceptance and rejection of “extraordinary” beliefs using conjuring theory, frame and discourse analysis. The relation of psychology to parapsychology has also been analyzed (Sommer, 2012; Wolf-Braun, 1998). Crabtree (1993) and Plas (2000), for example, argued that parapsychological research has contributed greatly to psychology, especially to the understanding of the subconscious mind. Alvarado (2002) made similar points for the understanding of dissociation. These histories of modern research have illustrated how far parapsychologists’ interests have broadened since J. B. Rhine (1959) considered the future of the field. Finally histories of gifted subjects (Gregory, 1985; Méheust, 2003) and of the work of important past contributors to the field have also appeared, among them, Hövelmann (in press) on Max Dessoir, Junior, Araujo, and Moreira-Almeida (2013) on William James, and Rabeyron and Evrard (2012) on Sigmund Freud and Sándor Ferenczi. Sociology Sociological perspectives have proved useful in studies of the field. Gavilán Fontanet (1978) surveyed parapsychologists’ motivations, while McConnell and Clark (1980) investigated training, beliefs, and intellectual conflicts. Milton (1995) investigated publishing and funding while Zingrone (1988) looked at the relation of gender to authorship in two American journals of parapsychology. Schouten (1993) compared access to funding and other resources in psychology to that of parapsychology over a similar period. Mayer (2003) covered the depiction of parapsychology and other disciplines in specific popular German publications. Hansen (2001) argued that psychic phenomena are intrinsically associated with patterns of disorder and destructuring that prevent both systematic study and acceptance. Various analysts have used parapsychology as a case study, examining its rejection by mainstream science as well as the strategies by which proponents and debunkers defend or condemn the field (Allison, 1979; McClenon, 1984; Pinch, 1979; Pinch & Collins, 1984; Zingrone, 2006). Religion J. B. Rhine (1977–1978/1987) argued for a parapsychology of religion. In the last twenty years others have highlighted the relation between religion and parapsychology, among them Kripal (2008) and Grosso (1997). González Quevedo (1996) and Schwebel (2004) argued that much of what passes for religious miracles may be accounted for by psi from the living. It has also been argued that supernatural forces may be distinguished from living-agent psi (Bouflet, 2006; González Quevedo, 1996). Many authors have discussed phenomena reported around Christian saints. Bouflet (2001–2003) compiled a three-volume work of such phenomena as immunity to fire, inedia, incorruption of the physical body, levitation, lights, multiplication of food, the odor of sanctity, stigmata, and walking on water. Similarly, Grosso (in press) has investigated the levitation associated with Saint Joseph of Copertino, Laurentin and Mahéo (1990) have examined bilocation, and White (1982) reviewed ESP in the lives of Catholic saints. In addition, work has been done on representation of seemingly psychic phenomena in the fields of literary criticism as well as in art and theater history and criticism, but a review of these literatures is beyond the scope of this chapter. Conceptual and Disciplinary Approaches Although the previous Handbook included research into possible psi in animals (“anpsi”), much less has been done along these lines in recent times (Dutton & Williams, 2009). This may be due to the additional problems with which experimenters who work with animals have to cope (Hövelmann, 1989a, 1989b), such as the virtual unavoidability of Clever Hans cueing artifacts (Rosenthal, 1965) and of subtle dressage and expectancy effects. Among the studies done, Chauvin (1986) investigated PK with mice, Peoch (1988) with chicks, and Sheldrake and his colleagues studied ESP in dogs (Sheldrake & Smart, 1998), and in a parrot (Sheldrake & Morgana, 2003) [chapters 11 and 27, this volume]. Psychological Theories Much of the work conducted since 1977 has been psychological. Efforts have been made to develop psychological models of ESP and PK, among them Irwin (1979) on information-processing, Stanford (1990) and Thalbourne (2004) on dispositions and needs, and Carpenter’s (2012) First Sight model in which the core idea is that psi processes are in operation all the time, influencing our behavior and thinking at an unconscious level [see chapter 8, this volume]. Clinical Concerns Attention to clinical issues raised by ostensible psychic phenomena has grown significantly in recent decades (Coly & McMahon, 1993) [see chapter 28, this volume]. Among the specific concerns voiced are experients’ worry about their psychological health, and the differentiation of pathological from nonpathological experiences (Belz, 2009; Evrard, 2014; Iannuzzo, 2008; Kramer, Bauer, & Hövelmann, 2012). Clinical parapsychology does not seek to establish the veridicality of the experiences being reported. Rather, the point is to support troubled experients through counseling, psychotherapy, and other interventions. Related to this are seemingly psychic phenomena reported in psychotherapeutic or psychoanalytic contexts (Rosenbaum, 2011; Servadio, 1978). Mazza (1995) has argued that therapists should be aware of the presence of psychic phenomena when working with clients. In addition, some have tested for the presence of ESP phenomena in clinical populations (Iannuzzo, 1978, working with patients with anxiety neurosis) or for pathological conditions among psychics and mediums (e.g., MoreiraAlmeida, Neto, & Cardeña, 2008). Anthropology Beginning with Long (1977), a number of anthropologists (Giesler, 1984; Winkelman, 1982) and psychiatrists (Iannuzzo, 1984) have shown an interest in the development of an anthropological subspecialty that centers on psychic phenomena. Giesler (1985a, 1985b, 1986), for example, developed field-testing procedures that incorporated the belief systems of the participants. Shamanism and psi, long thought to be connected (Bernardi, 1986), have been subjected to sustained research in recent years (Hunter & Luke, 2014). Several authors have argued for the utility of an anthropological approach (Caswell, Hunter, & Tessaro, 2014; Hunter, 2010), noted relations between anthropology and parapsychology (Luke 2010), and pointed out the importance of taking the beliefs and experiences of other cultures seriously (Turner, 2006). In 2010, the journal Paranthropology (Anonymous, n.d.c.) was founded by Jack Hunter and colleagues. As Hunter (2010) argued: “Not only does anthropology provide a promising methodology for our elucidation and understanding of the paranormal, but the paranormal also presents an opportunity for anthropology’s theories and techniques to be tested and expanded” (p. 2). Survival of Death Interest in investigating the survival of bodily death has not waned in the modern period (Braude, 2003; Gauld, 1982). Although Gauld (1982) defended the notion that some phenomena indicate the possible presence of discarnate agency, others have favored alternate explanations (presented and discussed by Braude [2003], although he favors slightly the survival hypothesis; see also Rock, 2013; Roll, 2006). Still others have argued that the survival hypothesis is scientifically untestable and, consequently, should be set aside as an unproductive area of research (Hövelmann, 1983; Irwin, 2002; Krippner & Hövelmann, 2005). Influential Conceptual Frameworks In this section we review theoretical ideas that have become conceptual frameworks in the modern era, and in some cases, have reached the level of testable hypotheses. These topics are anomalistic psychology, quantum mechanics, and the nonphysical mind. Anomalistic Psychology Since 1977, attention to conventional explanations of psychic phenomena has increased. Reed (1988) and Zusne and Jones (1989) provided the starting point for anomalistic psychology as a subspecialty. Research from this perspective (French, Haque, Bunton-Stasyshyn, & Davis, 2009) seeks “to explain anomalous experiences and paranormal beliefs in terms of known psychological and physical factors” (Holt, Simmonds-Moore, Luke, & French, 2012, p. 5) such as fraud, suggestion, hallucinations, and unconscious misperceptions or misinterpretations of sensory input. Other researchers have placed equal emphasis on conventional and unconventional explanations of seemingly psychic phenomena under the term (see Roe, 2009; Zangari, 2011, and the influential anthology of Cardeña, Lynn, & Krippner, 2014). Active engagement with conventional explanations has always been an important part of parapsychology. For example, Braude (2000) discussed such capabilities of the mind as the subconscious creation of personalities and literature. Stevenson (1983) was well aware that cryptomnesia might best explain some phenomena, including some cases that seemed to provide evidence for reincarnation. Although critics have generally speculated on conventional explanations for seemingly psychic phenomena, they have rarely done research on the topic (Hansel, 1980; Wiseman, Smith, & Kornbrot, 1994). On the other hand, parapsychologists have actively experimented with, and uncovered evidence for, the operation of conventional processes throughout the history of the field. For example, Bierman (1999) and Palmer (1983) investigated conventional explanations for ESP results [and found them insufficient], Alvarado and Zingrone (1997–1998) discussed NDE cases, and Schouten and Stevenson (1998) reincarnation-type cases. Quantum Mechanics In the 1970s, serious interest in the relation of physics and parapsychology began to grow, especially in the area of quantum mechanics (Oteri, 1975). Engaging the literature and findings of quantum mechanics has led many to speculate about consciousness and its relation to psychic phenomena, including Walker (1975, 2000), Mattuck (1984), and Schmidt (1978). Observational theories (Millar, 1978) and discussions of entanglement (Radin, 2006) resulted from this fruitful collision of parapsychology with physics [see chapter 13, this volume]. In 1975, Lucadou proposed one of the most important theories in his Model of Pragmatic Information (MPI). In 2013, he provided a concise statement of his model: The most important aspect of [my] Model of Pragmatic Information … is the so-called “NT-Axiom.” It assumes that the origin of psi phenomena is not signals but entanglement correlations created by the “meaning” (pragmatic information) of the situation. Further, MPI … assume[s] that the entanglement correlations cannot be used as signal transfers or causal influences. The axiom leads to a naturalistic explanation of the decline effect and of the displacement effect … and to [an explanation of] the temporal development of RSPK phenomena [Lucadou, 2013, pp. 410–411; see also Lucadou, 1995; Lucadou & Kornwachs, 1983]. The Nonphysical Mind Another—albeit contentious—concept that has been around since the beginning of the field is the idea that psychic phenomena support the concept of a nonphysical mind separate from the physical body. Beloff (1990), Schwartz and Dossey (2010), Stevenson (1981), and Tart (2009), to name a few, have made strong arguments for this idea. The most important contribution to the topic, however, has been Irreducible Mind (Kelly, Kelly, Crabtree, Gauld, Grosso, & Greyson, 2007). The authors strongly defended the theory that mind exists separately from, but is expressed through the brain [see chapter 2, this volume]. Other authors (van Lommel, 2013) have argued that NDEs provide evidence that mind is independent of the body. As Greyson (2010) wrote: “The challenge of NDEs to materialist reductionism lies in asking how complex consciousness, including mentation, sensory perception, and memory, can occur under conditions in which current physiological models of mind deem it impossible” (p. 43). Methodological and Statistical Developments The Impact of Computers In 1977, very few individuals in the field had access to computers. As Broughton (1982) and White (1990b) have said, the impact of the proliferation of computers on parapsychology has been transformational. This profound impact is nowhere more visible than in the efficiency and security of data recording, the speed at which studies might be run and large data sets analyzed, and in the presentation of quick or immediate feedback to experimental participants (Dalton et al., 1994; Honorton et al., 1990). The selection of targets is now routinely computerized, one result being the ability to develop and share experiments that use standardized digital procedures (Goulding, Westerlund, Parker, & Wackermann, 2004), allowing more effective direct replication attempts (Bem, 2011; Bem, Tressoldi, Rabeyron, & Duggan, 2014). The importance of the ability to analyze large data sets cannot be over-emphasized, having been foundational to much productive research on micro–PK (Jahn, Dunne, Nelson, Dobyns, & Bradish, 1997) and to the rise and international dissemination of the Global Consciousness Project (Nelson, 2013). Other Technology The development of instrumentation for use in research on physical effects (Joines, Baumann, & Kruth, 2012; Minami, Usui, & Kokubo, 2014) and psychophysiological research (Modestino, 2013; Schmidt & Walach, 2000) has also been profound. The full impact of neuroimaging techniques is just beginning to be felt in studies of ESP (Bierman & Scholte, 2002), distant intention (Achterberg et al., 2005), and brain states during mediumship (Delorme et al., 2013). Statistics From its inception, parapsychology has been at the forefront of adopting (or developing) new statistical methods (Hövelmann, 2012, pp. 311–314). Such an emphasis is still in evidence. A recent controversial development has been the introduction of Bayesian statistics. Although parapsychological researchers have been criticized for not using this approach (Wagenmakers, Wetzels, Borsboom, & Van der Maas, 2011), others have countered by acknowledging the advantages of the Bayesian approach while outlining its limitations (Bem, Utts, & Johnson, 2011). The application of Bayesian statistics to our field has also highlighted the subjectivity of one of its foundational steps, that of articulating an acceptable a priori probability. The impact of meta-analyses in the recent period has also been profoundly important. Although susceptible to subjectivity as well, the method has underscored not only the existence of an extensive database of findings in parapsychology but also uncovered overall significance in major experimental areas of the field. As Jessica Utts (1991) argued: The recent focus on meta-analysis in parapsychology has revealed that there are small but consistently nonzero effects across studies, experimenters and laboratories…. It may be that the nonzero effects observed in the meta-analyses can be explained by something other than ESP…. Nonetheless, there is an anomaly that needs an explanation [p. 377]. Many meta-analyses have been conducted since the 1980s [see chapters 15, 17, and 18, this volume]. In addition to the well-known Bem and Honorton (1994) meta-analysis of ganzfeld results published in Psychological Bulletin, other research programs thus analyzed include: precognition (Honorton & Ferrari, 1989), psychokinesis on dice (Radin & Ferrari, 1991), distant intention effects on individuals (Schmidt, 2012), free-response and forced-choice ESP (Storm, Tressoldi, & Di Risio, 2010, 2012), and physiological measures (Mossbridge, Tressoldi, & Utts, 2012). Such analyses have, by no means, ended the controversies surrounding these topics, but instead have inspired critiques and re-analyses (Bösch, Steinkamp, & Boller, 2006 vs. Radin, Nelson, Dobyns, & Houtkooper, 2006a, 2006b; Hyman, 2010; Milton & Wiseman, 1999). Qualitative Research Qualitative methodology has been present in parapsychological research across its history in the sense that case studies have largely been descriptive and in many cases preserved the original testimony of the experient (Hearne, 1982; Piccinini & Rinaldi, 1990; Stevenson, 2003). Where the difference lies between the old and the new is the use of methodologies developed in ethnography, anthropology, sociology, history, and literary criticism, among other fields. Rhea White (1990a) was the first in parapsychology to recognize not only the power of qualitative methodology but its relevance to our work. A recent editorial published in Qualitative Research Psychology (Murray & Wooffitt, 2010) supports White’s contention. The authors argued that qualitative research of the topics we study “begin from the assumption that anomalous experiences are fundamentally meaningful events, symbolically mediated through language and communication, … inextricably enmeshed in the fabric of interpersonal actions in social settings, and reflect their broader historical and cultural context” (p. 1). Modern examples include the work of Heath (2011), Rock, Beischel, and Schwartz (2008), Roxburgh and Roe (2013), Virtanen (1990), and Wooffitt (2006). Social Aspects: Criticism and Institutional Developments Criticism Parapsychology is continuously involved in controversy that ranges from methodological concerns and the interpretation of data to accusations of fraud [see chapter 3, this volume], not to mention what seem to be neverending paradigm wars (Alcock, 1981; Bunge, 1991; Diaconis, 1978; Hansel, 1980; Hyman, 1989; Kurtz, 1985). In the 1980s, a commission of the National Research Council of the National Academy of Sciences in the U.S. was asked to analyze the field’s entire body of literature, assessing the weight of the evidence. They concluded that there is “no scientific justification from research conducted over a period of 130 years for the existence of parapsychological phenomena” (Druckman & Swets, 1988, p. 22). The report was roundly criticized in parapsychology for, among other problems, the refusal either to incorporate or to print as appendices the positive reviews written by dissenting members of the commission (Palmer, Honorton, & Utts, 1989). The persistence of controversy in parapsychology has been discussed from a variety of perspectives (Bauer, 1982; Carter, 2012; Hövelmann & Michels, in press; Krippner & Friedman, 2010; Zingrone, 2010). For example, many have characterized parapsychology as a marginal discipline that exists beyond the boundaries of mainstream science (Allison, 1979; Hess, 1992, 1993; Zingrone, 2002). As such, Hess (1992) has argued that parapsychologists are often penalized for working in the field, suffering barriers to, or the loss of scientific careers. The rise of organized skepticism over the last nearly forty years has impacted the field and its research negatively in a variety of countries. In the U.S., organized skepticism began with the Committee for the Scientific Study of Claims of the Paranormal (CSICOP) founded in 1976. Pinch and Collins (1984) first discussed its agenda followed by Hansen (1992) who analyzed it more deeply. Although CSICOP claimed its purpose was to provide, based on objective and original research, a rational counterargument against phenomena and fields characterized as pseudoscientific, the organization’s magazine, Skeptical Inquirer, from its beginnings, published mainly articles debunking the topic at hand, rather than reporting disconfirmatory evidence. The Committee’s “true” goal was characterized by one of its founders as “not inquiry but [rather] to serve as an advocacy body, a public relations group for scientific orthodoxy” (Truzzi, 1991, p. 25). From our perspective, parapsychology has taken internal and external criticisms (Milton & Wiseman, 1997) and conceptual prescriptions (Hövelmann, 1983; Morris, 2001) very seriously. Because of criticism, ESP-testing methodology was improved by advances in automated ESPtesting systems (Dalton, et al., 1994; Honorton et al., 1990), psychophysiological measurements were refined (Schmidt & Walach, 2000), and the recording of PK experiments was modified (Schmidt, Morris, & Rudolph, 1986). An active tradition of self-criticism (Akers, 1984; Hansen, 1990; Hövelmann, 1984) also exists and detailed replies to critics have been undertaken (Hansen, 1991; Honorton, 1993; Stanford, 1982; Zingrone, n.d.). This mix of internal and external criticism has had some definitional consequences, however: A proper distinction between “parapsychologist” and “skeptic” is lacking and seems to be anybody’s guess (Hövelmann, 1988). A recent strong defense of parapsychological research (Cardeña, 2014) included 100 names of academics and scientists from prestigious universities who support the movement of our research from the margins to the mainstream. The author argued: Increased experimental controls have not eliminated or even decreased significant support for the existence of psi phenomena … data supportive of psi phenomena cannot reasonably be accounted for by chance or by a “file drawer” effect…. The effect sizes reported in most meta-analyses are relatively small and the phenomena cannot be produced on demand, but this also characterizes various phenomena found in other disciplines that focus on complex human behavior and performance such as psychology and medicine … [the findings of psi research] do not prima facie violate known laws of nature given modern theories in physics [p. 1]. A wide variety of overview articles designed to open dialogue and bring parapsychology closer to mainstream science have also been published in refereed journals of other disciplines. Examples include articles about the interaction of psychology and parapsychology (Alvarado & Zingrone, 1998), dream ESP (Child, 1985), psychiatry and parapsychology (Pasricha, 2011), psychokinesis (Radin & Nelson, 1989), survival of death (Stevenson, 1977), statistics (Utts, 1991), and magic (Winkelman, 1982). Also published have been articles that focus on research results (McClennon, 1988; Tressoldi, Martinelli, Semenzato, & Cappato, 2011) and metaanalyses of such topics as free-response ESP (Storm & Tressoldi, & Di Risio, 2010) and presentiment (Mossbridge, Tressoldi, & Utts, 2012). In addition, articles about parapsychological research have also appeared in anthologies of other disciplines (Bender & Bauer, 1977; Ullman, 1980), and some authors have highlighted the contributions the field has made to knowledge in general, and to psychology in particular (Alvarado, 2003; Child, 1984; Hövelmann, 2012; Watt, 2005). Although this neither implies acceptance nor progress, some inroads have been made when papers on the topic have appeared in the journals of other disciplines, or when such journals as Brain and Behavioral Sciences (1982), the Journal of Consciousness Studies (2003), and Qualitative Research in Psychology (2010) have devoted entire issues to the topic. But even with the attention paid to criticism, the methodological improvements, and the attempts to make rational arguments for the validity, reliability, and even the amount of positive research findings in the field, progress from the margins to the mainstream has been minuscule. Palmer (2009) noted that persuasive efforts have largely been unsuccessful, and, in fact, as Storm (2009) argued: “psi research [has failed] to overthrow the long-suffering ideological intolerance and prejudice that have been thrust upon it” (p. 199). The editors of the current volume of Advances in Parapsychological Research (Krippner, Rock, Beischel, Friedman, & Fracasso, 2013) emphasized the deadening influence of rhetoric, a topic also analyzed by others in the field as well (Honorton, 1993; Zingrone, 2010). Krippner and colleagues (2013) argued that although it may be said that psi is established, “parapsychologists are mindful that evidence will remain ineffectual when refracted through the epistemological lenses of a counter-advocate who privileges rhetoric over substance” (p. 7). Indeed, most critics and skeptics insist that the data is not convincing for scientific reasons (Hyman, 2007). Parapsychology as an International Community Parapsychology suffers from a language barrier that is particularly noticeable when English-speaking researchers ignore work published in other languages (Alvarado, 1989; Hövelmann, 1986). This is particularly obvious in the reference lists of overviews of the field (Irwin & Watt, 2007). English-language journals, similarly, seldom review books published in other languages. Yet interest has grown in international collaboration, even though such alliances can be fraught with cultural complications (Varvoglis, 1990– 1991). A number of recent publications are evidence of this, among them Moreira-Almeida, Neto, and Cardeña (2008), Mossbridge, Tressoldi, and Utts (2012), and Storm, Tressoldi, and Di Risio (2012). Although much more is needed to knit the international community together, an important and very positive change has been the increase in non–Anglo-American venues for the Parapsychological Association’s annual convention, for example, Iceland (1980), Germany (1991), Holland (1994), Austria (2004), France (2010), Brazil (2011), and Italy (2013). Equally positive has been the increasing presence of non-native speakers of English on the PA Board of Directors. In the last 20 years, more English-language articles have been published by non-native speakers of English as well (Moreira-Almeida, Neto, & Cardeña, 2008; Parra & Villanueva, 2003). The field benefits greatly from the work of these multilingual researchers. Sadly, only one Englishlanguage journal in the field (the Journal of Parapsychology) routinely publishes non–English language abstracts (albeit only in French, German, and Spanish), while the German journals—Zeitschrift für Parapsychologie und Grenzgebiete der Psychologie, and the Zeitschrift für Anomalistik (ZfA) —publish English abstracts for all major articles and some discussions. In such exceptional cases as an international prize essay competition, the ZfA publishes full articles and discussions in English. Cross-translation practices are so limited in the field, however, that much important work (Piccinini & Rinaldi, 1990; Huesmann & Schriever, 1989; Machado, 2010; Zangari, 2007) has gone unnoticed by monolingual English-speakers. Institutions Many institutions of the field founded before 1977 are still active today, such as the Centro Studi Parapsicologici (Center of Parapsychological Studies, Italy), the Institut für Grenzgebiete der Psychologie und Psychohygiene (Institute for Frontier Areas of Psychology and Mental Health, Germany), the Institut Métapsychique International (International Metapsychic Institute, France), the Rhine Research Center (formerly Institute of Parapsychology, U.S.), and the Society for Psychical Research (England). Some have ceased to exist, and others have declined, we hope, temporarily, in activity. One of these, the Parapsychology Foundation (PF), made important contributions to the support of the field as a global enterprise in direct funding and through its international conference program (Alvarado, Coly, Coly, & Zingrone, 2001). Fifteen of these conferences have been hosted since 1977. The Foundation’s last major contribution to the field was the 2008 conference “Utrecht II: Charting the Future of Parapsychology.” New organizations have been established including the Instituto de Psicología Paranormal (Institute of Paranormal Psychology, Argentina), the International Society for Life Information Science (Japan), and the Windbridge Institute for Applied Research in Human Potential (U.S.). The presence of university-based research has also changed. Some units have disappeared, others persisted, and new ones have been founded. The University of Edinburgh is still a seat of research in the field. The Koestler Parapsychology Unit, a research group in the Department of Psychology, owes its existence to the endowment of the Koestler Chair of Parapsychology. The late Robert L. Morris held the chair from 1985 through his untimely death in 2004, after which the University decided not to seek a new candidate. However, two faculty members attached to the KPU obtained permanent faculty appointments ensuring the persistence of research relevant to the field in the department at least while they still hold their positions. As for Morris, like Beloff before him, his principal achievement at Edinburgh was mentoring more than 20 doctoral students. Because a good number of these new PhDs have been able to obtain mainstream faculty positions in psychology in the UK and elsewhere, new research units have been established as well as new sites for post-graduate student supervision (Carr, 2008). In fact, at this point, several generations of PhDs can trace their intellectual genealogy back to Morris (Hövelmann & Schriever, 2004). In 2005, another important chair was established at Lund University. One of the editors of this volume, Etzel Cardeña, holds the Thorsen Professor of Psychology at Lund and is also head of the research group Center for Research on Consciousness and Anomalous Psychology (Anonymous, 2012). At the University of Virginia, Jim B. Tucker, Benner-Lowry Associate Professor of Psychiatry and Neurobehavioral Sciences, heads the Division of Perceptual Studies (formerly called the Division of Parapsychology) that was founded by Ian Stevenson in the late 1960s. The research unit now includes a neuroimaging laboratory and has expanded its traditional emphasis on spontaneous case investigations to include experimental research (Anonymous, 2014). Other important institutional developments have taken place in a variety of countries, but due to space constraints we will focus on four countries as exemplars of the rest. France. New approaches to psi testing have emerged at the Institut Métapsychique International, among them the development of the Cin-EEG (PK) and the Sharefield (similar to the ganzfeld) projects. Communication with, and involvement of, the public has also expanded (Varvoglis & Evrard, 2010). Similarly, the Groupe d’Études et de Recherches en Parapsychologie (Group of Study and Research in Parapsychology), which focused on theoretical and conceptual discussions and was active from the 1970s through the 1980s, was re-imagined (Evrard, 2010). Currently, a new group concerned with clinical aspects of psychic phenomena, the Centre d’Information, de Recherche et de Consultation sur les Expériences Exceptionnelles (Center of Information, Research, and Consultation about Exceptional Experiences) has begun operating (Anonymous, n.d.a.). Germany. The Institut für Grenzgebiete der Psychologie und Psychohygiene (Institute for Frontier Areas of Psychology and Mental Health; IGPP) was founded in 1950 as an independent non-profit organization by Hans Bender. Since 1992, because of funding from the Asta Holler Foundation, the institute has expanded considerably. Today, the main part is still located in Freiburg and consists of four departments that focus on data analysis, psychophysics, cultural studies and social research, and historical studies that includes the archives and the library. In addition, IGPP supports the Bender Institute for Neuroimaging (BION) at the University of Giessen (for more information see Bauer, Hövelmann, & Lucadou, 2013; IGPP, 2010). Since 1957, the IGPP has also published the Zeitschrift für Parapsychologie und Grenzgebiete der Psychologie. Founded in 2001, the Gesellschaft für Anomalistik (Society for Anomalistics or GfA) is considered to be the second major organization in Germany. The scope of the GfA covers astrology, ufology, cryptozoology, and other fields of anomalistics in addition to parapsychology. The GfA publishes the Zeitschrift für Anomalistik (Journal of Anomalistics) and holds annual conferences. Finally, the Wissenschaftliche Gesellschaft zur Förderung der Parapsychologie (Scientific Society for the Furtherance of Parapsychology; WGFP) is also known as the “German SPR.” The WGFP founded and continues to support the Parapsychologische Beratungsstelle (Parapsychological Counseling Center) directed by Walter von Lucadou. Brazil. At the University of São Paulo in Brazil, Wellington Zangari introduced the discipline of “anomalistic psychology” to the psychology department, defining his remit to include both conventional and parapsychological approaches. In 2010, working with Fátima R. Machado, he established Inter Psi-Laboratório de Psicologia Anomalística e Processos Psicossociais (Inter Psi-Laboratory of Anomalistic Psychology and Psychosocial Processes) at the University. Inter Psi brings together students and interested others to explore the whole range of anomalistic psychology (Zangari, 2011). In recent years a number of publications have come from this group (e.g., Machado, 2010; Zangari, 2007). The psychiatrist Alexander Moreira-Almeida has recently established at the Federal University of Juiz de Fora in Brazil an interdisciplinary institute called Núcleo de Pesquisa em Espiritualidade e Saúde (Research Group on Spirituality and Health; Anonymous, n.d.b.). In addition to research on spirituality, the Núcleo also covers topics of relevance to parapsychology. Funding Sources Finally, it is important to note those institutions that have supported the field’s research in the modern period. Although the Parapsychology Foundation had been a significant source of funding from 1951, the size and extent of its research grants declined significantly over the modern period (Alvarado et al., 2001). The Society for Psychical Research and the PerrottWarrick Fund in England expanded their grants programs over the same period, with the former focusing on funding for students and research, and the latter establishing Perrott-Warrick Research Units in the UK as well as providing additional funding to an international group of researchers. In recent years, the Parapsychological Association has also established research grants through such small bursaries as the PARE, Roller, and other funds. Since 2005, the Johan Borgman Foundation in the Netherlands has sponsored a number of parapsychological publication projects and four substantial conferences, three on clinical parapsychology and one on preserving the historical collections of parapsychology, as well as hosted and co-funded the Parapsychology Foundation’s “Utrecht II” conference. The Fundação BIAL (BIAL Foundation) from Portugal has provided significant research funding for research in the field since 1994. In addition to its bursaries, BIAL hosts a biannual conference at which scientists working in parapsychology present their research alongside grantees who toil in more conventional, primarily psychophysiological, fields. Since the mid–2000s, Bial has become the most important source of financial support for international researchers in the field (Parra, 2012). Education Although a number of universities were mentioned in the section above, very few university-based educational opportunities existed for students prior to 1977. Some faculty mentors in Australia, the U.S., but most especially in Europe, supervised masters or doctoral students in the earlier period (Hövelmann, 2010). A study guide published in the early 1980s (American Society for Psychical Research, 1983) listed 66 schools globally that offered at least a single course in parapsychology. Schools that offered some kind of program included Franklin Pierce College in New Hampshire (now Franklin Pierce University, with an undergraduate concentration in parapsychology through the Psychology Department), and John F. Kennedy University in California (a Masters in Science in parapsychology). Among those who supervised students in their own departments (primarily psychology) were Gertrude Schmeidler at the City Colleges of New York, Stanley Krippner at Saybrook Institute (now Saybrook University), Rex Stanford at St. John’s University in Jamaica, New York, Charles Tart at the University of California at Davis, John Beloff at the University of Edinburgh, and IGPP staff who supervised masters and doctoral work through the University of Freiburg. But the bulk of the opportunities listed in the 1983 guide were adult education courses, with the most intensive offering being the Institute for Parapsychology’s Summer Study Program (in operation from the mid–1970s through the early 2000s) in Durham, North Carolina. So unless a student was able to secure a faculty mentor at a university, education in the field was obtained mainly through a single university course, independent study, membership in and attendance at the events of such organizations as the Society for Psychical Research, or through the use of such lending and/or read-in libraries as the Parapsychology Foundation’s Eileen J. Garrett Research Library in New York City and the Fanny-Moser Library in Freiburg. By comparison, a recent review (Zingrone, 2011) found that 43 universities offered some form of formal education in parapsychology or anomalistic psychology; 13 of these providing a single course, 18 post-graduate degree supervision, and 12 a combination of both. Although a few of the institutions listed in 1983 still have faculty members who supervise students (such as the University of Edinburgh and the University of Freiburg), new opportunities have sprung up. New opportunities are available in the UK at the Universities of Greenwich, Hertfordshire, London (Goldsmith’s College), and Northampton (among others), and in Sweden at the Universities of Gothenburg, Lund, and Stockholm, as well as at other universities in other countries. Therefore, although the number of institutions offering at least a single introductory course has decreased by 30 percent, the number of university-based post-graduate degree programs and faculty mentoring available these days is significantly greater than in 1977. Journals Similar to other fields, parapsychology has always had specialty journals. Many of these have persisted from earlier days, such as the Journal of Parapsychology, the Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, and the Zeitschrift für Parapsychologie und Grenzgebiete der Psychologie (Journal of Parapsychology and Border Areas of Psychology). Several others have appeared since 1977 and are still in existence: Australian Journal of Parapsychology (Australia), E-Boletín Psi (Argentina), Journal of Exceptional Experiences and Psychology (U.S.), Journal of Near-Death Studies (U.S.), and Paranthropology (England). Other journals—in the U.S., Explore: The Journal of Science and Healing, and the Journal of Scientific Exploration (JSE), and in Germany, Zeitschrift für Anomalistik (Journal of Anomalistics)—publish papers relevant to parapsychology but also cover other topics. Several other journals, such as the European Journal of Parapsychology, the Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, the Journal of Theoretical Parapsychology (formerly Psychoenergetic Systems), Revista Argentina de Psicología Paranormal, and the Synchronicity Research Unit Bulletin (SRU Bulletin), ceased publication at various points over the last forty years. The International Journal of Parapsychology restarted in 2000, but only two volumes were issued before it ceased publication. Sustained Lines of Investigation Other chapters in this volume flesh out in greater depth the areas of the research we have reviewed, but before we close our chapter we want to emphasize some remarkable researchers whose programs have had a significant impact on the field as a whole. One of these is the systematic program of research that was carried on by Robert Jahn, Brenda Dunne, Roger Nelson, and others at the Princeton Engineering Anomalies Research (PEAR) Laboratory for over 25 years. The PEAR Laboratory focused primarily on a very productive line of PK research, and to a lesser extent pursued remote perception research (Jahn & Dunne, 2005). Another remarkable line of research that was active for over 35 years was the work of Ian Stevenson who focused mainly on spontaneous cases, especially on the study of children claiming to remember previous lives (Tucker, 2008). Finally, several other researchers deserve to be mentioned for their systematic contributions since the 1970s: William Braud (2003) whose work focused on distant mental influence on living systems; Bruce Greyson (2014) who has investigated near-death experiences; Roger Nelson (2013) who founded the Global Consciousness Project; William G. Roll (2003) whose major contributions were in the area of poltergeist research; and of course, the ganzfeld and other internal attention work conducted by Charles Honorton (Rao, 1994). Concluding Remarks The comments we have presented here are far from an exhaustive review of the research and institutional history of the field. Nonetheless, we hope we have shown that a great deal of work has been done, both in and outside the laboratory, in scholarly contributions, in the professionalization of the field, and on related topics. Although we have not performed a systematic analysis of trends in the literature, it seems to us that the shape of the field has not changed much since the earlier period. Not only are we still emphasizing experimental and quantitative work over spontaneous cases and qualitative approaches, we are still battling armchair skeptics who refuse to do research—a fact that makes the skeptics who do conduct research (e.g., French, Haque, BuntonStasyshyn, & Davis, 2009; Hövelmann & Michels, in press) all the more appreciated. Our primary problems remain: the lack of researchers; the difficulty of obtaining or maintaining a normal academic or scientific life while dedicated to the field; the unavailability of mainstream funding; and the social, financial, and intellectual disadvantages of being involved in a hotly contested science. There are also some striking differences. Some positive trends, such as the increased use of meta-analysis in the recent period, may eventually ameliorate at least some of these problems with mainstream science, but whether or not that happens, meta-analysis has facilitated our own understanding of our increasingly consistent and positive database as well as highlighted the pluses and minuses of our current methodologies. We can say that parapsychological research is more varied, more interdisciplinary, and more international than in the earlier period. More of our articles now appear in mainstream journals in psychology, physics, and other disciplines, for example in Brain; Dreaming, History of Psychiatry; Imagination, Cognition and Personality, Journal of Consciousness Studies; the Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences, Journal of the Scientific Study of Religion; Memory and Cognition; Psychological Bulletin, Psychonomic Bulletin and Review, Religious Studies Review, and many others, including several sections of the widely-read Frontiers journals series. Our research constituencies have also broadened: Instead of the small group of parapsychologists who published mainly in parapsychology journals, today researchers in our field have wider professional identifications and broader agendas. Many of these who regularly contribute to our literature do not consider themselves to be parapsychologists. This is certainly true of many of the physicians who conduct NDE and distant healing research, as well as the historians, anthropologists, and sociologists who have dealt with mediumship, spirit possession, Spiritualism, and Spiritism. Specific interests have also expanded. While proof-oriented studies are still conducted, many of us have set that issue aside to investigate the features of claimed experiences, and the psychological correlates of experients and successful experimental participants. The importance of clinical research and its integration into clinical practice has also increased. Still, with the weight of continued criticism and the debilitating advent of organized skepticism, it does not seem likely that the field will be accepted as a part of mainstream science any time soon. This is especially true of the subspecialties in the field that emphasize evidentiality or seek a mechanism that cannot, as yet, be explained in a way that is coherent or persuasive to most scientists. It is possible, however, that the research that does not assume evidentiality, or that deals only with correlates of, or relations with, psychological, sociological, or anthropological variables—such as aftereffects, meaningfulness, personality and cognitive variables, discourse, or culture—present less of a perceived threat to the mainstream. It may be that for these areas, at least, the road ahead may be smoother. Acknowledgments We thank Massimo Biondi, Renaud Evrard, Andreas Sommer, and Wellington Zangari for providing us with information relevant to this chapter. The second author gratefully acknowledges financial support by the Society for Psychical Research. References Achterberg, J., Cooke, K., Richards, T., Standish, L., Kozak, L., and Lake, J. (2005). Evidence for correlations between distant intentionality and brain function in recipients: A functional magnetic resonance imaging analysis. Journal of Alternative and Complementary Medicine, 11, 965–971. Akers, C. (1984). Methodological criticism of parapsychology. In S. Krippner (Ed.), Advances in parapsychological research 4 (pp. 112–164). Jefferson, NC: McFarland. Alcock, J. E. (1981). Parapsychology: Science or magic? New York: Pergamon Press. Allison, P. D. (1979). Experimental parapsychology as a rejected science. In R. Wallis (Ed.), On the margins of science: The social construction of rejected knowledge (pp. 271–291, Sociological Review Monograph No. 27). Keele, UK: University of Keele. Alvarado, C. S. (1987). Observations of luminous phenomena around the human body: A review. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 54, 38–60. Alvarado, C. S. (1989). The language barrier in parapsychology. Journal of Parapsychology, 53, 125–139. Alvarado, C. S. (2002). Dissociation in Britain during the late nineteenth century: The Society for Psychical Research, 1882–1900. Journal of Trauma and Dissociation, 3, 9–33. Alvarado, C. S. (2003). Reflections on being a parapsychologist. Journal of Parapsychology, 67, 211–248. Alvarado, C. S., Coly, E., Coly, L., and Zingrone, N. L. (2001). Fifty years of supporting parapsychology: The Parapsychology Foundation (1951– 2001). International Journal of Parapsychology, 12, 1–26. Alvarado, C. S., and Zingrone, N. L. (1995). Characteristics of hauntings with and without apparitions: An analysis of published cases. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 60, 385–397. Alvarado, C. S., and Zingrone, N. L. (1997–1998). Factors related to the depth of near-death experiences: Testing the “embellishment over time” hypothesis. Imagination, Cognition and Personality, 17, 339–344. Alvarado, C. S., and Zingrone, N. L. (1998). Anomalías de interacción con el ambiente: El estudio de los fenómenos parapsicológicos [Anomalies of interaction with the environment: The study of parapsychological phenomena]. Revista Puertorriqueña de Psicología, 11, 99–147. Alvarado, C. S., and Zingrone, N. L. (1999). Out-of-body experiences among readers of a Spanish New Age magazine. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 63, 65–85. Alvarado, C. S., and Zingrone, N. L. (2007–2008). Interrelationships of psychic experiences, dream recall and lucid dreams in a survey with Spanish participants. Imagination, Cognition and Personality, 27, 63–69. Alvarado, C. S., Zingrone, N. L., and Dalton, K. (1998–1999). Out-of-body experiences: Alterations of consciousness and the five-factor model of personality. Imagination, Cognition and Personality, 18, 297–317. Ambach, W. (Ed.). (2012). Experimentelle Psychophysiologie in Grenzgebieten [Experimental psychophysiology in frontier areas]. Würzburg, Germany: Ergon. American Society for Psychical Research (1983). Courses and study opportunities in parapsychology (9th edition). New York: American Society for Psychical Research. Andrade, H. G. (1984). O poltergeist de Guarulhos [The Guarulhos poltergeist] (Monograph No. 6, Instituto Brasileiro de Pesquisas Psicobiofisicas). Sao Paulo, Brazil: Instituto Brasileiro de Pesquisas Psicobiofisicas. Anonymous. (2012). CERCAP. Mindfield, 4(3), 92–93. Anonymous. (2014). The Division of Perceptual Studies. Retrieved from: http://www.medicine.virginia.edu/clinical/departments/psychiatry/sections/c spp/dops/home-page. Anonymous. (n.d.a.) CIRCEE: Centre d’Information, de Recherche et de Consultation sur les Expériences Exceptionnelles [CIRCEE: Center of Information, Research and Consultation about Exceptional Experiences]. Retrieved from: http://www.circee.org/. Anonymous. (n.d.b.) Núcleo de Pesquisa em Espiritualidade e Saúde [Group of Research on Spirituality and Health]. Retrieved from: http://www.ufjf.br/nupes/. Anonymous. (n.d.c.) Paranthropology: Journal of Anthropological Approaches to the Paranormal. Retrieved from http://paranthropologyjournal.weebly.com/. Bauer, E. (1982). Kritik und Kontroversen der Parapsychologie [Criticisms and controversies of parapsychology]. In G. Condrau (Ed.), Die Psychologie der Kultur (Vol. 2) (pp. 66–79). Basel, Switzerland: Beltz. Bauer, E., Hövelmann, G. H., and Lucadou, W. von (2013). Betraying the present by distorting the past: Comments on Parker’s tendentious portrait of German psychical research. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 77, 32–42. Beischel, J., and Schwartz, G. E. (2007). Anomalous information reception by research mediums demonstrated using a novel triple-blind protocol. Explore: The Journal of Science and Healing, 3, 23–27. Beloff, J. (1990). The relentless question: Reflections on the paranormal. Jefferson, NC: McFarland. Beloff, J. (1977). Historical overview. In B. B. Wolman (Ed.), Handbook of parapsychology (pp. 3–24). New York: Van Nostrand Reinhold. Beloff, J. (1993). Parapsychology: A concise history. London, UK: Athlone Press. Belz, M. (2009). Aussergewöhnliche Erfahrungen. [Exceptional experiences.] Göttingen, Germany: Hogrefe. Bem, D. J. (2011). Feeling the future: Experimental evidence for anomalous retroactive influences on cognition and affect. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 100, 407–425. Bem, D. J., and Honorton, C. (1994). Does psi exist? Replicable evidence for an anomalous process of information transfer. Psychological Bulletin, 115, 4–18. Bem, D. J., Tressoldi, P., Rabeyron, T., and Duggan, M. (2014). Feeling the future: A meta-analysis of 90 experiments on the anomalous anticipation of random future events. Retrieved from the Social Science Research Network, http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=2423692. Bem, D. J., Utts, J., and Johnson, W. O. (2011). Must psychologists change the way they analyze their data? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 101, 716–719. Bender, H., and Bauer, E. (1977). Parapsychologie [Parapsychology]. In T. Herrmann, P. R. Hofstätter, H. P. Huber, and F. E. Weinert (Eds.), Handbuch psychologischer Grundbegriffe (pp. 335–341). München, Germany: Kösel. Bengston, W. F., and Krinsley, D. (2000). The effect of “laying on of hands” on transplanted breast cancer in mice. Journal of Scientific Exploration, 14, 353–364. Bernardi, S. (1986). Shamanism and parapsychology. Parapsychology Review, 17(5), 7–11. Bierman, D. J. (1999). The PRL autoganzfeld revisited: Refuting the sound leakage hypothesis. Journal of Parapsychology, 63, 271–274. Bierman, D. (2011). Anomalous switching of the bi-stable percept of a Necker cube: A preliminary study. Journal of Scientific Exploration, 25, 721–733. Bierman, D., and Scholte H. (2002). A fMRI brain imaging study of presentiment. Journal of International Society of Life Information Science, 20, 380–389. Biondi, M. (1988). Tavoli e medium: Storia dello spiritismo in Italia [Table and medium: A history of spiritism in Italy]. Rome, Italy: Gremese. Biondi, M., and Caratelli, G. (1993). La natura del poltergeist: Studio su due casistiche [The nature of the poltergeist: Study of two case collections]. Quaderni di Parapsicologia, 24, 12–36. Blackmore, S. J. (1982). Out-of-the-body experiences, lucid dreams and imagery: Two surveys. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 76, 301–317. Blanke, O., Landis, T., Spinelli, L., and Seeck, M. (2004). Out-of-body experience and autoscopy of neurological origin. Brain, 127, 243–258. Bösch, H., Steinkamp, F., and Boller, E. (2006). Examining psychokinesis: The interaction of human intention with random number generators—a meta-analysis. Psychological Bulletin, 132, 497–523. Bouflet, J. (2001–2003). Encyclopédie des phénomènes extraordinaires dans la vie mystique (3 Vols.) [Encyclopedia of extraordinary phenomena in mystical life.] Paris, France: Le Jardin des Livres. Bouflet, J. (2006). La lévitation [Levitation]. Paris, France: Jardin de Livres. Braithwaite, J. J., Samson, D., Apperly, I., Broglia, E., and Hulleman, J. (2011). Cognitive correlates of the spontaneous out-of-body experience (OBE) in the psychologically normal population: Evidence for an increased role of temporal-lobe instability, body-distortion processing, and impairments in own-body transformations. Cortex, 47, 839–853. Braud, W. (1980). Lability and inertia in conformance behavior. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 74, 297–318. Braud, W. (1990). Distant mental influence of rate of hemolysis of human red blood cells. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 84, 1–24. Braud, W. G. (2003). Distant mental influence: Its contributions to science, healing, and human interactions. Charlottesville, VA: Hampton Roads. Braud, W., Davis, G., and Wood, R. (1979). Experiments with Matthew Manning. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 50, 199–223. Braud, W. G., and Dennis, S. P. (1989). Geophysical variables and behavior: LVIII. Autonomic activity, hemolysis, and biological psychokinesis: Possible relationships with geomagnetic field activity. Perceptual and Motor Skills, 68, 1243–1254. Braud, W., and Schlitz, M. (1983). Psychokinetic influence on electrodermal activity. Journal of Parapsychology, 47, 95–119. Braude, S. E. (1997). The limits of influence: Psychokinesis and the philosophy of science (2nd ed.). Lanham, MD: University Press of America. Braude, S. (2000). Dissociation and latent abilities: The strange case of Patience Worth. Journal of Trauma and Dissociation, 1, 13–48. Braude, S. E. (2002). ESP and psychokinesis: A philosophical examination (2nd ed.). Parkland, FL: Brown Walker. Braude, S. E. (2003). Immortal remains: The evidence of life after death. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield. Broughton, R. S. (1982). Computer methodology: Total control with a human face. In B. Shapin, and L. Coly (Eds.), Parapsychology and the experimental method (pp. 24–42). New York: Parapsychology Foundation. Bunge, M. (1991). A sceptic’s beliefs and disbeliefs. New Ideas in Psychology, 9, 131–149. Cardeña, E. (2014). A call for an open, informed study of all aspects of consciousness. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 8, doi: 10.3389/fnhum.2014.00017. Cardeña, E., Lynn, S, J., and S. Krippner (Eds.) (2014). Varieties of anomalous experience: Examining the scientific evidence (2nd ed.). Washington, D.C.: American Psychological Association Press. Carpenter, J. C. (1983). Prediction of forced-choice ESP performance: I. Journal of Parapsychology, 47, 191–216. Carpenter. J. C. (1991). Prediction of forced-choice ESP performance: III. Three attempts to retrieve coded information using mood reports and a repeated-guessing technique. Journal of Parapsychology, 55, 227–280. Carpenter, J. C. (2012). First sight. ESP and parapsychology in everyday life. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield. Carter, C. (2012). Science and psychic phenomena: The fall of the house of skeptics. Rochester, VT: Inner Traditions. Carr, B. (2008). The growth of UK academic parapsychology. Paranormal Review, 48, 23–25. Cassoli, P. (1979). Il guaritore [The healer]. Milan, Italy: Armenia. Caswell, J. M., Hunter, J., and Tessaro, L. W. E. (2014). Phenomenological convergence between major paradigms of classic parapsychology and crosscultural practices: An exploration of paranthropology. Journal of Consciousness Exploration & Research, 5, 467–482. Retrieved from: http://www.jcer.com/index.php/jcj/article/view/378. Chauvin, R. (1986). A PK experiment with mice. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 53, 348–351. Child, I. (1984). Implications of parapsychology for psychology. In S. Krippner, M. L. Carlson, M. Ullman, and R.O. Becker (Eds.), Advances in parapsychological research 4 (pp. 165–182). Jefferson, NC: McFarland. Child, I. (1985). Psychology and anomalous observations: The question of ESP in dreams. American Psychologist, 40, 1219–1230. Colvin, B. (2010). The acoustic properties of unexplained rapping sounds. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 73, 65–93. Coly, L., and McMahon, J. D. S. (Eds.). (1993). Psi and clinical practice. New York: Parapsychology Foundation. Crabtree, A. (1993). From Mesmer to Freud: Magnetic sleep and the roots of psychological healing. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Dalton, K. S., Morris, R. L., Delanoy, D. L., Radin, D., Taylor, R., and Wiseman, R. (1994). Security measures in an automated ganzfeld system. In D. Bierman (Ed.), Proceedings of Presented Papers: 37th Annual Convention of the Parapsychological Association (pp. 114–123). Amsterdam, The Netherlands: University of Amsterdam. Debes, J., and Morris, R. L. (1982). Comparison of striving and nonstriving instructional sets in a PK study. Journal of Parapsychology, 46, 297–312. Delorme, A., Beischel, J., Michel, L., Boccuzzi, M., Radin, D., and Mills, P. J. (2013). Electrocortical activity associated with subjective communication with the deceased. Frontiers of Psychology, 4. doi:fpsyg.2013.00834. Diaconis, P. (1978). Statistical problems in ESP research. Science, 201, 131–136. Druckman, D., and Swets, J. A. (Eds.). (1988). Enhancing human performance: Issues, theories, and techniques. Washington, D.C.: National Academy Press. Duplessis, Y. (2002). Surréalisme et paranormal: L’aspect expérimental du surréalisme. [Surrealism and the paranormal: The experimental aspect of surrealism.] Agnières, France: JMG Editions. Dutton, D., and Williams, C. (2009). Clever beasts and faithful pets: A critical review of animal psi research. Journal of Parapsychology, 73, 43– 70. Evrard, R. (2010). Parapsychology in France after May 1968: A history of the GERP. Journal of Scientific Exploration, 24, 283–294. Evrard, R. (2014). Folie et paranormal: Vers une clinique des expériences exceptionnelles. [Madness and the paranormal: Towards an exceptional experiences clinic.] Rennes, France: Presses Universitaires de Rennes. French, C. C., Haque, U., Bunton-Stasyshyn, R., and Davis, R. (2009). The “Haunt” Project: An attempt to build a “haunted” room by manipulating complex electromagnetic fields and infrasound. Cortex, 45, 619–629. Gauger, W. (1980). Y. Paranormale Welt, Wirklichkeit und Literatur [Y: The paranormal world in reality and literature]. Berlin, Germany: Henssel. Gauld, A. (1982). Mediumship and survival: A century of investigations. London, UK: Heinemann. Gauld, A., and Cornell, A. D. (1979). Poltergeists. Boston, MA: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Gavilán Fontanet, F. (1978). Los factores motivacionales del investigador en parapsicología. [The motivational factors of the researcher in parapsychology]. Psi Comunicación, 4, 9–18. Giesler, P. V. (1984). Parapsychological anthropology. I: Multi-method approaches to the study of psi in the field setting. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 78, 289–330. Giesler, P. V. (1985a). Differential micro–PK effects among Afro-Brazilian cultists: Three studies using trance-significant symbols as targets. Journal of Parapsychology, 49, 329–366. Giesler, P. V. (1985b). Parapsychological anthropology. II: A multi-method study of psi and psi-related processes in the Umbanda ritual trance consultation. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 79, 113–166. Giesler, P. V. (1986). GESP testing of shamanic cultists: Three studies and an evaluation of dramatic upsets during testing. Journal of Parapsychology, 50, 123–153. Gissurarson, L. R. (1990–1991). Some PK attitudes as determinants of PK performance. European Journal of Parapsychology, 8, 112–122. González Quevedo, O. (1996). Milagres: A ciência confirma a fé [Miracles: Science confirms faith]. Sao Paulo, Brazil: Loyola. Goulding, A., Westerlund, J., Parker, A., and Wackermann, J. (2004). The first digital autoganzfeld study using a real-time judging procedure. European Journal of Parapsychology, 19, 66–97. Gregory, A. (1985). The strange case of Rudi Schneider. Metuchen, NJ: Scarecrow Press. Greyson, B. (2010). Implications of near-death experiences for a postmaterialist psychology. Psychology of Religion and Spirituality, 2, 37– 45. Greyson, B. (2014). Near death experiences. In E. Cardeña, S. J. Lynn, and Krippner, S. (Eds.), Varieties of anomalous experience: Examining the scientific evidence (2nd ed.) (pp. 333–367). Washington, D.C.: American Psychological Association. Greyson, B., and Stevenson, I. (1980). The phenomenology of near-death experiences. American Journal of Psychiatry, 137, 1193–1196. Griffin, D. R. (1997). Parapsychology, philosophy, and spirituality: A postmodern exploration. Albany: State University of New York Press. Grosso, M. (1997). The parapsychology of God. In C. T. Tart (Ed.), Body mind and spirit: Exploring the parapsychology of spirituality (pp. 101– 117). Charlottesville, VA: Hampton Roads. Grosso, M. (in press). The strange case of St. Joseph of Copertino: Ecstasy and the mind-body problem. New York: Oxford University Press. Hansel, C. E. M. (1980). ESP and parapsychology: A critical re-evaluation. Buffalo, NY: Prometheus Press. Hansen, G. P. (1990). Deception by subjects in psi research. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 84, 25–80. Hansen, G. P. (1991). The elusive agenda: Dissuading as debunking in Ray Hyman’s The Elusive Quarry. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 85, 193–203. Hansen, G. P. (1992). CSICOP and the skeptics: An overview. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 86, 19–63. Hansen, G. P. (2001). The trickster and the paranormal. Philadelphia, PA: Xlibris. Haraldsson, E. (1980). Confirmation of the percipient-order effect in a plethysmographic study of ESP. Journal of Parapsychology, 44, 105–124. Haraldsson, E. (2003). Children who speak of past-life experiences: Is there a psychological explanation? Psychology and Psychotherapy: Theory Research and Practice, 76, 55–67. Haraldsson, E. (2012). The departed among the living: An investigative study of afterlife encounters. Guilford, UK: White Crow. Haraldsson, E., and Gissurarson, L. R. (1987). Does geomagnetic activity effect extrasensory perception? Personality and Individual Differences, 8, 745–747. Hassler, D. (2013). A new European case of the reincarnation type. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 77, 19–31. Hearne, K. M. T. (1982). An ostensible precognition of the accidental sinking of H. M. submarine Artemis in 1971. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 51, 283–287. Heath, P. R. (2011) Mind-matter interaction: A review of historical reports, theory and research. Jefferson, NC: McFarland. Hess, D. J. (1992). Disciplining heterodoxy, circumventing discipline: Parapsychology, anthropologically. In D. Hess and L. Layne (Eds.), Knowledge and society Vol. 9: The anthropology of science and technology (pp. 191–222). Greenwich, CT: JAI Press. Hess, D. J. (1993). Science in the New Age: The paranormal, its defenders and debunkers, and American culture. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press. Higuchi, Y., Kotani, Y., Higuchi, H., Minegishi, Y., and Momose, S. (1999). Endocrine changes during qigong therapy. Journal of International Society of Life Information Science, 17, 83–89. Holt, N. J., Simmonds-Moore, C., Luke, D., and French, C. C. (2012). Anomalistic psychology. Hampshire, UK: Palgrave Macmillan. Honorton, C. (1993). Rhetoric over substance: The impoverished state of skepticism. Journal of Parapsychology, 57, 191–214. Honorton, C. (1997). The ganzfeld novice: Four predictors of initial ESP performance. Journal of Parapsychology, 61, 143–158. Honorton, C., Berger, R. E., Varvoglis, M. P., Quant, M., Derr, P., Schechter, E. I., and Ferrari, D. C. (1990). Psi communication in the ganzfeld: Experiments with an automated testing system and a comparison with a meta-analysis of earlier studies. Journal of Parapsychology, 54, 99– 139. Honorton, C., and Ferrari, D. C. (1989). “Future telling”: A meta-analysis of forced-choice precognition experiments, 1935–1987. Journal of Parapsychology, 53, 281–308. Hou, Y., Huang, Q., Prakash, R., and Chaudhury, S. (2013). Infrequent near death experiences in severe brain injury survivors—A quantitative and qualitative study. Annals of Indian Academy of Neurology, 16, 75–81. Houtkooper, J. M., Schienle, A., Stark, R., and Vaitl, D. (1999) Geophysical variables and behavior: LXXXVIII. Atmospheric electromagnetism: The possible disturbing influence of natural sferics on ESP. Perceptual and Motor Skills, 89, 1179–1192. Hövelmann, G. H. (1983). Seven recommendations for the future practice of parapsychology. Zetetic Scholar, 11, 128–138. Hövelmann, G. H. (1984). Are psi experiments repeatable? A conceptual framework for the discussion of repeatability. European Journal of Parapsychology, 5, 285–306. Hövelmann, G. H. (1986). Neglected figures in the history of parapsychology: I. Some general reflections. In F. W. J. J. Snel (Ed.), In honour of G. A. M. Zorab (pp. 94–126). The Hague, Netherlands: Nederlandse Vereniging voor Parapsychologie. Hövelmann, G. H. (1988). Parapsychologists and skeptics—problems of identification: Some personal comments evoked by J. C. Jacobs. SRU Bulletin, 13, 125–132. Hövelmann, G. H. (1989a). Animal “language” research: The perpetuation of some old mistakes. Semiotica, 73, 199–217. Hövelmann, G. H. (1989b). Animal “language” research now and then: Problems of method and interpretation. SRU Bulletin, 14, 39–62. Hövelmann, G. H. (2010). Akademische Abschlussarbeiten zu Themen der Anomalistik, 2000–2010. Eine Auswahlbibliographie [Academic graduation theses on anomalistic topics, 2000–2010. A select bibliography]. Zeitschrift für Anomalistik, 10, 123–135. Hövelmann, G. H. (2012). Vom Nutzen der Grenzgebietsforschung für die Wissenschaft [On the utility of frontier research for science at large]. In W. Ambach (Ed.), Experimentelle Psychophysiologie in Grenzgebieten (pp. 303–337). Würzburg, Germany: Ergon. Hövelmann, G. H. (in press). Terminologische Reform als Selbstgespräch: Max Dessoir und die Erfindung der “Parapsychologie“ [Terminological reform as a monologue: Max Dessoir and the invention of “parapsychology“]. Zeitschrift für Anomalistik, 15. Hövelmann, G. H., and Michels, J. A. G. (in press). Legitimacy of unbelief: The collected papers of Piet Hein Hoebens. Münster, Germany: Lit-Verlag. Hövelmann, G. H., and Schriever, F. (2004). Der leise Revolutionär: Prof. Dr. Robert L. Morris (1942–2004) [The silent revolutionary: Prof. Dr. Robert L. Morris (1942–2004)]. Zeitschrift für Anomalistik 4, 6–13. Huesmann, M., and Schriever, F. (1989). Steckbrief des Spuks: Darstellung und Diskussion einer Sammlung von 54 RSPK-Berichten des Freiburger Instituts für Grenzgebiete der Psychologie und Psychohygiene aus den Jahren 1947–1986 [Wanted: The Poltergeist. Description and discussion of a collection of 54 RSPK reports from the years 1947–1986, collected by the Freiburg IGPP]. Zeitschrift für Parapsychologie und Grenzgebiete der Psychologie, 31, 52–107. Hunter, J. (2010). Anthropology & the paranormal: What’s the point? Paranthropology: Journal of Anthropological Approaches to the Paranormal, 1(1), 2–3. Hunter, J., and Luke, D. (2014). (Eds.). Talking with spirits: Ethnographies from between the worlds. Brisbane, Australia: Daily Grail. Hyman, R. (1989). The elusive quarry: A scientific appraisal of psychical research. Buffalo, NY: Prometheus Books. Hyman, R. (2007). Evaluating parapsychological claims. In R. J. Sternberg, H. L. Roediger, and D. F. Halpern (Eds.), Critical thinking in psychology (pp. 216–231). New York: Cambridge University Press. Hyman, R. (2010). Meta-analysis that conceals more than it reveals: Comment on Storm et al. (2010). Psychological Bulletin, 136, 486–490. Iannuzzo, G. (1978). Osservazioni su una famiglia di sensitivi: Il caso Lo Cascio [Observations of a family of sensitives: The Lo Cascio case]. Metapsichica, 33, 30–40. Iannuzzo, G. (1984). Verso una parantropologia: Fenomeni paranormali e magia [Towards a paranthropology: Paranormal phenomena and magic]. Luce e Ombra, 84, 214–230. Iannuzzo, G. (2008). Sul lettino dello sciamano: Il fondamenti della parapsicologia clinica [On the bed of the shaman: The foundations of clinical parapsychology]. Rome, Italy: GSE. Inglis, B. (1984). Science and parascience: A history of the paranormal, 1914–1939. London, UK: Hodder and Stoughton. Institut für Grenzgebiete der Psychologie und Psychohygiene (IGPP). (2010). Tätigkeitsbericht/Biennial Report 2008/2009. Freiburg i.Br., Germany: IGPP. Irwin, H. J. (1979). Psi and the mind: An information processing approach. Metuchen, NJ: Scarecrow Press. Irwin, H. J. (1980). Out of the body down under: Some cognitive characteristics of Australian students reporting OBEs. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 50, 448–459. Irwin, H. (2002). Is scientific investigation of postmortem survival an anachronism?: The demise of the survival hypothesis. Australian Journal of Parapsychology, 2, 19–27. Irwin, H. J., and Watt, C. A. (2007). An introduction to parapsychology (5th ed.). Jefferson, NC: McFarland. Jahn, R. G., and Dunne, B. J. (2005). The PEAR proposition. Journal of Scientific Exploration, 19, 195–245. Jahn, R. G., Dunne, B. J., Nelson, R. D., Dobyns, Y. H., and Bradish, G. J. (1997). Correlations of random binary sequences with pre-stated operator intention: A review of a 12-year program. Journal of Scientific Exploration, 11, 345–367. Joines, W. T, Baumann, S. B., and Kruth, J. G. (2012). Electromagnetic emission from humans during focused intent. Journal of Parapsychology, 76, 275–294. Junior, A. S., Araujo, S. de F., and Moreira-Almeida, A. (2013). William James and psychical research: Towards a radical science of mind. History of Psychiatry, 24, 62–78. Keen, M., Ellison, A., and Fontana, D. (1999). The Scole report: An account of an investigation into the genuineness of a range of physical phenomena associated with a mediumistic group in Norfolk, England. Proceedings of the Society for Psychical Research, 58, 149–392. Kelly, E. F., Kelly, E. W., Crabtree, A., Gauld, A., Grosso, M., and Greyson, B. (2007). Irreducible mind: Toward a psychology for the 21st century. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield. Kelly, E. W., and Arcangel, D. (2011). An investigation of mediums who claim to give information about deceased persons. Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, 199, 11–17. Kramer, W., Bauer, E., and Hövelmann, G. (Eds.) (2012). Perspectives of clinical parapsychology: An introductory reader. Bunnik, Netherlands: Stichting HJBF. Kripal, J. J. (2006). Authors of the impossible: The paranormal and the sacred. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Krippner, S., and Friedman, H. L. (Eds.) (2010). Debating psychic experience: Human potential or human illusion? Santa Barbara, CA: Praeger. Krippner, S., and Hövelmann, G. H. (2005). The future of psi research: Recommendations in retrospect. In M. A. Thalbourne & L. Storm (Eds.), Parapsychology in the twenty-first century: Essays on the future of psychical research (pp. 167–188). Jefferson, NC: McFarland. Krippner, S., Rock, A. J., Beischel, J., Friedman, H. L., and Fracasso, C.L. (2013). Introduction: Science and psi. In S. Krippner, A. J. Rock, J. Beischel, H. L. Friedman, and C. L. Fracasso (Eds.), Advances in parapsychological research 9 (pp. 1–8). Jefferson, NC: McFarland. Kurtz, P. (Ed.). (1985). A skeptic’s handbook of parapsychology. Buffalo, NY: Prometheus Books. Lachapelle, S. (2011). Investigating the supernatural: From spiritism and occultism to psychical research and metapsychics in France, 1853–1931. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press. Lamont, P. (2013). Extraordinary beliefs: A historical approach to a psychological problem. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Laurentin, R., and Mahéo, P. (1990). Bilocations de Mère Yvonne-Aimée. [Bilocations of Mother Yvonne-Aimée] Paris, France: O.E.I.L. Leibovici, L. (2001). Effects of remote, retroactive intercessory prayer on outcomes in patients with bloodstream infection: Randomised controlled trial. British Medical Journal, 323, 1450–1451. Long, J. K. (Ed.). (1977). Extrasensory ecology: Parapsychology and anthropology. Metuchen, NJ: Scarecrow Press. Lucadou, W. von. (1995). The model of pragmatic information (MPI). European Journal of Parapsychology, 11, 58–75. Lucadou, W. von. (2013). The paranormal is normal but quite different. In R. Pilkington (Ed.), Esprit: Men and women of parapsychology, personal reflections, volume 2 (pp. 409–422). San Antonio: Anomalist Books. Lucadou, W. von, and Kornwachs, K. (1983). On the limitations of psi—A system-theoretic approach. Psychoenergetics, 5, 53–72. Luke, D. (2010). Anthropology and parapsychology: Still hostile sisters in science. Time and Mind: The Journal of Archaeology, Consciousness and Culture, 3, 245–265. Luke, D. P., Delanoy, D. L., and Sherwood, S. J. (2008). Psi may look like luck: Perceived luckiness and beliefs about luck in relation to precognition. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 72, 193–207. Machado, F. R. (2010). Experiências anômalas (extra-sensório-motoras) na vida cotidiana e sua associação com crenças, atitudes e bem-estar subjetivo [Anomalous experiences (extra-sensory-motor) in everyday life and their associations with beliefs, attitudes, and subjective well-being]. Boletim Academia Paulista de Psicologia, 30, 462–483. Maher, M. C., and Hansen, G. P. (1995). Quantitative investigation of a haunted castle in New Jersey. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 89, 19–50. Marcusson-Clavertz, D., and Cardeña, E. (2011). Hypnotizability, alterations in consciousness, and other variables as predictors of performance in a ganzfeld psi task. Journal of Parapsychology, 75, 235– 259. Mattuck, R. D. (1984). A quantum mechanical theory of the interaction of consciousness with matter. In M. Cazenave (Ed.), Science and consciousness (pp. 49–65). New York: Pergamon Press. Mauskopf, S. H., and McVaugh, M. R. (1980). The elusive science: Origins of experimental psychical research. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press. May, E. C., Spottiswoode, S. J. P., and James, C. L. (1994). Shannon entropy: A possible intrinsic target property. Journal of Parapsychology, 58, 384–401. Mayer, G. (2003). Über Grenzen schreiben: Presseberichterstattung zu Themen aus dem Bereich der Anomalistik und der Grenzgebiete der Psychologie in den Printmedien Spiegel, Bild und Bild am Sonntag [Writing about frontiers: Press coverage on issues of anomalistics and the frontier areas of psychology in the print media Spiegel, Bild, and Bild am Sonntag]. Zeitschrift für Anomalistik, 3, 8–46. Mazza, G. M. (1995). Esperienze ESP in psicoterapia infantile con bambini borderline [ESP experiences in child psychotherapy with borderline children]. Quaderni di Parapsicologia, 26, 54–69. McClenon, J. (1984). Deviant science: The case of parapsychology. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press. McClenon, J. (1988). A survey of Chinese anomalous experiences and comparison with Western representative samples. Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion, 27, 421–426. McConnell, R. A., and Clark, T. K. (1980). Training, belief, and mental conflict within the Parapsychological Association. Journal of Parapsychology, 44, 245–268. McDonough, B. E., Don, N. S., and Warren, C. A. (2002). Differential event-related potentials in targets and decoys in guessing task. Journal of Scientific Exploration, 16, 187–206. Méheust, B. (1999). Somnambulisme et mediumnité (1784–1930): Vol. 2: Le choc des sciences psychiques [Somnambulism and mediumship (1784– 1930): Volume 2: The impact of the psychic sciences]. Le Plessis-Robinson, France: Institut Synthélabo pour de Progrès de la Connaissance. Méheust, B. (2003). Un voyant prodigieux: Alexis Didier, 1826–1866 [A prodigious seer: Alexis Didier, 1826–1866]. Paris, France: Empêcheurs de Penser en Rond. Millar, B. (1978). The observational theories. A primer. European Journal of Parapsychology, 2, 304–332. Mills, A. (1988). A preliminary investigation of cases of reincarnation among the Beaver and Gitksan Indians. Anthropologica, 33, 23–59. Milton, J. (1995). Publishing and funding parapsychology in the mainstream: A mail survey of experiences and strategies for success. European Journal of Parapsychology, 11, 1–18. Milton, J., and Wiseman, R. (1997). Guidelines for extrasensory perception research. Hatfield, UK: University of Hertfordshire Press. Milton, J., and Wiseman, R. (1999). Does psi exist? Lack of replication of an anomalous process on information transfer. Psychological Bulletin, 125, 387–391. Minami, E., Usui, T., and Kokubo, H. (2014). Relationship between age and healing power—A study using a bio-sensor for non-contact healing. Journal of International Society of Life Information Science, 32, 49–52. Modestino, E. J. (2013). Physiological responses as unconscious measures of psi. In S. Krippner, A. J. Rock, J. Beischel, H. L. Friedman, and C. L. Fracasso (Eds.), Advances in parapsychological research 9 (pp. 126–157). Jefferson, NC: McFarland. Moga, M. M. (2014). Magnetic field activity during psychic healing: A preliminary study with healing touch practitioners. Journal of Nonlocality, 3(1), Retrieved from: http://journals.sfu.ca/jnonlocality/index.php/jnonlocality/issue/view/7/show Toc. Moody, R. (1975). Life after life. Atlanta, GA: Mockingbird Books. Moreira-Almeida, A., Neto, F. L., and Cardeña, E. (2008). Comparison of Brazilian spiritist mediumship and dissociative identity disorder. Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, 196, 420–424. Morris, R. L. (2001). Guest editorial: The continuing evolution of parapsychology. Journal of Parapsychology, 65, 327–333. Morris, R. L., Harary, S. B., Janis, J., Hartwell, J., and Roll, W. G. (1978). Studies of communication during out-of-body experiences. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 72, 1–21. Morris, R. L., Nanko, M., and Phillips, D. (1982). A comparison of two popularly advocated visual imagery strategies in a psychokinesis task. Journal of Parapsychology, 46, 1–16. Mossbridge, J., Tressoldi, P., and Utts, J. (2012). Predictive physiological anticipation preceding seemingly unpredictable stimuli: A meta-analysis. Frontiers in Psychology: Perception Science, 17, doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2012.00390. Murray, C. D. (Ed.). (2009). Psychological scientific perspectives on out-ofbody and near-death experiences. New York: Nova Science. Murray, C., and Wooffitt, R. (2010). Anomalous experience and qualitative research: An introduction to the special issue. Qualitative Research in Psychology, 7, 1–4. Nahm, M. (2014). The development and phenomena of a circle for physical mediumship. Journal of Scientific Exploration, 28, 229–283. Nelson, R. D. (2013). The Global Consciousness Project: Meaningful patterns in random data. In S. Krippner, A. J. Rock, J. Beischel, H. L. Friedman, and C. L. Fracasso (Eds.), Advances in parapsychological research 9 (pp. 15–37). Jefferson, NC: McFarland. Nichols, A. A. (2000). A water poltergeist in Florida. International Journal of Parapsychology, 11, 143–159. Novelletto, A. (1980). Comunicazioni inconsce (cosiddetti sogni telepatici) tra pazienti diversi di uno stesso analista [Unconscious communications (so-called telepathic dreams) between different patients by the same analyst]. Rivista di Psicoanalisi, 26, 237–363. Osis, K., and Haraldsson, E. (1997). What they saw … at the hour of death (3rd ed.). Norwalk, CT: Hastings House. Osis, K., and McCormick, D. (1980). Kinetic effects at the ostensible location of an out-of- body projection during perceptual testing. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 74, 319–329. Osis, K., and Mitchell, J. L. (1977). Physiological correlates of reported out-of-body experiences. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 49, 525–536. Oteri, L. (Ed.). (1975). Quantum physics and parapsychology. New York: Parapsychology Foundation. Owens, J. E., Cook, E. W., and Stevenson, I. (1990). Features of ‘‘neardeath experience’’ in relation to whether or not patients were near death. Lancet, 336, 1175–1177. Palmer, J. (1979). A community mail survey of psychic experiences. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 73, 221–251. Palmer, J. (1983). Sensory contamination of free-response ESP targets: The greasy fingers hypothesis. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 77, 101–113. Palmer, J. (2009). Editorial: Winning over the scientific mainstream. Journal of Parapsychology, 73, 3–8. Palmer, J. A., Honorton, C., and Utts, J. (1989). Reply to the National Research Council Study on parapsychology. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 83, 31–49. Parker, A., and Jensen, C. (2013). Further possible physiological connectedness between identical twins. Explore :The Journal of Science and Healing, 9, 26–31. Parra, A. (2010). Out-of-body experiences and hallucinatory experiences: A psychological approach. Imagination, Cognition and Personality, 29, 211– 223. Parra, A. (2012). Fundraising for psi research: Bial Foundation’s contributions to the development of parapsychology. Mindfield, 5, 8–12. Parra, A. (2013). Cognitive and emotional empathy in relation to five paranormal/anomalous experiences. North American Journal of Psychology, 15, 405–412. Parra, A., and Villanueva, J. (2003). Personality factors and ESP during ganzfeld sessions. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 67, 26–36. Pasricha, S. (1990). Claims of reincarnation: An empirical study of cases in India. New Delhi, India: Harman. Pasricha, S. K. (2011). Relevance of parapsychology in psychiatric practice. Indian Journal of Psychiatry, 53, 4–8. Peoch, R. (1988). Chicken imprinting and the tychoscope: An anpsi experiment. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 55, 1–9. Peres, J. F., Moreira-Almeida, A., Caixeta, L., Leao, F., and Newberg, A. (2012). Neuroimaging during trance state: A contribution to the study of dissociation. PLoS ONE, 7:e49360. DOI: 10.1371/journal.pone.0049360 Piccinini, G., and Rinaldi, G. M. (1990). I fantasmi dei morenti: Inchiesta su una credenza [Phantasms of the dying: Survey of a belief]. Viareggio, Italy: Il Cardo. Pinch, T. J. (1979). Normal explanations of the paranormal: The demarcation problem and fraud in parapsychology. Social Studies of Science, 9, 329–348. Pinch, T. J., and Collins, H. M. (1984). Private science and public knowledge: The Committee for the Scientific Investigation of the Claims of the Paranormal and its use of the literature. Social Studies of Science, 14, 521–546. Plas, R. (2000). Naissance d’une science humaine: La psychologie: Les psychologues et le “merveilleux psychique” [Birth of a new science: Psychology: Psychologists and the “psychic marvelous”]. Rennes, France: Presses Universitaires de Rennes. Rabeyron, T., and Evrard, R. (2012). Perspectives historiques et contemporaines sur l’occulte dans la correspondance Freud-Ferenczi [Historical and contemporary perspectives on occultism in the FreudFerenczi correspondence]. Recherches en Psychanalyse, 13, 97–111. Radin, D. (2004). Electrodermal presentiments of future emotions. Journal of Scientific Exploration, 18, 253–273. Radin, D. (2006). Entangled minds: extrasensory experiences in a quantum reality. New York: Paraview. Radin, D. I., and Ferrari, D. C. (1991). Effects of consciousness on the fall of dice: A meta-analysis. Journal of Scientific Exploration, 5, 61–83. Radin, D., and Nelson, R. (1989). Evidence for consciousness-related anomalies in random physical systems. Foundations of Physics, 19, 1499– 1514. Radin, D., Nelson, R., Dobyns, Y., and J. Houtkooper (2006a). Reexamining psychokinesis: Comment on Bösch, Steinkamp and Boller (2006). Psychological Bulletin, 132, 529–532. Radin, D., Nelson, R., Dobyns, Y., and J. Houtkooper (2006b). Assessing the evidence for mind-matter interaction effects. Journal of Scientific Exploration, 20, 361–374. Rao, K. R. (Ed.). (1994). Charles Honorton and the impoverished state of skepticism: Essays on a parapsychological pioneer. Jefferson, NC: McFarland. Reed, G. (1988). The psychology of anomalous experience (Rev. ed.). Buffalo, NY: Prometheus. Rhine, J. B. (1959). What do parapsychologists want to know? Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 53, 3–15. Rhine, J. B. (1987). The parapsychology of religion: A new branch of inquiry. In B. Shapin, and L. Coly (Ed.), Parapsychology, philosophy and religious concepts (pp. 191–215). New York: Parapsychology Foundation. (Original work published 1977–1978). Richards, D. (1991). A study of the correlation between subjective psychic experiences and dissociative experiences. Dissociation, 4, 83–91. Ring, K. (1980). Life at death: A scientific investigation of the near-death experience. New York: Coward, McCann & Geoghegan. Ring, K., and Lawrence, M. (1993). Further evidence for veridical perception during near-death experiences. Journal of Near-Death Studies, 11, 223–229. Rock, A. J. (Ed.). (2013). The survival hypothesis: Essays on mediumship. Jefferson, NC: McFarland. Rock, A. J., Beischel, J., and Schwartz, G. E. (2008). Thematic analysis of research medium’s experiences of discarnate communication. Journal of Scientific Exploration, 22, 179–192. Roe, C. A. (2009). Anomalistic psychology. In N. Holt and R. Lewis (Eds.), A2 Psychology 2009 AQA A Specification: The student’s textbook (pp. 426– 463). London, UK: Crown House. Roll, W. G. (2003). Poltergeists, electromagnetism and consciousness. Journal of Scientific Exploration, 17, 75–86. Roll, W. G. (2006). A discussion of the evidence that personal consciousness persists after death with special reference to poltergeist phenomena. Australian Journal of Parapsychology, 6, 5–20. Roll, W. G., Saroka, K. S., Mulligan, B. P., Hunter, M. D., Dotta, B. T., Gang, N., … Persinger, M. A. (2012). Case report: A prototypical experience of “poltergeist” activity, conspicuous quantitative electroencephalographic patterns, and sLORETA profiles—suggestions for intervention. Neurocase, 18, 527–536. Rosenbaum, R. (2011). Exploring the other dark continent: Parallels between psi phenomena and the psychotherapeutic process. Psychoanalytic Review, 98, 57–90. Rosenthal, R. (1965). Introduction: Clever Hans: A case study of scientific method. In O. Pfungst, Clever Hans (The horse of Mr. von Osten) (pp. ix– xlii). New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston. Roxburgh, E. C., and Roe, C. A. (2011). A survey of dissociation, boundary-thinness, and psychological well-being in Spiritualist mental mediumship. Journal of Parapsychology, 75, 279–299. Roxburgh, E. C., and Roe, C. A. (2013). “Say from when you owe this strange intelligence”: Investigating explanatory systems of Spiritualist mental mediumship using interpretative phenomenological analysis. International Journal of Transpersonal Studies, 32, 27–42. Sabom, M. B. (1982). Recollections of death: A medical investigation. New York: Harper & Row. Schlitz, M., and Honorton, C. (1992). Ganzfeld psi performance within an artistically gifted population. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 86, 83–98. Schmeidler, G. R., and Maher, M. (1981). Judges’ responses to the nonverbal behavior of psi-conducive and psi-inhibitory experimenters. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 75, 241–257. Schmidt, H. (1978). Can an effect precede its cause? A model of a noncausal world. Foundations of Physics, 8, 463–480. Schmidt, H., Morris, R. L., and Rudolph, L. (1986). Channeling evidence for a PK effect to independent observers. Journal of Parapsychology, 50, 1– 15. Schmidt, S. (2012). Can we help just by good intentions? A meta-analysis of experiments on distant intention effects. Journal of Alternative and Complementary Medicine, 18, 529–533. Schmidt, S., and Walach, H. (2000). Electrodermal activity (EDA)—Stateof-the art measurement and techniques for parapsychological purposes. Journal of Parapsychology, 64, 139–163. Schmied-Knittel, I., and Schetsche, M. (2005). Every-day miracles: Results of a representative survey in Germany. European Journal of Parapsychology 20, 3–21. Schouten, S. A. (1979). Analysis of spontaneous cases as reported in “Phantasms of the Living.” European Journal of Parapsychology, 2, 408– 455. Schouten, S. A. (1981). Analysing spontaneous cases: A replication based on the Sannwald collection. European Journal of Parapsychology, 4, 9–48. Schouten, S. A. (1982). Analysing spontaneous cases: A replication based on the Rhine collection. European Journal of Parapsychology, 4, 113–158. Schouten, S. A. (1993). Are we making progress? In L. Coly and J. McMahon (Eds.), Psi research methodology: A re-examination (pp. 295– 322). New York: Parapsychology Foundation. Schouten, S. A., and Stevenson, I. (1998). Does the socio-psychological hypothesis explain cases of the reincarnation type? Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, 186, 504–506. Schriever, F. (1987). A 30-year “experiment with time”: Evaluation of an individual case study of precognitive dreams. European Journal of Parapsychology, 7, 49–72. Schwartz, S. A., and Dossey, L. (2010). Nonlocality, intention, and observer effects in healing studies: Laying a foundation for the future. Explore: The Journal of Science and Healing, 6, 295–307. Schwebel, S. J. (2004). Apparitions, healings, and weeping Madonnas: Christianity and the paranormal. Mahwah, NJ: Paulist Press. Servadio, E. (1978). Un caso di ESP durante l’analisi [An ESP case during analysis]. Metapsichica, 33, 134–135. Sheldrake, R., and Morgana, A. (2003). Testing a language-using parrot for telepathy. Journal of Scientific Exploration, 17, 601–616. Sheldrake, R., and Smart, P. (1998). A dog that seems to know when his owner is returning: Preliminary investigations. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 62, 220–232. Sherwood, S. J. (2000). Black Dog apparitions. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 94, 151–164. Sherwood, S. J., Dalton, K., Steinkamp, F., and Watt, C. (2000). Dream clairvoyance study II. Using dynamic video-clips: Investigation of consensus voting judging procedures and target emotionality. Dreaming, 10, 221–236. Simmonds-Moore, C. (2009–2010). Sleep patterns, personality, and subjective anomalous experiences. Imagination, Cognition, and Personality, 29, 71–86. Spottiswoode, S. J. P. (1997). Geomagnetic fluctuations and free-response anomalous cognition: A new understanding. Journal of Parapsychology, 61, 3–12. Sommer, A. (2012). Psychical research and the origins of American psychology: Hugo Münsterberg, William James and Eusapia Palladino. History of the Human Sciences, 25, 23–44. Stanford, R. G. (1982). Is scientific parapsychology possible? Some thoughts on James E. Alcock’s Parapsychology: Science or magic? Journal of Parapsychology, 46, 231–271. Stanford, R. G. (1990). An experimentally testable model for spontaneous psi events: A review of related evidence and concepts from parapsychology and other sciences. In S. Krippner (Ed.), Advances in parapsychological research 6 (pp. 54–167). Jefferson, NC: McFarland. Steinkamp, F. (Ed.). (2002). Parapsychology, philosophy and the mind: Essays honoring John Beloff. Jefferson, NC: McFarland. Stevenson, I. (1977). Research into the evidence of man’s survival after death: A historical and critical survey with a summary of recent developments. Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, 165, 152–170. Stevenson, I. (1981). Can we describe the mind? In W. G. Roll, J. Beloff, and J. McAllister (Eds.), Research in parapsychology 1980 (pp. 130–142). Metuchen, NJ: Scarecrow Press Stevenson, I. (1983). Cryptomnesia and parapsychology. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 52, 1–30. Stevenson, I. (1984). Unlearned language: New studies in xenoglossy. Charlottesville: University Press of Virginia. Stevenson, I. (1992). A series of possibly paranormal recurrent dreams. Journal of Scientific Exploration, 6, 281–289. Stevenson I. (1997). Reincarnation and biology: A contribution to the etiology of birthmarks and birth defects (2 vols.). Westport, CT: Praeger. Stevenson I. (2003). European cases of the reincarnation type. Jefferson, NC: McFarland. Storm, L. (2009). Review of The outline of parapsychology. Journal of Parapsychology, 73, 195–200. Storm, L., Tressoldi, P. E., and Di Risio, L. (2010). Meta-analysis of freeresponse studies, 1992–2008: Assessing the noise reduction model in parapsychology. Psychological Bulletin, 136, 471–485. Storm, L., Tressoldi, P. E., and Di Risio, L. (2012). Meta-analysis of ESP studies, 1987–2010: Assessing the success of the forced-choice design in parapsychology. Journal of Parapsychology, 76, 243–274. Tart, C. T. (2009). The end of materialism: How evidence of the paranormal is bringing science and spirit together. Oakland, CA: New Harbinger Publications. Thalbourne, M. A. (2004). The common thread between ESP and PK. New York: Parapsychology Foundation. Tressoldi, P. E., Martinelli, M, Semenzato, L., and Cappato, S. (2011). Let your eyes predict: Prediction accuracy of pupillary responses to random alerting and neutral sounds. Sage Open. doi:10.1177/2158244011420451. Truzzi, M. (1991). Reflections on the reception of unconventional claims in science. (Reported by S. Solovey.) Frontier Perspectives, 1, 12–15, 25. Tucker, J. B. (2008). Ian Stevenson and cases of the reincarnation type. Journal of Scientific Exploration, 22, 36–43. Tucker, J. B., and Keil, H. H. J. (2013). Experimental birthmarks: New cases of an Asian practice. Journal of Scientific Exploration, 27, 269–282. Turner, E. (2006). Advances in the study of spirit experience: Drawing together many threads. Anthropology of Consciousness, 17(2), 33–61. Ullman, M. (1980). Parapsychology. In H. Kaplan, A. M. Freedman, and B. J. Sadock (Eds.), Comprehensive textbook of psychiatry (Vol. 3, 3rd ed., pp. 3235–3245). Baltimore, MD: Williams & Wilkins. Utts, J. (1991). Replication and meta-analysis in parapsychology. Statistical Science, 6, 363–403. Van Lommel, P. (2013). Nonlocal consciousness: A concept based on scientific research on near-death experiences during cardiac arrest. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 20, 7–48. Van Lommel, P., van Wees, R., Meyers, V., and Elfferich, I. (2001). Neardeath experience in survivors of cardiac arrest: A prospective study in the Netherlands. Lancet, 358, 2039–2045. Varvoglis, M. (1990–1991). Anglo-Saxon vs. Latin parapsychology: Behind the communication barrier. European Journal of Parapsychology, 8, 41–50. Varvoglis, M., and Evrard, R. (2010). Institut Métapsychique International. Mindfield, 2(3), 10–11. Virtanen, L. (1990). That must have been ESP! An examination of psychic experiences. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. Wagenmakers, E. J., Wetzels, R., Borsboom, D., and Van der Maas, H. (2011). Why psychologists must change the way they analyze their data: The case of psi: Comment on Bem (2011). Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 100, 426–432. Walker, E. H. (1975). Foundations of paraphysical and parapsychological phenomena. In L. Oteri (Ed.), Quantum physics and parapsychology (pp. 1– 44). New York: Parapsychology Foundation. Walker, E. H. (2000). The physics of consciousness. Cambridge, MA: Perseus Books. Watt, C. (2005). Parapsychology’s contribution to psychology: A view from the front line. Journal of Parapsychology, 69, 215–232. Watt, C. A., and Morris, R. L. (1995). The relationships among performance on a prototype indicator of perceptual defence/vigilance, personality, and extrasensory perception. Personality and Individual Differences, 19, 635–648. White, R. A. (1982). An analysis of ESP phenomena in the saints. Parapsychology Review, 13(1), 15–18. White, R. A. (1990a). An experience-centered approach to parapsychology. Exceptional Human Experience, 8, 7–36. White, R.A. (1990b). New views of parapsychology and parapsychological phenomena. In R. A. White (Ed.), Parapsychology: New sources of information, 1973–1989 (pp. 492–550). Metuchen, NJ: Scarecrow Press. Williams, B. J. (2011). Revisiting the ganzfeld ESP debate: A basic review and assessment. Journal of Scientific Exploration, 25, 639–661. Winkelman, M. (1982). Magic: A theoretical reassessment. Current Anthropology, 23, 37–44. Wiseman, R., Smith, M., and Kornbrot, D. (1994). Assessing possible sender-to-experimenter acoustic leakage in the PRL Autoganzfeld. In D. J. Bierman (Ed.), Proceedings of the 37th Parapsychological Association Convention (pp. 439–454). Wolf-Braun, B. (1998). Zur Rezeptionsgeschichte der Parapsychologie im Rahmen der akademischen Psychologie: Die Stellungnahmen von Wilhelm Wundt (1832–1920) und Hugo Münsterberg (1863–1916) [On the reception history of parapsychology in the context of academic psychology: The views of Wilhelm Wundt (1832–1920) and Hugo Münsterberg (1863– 1916)]. In J. Jahnke, J. Fahrenberg, R. Stegie, and E. Bauer (Eds.), Psychologiegeschichte: Beziehungen zur Philosophie und Grenzgebieten (pp. 405–419). München, Germany: Profil. Wolffram, H. (2009). The stepchildren of science: Psychical research and parapsychology in Germany, c. 1870–1939. Amsterdam, Netherlands: Rodopi. Wolman, B. B. (Ed.). (1977). Handbook of parapsychology. Orig. pub. Van Nostrand Reinhold; repr. 1986, Jefferson, NC: McFarland. Wooffitt, R. (2006). The language of mediums and psychics: The social organization of everyday miracles. Aldershot, UK: Ashgate. Zangari, W. (2007). Experiências anômalas em médiuns de Umbanda: Uma avaliação fenomenológica e ontológica [Anomalous experiences of Umbanda mediums: A phenomenological and ontological evaluation]. Boletim Academia Paulista de Psicologia, 27, 67–86. Zangari, W. (2011, August). Psi research in Brazil: The new horizons. Paper presented at the 54th Annual Convention of the Parapsychological Association, Curitiba, Brazil. Zingrone, N. L. (1988). Authorship and gender in American parapsychological journals. Journal of Parapsychology, 52, 321–343. Zingrone, N. L. (2002). Controversy and the problems of parapsychology. Journal of Parapsychology, 66, 3–30. Zingrone, N. L. (2006). Complicating the conversation: Rhetoric, substance, and controversy in parapsychology. Journal of Parapsychology, 69, 3–21. Zingrone, N. L. (2010). From text to self: The interplay of criticism and response in the history of parapsychology. Saarbrücken, Germany: Lambert. Zingrone, N. L. (2011). Petition to submit a proposal for a Masters of Arts in parapsychology. Unpublished document. Virginia Beach, VA: Atlantic University. Zingrone, N. L. (n.d.). Failing to go the distance: On critics and parapsychology. Retrieved from: http://www.skepticalinvestigations.org/Examskeptics/Zingrone_critics.html. Zingrone, N. L., Alvarado, C. S., and Agee, N. (2009). Psychological correlates of aura vision: Psychic experiences, dissociation, absorption, and synaesthesia-like experiences. Australian Journal of Clinical and Experimental Hypnosis, 37, 131–168. Zusne, L., and Jones, W. H. (1989). Anomalistic psychology: A study of magical thinking (2nd ed.). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum. OceanofPDF.com CHAPTER 2 Parapsychology in Context The Big Picture1 EDWARD F. KELLY Our point of departure is the currently prevailing scientific conception of the brain/mind relation. Most contemporary psychologists, neuroscientists, and philosophers of mind subscribe—explicitly or implicitly—to some version of ontological physicalism, the modern philosophical descendant of the materialism of previous centuries. Physicalist conceptions of human mind and personality vary significantly in nuance and detail but are fundamentally alike insofar as they conflict sharply with traditional and common-sense notions and run instead along roughly the following lines: All facts are determined by physical facts. Thus we human beings are in the end nothing but extremely complicated biological machines and everything we are and do is explainable, at least in principle, in terms of local interactions among self-existent bits of matter moving in accordance with mathematical laws under the influence of fields of force. Some of what we know, and the substrate of our general capacities to learn more, are built in genetically as complex resultants of biological evolution. Everything else comes to us directly or indirectly by way of our sensory surfaces, through energy exchanges with the environment of types already largely understood. All aspects of mind and consciousness are generated by, or supervenient upon, or in some mysterious way identical with, neurophysiological processes occurring in the brain. Mental causation, free will, and the self are mere illusions, by-products of the grinding of our neural machinery. And of course since mind and personality are entirely products of our bodily machinery, they are necessarily extinguished, totally and finally, by the demise and dissolution of the body. Views of this sort hold sway over a great majority of contemporary scientists, and mass-media science reporters routinely pass them along without question or hesitation to the public at large. They seem to most observers to be supported by mountains of evidence. Nevertheless, I submit that such pictures are not only seriously incomplete—which few if any would deny—but at a number of critical points demonstrably incorrect. My reasons for believing this are spelled out in detail in Irreducible Mind (Kelly, Kelly, Crabtree, Gauld, Grosso, & Greyson, 2007, henceforth IM), which builds upon Human Personality and Its Survival of Bodily Death, the extraordinary magnum opus of F. W. H. Myers (1903) to assemble in one place many lines of empirical evidence and argument demonstrating the inadequacy of contemporary physicalism. Myers, one of the founders in 1882 of the Society for Psychical Research, had systematically collected evidence of human capacities that resist understanding in conventional materialist terms, and on that basis he advanced an expanded model of mind and consciousness that was greatly admired by many leading contemporaries including William James. James himself had also gone on to apply this model explicitly to his later work on religious experience and metaphysics. Our original plan for IM was to take advantage of the centennial of Myers’s landmark contribution by revisiting and re-evaluating it in the context of the subsequent century of relevant psychological and neurobiological research. This proved to be a mammoth project—far larger than we imagined at the outset—and we missed our target date by almost four years. The resulting book is over 800 pages in length, and its initial hardback version also included on CD a complete digital copy of Myers’s Human Personality itself (1400 pages in two volumes) plus its five most significant contemporary reviews. Parenthetically, IM has subsequently been released in paperback without the CD, but all of that supplementary material and several other relevant scholarly resources are now freely available on the website of Esalen Institute’s Center for Theory and Research (http://esalenctr.org). I believe IM accomplished its central objective of demonstrating empirically the inadequacy of conventional mainstream physicalist conceptions of the brain/mind connection. Not everybody has sufficient time or interest, of course, to work through that mountain of material in detail, and I will therefore summarize here in condensed outline form its central arguments. I will do this under ten major headings representing the main types of empirical phenomena we regard as difficult or impossible to explain in conventional physicalist terms. More detailed presentations and discussions of relevant evidence, and abundant supporting references, can be found in IM itself, which provides the real authority for most of the views expressed here. 1. Psi phenomena. The basic phenomena in question here involve, by definition, correlations occurring across physical barriers that should be sufficient, on presently accepted physicalist principles, to prevent their formation (“basic limiting principles” as formulated by Broad, 1962, and refined by Braude, 2002). In the context of this volume (and its predecessor) I can therefore simply appropriate in service of my central thesis the entire body of evidence that has been adduced in the course of well over a century of competent scientific effort by workers in psychical research and its narrower modern descendant, experimental parapsychology. In my opinion, the existing large volume of peer-reviewed research involving experimental, quasi-experimental, and case studies of various kinds has produced cumulative results sufficient to demonstrate beyond reasonable doubt—at least to open-minded persons who take the trouble to study it—that the sheer existence of the basic input/output phenomena is a fact of nature with which we must somehow come to scientific terms (Radin, 2006; Tart, 2009). Indeed, I predict with high confidence that future generations of historians, sociologists, and philosophers of science will make a good living trying to understand why it has taken so long for scientists in general to accept this conclusion. All psi phenomena are theoretically important by virtue of providing examples of human behavioral capacities that appear impossible to account for in terms of presently recognized psychological, biological, or classicalphysics principles. Even more important for theoretical purposes, however, is the large further body of evidence suggestive of post-mortem survival, the persistence of elements of mind and personality following bodily death. It is simply false to declare, as does physicalist philosopher Paul Churchland (1988, p. 10), that we possess no such evidence. We in fact possess a great deal of such evidence, much of it of very high quality. The historically most important lines of such investigation, including studies of trance mediumship, cases of the reincarnation type, and crisis apparitions, are covered in Part 7 of this volume. This work unfortunately is practically unknown outside the small circle of persons professionally involved with it. Ironically, the primary threat to its survivalist interpretation arises not from considerations of evidential quality —problems of fraud, credulity, errors of observation, or memory and the like—but from the difficulty of excluding alternative explanations based upon psi-type interactions involving only living persons (the survival vs. super-psi debate). Either horn of this interpretive dilemma—survival or psi—seriously threatens the prevailing physicalist brain/mind orthodoxy, and this undoubtedly helps explain the hostility of its dogmatic defenders to both. It should also be evident that compelling evidence for post-mortem survival, an element of belief common to all of the world’s great religious traditions, would demonstrate clearly the inadequacy of present-day mainstream physicalism. In my judgment we are at or very close to that point—close enough, certainly, to justify rational belief in the possibility if not indeed the likelihood of one’s own personal survival. Evidence for the occurrence of psi phenomena in general and post-mortem survival in particular played an important though largely tacit role in the overall argument of IM, and my efforts here will be rewarded if they lead scientifically-minded readers to take these subjects more seriously than they otherwise might. It is crucial to recognize, however, that psi cannot be isolated and quarantined as though it were the only serious threat to contemporary physicalism. The many other kinds of evidence surveyed in following sections point in the same general direction. 2. Extreme psychophysiological influence. Under this heading are a variety of phenomena especially suggestive of direct mental agency in the production of physiological or even physical effects (for a comprehensive review see IM Chapter 3). Placebo effects and related kinds of psychosomatic phenomena, to begin with, have long been informally recognized and are now widely accepted, but they were accepted by modern biomedical science only grudgingly, as new mechanisms of brain-body interaction came to light that seemed potentially capable of explaining them. In particular, psychoneuroimmunology has demonstrated the existence, previously unknown, of interactions between the central nervous and immune systems. Nevertheless, the adequacy of such explanations even for some kinds of placebo effects remains in question, and there are many kindred phenomena that pose progressively greater challenges to explanation in such terms. The following examples will serve to capture their flavor. Both Sigmund Freud and F. W. H. Myers were impressed by “glove anesthesias,” in which a patient loses sensation from the skin of a hand in the absence of identifiable organic lesion. In such cases the anesthetic skin region typically corresponds only to a psychological entity, the patient’s idea, in complete disregard of the underlying anatomical organization. At the same time, curiously, something in the patient remains aware of the afflicted region and protects it from injury. Related phenomena have often been reported in the context of hypnosis. Highly suggestible persons who can vividly imagine undergoing an injurious circumstance such as receiving a burn to the skin sometimes suffer physiological effects closely analogous to those that the physical injury itself would produce, such as a blister. More rarely, the correspondence between the hypnotic blister and its imagined source extends even to minute details of geometric shape, details too specific to account for in terms of known mechanisms of brain/body interaction. Similarly dramatic phenomena have occasionally been documented in psychiatric patients in connection with exceptionally vivid recall of prior physical trauma (see IM pp. 156–158). A closely related and well-documented phenomenon is that of stigmata, in which fervently devout or pious believers in Christ develop wounds analogous to those inflicted during his crucifixion. The injuries are again localized and specific in form, vary in locus and character in accordance with the individuals’ differing conceptions of Christ’s own injuries, and appear and disappear, often suddenly and regularly, also in accordance with their expectations. The conventional hope, of course, is that even the most extreme phenomena of the sorts just mentioned will ultimately prove explainable in terms of physiological processes alone. Continuing allegiance to this hope, despite the indicated explanatory difficulties, is undoubtedly encouraged by the fact that the phenomena described so far all involve the effects of a person’s mental states on that person’s own body. Still more drastic explanatory challenges are posed, however, by phenomena in which one person’s mental state seems to have directly influenced another person’s body. These include “maternal impressions” (unusual birthmarks or birth defects on a newborn that correspond to an unusual and intense experience of the mother during the pregnancy), distant healing (including studies of effects of prayer on healing), experimental studies of distant mental interaction on living systems [chapter 18, this volume], and cases in which a child who claims to have memories of the life of a deceased person also displays unusual birthmarks or birth defects corresponding closely with marks (usually fatal wounds) on the body of that person (Stevenson, 1997) [chapter 24, this volume]. In addition, there has been a considerable accumulation of spontaneous cases and experimental evidence demonstrating the reality of psychokinesis (PK), which by definition involves direct mental influence on the physical environment [chapters 19 and 20, this volume]. 3. Informational capacity, precision, and depth. A number of welldocumented psychological phenomena involve levels of detail, precision, or logical depth that are difficult to reconcile with what can be achieved by a brain that must operate in statistical fashion with neural components of low intrinsic precision and reliability. Here are some examples: The first involves a case of “automatic writing” observed by William James (1889). The subject wrote with his extended right arm on large sheets of paper, his face meanwhile buried in the crook of his left elbow. For him to see what he was doing was “a physical impossibility.” Nevertheless, James continues: “Two or three times in my presence on one evening, after covering a sheet with writing (the pencil never being raised, so that the words ran into each other), he returned to the top of the sheet and proceeded downwards, dotting each i and crossing each t with absolute precision and great rapidity.” This remarkable episode illustrates two features that have often appeared together in the large but neglected scientific literature dealing with automatic writing (Stevenson, 1978): The person is in an altered state of consciousness and the motor performance, itself remarkable, is apparently guided by an extremely detailed memory record, an essentially photographic representation of the uncompleted page. The latter property relates to the phenomenon of eidetic imagery, the most dramatic demonstration of which has been provided by Charles Stromeyer using Julesz stereograms (Stromeyer, 1970; Stromeyer & Psotka, 1970). These are essentially pairs of computer-generated pictures, each of which by itself looks like a matrix of randomly placed dots, but constructed in such a way that when viewed simultaneously (by presentation to the two eyes separately) a visual form emerges in depth. Stromeyer presented pictures of this type to the eyes of a gifted female eidetiker, at different times, ultimately as much as 3 days apart. Under these conditions, she could extract the hidden form only if she could somehow fuse current input to one eye with an extremely detailed memory-image of previous input to the other eye. Remarkably, she was able to succeed under a wide variety of increasingly demanding conditions: The original stereograms, for example, were 100 × 100 arrays, but she eventually succeeded under double-masked conditions with arrays as large as 1000 × 1000, or a million “bits,” viewed up to 4 hours apart. These results were understandably shocking to many psychologists, who sought to escape their force by pointing to the dependence on a single participant and the absence of replications. At least one successful replication has subsequently occurred. Crawford, Wallace, Nomura, and Slater (1986) demonstrated that their highly hypnotizable subjects were able to succeed with small stereograms, but only when hypnotized. The literature already contains many additional examples of prodigious memory. Stromeyer and Psotka themselves mention the famous mnemonist studied by Luria (1968) and the case of the “Shass Pollaks,” who memorized all 12 volumes of the Babylonian Talmud, and Oliver Sacks (1987, Chapter 22) has reported a similar case of a person who, among other things, knew by heart all 9 volumes and 6000 pages of Grove’s Dictionary of Music and Musicians. Other examples could easily be cited. Prodigious memory of this sort is a real psychological phenomenon. Third in this group is the family of “calculating prodigies.” Of special interest is the “savant syndrome,” often associated with autistic disorders, in which islands of spectacular ability appear in the midst of generalized mental disability (Treffert, 2010). The abilities are of many types but almost invariably involve prodigious memory. The depth of the problems they pose for brain theory is exemplified by the case of “The Twins,” also described by Sacks (1987). These profoundly impaired individuals, unable to perform even single-digit additions and subtractions with any accuracy, nonetheless proved able to generate and test prime numbers “in their heads.” Sacks was able to verify the primacy up to 10 digits, but only by means of published tables, while the twins themselves went on exchanging numbers of steadily greater length, eventually reaching 20 digits. Sacks makes the intriguing suggestion that they cannot literally be calculating these enormous numbers, but may instead be discovering them by navigating through some vast inner imaginal landscape in which the relevant numerical relations are somehow represented pictorially. The twins themselves cannot say how they do it. Phenomena of these sorts seem hard to explain in terms of brain processes. The most serious attempt to do so known to me (Snyder & Mitchell, 1999) is in fact devoid of specific neural mechanisms. Its central argument is rather that early-stage brain processes like those subserving visual perception, for example, must also be savant-like in terms of their speed, precision, and informational capacity. What is unusual about savants, therefore, might consist merely in their access to these mechanisms. This “explanation” of course presupposes a positive answer to the fundamental question at issue, whether the brain alone can accomplish any of these things including ordinary perceptual synthesis itself, and in a later section I will explain my doubts about that. As proved long ago by mathematician John von Neumann, the only practical way to get increased arithmetical precision out of individually unreliable computing elements is to use more of them. This biocomputational perspective clearly implies that calculating prodigies must use large portions of their brains in very abnormal ways to achieve the observed effects, but the few neuroimaging studies currently available provide little if any support for that expectation (Corrigan, Richards, Treffert, & Dager, 2012; Treffert, 2010). Furthermore, although the cognitive deficits that typically accompany autistic-savant skills could conceivably reflect such substitutions, we must remember that comparable skills have sometimes occurred in geniuses such as the mathematicians Gauss, Ampére, and Ramanujan, as well as von Neumann himself. 4. Memory. The previous section focused on phenomena such as highprecision calculations and prodigious memory that appear incompatible with the physical properties of the brain considered as a kind of computing device. Problems also arise, however, in regard to memory in its more familiar and everyday forms. Memory is increasingly recognized as central to all human cognitive and perceptual functions, yet we remain largely ignorant of where and in what forms our past experience is stored and by what means it is brought to bear upon the present. Generations of psychologists and neurobiologists have taken it as axiomatic that all memories must exist in the form of “traces,” physical changes produced in the brain by experience and carried forward more or less reliably in time, but there has been little real progress toward scientific consensus on the details of these mechanisms despite many decades of intensive research. Significant progress has been made, to be sure, in regard to “learning” and “memory” in simple creatures such as the sea-slug, and more generally in regard to what might be called “habit memory” (Bergson, 1908/1991), the automatic adjustments of organisms to their environments. But these discoveries fall far short of providing satisfactory explanations of the most central and important characteristics of the human memory system, including in particular our supplies of general knowledge (semantic memory) and our ability to recall voluntarily and explicitly our own past experience (autobiographical or episodic memory). Furthermore, recent functional neuroimaging studies, although generating vast amounts of data, have yielded little if any progress toward a comprehensive and coherent account of memory based on trace theory. Meanwhile, deep conceptual problems have been identified in trace theory itself (Braude, 2002; Bursen, 1978; IM Chapter 4). For example, autobiographical memory clearly involves something more than mere revival of traces of past experiences, something that allows us to interpret what we experience now as a representation of our own past rather than a contemporary perception, dream, or hallucination. Traces as such, that is, provide only memory-aids rather than memories per se, and it has proven extremely difficult to specify in conventional physicalist terms what that extra something is, without falling into regressive forms of explanation that presuppose and hence cannot explain the phenomenon of memory itself. Similarly, the content of a concept or semantic memory typically transcends any finite set of experienced circumstances that can plausibly be imagined as having deposited corresponding “traces” in a form capable of explaining its future deployment in an unlimited variety of novel but appropriate contexts, including metaphorical contexts. Most challenging of all to current mainstream views is the large body of evidence suggesting that autobiographical, semantic, and procedural (skill) memories sometimes survive bodily death. If this is the case, memory in living persons presumably exists at least in part outside the brain and body as conventionally understood. These conceptual problems regarding trace theories of memory have deep connections with issues raised in Section 9 below, and as shown in Chapter 4 of IM, similar issues arise in relation to allied components of current cognitive theory such as “information” and “representation.” 5. Psychological automatisms and secondary centers of consciousness. Phenomena catalogued under this heading involve what looks like multiple concurrent engagement, in potentially incompatible ways, of major cognitive skills (linguistic skills, for example) and the corresponding brain systems. I will next explain in more detail what this means and provide relevant examples. Current cognitive neuroscience pictures the mind or “cognitive system” as a hierarchically ordered network of subprocessors or “modules,” each specialized for some particular task and corresponding (it is hoped) to some particular brain region or regions. Leaving aside major issues regarding the details of its specification, this picture seems broadly consistent with the overall manner in which our minds seem ordinarily to operate. Our basic way of consciously doing things is essentially one at a time in serial fashion. Although psychologists recognize that with suitable training people can do more things simultaneously than they customarily suppose, this generalization applies mainly to relatively divergent things, and conspicuously fails as the simultaneous tasks become more complex and more similar. Nevertheless, a large body of credible evidence, some dating back to the late 19th century, demonstrates that additional “cognitive systems,” dissociated psychological entities indistinguishable from full-fledged conscious minds or personalities as we normally understand these terms, can sometimes occupy the same organism—not in alternation, moreover, but concurrently—carrying on their varied existences as it were in parallel and largely outside the awareness of the primary, everyday consciousness. In essence, the structure that cognitive neuroscience conventionally pictures as unitary, as instantiated within and identified with a particular organization of brain systems, can be functionally divided—divided, moreover, not “side-to-side,” leading to isolation of the normal cognitive capacities from each other, but “top-to-bottom,” leading to the appearance of what seem to be two or more complete cognitive systems each of which includes all of the relevant capacities. Emergent “multiple” or “alter” personalities also can differ widely, not only in demeanor and knowledge but even in regard to deep involuntary physiological characteristics such as visual defects and susceptibilities to allergies. Secondary personalities are also sometimes markedly superior to the primary personality in knowledge, skills, and creativity, as in the cases of Victor Race, “Hélène Smith,” and Patience Worth described in IM (pp. 447–450). More challenging still, it sometimes happens that one of these personalities has direct access to the conscious experience of one or more others, but not vice-versa (Braude, 1995; IM Chapter 5). Two brief examples drawn from an enormous literature will help convey a more concrete sense of the character of these phenomena. The first comes from a report by Oxford philosopher F. C. S. Schiller on automatic writing produced by his brother (Myers, 1903, Vol. 2, pp. 418–422). As is characteristic of this genre of automatisms, the writer was typically unaware of the content of his writing, which went on continuously while he was fully and consciously engaged in some other activity such as reading a book or telling a story. Of particular relevance here, however, were occasions on which he wrote simultaneously with both hands and on completely different subjects, one or the other of these streams of writing also sometimes taking mirror-image form. Second is the case of Anna Winsor, described by William James (1889) in his report on automatic writing. This case was protracted and bizarre, and only superficially resembles the neurological “alien hand” syndrome. Its central feature is that the patient, Anna, at a certain point lost voluntary control of her right arm, which was taken over by a distinctive secondary personality. This personality, whom Anna herself named “Old Stump,” was benign, often protecting Anna from her pronounced tendencies toward selfinjury. As in the case of Schiller’s brother, Stump typically wrote or drew while Anna was occupied with other matters. But Stump also continued writing and drawing even when Anna was asleep, and sometimes in total darkness. This secondary personality also remained calm and rational during periods when Anna was feverish and delusional, and it manifested knowledge and skills—such as knowledge of Latin—which Anna herself did not possess. 6. The unity of conscious experience. Under this heading I will briefly address two interrelated problems. The first and narrower is the so-called “binding” problem, which emerged as a consequence of the success of contemporary neuroscientists in analyzing sensory mechanisms, particularly in the visual system. It turns out that different properties of a visual object such as its form, color, and motion in depth are handled individually by largely separate regions or mechanisms within the brain. But once the stimulus has been thus dismembered, so to speak, how does it get back together again as a unit of visual experience? Only one thing is certain: The unification of experience is not achieved anatomically. There are no privileged places or structures in the brain where everything comes together, either for the visual system itself or for the sensory systems altogether. Some early theorists such as James and McDougall had argued that the evident disparity between the multiplicity of physiological processes in the brain and the felt unity of conscious experience could only be resolved in materialist terms by anatomical convergence, and since there is no such convergence, materialism must be false. This argument, although ingenious, relied upon the faulty premise that the only possible physical means of unification must be anatomical in nature. All current neurophysiological proposals for solving the binding problem are instead functional in nature: The essential concept common to all of them is that oscillatory electrical activity in widely distributed neural populations can be rapidly and reversibly synchronized, particularly in the gamma band of EEG frequencies (roughly 30–80 Hz), thereby providing a possible mechanistic solution. A great deal of sophisticated experimental and theoretical work over the past 30 years has demonstrated that such mechanisms do in fact exist in the nervous system and that they are active in conjunction with normal perceptual synthesis. Indeed, contemporary physicalism has crystallized neurophysiologically in the form of a family of “global neuronal workspace” theories, all of which make the central claim that conscious experience occurs specifically—and only—in conjunction with large-scale patterns of oscillatory neuroelectric activity capable of linking widelyseparated areas of the brain at frequencies extending into the gamma band (e.g., Crick, 1994; Dehaene & Naccache, 2001; Edelman, Gally, & Baars, 2011; Engel, Fries, & Singer, 2001; Laureys & Tononi, 2009; Singer, 2007; Varela, Lachaux, Rodriguez, & Martinerie, 2001). The neurophysiological global workspace, however, cannot be the whole story, because a large body of recent research on “near-death experiences” (NDEs) demonstrates that elaborate, vivid, and life-transforming conscious experience sometimes occurs under extreme physiological conditions— including conditions such as deep general anesthesia, cardiac arrest, and coma—that preclude normal workspace operation (cf. Laureys & Tononi, 2009). Moreover, the more extreme transformations of consciousness associated with NDEs extend deep into the mystical realm, sometimes include veridical psi elements, and more commonly occur when the individuals are in fact physiologically closer to death (see IM Chapter 6; Alexander, 2012; Holden, Greyson, & James, 2009; Owens, Cook [Kelly], & Stevenson, 1990; Van Lommel, 2010, 2013). In short, it appears that McDougall and James were right after all, albeit for the wrong reason. In effect, I believe, recent progress in biomedical science has provided new means for falsification of mainstream physicalist theories of the brain/mind relation. We can expect to see many more such cases as our technical capacity to retrieve human beings from the borderlands of death continues to improve (Parnia, 2013). Availability of this emerging evidence emboldens me to make some further and more contentious remarks regarding the larger problem of ordinary perceptual synthesis, and the direction in which things seem to me to be moving. It is an historical fact that mainstream psychology has always tended on the whole to try to solve its problems in minimalist fashion and with as little reference as possible to what all of us experience every day as central features of our conscious mental life. The early workers in mechanical translation, for example, imagined that they could do a decent job simply by constructing a large dictionary that would enable substitution of words in one language for words in the other. This approach failed miserably, and we were slowly driven, failed step by failed step, to the recognition that truly adequate translation presupposes understanding, or in short a full command of the capacities underlying the human use of language. A similar evolution is underway in perceptual theory. Following the lead of Marr (1982), most work to date has taken a strongly “bottom-up” approach, which views perceptual synthesis as a kind of exhaustive calculation from the totality of input currently present at our sensory surfaces. Machine vision and robotics, for example, necessarily took this approach, and even in neuroscience it seemed to make sense to start with the most accessible parts of the perceptual systems—the end organs and their peripheral connections—and work our way inward. The great sensory systems themselves—vision, audition, somatosensation, and so on—were also presumed to operate more or less independently and were in fact typically studied in isolation. A separate tradition dating back at least to Kant and the early Gestalt theorists, and carried forward into the modern era by psychologists such as Ulric Neisser and Jerome Bruner, has been sensitive to the presence of “topdown” influences, both within and between sensory modalities. Although a few perceptual subsystems (such as those that engender incorrigible visual illusions) may be truly autonomous or “cognitively impenetrable,” these seem to be isolated and special cases. A very different overall picture of perceptual synthesis is currently emerging in which top-down influences predominate. On this view perceptual synthesis is achieved not from the input, but with its aid. This is necessarily the case for example in regard to ambiguous figures such as the Necker cube, where the stimulus information itself is insufficient to determine a uniquely “correct” interpretation. More generally, we routinely ignore information that is present in the input and supply information that is not, speed-reading providing a characteristic example. Note here too that phenomena such as externalized eidetic images and especially crisis apparitions (Tyrrell, 1953) sometimes partly or wholly override current stimulus input. Something within us, a sort of cosmogenic, world-generating, or virtual-reality system, is continuously updating and projecting an overall model of the perceptual environment and our position within it, guided by very selective samplings of the available information (Simons & Chabris, 1999; Tart, 1993). As in the case of understanding spoken or written language, an enormous amount of general knowledge is constantly mobilized in service of this projective activity, which freely but selectively samples the information potentially available to it. Top-down and cross-modal sensory interactions have recently been recognized as the rule rather than the exception in perception, and neuroscientist Rodolfo Llinás and his co-workers have even advanced the view, which I believe is profoundly correct, that dreaming, far from being an odd and incidental part of our mental life, also reflects the workings of this projective activity. Ordinary perceptual synthesis, on this inverted view of things, amounts to oneiric (dreamlike) activity constrained by sensory input (Llinás & Ribary, 1994). Psychoanalyst Ernest Hartmann (1975) has proposed similar ideas in regard to hallucinatory activity more generally, dreaming included: On his view such activity is again a ubiquitous and fundamental feature of our mental life and the critical question is not “why do we sometimes hallucinate?” but rather “what keeps us from hallucinating most of the time?” The answer, he suggests, lies in inhibitory influences exerted by the brain activity that accompanies ongoing perceptual and cognitive functions of the ordinary waking sorts. Similar arguments for the primacy and importance of this sort of cosmogenic imaginative capacity have been advanced by persons as diverse as Brann (1991), Corbin (1997), and Globus (1987). So far so good, but where exactly is the “top,” the ultimate source of this top-down projective activity? The mainstream scientists who have already recognized its existence invariably presume that it arises entirely within the brain itself, in accordance with conventional production models of the brain/mind relation. However, evidence such as that of near-death experiences occurring under extreme physiological conditions, and the more direct evidence of post-mortem survival, indicates that it actually originates outside the brain as conventionally understood, in accordance with the alternative Myers/James “permission” or “filter” model advanced in IM. 7. Genius-level creativity. Any scientific theory of mind and personality truly worthy of the name surely must help us to understand this humanly vital topic, but by this standard we have so far made distressingly little progress. The main reason for this failure, in my opinion, is that for the most part we have tried to understand the exceptional—real genius, in its fullest expressions—as an amplification of the commonplace—“creativity,” or even “talent,” as found in convenience samples of undergraduates and the like. Consider for example some recent work on the closely allied topic of “intuition.” Several recent treatments by mainstream psychologists and neuroscientists essentially ignore the vast historical literature on this subject and seek instead to reduce it without residue to “unconscious cerebration”—the automatic, fast, parallel, cheap, and often-reliable but sometimes error-prone out-of-sight operations of a nervous system tuned to its environment by factors such as genetics, learning and conditioning, priming, and so on (Eagleman, 2011; Kahneman, 2011; D. G. Myers, 2002). There is undoubtedly much truth in this picture, especially in the context of everyday life and ordinary cognitive function, but it does not by any means exhaust the subject matter. Indeed, as reviewed in Chapter 5 of IM, we’ve had this conversation before: Specifically, at the end of the 19th century F. W. H. Myers and William James found the unconscious cerebration doctrine then being advanced by W. B. Carpenter, T. H. Huxley, and others specifically unable to account for well-documented empirical phenomena such as the highly developed secondary personalities that sometimes also displayed paranormally acquired knowledge in the context of automatic writing. Many social psychologists in particular appear to have forgotten James’s counsel that postulation of unconscious mental states “is the sovereign means for believing what one likes in psychology, and of turning what might become a science into a tumbling-ground for whimsies” (James, 1890, vol. 1, p. 163). The farther reaches of intuition and creativity include much more than psi phenomena, too, as recognized clearly by more traditional authors such as Wild (1938), who surveyed the long philosophical history of the subject and its deep association with unusual states of consciousness and unusual forms of cognition. Her work complements that of F.W.H. Myers and William James, who similarly upended the modern “deflationary” approach by consciously and deliberately focusing on extreme examples of genius that point in the direction of the enlarged conception of human personality they were struggling to articulate. Myers himself specifically targeted “what the highest minds have bequeathed to us as the heritage of their highest hours” (1903, vol. 1, p. 120). Responding to the cultural levelers of his own era, he encapsulated the main features of his picture of genius as follows: Genius … should rather be regarded as a power of utilizing a wider range than other men can of faculties in some degree innate in all;- a power of appropriating the results of subliminal mentation to subserve the supraliminal stream of thought;- so that an “inspiration of Genius” will be in truth a subliminal uprush, an emergence into the current of ideas which the man is consciously manipulating of other ideas which he has not consciously originated but which have shaped themselves beyond his will, in profounder regions of his being. I shall urge here that there is no real departure from normality; no abnormality, at least in the sense of degeneration; but rather a fulfillment of the true norm of man, with suggestions, it may be, of something supernormal;- of something which transcends existing normality as an advanced stage of evolutionary progress transcends an earlier stage [p. 71]. The deeper forms of subliminal uprush, moreover, are notable both for their typically involuntary character and for their “incommensurability” with the individual’s characteristic forms of mentation. Myers saw both of these properties as present in germ in the case of calculating prodigies (Section 3), but he also pointed to the existence of a “mythopoeic” realm of heightened imagination potentially available to all of us. In this he echoed the views of Romantic poets such as Blake, Wordsworth, and especially Coleridge, who distinguished between the imaginal and the imaginary— between Imagination, which he regarded as a higher faculty of the mind, and mere Fancy or fantasy (IM, pp. 454–457)—and anticipated the views of contemporary scholars such as Brann (1991), Corbin (1997), and Globus (1987), noted in the previous section. All of the challenging phenomena surveyed in this chapter—including extreme psychophysiological influence, psychological automatisms and secondary centers of consciousness, flashes of inspiration involving unusual forms of thinking and symbolism, prodigious memory, spontaneous psi phenomena, and altered states of consciousness sometimes overlapping the mystical realm—are inescapably bound up with genius in its fullest development, but these connections go virtually unmentioned in contemporary mainstream discussions (see IM, chapter 7). A particularly dramatic case in point is that of the Indian mathematician Ramanujan, rated by his distinguished British sponsor Hardy as standing alone at 100 atop a scale of mathematical ability on which most of us lie at or near zero, Hardy himself at 25, and the magnificent David Hilbert, Ramanujan’s nearest rival, only at 80. Replete with demonstrations of prodigious memory, psychological automatisms, mathematical discoveries presented in the form of dreams, and profound and beautiful intuitions of hidden but ultimately verifiable properties of the physical world, this astonishing case fairly beggars the theoretical apparatus currently available to cognitive science and could well serve as a kind of reality check and navigational aid for this important field of study (Eysenck, 1995; Kanigel, 1991). To put the central point of this section in more general terms, the speed, precision, complexity, novelty, and truth-bearing character of these “subliminal uprushes” reveal the presence within human beings of something that radically transcends ordinary cognitive capabilities and forms, and something moreover that is rooted more deeply than ordinary experience in the world in which we find ourselves embedded. This leads directly to our next topic, with which genius is profoundly connected both psychologically and historically. 8. Mystical experience. Experiences of this type have deeply influenced the world’s major religious traditions and civilizations, and have occurred throughout history and across cultures. Their existence as a distinctive and important class of psychological phenomena can scarcely be denied. Nevertheless, they have largely been ignored by modern mainstream science, and the few previous commentators from the viewpoints of clinical psychology, psychiatry, and neuroscience have almost invariably sought to devalue and pathologize them. Even when acknowledging that such experiences are typically life-transforming and self-validating for those who have them, the historically standard epistemological approaches in psychology and philosophy treat them as purely subjective events having authority only for those who experience them, and thus deny their objective significance and the testability of the associated truth-claims. However, a large though scattered literature testifies to the common occurrence in such experiences, or in individuals who have them, of geniuslevel creativity, spontaneous psi-type events, and many other unusual empirical phenomena of the sorts catalogued in this chapter (Marshall, 2011). Mystical-type states of consciousness are also now known to be at least partially reproducible by psychedelics (“entheogens”) such as LSD and psilocybin, and they can be induced by protracted self-discipline involving transformative practices such as the various forms of meditation [see chapters 10 and 12, this volume]. A more objective, informed, and sympathetic appraisal of mystical experience thus finds within it much additional support for an enlarged conception of human personality, and many new opportunities for empirical research (see IM Chapter 8). Furthermore, insofar as it may provide direct experiential access to aspects of reality that remain hidden to us in ordinary states of consciousness, this region of human experience appears especially germane to efforts to identify a metaphysics more comprehensive and satisfying than that of contemporary physicalism (Marshall, 2005). 9. The heart of the mind. In this section I will comment briefly on a hornet’s nest of issues lying at the core of human mental life as all of us routinely experience it, every day of our lives. These issues have been the focus of extensive recent debates, especially in the philosophical literature, precisely because of their resistance to understanding in conventional physicalist terms. The issues are deep, individually complex, and densely interconnected, and what I can say here will necessarily amount to little more than a summary of my own opinions. The crucial point I want to make, especially to my fellow psychologists, is this: Our a priori commitment to conventional physicalist accounts of the mind has rendered us systematically incapable of dealing adequately with the mind’s most central properties. We need to rethink that commitment. Consider first the issue of semantic content, the “meanings” of words and other forms of representation. Throughout our history, we have tried unsuccessfully to deal with this by “naturalizing” it, reducing it to something else that seems potentially more tractable. An old favorite among psychologists and philosophers, traceable at least as far back as Locke and Hume, was the idea that representations work by resembling what they represent, by virtue of some sort of built-in similarity or structural isomorphism, but any hope along these lines was long ago exploded (see for example Braude, 2002; Goodman, 1972; McClendon, 1955). The central move subsequently made by classical cognitive psychology is essentially the semantic counterpart of the prevailing functionalist doctrine in philosophy of mind: Meanings are not to be conceived as intrinsic to words or concepts, but rather as deriving from and defined by the functional role those words or concepts play in the overall linguistic system. Similarly, there is currently great interest in “externalist” causal accounts of meaning: In connectionism, dynamic systems theory, and neuroscience, for example, the “meaning” of a given observed response (such as the settling of a neural network into one of its attractors, or the firing of a volley of spikes by a neuron in the visual cortex) is identified with whatever in the organism’s environment produced that response. But this simply cannot be right: How can such an account possibly deal with abstract things, for example, or nonexistent things? Responses do not qualify ipso facto as representations, nor signs as symbols. Something essential is being left out. That something, as John Searle (1992) so effectively argued, is precisely what matters, the semantic or mental content. Closely related to this is the more general and abstract philosophical problem of “intentionality,” the ability of representational forms to be about things, events, and states of affairs in the world. Mainstream psychologists and philosophers have struggled to find ways of making intentionality intrinsic to the representations themselves, but again it just does not and cannot work, because something essential is left out. That something is the user of the representations. Intentionality is inherently a three-way relation involving users, symbols, and things symbolized, and the user cannot be eliminated. As Searle puts it in various places, the intentionality of language is secondary and derives from the intrinsic intentionality of the mind. Searle thus agrees in part with Brentano (1874/1995), for whom intentionality was the primary distinguishing mark of the mental, but he ignores the other and more fundamental part of Brentano’s thesis, which is that intentionality cannot be obtained from any kind of physical system, including brains (but see for example Dupuy, 2000 for an opposing point of view). Talk of “users” and the like raises for many contemporary psychologists and philosophers the terrifying specter of the self as a homunculus, a little being within who embodies all the capacities we sought to explain in the first place. Such a result would be disastrous, because that being would evidently need a similar though yet smaller being within itself, and so on without end. Cognitive modelers seeking to provide strictly physicalist accounts of mental functions must therefore do so without invoking a homunculus, but in this they routinely fail. Often the homuncular aspect is hidden, slipped into a model by its designers or builders by covertly enlisting the semantic and intentional capacities of its users or observers. Much contemporary work on computational modeling of memory, metaphor, and semantics harbors subtle problems of this sort (see Chapters 4 and 7 of IM for examples). Sometimes, however, the homunculus is more brazenly evident. Searle (1992) uses as an example the influential account of vision by David Marr (1982), which applies computations to the twodimensional array of retinal input in order to generate a “description” of the three-dimensional world that produced it, but then needs somebody else to read and interpret that description. Another is Stephen Kosslyn’s model of visual imagery, which essentially puts up an image on a sort of internal TV screen, but then needs somebody else to view the image. Particularly in its more blatant forms the homunculus has attracted the attention of physicalist philosophers such as Daniel Dennett (1978), who have attempted to remove its philosophic sting. Dennett’s solution is to “discharge” the homunculus by a process of “recursive decomposition.” His basic idea is that the “smart” homunculus appearing at the top of a model can be replaced by progressively larger numbers of less-smart homunculi at lower levels until we get to a vast bottom layer corresponding to the “hardware” level of computer flip-flops or neuron firings. But as Searle (1992) pointed out, this maneuver fails, because even at the bottom level there has to be something outside the decomposition, a homunculus in effect, that knows what those lowest-level operations mean. Cognitive models cannot function without a homunculus, I believe, precisely because they lack what we have—conscious minds, with their capacities for semantics, intentionality, and all the rest built in. No homunculus problem, moreover, is posed by the structure of our conscious experience itself. The efforts of Dennett and others to claim that there is such a problem, and to use that to ridicule any residue of dualism, rely upon their deeply flawed metaphor of the “Cartesian theater,” a place where mental contents get displayed and we then supposedly pop in separately to view them. But we and our experience cannot be separated in that way. Descartes himself, James, and Searle, among others, all have this right: Conscious experience comes to us whole and undivided, with the qualitative feels, phenomenal content, unity, and subjective point of view all built-in, intrinsic features. Finally, I wish simply to record, without argument, my own deepest intuition as to where these issues lead. All of the great unsolved mysteries of the mind—semantics, intentionality, volition, the self, and consciousness —seem to me inextricably interconnected, with consciousness the supreme mystery at the root of all. The consciousness I have in mind, however, is emphatically not that of people such as David Chalmers (1996), irreducible but ineffectual, consisting merely of phenomenal properties or “qualia” arbitrarily tacked on to some sort of computational intelligence that supposedly does all the cognitive work. Ordinary perception and action are saturated with conceptual understanding, and conceptual understanding is saturated with phenomenal content. Volition too has an intentionality aspect, for one cannot just will, one must will something. And as William James so forcibly argued at the dawn of our science, all of this perceptual, cognitive, and volitional activity somehow emanates from a mysterious and elusive “spiritual self,” which we often sense at the innermost subjective pole of everyday conscious experience—the “something more” that James himself traced in his later years into the depths of Myers’s subliminal consciousness as revealed in mystical experience (Leary, 1990; IM chapter 8). Consciousness, in short, far from being a passive epiphenomenon, seems to me to play an essential role—indeed the essential role—in all of our most basic cognitive capacities. I applaud the trenchant conclusion of philosopher E. J. Lowe (1998, pp. 121–122), which encapsulates my own views: “Reductive physicalism, far from being equipped to solve the socalled ‘easy’ problems of consciousness, has in fact nothing useful to say about any aspect of consciousness.” I find it astonishing, and predict that it will be found so as well by our intellectual descendants, that so much of contemporary science and philosophy has sought—consciously!—to slight or ignore these first-person realities of the mind, and sometimes even to deny that they exist. There is perhaps no better example of the power of pre-existing theoretical commitments to blind us to countervailing facts. 10. Quantum mechanics and its implications. It cannot be emphasized too strongly that these unresolved explanatory problems concerning consciousness, the heart of the mind, and all the other empirical phenomena surveyed above have a common source in the narrow physicalist consensus that undergirds practically everything now going on in mainstream psychology, neuroscience, and philosophy of mind. But that consensus itself rests upon an outdated conception of nature, deriving from Galileo, Descartes, Newton, and Laplace, that began its career by deliberately banishing conscious human minds from its purview! And as I will next briefly explain, that sort of physicalism is itself incompatible with the deepest of our current physical sciences. William James, like Newton and Leibniz before him, clearly recognized the impossibility of explaining consciousness and allied phenomena within the framework of classical physics. James himself cautioned that its underlying physical-science concepts were “provisional and revisable things,” but he had no good alternatives in sight. As he clearly and correctly anticipated, however, that classical conception of nature was soon to be undermined by a tectonic shift in the foundations of physics itself—specifically, the shift driven in particular by the rise of quantum mechanics early in the 20th century. The founders of quantum mechanics discovered to their horror that applying to the subatomic world the fundamental ideas of classical physics were not just limited but wrong, leading repeatedly to predictions that were falsified by experiments. The theory they were ultimately driven to in response, quantum theory, is a more fundamental physical theory that explains everything explainable in classical terms and a host of additional things as well, often to extraordinary levels of accuracy. No prediction made by it has ever been experimentally falsified. Furthermore, the rise of quantum theory demonstrates that the undeniable experimental and practical triumphs of classical physics were not sufficient in themselves to validate the associated physicalist ontology. It may in the past have seemed appropriate to say, as did Burtt (1923, p. 305) just prior to the advent of quantum theory, that “it has, no doubt, been worth several centuries of metaphysical barbarism to possess modern science,” but the situation now is radically different. Despite many remaining uncertainties regarding its proper interpretation, quantum theory clearly impacts our most fundamental ideas about the nature of reality and opens the door to radically different overall conceptions of nature (Rosenblum & Kuttner, 2011). Conventional physical realism has been undermined, and “matter” as classically conceived shown not to exist. Quantum theory essentially inverts the priority of the mental and physical aspects of nature by shifting the focus of physics itself to regularities in the connections between psychologically described events—i.e., conscious experiences of human observers. Mathematical physicist Henry Stapp (2007), for example, has proposed an interpretation in which the conscious human mind with its powers of attention and decision-making plays a critical role in completing the quantum dynamics. As a corollary, the classical doctrine of causal closure or completeness of the physical, which underwrites contemporary physicalist denials of free will, collapses. It also appears likely that many of the “rogue” empirical phenomena cited above, from stigmata and hypnotic blisters to psi phenomena and even post-mortem survival, are potentially accommodated within broader conceptual frameworks of this sort. Where Is This All Headed? The empirical challenges systematically marshaled in IM and sketched above seem to me sufficient in themselves to compel, and to some extent foreshadow, a radical reworking of conventional production models of brain/mind relations along the alternative lines envisioned by Myers and James, among numerous others. But it is also vital to recognize that a scientific psychology enlarged in these ways will likely prove not less but more compatible than current mainstream doctrine both with everyday human experience and with our most fundamental physical science! In effect we have taken a hundred-year detour. Myers and James were scarcely in their graves when their fledging “transmission” or “permission” or “filter” theory of the brain/mind relation was pushed aside by the aggressive rise of behaviorism and psychoanalysis. Although psychoanalysis has subsequently faded (in the U.S. at least), behaviorism maintained its original hegemony within academic psychology well into the 1960s, and it has perpetuated itself since then by evolving into more sophisticated forms, in particular the “Computational Theory of the Mind” (CTM) in its main variants—classical cognitivism, connectionism, and most recently dynamic systems theory—which have now become deeply allied with developments in neuroscience under the umbrella of the thriving academic industry known as “cognitive neuroscience.” I believe we have come full cycle since Myers and James, to the corresponding point at a higher turn of an evolutionary spiral. This centurylong detour was painful but also historically necessary, because the mainstream physicalist approach to psychology that arose in the late 19th century, self-consciously seeking to emulate the astonishing triumphs of classical physics, had to exhaust its resources and expose its own intrinsic limitations before anything else could realistically hope to take its place. That first century has also undeniably produced many genuinely positive developments including the contemporary explosion of knowledge in neuroscience and neuropsychology and associated technical contributions such as the rapidly evolving methods for functional neuroimaging and indeed the whole diversified apparatus of modern statistics-based experimental science. Conventional production models of the brain/mind relation and the associated metaphysics of classical physicalism are inadequate and must be rejected, but what should take their place? Here I wish to offer in general terms some fairly radical personal opinions. Many parapsychologists will no doubt regard these as excessively radical, but I share with philosopher Thomas Nagel (2012) the strong sense that the failure of physicalism to explain the brain/mind relation generally (let alone the various supernormal phenomena catalogued above) casts a shadow retrospectively on other, intertwined aspects of the received physicalist conception of reality, and that to remedy this situation will require some kind of major conceptual revolution. Let us begin from the theoretical situation in parapsychology itself. Everybody agrees that we need good theories of psi, and accounts can be found elsewhere in this book of many previous attempts to provide them. I do not wish to demean these efforts, but my own driving intuition is that theories or conceptual frameworks capable of accommodating more extreme phenomena, for example precognition and macro–PK in the arena of psi (Braude, 1995), will in general accommodate simpler or lesser ones of related type. I also believe that this principle should be applied more widely, and thus, rather than starting with a theory or conceptual framework that deals with psi phenomena alone, or perhaps even some subset of these, I think it makes sense to look from the beginning for some more comprehensive framework that can potentially accommodate not only the full range of psi phenomena but other related things as well, including in particular mystical experiences and higher states of consciousness (see Marshall, 2005, 2011), along with the unexplained phenomena at the heart of the mind that so trouble Nagel and other contemporary philosophers. What we are groping toward here is a correct or at least useful abduction in the sense of the American logician and philosopher Charles Sanders Peirce —in effect, an educated guess as to how reality as a whole must be structured in order that the targeted phenomena can occur. In a theoryoriented follow-up book to IM (Kelly, Crabtree, & Marshall, 2015) we have reviewed a variety of past and present abductive efforts of this sort, all starting from a synoptic empiricism that specifically includes “rogue” phenomena of the sorts described above, and on that basis I believe we can glimpse at least roughly what that overall constitution must be like— specifically, a panpsychist pluralist or panentheist metaphysics of the sort William James was attempting to articulate in his most mature philosophical work (James, 1909/1971). As James fully understood, the underlying issue here is not whether we will have metaphysics, because we inevitably will, but whether we will have good metaphysics or bad. For details of that theoretical exercise I must refer readers to our new book itself, but in closing I wish to say just a little bit more about its implications for research. To expand upon views expressed previously (Kelly & Locke, 1981/2009; Cardeña & Winkelman, 2011), it now seems to me that further research on mystical experience, and on the known means of facilitating it —in particular, deep meditation and the major psychedelics—is of the highest priority, scientifically speaking, affording numerous opportunities for ground-breaking research with potentially profound implications for human development and the effective use of human potentials. Work of that sort can certainly be conducted without prior commitment to the sort of metaphysics indicated here, and it also is likely in my opinion to bring with it, as a corollary, stronger sources of psi for future experimental investigations. Note 1. I wish to thank Rowman & Littlefield for permission to use material from Beyond physicalism (Kelly, Crabtree, & Marshall, 2015) in preparing this chapter. References Alexander, E. A. (2012). Proof of heaven: A neurosurgeon’s journey into the afterlife. New York: Simon & Schuster. Bergson, H. (1991). Matter and memory (N. M. Paul and W. S. Palmer, Trans.). New York: Zone Books. (Original 5th ed. published 1908). Brann, E. T. H. (1991). The world of the imagination. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield. Braude, S. (1991). The limits of influence. London, UK: Routledge. (Original work published 1986). Braude, S. (1995). First person plural: Multiple personality and the philosophy of mind (Rev. ed.). Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield. Braude, S. (2002). ESP and psychokinesis: A philosophical examination (Rev. Ed.). Parkland, FL: Brown Walker Press. Brentano, F. (1995). Psychology from an empirical standpoint (A. C. Rancurello, D. B. Terrell, and L. L. McAlister, Trans.). London, UK: Routledge. (Original work published 1874). Broad, C. D. (1962). Lectures on psychical research. London, UK: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Bursen, H. A. (1978). Dismantling the memory machine. Dordrecht, Netherlands: Reidel. Burtt, E. A. (1923). The metaphysical foundations of modern physical science: A historical and critical essay. London, UK: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trübner. Cardeña, E., and Winkelman, M. (Eds.) (2011). Altering consciousness: Multidisciplinary perspectives (2 vols.). Westport, CT: Praeger. Chalmers, D. (1996). The conscious mind: In search of a fundamental theory. New York: Oxford University Press. Churchland, P. M. (1988). Matter and consciousness (Rev. ed.). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Corbin, H. (1997). Alone with the alone: Creative imagination in the sufism of Ibn Arabi. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. (Original work published 1969). Corrigan, N. M., Richards, T. L., Treffert, D. A., and Dager, S. R. (2012). Toward a better understanding of the savant brain. Comprehensive Psychiatry, 53, 706–717. Crawford, H. J., Wallace, B., Nomura, K., and Slater, H. (1986). Eideticlike imagery in hypnosis: Rare but there. American Journal of Psychology, 99, 527–546. Crick, F. (1994). The astonishing hypothesis: The scientific search for the soul. New York: Simon & Schuster. Dehaene, S., and Naccache, L. (2001). Towards a cognitive neuroscience of consciousness: Basic evidence and a workspace framework. Cognition, 79, 1–37. Dennett, D. (1978). Brainstorms: Philosophical essays on mind and psychology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Dupuy, J.-P. (2000). The mechanization of the mind: On the origins of cognitive science. (M. B. DeBevoise, Trans.). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Eagleman, D. (2011) Incognito: The secret lives of the brain. New York: Pantheon Books. Edelman, G. M., Gally, J. A., and Baars, B. J. (2011). Biology of consciousness. Frontiers in Psychology. 2:4. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2011.00004 Engel, A. K., Fries, P., and Singer, W. (2001). Dynamic predictions: Oscillations and synchrony in top-down processing. Nature Reviews: Neuroscience, 2, 704–716. Eysenck, H. J. (1995). Genius: The natural history of creativity. New York: Cambridge University Press. Globus, G. (1987). Dream life, wake life: The human condition through dreams. Albany: State University of New York Press. Goodman, N. (1972). Seven strictures on similarity. In N. Goodman (Ed.), Problems and projects (pp. 437–446). New York: Bobbs-Merrill. Hartmann, E. (1975). Dreams and other hallucinations: An approach to the underlying mechanism. In R. K. Siegel and L. J. West (Eds.), Hallucinations: Behavior, experience, and theory (pp. 71–79). New York: John Wiley & Sons. Holden, J., Greyson, B., and James, D. (2009). The handbook of near-death experiences: Thirty years of investigation. Santa Barbara, CA: Praeger Publishers. James, W. (1889). Notes on automatic writing. Proceedings of the American Society for Psychical Research, 1, 548–564. James, W. (1890). The principles of psychology (2 vols.). New York: Henry Holt. James, W. (1971). A pluralistic universe. In Essays in radical empiricism and A pluralistic universe (pp. 121–284). New York: E. P. Dutton. (Original work published 1909). James, W. (1986). Essays in psychical research. (F. H. Burkhardt, Ed.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking, fast and slow. New York: Farrar, Strauss, and Giroux. Kanigel, R. (1999). The man who knew infinity: A life of the genius Ramanujan. New York: C. Scribner’s. Kelly, E. F., Crabtree, A., and Marshall, P. (Eds.) (2015). Beyond physicalism: Toward reconciliation of science and spirituality. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield. Kelly, E. F., Kelly, E. W., Crabtree, A., Gauld, A., Grosso, M., and Greyson, B. (2007). Irreducible mind: Toward a psychology for the 21st century. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield. Kelly, E. F., and Locke, R. G. (2009). Altered states of consciousness and psi: An historical survey and research prospectus. New York: Parapsychology Foundation. (Original work published 1981). Laureys, S., and Tononi, G. (Eds.) (2009). The neurology of consciousness: Cognitive neuroscience and neuropathology. London, UK: Academic Press/Elsevier. Leary, D. (1990). William James on the self and personality: Clearing the ground for subsequent theorists, researchers, and practitioners. In M. G. Johnson and T. B. Henley (Eds.), Reflections on the principles of psychology: William James after a century (pp. 101–137). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum. Llinás, R., and Ribary, U. (1994). Perception as an oneiric-like state modulated by the senses. In C. Koch and J. L. Davis (Eds.) Large-scale neuronal theories of the brain (pp. 111–124). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Lowe, E. J. (1998). There are no easy problems of consciousness. In J. Shear (Ed.), Explaining consciousness—the hard problem (pp. 117–123). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Luria, A. R. (1968). The mind of a mnemonist (L. Solotaroff, Trans.). New York: Avon Books. Marr, D. (1982). Vision: A computational investigation into the human representation and processing of visual information. San Francisco, CA: W. H. Freeman. Marshall, P. (2005). Mystical encounters with the natural world: Experiences & explanations. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Marshall, P. (2011). The psychical and the mystical: Boundaries, connections, common origins. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 75, 1–13. McClendon, H. J. (1955). Uses of similarity of structure in contemporary philosophy. Mind, 64, 79–95. Myers, D. G. (2002). Intuition: Its powers and perils. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Myers, F. W. H. (1903). Human personality and its survival of bodily death (2 vols.). London, UK: Longmans, Green. (available on Esalen CTR website). Nagel, T. (2012). Mind and cosmos: Why the materialist neo-darwinian conception of nature is almost certainly false. New York: Oxford University Press. Owens, J. Cook [Kelly], E. W., and Stevenson, I. (1990). Features of “neardeath experience” in relation to whether or not patients were near death. Lancet, 336, 1175–1177. Parnia, S. (2013). Erasing death: The science that is rewriting the boundaries between life and death. New York: HarperOne. Radin, D. (2006). Entangled minds: Extrasensory experiences in a quantum reality. New York: Simon and Schuster. Rosenblum, B., and Kuttner, F. (2011). Quantum enigma: Physics encounters consciousness (2nd ed.). New York: Oxford University Press. Sacks, O. (1987). The man who mistook his wife for a hat. New York: Simon and Schuster. Searle, J. R. (1992). The rediscovery of the mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Simons, D. J., and Chabris, C. F. (1999). Gorillas in our midst: Sustained inattentional blindness for dynamic events. Perception, 28, 1059–1074. Singer, W. (2007). Large-scale temporal coordination of cortical activity as a prerequisite for conscious experience. In M. Velmans and S. Schneider (Eds.) The Blackwell companion to consciousness (pp. 605–615), Malden, MA: Blackwell. Snyder, A. W., and Mitchell, D. J. (1999). Is integer arithmetic fundamental to mental processing? The mind’s secret arithmetic. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London—B, 266, 587–592. Stapp, H. P. (2007). Mindful universe: Quantum mechanics and the participating observer. Berlin, Germany: Springer. Stevenson, I. (1978). Some comments on automatic writing. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 72, 315–332. Stevenson, I. (1997). Reincarnation and biology: A contribution to the etiology of birthmarks and birth defects (2 vols.). New York: Praeger. Stromeyer, C. F. III (1970). Eidetekers. Psychology Today, 4, 76–80. Stromeyer, C. F. III, and Psotka, J. (1970). The detailed texture of eidetic images. Nature, 225, 346–349. Tart, C. T. (1993). Mind embodied: Computer-generated virtual reality as a new, dualistic-interactive model for transpersonal psychology. In K. R. Rao (Ed.), Cultivating consciousness: Enhancing human potential, wellness and healing (pp. 123–137). Westport, CT: Praeger. Tart, C. T. (2009). The end of materialism: How evidence of the paranormal is bringing science and spirit together. Oakland, CA: New Harbinger Publications. Treffert, D. (2010). Islands of genius: The bountiful mind of the autistic, acquired, and sudden savant. Philadelphia, PA: Jessica Kingsley Publishers. Tyrrell, G. N. M. (1953). Apparitions (Rev. Ed.). London, UK: The Society for Psychical Research. Van Lommel, P. (2010). Consciousness beyond life: The science of the neardeath experience. New York: Harper Collins. Van Lommel, P. (2013). Non-local consciousness: A concept based on scientific research on near-death experiences during cardiac arrest. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 20, 7–48. Varela, F. J., Lachaux, J.-P., Rodriguez, E., and Martinerie, J. (2001). The brainweb: Phase synchronization and large-scale integration. Nature Reviews: Neuroscience, 2, 229–239. Wild, K. W. (1938). Intuition. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. OceanofPDF.com CHAPTER 3 The Case Against Psi DOUGLAS M. STOKES In this chapter, I will argue that the experimental evidence for psi phenomena amassed by parapsychologists strongly supports the conclusion that psi phenomena (such as telepathy, clairvoyance, precognition, and psychokinesis) do not exist. At the very least, their existence has not been experimentally demonstrated. The existing body of evidence does not conform to the pattern that would be expected if psi exists and is susceptible to experimental study, but it does conform to the pattern that would be expected if a small minority of psi researchers has engaged in fraud. I have reached this conclusion reluctantly after four decades of involvement in the field of parapsychology. Of necessity, this chapter will recount my personal journey in confronting this question. Over the past few years, I have moved from a position of agnosticism regarding the existence of psi to one of fullfledged atheism (or should I say “a-psi-ism?”). At the very least I have retreated to the psi equivalent of radical Unitarianism. For more than 20 years, I reviewed the published proceedings of the Parapsychological Association for the Journal of Parapsychology, at the request of the Editor, stopping only when the Research in Parapsychology series ceased publication. In those reviews and other publications (e.g., Stokes, 1997b, 2007), I have presented critiques of the experimental methodologies used by many parapsychologists. However, my conclusion that the body of experimental findings points to the nonexistence of psi is not based on methodology flaws but on much wider grounds. Spontaneous Psi Before addressing the experimental evidence, I will first consider the evidence for psi provided by spontaneously occurring events in the “real world.” Consider the following seemingly precognitive dream, taken from Louisa Rhine’s collection. It was provided to Rhine by the district manager of a sheet and tin plate company. The experience occurred shortly before he and several business associates were to return home from a two-week vacation in the wilderness, where they had been cut off from all news sources: The night before they were to return home, the district manager had a dream, so clear, so vivid, he could not sleep afterward. In it, he writes, “one of our locomotive cranes that was unloading a car of scrap iron, together with the car, was on the track near the bank of a river alongside the water tower which served the locomotives. For some unaccountable reason, as the huge magnet swung around with a heavy load of scrap, it suddenly toppled over the river bank. The operator, whom I called by name, jumped clear of the crane and landed below it as it came bounding, tumbling and bouncing down the river bank, and he finally disappeared from view as the crane came to rest twenty feet below at the water’s edge. I particularly noted the number of the crane and the number and positions of the railroad cars, and was able to tell how the crane operator was dressed. Furthermore, I noticed the approximate damage done to the crane. I did not know, however, what had finally happened to the operator. He had disappeared under or behind the crane after it had come to rest. In other words, I was observing the accident from somewhere in or across the river. Upon my return to the mill the following day, the first man I met was the master mechanic. He told me to come with him to inspect the crane of my dream, to talk with the operator who had emerged from the accident without a scratch. The operator explained his lack of injury by the fact that the crane had fallen over in front of him as he made his last jump and as it made its last bounce. The record showed the smallest detail to be as I had dreamed it, with one exception. The exception was that the accident had happened two hours after the dream” [Rhine, 1961, pp. 43–44]. There are a number of problems with accepting this dream at face value. The manager may have embellished the dream. His memory may be unreliable and perhaps the dream occurred after he learned about the falling crane. He may be constantly worrying about such accidents and may have similar dreams on most nights. He may have subconsciously been aware that the crane operator was sinking into alcoholism. He may have fabricated the whole incident. To address such concerns, many parapsychologists have chosen to use experimental methodology to study psi processes so that one can be sure of the order of events, that the psi experience is not due to the unconscious processing of sensory information, that the event is not merely a coincidence (as the probability may be computed), and that the event has not been fabricated out of whole cloth (unless the experimenter has engaged in fraud, as discussed in more detail below). There is a cost associated with the experimental approach. Without spontaneous case investigations parapsychologists would be unaware of the evidence suggesting that dream experiences tend to be precognitive in nature, whereas waking intuitions generally involve events occurring at the same time (Stokes, 1997a). Many spontaneous cases involve macroscopic physical effects, such as portraits falling and clocks stopping at the time of a person’s death. Such effects are not generally amenable to experimental study and involve primal emotions and events such as those associated with death or severe injury that are not easily reproduced in an experimental study and would likely be banned as unethical by contemporary ethical review panels. For a review of such spontaneous phenomena and research based on them, the reader is referred to my previous works (Stokes, 1997a, 1997b, 2007, and 2014), as well as to other chapters in this Handbook. Many parapsychologists contend that spontaneous cases may be explained by normal processes such as those discussed above. In my opinion this dismissal of the evidence from spontaneous cases may be a bit cavalier, especially in light of the weakness of the experimental evidence as discussed below. I myself continue to work in the area of the survival problem, which often involves apparent cases of spontaneous psi (for a progress report, see Stokes, 2014). This is the reverse of the typical pattern for a parapsychologist, which is to abandon the survival problem for the apparently more tractable field of experimental psi research. A Priori Skepticism Many skeptics reject psi based on the fact that psi phenomena are inconsistent with the findings of modern science. It is indeed difficult to explain causal signals that seem to travel backward in time (as in precognition and retroactive psychokinesis) as well as apparent instances of telepathy between people separated by great distances. Some skeptics who reject psi phenomena out of hand are seemingly mired in the classical, deterministic Newtonian billiard ball physics they learned in high school. The non-physicists among them do not seem to be aware of the implications of quantum mechanics, despite the fact that the basic theory of quantum mechanics was developed in the first half of the last century. Quantum theory paints a picture of the universe in which seemingly isolated events are connected in a nonlocal manner. This universe would appear to be much friendlier to psi phenomena than is the billiard ball world of Newtonian mechanics. However, these nonlocal interconnections between separated physical systems cannot be used to transmit a psi signal between them, as the two observers will see only a sequence of random, albeit pair-wise correlated, events. The only way to send a signal would be if the sender could psychokinetically impose a pattern of outcomes on these random events. But this would be using psi to explain psi. It is thus extremely difficult to explain psi phenomena on the basis of currently accepted scientific theories. This is a legitimate basis for skepticism regarding the existence of psi, but not for the a priori dismissal of psi as impossible. In fact, this very difficulty is precisely the allure of psi phenomena. The theory of quantum mechanics is inconsistent with Einstein’s theory of relativity. Attempts to unify the two have failed. Thus, the picture of the universe painted by currently accepted theories of physics is an inconsistent and perhaps even contradictory one. Is the physical world screaming at us that it does not exist? Psi phenomena may point the way to extending our understanding of the universe to encompass mind and consciousness as well as matter. That is why they are so important (if they exist). If psi exists, the world would be a far more interesting place than it appears to be based on the outdated Newtonian physics subscribed to by most a priori skeptics. I remember my graduate advisor at the University of Michigan asking me why, granting that psi phenomena exist, they would be of any importance, given the slight signal-to-noise ratio of the psi process. This reflects the fact that he was an experimental psychologist focused on understanding psychological processes in general, whereas I had evolved (or possibly devolved) into an ontologist (one who is concerned with the very nature of reality). No satisfactory, well-tested theory of psi has been developed, although many have been proposed (see Stokes, 1987). Of course, it is next to impossible to refine any theory about phenomena that are not stable or replicable. If psi phenomena do not exist, it would of course be a pointless exercise to develop a theory about their operation. Methodological Flaws Some critics ascribe the experimental evidence for psi to methodological flaws committed by parapsychological researchers, leading to the witticism that ESP stands for “error some place.” In general, parapsychologists have tightened up their methodology over the four decades I have been involved in the field. However, studies with egregious methodological flaws continue to be reported. Most remote-viewing studies are based on procedures that provide sensory cues as to the correct target to supposedly masked judges as well as the nonrandom selection and construction of targets (see Stokes, 1997b, 2007 for the details). Papers are even now being published on ESP tests in which the participant pulls numbered balls out of a bag, sometimes at home and without supervision (Storm, Ertel, & Rock, 2013). Space restrictions prohibit a detailed analysis of methodological flaws in this chapter. Many meta-analyses have found no evidence for a positive relation between methodological flaws and the size of reported psi effects. This is true of the meta-analysis of experimental studies of forced-choice ESP experiments reported by Storm, Tressoldi, and Di Risio (2012), which we will use as an example in the discussions below. Of course, people who report fraudulent results may also report more perfect methodology than was actually used (assuming that the experiment was even conducted). In the following analysis, we will make the conservative assumption (from the skeptical point of view) that all parapsychological experiments have been conducted with perfect methodology. Even under this assumption, the existing evidence for psi most strongly supports the hypothesis that psi phenomena do not exist, as will be shown below [but see chapter 15, this volume]. Experimenter Fraud There is always the possibility that the experimenters themselves might engage in fraud. A major scandal in parapsychology in 1974 involved Walter J. Levy, Jr., a young medical school graduate. Levy had recently been appointed as Director of J. B. Rhine’s Institute for Parapsychology, and many people regarded him as Rhine’s heir-apparent. When I joined Rhine’s research staff in 1974 shortly after completing my own doctorate in experimental psychology, one of the primary things that lured me to the lab was Levy’s active and hugely successful program in investigating the psi powers of animals, including the precognitive abilities of jirds (a fancy name for what are essentially gerbils) and the psychokinetic powers of rats and chicken embryos. The hapless little jirds had to use their ESP to avoid getting zapped by an electrical shock by moving to the part of their cage or exercise wheel that would not be shocked. The chicken embryos (still of course encased in their eggs) had to use their PK powers to get a random event generator (REG) to turn on a light to warm them up in lieu of a hen. The rats had to use their PK to convince an REG to send them a jolt in the pleasure center of their brains. The rat experiment proved to be Levy’s undoing. I recall one night when he showed me a live data feed indicating that a rat was getting about 25 jolts to his pleasure center in a row. This was most remarkable, as the rat should have been getting a joy burst on only about half the trials by chance. Levy asked me what I thought, and I told him he should check to see if his equipment was functioning properly. Unfortunately, he had already taken this hint a little too much to heart as we shall see. Levy used to take the laboratory staff out to lunch and excitedly read us passages about the fraudulent cancer research of William Summerlin, which was big news in the pages of Science and Nature at the time. At one such lunch, I asked the research team whether they could rule out the possibility that one member of the research team might be doing something to fake all the spectacular results they were getting. I never suspected Jay Levy himself, as he seemed to work too hard. Having newly arrived in Durham, I was Levy’s roommate for a period while I searched for my own apartment. He worked day and night. He read constantly. It is still not clear to me why a person engaged in fraudulent activity would put in such long hours at it. If I were to perpetrate a fraud myself, I would surely get home soon after 5:00 p.m. Levy was energetic, charismatic, and a strong leader. Sadly, based on my reading of the literature over the past four decades, these traits are characteristic of many fraudulent researchers in mainstream science who have been exposed over the years. It is easy to be fooled by such persons. Three researchers on Levy’s team (Jim Kennedy, Jim Davis, and Jerry Levin) noticed him frequently puttering around the equipment when experiments were in progress and there would normally be no reason to interact with the experimental apparatus. To see if he were up to some monkey business, they secretly wired up the computer to make a duplicate record of the output of the REG. This second record showed the output of the REG to be perfectly random, while Levy’s official record showed that the rat was getting jolt after jolt to his pleasure center and obtaining truly prodigious PK scores in the process. It transpired that Levy was disconnecting the wire that recorded the trials on which the rat was unsuccessful and shorting it out on the side of the computer for brief periods of time, thus making it seem as though the rat was achieving remarkable PK success. Doug Richards, another researcher at the Institute, told me that he should have known something was wrong with the chicken embryo experiments when the eggs continued to get good scores even though they were quite malodorous (that is, the embryos had long since died). Confronted with the evidence of his crimes, Levy was forced to resign as Director of Rhine’s Institute and returned to the practice of medicine (see Rhine, 1974, 1975 for a discussion of the Levy case). Shortly after the discovery of Levy’s fraud, Helmut Schmidt (one of the primary pioneers of psi research using REGs) came into my office for a brief conversation about the Levy affair. “How could he [Levy] be so stupid?” he asked me. I found Helmut’s choice of questions to be an intriguing one, which is why I have remembered it to this day. Experimental studies of telepathy by S. G. Soal (Soal & Bateman, 1954), long regarded as among the studies providing the most impressive evidence for ESP, have been demonstrated through statistical analyses by Scott and Haskell (1974) and a computer analysis of Soal’s target series by Markwick (1978) to be due to a crude form of fraudulent alteration of the experimental data by Soal. I was tasked with presenting the Scott and Haskell study to a lunchtime gathering of Rhine’s research group. I remember J. B. Rhine rising at the end of my presentation and saying that he had long suspected that Soal’s research was fraudulent. Someone later suggested that Rhine’s reaction may have reflected lingering animosity toward Soal, triggered by Soal’s initial inability to replicate Rhine’s card-guessing experiments and his early skeptical criticisms of Rhine’s work (see Hyman, 1986). In my second book, I came to the following conclusion regarding experimenter fraud in parapsychology: In view of the fact that most investigators are not able to obtain reliable and replicable experimental evidence for psi, the possibility that the most striking evidence for psi is due to experimenter fraud should not be completely discounted. If such is the case, parapsychology would stand head and shoulders above the typical run- of-the-mill case of experimenter fraud in terms of the large number of investigators and studies involved. It would be fraud on a scale that is unprecedented in the history of science [Stokes, 2007, p. 80]. Sadly in the past two years, it has been discovered that fraud is rampant even in orthodox scientific fields. My newfound skepticism regarding the existence of psi is not based on any new concrete evidence for fraud among parapsychologists, but rather on a general lowering of my respect for all scientists, especially in terms of their honesty and desire to seek out the truth, regardless of its impact on the scientist’s curriculum vitae. The level of experimenter mendacity needed to explain the experimental evidence for psi pales in comparison to the skullduggery being perpetrated on a daily basis by psychologists and medical researchers. There is no shortage of fraudulent experimenters in today’s world. To paraphrase Special Agent Mulder, the fraud is out there. For instance, a news item in Science (Anonymous, 2013) reports the results of an analysis of scientific misconduct in biomedicine by John Krueger of the federal Office of Research Integrity. His analysis indicates that the number of published retractions in biomedicine have climbed from 254 in 2011 to 348 in 2012. The percentage of biomedical publications that are retractions has steadily climbed from 0.5 percent in 1996 to 4.5 percent in 2012. Fang and Casadevall (2013) note that there has been a ten-fold increase in the retraction rate in the life sciences over the past two decades and that most such retractions are the result of uncovered fraud. It should also be noted that these retractions represent only exposed fraud. If one assumes that only half of fraudulent experimenters are actually caught, then the rate of fraud in biomedical search would be 9 percent based on Krueger’s analysis. This fraud does not come without costs. In one such case involving medical research on beta-blockers, the cost is estimated as 800,000 lives lost (Vogel, 2014). The chief harm caused by most fraudulent parapsychological research is to lure young experimenters away from promising lines of research into parapsychological careers that will be futile and heavily punished by the academic community. However, fraudulent parapsychological research could also kill large numbers of people (such as those who forgo mainstream treatments based on reported research on psychic surgery, psychic healing, the power of prayer, etc.). In an anonymous survey of over 2,000 psychologists, John, Loewenstein, and Prelec (2012) found that approximately 10 percent of research psychologists have introduced false data into the scientific record and that a majority of research psychologists have engaged in questionable practices such as selective reporting, not reporting all dependent measures, deciding whether to collect more data after determining whether the results were significant, reporting unexpected findings as having been predicted, and excluding data on a post hoc basis. The authors conclude that the results of their survey may explain why there are so many failures to replicate psychological studies. It also would explain the decline effect, in which the effect sizes decrease with subsequent attempts at replication, which is also a pattern seen in parapsychology. Pashler and Harris (2012) argue that use of the traditional 0.05 level of statistical significance as the criterion for the admission of a research finding into the academic literature will result in a majority of the published findings being false, once false positives are taken into account. Simulations by Simmons, Nelson, and Simonsohn (2011) suggest that given typical practices, 60 percent of the findings in psychological journals represent false positives. Ioannidis (2012) estimates that 56 percent of published findings in psychology are false positives that go unchallenged, as few replication studies are reported in psychology, due to publication biases against them. He estimates that 95 percent of the published findings are fallacies, based on these biases. Parapsychology’s record seems no worse than this. However, there are generally only a handful of parapsychologists who regularly obtain significant effects, which is cause for concern. This pattern is called the “experimenter effect” in parapsychology and is often attributed to the experimenter’s own psi influences on the results or to the effect of the experimenter’s personality on the performance of volunteers. Of course, a more parsimonious interpretation is that psi-conducive experimenters are those willing to engage in fraud and/or data selection One method of minimizing the possibility of experimenter fraud, which was endorsed by J. B. Rhine, is to run experiments in such a way that the integrity of the procedures and data is under the control of several observers. Experiments can (and have been) designed in such a way that no one member of an investigating team could fraudulently generate a significant result. In such experiments, a determined skeptic would have to postulate a conspiracy among all the members of the investigating team, which is of course much less plausible than the allegation of fraud against a single person. Some experiments along this line have been reported (e.g., Schmidt, Morris, & Rudolph, 1986). In light of the vast number of researchers in the general scientific community that appear to be willing to engage in fraud and other questionable practices, it is important to ensure the integrity of the data and adherence to the described experimental procedure. This might be achieved by having multiple parties observe the experiment and receive the primary data through secure and separate data streams, as J. B. Rhine suggested. The Effects of Fraud and Data Selection in Psi Research What pattern of results might we expect if there is no psi but a substantial number of psi researchers are frauds or are guilty of data selection? Suppose that experimenters may be classified into three types. The first category comprises “frauds.” We will assume that frauds typically report a z-score of 2.58, a psi-hitting rate that will be just significant at the 0.01 level under a two-tailed test (a cheater would not want to get too fancy). This is likely a conservative assumption. The second category of investigators comprises “filers.” Filers do not fabricate results, but only publish experiments that are significant at the one-tailed 0.05 level. This may reflect a combination of the filers’ decisions not to submit their own nonsignificant studies and journal editors’ rejection of such papers. In the absence of psi, the median z-score reported by filers would be 1.96 (the median score in the upper 5 percent of the distribution in the absence of psi, which is also happens to be the z-score for a two-tailed 0.05 level test). The third category of investigators comprises non-filers, who publish all their findings without regard to significance. In the absence of psi, the median score reported by non-filers would be expected to be zero. Suppose that 100 experiments are conducted, four by frauds (4 percent), 80 by filers, and the remaining 16 by non-filers. The mean z-score for the four fraudulent experimenters will be 2.58. The 80 filers would be expected to report only 5 percent, or four, of their studies. The typical z-score for these four studies is expected to be 1.96. The remaining 76 studies by filers would not be published. The 16 non-filers will report typical z-score of 0 (remember, we are assuming psi does not exist). Thus, only 24 of the 100 conducted studies would be published and the mean z-score for these studies would be expected to be around 0.757. When combined, the Stouffer z-score for the 24 published experiments would be 3.707, which is highly significant. This, however, is not evidence of psi, as the above estimates are based on the assumption that psi does not exist. Parapsychologists often compute the size of the “file drawer” or the number of nonsignificant and unreported studies that would be needed to reduce the overall significance levels to nonsignificance (i.e., to a Stouffer z-score below 1.645). Most often, this is computed using the method developed by Robert Rosenthal (1976), probably for ease of computation. Rosenthal’s method is based on the assumption that the unreported studies have an average z-score of 0. However, this assumption is not met if the “filers” selectively publish only those findings that are significant at the one-tailed 0.05 level. This would result in a median z-score of -0.063 rather than 0 for the unpublished studies. Thus, Rosenthal’s estimate is an overestimate of the size of the file-drawer required to explain the results of psi experiments. For the present example, the Rosenthal’s file-drawer estimate is 98 unpublished studies, whereas the actual number of unpublished studies is 76 [see chapter 15]. In their meta-analysis of forced-choice ESP experiments, Storm, Tressoldi, and Di Risio (2012) reported an average z-score of 0.570. This is typical of the small average psi effects found in statistical meta-analyses. Please note that this falls below the estimated average z-score of 0.757 in the above example (which assumes that psi does not exist). Storm et al. report a mean effect size per trial of 0.01 standard deviations. This is equivalent to a hit rate of 50.5 percent in guessing an electric coin toss. Statistical significance is an estimate of the probability that an effect of the given size would arise by chance. This is equivalent to the assumption that all the experimenters are non-filers who are honest and publish all of their studies. If frauds and filers lurk among the experimenters, then all bets are off. A non-zero effect size would be expected in the absence of psi if there are frauds and filers among the researchers. Such non-zero effect sizes will reach higher and higher significance levels as the number of published studies increases. Traditional significance tests are irrelevant if there are scoundrels in the pot. In this context, it should be noted that more orthodox areas of research such as psychology and medical research suffer from exactly the same problems of fraud and selective publication as does parapsychology. In fact, my analysis above has been largely based on reports in these two fields and is thus applicable to these fields as well. As a means of addressing the file drawer problem, Bösch (2004) suggested that psi experiments be preregistered before the data collection process. Kennedy (2011) proposes that parapsychology adopt the standard used in the pharmaceutical industry and that research protocols be developed and registered and calculations of statistical power (the ability to detect an effect of the predicted size) be performed prior to the data collection process. Caroline Watt (2013) has just established such a preregistry of parapsychological experiments, which should prove very helpful in addressing the issue of underreporting of nonsignificant studies. However, such preregistration does not address the problem of fraudulent experimenters. Preregistration could be “gamed” through registration on multiple sites. Also a semi-fraudulent researcher might run “practice studies” to perfect the experiment (i.e., until significant results are obtained) and only then “preregister” the experiment and report the results on a timedelayed basis. Such experimenters might even convince themselves that they are engaging in only a “white lie” so that their magnificent evidence may be published and taken seriously. Given the recent avalanche of exposed fraud in mainstream biological and psychological science, there is no doubt that parapsychologists will be increasingly scrutinized for possible fraud, even if fraud has not been explicitly exposed. Thus, parapsychologists would do well to adopt some of the fraud-resistant procedures discussed above (e.g. multiple observers and records, and independent and publically-verifiable data streams). The Repeatability Problem One of the reasons why parapsychology has not been embraced by the scientific establishment is that many or most researchers have been unable to obtain reliable evidence of psi. In the critic’s mind, this raises the suspicion that the evidence for psi may be due to undetected methodological errors, data selection, or possibly even fraud on the part of the experimenters. Parapsychologists have been quick to point out that many naturally occurring phenomena, such as ball lightning and meteorite landings, are not reproducible on demand but are nonetheless real. Interestingly, both ball lightning and meteorites were initially disputed by many scientists in much the same way as current scientists reject psi phenomena. What Pattern of Results Would Be Expected If Psi Does Not Exist? If psi does not exist, one would expect to see a series of fraudulent experimenters entering the field one by one. These individuals would be expected to exhibit the charisma, charm, narcissism, and ethical standards typical of psychopaths (Dutton, 2012). They would claim to have discovered marvelous experimental evidence of psi. To enhance the perceived originality of their research (as well as to dismiss the prior body of experimental psi research), they might be expected to coin a new term for psi, which they would then lay claim to as its discoverer. Nonfraudulent experimenters might then abandon lines of psi research that seem to have dried up to the point of sterility and jump on the new bandwagon in the hope of obtaining a significant result. As they do, the size effects in the new paradigm would be expected to decline, as more and more researchers would report an inability to replicate the new psi effect. On the other hand, the statistical significance level in the meta-analysis might be expected to increase as the sample size grows larger and larger. However, this would reflect the continuing presence of frauds and filers in the sample of experimenters rather than the existence of psi. The cycle would renew when another fraudulent researcher bursts upon the scene, setting in motion another growing snowball of wasted effort and time. If this is true, parapsychology’s heroes may be in fact its primary villains. However, even in this analysis most parapsychologists are assumed to be basically honest, and I think they are. However, contra Donny Osmond, “one bad apple do spoil the whole bunch, girl.” What Pattern of Results Would Be Expected If Psi Does Exist? What would be expected if psi does exist and could be manifested under conditions of experimental control? I for one would have expected that during the contagious public “ESP fever” that followed the publication of Rhine’s card-guessing results at Duke University, many more high-scoring individuals would have been discovered among the public. (My own sixth grade teacher tested me with Zener cards, long before I had heard of Rhine’s results). The silence from the general public on this issue is deafening. Similarly, I would have expected that efforts to boost scoring rates by selecting participants and experimental conditions that are psifavorable would have eventually led to the discovery of a psi effect that is replicable by the vast majority of qualified, independent investigators. This has not occurred. Does Psi Exist? To me, this question is a no-brainer. The pattern of experimental results is exactly what would be expected if there is no psi and quite different from the pattern that would be expected if psi exists. Fraud at rates known to occur in other disciplines is a much more parsimonious explanation of the data than is the postulation of mysterious and inexplicable psi powers. The only rational conclusion is that psi does not exist. However, at times I wonder if I am really rational Could the Existence of Psi Be Established? The answer is yes. New studies of spontaneous psi are needed. Collections of such cases can provide clues as to how psi operates, as suggested by Louisa Rhine. The usual counterexplanations of such cases, including fraud, false memory, and sensory cues, might be addressed through the thorough investigation of such cases, including interviewing witnesses. Striking, well-attested cases might further the acceptance of psi. Long forgotten phenomena, such as psi-trailing in animals (see Rhine & Feather, 1962) could be reinvestigated. Such reinvestigation would be facilitated by the Internet. Experimentally, the existence of psi could be established through experiments that are free from methodological errors and that could be repeated by the vast majority of competent scientists. References Anonymous (2013). Biomed retractions climb. Science, 339, 889. Bösch, H. (2004). Reanalyzing a meta-analysis of extra-sensory perception dating from 1940, the first comprehensive meta-analysis in the history of science. Paper presented at the 47th Annual Convention of the Parapsychological Association, Vienna University. Dutton, K. (2012). The wisdom of psychopaths. New York: Scientific American/Farrar, Straus and Giroux. Fang, F., and Casadevall, A. (2013, May/June). Why we cheat. Scientific American Mind, 31–37. Hyman, R. (1989). The elusive quarry: A scientific appraisal of psychical research. Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books. Ioannidis, J. (2012). Why science is not necessarily self-correcting. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 7, 645–654. John, L. K., Loewenstein, G., and Prelec, D. (2012). Measuring the prevalence of questionable research practices with incentives for truth telling. Psychological Science, 23, 525–531. Kennedy, J. E. (2011). Information in life, consciousness, quantum physics, and paranormal phenomena. Journal of Parapsychology, 75, 15–43. Markwick, B. (1978). The Soal-Goldney experiments with Basil Shackelton: New evidence of data manipulation. Proceedings of the Society for Psychical Research, 56, 250–277. Pashler, H., and Harris, C. R. (2012). Is the replicability crisis overblown? Three arguments examined. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 7, 531– 536. Rhine, J. B. (1974). A new case of experimenter unreliability. Journal of Parapsychology, 38, 215–225. Rhine, J. B. (1975). Comments: A second report on a case of experimenter fraud. Journal of Parapsychology, 39, 306–325. Rhine, J. B., and Feather, S. R. (1962). The study of cases of “psi-trailing” in animals. Journal of Parapsychology, 26, 1–22. Rhine, L. E. (1961). Hidden channels of the mind. New York: William Sloane Associates. Rosenthal, R. (1979). The file drawer problem and tolerance for null results. Psychological Bulletin, 86, 638–641. Scott, C., and Haskell, P. (1974). Fresh light on the Shackleton experiments. Proceedings of the Society for Psychical Research, 56, 43–72. Simmons, J. P., Nelson, L. D., and Simonsohn, U. (2011). False positive psychology: Undisclosed flexibility in data collection and analysis allows presenting anything as significant. Psychological Science, 22, 1359–1366. Schmidt, H., Morris, R., and Rudolph, L. (1986). Channeling evidence for a psychokinetic effect to independent observers. Journal of Parapsychology, 50, 1–15. Soal, S. G., and Bateman, F. (1954). Modern experiments in telepathy. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Stokes, D. M. (1987). Theoretical parapsychology. In S. Krippner (Ed.), Advances in parapsychological research. Volume 5 (pp. 77–189). Jefferson, NC: McFarland. Stokes, D. M. (1997a). Spontaneous psi phenomena. In S. Krippner (Ed.), Advances in parapsychological research. Volume 8 (pp. 6–87). Jefferson, NC: McFarland. Stokes, D. M. (1997b). The nature of mind. Jefferson, NC: McFarland. Stokes, D. M. (2007). The conscious mind and the material world. Jefferson, NC: McFarland. Stokes, D. M. (2014). Reimagining the soul. Jefferson, NC: McFarland. Storm, L., Ertel, S., and Rock, A. J. (2013). Paranormal effects and behavioural characteristics of participants in a forced-choice psi task: Ertel’s ball selection test under scrutiny. Australian Journal of Parapsychology, 13, 111–131. Storm, L., Tressoldi, P. E., and Di Risio, L. (2012), Meta-analysis of ESP studies, 1987–2010: Assessing the success of the forced-choice design in parapsychology. Journal of Parapsychology, 76. 243–273. Vogel, G. (2014). Suspected drug research blamed for massive death toll. Science, 343, 473–474. Watt, C. (2013). Registry for parapsychological experiments. Skeptical Inquirer, 37, 9. OceanofPDF.com Part Two: Research Methods and Statistical Approaches OceanofPDF.com CHAPTER 4 Experimental Methods in Anomalous Cognition and Anomalous Perturbation Research1 JOHN PALMER The purpose of this chapter is to introduce the wide variety of methods parapsychologists have developed over the years for testing anomalous cognition (AC) and anomalous perturbation (AP) in controlled laboratory situations, and to serve as an introductory guide to those who may wish to attempt such tests themselves. To choose intelligently which method to use in a particular experiment, it is first necessary to specify as clearly as possible the objectives of the research. Then it is necessary to determine what characteristics the test must have to meet these objectives and, finally, which available procedure includes the greatest number of these characteristics. The chapter is restricted to methods for testing psi, the dependent variable in most psi experiments. However, much modern psi research is aimed at understanding how psi works by manipulating test conditions or exploring the relation of psi scores to scores on personality tests or rating scales. The additional methodological principles needed for such studies are generally the same as those employed in mainstream psychology experiments and will not be covered here. Anomalous Cognition Illustration: A Card Guessing Test A simple example that illustrates many of the basic principles of an AC test is card guessing. As we will see later, the following example is not state-ofthe-art methodology, but it will suffice for present purposes. Take a deck of ordinary playing cards, shuffle it thoroughly, and place it face down on the table in front of you. Write down on a sheet of paper your guess as to the suit of the top card. Then remove the card from the deck, turn it over, and record its suit next to your guess for that card. Repeat this for the remaining 51 cards. The cards are called targets and your guesses are called responses. The 52 guessing events are called trials, and trials completed successively without a break are called a run. Thus, you completed one run. Next, count up the number of times your guess was correct. These correct guesses are called hits. The question you want to answer is whether you got enough hits to provide evidence of AC. To answer this question, we must apply statistics. This topic will be addressed in detail in chapter 7 in this volume, but it is appropriate to review some of the basics here. First, we must specify the number of hits you are likely to get by chance, which is called mean chance expectation or MCE, defined as the number of trials divided by the number of target alternatives, which in this case is four (the four suits). Thus MCE is 52/4, or 13. Note that MCE is only the mean (or average) number of hits you would obtain by chance if you completed a very large number of runs. On any given run, you are likely to get slightly more or slightly fewer than the 13 chance hits assuming no AC. An estimate of how much, on average, the number of chance hits is likely to deviate from MCE is reflected by the standard deviation. The question now becomes how likely is it that the number of hits you actually obtained, compared to MCE, can be attributed to chance. Following a somewhat arbitrary convention adopted by psychologists, we reject the chance or null hypothesis if the probability of your score being as far away from MCE as it was is less than one in 20, or .05. This is often expressed as p < .05. In our example, if you scored 20 hits or more, we would conclude (based on appropriate statistical analysis) that you had obtained a significant score and demonstrated AC. This is because a score that high will occur less than one in 20 times by chance. It of course is also possible to get fewer than 13 hits. This will occur by chance a little less than half the time, but if the score is low enough (in our example, 6 or less) we would attribute it to AC operating in a negative direction, somehow causing you to consistently avoid the target. This form of AC, called psimissing, occurs rather frequently. If we have theoretical or empirical reasons to predict in advance the direction of scoring, we would be entitled to apply a so-called one-tailed statistical test, which doubles the probability of statistical significance if the results are in the predicted direction. Ideally, one should only use a onetailed test when one is willing to ignore a significant outcome in the “wrong” direction, but there is some disagreement among parapsychologists (and statisticians) about how strictly this rule should be applied. Eliminating Alternative Interpretations Actually, it would be premature to conclude that a score of 20 or higher (or six or lower) on our card test means that you have demonstrated AC. A statistically significant score only indicates that the score probably cannot be entirely attributed to chance. We must be able to rule out other reasonable alternative interpretations of the extra-chance scoring before concluding that AC has been demonstrated. Sensory cues. The most common alternative interpretation of AC results is sensory cues. We must be sure that participants have no sensory contact with the targets, or with persons having knowledge of the targets or target order, prior to making their responses. This means that in a telepathy test the sender must have no sensory contact with the receiver; at the very least, they should be in separate rooms. In fact, they should be far enough apart so that even subliminal auditory cues are eliminated. If the sender must be within a few rooms of the participant, it is recommended that the sender be in an acoustically shielded room or chamber. Also, any experimenter who is in sensory contact with the person making the guesses (hereafter referred to generically as the participant) should be unaware of the targets or target order. Elimination of sensory cues is primarily common sense, but that is not to say that such cues are always apparent. Any sensory cue hypothesis, however far-fetched, is likely to be preferred over the AC hypothesis by most mainstream scientists and some parapsychologists. Recording and scoring errors. In our card guessing example, you have to double check (or, ideally, have someone else check) the accuracy of your recording of the hits to be sure you end up with the correct number. Nowadays, such scoring is commonly done by computers. Although this goes a long way to solving the problem, you have to be sure there are no bugs in the programs you use to record the targets and responses and to score the test. Nonrandom target sequences. It is also important for the target sequence to be unpredictable, or as random as possible. This is particularly crucial if the test is designed such that the participant is informed after each trial what the target for that trial was. If this modification were to be introduced into our card test and the target sequence had some nonrandom feature (e.g., no suit ever turning up twice in a row), participants might use this information to improve their scores. As soon as they caught on, perhaps unconsciously, they would avoid calling the same suit twice in a row. This would effectively increase the probability of a hit on each trial. Although logical inference is not usually a serious problem in tests without such trial-by-trial feedback, a related problem can occur if a bias in the target sequence happens to match a bias in the sequence of the participant’s responses. For example, if there were an excess of hearts at the beginning of the deck and you called a large number of hearts early in the run and then tried to compensate by calling few hearts toward the end of the run, an artifactual (i.e., illegitimate) excess of hits could result simply by a matching of the corresponding biases in the target and response sequences. Some Basic Distinctions and Choices A researcher confronted with the task of designing an AC test faces a number of choices. In the next main section, these choices will be outlined in a more or less sequential order. However, there are several major choices germane to our card-guessing example that it is appropriate to introduce at this point. Mode of Target Presentation: Telepathy, Clairvoyance, or Precognition Telepathy, clairvoyance, and precognition are philosophical or, more precisely, ontological distinctions that derive from the often implicit assumption some parapsychologists have made that AC is a quasiperceptual process. In practice, it is impossible to entirely isolate these subspecies of AC. If we modified our card test so that your friend “sent” you the cards, you could get the information either from your friend’s mind (telepathy) or from the card (clairvoyance). In either case, your friend could access the information as it existed at the time of the response or as it would exist at some future time (precognition). Strictly speaking, telepathy is impossible to demonstrate because there must be some objective record of the target sequence (even if it is coded) for purposes of scoring. Clairvoyance can be isolated from telepathy by generating the targets by a computer and destroying the target sequence as well as information about which trials were hits after the test has been scored and before anyone has seen these data. However, this assumes that a summary of the results is an insufficient telepathic source. Precognition can be isolated from contemporaneous AC if the target sequence does not exist and cannot be inferred from information available at the time the participant makes the response, but it is not possible to rule out using anomalous perturbation (AP), traditionally called psychokinesis, to affect a future target series to match the responses. The participant could use AP retroactively in the same way to succeed in a clairvoyance test. Because of these problems, it has become increasingly common for parapsychologists to define the types of AC operationally rather than ontologically. If a test involves a sender observing a target and trying to send it to a percipient, we call it telepathy. If no one is trying to send the targets to the participant, we call it clairvoyance. If in either case the target is not generated until after the participant makes the response, we call it precognition. There is no clear evidence that participants score better on one kind of test than the other, so the choice often depends on the personal taste of the researcher. Precognition tests have the advantage of eliminating sensory cues, because the target does not exist at the time of the response. Telepathy tests are the most difficult to control against sensory cues because of the need to prevent sensory contact with the sender. On the other hand, telepathy is more likely than precognition to seem plausible to participants. Trial-by-Trial Feedback Another choice faced by the researcher is whether or not to inform the participant after each trial that the response was a hit or a miss and/or the correct identity of the target. Such feedback might be useful if the objective is to train AC. Some parapsychologists suggest that such feedback heightens participants’ motivation and interest in the task (Tart, 1966) whereas others contend that it is likely to be distracting, frustrating, or anxiety-arousing (Kennedy, 1980b). A meta-analysis has shown that feedback improves scoring in forced-choice precognition experiments (Honorton & Ferrari, 1989). Modes of Response: Forced-Choice and Free-Response Testing procedures in which the participant’s responses are limited to a fixed set of alternatives, as in our card guessing test, are commonly called forced-choice tests. However, parapsychologists have turned increasingly to another kind of procedure in which the participant is allowed to report any impression that comes to mind. These free-response tests commonly employ more complex targets than playing cards to capitalize on the richness of the participant’s impressions. To score free-response tests, it is common for a judge (who might be the participant) to match or to otherwise assess the correspondences between a series of targets and responses. I will describe these procedures in more detail later in the chapter. Free-response tests have several advantages. By allowing participants to explore their minds freely, they capture the spontaneity characteristic of AC as it usually occurs in real life. They are generally more appealing to participants than forced-choice tests, which tend to get tedious after a while. They are especially appropriate if you want to study complex mental imagery in relation to AC. On the other hand, forced-choice tests are much easier to score than free-response tests. Because a large number of trials can be accumulated over a short period of time in forced-choice tests, they are ideal for comparing a participant’s performance on two or more sets or types of trials, or for assessing changes in scoring over time. In freeresponse tests, it is customary to conduct one trial per session. Duration or Length of Test In determining the length of a forced-choice test (i.e., the number of trials), one must strike a balance between competing considerations. If the test is too long, the participant is apt to become fatigued and scores might decline. Such “decline effects” have often been noted in psi tests (Palmer, 1978). On the other hand, enough trials must be accumulated to provide a relatively reliable measure of the participant’s AC. As a general rule in psychological testing, the longer the test the more reliably and accurately it measures the ability or trait tested. In AC tests, this is especially true if the number of target alternatives is large, say ten or greater. (For example, 52 trials would be too short in our card test if you guessed the ranks of the cards instead of their suits.) Researchers have adopted no strict convention regarding the length of forced-choice tests, but tests of between 50 and 100 trials per session are common, with a pause of a couple of minutes between each 25-trial run. The important principle, though, is to give as long a test as possible without fatiguing the participant. But always be sure to set the number of trials in advance and stick to it. Otherwise an artifact due to optional stopping may result, that is, stopping the test at a point which just happens to coincide with a higher than chance score. As mentioned earlier, free-response tests usually consist of one trial per session. They have been known to last anywhere from 5 to 45 minutes each. The principle here is to allow participants enough time to fully develop their impressions of the target. Such impressions do not always pop up right away, so both the experimenter and the participant need to be patient. Steps in an AC Test: Decisions and Tradeoffs In the remainder of the chapter, I will review in more detail and roughly in chronological order the steps a researcher must follow in designing and executing a good AC test and the decisions to make along the way. Selecting the Participants Psychics or “gifted” participants. The most obvious choice would seem to be to test someone who is “psychic,” but this is trickier than it seems. A person who has had many seemingly psychic experiences may not necessarily be able to produce AC on demand under laboratory conditions. Fortunately, there are a small number of people who seem to have at least some control over their AC faculties, and some of them have been willing to explore these apparent talents with scientists. However, working with talented participants is not always an easy task. They are often very sensitive people who have been ostracized because of their “gift.” As a result, the researcher may need a great deal of tact and interpersonal skill to do effective research with them. Many psychics have strong feelings about the kinds of tests in which they are willing to engage, and the researcher must be able to accommodate these preferences while still maintaining rigid experimental controls. On the other hand, some people who claim to be psychic are deluded or are charlatans out to exploit the field for fame and fortune. Such “psychics” may seek credibility by “triumphing” in scientific tests. Some may be hybrids: people with genuine psi abilities who supplement real AC with pseudo–AC when the situation requires it. These charlatans employ standard magic or mentalist tricks to mimic AC. Thus, the parapsychologist should have some familiarity with these techniques and be willing to consult with skilled magicians or mentalists when appropriate [chapter 6, this volume]. If a professed psychic is a stage performer or is known to have a magician’s skills, particular caution is required. Results with such persons are likely to be suspect regardless of how well controlled the test appears to be. Such skepticism may not always be logically justified, but it is a good reason to consider whether research with such participants is worth the effort. Finally, some psychics, particularly those who earn a living at it, may be tempted to seek publicity that might misrepresent or exaggerate the outcome of the research, or otherwise embarrass the investigator or the field of parapsychology. Special participant populations. An alternate approach for obtaining talented participants is mass screening. Tart (1976), for example, gave a short card guessing test to hundreds of students in classes at a large American university. Recognizing that a few would obtain significant scores by chance, he retested the “successful” students on another forcedchoice test. Those students who continued to score significantly were then chosen for more extensive investigation. Yet another approach is to work with participants who may or may not appear to be talented but who have other skills or attributes that would make them especially suitable for AC research. Honorton (1997) found that successful participants in a freeresponse test called the ganzfeld (see below) had four characteristics: previous psi testing, previous psi experience, practice of a mental discipline such as meditation, and “feeling” and “perceiving” personality styles as measured by the Myers-Briggs Type Indicator. There also is evidence that people with artistic skills perform especially well in the ganzfeld (Dalton, 1990; Schlitz & Honorton, 1992) [see chapter 9, this volume]. Unselected participants. Although research with talented participants captures most of the public attention, the bulk of the research in parapsychology has been conducted using ordinary people who volunteer out of curiosity or interest in psi, or college students who may get academic credit for participating in the study. This research strategy is predicated on the assumption made by most—but not all—parapsychologists that psi is an ability common to all and distributed in the population much like intelligence. Although few such persons are likely to be psychic enough to score significantly on their own, collectively the total or average of their scores may be high (or low) enough to achieve significance. Because of the large number of scores obtained in such group experiments, a lower total or average score is required for statistical significance than ordinarily is the case in research with a single participant. Working with unselected participants requires patience, as the magnitude of the results is likely to be small and studies do not replicate as consistently as we would like. On the brighter side, unselected participants are readily accessible, relatively easy and pleasant to work with, and their results can be generalized more readily to other people than those obtained from more specialized populations. Animals as subjects. A final option available to the researcher is to test animals. This choice assumes, of course, that animals are capable of manifesting psi. The evidence we have suggests that if psi exists, animals probably have it as well as humans (Morris, 1970) [see chapters 11 and 27]. There is no intrinsic reason to choose one species over another, but most “anpsi” research has been conducted with rodents, cats, and dogs, largely for reasons of convenience. The most obvious reason for testing animals is an interest in exploring AC in a particular species. Second, a researcher may wish to examine the relation between AC and relatively simple motivational or cognitive factors without having to deal with the complexities of these characteristics in humans. Finally, certain studies involving drugs or noxious stimulation such as electric shocks might be prohibited with humans for ethical reasons, but not with animals. On the other hand, many people (including many scientists) consider such studies to be unethical even with animals unless substantial and tangible benefits from the research can be foreseen. Parapsychologists tend to be a rather humane lot, so one finds very little research of this type in the parapsychological literature. Selecting the Target Material The choice of target material for AC tests is limited only by the creativity of the researcher. Although the exercise of such creativity is often beneficial, the use of standardized targets has the important advantage of allowing greater comparability of results across experiments. In this section I will examine some of the various types of target material used in AC experiments. Forced-Choice Tests Types of targets. In forced-choice tests, the standard targets for many years consisted of a deck of 25 cards containing five of each of five symbols: circle, cross, waves, square, and star. J. B. Rhine (1934/1973) selected these symbols after consulting with a perceptual psychologist, because they were simple, easily discriminable, and emotionally neutral. Discriminability, at least, is still considered an attribute of good forced-choice targets, but they need not be dull. It sometimes may be advantageous to use targets with multiple attributes, each of which can be scored independently. These are called multiple-aspect targets (Kennedy, 1980a). An example is the deck of playing cards in our earlier example, where the independent attributes are suit and rank. The multiple-aspect nature of such targets can be capitalized upon by having participants respond to each attribute on each trial. We can then compare the results on the different attributes and also assess whether participants obtain more exact hits than we would expect by chance given their rate of success on the component attributes. Physical cards have given way for the most part to computer displays of targets, with the order determined by an electronic random event generator (REG) or a mathematical algorithm activated by the computer software. These mechanisms, described more fully below, generate a target for each trial and then record the targets, responses, and hits. The graphics capabilities of computers give the researcher tremendous flexibility in creating appealing and motivating target displays. Finally, AC targets need not be visual. In one study, the targets were five musical selections recorded on tape (Keil, 1965). In short, any discriminable stimulus is a potential AC target. Number of target alternatives. The number of target alternatives in a forced-choice AC test generally ranges from 2 to 10. A smaller number of alternatives is easier to keep track of and may be more reinforcing or encouraging to participants because they provide a greater proportion of hits. They also may decrease the possibility of participants confusing their impressions of one target symbol with those of another. Tests with a smaller number of alternatives are also easier to evaluate statistically if the number of trials is small, because the distribution of scores more readily approximates the normal curve, a mathematically defined, bell-shaped distribution of numbers required for the application of many statistical tests. A large number of alternatives has the advantage of reducing the proportion of chance hits relative to AC hits. This is especially a consideration in training projects in which the participant receives feedback after each trial and is asked to try to discriminate internal sensations or impressions associated with correct as opposed to incorrect responses; chance hits in such a context provide the participant with false feedback that makes such discrimination difficult. In practice, most researchers split the difference and use tests with four or five target alternatives. Free-Response Tests Types of targets. Free-response targets are generally richer and more complex than forced-choice targets. Examples from past experiments include line drawings (e.g., Stuart, 1945), magazine photographs (e.g. Stanford & Palmer, 1975), postcard prints of famous paintings (e.g. Ullman, Krippner, & Vaughan, 1973), movie clips (Honorton et al., 1990), and geographical or architectural sites (Targ & Puthoff, 1977). Researchers agree that free-response targets should be motivating or arousing to participants, but they disagree on how best to accomplish this. Some believe that the targets should represent emotional or archetypal themes likely to stimulate unconscious mental processes and bring latent imagery to the surface. Such targets are especially appropriate when studying AC in altered states of consciousness, particularly dreams. On the other hand, researchers who use geographical sites as targets stress that their realism and the potential practical application of identifying real targets is an important motivating factor that is absent when the targets are not real (Targ & Puthoff, 1977). May, Spottiswoode, and James (1994) have argued based on theoretical considerations that remote viewing targets should be characterized by a high change in Shannon’s entropy such as change in color intensity across pixels in a photograph. Size and structure of the target pool. Whatever type of target material is selected, it is good to have a large pool of potential targets to draw from, so that a full range of content is represented. If possible, the pool should consist of at least 50 potential targets. Because free-response tests are usually evaluated statistically as if they were forced-choice tests, it is often desirable to divide the pool in advance into sets of from 2 to 10 pictures each. The members of each set should be as discriminable as possible in terms of semantic content, geometric form of objects, and type of emotion the picture is likely to evoke. Getting a group of judges to make similarity ratings of all possible pairs of pictures is a time-consuming but effective way of helping to assure that sets meet this criterion. Determining the Sequence of Targets As noted earlier in discussing our card guessing example, it is important that participants not be able to infer the order of the targets. Such inference is less of a problem in free-response experiments with only one trial per participant, but it is still important that each picture have an equal opportunity of being selected as the target for each session. The best way to assure that this condition is met is to select the sequence of targets in as random a manner as possible. Methods of Randomization Shuffling. In card tests, the traditional method of obtaining a random sequence of cards is simply to shuffle the deck thoroughly and cut it. However, shuffling is not a reliable method of assuring randomness and it is not used in modern AC research. Random algorithms. A more reliable method is to use an algorithm, a mathematical formula that produces a sequence of random numbers. The numbers that appear in published random number tables are produced in this way. There are also algorithms in the form of computer programs that can be accessed directly. It is usually required to start the process by entering “seed numbers.” In either case, it is necessary to assure that the algorithm’s output has been thoroughly checked for randomness by statistical tests. An algorithm by Marsaglia and Zaman (1987) has become something of a standard in parapsychology because of how thoroughly its output was tested for randomness. Such output usually consists of digits that are then translated into the corresponding targets according to a predetermined code. For example, in our card guessing example, the code might be: 1 or 2 = spade, 3 or 4 = heart, 5 or 6 = diamond, 7 or 8 = club, with 9 and 0 skipped over. Random event generators. REGs generate outcomes electronically, often at a very rapid rate, most commonly using either electronic noise (like radio static) and/or the emission of electrons from a very weak radioactive source (e.g., strontium 90) to assure random selection (e.g., Schmidt, 1970). The researcher can cause the machine to select a single target or a whole sequence of targets by simply pressing a button. Unlike most other kinds of forced-choice tests, in REG tests it is common for the REG to select the target before each trial, rather than the full target sequence being generated beforehand. The implications of this feature are greatest in precognition tests, because the time interval between response and target designation is considerably shortened. Confirming randomness. When using an REG it is imperative that you perform extensive randomness tests at the beginning and end of the experiment to be sure that the device is creating random outputs. The researcher should also conduct a randomness test of the target sequence actually used in the experiment, summed across all participants and sessions, to be sure that at least each possible target and target pair appear an equal number of times. Contamination by experimenter psi. All of the above procedures have to a greater or lesser extent a potential drawback that becomes an issue whenever it is important to isolate the source of psi in an AC experiment. The problem is that the experimenter, or whoever else generates the target sequence, might use his or her own psi to produce a sequence that happens to match the participant’s response sequence to a greater than chance degree. The problem is most severe when the targets are produced by an REG and there is no good way to overcome it. Thus, I recommend never selecting AC targets this way, using an algorithm instead. But with this method you must be sure to select the seed numbers in a way that is not susceptible to influence by psi. In most of my studies I seed the Marsaglia algorithm with the numbers 1 and 2. Experimenter psi becomes particularly problematic if an REG is used to assign participants to experimental and control conditions. This mistake was made in a prominent psychic healing study in which participants in the group that received healing may have shown more improvement than the controls not because they were healed but because the experimenter could have unconsciously used his or her own psi (AP) to influence the REG to place those who would have the milder symptoms in the experimental (healing) condition (Sicher, Targ, & Moore, 1998). Forms of Target Dependency Random selection of targets generally guarantees that the targets will be independent of one another, that is, no target can be predicted from knowledge of the others. However, certain research designs impose limits on target independence even when the selection procedure is otherwise random. We will now discuss the two most prevalent of these research designs. Closed versus open decks. The most common procedure that limits target independence is the use of a closed deck. A closed deck is a target sequence in which the number of times each target appears is stipulated in advance. A playing card deck is a closed deck because, for example, each suit appears exactly 13 times, only the order of their appearance is randomized. In contrast, sequences derived from random algorithms or REGs are generally open decks; each alternative can appear any number of times, although in most situations they will tend to appear with about equal frequency. In free-response tests, a closed-deck target sequence is one in which each picture is the target for one and only one trial. This procedure is sometimes called selection without replacement, because once a picture is selected for a trial it is not put back in the pool and thus is not available for subsequent trials. On the other hand, an open deck is generated by selection with replacement: Once a picture is selected it is put back in the pool and has as much chance as any other picture of being selected for a subsequent trial. The concept of target dependency in closed decks can be readily grasped by considering a standard AC card guessing test in which the participant is informed of the target after each trial. By keeping track of how many of each symbol has appeared, the participant can identify with certainty the target for the last trial of the run; in other words, the 25th target is predictable from knowledge of the preceding 24. This could only happen in a free-response test if participants knew in advance which pictures were to be included in the target set. But if the pictures in the pool are not highly diversified and participants receive trial-by-trial feedback of targets, they could increase their chances of getting a high score on the test by avoiding mention of characteristics present in earlier targets. For example, if the target picture on trial 1 included a bridge, participants could improve their scores artifactually by not mentioning bridges in their responses on later trials. The upshot of all this is that closed decks should be avoided in experiments where participants are given trial-by-trial feedback of targets. Closed decks can be used when such feedback is not given, but corrections may need to be applied to the statistical evaluation of the results. The stacking effect. Another kind of target dependency occurs when more than one participant responds to the same target sequence. In parapsychological jargon this is called the stacking effect. It is most likely to occur when participants are tested in a group setting such as a classroom. The target sequence in effect is being duplicated for each participant in the experiment, hence the dependency. The bias is relatively minor in forced choice tests with relatively long target sequences, but it can be a serious problem in free-response testing in which the target “sequence” might consist of only one trial. Say, for example, a test is given to a class of 30 students in which the target happens to be a scene of a lake with trees near it. Because many people automatically think of such things when asked to spontaneously generate mental imagery, you could end up with a lot of hits having nothing to do with AC. (Likewise, if the target happened to be something obscure, you might get pseudo psi-missing). As more targets are included in the test, such biases eventually wash out. To be safe, it is best to avoid the stacking effect whenever possible, even in forced-choice tests. In group clairvoyance or precognition tests, the best solution is to simply generate a separate independent, target sequence for each participant. This becomes more of a problem in telepathy tests because a separate sender for each percipient is required. Preparing the Participant Putting the Participant at Ease Experimenters’ interactions with their research participants should be conducted in a friendly and supportive manner that puts the participant at ease and inspires confidence. Such an approach is not only mandated by humanistic considerations, but it is also likely to help participants achieve a high score. The idea of psi can be threatening to people, perhaps at an unconscious level, and most parapsychologists believe it can be suppressed if the social and (to a lesser extent) the physical environment is not supportive. The only exception to this advice would be experiments in which the social or physical situation is to be manipulated to test an experimental hypothesis about the effect of such a manipulation on AC scores. But even in this case a humanistic approach should be adopted as much as possible, and the experimenter should explain to the participant at the end of the session why the manipulation was necessary. One should also avoid testing contexts that participants find uncomfortable. For example, it is not a good idea to give computer tests to participants who are uncomfortable with computers. Also, participants who are even a little claustrophobic are unlikely to give you good results if you test them in an fMRI chamber, as was done in a famously nonsignificant experiment by Moulton and Kosslyn (2008). When it is necessary to test participants in unfavorable circumstances to evaluate a hypothesis, the experimenter should ask participants to rate their discomfort and use these ratings as a control variable in the statistical analysis. Inducing Altered States of Consciousness In some experiments, the researcher may wish to further prepare the participant for the AC test by inducing an altered state of consciousness (ASC). Such inductions are particularly common prior to free-response tests, where ASCs may help the participant to access complex imagery or impressions that might be relevant to the target. Not all ASCs are considered to be psi-conducive. Those commonly induced by psychedelic drugs such as LSD, for example, may be too extreme and disorienting for AC testing. The participant must be able to maintain enough alertness and self-control to orient toward the test while at the same time being free from the constraints of overly structured thought processes [see chapters 9 and 12, this volume]. This is a delicate balance that can best be achieved through less extreme ASCs induced without chemicals. Types of ASC inductions. Traditionally, the most common procedure used to induce an ASC in AC research has been hypnosis. However, the two most popular procedures in recent years have been progressive relaxation and the ganzfeld. Progressive relaxation was developed by psychologist Edmund Jacobson (1938/1974) to help people cope with stress. The person is asked to alternately tense and relax a sequence of specific muscle groups (e.g. toes, calves, thighs, etc.) and to notice the contrast between the feelings of tension and relaxation. The body can become extremely relaxed following this procedure. A modification of the procedure that is sometimes used in AC experiments is to have participants simply imagine relaxing their muscles without actually doing so. The progressive relaxation exercise is customarily followed by stilling the mind by having the participant imagine relaxing scenes. The ganzfeld procedure is based on the principle of perceptual deprivation, eliminating sources of patterned or meaningful stimulation from the external environment. Patterned visual stimulation is eliminated by affixing acetate hemispheres (halves of ping-pong balls) over the participant’s eyes and shining a moderately bright white or colored light (red is generally used) through them. Patterned auditory stimulation is eliminated by playing white or, preferably, pink noise (which sounds like a waterfall) through comfortable headphones. (If pink noise is used, waterfalls should be avoided as potential targets!) No formal attempts to exclude tactile stimulation are usually included, but the participant should either be lying down or seated in a comfortable reclining chair. The participant is left in the ganzfeld between 20 and 45 minutes. Participants are generally asked to observe and/or report their imagery during the reception period. Other induction procedures used include meditation and brainwave biofeedback, particularly alpha and theta frequencies [see chapter 10, this volume]. Are ASCs necessary? Not all parapsychologists are sold on the value of ASC inductions. Advocates of the remote viewing procedure, for example, insist that equally good results can be obtained in normal waking consciousness (Targ & Puthoff, 1977), although I know of one case in which a prominent reviewer admitted to me that he enters an ASC, unaided by any props, before a trial. In fact, artificial induction techniques should not be used with persons who have developed their own procedures for entering an altered state; an induction such as the ganzfeld may only get in the way. ASCs are likely to be most effective when the target material is abstract, archetypal, or dreamlike, whereas they may be less psi-conducive when the targets are realistic. Testing and Response Procedures The procedures for standard forced-choice tests are fairly straightforward and I have nothing further to say about them here. I do have some additional points to make about free-response testing. Free-response methods. The participant should be asked to carefully observe whatever impressions come to awareness. These include sounds, bodily sensations, and emotions, as well as visual images. It is recommended that participants avoid censoring their impressions, and for remote viewing studies it is additionally recommended that they minimize interpreting them (McMoneagle, 2000). Often, for example, a participant will correctly apprehend the shape of a target object but be led astray by an improper interpretation or labeling of it. It is also best to allow images to come independently of one another and to avoid trains of logical associations. Participants can either write down their impressions or report them orally. In the latter case, the experimenter can either transcribe them directly or record them on tape for later transcription. It is sometimes a good idea to have participants draw their impressions, particularly in remote viewing studies. The researcher must decide whether to have participants give ongoing reports of their impressions during the reception period or wait until afterwards. Ongoing reporting helps assure that the participant will not forget to report some impressions, but it also can be distracting and interrupt the flow of imagery or the altered state, especially if the participant is inexperienced. Another decision the researcher faces is whether to be present in the room with the participant during the reception period. Some participants may find the experimenter’s presence reassuring while others may find it uncomfortable or distracting. The alternative is to have the experimenter in another room monitoring the participant via intercom, and that is the most commonly used procedure. It is often desirable for the experimenter to ask participants to elaborate on their impressions or to describe them more precisely, generally after the reception period. In the latter case, the experimenter should read the initial reports back to the participants to jog their memories. Obviously if the experimenter interacts with participants in such a way, he or she should not know the identity of the target. Ideally, the experimenter should not even be aware of the target pool. For example, if the participant accurately apprehends one aspect of the target, a careless experimenter who knows the target pool might guide the participant to elaborate this imagery in such a way as to artifactually increase its degree of correspondence to the target. Thus a modest hit comes to look like a striking hit. Participants, of course, can do the same thing on their own, and this is one reason for keeping even participants unaware of the target pool in free-response experiments (Irwin, 1980). A second reason is that the less participants know about the target pool, the less their responses are likely to be biased by logical constraints; one key to successful performance on AC tests seems to be spontaneity (Stanford, 1975). Physiological Response Methods In most AC tests the participant makes an overt, behavioral response representing some conscious impression of the identity of the target. However, parapsychologists have theorized that AC information may exist unconsciously but fail to reach consciousness because it is repressed or because it is distorted when it interacts with other mental processes (e.g., L. E. Rhine, 1962). Can such information be retrieved? One solution is to tap the involuntary physiological processes of the participant. More often than not, the choice has been the activity of the autonomic nervous system [see chapter 18, this volume]. This system, among other things, controls our physiological reactions to stress or danger. The autonomic measures most commonly used by parapsychologists are the plethysmograph (a measure of changes in blood volume in the finger due to constriction or dilation of blood vessels) and the electrodermal response (a measure of the activation of sweat glands). Because these responses reflect emotional arousal, the target sequence must consist of a random ordering of emotionally arousing and emotionally neutral targets. Examples of emotional target stimuli are index cards containing names of significance to the percipient mixed in with blank cards or cards with neutral names (e.g., Schouten, 1976). The design of the experiment is thus basically the same as in any forced-choice test; the participant’s score is a function of the degree of physiological response on the emotional trials as compared to the neutral ones. Nowadays the most common methodological paradigm is presentiment, a precognition procedure in which differential electrodermal responses to observed emotional or neutral pictures have been found 3 seconds before the picture selected by the REG [see chapter 18, this volume]. Less frequently, brainwaves (measured by the electroencephalograph, or EEG) are used as the response measure. In one study, a strobe light was flashed into the eyes of an agent on randomly selected trials, disrupting her normal resting EEG pattern. A similar effect was noted in the EEG record of a percipient seated in a different room (May, Targ, & Puthoff, 1976). In the case of presentiment, parapsychologists have discovered that in some cases participants can demonstrate a significant result because of a “logical” but invalid expectation that the next stimulus will be reliably different than the immediately preceding one in terms of emotionality. There is currently a debate about the best way to handle the problem (Dalkvist, Mossbridge, & Westerlund, 2013; Kennedy, 2013.) Covert Test Methods One characteristic generally shared by the tests we have considered so far (with the exception of some tests employing physiological responses) is that the participants are quite aware that they are being tested for AC and that their responses are potentially AC-mediated. However, this often is not the way AC operates in the real world. For example, a person may dream of an airplane crash and not realize that the dream may have been psychic until reading about the crash in the newspaper the next day. Conventional AC tests also may engage conscious or unconscious psychological defenses capable of blocking AC. Recognizing these difficulties, parapsychologists have devised ingenious procedures for testing AC covertly. These procedures rely on other kinds of tests structured in such a way as to be scoreable for AC. For example, Johnson (1973) adapted an envelope test to an exam in a psychology class. Instead of a sequence of AC symbols, each opaque envelope contained answers to a randomly selected half of the exam questions. The exam itself was taped to the outside of the envelope. The students had no idea that their exam was a covert AC test. Their scores were the differences between their test scores on the items “answered” inside the envelopes and their scores on the other items. Recently, Bem (2011) reported a series of precognition studies in which stimuli that have been shown to affect performance on standard cognitive psychological tasks (e.g., a list of words to memorize) are presented after the performance test instead of before [see chapter 18, this volume]. A disadvantage of fully covert tests is that they require the experimenter to deceive the participant about the nature of the study. Some researchers consider such deception to be a breach of ethics. With academic exams, there is a potential ethical problem if the manipulation could influence students’ grades in the course. Test methods with animals. AC tests with animals can be considered examples of covert tests because animals are not aware they are being tested for psi. In this case, parapsychologists have borrowed procedures from experimental psychologists who study animal learning. For example, a rat can be taught to discriminate levels of brightness by placing it in a box containing two adjacent bars with an illuminable disk above each one. On each trial the two disks light up. One is brighter than the other, which one being determined randomly on each trial. The rat must learn to press the bar under the brighter disk. If it does so, it receives a food pellet as a reward. To turn this into an AC test, it is only necessary to equate the brightness of the two lights, forcing the rat to use AC to determine which bar to press. Another example is avoidance learning. In an ordinary psychology experiment, the experimenter might place a rat in a cage with an electrified grid floor and a short barrier dividing the cage into two equally sized compartments. The rat must learn that whenever it hears a certain sound stimulus it has 5 seconds to jump the barrier to the other compartment. If it fails to do so, it receives punishment in the form of a shock. To make this an AC test, the floor of the box can be attached to an REG which randomly chooses one of the two compartments to receive shock on each trial (Duval & Montredon, 1968). The rat must use precognition to locate itself in the other compartment. As the avoidance learning procedures involve pain to the animal, it would seem ethically advisable to use procedures in which the reinforcements are positive. Scoring the AC Test Forced-choice tests. Scoring of forced-choice AC tests is usually a straightforward matter. If the test is conducted with an REG or computer, the machine can do the scoring. It is also important to be sure that scores are transferred properly to all statistical software programs or data sheets during data analysis. Free-response tests. Scoring of free-response tests is much more complicated than scoring of forced-choice tests. Most free-response scoring methods require that a judge, who may or may not be the participant, assess the degree of correspondence between the participant’s impressions on a given trial and the target for that trial. If a closed-deck target selection procedure is used, the judge may be asked to match up the targets and responses over a series of trials. At least one of these sequences must be randomized. If an open-deck procedure is chosen, the judge might be asked to pick out the target for each trial from among the members of a set of potential targets for that trial. The location of the target within the judging set must be randomized, separately for each trial. If the responses consist of psychic readings for a group of individuals, each reading may be broken down into component phrases and the judge asked to determine whether or not each phrase applies to each individual. No one really has any clear idea what specifically to look for in judging free-response correspondences, and the nature of the correspondence is likely to vary depending on the individual participant and the nature of the targets and test procedure. This is a problem that can only be solved by more research. In the meantime, common sense is the best guide for the prospective judge. A different approach to scoring free-response tests is to define a set of target characteristics (e.g., buildings in a remote viewing experiment) and then code each target for the presence or absence of each characteristic. The judge then codes the participant’s response for the presence or absence of the same characteristics. The participant’s score is the number of correct matches. This approach has been applied to both the ganzfeld (Honorton, 1975) and remote viewing (Jahn, Dunne, & Jahn, 1980; May et al., 1990) paradigms. A drawback of this atomistic approach is that it fails to make use of the judge’s capacity to integrate the information presented in both the target and the response. For instance, in an informal ganzfeld trial I conducted using Honorton’s (1975) pool, the participant correctly identified the target as Santa Claus but only matched 3 of the 10 target characteristics correctly, receiving a below-chance score for the trial! The problem is somewhat less severe in remote viewing studies because the presence or absence of features is closer to what the viewer is aiming for than it is with the ganzfeld. Participant judging versus independent judging. A controversial issue among parapsychologists is whether it is better to have participants serve as judges of their own responses or to employ independent judges who are not otherwise involved with the experiment. As usual, each alternative has its advantages. One obvious advantage of having participants be the judges is that they are the ones most intimately familiar with their own impressions. Even if they describe their impressions in great detail for independent judging, something is bound to be lost in the translation. Moreover, only the participant is likely to be able to evaluate symbolic correspondences, especially if the symbolism is personal. For example, an independent judge is unlikely to give a high score to a response with a religious theme if the target was a bluebird. Yet the participant might give this correspondence a very high score if the bluebird happened to be the symbol of a religious sect to which he or she belonged. But independent judging also has its advantages. Persons can be selected who seem to have particular skill in judging or who have been trained to look for particular things in the protocols. If a group of participants is being tested and each participant is the judge for his or her own trial, the differences in the scores are likely to be influenced by differences in the styles or skill of the (participant) judges. These judging idiosyncrasies are eliminated if the same (independent) judge scores all trials. In scoring methods that require the participant as judge to examine pictures in the target pool other than the target, these other pictures might serve as unintentional precognition targets that could influence the participant’s impressions. In other words, the participant might look ahead precognitively to the judging task during the reception period. If independent judges are used, the participant need be shown no other picture than the target. Finally, in studies where it is important to identify the specific source of AC, there exists the problem that AC might contaminate the judging process per se. If the participants are the judges, there is little the investigator can do to detect this. If independent judges are used, persons who seem to have minimal AC ability themselves can be selected. The possibility of contamination can be reduced further by using several judges and averaging the scores they assign to each trial. Not only does this procedure improve the reliability of the final scores, but if the scores assigned by one judge are contaminated by AC in the judging process this effect is likely to be washed out by the scores assigned by the other judges. Sources of judging bias. It is obviously essential that the judge have no information about the identity of the target for each trial during the judging task, that is, the judge must be “masked” or “blinded.” One potential source of such information is available in telepathy studies in which the participant handles a target picture that is later included among the set of materials given to the judge. For example, the picture might reveal extra signs of handling (e.g., bent edges, fingerprints) or the odor of a perfume or cologne that the agent was wearing (Palmer, 1983). One way to avoid such contamination is to have duplicate sets of target materials, one set to be handled only by agents and the other set only by judges, but a better way is to present the judging set by computer. When the judge is someone other than the participant, careful attention must be paid to how the transcripts of the participant’s responses are edited. As a general rule, the transcripts should not be edited at all; even remarks that on the surface might seem to be irrelevant to the task might reveal emotions or attitudes that have something to do with the target. On the other hand, transcripts sometimes contain comments that could bias the experiment, especially if the same participant is completing more than one trial. In remote viewing experiments, for example, a participant might refer to “that lake which was the target yesterday” or comment that “I can’t see the target very well because it is raining.” An alert judge could use such information to help identify the target. For example, the judge could rule out a lake as being the target in the first example if he or she knew that a closed deck target selection procedure had been utilized. The judge could at least narrow down the choice of possible targets in the second example if photographs of the target sites taken by the agent at the time of the trial constituted the target material given to the judge. These artifacts became a topic of considerable debate about the SRI remote viewing experiments (Palmer, 1986). The researcher or some person not otherwise involved in the experiment should carefully examine transcripts to eliminate potentially biasing statements prior to the judging. Anomalous Perturbation In this section, I will examine methodological issues pertaining to the other major branch of parapsychology, anomalous perturbation (AP), which has traditionally been called micro-psychokinesis (PK) [see chapters 20 and 21]. Anomalous force (AF) effects on larger systems (erstwhile macro–PK) are discussed in chapters 6 and 19. Many of the principles and recommendations described earlier in this chapter for AC tests also apply to AP tests. The participant’s task in an AP or AF experiment is to paranormally influence the state or motion of a physical object or system. In so doing, the participant must be rendered incapable of exerting any physical effect on the object or system. This includes indirect influence by means such as magnets or the induction of air currents as well as by direct touching. As for the participant’s orientation to the task, most parapsychologists would recommend an attitude of passive volition. But the evidence on this point is by no means conclusive and different strategies may work best for different people. AP effects can rarely be identified as such by the naked eye and usually require the application of statistics for their detection. Because they are readily adaptable to laboratory procedures, the methods for investigating them tend to become standardized and generally adopted. Targets and Test Procedures In AP research, it is important that the object or system to be influenced be sensitive or labile, that is, it should require a minimal amount of physical energy to change it from one of its potential target states to another one. Random Event Generators By far the most common method of testing AP in modern parapsychology is to have participants attempt to influence (hardware) REGs. In conjunction with computer graphics, REGs can readily be adapted for AP testing by having the participant aim for a given outcome to be generated on each trial or group of trials. Many REGs can produce sequences on their own without the participant pressing a button to activate each trial, often at very rapid rates (e.g., 300 per second) that allow large quantities of data to be accumulated in a short period of time. Some physicists are particularly interested in those REGs in which the outcomes are determined by the emission of electrons from a radioactive source, because the influence of such a subatomic process is especially relevant to quantum mechanics. Other REGs use electronic noise sources such as Zener diodes that are sufficiently sensitive for AP testing. In addition to giving ongoing feedback, REG tests that take advantage of computer graphic capabilities can provide the participant with a goal that is more comprehensible and psychologically captivating than the behavior of the REG per se. A particularly appealing option in this regard is to have participants play video games in which winning the game requires influencing the output of the REG (Honorton & Tremmel, 1980). Another desirable feature of REGs is that they can be attached to peripheral equipment that can segregate test trials that are generated at moments when the participant is thought to be in a psi-conducive state. In one successful application of this principle, trials were classified according to whether or not the participant’s brainwaves at the time were in the alpha range (Honorton & Tremmel, 1979). Movement of Objects Different procedures are needed if the investigator wants to study effects on objects that can be seen with the naked eye. To qualify as AP rather than AF, the attempt must be to influence the movement of an object already in motion. The traditional way to test this kind of AP is dice throwing. Having a person throw the dice as in a casino is taboo, because the person’s skill at dice throwing provides an obvious alternative to the psi hypothesis. Thus, in tests of this type the dice are thrown by a machine. The participant presumably influences the dice after they are ejected by the machine, but in theory they could be influencing the operation of the machine itself. An alternative type of test is the placement test. The dice machine can readily be modified for placement testing by dividing the surface onto which the dice are ejected lengthwise into two halves. The participant’s task is to make the dice fall more frequently on one side than the other, the probability of a hit thus becoming one-half for each trial. An example of this principle in the modern era is the use of a 10' × 6' “random mechanical cascade” (Dunne, Nelson, & Jahn, 1988). Nine thousand Styrofoam balls are released and cascade downward into 19 collection bins such that they tend to form a Gaussian distribution. However, because this ideal distribution can be compromised by various environmental factors such as temperature and humidity, results are compared not to theoretical chance but rather to the differences among three participant intentions: bias the distribution to the right, bias it to the left, and no intention (baseline). This form of analysis should be applied in all placement tests, regardless of the particular apparatus. Ambient Energy A procedure based on physical principles similar to those governing the REG is to attempt AP influence on various forms of ambient energy. The easiest of such energies to isolate experimentally is temperature. Schmeidler (1973) asked participants to use their AP to modify the temperature at a specific point in space and measured the result with a highly sensitive kind of thermometer called a thermistor, which was sealed inside a thermos container to eliminate the effect of outside room temperature. As an additional control, other thermistor units were placed elsewhere in the room. A trial was considered a hit if the temperature change recorded by the target thermistor was greater than the changes recorded by the controls. Biological Systems The growing interest in the possibility of psychic healing has led many parapsychologists to explore AP effects on biological systems, now referred to as distant mental interactions with living systems (DMILS) [chapter 18]. The basic strategy is similar to that used by Schmeidler in her thermistor experiment. Separate target and control systems, initially in the same biological state, are assigned to each trial. The participant attempts to exert an AP effect on the target system. If the degree of change is greater in the target than in the control system at the end of a specified period of time, the trial is scored a hit. The target systems used in such experiments have ranged from hemolysis of red blood cells (Braud, 1990) to plants (Grad, 1963) to mice (Watkins & Watkins, 1974). In another application similar in concept to the placement test, a participant attempted to use AP to cause tiny one-celled organisms called paramecia to migrate from the center of a Petri dish into one of its four quadrants (Richmond, 1952). Although simplicity is generally the goal in selecting biological target systems, humans have occasionally been studied in such experiments. For example, Braud (1978) successfully activated or suppressed the electrodermal responses of participants in a free-response AC test. In such studies, it is necessary to compare trials in which influence is attempted with trials in which it is not. The order of these trials should be randomized. If the person to be influenced is not aware of whether a given trial is experimental or control, each type of trial should occur an equal number of times. If the person is aware, the randomization should be open-deck. The same principles apply when one seeks to influence a participant’s behavior or cognition. For example, Watt and Baker (2002) had “helpers” try to assist “helpees” maintain concentration on a candle, as in meditation, by concentrating on the candle themselves via a computer monitor in another room during help trials. The sequence of help and control trials was randomized with the helpee masked to the order. Some Adaptations of Testing Procedures Hidden Target and Covert Test Methods AP tests can be successfully conducted without participants being given complete information about the task. For example, the researcher can decline to tell participants the identity of the target process, asking them simply to “make it come out right.” This helps make the test less cognitively complicated for the participant. In most such tests the participant is informed of the general kind of effect desired (e.g., make the dice come up with a certain face uppermost) but not the specific effect (e.g., make them come up “six”). However, it would be theoretically possible to deny the more general information as well (e.g., fail to tell the participant that you are scoring for placement of the dice as well as their faces). In the more extreme kinds of covert AC tests, participants are not informed that they are participating in a psi test at all. REGs are excellent for this purpose because they can easily be left running out of sight of the participant while the latter is engaged in some other task. This principle has been applied in the global consciousness project, in which REGs are left to grind out data during events in which a large number of people are absorbed, such as a World Cup soccer match. The theory is that their collective consciousness biases the normally random output of the REG (Nelson, 2001; chapter 21, this volume). Time-displaced AP. If we are willing to assume that AC can violate the conventional laws of time by extending into the future (precognition), it is no less absurd to assume that AP can violate these same laws by extending backwards in time. Parapsychologists have studied the latter possibility, which they call retroactive AP or simply retro–AP (Schmidt, 1976). A retro–AP experiment is conducted by generating the event sequence prior to the time that the participant attempts to influence it. For example, we might have an REG generate a sequence of binary numbers and store electrical signals representing those numbers on magnetic tape such that no one observes them. Later a participant listens to the tape, on which the ones might be heard as clicks and the zeroes not heard at all, and tries to increase or decrease the number of clicks by, in effect, influencing the production of the numbers by the REG at the earlier time. If a covert test is desired, the participant can simply be told to listen to the clicks or to count them for some other purpose. There is no conclusive way to rule out that the experimenter or even the participant might use AP to influence the sequence of numbers at the time they are generated. As noted above, a person need not be aware of the target or even consciously attempt an AP effect in order to exert one. So again, we must resort to defining retro–AP operationally rather than theoretically. Of course, AP might extend into the future as well as the past, and here our problem is a good deal simpler. All we need to do is measure the event a predetermined amount of time following the attempted AP influence. Such delayed AP effects are customarily called linger effects or lag effects when they persist after attempted influence has ceased (e.g., Wells & Watkins, 1975) and release-of-effort effects when they commence following attempted influence (e.g., Stanford & Fox, 1975). Determining the Event and Target Sequences At this point it is necessary formally to introduce a terminological distinction between events and targets. Events are the sequence of outcomes upon which the participant attempts to exert influence. The targets are those particular outcomes the participant attempts to create. The events in AP tests should be independent of one another, like open decks in AC testing. This is automatically the case when different target objects or systems are used for each trial. It is also the case with properly functioning REGs. Lack of independence is most likely to be a serious problem in ambient energy or psychophysiological studies, in which the event sequence might be, for example, electrodermal responses. It is also necessary that in the absence of AP influence each possible outcome in the event sequence occurs an approximately equal number of times, according to the laws of randomness. Thus, in a standard dice test each die face should be the target an equal number of times, and in a placement test each location should be the target an equal number of times. In other words, the sequence of targets should be a closed deck. How exactly should the target sequence be determined? At least in overt tests, it is not a good idea to select a target separately for each trial. This forces participants to shift their focus after each trial, which of course is impossible anyway in REG studies in which trials are being generated at a rapid rate. If the target sequence is selected randomly, the possibility is also enhanced that the person generating the target sequence might use his or her own psi to match the event sequence. A better solution is to have each target alternative be the target for a particular group of “block” of trials. For example, a 60-trial dice test might be divided into six 10-trial runs with each face being the target for one run. But how do we determine the order of targets? The important principle here is to avoid sequences that might mimic a naturally occurring fluctuation in the system (which could mean that there is an intertrial dependency problem) or an internal scoring trend of possible interest. For example, if dice are used (you must always assume they are biased) and the target sequence is 6,5,4,3,2,1, the overall score will be properly close to MCE if no AP is operative, but the scores might decline significantly from psi-hitting to psi-missing. This decline effect would of course not be real evidence of AP, but simply an artifact of the biased dice. The best way to overcome this problem is not through randomization but through counterbalancing, such that each possible permutation of the six die faces is assigned to one and only one of the blocks. Even though you can demonstrate that REGs are unbiased by control tests, it is still a good idea to have participants aim for high and low scores (1s and 0s in a binary REG) for an equal number of trials. By having two investigators separately generate the aim sequences (targets) and the event sequences in a retro–AP experiment, Schmidt, Morris, and Rudolph (1986) were able to claim that neither investigator by himself could have compromised the integrity of the significant results (i.e., cheated). Note 1. This chapter is an update of parts of two chapters by the author that appeared in Foundations of parapsychology (Edge, Morris, Palmer, & Rush, 1986). References Bem, D. J. (2011). Feeling the future: Experimental evidence for anomalous retroactive influences on cognition and affect. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 100, 407–425. Braud, W. (1978). Allobiofeedback: Immediate feedback for a psychokinetic influence upon another person’s physiology. In W. G. Roll (Ed.), Research in parapsychology 1977 (pp. 123–134). Metuchen, NJ: Scarecrow Press. Braud, W. G. (1990). Distant mental influence of rate of hemolysis of human red blood cells. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 84, 1–24. Dalkvist, J., Mossbridge, J., and Westerlund, J. (2013). How to remove the influence of expectation bias in precognition experiments: A recommended strategy. Journal of Parapsychology, 78, 80–97. Dalton, K. (1997). Exploring the links: Creativity and psi in the ganzfeld. Proceedings of Presented Papers: The Parapsychological Association 40th Annual Convention (pp. 119–134). Dunne, B. J., Nelson, R. D., and Jahn, R. G. (1988). Operator–related anomalies in a random mechanical cascade. Journal of Scientific Exploration, 2, 155–179. Duval, P., and Montredon, E. (1968). ESP experiments with mice. Journal of Parapsychology, 32, 153–166. Edge, H., Morris, R., Palmer, J., and Rush, J. H. (1986). Foundations of parapsychology. London, UK: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Grad, B. (1963). A telekinetic effect on plant growth. International Journal of Parapsychology, 5, 117–133. Honorton, C. (1975). Objective determination of information rate in psi tasks with pictorial stimuli. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 69, 353–359. Honorton, C. (1997). The ganzfeld novice: Four predictors of initial ESP performance. Journal of Parapsychology, 61, 143–158. Honorton, C., Berger, R. E., Varvoglis, M. P., Quant, M., Derr, P., Schechter, E. I., and Ferrari, D. C. (1990). Psi communication in the ganzfeld: Experiments with an automated testing system and a comparison with a meta-analysis of earlier studies. Journal of Parapsychology, 54, 99– 139. Honorton, C., and Ferrari, D. C. (1989). A meta-analysis of forced-choice precognition experiments, 1935–1987. Journal of Parapsychology, 53, 281– 308. Honorton, C., and Tremmel, L. (1979). Psi correlates of volition: Preliminary test of Eccles’ “neurophysiological hypothesis” of brain-mind interaction. In W. G. Roll (Ed.), Research in parapsychology 1978 (pp. 36– 38). Metuchen, NJ: Scarecrow Press. Honorton, C., and Tremmel, L. (1980). PSITREK: A preliminary effort toward development of psi-conducive computer software. In W. G. Roll (Ed.), Research in parapsychology 1979 (pp. 159–161). Metuchen, NJ: Scarecrow Press. Irwin, C. P. (1980). The implications of subject familiarity with freeresponse target pools. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 74, 183–190. Jacobson, E. (1974). Progressive relaxation (rev. ed.) Chicago: University of Chicago Press. (Original work published 1938). Jahn, R. G., Dunne, B. J., and Jahn, E. G. (1980). Analytical judging procedure for remote perception experiments. Journal of Parapsychology, 44, 207–231. Johnson, M. (1973). A new technique of testing ESP in a real life, high motivational context. Journal of Parapsychology, 37, 210–217. Keil, H. H. J. (1965). A GESP test with favorite music targets. Journal of Parapsychology, 29, 35–44. Kennedy, J. E. (1980a). Information processing in ESP: A survey of forced choice experiments using multiple-aspect targets. Journal of Parapsychology, 44, 9–34. Kennedy, J. E. (1980b). Learning to use ESP: Do the calls match the targets or do the targets match the calls? Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 74, 191–209. Kennedy, J. E. (2013). Methodology for confirmatory experiments on physiological measures of precognitive anticipation. Journal of Parapsychology, 77, 237–248. Marsaglia, G., and Zaman, A. (1987). Toward a universal random number generator (FSU-SCRI-87–50). Gainesville: Florida State University. May, E. C., Spottiswoode, S. J. P., and James, C. L. (1994). Shannon entropy: A possible intrinsic target property. Journal of Parapsychology, 54, 384–401. May, E. C., Targ, R., and Puthoff, H. E. (1976). EEG correlates to remote light flashes under conditions of sensory shielding. In C. T. Tart, H. E. Puthoff, and R. Targ (Eds.), Mind at large. New York: Praeger. May, E. C., Utts, J. M., Humphrey, B. S., Luke, W. L. W., Frivold, T. J., and Trask, V. V. (1990). Advances in remote-viewing analysis. Journal of Parapsychology, 54, 193–228. McMoneagle, J. (2000). Remote viewing secrets: A handbook. Charlottesville, VA: Hampton Roads. Morris, R. L. (1970). Psi and animal behavior: A survey. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 64, 242–260. Moulton, S. C., & Kosslyn, S. M. (2008). Using neuroimaging to resolve the psi debate. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 20, 182–192. Nelson, R. (2001). Correlation of global events with REG data: An internetbased, nonlocal anomalies experiment. Journal of Parapsychology, 65, 247–271. Palmer, J. (1978). Extrasensory perception: Research findings. In S. Krippner (Ed.), Advances in parapsychological research 2 (pp. 59–243). New York: Plenum Press. Palmer, J. (1983). Sensory contamination of free-response ESP targets: The greasy fingers hypothesis. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 77, 101–113. Palmer, J. (1986). The ESP controversy. In H. L. Edge, R. L. Morris, J. Palmer, and J. H. Rush, Foundations of parapsychology (pp. 161–183). London, UK: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Rhine, J. B. (1973). Extrasensory perception (rev. ed.). Boston, MA: Bruce Humphries. (Original work published 1934). Rhine, L. E. (1962). Psychological processes in ESP experiences. Part I. Waking experiences. Journal of Parapsychology, 26, 88–111. Richmond, N. (1952). Two series of PK tests on paramecia. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 36, 577–588. Schlitz, M. J., and Honorton, C. (1997). Ganzfeld psi performance within an artistically gifted population. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 86, 83–98. Schmeidler, G. R. (1973). PK effects upon continuously recorded temperature. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 76, 325–340. Schmidt, H. (1970). A quantum mechanical random number generator for psi tests. Journal of Parapsychology, 34, 219–224. Schmidt, H. (1976). PK effect on pre-recorded targets. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 70, 267–292. Schmidt, H., Morris, R. L., and Rudolph, L. (1986). Channeling evidence for a PK effect to independent observers. Journal of Parapsychology, 50, 1– 15. Schouten S. A. (1976). Autonomic psychophysiological reactions to sensory and emotive stimuli. European Journal of Parapsychology, 1(2), 57–71. Sicher, F. Targ, E., and Moore, D. 2nd (1998). A randomized double-blind study of the effect of distant healing in a population with advanced AIDS. Report of a small scale study. Western Journal of Medicine, 169, 356–363. Stanford, R. G. (1975). Response patterns in extrasensory performance. Journal of Communication, 25, 153–161. Stanford, R. G., and Fox, C. (1975). An effect of release of effort in a psychokinetic task. In J. D. Morris, W. G. Roll, and R. L. Morris (Eds.), Research in parapsychology 1974 (pp. 61–63). Metuchen, NJ: Scarecrow Press. Stanford, R. G., and Palmer, J. (1975). Free-response ESP performance and occipital alpha rhythms. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 69, 235–243. Stuart, C. E. (1945). A classroom ESP experiment with the free-response method. Journal of Parapsychology, 9, 92–105. Targ, R., and Puthoff, H. (1977). Mind-reach. New York: Delacorte. Tart, C. T. (1966). Card guessing test: Learning paradigm or extinction paradigm? Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 60, 46– 55. Tart, C. T. (1976). Learning to use extrasensory perception. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Ullman, M., Krippner, S., and Vaughan, A. (1973). Dream telepathy. New York: Macmillan. Watkins, G. K., and Watkins, A. M. (1974). Possible PK influence on the resuscitation of anesthetized mice. Journal of Parapsychology, 35, 257– 272. Watt, C., and Baker, I. S. (2002). Remote facilitation of attention focusing with psi-supportive versus psi-unsupportive experimenter suggestions. Journal of Parapsychology, 66, 151–168. Wells, R., and Watkins, G. K. (1975). Linger effects in several PK experiments. In J. D. Morris, W. G. Roll, and R. L. Morris (Eds.), Research in parapsychology 1974 (pp. 143–147). Metuchen, NJ: Scarecrow Press. OceanofPDF.com CHAPTER 5 Research Methods with Spontaneous Case Studies EMILY WILLIAMS KELLY and JIM B. TUCKER In this volume, as in the first Handbook, the chapter on studying spontaneous experiences has been placed in the general section on Methodology. Throughout the nearly century and a half of research on psi and related phenomena, the methods for studying spontaneous experiences, as well as experimental methods, have been broad and varied and have evolved along with the technological resources available. One important point remains unchanged, however: Methodology—how one studies a phenomenon—is derived from, and hence secondary to, the question of what one studies—that is, the types of phenomena—which in turn derives from the question of why one is studying them—that is, the issue or theoretical question one wishes to address. We want therefore from the outset to make clear four major premises on which our discussion of spontaneous case research is based. First, we do not think that psi research should be defined as the study of isolated anomalies that cannot be explained by ordinary sensorimotor processes. Instead, we define it more broadly as the science that studies phenomena suggesting the active, primary role of consciousness, and especially volition, in the external world. It is important to emphasize that by “consciousness” and “volition” we are not referring just to what F. W. H. Myers (1903) called the “supraliminal” aspects of consciousness, those mental processes of which we are aware, but instead to the much more extensive “subliminal” contents and activities of consciousness. Second, we think that spontaneous experiences provide a broad base on which to both generate and test hypotheses, models, and theories of the role of consciousness in the physical world, simply because they occur in the broad context of naturally occurring conditions. Additionally, as we hope to make clearer later in the chapter, we think that the base of spontaneous cases themselves must be expanded beyond the traditional psi categories of ESP, PK, and survival-related phenomena such as apparitions to include other related phenomena that themselves suggest the active, primary role of mind. Third, we recognize that people come to the study of spontaneous experiences with different purposes. In particular, these divide broadly into the evidence-based approaches and the experiential-based approaches. The former seek to understand what these phenomena are and what they have to say about human nature and its place in the world. The latter seek to understand the meaning of experiences in the lives of the people who have them. Both are important endeavors, but in our view the latter fall into the domain of clinical or sociological questions. We unabashedly adopt the approach of, and define psi research as, studying the phenomena for what they have to tell us about the theoretical question of the nature of the relation of consciousness and matter. Finally, we think that methodology involves a continuum of complementary approaches. There is no either/or choice to be made between, say, spontaneous case studies and experiments, or between investigating individual cases and amassing large case collections. Similarly, there is no linear progression or “advance” in science from an “anecdotal” stage to an “experimental” stage, or from “proof”-oriented to “process”-oriented research. Individual researchers will choose one or another approach for their own work, but psi research as a whole must involve a constant interplay of methods and approaches, working in tandem and informing each other. These general comments apply to the science of psi research as a whole, but in this chapter we will limit our discussion in the following ways. First, as with the chapter in the original Handbook, we are here dealing only with non-recurrent spontaneous experiences and thus will not include field studies of recurring phenomena such as poltergeist or haunting cases, nor will we deal with near-death experiences (NDEs), out-of-body experiences (OBEs), or cases of the reincarnation type, although they are relevant to this chapter, because some of them are covered in other chapters. Second, this chapter is by no means meant to be a review of all pertinent studies carried out in the nearly four decades since 1977. Instead, we aim only to give enough examples of relevant research and publications to illustrate what we view as the most important points about method and theory. Summary of Louisa Rhine’s 1977 Chapter Louisa Rhine’s chapter on spontaneous cases in the original Handbook, and indeed all her work on spontaneous cases, was based on her conviction that, whatever value such cases might have, the study of them was “peripheral” to experimental studies of psi (p. 77). They are, she said, “peripheral … because science in general has now advanced from the anecdotal stage to the experimental.” They are also inherently weak, primarily because of the unreliability of human testimony (p. 61), and therefore “case studies must always be peripheral [because] they never prove anything by themselves. They can only suggest … [and] give tentative hints on which the slower methods of experimentation can capitalize” (p. 78). With that premise, she devoted most of her chapter to contrasting the “old” methods used by the early psychical researchers and her own “new” methods. The old methods consisted of the authentication and verification of the accounts reported because, she said, the primary goal of the psychical researchers was “to prove that telepathy occurs … preliminary to the great question of [proving] survival” (p. 61). She explained that the weakness of this approach was, first, that one could never eliminate errors of testimony to the point of proof and, second, that the investigators limited their purview by excluding the many reports of experiences that did not fit the criteria set for cases to be considered adequate for the intended goal. The Phantasms of the Living collection, for example, included only cases that fell within a certain time span (12 hours before or after the related event) and emphasized waking experiences over dreams. After reviewing some older research intended to overcome some of the weaknesses of the old method, Rhine then turned to a brief summary of her own “new methods.” She admitted that her original intent in studying spontaneous cases had been to use analyses of them only to generate hypotheses for experimental work, but later, “with psi experimentally established, emphasis was shifting to a study of its nature,” to which “spontaneous cases might give clues” (p. 69). Her method was to broaden the base of cases examined by including all reports sent to her if the description fit the definition of psi, and if the letter seemed to have been written “intelligently … and in apparent good faith” (p. 70). This meant, in practice, that over half of all accounts sent to her were eliminated because of “obvious weaknesses” (p. 69), although she did not specify exactly what those weaknesses were. Nevertheless, the database of cases was extensive, eventually growing to more than 14,000 (Feather & Schmicker, 2005). Rhine did not, as we will later discuss further, investigate or follow up on the accounts she received, explaining that this “method could not have been used 50 years earlier, before psi was established experimentally.” Unlike the early psychical researchers, she said, she no longer needed evidential “proof” of psi, and so she could dispense with proof-oriented investigations and concentrate on process-oriented analysis. In a rather odd twist of logic, she went on to say that, because psi was now experimentally established, “it was necessary to conclude that psi must also occur spontaneously” (p. 70). The persisting question was whether any given experience could be attributed to psi or was a chance coincidence, but she believed that non-psi cases would be cancelled out, for purposes of describing psi processes, in large-scale pattern analyses. Comments on Rhine’s Chapter Although Rhine’s extensive research and classification system of spontaneous cases were valuable contributions, we would challenge her position on several important issues. In general, we believe that behind much of her attitude was a narrow understanding of the nature of science. First, she placed a misguided emphasis on the concept of “proof.” Throughout her chapter, she used the word numerous times, especially in alleging that only statistics and experiments, and not unreliable eyewitness testimony, can ever “prove” psi. Second, she believed that science progresses from an anecdotal to an experimental stage, and from “proof”oriented to “process”-oriented research. However, as Ian Stevenson pointed out frequently (e.g., 1968), there is no “proof” in science; the concept of proof belongs only to mathematics. Science consists most fundamentally not of experiment and “proof,” but of increasing or diminishing probabilities of hypotheses or theories by “testing interpretations of observed phenomena against further observations until one interpretation emerges as the best” (Stevenson, 1999, p. 257). Because of this mistaken notion about “scientific proof,” Rhine strictly dichotomized the “old” anecdotal methods of psychical research and her own new methods, but in doing so she seriously misunderstood much of the work that preceded her. She believed that experimental studies had conclusively “established” the existence of ESP, clairvoyance, and PK (p. 69; see also 1981, pp. 47, 205), and therefore that “the reality of psi and the field of parapsychology are gaining wider acceptance” (1981, p. 7). In contrast, the early psychical researchers “knew nothing of psi,” although they “did suspect that telepathy does somehow occur” (1981, p. 121). They were “not informed of or not in sympathy with the experimental kind of inquiry,” and their methods, “fixed by tradition,” were “a remnant of a day long before any type of extrasensory perception had been established and when the concept of telepathy was not accepted in orthodox scientific circles” (1977, p. 60). Moreover, she believed that the psychical researchers were interested only in certain religious or philosophical questions (read, post-mortem survival), and not in “psi as a human ability,” or what she labeled “process” research. As a result, it took “investigators in the laboratory … to recognize that psi operates unconsciously” (1981, p. 81, 166). There is probably no need to comment on Rhine’s belief that experimental studies had led to the acceptance of psi in “orthodox scientific circles.” But others of her remarks are similarly mistaken. To say that the early psychical researchers “knew nothing of psi” is odd, as they invented the concept, and even the term, “telepathy” and published numerous papers not only on it but on PK (or “telekinesis”), clairvoyance (or “telesthesia”), and precognition. The whole premise of Phantasms of the Living was to see how far the hypothesis of telepathy could go in accounting for apparitions and other such experiences. Rhine’s remark that the psychical researchers were ignorant of or “not in sympathy with” the experimental method is off base as well; they in fact carried out numerous experimental studies, including some with quantitative or statistical evaluations. Perhaps most egregious of all, anyone aware of the Subliminal Self theory of Myers must feel a bit stunned when Rhine gives credit to experimental parapsychologists for “discovering” that psi is an “unconscious” process. Moreover, although some (but not all) psychical researchers were certainly interested in the survival question, this interest was part of a broader motivation. Myers’s theory of the Subliminal Self is in fact a complex theory of human personality, examining a wide range of normal, abnormal, and supernormal psychological phenomena and the processes by which they occur (see Cook [Kelly], 1994; Kelly, Kelly, Gauld, Crabtree, Grosso, & Greyson, 2007, Chapter 2; Myers, 1903). More specifically, a review of the broader methods and approaches adopted by the psychical researchers reveals work that predates Rhine’s own classification methods and “process-oriented” research by decades (Alvarado, 1987, also makes this point). Myers, for example, published “Specimens of the Classification of Cases for ‘Phantasms of the Living,’” a series of nine papers (1884–1885) setting out a classification system for a wide range of cases, those evidentially weak as well as strong. The psychical researchers did not, as Rhine stated (1977, p. 69; 1981, pp. 32–33), ignore cases not meeting certain evidential standards and thereby prematurely narrow the type of cases considered. On the contrary, they took into account as wide a range of cases as they received, because “our aim is not only evidential, but theoretical” (Myers, 1884–1885, p. 54). In complete opposition to narrowing their base of cases, a major purpose was to expand the base, so that new cases could be compared to the classification system and hypotheses suggested by the old cases, and the system and hypotheses modified accordingly. Expanding Contemporary Research on Spontaneous Cases Our intent is not to dwell on either the accomplishments or the mistakes of the past. Unfortunately, as Alan Gauld (1993, p. 256) has cogently observed, even though spontaneous case research has continued, it is in many respects “static” because, with just a few exceptions, in recent decades it has “greatly diminished” in quantity, and qualitatively it does “not seem to carry us substantially beyond the point that had already been reached at the beginning of [the 20th] century.” Gauld cites a number of political and sociological reasons for this stagnation that have been detrimental to psi research in general. We believe further that factors internal to the field have contributed to the decline of spontaneous case studies. Interest in spontaneous cases among psi researchers has nearly died away because most of them have adopted attitudes similar to Rhine’s, particularly with regard to the concept of “proof” in science and the accompanying rejection of “anecdotes” as scientific evidence. The overwhelmingly predominant attitude toward spontaneous case research today is that it is—at best—“peripheral” because there has been “a clear progression [italics added] in parapsychology from the collection of anecdotal material to the experimental investigation of laboratory analogues of psi phenomena…. [A] field of research that has any scientific merit must be represented in the laboratories of recognized universities” (Irwin & Watt, 2007, pp. 247–248). As we explained earlier, we emphatically reject attitudes that dichotomize unscientific, unreliable, anecdotal methods and “truly scientific” (Irwin & Watt, 2007, p. 248), statistical, laboratory methods as a parochial remnant of a narrow view of science. To those who simply rehearse the old arguments about the unreliability of eyewitness testimony (e.g., Irwin & Watt, 2007, pp. 40–45; Morris, 1986), we would reply, as Gauld (1993, p. 260) does, that they apparently “have not done the relevant homework” of studying the detailed discussions by Gurney and others about this issue. As Stokes (1997) further points out, the frequently invoked counterexplanations of fraud, unreliable testimony, or coincidence are always possible “for any given case,” but they often involve “a considerable amount of mental gymnastics” to make them plausible, and he rejects this essentially knee-jerk reaction to spontaneous cases as “far too cavalier an approach” (p. 65) [see chapter 3]. Moreover, to those who dismiss spontaneous cases because one cannot “specify the statistical probability of the event’s occurrence by chance” (Irwin & Watt, 2007, p. 44), we would reply that the scientific method is not most fundamentally one of quantification, but of systematization, that is, bringing meaningful order to events, particularly those that are not by nature quantifiable (Braude, 1992, p. 227; Cook [Kelly], 1991, p. 191; Grimaldi & Engel, 2007; G. Murphy, 1953, p. 101). In short, we have emphasized this simplistic and erroneous view of science, adopted by psi researchers and critics alike, because a major objective in this chapter is to argue that the issues raised by psi require a broad-based and expanded approach, and our view is that any science that ignores its “ethology” (Stevenson, 1968, p. 123), or naturally occurring phenomena, and limits itself to observing artificially produced phenomena, whether in a lab or in a zoo, is doomed to failure. Reasons for Studying Spontaneous Cases All good science begins, not with a phenomenon or a position that one wishes to “prove,” but with a question or unresolved issue that one wishes to address. In the case of psi research, that issue is, broadly, the place of consciousness, and particularly volition, in the physical world, and the question is, what is the nature of mind-brain correlation? Is mind produced by the brain, as the vast majority of scientists today assume? Or is it instead limited, shaped, or “filtered” by the brain, as suggested by James (1898/1900), Bergson (1913), Huxley (1954/1990), and others (see Kelly et al., 2007, for further discussion and references to these two models of mindbrain correlation)? [see chapter 2, this volume] This large question about the nature of consciousness looms over neuroscience, psychology, and philosophy, and psi research has a central role to play in addressing it— once parapsychologists themselves recognize that the issue is not one of “proving” psi but of addressing this fundamental, wholly unresolved question. But spontaneous case research also has a central role to play in unresolved issues in psi research itself. Much effort has been expended in connection with experimental studies of psi to determine conditions under which psi is most likely to occur, especially altered states of consciousness and internal attention states, such as hypnosis and the ganzfeld [see chapters 9 and 15]. Spontaneous case research had already identified such states as being frequently associated with psi experiences, and we would argue that such conditions are more likely to be identified under natural, and not artificial, circumstances. Similarly, there has been much research on personality characteristics associated with psi, but most of it has involved either experimental participants or people who claim psi experiences. Unfortunately, many claims of experiences do not correspond to what a researcher would consider psi; we remind readers that Louisa Rhine (1977, pp. 69–70) discarded about 60 percent of the letters sent to her as not meeting her definition of psi. A big gap should be filled by examining the personality characteristics of people reporting experiences whose descriptions fit the kinds of cases we are actually interested in studying. Along with Haight’s (1979) use of a personality questionnaire with high school participants of “good” psi cases, much more work could be done on the correlates between spontaneous psi experiences and patterns on standard personality instruments. We would argue, however, that an even bigger gap remains to be filled. All “process-oriented” work on identifying conducive conditions and “good” experimental participants has been aimed at improving the “hit” rate, or evidence for psi. We believe that describing conditions and personality characteristics associated with psi ought to be carried further and undertaken with a theoretical aim in mind. Process-oriented research aims at seeing patterns in the data. Theory-oriented research asks why those patterns occur. For example, a major part of a “filter” view of mind-brain relations is that psi experiences occur more readily in people for whom the psychological boundaries between supraliminal and subliminal regions of consciousness are more “permeable,” such as fantasy-proneness, dissociative tendencies, and transliminality, and that these boundaries are further relaxed under conditions such as drowsiness, hypnosis, or sensory deprivation. Thus, certain personality characteristics and conditions that have been repeatedly associated with the occurrence of psi are not only conducive, but are so in a way that makes sense within the theoretical framework of a “filter” theory of consciousness. Another perennial problem in psi research, no closer to being solved now than when it was first raised in the late 19th century, is what is known as the “source of psi” question, an issue toward which Palmer (1992, p. 234) thinks “surprisingly little empirical research has been directed,” given its central importance to the field. As Louisa Rhine (1981, p. 196) put it, “which of the two persons ‘did it’?”; and in recent decades a third person— the experimenter—has been added as the possible active party. The issue of whether the percipient or the agent is the active party became of central importance to Rhine. She argued throughout her career that the percipient was the active and important party, drawing this conclusion primarily because in clairvoyance and precognition cases there is no agent (she assumed) and even in many telepathy cases there is no evidence that the ostensible agents were trying, or even motivated, “to send their thoughts to the percipient” (1981, p. 126). Stevenson (1970) stressed the dangers of drawing conclusions, as Rhine did, from cases in which the percipient’s point of view is the primary, even only, one the researcher sees and takes into account. Stokes (1997) noted that, in attributing agency to the percipients, Rhine herself showed a “reverse prejudice” (p. 47) in apparently ignoring findings that complicate her conclusion. Weiner and Haight (1986) similarly believed that Rhine “did seem to stack the deck against an active-agent hypothesis” (p. 25). Such cautions, however, have not stopped some contemporary researchers from asserting that one of her “most interesting ideas” was that the experience was “instigated by the experient” (Irwin & Watt, 2007, p. 37). An “active-percipient” hypothesis was not, in fact, original with Rhine. Myers (1884–1885) raised the issue of whether the percipient or the agent is the active party by asking: “Are we to suppose … that potential telepathic impressions are perpetually flying about, but only certain minds can catch and develop them? or are we, on the contrary, to assume that it is only the one rare mind here and there which has the power of projecting an impression sufficiently vigorous to be felt by another?” (p. 80). He tentatively suggested that the limited evidence to that point suggested the percipient as the important party, because percipients often report more than one experience, whereas agents do not seem to figure in more than one (pp. 80–81).We would argue, however, that the crucial point to keep in mind is the need to evaluate cases from both perspectives, and not to defend prematurely one or another as universally correct. Moreover, some early psychical researchers considered an interesting third possibility, one that we believe remains a vitally important one to explore, both in spontaneous cases and experimental research. Is “percipient or agent” another false dichotomy? Is it neither one nor the other alone, but something about the interaction or interconnection of the two that is the important factor? Eleanor Sidgwick (1922, pp. 420–423) suggested that some kind of direct “contact” between or “merging” of minds in varying degrees was a better model than a transmission-through-space model. Myers also proposed a kind of psychological link, or rapport, between subliminal minds (see Kelly et al., 2007, p. 90). As he quickly pointed out, a difficulty arises when one considers cases “between persons who not only are not thinking of each other at the time, but who are absolute strangers … where no pre-existing rapport can even be suggested” (1884–1885, pp. 121–122). Clearly, the matter is more complicated than one of kinship or affection, of motivation, or of the direction of attention (pp. 100, 121). Perhaps additional to—or instead of, in some cases—these factors, there may be a kind of “diffused excitement” surrounding the nature of the event itself that spreads, even to strangers who are, in some as yet unknown way, connected psychologically to that event (p. 123). Without abandoning attempts to “pinpoint” the source of psi, a more promising approach might be to examine more fully this third possibility that something about the relationship, interaction, or interconnectedness of all parties involved is the primary factor. In his evaluation of “The Importance of Spontaneous Cases,” Gardner Murphy (1953) thought that their importance might well lie in “a systematic and intelligible picture of what happens in the deep-level interactions [emphasis added] of human beings” (p. 101). Of particular interest, given the prominence of contemporary ideas about “non-locality,” might be the suggestion of Myers and Gurney that this conjectured link or rapport could be the conceptual equivalent in psychology of gravitation or molecular attraction in physics (Gurney & Myers, 1884, pp. 814–815; Myers, 1903, vol. 1, p. 38). In 1919 the biologist Paul Kammerer, who was interested in coincidences, expressed a similar idea of “an a-causal principle active in the universe, which tends toward unity. In some respects it is comparable to universal gravity … but … acts selectively on form and function to bring similar configurations together in space and time; it correlates by affinity … ‘bringing like and like together’” (Koestler, 1972, p. 86). Perhaps asking “which person did it?” is a bit like asking “what is the sound of one hand clapping?” Such explorations indicate that research on spontaneous cases has much to contribute to a better understanding of consciousness, if we carry the research beyond the question of whether certain conditions or people are associated with psi experiences, and ask also the theoretical question of why they are so associated. Methods Used to Study Spontaneous Cases As White (1992) outlined, there are many ways of studying spontaneous experiences; most of the methods she described approach cases from an “experiential” point of view. For those of us interested primarily in the theoretical issue of what spontaneous experiences tell us about the nature of consciousness, there are several methodological approaches one can take— all, we again emphasize, to be undertaken as contributory steps in an ongoing process, and not in isolation—but the primary question is how best to identify cases and gather data relevant to the question one is asking. Surveys In recent decades one frequent approach has been the survey method, with questionnaires being administered to a (usually) random sample of people, often to learn the prevalence of particular types of experiences in that population. One of the earliest such surveys was that of McCready and Greeley (1976), sociologists who, in the context of a larger study of values in America, asked several questions related to psi phenomena. They found that 59 percent reported experiencing déjà vu, 58 percent ESP, 35 percent mystical experiences, 27 percent contact with the dead, and 24 percent clairvoyance. Palmer (1979), who surveyed a population of students and non-student adults in Charlottesville, Virginia, asked about similar types of experiences, as well as poltergeists, OBEs, past-life memories, and auras, and similarly found that many people reported them (82 percent of the adult sample and 96 percent of the student sample). Haraldsson has reported the largest and most widespread surveys on psirelated experiences. In a 1985 paper he compared data from six surveys in Iceland, the U.K., Sweden, the USA, and 16 western European countries about beliefs as well as experiences of psi phenomena. Perhaps the most striking finding of these studies was the wide variation in prevalence of the various types of experiences reported in different countries. Not surprisingly, the different surveys asked different questions, and such differences “have made direct comparisons across countries both difficult and highly tentative” (Haraldsson & Houtkooper, 1991, p. 145). In another large survey, the European Value System Study Group, undertaken under the auspices of Gallup and its affiliates, cross-cultural comparisons were somewhat easier because the three questions on telepathy, clairvoyance, and contact with the dead devised by Greeley (McCready & Greeley, 1976) were used in all countries (Haraldsson & Houtkooper, 1991). In this study, there were 18,607 respondents in the USA and 13 western European countries. In the USA, 60 percent reported at least one such experience, and in Europe 46 percent did, ranging from 24 percent in Norway to 60 percent in Italy. With more consistency in the questions asked, Haraldsson and Houtkooper could use the data to look at the effect of other variables, including demographics, beliefs, and psychological wellbeing. Other surveys have focused, not so much on prevalence, but on factors pertinent to a particular hypothesis about the experiences. McClenon (1994), for example, undertook random surveys using Greeley’s questions about déjà vu, ESP, and contact with the dead, as well as questions about OBEs, sleep paralysis, belief about ESP, and religion. His purpose was primarily to evaluate the “cultural source” hypothesis, which says that the occurrence and nature of spontaneous psi experiences are shaped entirely by culture, especially religious background and needs and the extent of one’s exposure to scientific education. Questionnaires were distributed to Caucasian-American, African American, Chinese, and Japanese students at seven colleges and universities in the USA, China, and Japan. In general, he, like others before him, found little support for the cultural source hypothesis (pp. 117, 128). Instead, he argues that psi experiences are associated with psychological characteristics such as hypnotic susceptibility, absorption, fantasy-proneness, and dissociative tendencies, among the characteristics we mentioned earlier in connection with the filter theory of mind and brain and a “permeable” boundary between the supraliminal and subliminal areas of consciousness. Ross and Joshi (1992) conducted a random survey to look further at observations they had made, primarily in a psychiatric context, of a relation between dissociation and reports of psi-related experiences. They administered the Dissociative Disorders Interview Schedule, including questions about various psi-related experiences, to 502 adults in Winnipeg, Canada. Of these, 66 percent reported at least one experience, and the reports of psi experiences correlated with childhood abuse and dissociative tendencies. The authors propose that “paranormal experiences are not necessarily pathological in nature … [but] an expression of normal dissociative capacity” that can be “activated by trauma” but also occur “in highly dissociative individuals who are healthy” (p. 360). They also insist that “paranormal experiences are so common in the general population … that no theory of normal psychology or psychopathology which does not take them into account can be comprehensive” (p. 360). Surveys can tell us how many people believe they have had certain experiences, and they may be useful in identifying reports that can be followed up to learn details about what actually happened. West (1995), however, has cautioned about the limited use of survey studies, based on his own experience. In addition to his earlier attempt (1948) to replicate the original SPR Census of Hallucinations, he conducted two studies, one was not a random survey (West, 1990), the other one was (West, 1995). In the 1990 study, respondents were asked about four kinds of experiences (apparitions, precognition, PK, and NDEs), and also asked to give a brief description of the experience. In the 1995 study, simple “yes” or “no” responses were given, with no further elaboration. On the basis of descriptions given in the first study, West found that many of the “yes” answers did not in fact correspond to an experience that a researcher would consider an example of the phenomenon in question. In the 1995 study, internal evidence suggested similarly that the “yes” answers were artificially inflated, perhaps because respondents had a different understanding of the terms and concepts being used. West’s (1995) conclusion is one that we endorse fully: “Simple questionnaires, … when not followed by further detailed inquiries into the exact nature of the experiences reported, can be misleading…. The combined survey and case study is a better way to research spontaneous experiences” (p. 171). Case Collections Single in-depth case studies are still occasionally carried out, such as those reported by Osis (1986) and Stevenson (1995). Regrettably, few contemporary case collections involve such extensive investigation. (A major exception is the collection of cases of the reincarnation type and related phenomena assembled by Ian Stevenson and his colleagues, discussed in chapter 25). Unlike a survey, which systematically canvasses members of a defined population, most case collections have resulted from appeals for experiences to the general public through various forms of the media, or from self-reports by people who have read or otherwise learned about a researcher’s particular interests. Hearne (1984), for example, asked in a newspaper for experiences of premonitions. Out of 450 letters received, he chose 127 for further study, and the respondents were sent a questionnaire about their experiences as well as the Eysenck Personality Inventory. The reports were not investigated, but based on the descriptions given Hearne determined, among other things, that 85 percent were associated with death or other unpleasant events, 54 percent occurred in dreams or hypnagogic imagery, and the vast majority of respondents (90 percent) were women. Virtanen (1977/1990) likewise collected experiences primarily by placing requests in newspapers and magazines. She asked for reports of “simultaneous informatory experiences,” by which she primarily meant crisis-type cases (p. 24). As a folklorist in Finland, she, like Hufford (1982), McClenon (1994), and Schouten (1983), wanted to evaluate the cultural source hypothesis, whether “traditional beliefs determin[e] the nature of our strange experiences,” or whether instead “traditions may arise after the fact to explain the strange experiences we have already had” (p. xvi). Recognizing that spontaneous experiences can never “prove the existence of ESP” and that any explanation, normal or paranormal, can only be judged “more or less probable,” she also focused her research on “the study of regularities observable in the experiences themselves” (p. 7). For the first objective, she looked at 865 experiences reported to her, supplemented by older cases and folklore accounts in Finland. For the second objective she analyzed the 865 questionnaires (together with data from some interviews) she had collected. Like Hufford, McClenon, and Schouten, she concluded that “the experiences are not dependent a priori on folk belief or the percipient’s repertoire of traditional belief” (p. xvii). She also found that the experiences were overwhelmingly (95 percent) negative in content, about deaths, accidents, or illness. About half of the experiences occurred in a waking state, the rest in dreams or borderline states, but “the nearer the percipient is to the normal waking state,” the more limited in details and more symbolic in nature was the information obtained (pp. 132, 148). The experiences took many forms, including dreams, hallucinations, intuitions, somatic sensations, physical phenomena, or unusual behavior of animals or birds. Haraldsson (1988–1989) is one of the few contemporary researchers—if not the only one—who has taken responses to surveys and systematically followed up the claims of experiences with some in-depth investigation. In a random survey in Iceland, 181 respondents had answered “yes” to a question of whether they had ever “experienced or felt the nearness of a deceased person.” Two years later Haraldsson attempted to contact all of them; 127 were reached and agreed to be interviewed. Of these, 27 reported experiences not of the kind being sought and these experiences were omitted from the survey. Of the remaining 100, 84 were sensory in nature, whether visual, auditory, tactile, or olfactory, and 16 involved a vivid sense of presence. In 13 cases the percipient did not know that the deceased person had died (p. 10). Thirteen other cases were collective, in that more than one person had the experience; these other persons were interviewed whenever possible. But perhaps the major importance of the study is that the investigator did not stop with unexamined survey data, but followed up with detailed questionnaires and interviews, eliminating reports that were not relevant to the questions being addressed, and then looking for patterns in the cases that remained. Haraldsson (1994, 2009, 2012) also conducted another study, in which a brief questionnaire was placed in several magazines in Iceland, again asking about experiences of perceiving or feeling the nearness of a deceased person. Over 700 replies were received, but again some responses were discarded as inappropriate for the study. Over 300 respondents were interviewed by telephone until resources for the study ran out. Additionally, the investigators were able to check the accuracy of the names, dates of death, and mode of death of the deceased persons involved, and in the collective cases they interviewed as many other witnesses as possible. As in Haraldsson’s first study, most of the experiences (90 percent) were sensory, especially visual, and 10 percent involved a vivid sense of presence. Most of the deceased people in both studies were male. Moreover, the mode of death was violent in a disproportionately large number of cases: 30 percent of those verified by the official records. High proportions of male agents and of a violent mode of death were also found in cases of Phantasms of the Living (Schouten, 1979; Stevenson, 1982). Other important factors that Haraldsson looked at were the state of consciousness of the percipient, whether the experience occurred in daylight or darkness, the relationship between the percipient and the deceased person, the time elapsed between the death and the experience, and in how many cases other persons were present and did (or did not) share the experience. Again, the specific findings are less important to comment on here than the fact that the experiences were investigated in enough detail to allow such features to be examined. We agree with West (1995) and Stevenson (1987) that what is most needed now are “systematic survey[s] of cases, combined with the careful investigation of every case identified in the survey” (Stevenson, 1987, p. 103). More generally, we agree with the arguments of two biologists who recently published a paper entitled “Why Descriptive Science Still Matters” (Grimaldi & Engel, 2007). Their attempt to clear up the “chronic misunderstanding as to what descriptive science actually is, and … ignorance of its significance” (p. 646) was addressed primarily to the sciences of astronomy, oceanography, and biology, but it applies fully to the study of spontaneous experiences in psi research. First, descriptive science is a “comparative method [that] assesses variation among individual things [e.g., experiences], and organizes it into systems and classifications that are used for making predictions … as descriptions become more refined and thorough, so do the systems of organization” (p. 646). Second, they point out that major scientific accomplishments have been achieved using “quaint tools,” including “old-fashioned natural history observations” (p. 646). Finally, the quality of a theory depends entirely on the quality of “the evidence (i.e., descriptions) that supports it … no theory is more profoundly explanatory than evolution,” and it succeeded so well because Darwin “assembled and explained vast descriptive evidence” (p. 647). The science of spontaneous psi experiences, we believe, has potentially an equally central role to play in the ultimate development of an equally profound theory of consciousness. Types of Spontaneous Cases Studied Descriptive science is, according to Grimaldi and Engel, first and foremost a comparative method, in which something is studied in its broader context of related phenomena. We would suggest that the study of traditional psi experiences should be expanded to examine them comparatively in the context of other phenomena that are related because they too bear on the issue of the nature of consciousness in relation to the physical world. The range of phenomena of interest to psychical researchers was much wider a century ago than in most of current parapsychology, and they were seen as “by no means isolated, but touch[ing] each other and mingl[ing] with each other in a variety of ways” (Myers, 1884–1885, p. 142). Stevenson (1990) described the “break-up” of the field, “rather in the manner of the AustroHungarian Empire after World War I,” so that areas once considered important parts of psychical research, such as hypnotism, unusual healings, lucid dreams, multiple personality, mystical or religious experiences, and what we now call NDEs, have all broken away into separate research arenas. This fragmentation has occurred in part because psychical researchers themselves “have come to identify the field of its endeavors as narrower than it once was or should now again become” (pp. 159–160). Perhaps one of the most important reasons for once again broadening the base of spontaneous case research, and rebuilding empirical and theoretical connections with these other areas, is to emphasize that none of these phenomena can be isolated, but that they fall on a continuum, adequately understandable only as they relate to each other death-related phenomena. One of the largest of these “breakaway” fields is that of near-death research, which has succeeded in attracting the attention of numerous scientists, primarily medical scientists, neuroscientists, and anthropologists, and is in large part carried out by persons not affiliated with psi research or its organizations. Many other phenomena besides NDEs, however, have been noted and studied in the broader context of death and dying. One area that has thus far received surprisingly little attention includes what are sometimes called death-bed visions, that is, the experiences of people shortly before they actually die. These experiences most often take the form of a dying person seeming to see or speak with someone who is not (usually) perceptible by others. From what the dying person says, others present are often able to identify this person as a deceased loved one. Occasionally the dying person will describe seeing a place that is also not seen by others. These experiences were of great interest to some of the early psychical researchers (e.g., Barrett, 1926; Bozzano, 1906; Hyslop, 1908), and several decades ago Osis and Haraldsson (1977/2012) conducted surveys of doctors and nurses in the United States and India to learn about their exposure to such experiences among their patients. Although hospice workers have long stated informally that such experiences are common, little systematic research has been conducted. One exception is that of Peter Fenwick and his colleagues, who have recently begun studies among hospice and nursing home caregivers in the U.K. They conducted a pilot study at a palliative care unit, in which nine medical personnel were given a questionnaire and then interviewed in person (Brayne, Farnham, & Fenwick, 2006). Three additional studies were conducted at a nursing home and two hospices, with 38 medical personnel (Fenwick, Lovelace, & Brayne, 2010). All interviewees had learned of such experiences, either directly from patients or from family members, and most of them distinguished clearly between these “meaningful” experiences and the confusional states accompanying drug-induced hallucinations. In addition to the dying person’s visions of people and places not physically present, other kinds of phenomena have been reported at or near the time of death. On rare occasions, a bystander will have a vision, or share the dying person’s vision (e.g., Fenwick et al., 2010, p. 176; Stevenson, 1995, pp. 359–363). Bystanders also occasionally report seeing an unusual light around the dying person at the time of death (Fenwick, 2005, p. 152; Fenwick et al., 2010, p. 176), a phenomenon that may prove of particular interest, given the frequent association of light with deep hypnotic states (Cardeña, 2005), NDEs, psi experiences, and mystical experiences. Bystanders also sometimes report seeing something leaving the body (Alvarado, 2006; Fenwick, Lovelace, & Brayne, 2007). Another phenomenon, apparently well known among physicians of the 18th and 19th centuries, is of particular interest theoretically. In some instances a dying person will recover his or her mental, or even physical, faculties shortly before death. The eminent early American physician Benjamin Rush (1812) observed that “most of mad people discover a greater or less degree of reason in the last days or hours of their lives” (p. 257). Such cases are of special interest when the disease in question involves clear destruction of brain tissue, as with Alzheimer’s patients. A striking example of this sort was reported recently by a surgeon whose patient was dying of a cancer that had eaten away most of his brain tissue, and yet he awoke from a coma to say goodbye to his family shortly before he died (Haig, 2007). Clearly, the importance of such cases lies in what they may have to tell us about the adequacy of the theory that consciousness is the product of the brain and nothing else (Kelly et al., 2007). Michael Nahm and his colleagues have published several papers reviewing the medical and scientific reports of such “terminal lucidity” cases (Nahm, 2009; Nahm & Greyson, 2009; Nahm, Greyson, Kelly, & Haraldsson, 2012). Moreover, Fenwick and his colleagues have also learned about such cases in their hospice and nursing home studies (Brayne, Lovelace, & Fenwick, 2008; Fenwick et al., 2010). Systematic studies in connection with hospices and nursing homes looking at experiences among the bereaved have recently been conducted as well. In an exploratory study undertaken by palliative care workers (Barbato, Blunden, Reid, Irwin, & Rodriguez, 1999), questionnaires were mailed to 100 people a month after their relative or friend had died in the palliative care unit of St. Joseph’s Hospital in Auburn, Australia. Forty-seven people returned the questionnaire, and of these 23 (49 percent) had some kind of experience to report: 11 of the 23 reported that the dying person had had some kind of experience, usually of seeing a deceased loved one, and 18 people had themselves had one or more experiences after the death, including a sense of presence of the deceased person, a hallucination (auditory, olfactory, or visual) of the deceased person, or unusual movement of objects associated with the deceased person. One person also reported a “crisis” dream that had alerted the dreamer to the person’s death. The authors stressed the need for palliative care workers, patients, and families to recognize that such experiences “are not uncommon” (p. 231). Likewise, from the beginning of their studies in hospices and nursing homes, Fenwick and his colleagues started learning about a phenomenon familiar to psychical researchers, one Fenwick calls “coincidence” cases and psychical researchers call “crisis” cases (Brayne et al., 2008; Fenwick et al., 2010), in which someone, usually a family member, has a dream, sees an apparition, has a telepathic impression, or experiences a PK event such as a picture falling or a clock stopping, at a time closely coinciding with the patient’s death. Moreover, because of the publicity their palliative care research has generated, many people have contacted Fenwick to tell him about their experiences, not only of deathbed visions, but also of crisis, or coincidence, cases (Fenwick & Brayne, 2011). The experiences of bereaved persons have received a lot of attention in the popular press in recent years as “after-death communications” (Arcangel & Schwartz, 2005; Guggenheim & Guggenheim, 1995; LaGrand, 1997). In the medical and psychiatric literature, however, other than the palliative care research of the Barbato and Fenwick groups, interest in the unusual experiences of bereaved persons has been confined to studies of one population—widows and widowers. An extensive study was undertaken by Rees (1971), who interviewed nearly all (293, or 94 percent) widowed persons in a particular area of mid–Wales who were fit enough to be interviewed. Rees was particularly interested in learning about hallucinatory experiences, and he found that 47 percent of his respondents reported them. Of these, 39 percent reported a sense of presence, 14 percent saw the deceased spouse, 13 percent heard him or her, and 3 percent reported a sense of being touched by the deceased spouse. The hallucinations often lasted 10 or more years. Most people found them positive or helpful but had told no one else about them. Other researchers have successfully replicated Rees’s study. Olson, Suddeth, Peterson, and Egelhoff (1985) interviewed 46 widows in two nursing homes in North Carolina. In this sample, nearly two-thirds (61 percent) reported hallucinations of their deceased spouse, including 79 percent visual, 50 percent auditory, 21 percent tactile, and 32 percent a sense of presence. Similarly, Grimby (1993) interviewed 50 randomly selected widows and widowers in Sweden, who were initially contacted within the first month after the death of their spouse. Of them, 82 percent reported experiencing a sense of presence or some form of hallucination, and many continued to have the experiences throughout the year that they were followed. Olson and his colleagues and Grimby learned, as Rees had, that the overwhelming majority of the widows and widowers had found the experiences to be positive and helpful, but that few of them had told anyone else about their experiences. As a result, these authors, like Barbato and his colleagues, echoed Stevenson’s (1983) call for a word to replace “hallucination” for such experiences that are clearly not pathological but, in contrast, psychologically helpful. Perhaps one of the most cogent conclusions to be drawn from the few studies so far of spontaneous experiences of dying and bereaved persons is the importance of predicting where phenomena of interest are to be found, and looking for cases there, rather than in random samples. Psi experiences occur most frequently in the context of death and other strongly emotional situations (Stokes, 1997, pp. 35–39). Where, then, are we more likely to learn about spontaneous psi experiences than in hospices, palliative care units, nursing homes, and bereavement support groups? Psychophysiological Phenomena As we made clear earlier, we define psi research as the study of phenomena that might throw light on whether consciousness is a by-product of the brain or is itself a primary, active agent in nature. Central to this theoretical issue is the question of volition. Is a sense of being able to think, choose, and act simply an illusion accompanying the inevitable grinding of stimulus and response in the neural machinery? If not, what is the nature of the connection between the “thought” and the “act”? Conclusions about the nature of mind-body correlation are often made on the basis of observations in which, in essence, brain is the independent variable and mind the dependent one: A change is introduced to the brain, and the change in behavior or consciousness is noted. What do we observe, however, when we reverse that procedure, when we induce changes in the mental or psychological state and observe changes in the body? There is, in fact, a vast range of phenomena in which beliefs, expectations, intentions, intense imagery, or strong emotional states seem to have generated a physiological reaction. Some of these phenomena have been induced deliberately, such as by hypnosis, meditation, or in experimental settings such as DMILS studies (for a review of many of these phenomena, see Kelly et al., 2007, Chapter 3), but our focus here is on ones that occur spontaneously [see chapter 18]. Psychoneuroimmunology has shown that the nervous system and the immune system, once thought to operate in isolation, in fact interact (Sternberg, 2000). Thus, many phenomena once dismissed as “folklore,” such as the effects of bereavement on mortality, the association of depression or hopelessness with cancer or heart disease, and even so-called “voodoo” or “hex” death, can now be accepted as the result of biochemical changes in the immune system resulting from stress or strong emotion (Kelly et al., 2007, pp. 122–129). A similar but opposite process can be conjectured to explain the association of positive emotions with healing, such as Norman Cousins’s (1976) well-known cure of his own illness through daily doses of humor. Such an explanation may seem adequate when the physiological state in question is a general, systemic one. Problems begin to arise, however, as the physiological responses become more targeted and specific in location. There are numerous reports of specific spontaneous healings, either by another person such as a “faith healer” or at a site such as Lourdes. Many such cases have been rightfully criticized as inadequately documented medically, or as probably involving a “functional” rather than “organic” disease, but by no means are all cases so easily dismissed. At Lourdes, for example, an international team of physicians has been in place since 1954, gathering the medical documentation and determining, among other things, the exact nature of the disease and how sudden, complete, and long-lasting the cure was. Between 1954 and 1984, 19 cases were judged “medically and scientifically inexplicable” (Dowling, 1984, p. 637). Nor were the diseases in question “functional”: In two cases, for example, there was recovery of bone that had been almost completely destroyed by cancer (Kelly et al., 2007, pp. 138–139). Another well-known phenomenon is that of stigmata, in which a person regularly develops marks, blisters, or bleeding at sites, such as the hands, feet, or sides of the torso, where the person believes Christ suffered wounds at the crucifixion. Like reported healings at Lourdes, reports of stigmatics are routinely dismissed as hagiographic myths, but, again like Lourdes, there are in fact a substantial number of well-documented cases. Margnelli (1999), for example, reported the case of a 64-year-old woman whose stigmata began in 1990, appearing the first Friday of every month and disappearing after 2 to 3 days. Margnelli followed her closely for 5 months, taking infrared and color photographs, measuring physiological reactions such as temperature, blood flow, and electrodermal response, and administering psychological tests. Similar cases have been reported in nonreligious contexts, but again in association with some strongly emotional situation (Kelly et al., 2007, pp. 156–159; Stevenson, 1997, pp. 68–78). Moody (1946, 1948) reported cases in which patients, reliving the memory of a traumatic experience, developed marks corresponding to wounds suffered at the time of the trauma. One patient, for example, developed weals on his forearms, corresponding to rope marks. On one occasion Moody himself witnessed the marks developing, and he published photographs taken at that time showing the many indentations on the arms resembling rope marks. Still other cases occur when a person’s emotional reaction to another person’s pain or suffering produces a comparable physical reaction in the first person (Stevenson, 1997, pp. 54–56). In some cases one person knew normally about the second person’s pain, as in the case of a mother who saw her child’s middle three fingers cut off by a falling window, and subsequently developed swelling and inflammation on the same three fingers of her own hand (Stevenson, 1997, p. 55). In other cases the first person did not know normally about the second person’s pain. Rhine (1967) published a report of 169 cases in her collection of what she called “psychosomatic psi.” A typical example was that of a woman who developed severe pain in her hip, which lasted several hours until she received a long-distance phone call telling her that her mother had fallen and broken a hip. Mann and Jaye (2007) published a more recent study of 20 pairs of twins who reported 50 instances of one twin experiencing pain or other bodily sensations similar to those being experienced by the other twin, although the first twin was not aware normally of that pain. From a general, systemic response to stress to the specific localized production of rope marks corresponding only to an idea and not to any anatomical pattern, all these phenomena raise the fundamental question of how an idea generates a physiological response. Many contemporary scientists attribute such psychophysiological reactions to a “holistic,” nondual “brain-mind.” Such a proposal is no answer, however, but an evasion of the question: How does “a person’s belief in a sham [placebo] treatment … send a message to his or her pituitary gland to release its own endogenous pharmaceuticals” (Harrington, 1997, p. 5)? What, Margnelli (1999, p. 464) asked about his stigmatic, “activates the nerve trunks, the contained areas of the lesions, the wound’s topographic precision and their long duration”? Psychophysiological cases involving two people also raise a question implicit in all psi experiences: As Mann and Jaye (2007, p. 193) put it, examples such as their twin cases “clearly ‘trouble’ the ontological separation of ‘A’ and ‘non–A.’” Synchronicity Experiences Additional experiences trouble the ontological separation of A and non–A, and these are what are vaguely called “coincidences,” or in more theoryladen terminology “synchronicities.” Jung, with a strong emphasis on the importance of meaning, defined synchronicities as coincidences between a psychic state and one or more external events that appear as meaningful parallels, his most famous example being when a scarabaeid beetle began knocking against the window of Jung’s office as a patient was relating a dream of receiving a golden scarab. He proposed that synchronicity was an “acausal” factor in nature in addition to physical cause and effect (Jung, 1952/1970). Psi experiences are, by definition, coincidences because they involve the meaningful connection between two events in which the ordinary sensorimotor means of connecting the events are ruled out. As such, they suggest that there may be some “cause” connecting the events that we have not yet discovered. Although, of course, “psi” is not a “cause” but simply a term designating what we presume is some as yet unknown causal factor or interplay of factors, what we call synchronicities seem to extend the range of those experiences to ones in which even “psi” becomes difficult to conjecture as an etiology. Psi researchers have grappled with the problems of chance, coincidence, and causality since the beginning of the field. One of the earliest people to try to systematize the problem was Alice Johnson (1899), in a paper specifically devoted to “Coincidences,” and she clearly recognized that some coincidences push the limits beyond conjectures about “psi” processes. A recent volume on the topic of synchronicity (Storm, 2008) makes clear that there is much disagreement about the relation, if any, between synchronicity and psi, but the disagreements seem to stem primarily from whether one limits synchronicity to Jung’s concept. Mansfield, Rhine-Feather, and Hall, for example, believe that “archetypal meaning [is] the sine qua non for synchronicity” (Storm, 2008, p. 138), and differentiated psi and synchronicities accordingly. Beitman (2011) has proposed that a new field be devoted to “coincidence studies,” which he believes should go beyond Jung’s concept of synchronicity. We agree and prefer an open-ended approach that asks whether both “meaningful coincidences and psi phenomena [may be] telling us something fundamental about the nature of consciousness and the structure of what we call reality, that goes beyond archetypes, and … may not be strictly acausal” (Nachman, 2010, pp. 390–391). We can do no better than John Beloff (1977) in stating the importance of incorporating the study of synchronicity into psi research: The literature of synchronicity has contributed to parapsychological knowledge in at least two important ways…. [I]t has drawn attention to real-life coincidences which, putting it at its lowest, provide a baseline for evaluating spontaneous cases of psi and, putting it at its highest, may have extended the scope of psi by demonstrating its unconscious manifestations. Secondly, it has emphasised again the futility of trying to explain psi in mechanistic terms. It has not … eliminated the concept of causality from the field; but the type of cause that we are left with is very different from the type of cause we associate with mechanical forces of attraction and repulsion. Further research may show that psychic causation has more in common with Aristotle’s formative or final cause than with his efficient cause [pp. 581–582]. Mystical Experiences Another large group of spontaneous experiences that we believe to be significant for psi research is mystical experience, also sometimes referred to as “religious” or “transcendent” experience or “cosmic consciousness,” after Bucke’s (1901/1969) famous study. Myers and James certainly included such experiences in their conception of psychical research, but mystical experiences unfortunately became one of the casualties that Stevenson (1990) lamented in his description of the “break-up” of the field. As we hope to make clear, there are important reasons, both empirical and theoretical, for psi researchers to once again expand their domain to include mystical experiences (see also Marshall, 2011). A mystical experience is generally understood to be “a strong impression of having encountered a reality radically different from the sensory-based world of everyday experience” (Wulff, 2014, p. 370). Perhaps the best overall definition of a mystical experience is that it “commonly brings unity, profound knowledge, and a sense of contact with reality” (Marshall, 2005, p. 26). Mystical experiences have been studied from many perspectives, from the theological to the neurobiological. Following Stace (1960/1987), they have generally been divided into two broad categories, introvertive and extrovertive. Generally speaking, in extrovertive experiences “the ordinary perceptual world remains, but in transfigured form,” where in introvertive experiences “one’s perceptual world is not merely transfigured but abolished,” resulting in a “pure, contentless, undifferentiated, unitary consciousness” (Kelly et al., pp. 505–506). Because introvertive experiences occur most frequently among long-term contemplatives and meditators, whereas extrovertive experiences often occur spontaneously among apparently ordinary persons, we focus here on the latter (for a recent general review of both types, see Kelly et al., 2007, Chapter 8; see Marshall, 2005, for an in-depth study of extrovertive experiences in particular). One of the most basic of the empirical arguments for studying mystical experiences in association with psi is that those who report having experienced one type are likely also to report the other. Blackmore (1984), Kohr (1980), and Palmer (1979) all reported positive correlations between the two kinds of experiences. Moreover, case collections of mystical experiences include many accounts of spontaneous psi experiences. The majority of these collections are based, in whole or in part, on reports collected by Alister Hardy and his colleagues at the Religious Experiences Research Unit, now the Alister Hardy Research Center (AHRC), first at Oxford, now at the University of Wales (Cohen & Phipps, 1979; Dinnage, 1991; Hay, 1990; Koestler, 1973; Maxwell & Tschudin, 1990). From the beginning of Hardy’s research, psi-type experiences have been frequently reported, including “warning” cases, OBEs, sensing the presence of or perceiving a deceased person (including crisis cases), PK events, healing, and precognition. People reported such experiences to the AHRC because they considered them somehow “mystical.” The line between psi and mystical experiences becomes even more difficult to draw with any precision when one realizes that the two classes share some important features. The experience of seeing an unusual light is “a major feature of classic mystical experiences” (Wulff, 2014, p. 395), and light is similarly reported in connection with many psi experiences, particularly accompanying apparitions or at deathbeds. A sense of presence is another commonly occurring feature of mystical experiences (Maxwell & Tschudin, 1990), and, as we have seen, a sense of presence figures frequently in telepathic impression or other crisis cases and among the experiences of bereaved persons. The sense of presence is often felt as vividly real, even as being physically located in space. The presence “is experienced paradoxically as ‘sensory’ yet unaccompanied by any of the normal sensory inputs” (Hay, 1994, p. 17). This sense of “reality” is another characteristic shared by mystical and psi experiences: “I remember it as the most real and living experience I have ever had” (Hay, 1990, p. 33). The line between psi and mystical experiences becomes particularly fuzzy with regard to NDEs, in which unusual light, sensing the presence of deceased loved ones or other figures, a strong feeling of the “realness” of the experience, psi cognitions, and a noetic, “mystical” component can all figure prominently. Perhaps one person reporting a mystical experience to AHRC summed it up best: “I am sure there is a difference between religious and ordinary psychic experience, but I don’t think it would be wise to draw an artificial dividing line” (Maxwell & Tschudin, 1990, p. 15). Other findings suggest that studying the two phenomena in conjunction with each other could shed important light on both. First of all, mystical experiencers seem to share many of the personality characteristics we have seen in connection with most of the other spontaneous phenomena discussed in this chapter, such as hypnotizability, absorption, creativity, and transliminality (Wulff, 2014, pp. 380–381). Because many of these same characteristics are found among schizophrenics and other persons suffering mental illness, the overwhelming tendency for many years has been to pathologize mystical experiences (Hufford, 1985). Yet research suggests that those having mystical experiences may even be, on average, better adjusted than others (Kelly et al., 2007, p. 555). Myers and James recognized what contemporary researchers are rediscovering, “the paradox that although religious experience and schizophrenic experience seem to have similarities, they have opposite effects” (Hay, 1994, p. 13). This observation led Myers to conjecture that the psychological mechanism behind psychic, creative, and mystical experiences, as well as pathological ones such as the dissociative disorders, was the same, but could take “evolutive” as well as “dissolutive” forms (see Kelly et al., 2007, pp. 83– 86, 470–481). Modern researchers on mystical experiences have echoed this hypothesis of a “personality trait [that] could be associated with both a proneness to having healthy spiritual experiences and, in some cases, a proneness to having psychotic breakdowns” (Maxwell & Tschudin, 1990, p. 7). Psi and mystical experiences also seem to share many of the same “triggers” or conducive conditions. Like psi experiences, mystical experiences often occur at times of stress or bereavement (Dinnage, 1991; Hay, 1990; Maxwell & Tschudin, 1990). Psi and mystical experiences also suggest the importance of an altered state, or the abeyance of ordinary, supraliminal consciousness. For example, both mystical and psi experiences tend to occur when a person is alone. Moreover, the association of psi, or siddhis, and mystical experiences, particularly as expounded in the Yoga Sutras of Patanjali, led psi researchers to adopt conditions conducive to the latter in ganzfeld research (Honorton, 1977). Marshall (2011) has argued that the empirical connections between psi and mystical experiences suggest the “need for an explanatory framework able to account for both…. An explanation that might seem reasonable for one may come to grief over the other” (p. 9). The personality characteristics and conducive conditions associated with both types of phenomena support the theory that a psychological “permeability” between the subliminal and supraliminal aspects of consciousness, together with the relaxation of the ordinary sensorimotor “filter,” can allow access to aspects of reality not usually accessible. We also called attention earlier to the idea that psi suggests, not stimulus and response, but an interconnection between, say, the percipient and the target person or object. In mystical experience there is “a sense of being unified with natural objects” through a “breakdown of boundaries between consciousness and object … the self is experienced as larger, expanded beyond the usual boundaries…. One’s boundaries become as if permeable, connected with the objects of the world” (Forman, 1998, pp. 198–199). This interconnectedness is, we believe, fundamental to psi, mystical, and all the other experiences we have been discussing in this chapter, and should form the bedrock of all theorizing about them. Conclusion The study of spontaneous experiences is of far more import than as, at best, a way-station or, at worst, a detour on the road to scientific respectability. Others before us have emphasized the methodological importance of studying psi phenomena in their natural context and the probable futility of ever understanding psi without doing that. More generally, we believe that in modern psi research we need to reemphasize a theoretical orientation sufficient to define, both for ourselves and for others, what exactly it is that we are studying, and why. Our conviction is that the theoretical issues behind psi research are those of volition and the mind-brain relation. We believe that clearly situating the phenomena we study in this broader theoretical context will help dispel the misperception that we are just studying “anomalies” like ghosts and mind-reading, and will instead attract the attention of what we think is a slowly growing number of scientists, philosophers, and others who recognize the incompleteness and inadequacy of the currently dominant physicalist model to account for consciousness. Whether we lead the way toward a more comprehensive model of consciousness, or remain marginalized, is up to us. References Alvarado, C. S. (1987). Comments on Case studies in parapsychology and on the value of research in this area. Journal of Parapsychology, 51, 337– 352. Alvarado, C. S. (2006). Neglected near-death phenomena. Journal of NearDeath Studies, 24, 131–151. Arcangel, D., and Schwartz, G. E. (2005). Afterlife encounters: Ordinary people, extraordinary experiences. Charlottesville, VA: Hampton Roads. Barbato, M., Blunden, C., Reid, K., Irwin, H., and Rodriguez, P. (1999). Parapsychological phenomena near the time of death. Journal of Palliative Care, 15 (2), 30–37. Barrett, W. F. (1926). Death-bed visions. London, UK: Metheun. Beitman, B. D. (2011). Coincidence studies. Psychiatric Annals, 12, 561– 562, 567–571. Beloff, J. (1977). Psi phenomena: Causal versus acausal interpretation. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 49, 573–582. Bergson, H. (1913). Presidential address. Proceedings of the Society for Psychical Research, 27, 157–175. Blackmore, S. J. (1984). A postal survey of OBEs and other experiences. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 52, 225–244. Bozzano, E. (1906). Apparitions of deceased persons at deathbeds. Annals of Psychical Science, 3, 67–100. Braude, S. E. (1992). Psi and the nature of abilities. Journal of Parapsychology, 56, 205–228. Brayne, S., Farnham, C., and Fenwick, P. (2006). Deathbed phenomena and their effect on a palliative care team: A pilot study. American Journal of Hospice and Palliative Medicine, 23, 17–24. Brayne, S., Lovelace, H., and Fenwick, P. (2008). End-of-life experience and the dying process in a Gloucestershire nursing home as reported by nurses and care assistants. American Journal of Hospice and Palliative Medicine, 25, 195–206. Bucke. R. M. (1969). Cosmic consciousness. New York: E. P. Dutton. (Original work published 1901). Cardeña, E. (2005). The phenomenology of deep hypnosis: Quiescent and physically active. International Journal of Clinical and Experimental Hypnosis, 53, 37–59. Cohen, J. M., and Phipps, J.-F. (1979). The common experience. Los Angeles, CA: J. P. Tarcher. Cook [Kelly], E. W. (1991). Psychology and parapsychology: Some comments on Paul Kline’s “Psychology exposed, or the emperor’s new clothes.” Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 85, 183– 192. Cook [Kelly], E. W. (1994). The subliminal consciousness: F. W. H. Myers’s approach to survival. Journal of Parapsychology, 58, 39–58. Cousins, N. (1976). Anatomy of an illness (as perceived by the patient). New England Journal of Medicine, 295, 1458–1463. Dinnage, R. (1991). Psi and religious experience. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 57, 355–359. Dowling, J. (1984). Lourdes cures and their medical assessment. Journal of the Royal Society of Medicine, 77, 634–638. Feather, S. R., and Schmicker, M. (2005). The gift: ESP, the extraordinary experiences of ordinary people. New York: St. Martin’s Press. Fenwick, P. (2005). Science and spirituality: A challenge for the 21st century. Journal of Near-Death Studies, 23, 131–157. Fenwick, P., and Brayne, S. (2011). End-of-life experiences: Reaching out for compassion, communication, and connection—meaning of deathbed visions and coincidences. American Journal of Hospice and Palliative Care, 28, 7–15. Fenwick, P., and Fenwick, E. (2008). The art of dying: A journey to elsewhere. London, UK: Continuum. Fenwick, P., Lovelace, H., and Brayne, S. (2007). End of life experiences and their implications for palliative care. International Journal of Environmental Studies, 64, 315–323. Fenwick, P., Lovelace, H., and Brayne, S. (2010). Comfort for the dying: Five year retrospective and one year prospective studies of end of life experiences. Archives of Gerontology and Geriatrics, 51, 173–179. Forman, R. K. C. (1998). What does mysticism have to teach us about consciousness? Journal of Consciousness Studies, 5, 185–201. Gauld, A. (1993). The function of a Society for Psychical Research at the present time. Proceedings of the Society for Psychical Research, 57, 253– 273. Grimaldi, D. A., and Engel, M. S. (2007). Why descriptive science still matters. BioScience, 57, 646–647. Grimby, A. (1993). Bereavement among elderly people: Grief reactions, post-bereavement hallucinations and quality of life. Acta Psychiatrica Scandinavia, 87, 72–80. Guggenheim, B., and Guggenheim, J. (1995). Hello from heaven. New York: Bantam. Gurney, E., and Myers, F. W. H. (1884). Visible apparitions. Nineteenth Century, 16, 791–815. Haig, S. (2007). The brain: The power of hope. Time magazine, 169, 118– 119. Haight, J. (1979). Spontaneous psi cases: A survey and preliminary study of ESP, attitude, and personality relationship. Journal of Parapsychology, 43, 179–203. Haraldsson, E. (1985). Representative national surveys of psychic phenomena: Iceland, Great Britain, Sweden, USA and Gallup’s multinational survey. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 53, 145–158. Haraldsson, E. (1988–1989). Survey of claimed encounters with the dead. Omega, 19, 103–113. Haraldsson, E. (1994). Apparitions of the dead: Analysis of a new collection of 357 reports. In E. W. Cook [Kelly] and D. L. Delanoy (Eds.), Research in parapsychology 1991 (pp. 1–6). Metuchen, NJ: Scarecrow Press. Haraldsson, E. (2009). Alleged encounters with the dead: The importance of violent death in 337 new cases. Journal of Parapsychology, 73, 91–118. Haraldsson, E. (2012). The departed among the living: An investigative study of afterlife encounters. Guildford, UK: White Crow Books. Haraldsson, E., and Houtkooper, J. M. (1991). Psychic experiences in the Multinational Human Values Study: Who reports them? Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 85, 145–165. Harrington, A. (1997). Introduction. In A. Harrington (Ed.), The placebo effect: An interdisciplinary exploration (pp. 1–11). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Hay, D. (1990). Religious experience today: Studying the facts. London, UK: Mowbray. Hay, D. (1994). “The biology of god”: What is the current status of Hardy’s hypothesis? International Journal for the Psychology of Religion, 4, 1–23. Hearne, K. M. T. (1984). A survey of reported premonitions and of those who have them. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 52, 261– 270. Honorton, C. (1977). Psi and internal attention states. In B. B. Wolman (Ed.), Handbook of parapsychology (pp. 435–472). New York: Van Nostrand Reinhold. Hufford, D. J. (1982). The terror that comes in the night. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press. Hufford, D. J. (1985). Commentary: Mystical experience in the modern world. In G. W. Foster, The world was flooded with light: A mystical experience remembered (pp. 87–183). Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press. Huxley, A. (1990). The doors of perception. In A. Huxley, The doors of perception and heaven and hell (pp. 7–79). New York: Perennial Library. (Original work published 1954). Hyslop, J. H. (1908). Psychical research and the resurrection. Boston, MA: Small, Maynard. Irwin, H. J. (1994). The phenomenology of parapsychological experiences. In S. Krippner (Ed.), Advances in parapsychological research 7 (pp. 10– 76). Jefferson, NC: McFarland. Irwin, H. J., and Watt, C. A. (2007). An introduction to parapsychology (5th ed.). Jefferson, NC: McFarland. James, W. (1900). Human immortality: Two supposed objections to the doctrine (2nd ed.). Boston & New York: Houghton, Mifflin. (Original work published 1898). Johnson, A. (1899). Coincidences. Proceedings of the Society for Psychical Research, 14, 158–330. Jung, C. G. (1970). Synchronicity: An acausal connecting principle (R. F. C. Hull, Trans.). In G. Adler, M. Fordham, and H. Read (Eds.), The structure and dynamics of the psyche (2nd ed., pp. 417–531). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. (Original work published 1952). Kelly, E. F., Kelly, E.W., Crabtree, A., Gauld, A., Grosso, M., and Greyson, B. (2007). Irreducible mind: Toward a psychology for the 21st century. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield. Koestler, A. (1972). The roots of coincidence. New York: Vintage Books. Koestler, A. (1973). Part three: Anecdotal cases. In A. Hardy, R. Harvie, and A. Koestler, The challenge of chance (pp. 157–204). London, UK: Hutchinson. Kohr, R. L. (1980). A survey of psi experiences among members of a special population. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 74, 395–411. LaGrand, L. E. (1997). After death communication: Final farewells. St. Paul, MN: Llewellyn. Mann, B. S., and Jaye, C. (2007). “Are we one body?” Body boundaries in telesomatic experiences. Anthropology & Medicine, 14, 183–195. Margnelli, M. (1999). An unusual case of stigmatization. Journal of Scientific Exploration, 13, 461–482. Marshall, P. (2005). Mystical encounters with the natural world: Experiences and explanations. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Marshall, P. (2011). The psychical and the mystical: Boundaries, connections, common origins. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 75, 1–13. Maxwell, M., and Tschudin, V. (1990). Seeing the invisible: Modern religious and other transcendent experiences. London, UK: Arkana. McClenon, J. (1994). Surveys of anomalous experience: A cross-cultural analysis. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 88, 117– 135. McCready, W. C., and Greeley, A. M. (1976). The ultimate values of the American population. Beverly Hills, CA: Sage. Moody, R. L. (1946). Bodily changes during abreaction. Lancet, 248, 934– 935. Moody, R. L. (1948). Bodily changes during abreaction. Lancet, 251, 964. Morris, R. L. (1986). What psi is not: The necessity for experiments. In H. Edge, R. L. Morris, J. Palmer, and J. H. Rush, Foundations of parapsychology (pp. 70–110). London, UK: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Murphy, G. (1953). The importance of spontaneous cases. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 47, 89–103. Murphy, M. (1992). The future of the body. Los Angeles, CA: Jeremy P. Tarcher. Myers, F. W. H. (1884–1885). Specimens of the classification of cases for “Phantasms of the Living.” Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 1, 54–245. Myers, F. W. H. (1903). Human personality and its survival of bodily death. London, UK: Longmans, Green. (Available at http://www.esalen.org/ctrarchive/book-hpsurvival.html). Nachman, G. (2010). Review of Synchronicity: Multiple perspectives on meaningful coincidences. Journal of Parapsychology, 74, 387–391. Nahm, M. (2009). Terminal lucidity in people with mental illness and other mental disability: An overview and implications for possible explanatory models. Journal of Near-Death Studies, 28, 87–106. Nahm. M., and Greyson, B. (2009). Terminal lucidity in patients with chronic schizophrenia and dementia. Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, 197, 942–944. Nahm, M., Greyson, B., Kelly, E. W., and Haraldsson, E. (2012). Terminal lucidity: A review and a case collection. Archives of Gerontology and Geriatrics, 55, 138–142. Olson, P. R., Suddeth, J. A., Peterson, P. J., and Egelhoff, C. (1985). Hallucinations of widowhood. Journal of the American Geriatric Society, 33, 543–547. Osis, K. (1986). Characteristics of purposeful action in an apparition case. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 80, 175–193. Osis, K., and Haraldsson, E. (2012). At the hour of death. Guildford, UK: White Crow Books. (Original work published 1977) Palmer, J. (1979). A community mail survey of psychic experiences. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 73, 221–251. Palmer, J. (1992). From survival to transcendence: Reflections on psi as anomalous. Journal of Parapsychology, 56, 229–254. Rees, W. D. (1971). The hallucinations of widowhood. British Medical Journal, 4, 37–41. Rhine, L. E. (1967). Hallucinatory experiences and psychosomatic psi. Journal of Parapsychology, 31, 111–134. Rhine, L. E. (1977). Research methods with spontaneous cases. In B. B. Wolman (Ed.), Handbook of parapsychology (pp. 59–80). New York: Van Nostrand Reinhold. Rhine, L. E. (1981). The invisible picture. Jefferson, NC: McFarland. Ross, C. A., and Joshi, S. (1992). Paranormal experiences in the general population. Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, 180, 357–361. Rush, B. (1812). Mental inquiries and observations upon diseases of the mind. Philadelphia, PA: Kimber & Richardson. Schouten, S. (1979). Analysis of spontaneous cases as reported in “Phantasms of the Living.” European Journal of Parapsychology, 2, 408– 455. Schouten. S. (1983). A different approach for analyzing spontaneous cases. Journal of Parapsychology, 47, 323–340. Sidgwick, E. (1922). Phantasms of the living. Proceedings of the Society for Psychical Research, 33, 23–429. Stace, W. T. (1987). Mysticism and philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press. (Original work published 1960). Sternberg, E. (2000). The balance within: The science connecting health and emotions. New York: W. H. Freeman. Stevenson, I. (1968). The substantiality of spontaneous cases. Proceedings of the Parapsychological Association, 5, 91–128. Stevenson, I. (1970). Letter. Journal of Parapsychology, 34, 143–149. Stevenson, I. (1982). The contribution of apparitions to the evidence for survival. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 76, 341– 358. Stevenson, I. (1983). Do we need a new word to supplement “hallucination”? American Journal of Psychiatry, 140, 1609–1611. Stevenson, I. (1987). Guest editorial: Why investigate spontaneous cases? Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 81, 101–109. Stevenson, I. (1990). Thoughts on the decline of major paranormal phenomena. Proceedings of the Society for Psychical Research, 57, 149– 162. Stevenson, I. (1995). Six modern apparitional experiences. Journal of Scientific Exploration, 9, 351–366. Stevenson, I. (1997). Reincarnation and biology: A contribution to the etiology of birthmarks and birth defects. Vol. 1. New York: Praeger. Stevenson, I. (1999). What are the irreducible components of the scientific enterprise? Journal of Scientific Exploration, 13, 257–270. Stokes, D. M. (1997). Spontaneous psi phenomena. In S. Krippner (Ed.), Advances in parapsychological research 8 (pp. 6–87). Jefferson, NC: McFarland. Storm, L. (Ed.). (2008). Synchronicity: Multiple perspectives on meaningful coincidence. Grosetto, Italy: Pari. Virtanen, L. (1990). “That must have been ESP!” An examination of psychic experiences. Bloomington and Indianapolis: Indiana University Press. (Original work published 1977). Weiner, D. H., and Haight, J. M. (1986). Charting hidden channels: Louisa E. Rhine’s case collection project. In K. Ramakrishna Rao (Ed.), Case studies in parapsychology (pp. 14–30). Jefferson, NC: McFarland. West, D. J. (1948). The investigation of spontaneous cases. Proceedings of the Society for Psychical Research, 48, 264–300. West, D. J. (1990). A pilot census of hallucinations. Proceedings of the Society for Psychical Research, 57, 163–207. West, D. J. (1995). Note on a recent psychic survey. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 60, 168–171. White, R. A. (1985). The spontaneous, the imaginal, and psi: Foundations for a depth parapsychology. In R. A. White and J. Solfvin (Eds.), Research in parapsychology 1984 (pp. 166–190). Metuchen, NJ: Scarecrow Press. White, R. A. (1992). Review of approaches to the study of spontaneous psi experiences. Journal of Scientific Exploration, 6, 93–126. Wulff, D. M. (2014). Mystical experience. In E. Cardeña, S. J. Lynn, and S. Krippner (Eds.), Varieties of anomalous experience: Examining the scientific evidence (2nd ed.) (pp. 369–408). Washington, D.C.: American Psychological Association. OceanofPDF.com CHAPTER 6 Macro-Psychokinesis Methodological Concerns GRAHAM WATKINS “Macro-PK” is a term used to describe ostensible psychokinetic effects (PK) so strong or so dramatic as to require no use of statistics. In practice, these effects have manifested in such ways as “table-tipping” (or complete table levitation), the movement of objects apparently by mental effort alone, the bending of rigid objects such as spoons, and levitation. Some other effects, such as quick and dramatic healings, creating images on photographic film, or the spontaneous starting of fires, can be included as well. In a few cases, apparent teleportation of objects (or perhaps spontaneous creation of objects or materials) has been observed. Whether all these are one unified process or several different processes is at present completely unknown, since currently there are not even testable hypotheses available concerning possible mechanisms. At first glance, it would seem that large-scale PK is an ideal phenomenon for study, far better than the “micro–PK” seen in experiments with random number generators or dice, in which the effects are small but statistically significant [see chapter 20, this volume]. It is an area, though, that is rife with problems for the researcher. Up until the 18th century at least, the literature does not contain much that might be ascribed to PK effects— probably because any such events were not seen this way. An event we would in modern times refer to as PK would in the year 1000 AD have been seen as either a miracle (that is, credited to a deity) or as witchcraft/sorcery, depending on the context. Some phenomena have been recorded from societies other than Western industrialized ones that might have been due to PK. One of the best examples of this was the Indigenous Pawnee “doctor performances,” which were held annually and which were observed by a number of outsiders, in particular Major Frank North and his brother Luthor. Frank North was the army officer in charge of the Pawnee scouts (allied with the army in the wars against the Sioux, Cheyenne, and other plains tribes). These shows by the “doctors” (shamans) were intended as both ritual and entertainment. Although there can be little question that some of the effects were accomplished by the same sort of sleight-of-hand that later magicians would use on stage —Franz Boas noted that this was commonly done, as shown by a shaman having his hands tied before “going into trance” and then claiming the spirits untied him (Boas, 1974)—there were some which were very difficult to explain considering the simple setting. Among these is the “mud duck” performance, in which a model of a duck is made from mud and apparently comes alive when placed on water, quacking and moving about—only to turn back into mud when removed from the water. Frank North records having seen this done by one of the “doctors” quite casually, without setting or preparation—a handful of ordinary mud is shaped like a turtle and then comes alive, after which it was converted back to a lump of mud. When North asked what would happen if the shaman left it as a live turtle he was assured it would soon die, and North states that this is what happened. In another performance, a boy or girl, clad only in a loincloth, was attacked and disemboweled by a “bear person” (a man dressed in a bearskin using knives as claws) that then ate some of the victim’s entrails. North could not see how this could conceivably be done under the circumstances unless the victim was actually killed, but the victim was always seen alive and well at the end of the performance (Weltfish, 1965). The shamans described above were the healers of their tribes (who often referred to themselves as “doctors” when speaking English). These were men and women with extensive knowledge of herbal medications and an understanding of surgical procedures. Just as important though, if not more so, was their role as mediators between the world of ordinary reality and the spirit world, a world believed to be inhabited by deities, nonhuman entities of various sorts, and the spirits of the dead, especially tribal ancestors. In a sense, the mediums that came to prominence during the 19th and early 20th century as part of the Spiritist movement were doing the same sort of thing as the shamans, acting as intercessors between the ordinary world and a presumed spirit world. Emanuel Swedenborg, whose works from 1741 to about 1770 are often cited as the foundation of the Spiritist movement, recited large numbers of dreams and visions that seem to correspond rather closely with the experiences of shamans (Crompton, 2005). Beginning in the middle of the 19th century, serious attempts at understanding these phenomena from a scientific perspective began. Quite a variety of investigators studied the “physical mediums,” common in the years between the 1850s and 1920s, who produced various physical effects at their séances, such as movement of objects (table-tipping), levitations, “materializations” and “apports” (the appearance or transportation of objects), unusual sounds, and the production of “ectoplasm” (said to be a physical manifestation of spiritual energy). Fraud was common in these performances, and was exposed many times. In some cases the mediums themselves admitted that their performances involved fraud (Keene, 1976). As a result, especially given that physical mediums are quite rare today, the general perception, by the public and the scientific establishment in general is that all mediums were merely duping a gullible audience. But for some fraud was never proved; perhaps most notably in the studies of D. D. Home done between 1870 and 1872 by noted physicist William Crookes (Crookes, 1874), which serve as early examples of how such studies should be conducted. As the 20th century continued, the physical mediums began to disappear. There were a few more, notably Eusapia Palladino, but by the 1940s the spectacular feats Home seemed capable of were no longer seen. Braude (2007) has suggested that this was because the interpretation of the phenomenon had changed, that the events were no longer seen as the actions of spirits but rather as psychokinetic (then normally called “telekinetic”) actions on the part of the medium—meaning the medium was responsible for them, and thus he/she could not claim to being a mere “tool” of the “spirits.” To be sure, séances are still held, but with few exceptions little attention is paid to them [but see chapters 19 and 23]. In the years following the end of the era of the mediums, only a handful of individuals apparently capable of anything close to macro–PK have come to the attention of science, and practically all of them fall into two categories: those who believe that they can do unusual things and present themselves to researchers, and those who witness someone else doing macro–PK and believe that they can do it as well. There are also those who are unable to control their presumable PK abilities, and most of these, of course, are normally regarded as poltergeist cases. There are a few others—for example, the case of noted theoretical physicist Wolfgang Pauli (one of the pioneers of quantum physics)—who did not fit the usual model of the poltergeist. There was such a strong tendency for equipment to break or malfunction, often for no known reason, when Pauli was around that experimental physicists banned him from their labs and dubbed the phenomenon “The Pauli Effect” (Enz, 2009). Pauli himself believed that this effect might be caused by PK and had considerable interest in the subject (Roth, 2002). One of the earlier examples of the first type was Ted Serios (Eisenbud, 1967), who was apparently able to produce images on Polaroid film. Others included Nina Kulagina, who was brought to the attention of the West by Ostrander and Schroeder in their book Psychic Discoveries Behind the Iron Curtain (1970). Although Kulagina became well-known, easily the best-known of the psychics at this time, and perhaps of all time, was Uri Geller. Geller became famous for a number of demonstrations, including remote-viewing and dowsing, but is most remembered for his alleged PK performances, particularly the bending of keys and, most notably, spoons. He was studied extensively at Stanford Research Institute (Targ & Puthoff, 1974), observed by a range of other scientists, and performed on various shows on television and in person for several years continuing to the present (although he now calls himself simply an entertainer and a “mystifier” rather than a psychic). Even so, “spoon bending,” popularized by Geller, has become almost standardized as a paradigm for macro–PK. “Spoon bending parties” are fairly common, continuing to the present. Author Michael Crichton (1988) reported success at one of these, as did researcher Dean Radin (2006), among many others. The experience reported is that the spoon (or other piece of tableware) rather suddenly becomes slightly warm and then quite soft and pliable, so that it can be bent effortlessly. At times spoons and such have been seen to droop and sag without any pressure at all being applied, as if the metal had become molten (Joines, 2014, personal communication). Interestingly, a successful spoon-bender at one of these parties was Michael Shermer, founder of the Skeptic’s Society and editor of the magazine Skeptic. In a posted video (Shermer, 2007) he is seen folding the bowl of a heavy spoon he initially could not bend at all. He then had the bend analyzed at a metallurgical laboratory, where it was determined that the bend was caused by physical force, not heat—which Shermer interprets as “proof” that this was done “simply by adrenalin, induced by the crowd’s enthusiasm” rather than PK. It should be apparent that showing that a spoon was bent by mechanical force and not heat does not allow us to determine whether it was or was not bent by PK, since we know almost nothing about any mechanism that might mediate the forces seen in PK phenomena. Other examples include Elmer Green’s (Green, 1977) studies with the yogi Swami Rama, the mouse-ether experiments (Watkins & Watkins, 1971; Watkins, Watkins, & Wells, 1972), and Felicia Parise (Honorton, 1993; Wells & Watkins, 1974). A few patterns should be apparent in the studies described above. First, they are primarily observational, the only “experimentation” done consisting of such things as placing the person inside a Faraday cage; but to be fair, with no theory of the mechanism of PK on the horizon, other than preliminary ideas advanced by Brian Josephson and others connecting paranormal phenomena with quantum concepts such as entanglement and the nonlocality implicit in Bell’s Theorem (Josephson & Pallikari-Viras, 1991), meaningful experiments are not easy to design. The second is that anything like a high-profile demonstration will be instantly and persistently attacked by skeptical critics, and historically these critics manage to convince the public—and by extension the larger scientific community—that such demonstrations are the result of error or, more commonly, fraud. This is done by showing, or at times by merely suggesting, that the phenomena can be emulated by stage magic techniques. In doing so, inconvenient facts—such as Ted Serios’s “error” pictures—are simply ignored. Beyond that, there is a logical error in this thinking, rarely mentioned; the fact that a stage magician can more or less duplicate the phenomenon does not prove that the original demonstration was accomplished by the same means. It would be a simple matter to construct an apparatus that would cause a basketball to go through the hoop when thrown toward it from a distance, but this does not mean that every college and professional basketball player who shoots a three-point shot is cheating. But because the “cheating” hypothesis is the easier of the two to accept, it is the task of the researcher to create, whenever possible, situations in which cheating, at least cheating by the participant, is simply not possible. Adding to the difficulties is the fact that many of the gifted participants one must work with in this area are eccentric, to say the least. This is very well illustrated by the enigmatic case of Ted Owens, the “PK Man” (Mishlove, 2000). Owens appeared to be able to cause—or perhaps predict, sometimes with startling accuracy—major weather events, plane crashes, blackouts, and in particular the appearance of UFOs. At first Owens himself attributed his talents to PK, but later claimed that space aliens, with whom he claimed to be in constant contact, were mediating these events. However, not all of the effects predicted by Owens actually took place—at least not in the way he had predicted, and he had a tendency to take credit for events in the past. The Owens case is difficult to evaluate. On the one hand, it is hard not to take seriously someone who can cause or predict lightning strikes with precision, as Owens is stated to have done. On the other, realistic statistical consideration of possible simple coincidence in such cases is virtually impossible; if, for instance, very large numbers of such predictions are made, and those that were accurate selected for, then the case for actual psychokinesis or precognition becomes weak. But if Owens was able to do what he is credited with by PK, then his abilities were similar to, or even greater than, the apparent abilities of physical mediums such as D. D. Home. Interestingly, this fits well with Braude’s theory, mentioned above, that the physical mediums might have disappeared when it was no longer felt that the “spirits” were causing the phenomena—in the case of Owens it was not spirits but rather alien intelligences. Also showing similarities with some of the performances of the 19th century mediums was Katie, the “Gold Leaf Lady,” a Florida housewife on whose skin gold-colored foil appeared, at times virtually right in front of investigators. This of course is very similar to the materializations and apports of the mediums. Katie was not limited to just the production of this foil, she also commonly received other apported objects, was said to be able to bend metal and to cause seeds to germinate in her cupped hands, and at times worked successfully with police in solving crimes. Analysis of the “gold leaf” that appeared on her face and body showed that it was not gold, but rather brass foil, also called “Dutch leaf” or “composition metal.” Although noted skeptic Paul Kurtz assured TV viewers she was merely attaching it to herself with some material like hair spray, no traces of adhesive were found in the analyses (Braude, 2007). More recently, experiments have been conducted using a “psychic healing” technique to treat cancer in mice (Bengston 2010; Bengston & Kinsley, 2000). In these, mice were infected with mammary adenocarcinomas of a type well known to cause the death of the mice within 27 days. These mice were then treated by “laying on of hands” (although the mice were in plastic cages and never actually touched) for one hour per day. In the course of a number of experiments, more than 85 percent of the treated mice showed remission and survived. Oddly, almost 70 percent of control mice that were housed in the same lab (and were “visited” by the healer, although not “treated”) also showed remission and survived, while other controls, sent to a different site, all died well within the 27-day limit. The “healing technique” Bengston describes was learned from a New York healer who in the end did not actually participate in the experiments. It involves a series of routine mental tasks not directly related to the process or idea of healing the mice; Bengston states that it takes “several weeks” to learn it. He also notes that “disbelievers” actually tended to do better (or at least as well) as believers in this task, in contrast to the usual “sheep-goat” effect seen so often in parapsychology (Schmeidler & Murphy, 1946) [see chapter 9, this volume]. In the experimental mice, the tumors followed an unusual pattern. After ten days, a “blackened area” developed in the vicinity of the tumor, which then ulcerated—and, in spite of the alarming appearance of these tumors, the mice did not seem especially distressed. These ulcerations then cleared up and healed, allowing the mice to live out their normal life span. Beyond that, it appears that the mice that had been healed were now immune to the adenocarcinoma, that is, they did not develop new tumors when reinfected. As of the present there has been no attempt to replicate these experiments in other laboratories. Experimenting with healers of various disciplines and using pieces of ordinary cucumbers as targets, Hideyuki Kokubo (2013) has demonstrated some interesting effects. The healers’ efforts have been measured in three ways: by the detection of biophoton emissions, by fluorescence, and by analysis of the gases emitted by the cucumber pieces—that is, their odor. Not only was Kokubo able to show an effect, but he has derived from his experiments an equation defining what he calls the J value, which is the natural logarithm of the ratio between control samples and experimental samples and which Kokubo suggests defines the strength of the phenomenon. In his experiments the effects were initially minor or negligible, but rose to a peak more than five hours after the healing session took place, after which they declined gradually. By using large numbers of slices in an array around the healer, he was also able to show a spiraling wave pattern of effects. Depending on the position of the cucumber slice in the spiral, the effect could be positive, negative, or zero. Averaged together the values tended toward zero. Relating this to quantum physics, Kokubo suggests that “there are plural unknown factors which cannot be understood, and that those unknown factors follow their own physical laws” (Kokubo, 2013). But even so, if Kokubo’s results can be confirmed there are several profound implications for future research. Although psi phenomena in general and PK specifically cannot be shown to be distance-dependent, exact distances may matter, as is the case with effects related to sound, especially in the lower frequencies. Second, as Kokubo points out, multiple healers or other PK agents may interfere with each other (depending on spatial arrangements). These findings might explain why some séances showed very dramatic effects and some none at all, and may also serve to explain why a particular experiment seems to work in one environment and not in another. At present, there is considerable public interest in a device commonly called a “psi wheel” (Norris, 2007). These are simple in construction, little more than a pyramid-shaped cap of paper or aluminum foil balanced on the top of a needle that has been fixed in an upright position. The user then attempts to make the cap spin. Advocates claim it can be used to train psychokinetic powers; critics point out, correctly, that it can easily be made to spin due to the rise of heated air at the base, which will occur if warm hands are placed close to the wheel. The wheels are also quite sensitive to static electricity, although exactly how this could make them spin (without systematic circular movements of a charged object) is not clear. A commercial version called the Egely Wheel (Egely & Dus, 1991) uses internal electronics to measure the rotation of the wheel and display it in visual or audio format (it is marketed as a “vitality meter”). Little or no formal research has as yet been done with psi wheels/Egely Wheels, but they do offer a possible vehicle for the testing of psychokinesis, as it is not difficult to eliminate heat and other air currents, static, or vibrations as causative factors in any observed movements of the wheel. Since two models of the commercial Egely wheel are available essentially world-wide and are standardized devices, they represent a better tool for parapsychologists than the individually-produced “psi wheels.” The first steps in this sort of research, of course, is finding a participant who can consistently make the wheel move and setting the stage so that any sort of cheating is simply not possible. To this end, the researcher must be cognizant of any normal ways the wheel can be made to move—for example, the Egely wheels are very easily controllable by directed air currents (i.e., simply blowing on it) and therefore must be isolated from the individual’s air space. This isolation must be complete—a mask such as the one Swami Rama was asked to wear (Green, 1977) is inadequate, as are any sort of simple air barriers. A method such as placing the wheel under a bell jar that is then sealed to the table is preferred. Wheels belonging to the participants should not be used and they should not be permitted any physical contact whatsoever with the wheels used in the formal trials. It has been argued (Truzzi, 1997) that the researcher who studies phenomena like macro PK should enlist the help of persons skilled in the techniques of stage magic, since the average scientist cannot be expected to know these and in many cases the purported effect can be simulated by a stage magic performer. There can be benefits in this, as there are quite a number of more or less standard tricks that most magicians would be familiar with, such as, for example, “invisible string.” Caution is still needed, however, since magicians are constantly inventing new tricks, and a potential participant may very well have created an illusion not known to the consultant. In general, the better approach is simply to eliminate any and all potential for intentional fraud or tampering, and this can be done. Perusing a text like Magic and Showmanship: A Handbook for Conjurers (Nelms, 2000) will offer a general picture of most of the general principles used in stage magic, and it will become apparent that, if the participant has no access of any ordinary sort to either the targets or the staging area, deceptions cannot take place. Caution should be used to take such effects as static and magnetism (which may not require direct contact) into account. Wiseman and Morris (1995) also provide good guidelines on managing selected participants. In experiments like those using the Egely wheel, taking steps to ensure that fraud is not possible is not difficult. Any and all equipment used should be kept under the absolute control of the researcher, nothing owned or provided by the participant can ever be used, and s/he should not be allowed any direct contact with the equipment—especially not when out of the researcher’s sight. Stage magic tricks are done in three primary ways: by the use of hidden or unseen equipment, by sleight-of-hand, and, most commonly, by misdirection—that is, the observer’s attention is directed away from the location where the real effect is taking place (Nelms, 2000). In the case of a study using a device like an Egely wheel, the researcher should take all steps to ensure that forces that can affect it are both known and absolutely blocked off, as noted above with respect to air currents, or measured during the experiment. As an example, if it were to be discovered that the Egely wheel was sensitive to magnetic forces (it is not), then steps would have to be taken to ensure that it was not being controlled by magnets on the participant’s person or hands, and the best way to do this would be to set up equipment to measure magnetic fields. Beyond matters like these, it should be clear that complete isolation of the apparatus from the participant at all times can render standard stage magic tricks impossible. In some case like spoon-bending, in which the participant has to be allowed to handle the materials, this is much more difficult. Here the advice of experienced magicians might be helpful, but, as noted above, even they cannot be assumed to know all the possible ways a trick can be accomplished. For these reasons, paradigms like these are not the best choices. In general, however, the experimental setting should be as comfortable as possible for the participant. As noted previously, talented individuals often have unusual personalities, and processes like these are fragile, easy to disrupt. As long as it does not compromise the soundness of the procedure, participants should be made to feel at ease and allowed to work in their preferred style. One example is Crookes allowing D. D. Home to dangle an accordion (that the “spirits” would then play) under the table rather than over it—after having taken precautions to eliminate the chance of fraud (Crookes, 1874). Once volunteers are located and the phenomenon can be reasonably consistently produced, various parameters and corollaries that should eventually shed light on the nature of macro–PK, and, by extension, psi in general can be explored. Examples include studies on the physiology or psychology of the participants—how and why they differ from average people, as was done in the mouse-ether experiments (Watkins et al., 1972). The authors found that successful participants showed changes specifically in fingertip plethysmography (an increase in peripheral vasoconstriction) and in the T waves of the EKG, changes not seen in unselected (and unsuccessful) volunteers. Similar physiological changes were seen during the experiments with Felicia Parise (Watkins & Watkins, 1973). Additionally, the researcher should look for post-effects such as the linger effect described by Watkins and Watkins (1973) in the experiments with Felicia Parise, by Watkins et al. (1972), and by Wells and Watkins (1974) in the mouse-ether experiments. Both studies showed effects continuing after the volunteers had not only ceased their efforts but had left the room, effects that decayed gradually over a period of approximately 30 minutes. Additionally, in the case of Felicia Parise the compass needle she apparently caused to move remained off north and was not responsive to a magnet when it was in the location where she had concentrated on it, but moved back to north and became responsive to a magnet when moved away. Additionally, possible pre-effects, while not shown in any current studies, might be considered as well. Arrays of Egely wheels might be used to determine whether the spatial and temporal effects reported by Kokubo (2013) apply. Finally, the effects of various physical phenomena such as electromagnetic fields, whether generated during the process or affecting the PK process either positively or negatively are ripe for exploration once a reliable procedure is established, taking examples from the literature such as the observation that Kulagina was negatively affected by thunderstorms (Parodi, 2005). That something seems unlikely to affect the process does not mean it should not be observed, since at the moment we know essentially nothing about how these processes work. It could be thought that almost any phenomenon which has been witnessed by a number of trained observers, photographed and filmed, and demonstrated in laboratory experiments under controlled conditions would be accepted by science as a reality, even if the phenomenon is elusive and occurs somewhat unpredictably, and even if it might require a reconsideration of some of the basic laws of physics. But the specter of fraud, as was unquestionably the case with some of the physical mediums, hangs over this area of research like some dark cloud. But the simple fact is that almost any psychokinetic effect a person might produce can be emulated by a sufficiently skilled illusionist, especially one who has had opportunity to set up the environment. Given that a stage magician can cause the Statue of Liberty to apparently vanish means there are few, if any, limits. In today’s technological world, no picture or film can be accepted as evidence of anything at all, virtually anything can be faked if desired. In the future, we may—we almost certainly will—see people like Nina Kulagina and Felicia Parise producing effects in the laboratory, but, since stage magicians can emulate such feats, science will not accept them as real. This problem can be expected to persist as long as macro–PK is the exclusive province of a few exceptional individuals, which makes ordinary replication experiments very difficult. Compounding this is the possibility that the experimenter, not the individual, is the actual source of the phenomena, something that, given our present state of knowledge of the subject, cannot ever be ruled out [see chapter 22, this volume]. Also, it should be understood that there probably are no demonstrations that will not be dismissed as fraudulent by skeptics and stage magicians. Stating that controls were in place to prevent illusions has never been accepted in the past and probably will not be for the foreseeable future. None of this means that such phenomena should not be reported in the literature. The building of a “natural history” of these phenomena will contribute to the future understanding of the parameters and dynamics surrounding them, and will certainly suggest future experimental approaches. References Barry, J. D. (1980). Ball lightning and bead lightning. New York: Plenum Press. Bengston, W., and Kinsley, D. (2000). The effect of the “laying on of hands” on transplanted breast cancer in mice. Journal of Scientific Exploration, 14, 353–364. Bengston, W. (2010). The energy cure. Unraveling the mystery of hands-on healing. Boulder, CO: Sounds True. Boas, F. (1974). A Franz Boas reader: The shaping of American anthropology, 1883–1911. (G. W. Stocking, Jr., Ed.). Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. Braude, Stephen E. (2007). The gold leaf lady and other parapsychological investigations. Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press. Cox, W. E. (1974). A scrutiny of Uri Geller. In J. D. Morris and W. G. Roll (Eds.), Research in parapsychology 1974 (pp. 63–66). Metuchen, NJ: Scarecrow. Crichton, M. (1988). Travels. New York: Alfred A Knopf. Crompton, S. (2005). Emanuel Swedenborg. New York: Chelsea House. Crookes, W. (1874). Researches in the phenomena of spiritualism. London. UK: J. Burns. Egely, G., and Dus, M. (1991). Apparatus and method for detecting effects indicating physical state of health and fitness. Patent application No. WO/1991/008703, 27.06.1991. Eisenbud, J. (1967). The world of Ted Serios: “Thoughtographic” studies of an extraordinary mind. New York: William Morrow. Enz, C. P. (2009). Rational and irrational features in Wolfgang Pauli’s life. Of matter and spirit: Selected essays by Charles P. Enz (pp. 149–160). London, UK: World Scientific. Green, E., and Green, A. (1977). Beyond biofeedback. New York: Knoll. Honorton, C. (1993). A moving experience. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 87, 329–340. Josephson, B. D., & Pallikari-Viras, F. (1991). Biological utilization of quantum nonlocality. Foundations in Physics, 21, 197–207. Keene, M. L. (1976). The psychic mafia. New York: St. Martin’s Press. Kokubo, H. (2013). Biophysical approach to psi phenomena. NeuroQuantology, 11(1), 8–15. Mishlove, J. (2000). The PK man: A true story of mind over matter. Charlottesville, VA: Hampton Roads. Nelms, H. (2000). Magic and showmanship: A handbook for conjurers. Mineola, NY: Dover. Norris, L. (2007). The secret behind the secret. Cohasset, MA: Dutchco Entertainment. Ostrander, S., and Schroeder, L. (1970). Psychic discoveries behind the Iron Curtain. New York: Prentice-Hall. Parodi, A. (2005). Science and spirit: What physics reveals about mystical belief. Honesdale, PA: Pleasant Mount. Radin, D. (2006). Entangled minds: Extrasensory experiences in a quantum reality. New York: Paraview Pocket Books. Randi, J., and Clarke, A. C. (1995). An encyclopedia of claims, frauds, and hoaxes of the occult and supernatural. New York: St. Martin’s Griffin. Roth, R. F. (2002) Wolfgang Pauli and parapsychology. Zurich, Switzerland: Pro Litteris. Salusbury, M. (2010, July). Meteor man: Ernst Chladni, the man who proved stones really do fall from the sky. Fortean Time, 265. http://www.forteantimes.com/features/articles/4009/meteor_man.html. Schmeidler, G., and Murphy, G. (1946). The influence of belief and disbelief in ESP upon ESP scoring level. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 36, 271–276. Shermer, M. (2007). [Video file] Retrieved from http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=h3X9h1WlQpA. Targ, R., and Puthoff, H. (1974). Information transmission under conditions of sensory shielding. Nature, 251 (5476), 602–607. Truzzi, M. (1997). Reflections on the sociology and social psychology of conjurors and their relations with psychical research. In S. Krippner (Ed.), Advances in parapsychological research 8, 221–271. Jefferson, NC: McFarland. Watkins, G. K., and Watkins, A. M. (1971). Possible PK influence on the resuscitation of anesthetized mice. Journal of Parapsychology, 35, 257– 272. Watkins, G. K., Watkins, A. M., and Wells, R. (1972). Further studies on the resuscitation of anesthetized mice. In G. W. Roll, R. L., Morris, and J. D. Morris (Eds.), Research in parapsychology 1972 (pp. 157–159). Metuchen, NJ: Scarecrow. Watkins, G. K., and Watkins, A M. (1973). Apparent psychokinesis on static objects by a gifted subject. In G. W. Roll, R. L. Morris, and J. D. Morris (Eds.), Research in parapsychology 1973 (pp. 132–134). Metuchen, NJ: Scarecrow. Wells, R., and Watkins, G. K. (1974). Linger effects in several PK experiments. In J. D. Morris, G. W. Roll, and R. L. Morris (Eds.) Research in parapsychology 1974 (pp. 143–147). Metuchen, NJ: Scarecrow. Wells, R., and Klein, J. (1972). A replication of a “psychic healing” paradigm. Journal of Parapsychology, 36, 144–149. Weltfish, G. (1965). The lost universe: Pawnee life and culture. New York: Basic Books. Wiseman, R., and Morris, R. L. (1995). Guidelines for testing psychic claimants. Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books. OceanofPDF.com CHAPTER 7 Statistical Guidelines for Empirical Studies PATRIZIO E. TRESSOLDI and JESSICA UTTS Premise Carrying out parapsychological investigations requires the same level of expertise and the same methodological and statistical tools necessary to investigate non-parapsychological phenomena. We are confident that in the near future parapsychological investigations will be one of the many lines of investigation about the human mind and its relation with the biological and physical world. Our view is that what differentiates parapsychological from non-parapsychological investigations is the content and not the procedures. In this sense, even though this chapter is part of a volume on parapsychology, its content is useful for every investigation using human participants. Aims of the Chapter The principal aim is to offer clear and practical advice on basic methodological and statistical practices used to answer the more frequent questions researchers ask when working with data. We hope to convince the reader of the importance of adopting sound methodological and statistical principles as described in this paper. Further readings are suggested that provide mathematical and statistical details, with links to reliable webpages. When available, we will suggest freeware software to be used to apply our statistical recommendations. We will provide examples for our recommendations, mostly drawn from the parapsychological literature, underlining their strengths and their limitations, and offering suggestions on how to overcome the limitations. What Researchers (Usually) Ask About Data and How to Answer Scientific research is conducted for a variety of reasons, but the underlying theme is that there is a question that cannot be answered in any other way. The answers to many of those questions can only be found by examining a sufficient amount of data, collected using unbiased and otherwise appropriate methods. Once data have been collected, the appropriate statistical analyses depend on the nature of the research question(s) and the type of data available. The two basic categories of statistical methods are descriptive and inferential statistics. Descriptive statistical methods are used to answer questions only about the data in hand. They are not meant to answer questions about the larger framework from which the measurements were collected. Inferential statistical methods are designed to answer questions about the larger framework. Traditionally, the two basic categories of inferential statistics have been null hypothesis significance testing (NHST) and confidence intervals. We will address the uses and misuses of these methods, and discuss some additional inference methods that are becoming more common. Summary of Data and Descriptive Statistics The most basic statistical analyses are simple numerical and graphical summaries. These are appropriate whether data represent measurements on an entire population, a sample from a larger population, a sample that is not representative of any larger population, or a situation that is observable and repeatable across time. Some of the reasons for performing simple descriptive analyses include: • Identifying mistakes in the data due to the recording apparatuses and/or experimenter error (such as switching the digits when a number is entered into the computer), which often are revealed using simple graphs of one or two variables. Mistakes sometimes become obvious when data points are in numerical regions where measurements are not expected to occur. • Identifying outliers, which need to be handled appropriately, as described in the next subsection. • Determining whether the conditions are met for performing the proposed statistical analyses. For example, one condition for using many statistical inference procedures is that the data set is approximately normally distributed or bell-shaped, or at least does not have any large outliers or asymmetry. • Obtaining descriptive summary information about the data, such as the average score on a test, or the proportion of successes in a guessing experiment. Handling Outliers There is no specific definition of an outlier in a data set and some judgment is needed in how to handle them. In general, an outlier is a datapoint that does not fit with the pattern of the rest of the data. For instance, in measurements of height a male who is 2 meters tall (6 feet 7 inches) would be an outlier in a college classroom, but not in a professional basketball team. Common reasons for outliers and what to do about them are: • A mistake was made in measuring or recording the data. If a mistake was clearly made, the data point should be corrected or removed. Of course if a value is removed it should be mentioned in the report of the analysis. • The data value represents natural variability. In this case, the outlier should not be removed. For most statistical methods an estimate of natural variability is part of the information used to answer questions. Removing an outlier will result in an underestimate of natural variability and thus could lead to erroneous conclusions. For example the suggestions to trim the data to estimate the central tendency of the parameters of interest (i.e., mean, correlation) is not recommended in this case. If it appears that there are outliers because the underlying population is highly skewed (rather than symmetric and/or bell-shaped), then a transformation such as the natural log can be used, and inferences can be made on the transformed data. It also makes more sense to use inferences on medians rather than on means for highly skewed data, or to make inferences on the mean of the logtransformed data instead of the original data. • The individual is from a different population than the majority of individuals measured. For instance, in a study that uses university students as participants, one of the variables measured might be age. A student returning to school after retirement might have an age of 65 or higher. That student represents a different population, and if age is a relevant variable in the study, a separate analysis might need to be performed for the population of older students. In that case, it would be acceptable to remove the individual as long as the process of doing so was reported. A different sample consisting only of students who are much older would then need to be obtained if information about that age group was desired. One situation that must be addressed in psi (and other) research is when one or a few effect sizes in a meta-analysis are outliers. Just as when dealing with outliers in a single data set, an effect size should never be removed from the analysis just because it is an outlier. Instead, possible explanations for the unusual effect size(s) should be investigated, and then these outlier effects should be handled using the above general criteria for handling outliers. A common practice in meta-analysis is to remove the top and bottom 5 percent to 10 percent of effect sizes. But this practice is too simplistic, and is not recommended. There was a strong push in statistics in the 1980s to use these “trimmed means” in all statistical inference, but as analysis methods became more sophisticated these “robust” methods were abandoned in favor of more complex analyses, such as using random effects models, transformations, and so on. Modeling Data and Processes Most statistical methods require that a model be proposed for the population or process that generated the data. For example, in a simple survey to estimate the proportion of voters who favor a particular candidate, the model is that every time a person is selected for the survey there is the same probability that the person selected will be someone who favors the candidate. The true population proportion that favors the candidate is some fixed but unknown value between 0 and 1, and the responses to the survey are used to estimate that parameter. (Parameters are fixed but with unknown population values, such as means or proportions.) A “margin of error” is given with the estimate, to indicate how accurately the estimate reflects the true population value, but the margin of error cannot be computed unless the “model” about the selection process is assumed to be true. Statistician George Box made an astute observation that was something like “No model is correct, but some are useful.” All of statistical inference relies on positing a model that is at least a good approximation of the truth. Otherwise, results of any analysis will be completely misleading. In the example of the poll of voters, if the sample was chosen using a biased method then the model will be incorrect and the results will be meaningless. For instance, if the poll is posted on an internet site and people are asked to respond if they are interested in doing so, then only those who feel strongly about the election will respond and the true proportion of the population who favors a candidate cannot be estimated. Example: Suppose we are interested in knowing if it is possible to identify an image at a distance beyond the range of our sensory organs, that is, if extrasensory perception is possible. From the literature we read that if participants are placed in a ganzfeld environment their probability of correctly identifying the targets is higher than chance, and it is also higher than it is in a nonganzfeld condition (e.g., Storm, Tressoldi, & Di Risio, 2010, 2013). In this case, an experiment would be done by conducting multiple trials in the ganzfeld environment. The simplest model is that there is a probability of correctly identifying the target on each trial in the experiment, and that the probability is the same for each trial. The parameter of interest is the probability of correct identification and the question of interest is how that probability compares with what is expected by chance. The data available after conducting an experiment would be the percentage of correct identifications in the experiment. A second goal might be to compare the probability of correct identification in the ganzfeld and nonganzfeld conditions, in which case trials would be done under both conditions and the parameter of interest would be the difference in probabilities of a correct identification under the two conditions. The null hypothesis in that case would be that the difference is 0. Most models used in parapsychological research rely on comparing observed data to a known probability distribution of values that would occur if chance alone could explain the results. Common statistical procedures that result from these simple models include exact binomial tests, one and two-sample t-tests, and chi-square tests for independence. There are many more complex models in statistics, such as structural equation models (Yuan & Bentler, 2007), multivariable regression models, logistic regression models (Harrell, 2001), and so on, but they are rarely used in parapsychology. Perhaps this is because it is important to keep the experiments relatively simple and straightforward if they are to be understood by the general scientific community. Questions of Interest After measuring the variable(s) of interest, the typical questions differ depending on the type of measurements taken. For numerical measurements, the usual questions are: What is the overall mean or median? What is the distribution of the data? What is the average dispersion of data around the mean or median? For categorical measurements, the questions of interest include: What proportion of responses fall into each category? How do the proportions in the different categories compare to each other? Do the proportions agree with what is expected by chance? In the special case of nominal variables (two categories only), the usual question is simply what proportion of responses fall into each of the two categories. Sometimes it is of interest to compare them to what is expected by chance. If two or more variables are measured, then questions may be somewhat more complicated, such as: What is the difference in means for the two variables? What is the degree of association between the two variables? If one variable is categorical and the other is numerical, a question might be whether the means for the numerical variable are the same for the categories of the other variable. An example is whether mean blood pressure is the same for people who meditate regularly (one category) and people who do not (the other category). It is important to examine the distributional characteristics of the data. Even if this practice is not customary, we emphasize its importance. Examination of the characteristics of the data is fundamental for the following reasons: a) to check if there are artifacts, wrong, or missing data; b) to observe if and how large are the differences among individual values; c) to evaluate the shape of the data distribution. The importance of point a) is obvious. The importance of point b) is relevant in order to understand if the individual differences are a consequence of cognitive or personality characteristics of participants and/or of different strategies adopted in solving the task. The importance of point c) is fundamental for testing the conditions required for inferential statistics if we want to use them to generalize the data obtained in our sample to the population from which it has been drawn. For example, if we want to use a binomial statistic for data obtained with the experiment using ganzfeld to test ESP, it is necessary to check the following requirements: • There are n “trials” where n is determined in advance. (No “optional stopping” allowed.) • There are the same two possible outcomes on each trial, called “success” and “failure” and denoted S and F. • The outcomes are independent from one trial to the next. Knowledge of one does not help predict the next one. • The probability of a “success” remains the same from one trial to the next, and this probability is denoted by p. The probability of “failure” is (1-p) for every trial. Inferential Statistics As mentioned earlier, the two traditional inferential statistical methods are null hypothesis significance testing and confidence intervals. We discuss the weaknesses of hypothesis testing, and suggest some other methods of statistical inference. The Limitations of Null Hypothesis Significance Testing (NHST) Kline (2004), Nickerson (2000), and Cumming (2012) provided detailed explanations of the problems of NHST, whose typical use was termed the “null ritual” by Gigerenzer, Krauss, and Vitouch (2004), and described as (a) set up a statistical null hypothesis of “no mean difference” or “zero correlation”; (b) do not specify the predictions of your research hypothesis or of any alternative substantive hypotheses; (c) use 5 percent as a convention for rejecting the null; (d) if significant, accept your research hypothesis; and (e) always perform this procedure. For the purposes of this chapter, we will mention six of the limitations of NHST that seriously undermine its scientific value and consequently the reliability of results reported in studies that rely on NHST. The first is that NHST centers on rejection of the null hypothesis at a stated probability level, usually .05. Consequently, researchers can at most obtain the answer “Yes, there is a difference from zero.” However very often researchers are primarily interested in a “No” answer, and are therefore tempted to commit the logical fallacy of stating: “if H0 is rejected then H0 is false, if H0 is not rejected then H0 is true” (Nickerson, 2000). A p-value > .05 does not mean that the null hypothesis is true and can be accepted. Failing to reject H0 should usually be regarded as an open verdict, no conclusion is justified. The second limitation is that the p value is very likely to be quite different if an experiment is repeated. Cumming (2008) presents the following example. If the difference between two independent samples with n = 32 and an estimated population effect size, d = 0.5, gives a two-tailed result p = .05, there is an 80 percent chance the one-tailed p value from a replication will fall in the interval (.00008, .44), a 10 percent chance that p < .00008, and a 10 percent chance that p > .44. In other words, a p value provides only extremely vague information about a result’s repeatability. Many researchers do not appreciate this weakness of relying on p-values (Lai, Fidler, & Cumming, 2012). The third limitation is that the conclusion “Yes, there is a difference from zero” is almost always true. In other words, the null hypothesis is almost never exactly correct. The probability that H0 will be rejected increases with the sample size (N), so the result of NHST says as much, or more, about N as about a hypothesis. One example is that a very low two-tailed correlation coefficient r = .10 is not sufficient to reject the H0 of a zero true correlation with p < .05, up to N = 380 participants. Above this number, H0 can be rejected. Another example is that 40 percent of correct responses obtained with 10 trials (i.e., 4 hits out of 10) with a MCE of 0.25, yields a one-tailed p-value of .224. In contrast, the same percentage obtained with 100 trials (i.e., 40 hits out of 100), yields p = .0007. This limitation is a consequence of the statistical power of the chosen statistic (for a more complete description of the statistical power see Faul, Erdfelder, Lang, & Buchner, 2007). In summary, statistical power depends on three numerical values: (1) the significance level (i.e., the Type I error probability) of the test, chosen by the experimenter and typically .05; (2) the size(s) of the sample(s) used for the test; and (3) an effect size (ES) parameter indexing the actual degree of deviation from H0 in the underlying population. Power analysis should be used prospectively to calculate the minimum sample size required so that one can reasonably detect an effect of a given size. Power analysis can also be used to calculate the minimum ES likely to be detected in a study using a given sample size. In most experimental designs, the accepted probability of making a Type I error is α = .05 and the desired power is not less than .80. However, in order to define how to obtain such a level of power, it is necessary to specify the ES of the phenomena being identified. It is intuitive that the smaller the phenomenon, the greater the sensitivity to detect it needs to be. This analogy is similar to the signal/noise relationship. The smaller the signal, the stronger must be the means to detect it in the noise. In psychology, the means of detection are the number of participants taking part in the study and the number of trials they are requested to perform. Because the true effect size cannot be known (or there would be no need to do an experiment), power analysis is usually done by specifying a minimum effect size that the researcher would like to be able to detect and then calculating how large the sample would need to be to have adequate power to detect it. There is no formula that can be used directly to calculate power, because it depends on finding probabilities of various outcomes, which usually requires finding areas under probability curves. But power is completely determined by specifying α, ES, and N, so if we know the estimated ES of a phenomenon, after the definition of the desired power and the α level, the only free parameter is N, that is, the number of participants or trials. Referring to our hypothetical binomial experiment (such as ganzfeld with 4 choices), figure 1 illustrates power as a function of the actual probability of success p for samples of size N = 20, 50, and 100. The null hypothesis value is .25 and α = .05. Notice how the power increases with the number of participants for any specific value of the true probability p. As an example, power is shown for the three samples sizes when the true hit rate is p = .33. Notice that even with a sample of 100 trials, the power, which is the probability of rejecting the null hypothesis, is only .54. In other words, the chance value of .25 would be rejected in only about 54 percent of all experiments with 100 participants, even if the truth is that the population hit rate is 33 percent instead of the chance value of 25 percent. A free applet to calculate power online is available here: www.stat.uiowa.edu/~rlenth/Power/index.htlm. The free software GPower is available here: http://www.psycho.uniduesseldorf.de/abteilungen/aap/gpower3. The fourth limitation of NHST is that it does not provide an estimate of the difference from H0, which is a measure of effect size, even when the answer is “Yes, there is a difference from zero.” A p-value < .05 does not mean the effect is large, even if the p-value is much smaller than .05. Again, this is a consequence of the fact that the p-value depends heavily on the sample size for all situations except when the null hypothesis is exactly true. (When the null hypothesis is true, the probability that it will be rejected, erroneously, is the probability of a Type 1 error, which is α, usually set at .05.) Figure 1. Power values with respect to the number of participants (trials) with a .33 hit rate. The fifth limitation is that NHST does not provide any information about precision, meaning the likely error in an estimate of a parameter, such as a mean, proportion, or correlation. Any data set measuring physical, biological, or behavioral values will contain natural variability, so the estimate of a population parameter will contain error. It is fundamental to know how large this error is likely to be. The error depends on both the sample size and the natural variability. One way to estimate the error and thus overcome this limitation is by the use of confidence intervals (CIs), see below. The sixth limitation is that researchers often test many hypotheses without correcting for the fact that they are performing multiple tests, each of which could produce a false result just by chance. If all null hypotheses are true and α = 0.05 = 1/20, then by chance alone about one in 20 independent hypothesis tests (i.e., about 5 percent) would yield a “false positive” result of rejecting the null hypothesis. In an experiment that tests many different hypotheses the test statistics used are generally not independent so the problem can be even worse. There are procedures that can be used to correct for multiple testing, but they are rarely used and they suffer from some of the same problems identified above for using a single NHST. Some Examples of Shortcomings Consequent to the Limit of NHST Here are some hypothetical examples of wording typical of what we have seen in the parapsychological literature, where the shortcomings of the NHST are not considered. (Although we have found actual quotes similar to these we have decided not to use them so as not to single out individuals who have published them.) No explanation or rationale for how the sample size was chosen. Example 1: No rationale for the choice of sample size that makes the study have very low power: “The study sample size was predefined to be 25 pairs of participants. We sought out volunteer pairs who had a positive relationship, were open to psi and were in good health both mentally and physically. ” Post-hoc instead of planned statistical power calculation. Example 2: Power analysis could and should have been done before deciding on the sample size and conducting the study. “The fact that this study failed to achieve statistical significance is probably due to low statistical power. A post-hoc analysis showed that if the hit rate observed in the study is the true population hit rate, with a sample of this size the power would only have been .15. So there would only have been a 15 percent chance of rejecting the null hypothesis.” No type I error control from multiple testing of the same hypothesis. Example 3: Testing many hypotheses in the same study and not accounting for the increased risk of making a Type 1 error. “We hypothesized that the scores on the physiology reaction measure would correlate positively with the subscales for the paranormal experiences questionnaire. Although all of the correlations were positive, they were not all statistically significant: telepathy (r = .12, p < .05), precognitive dreams (r = .18, p < .01), reading auras (r = .08, n.s.), out-of-body experiences (r = .03, n.s.), spontaneous PK (r = .09, n.s.).” Use of p < .05 as cutoff. Example 4: The temptation to use an α larger than .05 when the p-value is just slightly above .05. It would be better to simply report the p-values and let readers draw their own conclusions, instead of using terms like close to significance. “The difference in effect sizes between the two conditions was 0.10, z = 1.40, p = .081, one-tailed. The null hypothesis is not rejected, but the difference is close to significance.” Accepting a null hypothesis. Example 5: Misunderstanding of what conclusion can be made when the p-value is too large to reject the null hypothesis. It is never appropriate to accept a null hypothesis. Concluding that there is “no difference” is not the same as concluding that there is no statistically significant difference, or as epidemiologists phrase it, lack of evidence is not the same as evidence of lack. “When the four conditions were compared using analysis of variance, no differences were found between the means for the conditions (F = 1.90, df = 3, 30, p = .15). Therefore, we can conclude that the population mean scores for the four conditions are equal.” Are There Alternatives to the NHST? Statistical Recommendations from Professional Associations and Journals To reduce the impact of the limitations of NHST, psychological and medical professional associations and journals have made statistical recommendations to be adopted by all editors and reviewers. For example, for psychology, the 6th edition of the American Psychological Association Publication Manual (2010) emphasizes the prospective estimation of statistical power “…take seriously the statistical power considerations associated with the tests of hypotheses” (p. 30), the use of confidence intervals (CIs) and effect size “complete reporting of all tested hypotheses and estimates of appropriate effect sizes and confidence intervals are the minimum expectations for all APA journals” (p. 33), and, especially: “Wherever possible, base discussion and interpretation of results on point and interval estimates [i.e., confidence intervals]” (p. 34). In other words, researchers should base their conclusions on their observed effect sizes (point estimates), and the CIs (interval estimates) of those effect sizes. For medicine, the International Committee of Medical Journal Editors (ICMJE) released the Uniform Requirements for Manuscripts (URM). In the statistics paragraph of the updated April 2010 version, it is recommended “When possible, quantify findings and present them with appropriate indicators of measurement error or uncertainty (such as confidence intervals). Avoid relying solely on statistical hypothesis testing, such as pvalues, which fail to convey important information about effect size” (p. 13). Similar recommendations are emphasized in the CONSORT Statement (Schulz, Altman, & Moher, 2010): “For all outcomes, authors should provide a confidence interval to indicate the precision (uncertainty) of the estimate. A 95 percent confidence interval is conventional, but occasionally other levels are used” and “Although p-values may be provided in addition to confidence intervals, results should not be reported solely as p-values. Results should be reported for all planned primary and secondary end points, not just for analyses that were statistically significant or ‘interesting’” (item 17a). Confidence Intervals (CI) A confidence interval is an interval of values computed from sample data that is likely to include the true population value. The confidence level (often 95 percent) for an interval describes our confidence in the procedure we used. We are confident that most of the confidence intervals we compute using appropriate procedures will contain the true population value, where “most” is defined by the confidence level (for a more complete description, see Cumming, 2012). The width of a confidence interval is determined by (a) sample size (N = number of trials), a larger N provides greater accuracy and a narrower interval, and (b) confidence level, higher confidence, for example 99 percent instead of 95 percent, requires a wider interval. Useful demonstrations of the confidence interval concept are available here: http://www.rossmanchance.com/applets/NewConfsim/Confsim.html and here: https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=ez4DgdurRPg. There is a direct correspondence between a confidence interval and the rejection of the null value for a two-sided alternative hypothesis of the form “Population value ≠ null value.” • If the null value is covered by a 95 percent CI you cannot reject the null hypothesis at .05. The null value is a plausible value. • If the null value is not covered by a 95 percent CI you can reject the null hypothesis (and accept the alternative) at .05. For a one-sided alternative hypothesis, the correspondence is similar but requires care to make sure the interval is in the same direction as the alternative hypothesis. For instance, for the alternative hypothesis of the form “population value > null value” use a 90 percent CI and reject the null hypothesis at .05 if the entire interval is above the null value. You could also compute a one-sided confidence interval, but that is not standard. Confidence intervals give the magnitude of the effect and are easier to interpret than the results of hypothesis tests. The width of a confidence interval illustrates how much uncertainty there is; the wider the interval, the less accurately the parameter is estimated. Effect Size An effect size measures how far the true parameter value is from the null value, usually in terms of standard deviations or amount of variance explained. Just as with the population parameter, the population effect size cannot be known exactly but can be estimated. Effect sizes are easier to interpret than p-values, they give more information because they reveal how far the null value is from the true parameter value, and they are not as heavily influenced by the size of the sample. There is a direct relationship between the z and t test statistics and common effect size measures. For instance, for a t-test of a single mean, the test statistic is and the effect size is Notice that the effect size measures how many standard deviations apart the sample mean and null value are from each other. The “hypothesis testing paradox” illustrates why effect sizes are more useful than p-values. Suppose a researcher conducts a t-test for one mean with n = 100 and finds t = 2.50, p = .014, so the null hypothesis is rejected. Just to be sure, the experimenter repeats the experiment with n = 25, but to her dismay, she finds t = 1.25, p =.22, and she cannot reject the null. The effect has disappeared! To salvage the situation, she decides to combine the data, so now n = 125. Now she finds t = 2.80, p = .006! How could a second study that did not support the statistically significant result of the first study somehow make the result stronger when combined with the first study? Here is the paradox: The 2nd study alone did not replicate the finding of statistical significance, but when combined with the 1st study, the effect seems even stronger than the 1st study alone (p goes from .014 to .006)! What is going on? The problem is that the test statistic and p-value depend on the sample size. In fact in this example, both studies have the same effect size. See Table 1 for a numerical explanation. Note that the effect size is the test statistic/√n. Table 1. Hypothetical Example of the Relations among Statistic, p, and Effect Size Unlike p-values, effect sizes do not depend on sample size (but accuracy of estimating them does). They are a measure of the true effect or difference in the population. They can be compared even when different units or different tests are used. Easy and free ways to calculate effect sizes and their confidence intervals are indicated in the web resources. Think and Act Meta-analytically Evidence is supported only by cumulative and independent replications and not by a single even if seemingly perfect study. It follows that it is necessary to think about how to cumulate results both if obtained by a single study or by different ones. Figure 2 (drawn from Cumming, 2012) shows an example of reporting results from multiple studies in the form of a forest plot, and adding the results of a new study, “Mine, 2011” in the figure, to the results that had been accumulated to date. Each horizontal line represents one study and the diamonds represent accumulated results over multiple studies. Each line shows the range of a 95 percent confidence interval for the parameter of interest, based on a single study (lines with squares) or multiple studies (diamonds). The size of the square is proportional to the sample size used for that study, with a larger square indicating a larger sample size. The diamond shown just below the middle of the figure is the confidence interval for the combined results of the six studies above it, labeled as “Past research, metaanalyzed.” The next line with the square shows the confidence interval for the new study by Mine and the diamond at the bottom represents a confidence interval for the parameter after adding the new study. It is not obvious from this figure because of the relatively small study being added, but in general each new study added will reduce the width of the confidence interval represented by the diamond because the accumulated sample size keeps growing. Figure 2. Example of a meta-analysis forest plot. Squares represents the means of single studies with their corresponding CIs, whereas diamonds correspond to meta-analytic mean estimates. Thinking and acting meta-analytically can include calculating an effect size measure with the corresponding confidence intervals for each study and using a model to summarize all available evidence. Guidelines on how to carry out a meta-analysis of psychological studies are presented in the MetaAnalysis Reporting Standards (MARS) specified in the APA Manual (APA, 2008, pp. 251–252). Further sources are Borenstein, Hedges, Higgins, and Rothstein (2009) and Cooper, Hedges, and Valentine (2009). The Bayesian Approach Here we will give only a brief introduction to the logic of the Bayesian approach offering some further readings to expand the knowledge of this statistical approach. A good reference for nonstatisticians is the book Bayesian Ideas and Data Analysis: An Introduction for Scientists and Statisticians by Christensen. Johnson, Branscum, and Hanson (2011). Similar to NHST and confidence intervals, Bayesian analysis often focuses on estimating a parameter of interest. But unlike those methods, the Bayesian approach results in a distribution of possible values for the parameter, along with associated probabilities. To find this “posterior” distribution, the Bayesian approach uses a combination of the data and prior information or beliefs about the possible values for the parameter. This is a radical difference from the NHST approach, which only allows us to find the probability of observed data (or data more extreme) under the assumption that the null hypothesis is true (i.e., the p-value). To test hypotheses using the Bayesian approach there are two types of prior information or belief that must be specified. Each individual can specify his or her own beliefs, but ultimately, with enough data, the conclusions reached will be the same. The first specification is to assign prior probabilities to the null and alternative hypotheses. For instance, in the ganzfeld example a disbeliever might assign a probability of 1 in a million to the alternative hypothesis (that psi exists) where as a true skeptic might assign a probability of 1 in 1000, and a believer might assign a probability of ?. The second assignment of probabilities that must be made a priori is trickier and often hidden in the analysis. In this step, the analysts must enter a distribution of possible effect sizes that corresponds to what they think the effect size is if in fact the alternative hypothesis is true. (Specifying a single value is not good enough—a distribution of possibilities must be specified.) In our example, the analyst must answer the question “If the psi hypothesis is true, how large do you think the hit rate is? (Or, what do you think is the probability of a hit?)” The technical details are cumbersome, but the specification of these probabilities can be elicited by answering a few simple questions, such as “What is your best guess at the true value of the hit rate?” and “What is the value that you are 95 percent sure the hit rate will exceed, and at the other end, 95 percent sure it will not exceed?” For the binomial situation represented in the ganzfeld example, the website http://www.epi.ucdavis.edu/diagnostictests/betabuster.html provides software for this purpose. It is important that a reasonable distribution of possibilities be used for this prior distribution. In the ganzfeld example, if the distribution under the alternative hypothesis has most of the weight given to very high hit rate values, then almost no one would believe the alternative hypothesis to be more likely than the null hypothesis. In other words, if the choice is between a chance hit rate or a hit rate on the order of 70 percent to 100 percent, then most people would place their bets on the chance hit rate. And if the data were used to choose between those two possibilities, it would also favor the chance (null) hypothesis. This kind of misleading Bayesian analysis was used by Wagenmakers, Wetzels, Borsboom, and Van der Maas (2011). Two examples of appropriate Bayesian analysis in parapsychological investigations are reported in Utts, Norris, Suess, and Johnson (2010) and in Bem, Utts, and Johnson (2011). Bayesian models comparison. In one Bayesian approach to assessing null values, the analyst sets up two competing models of what values are possible. One model (the null model) posits that only the null value or a range of values is possible. The alternative model posits that a broad range of other values is possible. Bayesian inference is used to compute which model is more credible given the data. This method is called Bayesian model comparison. The result of this comparison is a value called the Bayes factor. The Bayes factor is heavily dependent on the a priori distribution specified for the alternative hypothesis, as just discussed, but does not depend on the prior odds placed on the two hypotheses. That part of the analysis comes after the Bayes factor has been found. Once the Bayes factor is found it can be used by each individual to find the “posterior odds” of the null versus the alternative hypothesis being true. The Bayes factor represents the odds of one hypothesis to the other for someone who had placed equal prior probabilities on the two hypotheses. For everyone else, the prior odds held by the individual are multiplied by the Bayes factor to find the posterior odds for that individual. For instance, if the Bayes factor for the alternative compared to the null is 5, it means that someone for whom the prior probabilities were equal would now conclude that the alternative hypothesis is 5 times as likely to be true as the null hypothesis. But for someone for whom the prior odds were 1 (for the alternative) to 100 (for the null), the posterior odds would only be Bayes factor × prior odds = 5(1/100) = 1/20. So for this person the null hypothesis would now seem to be 20 times as likely to be true as the alternative hypothesis. This person has had their odds shifted from 1 in 100 to 1 in 20, but would still not be convinced that the alternative hypothesis is likely to be true. Notice that if someone starts with prior odds of millions (for the null) to 1 (for the alternative) then it would take a very, very large Bayes factor (and thus a very, very large amount of data) to convince them that the alternative is more likely to be true than the null. One of the nice features of the Bayesian approach is that it requires people to be up front about their prior beliefs. Example: “The results showed approximately 20 percent of correct hits above the chance level of 50 percent for the threatening stimulus, and approximately 17 percent of correct hits below the chance level for the neutral stimulus. The Bayesian parameters estimation of these results (BFH1/H0 = 200 and 50 respectively) give strong support to the alternative (hits above chance level) hypothesis.” Notice that in this example the Bayes factor is 200 for the threatening stimulus, and 50 for the neutral stimulus. Bayesian parameter estimates. In a second Bayesian approach to assessing null values, the analyst simply sets up a range of candidate values, including the null value, and uses Bayesian inference to compute the relative credibility of each of the candidate values. This method is called Bayesian parameter estimation. A posterior distribution is found for the parameter of interest by combining the prior distribution placed on the parameter with the data observed in the experiment. This distribution contains 100 percent of the possible values for the parameter and shows how the possibilities are distributed over the number range. This distribution generally includes the entire possible number line, i.e., 0 to 1, or 0 to infinity, depending on the situation. Of course it does not help much to say that we are 100 percent sure that the true value (for instance, for a hit rate) is between 0 and 1—we don’t need data to tell us that! So what is used instead is an interval that contains a specified proportion of the possible distribution, usually 95 percent. This interval of possible values is called a “highest posterior density interval.” This is similar to a confidence interval in frequentist analysis. Example: ”Bayesian estimation provides information about the possible true effect sizes that is not available from examining Bayes factors, much like frequentist confidence intervals provide information that is not available from hypothesis testing. In this analysis the parameter of interest is the true probability of success. Following Kruschke (2011), we use a Bayesian hierarchical model in which the number of hits in study j is a binomial random variable with success probability θj, possibly different for each study. The values of θj are sampled from a beta distribution with mean μ, and we want to estimate μ. It represents the average of all the possible success probabilities. To be conservative, we used a noninformative beta distribution on μ, with a = 1 and b = 1 (i.e., a uniform distribution), and a gamma distribution on the dispersion” (from Storm, Tressoldi & Utts, 2013). Figure 3 shows the results of the Bayesian parameter estimation of μ (where chance = 25 percent, or 0.25). The entire range of possibilities actually goes from 0 to 1, but anything outside of the interval from about 0.24 to 0.36 has such low probability that it is not shown. The distribution of possibilities has a mean of 0.297, and the middle 95 percent of possibilities range from 0.2654 to 0.329. This is the 95 percent highest posterior density interval (labeled HDI for high density interval) for μ. The interval excludes the chance value of 0.25 and hence supports the hypothesis that ESP may be real. Figure 3. Bayesian Estimation of the Hit Probabilities with Corresponding High Density Interval (HDI). The Problem of Replication The gold standard to define the reliability of any finding in science is its replicability. No phenomenon can be considered real if it cannot be observed repeatedly. The lack of consistent replication undermines the foundations of any discipline, from psychology to medicine to physics. However, the definition of replicability must be made in the context of statistical variability. The hypothesis testing paradox discussed earlier reveals the dangers of defining replication based on p-values. A better approach is to look for similar effect sizes across studies, but even that approach has problems. First, effect size estimates are exactly that— estimates of a population effect and therefore not precise. Also, when a study has a large enough effect size to be considered interesting, it may be that chance variability produced an effect size in the “tail” of the possible effect size estimates for that situation. Therefore, further studies would be expected to produce smaller effect sizes, even if they are generated from the same population. This idea is similar to the well-known idea of “regression to the mean.” If a new study finds a smaller effect size than the original study it does not necessarily mean the new study is a failure to replicate the original finding. It could be because there is statistical variability and the initial study was at one end of the range of that variability. The problem of replication has received considerable attention in psychology recently, as witnessed by a recent special section of the journal Perspectives on Psychological Science titled “Replicability in Psychological Science: A Crisis of Confidence?” edited by Pashler and Wagenmakers (2012). Apart from calling for the importance of exact and conceptual replications and inviting all researchers and journal editors to invest more on this kind of research activity, the crucial question is how to define whether the results of an experiment can be considered a replication or a failure to replicate previous findings. When the evidence of a phenomenon is supported by quantitative statistical analyses, the criteria to define whether a new experiment replicates the evidence observed in previous studies are only statistical. Given all the limitations of the NHST described in the previous pages, at least one thing is clear, the conclusion about whether a successful replication has occurred cannot be established by referring to the p-values! If p-values cannot be used to define the validity of a replication, the solution must be found in the NHST alternative options. For example, replication could be defined as getting approximately the same effect size, taking into account its precision defined by its confidence intervals but subject to the idea that an initial attention-grabbing study may reflect the tail of a distribution. As is hopefully clear by now, the answer to the question of whether a follow-up study “replicates” an original study should not be answered with a “yes or no.” It is more complicated than that, and science progresses by noticing and explaining both similarities and differences across studies. For an extended discussion on how to carry-out and compare the results of replications, see Brandt et al. (2014). In the case of a Bayesian approach we can define a replication success or failure by referring to Bayes factor values, again taking into account the natural statistical variability in any data-calculated value. For instance, if in the original experiment BF(H1/H0) was 20 and in the replication it was 3, it seems clear that they are different. A more refined method is presented by Verhagen and Wagenmakers (2014). Another option is to see if the HDIs overlap with the original ones. Yet another option is to use the new study or studies to update the Bayesian results. Similar to the meta-analytic updating method shown above, with Bayesian analyses it is straightforward to simply keep accumulating evidence and updating the results. To conclude this chapter, we suggest some simple recommendations that could become requirements for each proposal of publication in a journal. We are sure that if applied most of the NHST limitations and negative consequences will be solved. Methodological and Statistical Recommendations We make the following recommendations for all studies. These include recommendations for issues that must be considered before the study, during the analysis phase, and in the reporting of the results. • Make explicit the difference between exploratory or pilot experiments and formal ones; • Make explicit the primary and the secondary hypotheses to be tested before collecting any data; • Report all experimental conditions, including failed manipulations; • Make explicit the initial choice of the sample size(s), and provide an explanation if it was not met; • If possible, explain the rationale for the sample size(s), including a power analysis; • Whenever possible, report confidence intervals and effect sizes along with or instead of p-values; • If Bayesian methods are used, be explicit about all priors, including the prior distribution represented in the alternative hypothesis; • Exact and conceptual replications are welcomed, but explain which one is being attempted; • Pre-registration of confirmatory hypotheses is recommended, for example posting them on http://www.openscienceframework.org • and/or http://koestlerunit.wordpress.com Statistical analyses reporting. When using the frequentist Null Hypothesis Significant Testing approach, adopt the APA 2010 and APS statistical guidelines (Cumming, 2014): Consideration of whether or not to reject the null hypothesis should be carried out using parameters’ confidence intervals, equivalence testing or model comparison procedures (see suggested readings and resources), except for hypotheses that are not about a single parameter, such as chi-square goodness-of-fit tests or tests based on the sum of ranks. References APA (2010). Publication manual (6th ed.). Washington, D.C.: American Psychological Association. APA Publications and Communications Board Working Group (2008). Reporting standards for research in psychology. Why do we need them? What might they be? American Psychologist, 63, 839–851. Bem, D. J., Utts, J., and Johnson, W. O. (2011). Must psychologists change the way they analyze their data? A response to Wagenmakers, Wetzels, Borsboom, and Van der Maas (2011). Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 101, 716–719. doi: 10.1037/a0024777 Borenstein, M., Hedges, L. V., Higgins, J. P. T., and Rothstein, H. R. (2009). Introduction to meta-analysis. Chichester, UK: Wiley. Brandt, M. J., IJzerman, H., Dijksterhuis, A., Farach, F. J., Geller, J., GinerSorolla, R., … and Van’t Veer, A. (2014). The replication recipe: What makes for a convincing replication? Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 50, 217–224. Christensen, R., Johnson, W., Branscum, A., and Hanson, T. E. (2011). Bayesian ideas and data analysis: An introduction for scientists and statisticians. Boca Raton, FL: Chapman & Hall. Cooper, H., Hedges, L. V., and Valentine, J. C. (Eds.). (2009). The handbook of research synthesis and meta-analysis (2nd ed.). New York: Russell Sage Foundation. Cumming G. (2012). Understanding the new statistics: Effect sizes, confidence intervals, and meta–analysis: www.thenewstatistics.com Cumming, G. (2014). The new statistics. Why and how. Psychological Science, 25, 7–29. Cumming, G. (2008). Replication and p intervals: p values predict the future only vaguely, but confidence intervals do much better. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 3, 286–300. doi: 10.1111/j.1745–6924.2008.00079.x Faul, F., Erdfelder, E., Lang, A.-G., and Buchner, A. (2007). G*Power 3: A flexible statistical power analysis program for the social, behavioral, and biomedical sciences. Behavior Research Methods, 39, 175–191. Gigerenzer, G., Krauss, S., and Vitouch, O. (2004). The null ritual what you always wanted to know about significance testing but were afraid to ask. In D. Kaplan (Ed.). The Sage handbook of quantitative methodology for the social sciences (pp. 391–408). Thousand Oaks CA: Sage. Harrell, F. E. (2001). Regression modeling strategies: with applications to linear models, logistic regression, and survival analysis. Berlin, Germany; Springer-Verlag. Kline, R. B. (2004). Beyond significance testing. Washington, D.C.: American Psychological Association. doi: 10.1177/1094428107307913. Kruschke, J. (2011). Bayesian assessment of null values via parameter estimation and model comparison. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 6, 299–312. doi: 10.1177/1745691611406925 Lai, J., Fidler, F., and Cumming, G. (2012). Subjective p Intervals. Methodology: European Journal of Research Methods for the Behavioral and Social Sciences, 8(2), 51–62. Nickerson, R.S. (2000). Null hypothesis significance testing: A review of an old and continuing controversy. Psychological Methods, 5, 241–301. doi: 10.1037//1082–989X.5.2.241. Pashler, H., and Wagenmakers, E. J. (2012). Editors’ introduction to the special section on replicability in psychological science. A crisis of confidence? Perspectives on Psychological Science, 7, 528–530. Schulz, K. F., Altman, D. G., Moher, D., and CONSORT Group (2010) CONSORT 2010 Statement: Updated guidelines for reporting parallel group randomised trials. PLoS Med, 7(3): e1000251 doi:101371/journalpmed1000251 Storm, L., Tressoldi, P. E., and Di Risio, L. (2010). Meta-analysis of freeresponse studies, 1992–2008: Assessing the noise reduction model in parapsychology. Psychological Bulletin, 136, 471. Storm, L., Tressoldi, P. E., and Utts, J. (2013). Testing the Storm et al. (2010) meta-analysis using Bayesian and frequentist approaches: Reply to Rouder et al.(2013). Psychological Bulletin, 139, 248–254. Utts, J., Norris, M., Suess, E., and Johnson, W. (2010). The strength of evidence versus the power of belief: Are we all Bayesians? Proceedings of the Eighth International Conference on Teaching Statistics (ICOTS8, July, 2010). Voorburg, The Netherlands: International Statistical Institute. Verhagen, A. J., and Wagenmakers, E.-J. (2014). Bayesian tests to quantify the result of a replication attempt. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 143, 1457–1475. Wagenmakers, E J., Wetzels, R., Borsboom, D., and Van der Maas, H. (2011). Why psychologists must change the way they analyze their data: The case of psi. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 100, 426–432. Yuan, K.-H., and Bentler, P. M. (2007). Structural equation modeling. In C. R. Rao & S. Sinharay (Eds.), Handbook of statistics. Vol. 26. Psychometrics (pp. 297–358). Amsterdam, Netherlands: North-Holland. Some Web Resources Frequentist statistics handbok.docxhttp://statpages.org (provides links to hundreds of free online resources for statistics) http://vassarstats.net http://www.danielsoper.com/statcalc3/default.aspx Estimation of frequentist parameters Effect size calculator: http://www.campbellcollaboration.org/resources/effect_size_input.php Confidence intervals calculator: http://www.latrobe.edu.au/psy/research/projects/esci Bayesian resources http://bayesfactorpcl.r-forge.r-project.org http://doingbayesiandataanalysis.blogspot.it OceanofPDF.com Part Three: Psychology and Psi OceanofPDF.com CHAPTER 8 Psychological Concepts of Psi Function A Review and Constructive Critique REX G. STANFORD This chapter will focus on two broad conceptual frameworks: The psimediated instrumental response model (PMIR; Stanford, 1974a, 1990, 2006, and a revised version in this chapter) and the first-sight model and theory (FSMT; Carpenter, 2004, 2005, 2008, 2012). Both PMIR and FSMT integrate ideas and findings from psychology and psi-research into a broad framework for understanding psi in a wide range of life situations, where it is presumed to subserve, usually unconsciously, the adaptational and/or personal inclinations of the organism. Both PMIR and FSMT are built on the conviction that developing a workable scientific understanding of psi events (both receptive and active psi, ESP and PK) requires examining them in a far broader context than in the past, when experimenters tried to force psi to manifest itself in the laboratory through tasks that required subjects to use psi in a very deliberate fashion. Looking Back at the 1977 Handbook of Parapsychology The 1977 Handbook of Parapsychology had a chapter (Stanford, 1977) entitled “Conceptual Frameworks of Contemporary Psi Research.” Like the present chapter, it focused on studies based on psychological concepts. One focus of that chapter was the concept of internal attention states, which was developed by Charles Honorton and guided most of the research intended to enhance performance on cognitive-perceptual, fully intentional, ESP tasks. The other focus was my model of psi-mediated instrumental response (PMIR). It represented a very fundamental conceptual shift relative to both traditional psi theorization and conventional psi-research methodology, because its primary focus was on understanding the potentially adaptive role of psi in life situations in which most of us certainly are not striving to make conscious use of psi. It proposed psychological mechanisms through which psi might function in the service of personal dispositions and needs and delineated how PMIR might efficiently serve those functions without any conscious effort to activate psi function or awareness of its occurrence. The Receptive-Psi (Extrasensory) PMIR Model: Some Reflections and Updating The first PMIR model was published 40 years ago (Stanford, 1974a, 1974b; the former concerned receptive psi, ESP, and the latter, active psi, PK). Elaborated and/or revised versions of the receptive-psi model were published (Stanford, 1977, 1982, 1990) that incorporated not only the organism’s needs as subserved by PMIR, but, more broadly, its dispositions. A more recent paper (Stanford, 2006) detailed PMIR’s ramifications for modeling receptive psi using memory-related concepts. Arguably my most complete, detailed, and deeply reflective presentation and review of the PMIR model (Stanford, 1990) was an examination of evidence, both from psi studies and psychology, bearing on the credibility of the assumptions of the model and on the methods used to investigate it. The model’s innovative, experimentally testable proposals strongly encouraged research on unconscious, adaptation-relevant receptive psi. Within the last 15 years or so there has been an upsurge in experimental study of hypotheses directly based on the PMIR model and on ideas, though possibly not derived from it, that nonetheless seem fully consonant with its proposals. There will be no attempt to review or even to list and cite all of that work here, but PMIR-inspired research has been done in several university settings. What follows are the assumptions of the latest PMIR model, which has been revised, usually in the interest of further delineating the implications of the model. ASSUMPTION 1: Fundaments Through psi the organism is able to respond to circumstances with which it lacks sensory contact if those circumstances are of a kind to which it would respond if it had sensory knowledge of them. Further, the approach/avoidance character of the organism’s psi-mediated response or response disposition to such a circumstance will tend to parallel those it would have if it had sensory contact with that circumstance, but that response of course will be shaped in consideration of its concerns relative to the current sensory environment. Considering the above, there is no implication here that PMIR invariably subserves what many people, including biologists, tend to think of as adaptation, for an individual’s psimediated response may at times work contrary to such interests on account of its existing dispositions and cognitive schemata relative to such situations (see ASSUMPTION (7). The term “adaptational,” as used in discussion of the PMIR model, refers to psi-mediated facilitation of the individual’s typical or preferred outcome relative to the situation apprehended unconsciously through psi. This is because each individual has characteristic ways of adapting to particular circumstances. It is supposed, though, that adaptation in the conventional, normative sense is the usual function of PMIR for most individuals. The term “circumstances” in this assumption refers not only to physical situations, but also to the thoughts and/or intentions, conscious or unconscious, of other individuals that have importance to the one who potentially could respond to them via PMIR. ASSUMPTION 2: Psi-Mediated State-Related Shifts as Preparation for or as the Actual Adaptational Response Preparation for PMIR involves psi-mediated state-related changes such as motivational or emotional arousal and orienting responses related to directing and focusing attention, as well as any other prerequisites for executing an overtly behavioral instrumental response (i.e., one that directly produces a personally desirable outcome relative to the psiaccessed material). In some instances such a preparatory-type affective/emotional response may constitute the instrumental response itself, specifically when the very nature of the psi-apprehended circumstance makes behavioral intervention impossible, but affective adaptation to that circumstance is possible. The final sentence of this assumption needs some explanation. Occasionally situations may exist to which a psi-mediated response might be helpful, but obviating an unfortunate situation (e.g., unexpected death of a love one) may be impossible under the circumstances. In such a case, advance emotional or even cognitive (e.g., dream) psi-mediated apprehension of the event may be adaptive if it subsequently helps the respondent to be able, upon sensory confirmation of a disastrous event, to cope with it psychologically and even behaviorally. Emotional/affective preparation as PMIR is not new to the PMIR model (Stanford, 1990). ASSUMPTION 3: Strength of the Tendency to Produce PMIR The strength of the tendency to produce PMIR is positively related to (a) the centrality and strength of the need(s) and/or dispositions that have relevance to the circumstance(s) to which psi is responding; (b) the degree of need-relevance or incentive value of that circumstance itself upon its being encountered; and (c) the closeness in time to the potential encounter with that circumstance, to the degree that earlier response to the circumstance would have greater adaptive benefit. This particular set of assumptions has been modified since its last publication (Stanford, 1990). Originally, the first part of this assumption indicated that the strength of the tendency toward PMIR is related “directly and positively” to the situations indicated thereafter by items (a), (b), and (c). The “directly” has been deleted from the current version because such an expression often is used to mean “linearly,” but that is an assumption that seems unjustifiable in the absence of relevant research or a cogent a priori argument favoring linearity in this regard. Sub-assumption (c) has been modified. Originally, it referred only to the closeness in time per se to the potential encounter with the circumstance motivating the PMIR, but it seems reasonable to assume that temporal closeness should be most important when an earlier response would allow a greater possibility of successful PMIR or would allow more efficacious PMIR. ASSUMPTION 4: The Role of Automatic Activation in PMIR Acting in interaction with the organism’s current action plans and circumstances, PMIR is accomplished through the psi-initiated automatic activation (or priming) of thoughts, feelings, desires, goals, situationally linked behavioral patterns (i.e., scripts), associative networks, imagery, and/or memories that may aid in the production of an instrumental behavioral response or that may per se constitute such a response, given those current action plans and situations. (See ASSUMPTION 2.) The activation of such pre-existing mental features is presumed to be easier if the structures or systems thus to be primed often have been utilized in support of past activities and experiences and thus are composed of associative linkages that relatively easily may be accessed and activated by unconscious primes, including psi-related ones. Through such means psi can directly facilitate or inhibit ideas or response tendencies if doing so is important to realizing adaptational goals or protecting against harm to the organism. PMIR also may facilitate response tendencies specifically to counter ongoing responses that would work against the organism’s adaptational interests relative to implicit, psi-derived knowledge. In line with this assumption, sometimes PMIR will activate a well-learned response tendency that will block, delay, or even supplant current action plans if consequences of the original plans would, unaltered, work counter to the organism’s adaptational interests in regard to the psi-accessed information driving the tendency toward PMIR. Some such events may manifest as serendipitous forgetting. In my first PMIR model paper (1974) I related how a retired attorney from New York City had one day boarded a subway train with the intention of changing trains, in course, to get him to easy walking distance of the home of friends whom he hoped to visit. When he got to the station where he had planned to transfer to another train, he instead “absentmindedly” walked through the exit gate and halfway up the stairs before realizing his mistake. Instead of going back in and paying another fare for the originally planned train, he decided to walk the six blocks to their place. As he walked up the street he fortuitously encountered them heading for an appointment of which he had been unaware. His mistake and the related change of plans thus had enabled at least a short visit while walking with them that he would have missed had he not forgetfully diverted from his original travel plan. Serendipitous forgetting is just one of many forms that wholly unconscious PMIR might take (see ASSUMPTION (5), but it may be fairly common [see chapter 2 and 5, this volume]. Unconscious activation of routines in pursuit of goals appears not only to be used in the pursuit of consciously activated goals but, also, in the pursuit of at least some goals that have been unconsciously activated, such as by subliminal stimuli or by unattended suprathreshold stimuli (discussion and related research citations in Bargh, 1997; and in Hassin, 2013). The same may be expected to happen via unconscious activation of a goal through psi. The earlier, but now discredited, assumption of exclusively conscious mediation of higher-level processing was largely a consequence of modeling mental activity via computer processing which, at that time (roughly mid–60s to mid–80s), was still serial in character, one process at a time (Bargh, 1997; Kihlstrom, 1987). Serial modeling has the character of conscious processing, namely, one thing at a time. Rescue from the conceptual roadblock posed by exclusively serial processing came with the idea of parallel processing and the development of computer-based models of parallel distributed processing (PDP; Rumelhart, McClelland, & the PDP Research Group, 1986). The term distributed derives from the fact that in such models the representation of something—whatever that might be—is spread across many units of the network, not housed in just one locus (unlike in earlier models), and is represented, specifically, by the pattern of activation/inhibition across many units of the network. Simultaneous activity (i.e., parallel activity) is widespread throughout the network. Models involving PDP are termed connectionist models. They have numerous important advantages, but our present focus is on the feature of allowing multiple processes, even potentially complexly interrelated ones, to run at the same time, a feature helpful in modeling unconscious processing. Such models have some unique and notable advantages in successfully modeling how the brain’s neural networks might handle problem solving of various kinds, including learning and generalization of constructs. Goldstein (2008) has provided a useful short description of PDP. Of course, models involving both serial and parallel processing are feasible and for some purposes may be particularly useful. ASSUMPTION 5: PMIR as Flexibly Adaptive Response to Psi-Mediated Implicit Knowledge PMIR often does, but need not always, occur (a) without any effort to use psi; (b) without a conscious effort to fulfill the need being addressed through PMIR; (c) without prior sensory knowledge of the existence of that need-relevant circumstance; (d) without the development of any type of conscious representation (e.g., image or thought) of the need-relevant circumstance; and (e) without awareness that anything psi-related is happening and often without even any sense of something unusual transpiring. If adaptational response is possible via these subtle, unconscious, and processing-efficient means, there ordinarily is no reason and no inclination for receptive psi to take on a more cognitive-perceptual manifestation. On the other hand, if unconsciously mediated adaptation is in principle not possible or proves impossible, perceptual-cognitive information may appear in consciousness. In that event, if the psi process has elicited unusual, very unexpected, out-of-context thoughts, waking imagery, or dream content related to someone or something of personal concern, the experiencing individual may, prior to any contact with confirming information, come to feel that some mysterious process of knowing must have or might have occurred. This is because he or she cannot otherwise account for the highly unexpected, unaccustomed experience, let alone any such experience arising in this situational context (see Stanford, 2006, pp. 137–139, for further discussion on the genesis of conviction and of a sense of certainty in life and laboratory instances of psi). PMIR tends to operate as efficiently as possible to achieve the organism’s adaptational goals relative to the information accessed via psi. One of the most subtle, but conceptually powerful consequences of the assumptions of this model is that the whole process of PMIR can, as stated in ASSUMPTION 5, run off entirely unconsciously. One very fundamental and important ramification of the model is that PMIR often can occur, simply and efficiently, by altering the timing of what the organism is engaged in doing. Depending on situational exigencies, PMIR can be accomplished either by speeding up or slowing down one’s travel (e.g., while walking or driving). This unconscious adaptive-timing implication of the PMIR model is extremely important to the model’s conceptual power because timing often conveniently can be adjusted via a variety of different tactics, on many different accounts, thus offering a large number of potential options for psimediated adaptational influence via timing-relevant behaviors. Thus, if one potential tactic is blocked, another might be possible. On the other hand, conscious apprehension of the need-relevant event actually might disrupt the occurrence of PMIR because of rumination, fear, or rationalization that “It cannot be so!” It therefore is fortunate that PMIR often can occur without the individual involved developing any idea at all of what has been transpiring. For such reasons, some of my earliest PMIR studies included timing as the potential mechanism for PMIR (Stanford & Associates, 1976; Stanford & Rust, 1977; Stanford & Thompson, 1974), and the mechanism proved its utility in those studies. Subsequently, several laboratory studies addressed the model’s assumption related to advantageous timing of response and generally found support (Stanford, 1990). I have not subsequently attempted a systematic review of such studies, but my impression is that most subsequent PMIR studies have involved other approaches to PMIR than the study of timing. Of special interest may be a group of studies devoted to addressing a particular proposed function of timing in psi research intended originally to provide evidence of psychokinesis. This was work based on Decision Augmentation Theory (DAT), that May, Utts, and Spottiswoode (1995) termed “a logical and formal extension of Stanford’s … PMIR model” (p. 198). DAT, like the PMIR model, assumes that the timing of decisions may unconsciously be guided toward favored outcomes through anomalous cognition (AC, May’s term for receptive psi) [see chapter 13, this volume]. Research on this proposed adaptive timing mechanism has provided multistudy evidence (May, Spottiswoode, Utts, & James, 1995) indicating that results of earlier work construed by investigators as exhibiting PK (in May’s term, anomalous perturbation, AP) on random number generators (RNGs) much more closely fit a model of psi-mediated advantageous unconscious timing in the triggering of RNG trials than they do a model of active psi-mediated physical influence on the RNG. The results, in short, were compatible with the proposal of DAT that the times of initiating RNG trials may be managed fortuitously (and unconsciously) by AC such that those trials tend to sample chance-produced, but relatively target-matching, sequences of RNG outputs, thereby simulating AP. Here we have an instance of work that helps to decide between competing models or theories. Palmer (2009) extended the application of DAT (and, thereby, also, the PMIR adaptive-timing implication) by finding evidence supportive of adaptive timing. In Palmer’s study the time-of-sampling requirement entailed a much narrower temporal focus than was needed in the work reviewed by May, Spottiswoode, et al. (1995), providing, thereby, evidence of the psi-mediated timing mechanism’s remarkable adaptive power. ASSUMPTION 6: Behavioral Dispositions That Can Block PMIR or Limit Its Efficacy Certain behavioral dispositions tend to limit the effectiveness of or entirely prevent PMIR. They include, but probably are not exhausted by, behavioral rigidity, response inhibition, stereotypy, response chaining, and strong preoccupations, including those engendered by worry or time pressure. The response dispositions mentioned in this assumption may be temporary or chronic and may be driven by or derive from immediate situations, from enduring personal characteristics, and, very often, from their interaction. Behavioral rigidity refers to dogged determination to follow preset plans, allowing no deviations, not even slight ones, relative to substance, timing, or circumstance. Response inhibition means the tendency to impose rigid rational or stylistic constraints on one’s behavior, such that before getting into action one must be sure of exactly what one intends to do and of how and why it is being done, prior to getting underway, especially if what one is considering doing is unusual or differs from what one usually does. Acting on an impulse of the moment is unthinkable if such a disposition rules one’s action. Stereotypy means the inclination always to do a given thing precisely as it has been done before, such as rigidly adhering to the route one always uses to get to a certain place. Response chaining means that one particular action always follows a particular other one, such as always stopping by a certain bookstore after attending the opera. Strong preoccupations are present when some situation or activity, including mental activity, preempts attention, thought, and/or action. In such an instance one does not, or cannot, do something else that comes to mind that might represent a push toward PMIR. There also are chronic preoccupations that may be presumed to block or inhibit PMIR, such as obsessive, chronic worry. Chronic worry, especially if it is strong, may be presumed to block or inhibit PMIR because of its almost continual usurpation of attention, affective resources, and thought. If the chronic worrier is able to perform at all, the worry may enforce familiar routines that do not make heavy demands on attention or thought. The adverse consequences of chronic worry for PMIR may be deemed to parallel the consequences of worry for performance on complex non-psi tasks, including problem solving, and for much the same reasons. The demands of PMIR often will require a readiness to act outside of everyday routine(s), including outside of routines activated by the current situation. If one is chronically worried, acting beyond everyday routines may be far less likely due, in part, to its usurpation of needed mental resources and, in part, to the uncertainties associated with acting in unaccustomed ways. Another way in which obsessive worry may reduce the likelihood of PMIR is that it enhances the level of arousal, sometimes to a very high level and consistently. There is experimental evidence that high levels of arousal tend to activate dominant responses (Spence, Farber, & McFann, 1956), and dominant responses certainly include, for particular kinds of individuals, the PMIR-inimical response dispositions enumerated in ASSUMPTION 6. Time pressure is another factor that tends to activate dominant (e.g., overlearned) responses (Horton, Marlowe, & Crowne, 1963), thereby working against any nonroutine thoughts and behaviors needed by PMIR. Therefore, just as time pressure is known to disfavor creativity, living in the “pressure cooker” may be deemed likely to block or greatly reduce the likelihood of PMIR and its attendant benefits. The dispositional constructs of ASSUMPTION 6 are predictor variables that are proposed in the model to have adverse consequences for the occurrence of PMIR. Testing the model’s prediction that these particular dispositions are inimical to receptive psi is critical to assessment of this aspect of the PMIR model. To do so, however, it is essential that what one measures or manipulates experimentally in regard to these dispositional variables is a valid instantiation of the construct at hand. Actual performance measures of a dispositional construct, when carefully developed and measured, arguably are apt, in most cases, to be more valid reflections of such a construct than can subjective measures obtained via self-reports in whatever format. Subjective measures are subject to a number of biases, including social ones, inability to recognize or understand what actually drives one’s personal behavior (Nisbett & Wilson, 1977), and/or errors of recollection. Objective performance measures, which are not subject to such reportage biases or memory errors, can be particularly valuable when they are obtained unobtrusively in the course of the psitesting session. They reflect mental activity as it actually exists at the moment of assessment and often their raw data (data from which scores are derived) may be had unobtrusively simultaneously with measurement of the dependent variable (the outcome variable). In-session performance measures generally should be more efficacious as dispositional predictors for a present-time task than should prediction from personality inventories, which are not designed to measure the state of the organism at a particular point in time, let alone at the desired moment. A paper by Stanford (2003) provides in-depth discussion of this unobtrusive measurement strategy, along with citations of evidence of its potential construct and predictive validity. Studies in which unobtrusive, performance-based predictorvariable measures were taken while subjects did the ESP task have provided for me, over the years, the most replicable effects in my work. As always, thoughtful planning of such measures in the interest of construct validity is essential. Two linked reports of a study of ESP in ganzfeld (Stanford, Frank, Kass, & Skoll, 1989a; Stanford, Frank, Kass, & Skoll, 1989b) illustrate approaches to assessment of spontaneity, arousal, and internal attention state through verbal-transcript analysis of session utterances (1989a) and the usefulness of such assessments in understanding samesession ESP-task performance (1989b). The following examples of other unobtrusive ESP-task-based predictors all have shown replicated significant prediction: (a) spontaneity, inversely indexed by call-balancing tendency across ESP-target options, predicted magnitude of deviation from chance expectation (reviewed by Stanford, 1975); (b) degree of upward shift in frequency of occipital alpha (EEG) rhythms from pretest relaxation/meditation to ESP testing predicted ESP-task performance (reviewed and conceptually interpreted by Stanford, 1990); (c) ESP-task response categories produced with relatively low frequency tend to show positive ESP-task performance, presumably due, in part, to reduced false alarms (reviewed by Stanford, 1975). ASSUMPTION 7: Normatively Maladaptive Uses of PMIR in Personal Adaptation If an individual is inclined through nonpsi means to harm self-interests of whatever kind(s), PMIR unconsciously may be deployed, alternatively or additionally, as a means to such ends. These self-harm-related interests could range from physical, psychological, and social ones, even to personal possessions (e.g., electing to own a vicious dog). This is a ramification of the general role of PMIR in support of the personalistic adaptational strategies and tactics of the individual. Thus, PMIR may be used in normatively maladaptive ways in the case of psychopathological dispositions. Psi-related considerations aside, persons may tend, consciously or unconsciously, to harm themselves and/or their possessions. The possibility of self-harm being actualized unconsciously has been mentioned at least as long as the writings of Sigmund Freud, for instance in his Psychopathology of Everyday Life (1965/1901), a treatise that still merits reading, both for its ideas and for an insight into the remarkable creativity of its author. Contemporary psychologists have been puzzled at and sometimes debated why depressed individuals often appear to affirm, through social interaction, their negative self-esteem. Such seemingly counter-intuitive behavior may suggest unconscious proclivities, but they need be neither psychodynamic in character nor imply masochistic inclinations. William B. Swann and colleagues, based on extensive research guided by his self-evaluation theory as applied to self-esteem, have adduced evidence (e.g., Giesler, Josephs, & Swann, 1996; Swann, Wenzlaff, Krull, & Pelham, 1992) that depressed individuals seek and welcome negative feedback about themselves and that they may do so at least in part nonconsciously in the interest of verifying their self concepts and thereby achieving a more stable view of themselves and their social world. For example, Swann, Wenzlaff, Krull, and Pelham (1992) commented, “We believe that depressives actively (although not necessarily consciously or intentionally) evoke such reactions as a means of verifying their self-conceptions” (p. 303). These investigators see depressed persons’ verification of their self-conceptions as bolstering their “perceptions of existential security and interpersonal control rather than a conscious desire to flagellate themselves” (p. 304). Their social world, it is suggested, thus appears to become more predictable. These investigators’ discussions of self-verification theory suggest a role for unconscious motivation in the ways depressed persons manage, through social interaction, to affirm their negative views of themselves. If this evidence of depressed persons’ active, albeit often unconscious, selfverification via social interaction is taken seriously, then depressed individuals perhaps also use PMIR toward that same end. They, for example, might use unconscious receptive psi as an aid in selecting things to do or say and the times to say or do them such that they will be effective in eliciting social verification of a negative self-concept. Beyond such a role in depression, PMIR might also be used in support of a variety of maladaptive dispositions. For example, it might be used, among those with paranoid inclinations, toward such ends as fostering encounters with information (e.g., remarks overheard) that easily could help feed delusional thinking. If so, psi-mediated encounters with a selected slice of “reality” could reinforce dispositionally delusional ideation. PMIR as a Possible Shaper of Research Outcomes Numerous psi researchers have commented that if the PMIR model is correct, then investigator-psi influences on study outcomes should be possible and, indeed, should occur (review by White, 1976) [see chapter 16, this volume]. I agree, but a few points merit caution. Discussion of this matter has tended far too often to focus exclusively, even obsessively, on studies related to psi, although psi studies are not the only ones in which this issue may be important. Psychology experiments often may provide opportunities for psi-mediated influence from the researcher—as well, also, for the non-psi subtle sensory influences that psi researchers routinely try to control. Stanford (1981) argued the importance of making concrete efforts to reduce potential experimenter psi in research and explained some methodologies directed toward that end. That paper still has relevance today. In our present ignorance of potential limits in the operation of psi, it seems unrealistic to think that all possible loci of experimenter psi influence can be obviated, but some of its possible routes certainly can be eliminated or their effectiveness reduced. Cross-experimenter replicability of outcomes may thereby be enhanced. An Issue Not Broached in Recent Versions of the PMIR Model In the present version of the PMIR model, as in its versions published in 1990 and 1982, none of the model’s assumptions is intended to address the underlying character of whatever it may be that allows psi to work in the service of the organism’s needs and dispositions. The PMIR model’s first version (1974a), though, proposed a scanning mechanism related to needrelevant information. As was explained in my 1990 presentation of the model, being thus presumptuous was a misstep. More than three decades ago I concluded that the PMIR model is best left to do what I think it always has done reasonably well, namely provide a psychological model of psi as it serves the needs and dispositions of the organism. First Sight Model and Theory (FSMT) In preparing to discuss FSMT theorization I have consulted several of Carpenter’s writings (2004, 2005, 2008, 2012). His book (2012) is a major work and, at almost 500 pages, is a reflection of the depth and breadth of the thought and extensive literature in both the parapsychology and psychology that underpin this volume. Carpenter, who adopts a phenomenological-existentialist approach to psychology, uses corresponding terminology and sometimes writes in a style that some readers at first may find difficult (he notes this himself). I have tried here to make his ideas as easily and quickly understandable as I am able by using some terms that may be more familiar. Carpenter’s discourse often is wonderfully rich in meaning and nuance and I hope that my efforts to communicate it tersely and at times a bit more familiarly have done it justice. Apologies are due the reader and Carpenter if I have done otherwise. Anyhow, I hope that my discourse here might encourage readers to read his writings. Carpenter’s knowledge of and understanding of the psychology of psi functioning is truly exceptional, and direct access to his thoughtfully detailed discourse on these matters is indispensable for those wishing to learn first-hand the rich potential insights about psi functioning and relevant evidence conveyed in his writings. My Synopsis of FSMT’s Central Concepts (based largely on Carpenter’s 2012 book) Two truly foundational premises. What follows are two FSMT premises that should be borne in mind at all times in studying this theorization. Psi as fundamental and foundational in organisms. In all organisms psi, which has unlimited reach in time and space, is a fundamental, continuously causal element in every experience from the very start, whether such experience involves mentation or action. Unconscious functioning underlies conscious experience and action. The mind operates unconsciously, not just consciously, and this continuous, unconscious functioning acts in support of individual needs and inclinations. Unconscious functioning does so in accord with the meanings, for the individual, of information accessed by psi, which knows no limitations of time and space. The results of such processing have a foundational role in the development of all conscious experience and action. This does not mean that the person necessarily becomes consciously aware of such information, which presumably is the exceptional case, but unconscious influences, including those made possible by receptive psi, are foundational in the development of conscious experience. Additionally, active psi (PK) influences are deemed to affect both neuronal activity and to prepare the physical world for the physical body’s interaction with it. Two fundamental analogy-based assumptions. The first of these assumptions concerns receptive psi (called by some ESP, extrasensory perception); the second, active psi (often called PK, psychokinesis) [see Preface for alternative terms]. Analogical relationship of receptive psi and subliminal stimulation. Receptive psi and response to subliminal stimuli are seen as analogous, similar in their objective consequences and in their representation in human experience (phenomenology). Receptive psi, for example, might promote arousal suitable to an upcoming physical encounter of some sort, preparing the organism to respond quickly to it at the time of that encounter. Similarly, a subliminal affective prime might prepare someone to respond affectively, rapidly, and in an appropriate way when a subsequent affectrelevant stimulus is presented. Active psi as unconscious expressive behavior analogous to bodily expression. Active psi is seen as a form of unconsciously expressive behavior (e.g., a light bulb that explodes as you walk out of the boss’s office consequent to his insulting you), an expression without bodily contact of an unconscious affective inclination. Such active-psi events are proposed by Carpenter as analogous to bodily expressions of feeling (e.g., an inadvertent, momentary sneer on one’s face or a snort), which can occur even if one is unaware of such expression and might not wish it to occur. The Twelve Corollaries (Chapter 2) The twelve corollaries are said (p. 17) to be elaborations of the two assertions (based on analogies) discussed earlier. Carpenter indicates that the bulk, but not all, of the testable implications of the corollaries are to be found under those termed intentionality, switching, and liminality. Personalness Corollary How the organism interacts with the circumstances of the world, whether they are accessed by extrasensory or sensory means, is determined by the meaning(s) of the situation at hand for that individual at that time. Carpenter’s remarks suggest that in writing of meaning he is referring to the judgment-related consequences of automatic, unconscious processes that determine the organism’s response to circumstances, including to unconsciously apprehended extrasensory and/or preconscious sensory ones. The meaning of such circumstances for the organism need not be consciously apprehended for meaning-guided response to occur. Ubiquity Corollary Receptive psi is, as noted earlier, independent of time and space, so the elements of the world relevant to personal meaning often are spatially remote and/or temporally distant. This is not a problem because receptive psi is an ongoing, constant process that precedes and guides sensory access and response to information. In first sight perspective one cannot be without psi because that is the way receptive psi operates, it leads the way. PK is said to affect the functioning of the nervous system in accord with intention, including the intention to act upon the world outside one’s own body. In regard to the relevance of active psi to the external physical world he notes that it acts on the object of one’s intention, whether that intention is conscious or unconscious. Integration Corollary It is not just psi that contributes to the development of experience and action. A wide range of other preconscious processes typically are involved. These, for example, might include memories of past experiences, purely imagined situations, personal motivations and enduring values relevant to the situation at hand, as well as preconsciously processed information from a variety of sensory sources. All would be accessed preconsciously, quickly, and holistically in the development of integrated consequences relative to action and experience. Anticipation Corollary Our minds need to be able to predict the circumstances of our personal lives. Interpreting (“construing”) the meaning of our experiences supports this goal, and our minds make use of preconscious processing in this regard. Our minds, says Carpenter, use preconscious information (e.g., subliminal or unattended sensory information, as well as extrasensory information) to anticipate the meaning of subsequent experience. Past experiences, personal concerns and interests, and psi-derived information all may prime, quite unconsciously, a particular meaning of an otherwise ambiguous event. This may influence subsequent behavior. Weighting and Signing Corollary This is one of the corollaries primarily intended to explain how unconscious processing uses unconscious material in the development of conscious experience and in the selection of behavior. All unconscious information, whether it is of sensory or extrasensory origin, is unconsciously weighted, early in processing, in terms of its potential relevance to the needs and goals —thus, the intentions—of the organism at that time. Items thus weighted more heavily will tend, in that degree, to be provided a higher priority in unconscious processing. According to FSMT analysis, even a high-end weighting does not mean that an item necessarily will be represented in conscious experience or influence overt behavior. It may or may not have a direct role to play in consciousness and/or behavior because, according to FSMT, before an item enters consciousness it must, in addition to and subsequent to weighting, be given a positive sign. Otherwise, it will be given a negative sign and be excluded from conscious awareness. This is termed signing and is posited to occur in the case of heavily weighted items. It consists of assigning either a positive or negative value to the information at hand. That evaluation, much like a directional highway sign, is said to determine whether one’s tendency is to become further involved with the information in question or to avoid it, whether in internal representation and/or physically. Signing is said to be controlled automatically by unconscious intention, but signing is posited always to occur subsequent to weighting. Carpenter provided a detailed example of this process (2012, pp. 23–24). Questioning universality in the timing of signing. The following are my ruminations. Should it be assumed that weighting and signing always are separate processes, with signing always subsequent to weighting? Presumably motivators and/or goals have a hierarchy, as some of Carpenter’s comments indicate. Might it be that those on top in certain types of hierarchies automatically command, at least, conscious attention (if not a specific present-time action)? They may be part of an extant script for such a situation. Experience, even vicarious experience, may teach us that in certain situations specific responses are requisite, and survival/adaptation interests would seem, in many instances, to favor the utility of such preexisting, circumstance-associated command tags (or signs). These could preempt the need for a temporally separate signing (as per FSMT) in particular situations. This could depend on the life experiences of the individual or it might depend on evolution. People may create enduring rules (required signage, if you will), consciously or unconsciously, for certain situations, based on personal experience with them. It sometimes may be very adaptive, in the interest of speed of response, not to have to select a sign de novo on each encounter with an exemplar of a particular construct. FSMT’s proposal about weighting-then-signing may well hold for particular situations (e.g., sufficiently novel ones), but it seems reasonable that alternatives may exist, such as those just mentioned. Need for testing FSMT’s weighting-then-signing proposal. Carpenter (2012, p. 21) states that FSMT’s weighting and signing proposal and his switching proposal (see later) are his theory’s most important innovative concepts. It would be interesting to know specifically how the proposition that signing always follows weighting might be tested. Is that really, in principle, a testable proposition (i.e., that a rule never has exceptions)? Be that as it may, how might testing proceed simply to find evidence that signing has followed weighting in at least some situations? If such as these are fundamental assumptions, it would be good to consider how they might be tested. A survival-related issue. Carpenter’s discussion of the signing corollary makes strong reference to the complexity of what must transpire in such computation of priority or gating, even in everyday situations. What is more, it is assumed that weighting and signing occur continually at both conscious and unconscious levels. How is it assumed that all this complex processing actually occurs? Is Carpenter positing that this processing occurs in the nervous system, rather than via some magical psi process? If he is proposing that, how might the brain accomplish all this? Optimally quick response to certain types of situations means the difference between life and death. The proposed serial character of the processing (i.e., weighting and then signing), might take a while, given that both require time and that there may be an inter-task interlude. On the other hand, if the organism were preset, whether by biological (evolutionary) endowment, via prior learning, or via some combination of those, to use command tags that have been preattached to certain danger-related stimuli, then survival or harm-prevention should be easier and quicker to accomplish. Recent research (reviewed by Öhman & Mineka, 2001, 2003) with humans and other primates has provided evidence suggesting that evolutionarily primitive emotion-related brain areas may include an evolutionarily based “preparedness” module that specifically elicits readiness for the development of a fear response to phylogenetically survival-relevant animals (e.g., snakes). This module is presumed to function at an unconscious level, both on conceptual grounds and because, for example, it appears that it can be activated by stimuli that are not processed consciously (e.g., subliminal stimulation with photos of such an animal). Phylogenetically fear-relevant animals presumably can elicit flight-preparatory response (and, presumably, fear or anxiety) without the fear-related creature being consciously noticed. The result could be a much quicker response in the face of an actual encounter. This evolutionary hypothesis about a very specifically attuned unit illustrates a possibility relevant both to Carpenter’s conceptualization and to my PMIR model (Carpenter, 2012, discusses the evolutionary angle but does not cite the potentially very useful research by Öhman and colleagues) [see chapter 11, this volume]. A module such as that posited by Öhman might, I suggest, be responsive to receptive-psi inputs, just as it can be activated by preconscious sensory stimuli. Summation Corollary Carpenter tries here to explain how the unconscious mind reaches its decisions (derived from many weighting and signing outcomes) on which information will be allowed to influence unconscious attention and from which it will turn away. To my mind Carpenter is not clear on the nature of the supposedly arithmetic process of the unconscious mind reaching its decisions of this kind. This corollary reiterates the essence of the ideas in the previous corollary about weighting and signing. However, in discussing how outcomes, implicit or conscious, are determined relative to various sources of personal meaning, what initially seems intended as something quantitatively precise dissolves, to my mind at least, into an unsuccessful effort at precision and explanation and becomes imprecise through declaring the processing to be holistic. Is precision a property of the discourse when one ultimately has to proclaim some loose kind of averaging process and then to declare that the whole thing is carried out, across potentially huge amounts of information, in some kind of holistic way? I was sorry to see the discourse invoke the ultimately unhelpful term of holistic processing. Unless such a term is clearly specified as to meaning, it seems to me an example of what Gigerenzer (2009), in discussing surrogates for theory, terms one-word explanation (i.e., nouns with broad meaning that, although presented as explanations, never specify an underlying mechanism, so they cannot be said to provide a model). Carpenter (2012) does cite many very useful resources related to unconscious processing, including a masterful synoptic paper by Dijksterhuis and Nordgren (2006) (his in-text citation, chapter note, and reference listing all have the junior author, Nordgren, omitted). This cited material, however, largely addresses unconscious thought in descriptive terms concerning how, based on research, it is believed to function in practice. Dijksterhuis and Nordgren do, though, opine that it may be best, at present, to think of unconscious processing in terms of a computational process and ask whether a connectionist concept might be useful in that regard. That seems a very good start. I wish Carpenter had followed it by saying something in that regard, rather than going no further than what seems merely a summary term, “holistic.” Dijksterhuis and Nordgren used the term “holistic” in their discourse, but their use of it was unequivocally as a phenomenological term, not as an effort at explanation. (They had asked their subjects in a study whether they had made their choice on the basis of a relatively holistic judgment.) In regard to such matters as processing of multiple strands of information, it was surprising for me to see that, judging from the index of Carpenter’s book (and my recollection of reading it), it never mentions the important concept of parallel processing, much less the possibility that some kind of PDP model might be developed that could address issues related to the handling of psi-related information. The emergence of concepts and models related to parallel processing has been seen as a major influence on initially very skeptical psychologists in regard to their increased readiness to consider the idea of unconscious processing (Kihlstrom, 1987). Some discussion by Carpenter of parallel processing might have made more understandable the possibility of handling a diversity of inputs— preconscious or conscious—in expeditious ways because it would have used modeling premises that, in the case of PDP, have successfully been used to master some important human tasks (e.g., pattern recognition and generalization of constructs; Rumelhart et al., 1986). It might be of interest that one of the fundamental outcomes of PDP processing is that if a concept already has been mastered by its network, inputting only a part of it allows reconstitution of the original. Might this be somewhat like what psi recipients would need to do? Both Carpenter’s theorization and my PMIR model assume that psi activates extant memory structures, but we know from many studies—and Carpenter discusses this at length in his book—that the information retrieved even by talented psi performers often is, initially, at least, fragmentary in character, sometimes more of an intimation of the corresponding reality than like, for example, a photo of it. If we assume that the construct appropriate to a psi target is available (from past experience) in the brain and can be activated in the brain by psi, but that only part of it initially is activated sufficiently for retrieval on demand, then if the brain is operating in the way it is modeled in PDP, perhaps the target construct ultimately may be more fully reconstituted for conscious access. This may take a while. Indeed, initial partial information in a free-response psi study often seems to develop into a fuller impression if the mind is allowed to relax and its outputs quietly observed (White, 1964). Bidirectionality Corollary This corollary simply elaborates on the implications of signing. This would appear to assume that any element of unconscious experience that has sufficient personal meaning will be evaluated (i.e., signed) either positively or negatively. A positive sign means that the organism will tend to turn toward (or “approach,” mentally and perhaps physically) the meaningful circumstance/object that has been evaluated, and a negative sign, that it will tend to turn away from (or “avoid”) that evaluated source. In FSMT, the former is called “assimilation” and the latter “dissimilation.” (In some cases, negative signing is said to produce contrast, rather than dissimilation, although I am not sure of the rationale for the shifting terms.) In a freeresponse ESP test, if a cat were the target, complete assimilation would include the response “cat,” however that construct might manifest in the individual. With incomplete assimilation, relevant partial impressions, like a long tail, might be reported. Dissimulation, on the other hand, would entail a response very different than “cat.” In the case of an unconscious behavioral receptive-psi task assimilation would be reflected in movement in the direction of engagement with the target (e.g., finding a movie ticket); with dissimulation, movement would be in some other direction. Carpenter stressed the point (p. 24) that dissimilation is not the same as ignoring something; rather it is as though the organism genuinely avoids it. In an ESP test, this might entail statistically significant evidence of psi-missing relative to a particular construct. I suggest that in such a case potential interpretation(s) other than motivated avoidance should be considered and empirically examined (e.g., consistent missing, which may involve confusion of targets due to similarities of meaning, association linkages, and/or visual similarity, i.e., cognitive, non-motivational, routes to psimissing; reviewed by Kennedy, 1979; see, especially, pp. 121–125). Intentionality Corollary This corollary largely elaborates on the implications of the Bidirectionality Corollary. Assimilative and dissimilative tendencies, in a given situation, are said to depend on unconscious intention relative to the personally meaningful circumstance that has been evaluated. If that circumstance unconsciously has positive incentive value for the individual in that situation, a tendency to assimilate that circumstance will be present. On the other hand, if that situation is unconsciously evaluated either to have no incentive value or negative incentive value (i.e., is undesirable), then dissimilation (or equivalently, contrast) is said to be observed. Switching Corollary The inclination toward assimilation (approach) or dissimilation (avoidance), that arises and manifests unconsciously, may be relatively constant or may switch over time, sometimes even oscillating between the two, sometimes much like someone might vacillate in a situation that favors both approach and avoidance, such as deciding to ask the boss for a raise or deciding on whether to see the dentist. The switching-related processes discussed in FSMT are deemed to be unconscious, and the constancy of a given inclination (approach or avoidance) and the switching between those two is governed by what Carpenter calls unconscious intention. Unconscious intentions are determined by the strength of the incentive value unconsciously associated with a given circumstance and, of course, by that incentive value’s constancy or lack of it. The tendency to switch between the two inclinations may be determined by a host of factors, many of which are discussed in explaining the switching corollary. Those factors include, but are not limited to, pondering via rational analysis, alertness, fatigue, moods, personal styles or habits of thinking or acting, and changes in the situation of the individual. Circumstances that are strongly relevant to an individual’s central values are likely to garner unconscious attention and there will be little or no switching until they are addressed. Situational factors that plausibly might influence the inclination to switch or remain constant are discussed at some length under this corollary. Also provided are two lists of presumptively somewhat stable individual differences deemed likely to influence the proclivity for switching. One such list provides characteristics thought to favor switching (e.g., a strongly cognitive-analytical orientation) and the other, those proposed to favor consistency in such evaluation (e.g., persons dispositionally well focused and less distractible). These make for interesting reading, and they might provide some starting points for productive characterologically based psi research [see chapter 9, this volume]. Studies of response dispositions (e.g., “traits”) and how they might relate to psi-task performance can be vitiated by a failure to acknowledge via research planning that it is dispositions actively engaged by the testing situation and active within the actual psi-test itself that logically should influence psi-task performance. Consequently, it is important (a) to ponder under what circumstances and through what cognitive/behavioral means the proposed disposition logically could and should influence psi-task performance in a particular way, and (b) broadly to incorporate these considerations into a conceptually relevant experimental design. Carpenter’s discussion in his chapter on fear and psi (and elsewhere) makes it clear that he appreciates the importance of such trait × situation interactions and recognizes the importance of matching traits and traitrelevant situations through research design. Extremity Corollary The discussion of this corollary is focused very heavily on the consequences for formal ESP-test performance of various kinds of unconscious switching patterns. If readers are able to follow this discourse, they may come to understand how the switching concept can explain certain outcomes in psi experiments. Indeed, it may be an eye-opener about the ways in which psi may manifest other than just the overall deviations from chance that one typically encounters, about how such outcomes often objectively derive from switching, and about the role that psychological factors are deemed to play in controlling switching. One eye-opening example is when scoring in a forced-choice task is so close to mean chance expectation across each of a substantial number of testing units that this result is, of itself, very improbable if only chance is operating. This outcome is known by various names, including low variance (or low runscore variance in some forced-choice ESP research). Low variance is not just a hypothetical outcome, for it has been observed to appear with some degree of reliability in forced-choice ESP testing that engenders rationalistic constraints upon the choice of symbols to be guessed in forcedchoice ESP testing (reviewed by Stanford, 1975). There is, as Carpenter addresses switching, some discussion, but not sufficient in my view, of how this construct might apply in everyday life experience as related to psi. Low variance and statistical cancellation effects are cases in which I gained the impression that the discourse stays too close for too long on laboratory findings (e.g., low variance) without making very clear their potential relevance to psi outside the laboratory. Inadvertency and Frustration Corollary The immediate consequences of receptive-psi influence on the mind take the form that Carpenter (2004, p. 224) terms inadvertency. His definition states, “Inadvertent psychological events are those that ‘just happen’ as opposed to being experienced as things ‘I do’” (p. 224). Here is one example (my own): A sudden, utterly unanticipated sense of sadness permeates one’s consciousness. Inadvertencies emerge unexpectedly, usually seeming to be disjunct from conscious wishes or the sensory circumstances in which one finds oneself. They often, but not always, are sudden. They may or may not have anything to do with psi influence, but they often have a way of garnering attention. They are reminiscent of the subtle effects of subliminal stimuli on, for example, feelings or interpretations of later events. In studies of receptive psi, inadvertencies typically are observed. They often are more like partial glimpses of something than like a photographic view of a target, or they may be like hints at its emotional tone or its sensory qualities (e.g., rough and jagged, whereas the photo shows mountaintops). One would have liked a whole picture, but that usually is not what one gets in such a setting. There are subtle hints of the target, allusions to its meaning, and/or perhaps feelings associated with it. Thus, one’s perceptual goal is in this situation is not realized, but, in its lieu are intimations of what it might have been. This is why the name of this corollary includes frustration. Carpenter (2012, p. 32) suggests that persons who have many reasonably consciously accessible inadvertencies, who are attentive to them, and who are able to interpret them may be thought to be somewhat “psychic.” His remarks suggest that this interpretational skill may be developed over time (p. 32), and my discussions with some such individuals also suggest that. His very interesting discussion of inadvertency is, to my mind, one of the best in this volume. Liminality Corollary Carpenter thinks of the kinds of experiences discussed under the Inadvertency and Frustration Corollary as liminal experiences. This term relates to the hypothetical boundary between conscious and unconscious awareness of material or thought. The thoughts underlying inadvertencies are unconscious and thus are not amenable to conscious scrutiny. Their existence and their influence, though, are revealed to consciousness indirectly through inadvertencies. Many people notice such experiences, and possibly everyone does at times. Some, however, pay more attention to them, take much greater interest in them, gain understanding of their own minds from them, and even have learned how to use them to advantage, both in thinking about themselves and in applying their implicit meanings constructively in their lives and work. Such individuals may be more likely to become aware of when psi is influencing their thinking and behavior. A major part of Carpenter’s discussion of the liminality corollary is devoted to characterizing individuals who are relatively likely to become aware of and even make use of such experiences. One such category consists of those who regularly take an interest in such experiences because they have a greater openness to unconscious thought, including to its psi-mediated influences. He suggests that highly creative individuals tend to be interested in personal inadvertencies and ready to make use of them in their lives and work. One of my favorite examples is the poet who pens lines but only recognizes much later that the words have more than one level of meaning, some of them not recognized at the time of composition. This can only happen to those willing and ready to give expression, in the first place, to something that seemed to flow out of a deeper level of the mind. Carpenter also discusses moods and readiness to notice and make use of liminal experiences. Conceptualization: Testability of Constructs in FSMT Three bases for concern are discussed here: Testability: One of the posited roles for PK in FSMT. Carpenter (2012, pp. 93–94) indicates that just as receptive psi is considered unconsciously to prepare the individual for experience, unconscious PK is deemed to prepare the physical object of intention for the organism’s acting upon it with its physical body. I have not succeeded in deriving any clear meaning from this assertion. What does this mean? In what respect(s) is such prior PK preparing the target of the physical action to be acted upon or is helpful for the physical body to act upon the physical world? My concern in this regard is not relieved by the subsequent assertion (p. 94) that this effect on the object generally is invisible. If so, how might one know about this preparatory effect? What kind is it? How might it be measured? In the absence of elaboration as to what should be happening, under what condition(s), and some statement of how this proposed action might be studied, this seems an untestable proposition. Testability: The blockage-required proposal for outside-body PK in FSMT. Chapter 7 also proposes that one observes PK only when action somehow is blocked. This at first seemed to me a very reasonable proposal, one that might help explain a release-of-effort effect sometimes observed in PK testing (Stanford, 1974b). Unfortunately, on more careful reading it seemed clear that the implied interpretation of the concept of “blockage” is so diffuse and flexible, that it, in principle, would fit any situation that one could define as providing a legitimate test of PK. It is so malleable that it can take on an indefinite number of forms, one of which presumably would have to be present in any test of PK. Here are two examples (in my own words) from two well-known PK research methodologies mentioned in Chapter 7 in an apparent effort to illustrate that blockage would be present in both of them. In a dice-rolling PK example it is said that upon the throw of the dice they may come up showing the target, although we cannot, thanks to this being a PK task, physically bring about what we wish. In the case of a random event generator running when someone is trying to influence which one of two outcomes it produces, the results may accord with our wishes but we have no physical way to influence outcomes as we would wish. These, it seems by my reading, are provided as examples of blockage as it is present in two different PK test methodologies. If the lack of opportunity, through non-psi means, to physically manipulate the target system in a deliberate test of PK is a form of the blockage said to be required for PK to occur, then it seemingly would be impossible to test this proposal. There has to be a way to obviate physical influence on the target system if someone is going to be properly tested for PK! How, then, does one test for PK without creating, by definition, a blockage? Consequently, any success would have to be regarded as support of the proposition put forward about blockage. There seemingly would be no possibility of falsifying the required-blockage proposal if there were adequate conditions for testing PK. Consequently, this proposition, so far as I can see, cannot be tested with a definition of blockage that has this ubiquitous form. One reviewer of this chapter insightfully noted that this blockage proviso also would appear to preclude using FSMT as an explanation of poltergeist phenomena. Testability: Universality and constancy of psi. Carpenter maintains as a fundament of his conceptualization that psi is universal among organisms and that it is a constant in basically all that happens with them, operating as a forerunner for both sensory processes and motor response. Psi is affirmed as a foundation, temporally, of all that happens, at least in the world of organisms. This is an extraordinarily bold idea, but it seems to me that by its very nature it may be an untestable proposition, for it would seem to have no implications about boundary conditions for the operation of psi. I therefore cannot imagine how it could be tested. A clear statement on whether these fundaments are deemed testable ideas—and, if so, how they might be tested—would have been helpful. There are many very worthwhile and some very exciting ideas under FSMT’s conceptual umbrella that can be tested, but I doubt that this is one of them. FSMT’s many scientifically useful ones relate, in my view, to FSMT’s treatment of the psychology of psi. FSMT at its intended deepest level, beyond its psychology, perhaps is most useful, in its present form, more as a pointer than as a true theory, an intimation of the deep and abiding significance of what we study and of the extraordinary insights toward which psi events may lead us at some point in our journey toward scientific understanding. Assessments of Justificational Efforts Needed caveats about a generalizable positive correlation of extrasensory and subliminal sensory performance. One of the two analogies around which FSMT is built is that the functioning of psi is analogous to what is found in subliminal perception. Much of the power of FSMT theorization hinges on the validity of that analogue. Carpenter devoted chapter 10 of his book to the parallels between psi and preconscious or subliminal sensory information, and that topic is revisited numerous times elsewhere in that volume. One section of the chapter discusses the correlation of ESP and subliminal sensory scores, but it did not discuss or mention the two sections of my 1990 PMIR chapter that were devoted to that topic. Those sections included (a) presentation of a meta-analysis of data bearing upon whether responses to extrasensory information and to subliminal visual information are correlated, and (b) methodological issues important in studying and making inferences on such matters. My meta-analysis involved a rigorously selected database relative to the question that motivated it, which was whether there exists a correlation, as various commentators had suggested on conceptual grounds, between accuracy of response to extrasensory and to subliminal visual sensory information. My meta-analysis excluded studies that did not report a correlation coefficient for these two variables or that did not appear to test the relation of interest (e.g., presence of confounding or of non-subliminal stimuli). It also excluded the single study with auditory stimuli. My conclusion was concordant with Carpenter’s ideas in this regard (but see caveat on generality below), and my metaanalysis found both an overall significant positive relationship and homogeneity of effect sizes across studies. The number of studies involved, though, was low, so more studies are needed for firm conclusions about the existence of such a correlation and any circumstances that may moderate it. A strong caveat must be voiced about any temptation to generalize the implications of this database (Stanford, 1990) because subjects always were asked to tell on each trial which of the several stimuli had been subliminally presented, with all of the possible stimuli known in advance (i.e., forcedchoice methodology). Such work leaves unknown whether the results would generalize to subliminal/ESP studies using other than forced-choice methodologies. The ability, though, to generalize beyond forced-choice situations would seem to be important for extrapolation to many of the situations of life. Of course, also, no generalization from my meta-analysis is merited about parallels between ESP and anything other than specifically visual subliminal information. Even that generalization may be too broad (or too coarse) in the absence of research carefully addressing potential differences of the efficacy of various kinds of visual presentations (e.g., words vs. pictures; or static vs. dynamic material). Errors in reporting and using specific literature. No systematic search was undertaken to discover reporting errors. The two instances described below involved my own work, where such problems were easy to recognize and seemed hard to ignore. I felt I should alert readers to substantial errors in the published description of my work rather than passively reinforce any misconceptions created by erroneous reporting. These two examples may interest readers because they relate to research on two topics that received major treatment in Carpenter’s FSMT discourse, namely the roles of memory and of anxiety/fear in receptive psi. Incorrect statement of key methodology of the Stanford (1970) memory– ESP study and inaccuracies in reporting its findings. Carpenter (2005) incorrectly described a key procedure in the Stanford (1970) study of extrasensory incursion into retrieval from incidental memory. Carpenter (2005) stated that my “participants heard material which they were asked to memorize (my emphasis) and about which they were later tested in a multiple-choice questionnaire” (p. 76). In fact, no one was asked to memorize anything in that study. Carpenter thus mischaracterized as a test of explicit memory (i.e., of memory for information that subjects are asked ahead of time to remember) a test of incidental memory (i.e., of memory of events about which subjects did not expect, at the time of exposure, later to be queried). This distinction is very important because the study was designed to provide (a) a test of possible unconscious extrasensory influence on retrieval of information from incidental memory, and (b) a separate test of incidental memory skill that could be used to understand how such skill affects extrasensory influence upon retrieval of items from incidental memory. This independent measure of incidental memory skill proved very important in understanding the role of unconscious extrasensory influence on retrieval of information from incidental memory. A test of explicit memory, which is what incorrectly was said to have occurred, would not have been suitable for such a purpose. There also were some serious errors in Carpenter’s reporting of the outcomes of that work. He (2005, p. 75) described what were supposed to be two closely related findings of Stanford (1970), but his descriptions of them do not match any findings from that study. He said of the findings he erroneously attributed to the study that, if they prove reliable, they would accord with his hypothesis that “extrasensory and other sorts of preconscious information should tend to be accessed in similar ways” (p. 75). In actuality, the Stanford (1970) study provided no support for that proposition and the report stated that incidental memory skill per se was not related to ESP performance (p. 177). An error in reporting evidence on anxiety/defensiveness and ESP. Carpenter (2012, p. 220) erroneously reported that Stanford and Schroeter (1978) found statistically significant psi-missing among high-anxious (our preferred term, high-defensive) subjects. In fact, our high-anxiety/defensive group had not shown significant psi-missing, but scored at mean chance expectation (ESP mean = .498, where mean chance expectation = .500). Our low-defensive group, though, had shown significant psi-hitting, but the difference of ESP performance for these two groups was not significant. Adequacy of statistical information in support of inferences. Troubling for me were statements, both in Carpenter’s 2012 book and in his FSMT journal articles, that seemed to claim support, from the study at hand, for an FSMT directional prediction (i.e., of psi-missing or of psi-hitting) when the only direct evidence in a study for that was a nonsignificant deviation below or above mean chance expectation in the predicted direction. Adequacy of Cited Studies/Data in Support of Arguments Potential problems related to explaining data ad hoc using motivational constructs. It seems safe to say that Carpenter, in his presentations of his model, has cited hundreds of psi studies, often claiming that their findings, even if puzzling to the authors of the studies, fit well with his over-arching theory, which he maintains makes sense of a very large number of these puzzling findings. For example, he (2008) remarks, “Many of the various proposals may serviceably account for their particular sets of results, but none of them has the general capacity to account for almost all of these findings in the way that the first sight model does” (p. 68). One has to be very careful here. It can be all too easy to rationalize specific research findings, after the fact, such that they seem compatible (or, at least, more compatible) with personally preferred concepts, perhaps especially if those ideas have high generality and breadth and/or have a diffuse or an elastic quality about them. Carpenter’s theorization seems to me to be built, first and foremost, around motivation or intention, and much of its theoretical power centers on the construct of bidirectionality, along with assimilation/contrast, and psihitting/psi-missing. Motivational constructs can be a slippery slope conceptually, and a theorist must guard the justifiable margins of it with some care. It may be very easy to suppose that certain feature(s) in a study elicited one or another kind of motivation, intention, or emotion that can then be invoked to explain the finding at hand. To me this seemed to have been at work when Carpenter (2008), in discussing a finding from one of my word-association-ESP studies (1973) remarked, “Thus, in general, more meaningful material should evoke a tendency to psi-hit and less meaningful material should evoke a tendency to psi-miss, and primary associates (being generally more meaningful) should tend to express hits and secondary associates should tend to express misses” (p. 67). This proposal about the relative meaningfulness of primary and secondary associates was unsupported by the cited empirical evidence. Very important, there was no significant psi-missing on the secondary associates, despite Carpenter’s supposition that there should have been. Carpenter assumes that a highcommonality response, as determined by word-association norms, represents something intrinsically more meaningful than a lowcommonality response. Although primary associates often reflect high familiarity, this need not mean that they have greater personal meaningfulness. Often it may be quite the opposite. Carpenter’s supposition about high-commonality responses reflecting greater personal meaningfulness ignores that such responses reflect high commonality in a population (i.e., are based on their word-association norms), which means they may have little, if anything, to do with what drives one personally but relate to what people often encounter in their culture. Although I was involved with word association research for many years, I cannot think of a way to make credible Carpenter’s claims about the relative personal meaningfulness of high- and lower-commonality responses. Anyhow, a typical example of a high-commonality STIMULUS-response pair is TABLE-chair. Where is the substantial individual meaningfulness in such a pair? Indeed, a lower-commonality response might get more at personally meaningful, more idiosyncratic material. The assertion that sampling from the top of the word-association norms reflects depth of personal meaning seems conceptually and empirically untenable and was empirically unsupported by Carpenter. Information of which readers should be apprised to obviate misinterpretation of correlational data. A source of concern about Carpenter’s reporting of correlational results is that he at times reports the p-value and signed direction of a correlation but provides little or no additional information that could guide his reader toward an accurate interpretation of the empirical and conceptual significance of that correlation. In the example that follows, Carpenter (2012, p. 258) provided a p-value of .000006 for the meta-analytic significance of the weighted- mean, positive, extraversion–ESP correlation as reported by Honorton, Ferrari, and Bem (1998) for 21 forced-choice ESP studies with individual testing. Carpenter noted, also, that significant evidence of a correlation of these variables was not found with group testing and that the difference of the extraversion–ESP correlations for individual- and group-testing situations was significant. These findings seem in line with his conceptualization of extraversion as interacting with the characteristics of social situations to influence psi-task performance. Missing from Carpenter’s review of this important meta-analytic work, though, are some facts that bear importantly on interpreting such a correlation, especially given the presentation of a tiny p-value associated with the extraversion–ESP correlation (in forced-choice studies with individual testing). Providing a tiny p-value without supplementary advice for potentially statistically naïve readers seems ill advised. Many of his readers may be unaware that a small p-value can reflect simply a large sample (as here) but a small effect size (as here). Unreported by Carpenter (2012, p. 258) were (a) the magnitude of the average weighted correlation (.15), so even the statistically sophisticated reader could not have inferred that the correlation accounted for only 2.25 percent of the extraversion–ESP covariation; (b) the information that the correlations across those studies were significantly heterogeneous, placing thereby a serious limitation on any effort to generalize the magnitude of correlation across studies; and (c) mention that 31 forced-choice (FC) studies judged by the meta-analysts to have acceptable protection against sensory leakage failed to show anything even approaching a significant weighted-mean extraversion–ESP correlation (r = .04); that the 14 forced-choice studies deemed potentially subject to sensory leakage showed a small (.14), albeit significant, correlation; and that those two correlations differed significantly. An additional interpretational caveat that might have merited mention in Carpenter’s discussion of this important meta-analysis concerns how subjects got into their testing condition (i.e., either individual or group testing). Individuals participating in individual or group testing were not there by random assignment and were not “forced labor” but agreed to participate in a given condition. Therefore contrasts of the extraversion– ESP correlations for individual-testing versus group-testing circumstances potentially were confounded by person-related differences (possibly, even, by extraversion, given the social nature of the test situations) in volunteering for a given condition. There were other instances in Carpenters’ literature reviews in which I felt that more information should have been supplied to help obviate overinterpretation or misinterpretation of the sometimes-scant information presented. Such information, though, may be deemed even more important in discussion of integrative findings, as with meta-analysis. How Might a Central FSMT Construct, “Switching,” Be Conceptualized, Operationalized, and Laboratory Tested for Its Relevance to Psi in Everyday Life? Knowing Carpenter’s obviously strong desire to provide ideas with relevance to life situations, I was disappointed not to find what I deemed sufficient discussion of how a central construct of FSMT, switching, would manifest in life situations, relate to adaptation, and might be empirically studied. How might switching and a proclivity for (or against) it relate to and affect adaptation, constructively or adversely, in particular kinds of situations? There are many potentially interesting questions that might be asked about this domain. I suspect that readers might have been intrigued by this construct, amazed by its ramifications in, for example, forced-choice ESP testing, but were left wondering about its relevance to everyday life. How easily can one extrapolate to the situations of real life—where most of the psi functions, according to FSMT, are unconscious—on the basis of laboratory testing with largely non-meaningful stimuli and conscious engagement with a multi-trial forced-choice ESP task? This, after all, was the nature of the forced-choice ESP-test paradigm that was the birthplace of the switching construct. How, in sum, does the switching construct translate into testable inferences related to life situations, situations where one or a very few trials may be allowed by the exigencies of life? Potentially High Value of Carpenter’s Suggestions for Guiding Psi Research to Greater Productivity at the Psi-Psychology Interface Six general suggestions for guiding psi research are presented by Carpenter (2012, Chapter 24). Each seems to hit directly on a high-value target relative to some of the central methodological needs of contemporary psiresearch programs, and the diversity of focus of these suggestions is a real strength of that chapter. This presentation is a very useful synopsis of some of the key methodology-relevant implications of the last four decades or so of innovative research and theorization, forthcoming from a substantial number of researchers and theorists, that has brought attention to the primarily unconscious functioning of psi and to its resonance with recent developments in psychology. Major Strengths of FSMT: Its Potential for Advancing This Field Major strengths of Carpenter’s FSMT writings are their thoughtful, wideranging, and thoroughgoing efforts to bring together concepts and findings from parapsychologists and psychologists. There is much promise, evident in his writings, that these two closely related disciplines are increasingly having something of interest to say to each other, both in terms of ideas and research findings. Carpenter’s writings on FSMT would seem to have the potential of helping to advance the perception of psi and psychological research as potentially being mutually enhancing. He seems to be arguing that this potential symbiosis is going to have to be seeded, in part, by serious efforts from psi-researchers to address problems of interest to psychologists, thereby making important contributions to psychology as a science. The boldness with which Carpenter puts before his reader a vision of psi as fundamental and important in the world of organisms is refreshing and one that likely is shared by quite a few among us, whether or not we agree with his particular vision. References Bargh, J. A. (1997). The automaticity of everyday life. In R. S. Wyer Jr. (Ed.), The automaticity of everyday life: Advances in social cognition, Vol. X. (pp. 1–62). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum. Carpenter, J. C. (2004). First sight: Part one, a model of psi and the mind. Journal of Parapsychology, 68, 217–254. Carpenter, J. C. (2005). First sight: Part two, elaboration of a model of psi and the mind. Journal of Parapsychology, 69, 63–112. Carpenter, J. C. (2008). Relations between ESP and memory in light of the first sight model of psi. Journal of Parapsychology, 72, 47–76. Carpenter, J. C. (2012). First sight: ESP and parapsychology in everyday life. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield. Dijksterhuis, A. & Nordgren, L. F. (2006). A theory of unconscious thought. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 1, 95–109. doi:10.1111/j.1745–6916.2006.00007.x Freud, S. (1965). The psychopathology of everyday life. New York: Norton. (Original work published 1901). Giesler, R. B., Josephs, R. A., and Swann, W. B. (1996). Self-verification in clinical depression: The desire for negative evaluation. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 105, 358–368. Gigerenzer, G. (2009). Surrogates for theory. Observer, 22(2), 21–23. Goldstein, E. B. (2008). Cognitive psychology: Connecting mind, research, and everyday experience (2nd ed.). Belmont, CA: Thompson/Wadsworth. Hassin, R. R. (2013). Yes it can: On the functional abilities of the human unconscious. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 8, 195–207. doi:10.1177/1745691612460684 Honorton, C., Ferrari, D. C., and Bem, D. J. (1998). Extraversion and ESP performance: A meta-analysis and a new confirmation. Journal of Parapsychology, 62, 255–276. Horton, D. L., Marlowe, D., and Crowne, D. P. (1963). The effect of instructional set and need for social approval on commonality of word association responses. Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, 66, 67– 72. Kennedy, J. E. (1979). Consistent missing: A type of informationprocessing error in ESP. Journal of Parapsychology, 43, 113–128. Kihlstrom, J. F. (1987). The cognitive unconscious. Science, 237, 1445– 1452. May, E. C., Spottiswoode, S. J. P., Utts, J. M., and James, C. L. (1995). Applications of decision augmentation theory. Journal of Parapsychology, 59, 221–250. May, E. C., Utts, J. M., and Spottiswoode, S. J. P. (1995). Decision augmentation theory: Toward a model of anomalous mental phenomena. Journal of Parapsychology, 59, 195–220. Nisbett, R. E., and Wilson, T. L. (1977). Telling more than we can know: Verbal reports on mental processes. Psychological Review, 84, 231–259. Öhman, A., and Mineka, S. (2001). Fear, phobias, and preparedness: Toward an evolved module of fear and fear learning. Psychological Review, 108, 483–522. doi:10.1037/0033–295X.108.3.483 Öhman, A., and Mineka, S. (2003). The malicious serpent: Snakes as a prototypical stimulus for an evolved module of fear. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 12, 5–9. doi:10.1111/1467–8721.01211 Palmer, J. (2009). Decision augmentation in a computer guessing task. Journal of Parapsychology, 73, 119–135. Rumelhart, D. E., McClelland, J. L., and the PDP Research Group (1986). Parallel distributed processing: Explorations in the microstructure of cognition: Volume 1: Foundations. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Spence, K. W., Farber, I. E., and McFann, H. H. (1956). The relation of anxiety (drive) level to performance in competitional paired-associates learning. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 52, 296–305. Stanford, R. G. (1970). Extrasensory effects upon “memory.” Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 64, 161–186. Stanford, R. G. (1973). Extrasensory effects upon associative processes in a directed free-response task. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 67, 147–190. Stanford, R. G. (1974a). An experimentally testable model for spontaneous psi events: I. Extrasensory events. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 68, 34–57. Stanford, R. G. (1974b). An experimentally testable model for spontaneous psi events: II. Psychokinetic events. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 68, 321–356. Stanford, R. G. (1975). Response factors in extrasensory performance. Journal of Communication, 75, 153–161. Stanford, R. G. (1977). Conceptual frameworks of contemporary psi research. In B. B. Wolman (Ed.), Handbook of parapsychology (pp. 823– 858). New York: Van Nostrand Reinhold. Stanford, R. G. (1981). Are we shamans or scientists? Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 75, 61–70. Stanford, R. G. (1982). An experimentally testable model for spontaneous extrasensory events. In I. Grattan-Guiness (Ed.), Psychical research: A guide to its history, principles and practices (pp. 195–205). Northamptonshire, UK: Aquarian Press. Stanford, R. G. (2003). Research strategies for enhancing conceptual development and replicability. Journal of Parapsychology, 67, 17–51. Stanford, R. G. (2006). Making sense of the extrasensory—modeling receptive psi using memory-related concepts. European Journal of Parapsychology, 212(special Issue), 122–147. Stanford, R. G., and Associates (1976). A study of motivational arousal and self-concept in psi-mediated instrumental response. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 70, 167–178. Stanford, R. G., Frank, S., Kass, G. and Skoll, S. (1989a). Ganzfeld as an ESP-favorable setting: Part I. Assessment of spontaneity, arousal, and internal attention state through verbal-transcript analysis. Journal of Parapsychology, 53, 1–42. Stanford, R. G., Frank, S., Kass, G. and Skoll, S. (1989b). Ganzfeld as an ESP-favorable setting: Part II. Prediction of ESP-task performance through verbal-transcript measures of spontaneity, suboptimal arousal, and internal attention state. Journal of Parapsychology, 53, 95–124. Stanford, R. G., and Rust, P. (1977). Psi-mediated helping behavior: Experimental paradigm and initial results. In J. D. Morris, W. G. Roll, and R. L. Morris (Eds.), Research in parapsychology 1976 (pp. 109–110). Metuchen, NJ: Scarecrow. Stanford, R. G., and Schroeter, W. (1978). Extrasensory effects upon associative processes in a directed free-response task: An attempted replication and extension. In W. G. Roll (Ed.), Research in parapsychology 1977 (pp. 52–64). Stanford, R. G., and Thompson, G. (1974). Unconscious psi-mediated instrumental response and its relation to conscious ESP performance. In W. G. Roll, R. L. Morris, and J. D. Morris (Eds.), Research in parapsychology 1973 (pp. 99–103). Metuchen, NJ: Scarecrow. Swann, W. B., Jr., Wenzlaff, R. M., Krull, D. S., and Pelham, B. W. (1992). Allure of negative feedback: Self-verification strivings among depressed persons. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 101, 293–306. White, R. A. (1964). A comparison of old and new methods of response to targets in ESP experiments. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 58, 21–56. White, R. A. (1976). The limits of experimenter influence on psi test results: Can any be set? Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 70, 333–369. OceanofPDF.com CHAPTER 9 States, Traits, Cognitive Variables and Psi ETZEL CARDEÑA and DAVID MARCUSSON-CLAVERTZ Researchers have examined a number of implicit and explicit psychological predictors of psi performance. For instance, Honorton (1997) compared different ganzfeld studies and concluded that there were four predictors of successful psi performance: previous psi experiences, previous participation in psi testing, involvement with a mental discipline, and being a feeling/perception type on the Myers-Briggs Type Indicator (MBTI). He recommended that psi participants have as many of those features as possible. The finding about previous psi performance has been replicated (see below), and the facilitative effect of following a mental discipline was partly supported by the finding of a ganzfeld meta-analysis that selected participants, including meditators, performed significantly better than unselected participants, but only when they were in the ganzfeld rather than the control condition (Storm, Tressoldi, & Di Risio, 2010; see also chapter 10, this volume). We discuss feeling/perception below. States of Consciousness We initiate our review with transitory changes in states of consciousness. It is often assumed that scientific and philosophical consideration of alterations of consciousness were evoked by the popular interest in drugs and Eastern philosophies of the 1960s, but they have a much longer history in both Western and non–Western cultures (Cardeña & Winkelman, 2011a). Just in the West, a discussion of the nature of alterations of consciousness and their relation to reality can be traced back at least to Plato (Cardeña, 2009) and has been an important aspect of the thought of philosophers of the caliber of Descartes (Windt, 2011). With regard to both research and clinical psychology, hypnotically induced or spontaneously occurring changes in consciousness were fundamental problems in the eyes of foundational figures of the discipline including Freud, James, Janet, and many others (Spiegel & Cardeña, 1991). Hypnosis and dissociation were also core areas of research and theory for the British Society for Psychical Research founded in 1882, and some of its researchers including Edmund Gurney, F. W. H. Myers, and William James contributed to the study of these phenomena and their potential relation to psi phenomena (Alvarado, 2014). This initial interest was, however, short-lived given the decades-long dominance of behaviorism. In the West, a sort of reawakening of interest in ASCs occurred in the 60s, partly spurred by influential works by Ludwig (1966) and Tart (1975), among others, which helped link this area to diverse subareas including parapsychology, to which Tart has also been an important contributor. Before reviewing the work on alterations of consciousness and psi performance, we will aim to clarify some confusions that keep recurring in the area: (a) biased or missing definitions, (b) reification of conscious experience, (c) confusing an induction with an experience and ignoring individual differences, and (d) disregarding the interactive co-creation of conscious experience. Definitional Absence or Bias Defining states of consciousness need not be an exercise in obfuscation, although that is sometimes what one finds in the literature. The concept of altered state of consciousness (ASC) is fuzzy (Lakoff, 1973) as are so many natural categories, but it need not be an unclear or biased one if a specific use of the term is delineated (Velmans, 2009). We follow here Tart’s (1975) definition of an ASC as a qualitatively different state of consciousness, or unique pattern of psychological structures, that differs from the ordinary, baseline, waking state of the person. His concept does not presuppose that the altered (or alternate) state involves psychopathology or is a better or worse way to apprehend reality. In contrast, some authors assume that ASCs “misrepresent or create delusional beliefs of the surrounding world and oneself” (Kallio & Revonsuo, 2003, pp. 141–142). This naïve realistic assumption has a number of problems, including the assumption that a nonaltered state does not misrepresent reality, a supposition that clashes not only with the whole idealist philosophical tradition since Plato, Kant, and others, but also with the conclusion that evolution is likely to produce a serviceable rather than a particularly accurate contact with reality (Hoffman, 2008). The implications of contemporary physics (D’Espagnat, 2006) that the best we can aim for is knowledge about the outcome of specific forms of measurement are also relevant [see chapter 31]. Another problem with the definition by Kallio and Revonsuo is that it presupposes that ASCs cannot provide valid information not accessible during the ordinary waking state, but research in parapsychology shows exactly the opposite. Valid information has been obtained particularly when techniques that have as a goal to induce an ASC have been used, including hypnosis (see below), ganzfeld and dreaming (chapter 15, this volume), drugs (chapter 12, this volume), and meditation (chapter 10, this volume). When trying to determine the characteristics of a state of consciousness (whether baseline or not), it is essential to try to obtain a comprehensive description of the state. There are a number of introspective methods available (Cardeña & Pekala, 2014), so ad-hoc questionnaires measuring only unawareness of stimuli and confusion (e.g., Pérez Navarro & Cox, 2012; Pérez Navarro, personal communication, 2013) should not be used. Nor should vague terms such as “trance,” which denote all kinds of experiences from being absent-minded to being a medium for another entity, be used, unless at the very least their referent is specifically described. Reification of Conscious Experience The philosopher Mario Bunge (1980) drew attention to the fallacy of reifying consciousness as an entity, rather than as an ongoing process. This had earlier on led master phrase-maker William James to coin the metaphor “stream of consciousness” to give a sense of the ungraspability of conscious experience, paralleling the philosophy of constant change of Heraclitus (James, 1890). A practical consequence of the reification of ASCs as entities is that some authors take them as signifying unchanging, monolithic states, making references to “the hypnotic state,” “the meditative state,” and so on. This façon de parler veils two important sources of differences: interindividual among experients, and intraindividual for “the same state.” Hinterberger (2014) described strong phenomenological and neurophysiological differences resulting from the same meditative practice. Marked changes within a state have been described in relation to a “neutral” hypnotic procedure (Cardeña, 2005), sleep onset (Foulkes & Vogel, 1965), and psychedelic ingestion (Siegel & Jarvick, 1975), among others. Confusing an Induction with an Experience and Ignoring Individual Differences Following the previous point, another problem with talking about “hypnotic,” (or “meditative,” or similar qualifiers) states of consciousness is that they are often presumed to occur automatically after someone has used a hypnotic (or meditative) procedure. Not so! A hypnotic or meditative technique will have strong, medium, or negligible effects depending on a number of long- and short-term factors including personality dispositions (Cardeña & Terhune, 2014; Kumar & Pekala, 1988), and set and setting characteristics (Tart, 1975). Furthermore, other contexts such as exposure to traumatic events can elicit some of the same phenomena found within a hypnotic context (Cardeña & Spiegel, 1993), and just asking some people to use their imagination can produce similar effects to those of a hypnotic induction (Hilgard & Tart, 1966). Disregarding the Interactive Co-creation of Conscious Experience Although the English cognate “conscious” refers to the having of joint or common knowledge, one of the most neglected areas in the study of consciousness is the interactive, interpersonal process involved in the cocreation of conscious experience. The literature on developmental psychology and clinical practice commonly refers to the effect of the “other” on what the child or the adult may be experiencing, but as we move to other areas in psychology and parapsychology we usually encounter only an abstracted “participant,” or “subject,” who seems to interact only with thin air. This is despite the fact that many studies have shown important experimenter effects on human and non-human animals (e.g., Silverman, 1974; Sorge et al., 2014). But even speaking of “experimenter effects,” whether psychological or psi [see chapter 22, this volume], hides the notion that what transpires in a study depends on the interaction of human beings, even if only the characteristics of the “participants” are described in most studies. We are very far from having developed a systems approach within psychology or parapsychology, but there is some recognition of this need in the hypothesis that some successful psi researchers exhibit certain characteristics that make them more likely to obtain psi performance from their participants (Schlitz, Wiseman, Watt, & Radin, 2006). Because hypnotists and participants may get in rapport (harmony) and experience some of the same alterations in consciousness during a procedure (Varga, Józsa, & Kekecs, 2014), the concordance between researcher and participant conscious experience requires investigation in parapsychology, rather than assuming that psi phenomena reside only either in the participant or the experimenter [see chapter 5, this volume]. Traits There have been impressionistic assessments of who is likely to have success in a psi experiment, such as a description of successful remote viewers as “confident, outgoing, adventurous, broadly successful individuals with some artistic bent” (emphasis in the original, Targ, Puthoff, Humphrey, & May, 1980, p. 10), but such broad personal judgments would likely have questionable reliability across different observers. Instead, researchers in the field have investigated more discrete and measurable personality traits. Traits have been defined as “relatively enduring, automatic patterns of thinking, feeling, and behavior … elicited in trait relevant situations” (Roberts, Donnellan, & Hill, 2013, p. 183). The last qualifier is important because the greatest amount of behavioral variance explained depends on the interaction between traits and situations characteristics (Bower, 1973) [see chapter 8, this volume]. We review below traits that have been related to performance in psi experiments. Extraversion and Openness to Experience A construct included in the “Big Five” personality traits, and measured by the NEO Personality Inventory (Costa & McCrae, 1985) and the MBTI is extraversion. Individuals who are extraverts tend to find gratification in things outside of their selves, such as large social gatherings. In the context of psi testing it has been conjectured that extraverts should perform better than introverts because the former are more relaxed with the novel social interaction that a laboratory test may provide (Palmer, 1977), but it has also been proposed that extraverts should score better because they typically have lower cortical arousal, which has been presumed to relate to psi ability (Eysenck, 1967; Honorton, 1977). In a 1977 review, Palmer identified 33 experiments correlating extraversion with performance in mainly forcedchoice psi tests; 8 revealed a significantly positive correlation, 15 were nonsignificantly positive, and 10 were nonsignificantly negative. He noted that group testing experiments generally obtained more negative correlational results compared to individual testing, but this should be interpreted with caution as most group testing experiments were contributed by only two investigator teams. Around two decades later, studies on extraversion and psi performance were meta-analyzed by Honorton, Ferrari, and Bem (1998). The 59 studies with almost 3,000 participants were categorized depending on whether they used forced-choice or free-response designs, and whether they tested participants individually or in groups. For individual testing, a weak positive correlation was found across 21 forced-choice, r = .15 (95 percent CIs [.09, .22]), and 12 free-response studies, r = .20 (CIs [.11, .29]). For group testing there were null results across 24 forced-choice tests, r = –.00 (CIs [–.06, .05]), but only 2 free-response studies by one investigator team were identified, which were non-significant, r = .19 (CIs [–.01, .37]). Thus, when tested individually there was a weak positive association between extraversion and psi. Honorton et al. identified a potential artifact for the forced-choice studies as extraversion measures were often administered after psi testing, making it possible that participants based their self-reports of extraversion on the basis of their testing performance. Palmer and Carpenter (1998) demonstrated, however, that this methodological flaw was more prevalent in group testing studies and that it was individual vs. group testing rather than the order of tests that mediated the relation between extraversion and psi. Although there was a possible confound of sensory leakage in the forced-choice studies, no methodological artifact was identified for the freeresponse studies. In a study on presentiment [see chapter 17, this volume], Broughton (2004) did not find an overall psi effect nor a relation between MBTI extraversion and the psi task, but reported that the MBTI intuition type was related to psi scoring. When subcomponents of extraversion were analyzed separately, Van Kampen, Bierman, and Wezelman (1994) found that the relation was restricted to two facets of extraversion, warmth and positive emotions. However, they also found that the extraversion-psi correlation disappeared when openness to experience was accounted for. Openness to experience was significantly related to psi in a precognition test (Luke, Roe, & Davison, 2008), not related in a replication, but related in both a metaanalysis of the previous two articles and a new one (Hitchman, Roe, & Sherwood, 2012). Carpenter (1991) reported that factors consistent with extraversion (being strong-willed and outgoing) and being in an altered stated correlated with psi-hitting. There has been also some research on the sense of personal luck and psi performance, with mixed results (cf. Luke et al., 2008; Hitchman et al., 2012). Clearly more research is needed to evaluate the robustness of these findings and elucidate which specific facets or aspects of a trait are more closely related to psi (see also, Carpenter, 2012 for a theoretical review of the extraversion–psi relation). Honorton et al. (1998) argued against a filedrawer effect in the case of extraversion by performing a Rosenthal filedrawer estimate that indicated that for every free-response study 10 unreported ones with an average zero correlation would be needed to make the effect disappear, although this estimate may be too liberal if unreported results are below zero (chapter 15, this volume). Neuroticism Emotional instability, or neuroticism, may decrease performance on psi tests by hindering the person from becoming comfortable in a relational, testing situation. Palmer (1977) reviewed 24 studies on neuroticism and psi: 7 studies had a significant negative association, 11 were nonsignificantly negative, and 6 were nonsignificantly positive, suggesting a negative association between neuroticism and psi performance. Palmer noted that studies that tested participants in groups, typically classrooms, usually found nonsignificant positive correlations. He speculated that neurotic persons may perform less poorly in those setting because the environment is more familiar than the laboratory setting and they may feel less pressure when others are tested at the same time. Compared to extraversion, neuroticism has received less attention post– 1977 although a number of studies have been published in peer-reviewed journals (Broughton & Alexander, 1997; Goulding, 2005; Houtkooper, 2003; Houtkooper, Schienle, Stark, & Vaitl, 2001; Roe, Henderson, & Matthews, 2008; Roe, Holt, & Simmonds, 2003; Watt & Baker, 2002; Watt & Brady, 2002; Watt & Ramakers, 2003). No meta-analysis has been published, but in recent studies the correlation coefficient has generally been close to zero and nonsignificant. A notable exception is Houtkooper (2003), who found some complicated but interesting post-hoc results. He administered a forced-choice psi task in two 40-trials runs with trial-by-trial feedback, and together with neuroticism he measured standard psi performance and forward displacement psi (measured by matching the guess of the current trial with the two subsequent targets rather than with the current one). For the first run of the psi task neuroticism did not correlate with any of the psi variables but for the second run neuroticism correlated negatively with standard psi scores and positively with forward displacement psi scores. A speculative interpretation is that very neurotic participants started to perform more poorly towards the end of the test after receiving disappointing trial-by-trial feedback, but why it would be accompanied by positive psi displacement is difficult to understand. The finding of a null correlation indicates poor reliability and further complicates the interpretation of the results; nevertheless, it would be informative to replicate this paradigm and further test the relation between standard psi scores, displacement scores, and neuroticism scores under feedback conditions. In the literature there is no strong support for a linear relation between neuroticism and psi (but see also Carpenter, 2012). We encourage more process-oriented research that specifies under what conditions the presumed negative relation between the two variables occurs, with individual vs. group testing and the characteristics of the experimenter(s) also evaluated. Feeling/Perception These two personality types are measured by the MBTI, whose validity and reliability has been questioned (e.g., Pittenger, 1993). The inventory evaluates four dichotomies: the social attitude of extraversion vs. introversion, the functions of sensing vs. intuition, and thinking vs. feeling, and the lifestyle of judging vs. perception. Replicating an earlier study by Murphy and Lester (1976), Brugger and Baumann (1994) reported that believers in ESP scored higher in feeling than nonbelievers. With regard to actual performance in controlled experiments, after reviewing data from different studies, Honorton (1997) indicated that individuals with the combination of feeling (arriving at a decision through empathizing with others and seeking harmony, rather than mostly basing the decision exclusively on logic) and perception (a preference for using the senses and intuition rather than just judging matters) performed better in ganzfeld psi tasks. The feeling type was also found to be a positive predictor of psi scoring by Parker, Grams, and Pettersson (1998), but was not significant in other studies (Alexander & Broughton, 2001; Roe, Davey, & Stevens, 2004, 2005). Overall sample sizes and power have been very low (see Milton & Wiseman, 1999, for a discussion on the original findings). Although parapsychology has had an advantage over other disciplines of encouraging publication of failures to replicate, given the possibility of publication bias and selective reporting in the social and natural sciences (e.g., Ioannidis, 2005; Rosenthal, 1979) a more convincing case for a relation between personality traits and psi would be made by presenting evidence from a pre-registered, open-source study with good statistical power, or from a meta-analysis with a reasonable number of good studies. The Propensity to Experience Alterations of Consciousness In the West, from the Eleusinian mysteries experiences through the medieval ecstatic or possessed people to the writings of the mesmerists, commentators have remarked on important individual differences in the ability to enter states of consciousness (Cardeña & Winkelman, 2011a). More recent investigation on anomalous experiences has revealed as well that individuals exhibit valid and reliable individual differences in some constructs such as absorption, dissociation, dream experiences, and hypnotizability, which can be partly traced to genetic and non-shared environmental factors (cf. Dalenberg et al., 2012). These constructs are also frequently associated with the propensity to have anomalous experiences (Cardeña, Krippner, & Lynn, 2014), and neuroscientific research has started pointing out potential genetic and neurotransmitters systems related to some of these constructs (Cardeña & Winkelman, 2011b). A recent study revealed the association among the following constructs: hypnotizability (especially when measured as experiential alterations after a hypnotic induction), absorption (adopting an experiential rather than a conceptual mindset, becoming immersed in an experience), mental boundaries (the permeability or communicability between psychological processes or states of consciousness) and self-transcendence (the likelihood of experiencing oneself as interconnected or transcendent) (Cardeña & Terhune, 2014). Reports of ostensible psi experiences have been consistently associated with fantasy proneness, dissociation, hypnotizability, absorption, and similar constructs (e.g., Gow, Hutchinson, & Chant, 2009; Pekala, Kumar, & Marcano, 1995; Richards, 1996; Wickramasekera, 1993), but there has been little research on the possible relation of these constructs and performance on psi studies. The construct of transliminality, developed by psi researcher Michael Thalbourne, is based on earlier ideas of F. W. H. Myers and purports to measure how easily subconscious material can become conscious. It is related to thin mental boundaries and the propensity to have mystical and another anomalous experiences (Thalbourne & Maltby, 2008), and has been correlated with psi scoring (Del Prete & Tressoldi, 2005), although Storm and Thalbourne (1998–1999, 2001) could not replicate their initial positive correlation between transliminality and psi scoring in a test loosely based on the I Ching. Houran and Lange (2013) found that transliminality correlated positively with New Age Philosophy and self-reported business intuition, but the correlation with psi performance was marginally non-significant. Others have tested the relation between transliminality and psi in ganzfeld (Parker, 2000) and shamanic-like and control conditions (Rock, Storm, Harris, & Friedman, 2012) with non-significant results. Rabeyron and Watt (2010) reported that thin mental boundaries (measured with a different questionnaire than that for transliminality) related to paranormal experiences but not to a retro-priming psi task. Alterations of Consciousness and Psi Performance In a very influential chapter, Honorton (1977) summarized more than 80 experimental studies produced by 26 different laboratories and using four different procedures: meditation, hypnosis, induced relaxation, and ganzfeld stimulation. All of these paradigms produced highly significant results, showing that chance could not reasonably explain the results. In his summarizing comments, Honorton proposed four common characteristics of what he considered noise-reduction, “psi-enhancing internal states”: (a) a level of cortical arousal permitting conscious awareness, (b) muscular relaxation, (c) reduction of exteroceptive stimulation, and (d) attention toward internal processes. He reported other important analyses, among them that the successful ganzfeld studies typically had an average exposure duration of 37 minutes as compared with an average of 22 minutes for the non successful ones, a significant difference. He also pointed out that most successful ganzfeld studies had used participants who had been in previous psi studies. He also referred to the importance of keeping the mind “blank” or content-free to succeed in psi tasks. Braud (1978) also proposed that noise-reduction processes may work by increasing the expectation that the participant will succeed, and we would propose that the increased sense of interconnectedness and decrease of self-critical thought brought about by some of these procedures in selected participants (e.g., Cardeña, 2005) may also foster psi performance. Later research has generally supported a relation between alterations of consciousness and successful psi performance. In a series of studies, including one using the ganzfeld with meditators (Palmer, Khamashta, & Israelson, 1979), Palmer found that deviations from chance were correlated with experience of an ASC, with the direction associated with the arousal level of the induction. Sargent as well conducted a number of studies (Sargent, 1980) in which psi scoring was associated with shifts in states of consciousness, although his methodology was criticized (Blackmore, 1987, but see also Harley & Matthews, 1987). Being more specific as to what alterations may be involved in psi scoring, Alvarado (1998) proposed that time distortion and body awareness changes were related to psi scoring, whereas Carpenter (2004) proposed self-transcendence experiences. In a study using a valid and reliable measure of alterations of consciousness, a number of alterations of consciousness measured during a ganzfeld session that preceded the session in which psi was evaluated were significant (Marcusson-Clavertz & Cardeña, 2011). We had initially predicted that high hypnotizability and alterations in consciousness would be main effects in the prediction of successful psi scoring. Although the main effects were not significant, the interaction between these variables revealed a number of interesting results. For high hypnotizables, but not lows, being in an altered state in ganzfeld, reporting altered experience, and time alteration correlated strongly with psi z scores. It is worth mentioning that although they did not reach significance (the study had a small N), negative correlations with psi scoring were related to processes related to rationality: decreases in selfawareness (significant for the whole sample of high and low hypnotizables), and in rationality, volitional control, and memory. Contrary to Honorton (1977), the correlation between arousal and psi scoring was close to zero. In a study of which only the abstract has been published at this point, psi scores related to greater absorption and decreased arousal and internal dialogue (Roe, Hodrien, & Kirkwood, 2012). In one of three studies investigating three “shamanic-like” procedures, psi performance was related to experiencing alterations in time sense, perception, and experience, overall, and (negatively) with memory (Rock, Storm, Harris, & Friedman, 2013). There have also been other studies that did not find a relation between alterations of consciousness and psi performance (da Silva, Pilato, & Hiraoka, 2003; Pérez Navarro & Cox, 2012), but they employed questionable, not validated measures. In sum, the results suggest a link between psi scoring and experiencing alterations in consciousness, along with decreases in rational, analytical processes, but much more research using validated and reliable instruments is needed. Hypnosis Hypnosis as a procedure involves responding to suggestions to alter experience, behavior, or physiology, following an induction procedure in which the person is asked to disregard extraneous concerns and focus on the hypnotist’s instructions to go into hypnosis (Barber, 1984). Hypnosis and its predecessor, mesmerism/magnetism, were claimed during the 18th and 19th centuries to give rise to extraordinary abilities including telepathy, clairvoyance, and precognition (Crabtree, 1988; Dingwall, 1967–1968). Many if not most earlier observations would not pass current methodological muster, but there were still some cases such as that of the 19th century somnambulist Alexis Didier, or some of the later, more systematic studies by Leonid Vasiliev that are far more difficult to explain away (Cardeña, 2014; Méheulst, 2013; Vasiliev 1962/2002). The first review of modern research (Van de Castle, 1969) concluded that hypnosis facilitated psi performance. A more quantitative analysis was conducted by Honorton (1977), who had a number of valuable observations. One was that when a hypnotic condition was compared with a nonhypnotic one, the former clearly and significantly produced more psi scoring. Another was that the effect sizes of studies using free-response paradigms were one order of magnitude greater than guessing studies. He also pointed out that the ability to respond to hypnosis (hypnotizability) had been rarely assessed, and that the specific hypnotic procedures administered had been rarely described. Nonetheless he observed that specific positive suggestions to enhance psi abilities used in two studies had enhanced psi scoring, and concluded that a person × situation (or procedure) interaction was a central consideration. After Honorton’s, two other meta-analyses (Schechter, 1984; Stanford & Stein, 1994) confirmed a highly significant relation between use of hypnosis and psi scoring that, furthermore, was unrelated to the quality of the studies. Nonetheless, Stanford and Stein (1994) did find that the studies conducted showed various flaws and that results varied considerable across principal investigators, but concluded that their criticisms “did not imply that hypnosis has no utility for enhancing extrasensory performance. It is simply that the extant studies provide more puzzles than useful clues” (p. 261), a conclusion with which we concur. Finally, in a study that used hypnotic suggestions to foster psi scoring, the overall results were significant and psi scoring related to the hypnotizability of the sender (McBain, Fox, Kimura, Nakanishi, & Tirado, 1970), suggesting the importance of studying all participants in the experiment [see chapter 22, this volume]. Since those meta-analyses, only a few studies have continued to evaluate the effect of hypnosis. Del Prete and Tressoldi (2005) reported that a hypnotic procedure (incorrectly described as “hypnagogic,” which refers to the state between being awake and asleep) emphasizing suggestions for outof-body experiences produced significant psi scoring whereas self-induced relaxation did not. In a replication study (Tressoldi & del Prete, 2007) they again found significant psi scoring under hypnosis, but only in the first of two sessions, a pattern similar to that reported earlier (Parker & Beloff, 1970). In a precognition study grouping for hypnotizability and dissociation, exposure to relaxing music revealed no main effect for hypnotizability (Cardeña, Marcusson-Clavertz, & Wasmuth, 2009). In a later study (Marcusson-Clavertz & Cardeña, 2011), mentioned earlier, participants listened to a relaxation tape and although there was no main effect for hypnotizability, there was an interaction between hypnotizability, experiencing alterations in consciousness, and psi performance. There is also a study by Parra and Argibay (2013) in which they claimed that high hypnotizables scored significantly higher than low hypnotizables, but the paper shows a misunderstanding of both hypnotizability (e.g., the authors divide their group in highs and lows when the typical classification is high, medium, and low hypnotizable) and the scale used (which the authors claimed has a range from 5 to 55 when in reality it has a range from 0 to 12), so their conclusion is difficult to evaluate. There have also been failures to replicate. A study, published so far only as an abstract, found no relation between hypnotizability and psi performance in a remote viewing experiment (May, Bányai, Vassy, & Faith, 2000) although the senior author mentions problems with the psi procedure (May, personal communication, 2008). In another study (Sondow, 1986), not reported either in a peer-reviewed journal, hypnotizability did not predict performance in a psi task, but no descriptive data were provided, making it impossible for the reader to evaluate the results fully. Overall, there is good reason to continue investigating the effect of hypnotic procedures on psi performance among high hypnotizables and using suggestions to increase performance. Early Trauma, Loss, and Dissociation One of the most innovative of Freud’s disciples, Sándor Ferenczi, wrote (1955) that early trauma could give rise to both (dissociative) alterations of consciousness and anomalous cognition. There is a positive association between paranormal beliefs and history of abuse, such as having been a child of an alcoholic and experienced physical abuse within family (Irwin, 1994). Although Lawrence, Edwards, Barraclough, Church, and Hetherington (1995) replicated the correlation between within-family abuse and psi belief, the latter did not correlate significantly with sexual abuse, family loss or parental divorce. Instead, the strongest correlate of psi belief was loss of property/home moving, r(80) = .38, p < .001. Moreover, Lawrence and colleagues compared two models, one proposing an indirect link between trauma and paranormal experiences mediated by childhood fantasy, and another in which trauma directly influences paranormal experiences without the mediation of childhood fantasy. The second model provided a better fit to the data. Insofar as some psi experiences may reflect genuine psi phenomena, trauma could make individuals more sensitive to psi interactions, as Ferenczi had postulated. However, Rabeyron and Watt (2010) found that childhood traumas and negative life events correlated with paranormal experiences but not with scores on a psi task. It is also of interest that they found a weak (r = .16) correlation between poorer mental health and paranormal experiences, which disappeared when they controlled for either childhood traumas or negative life events. According to the model proposed by Irwin (2009), paranormal beliefs may exist but remain inactive until some contextual stressor activates them. Some related observations have been made about the relation between trauma and paranormal beliefs in the context of attachment research and the Adult Attachment Interview (AAI). During this interview, respondents are probed about childhood experiences with attachment figures (mainly parents or other caregivers) including potentially traumatizing experiences of abuse or loss. In response to the trauma questions some adults seem to shift momentarily in their state of consciousness and exhibit lapses in the monitoring of reasoning and discourse (Hesse & Main, 2000), such as providing incoherent information or shifting to eulogistic speech or going into excessive details about irrelevant aspects of an event (Unresolved/disorganized trauma or loss). Main, van IJzendoorn, and Hesse (1993) observed that adults with Unresolved/disorganized trauma or loss also tend to express paranormal beliefs during these interview moments (e.g., “He died that night because I forgot to pray for him”). Main et al. (1993) devised a self-report measure of Unresolved/disorganized trauma or loss with two subscales: Unresolved State of Mind (e.g., Responsibility for tragedy, Uncontrolled memories, Memories Lost) and Unusual Beliefs. They called it “unusual beliefs” but we will refer to it as paranormal beliefs here as it includes astrology, telepathy, precognition, and spiritualism. Paranormal beliefs correlated with an unresolved state of mind, as assessed with both the self-report questionnaire and the standardized discourse analysis coded from the AAI. Sagi, Joels, van IJzendoorn, Joels, and Scharf (2002) replicated the correlation between the two questionnaire subscales in an Israeli sample of mostly holocaust survivors. Disorganized attachment in childhood, indicated by disoriented or chaotic behaviors when reuniting with attachment figures after a brief separation, is a predictor of later dissociation (e.g., Lyons-Ruth, Dutra, Schuder, & Bianchi, 2006), a concept that includes loss of continuity in subjective experience, inability to access information, and a sense of experiential disconnectedness (Cardeña & Carlson, 2011). Because dissociative tendencies are moderately related to reporting anomalous, including psi, experiences (e.g., Pekala et al., 1995), it is not surprising that Thomson and Jaque (2014) investigated dissociation as a potential mediator between Unresolved/disorganized trauma or loss and paranormal beliefs. They used eight items from a fantasy proneness inventory that they labeled “supernatural beliefs,” including items on out-of-body experiences, precognition, telepathy, and religious belief. Results showed that dissociation fully mediated the positive association between unresolved mourning and paranormal belief. In sum, there is a relation between history of childhood trauma and psi-related experiences and beliefs, with psi beliefs being particularly strong in individuals with Unresolved/disorganized trauma or loss and dissociation. “Trance” mediums, who experience being affected by other entities and some of whom have provided evidence for anomalous cognition (Gauld, 1982, also see chapter 23, this volume), should be considered by definition as expressing dissociation, which was, in fact, one of the major areas in which psychical research contributed to psychology in general (Alvarado, 2014, see also chapter 30, this volume). Van de Castle (1993) discussed a severe variant of pathological dissociation (dissociative processes are not necessarily pathological) called “multiple personality disorder,” nowadays known as dissociative identity disorder. He cited a number of striking ostensible psi instances from published accounts of therapists of individuals with this disorder, besides describing his own. The first author has also received various similar accounts from therapists specializing in the treatment of dissociative disorders. Individuals who believe in psi phenomena (Richards, 1991) and/or practice as mediums or psychics report greater dissociation than the average nonclinical population but lower levels of dissociation than people with dissociative disorders (e.g., Cardeña, Reijman, Wimmelmann, & Jensen, 2015), and out-of-body experients also report more somatoform and psychological dissociation (Gow et al., 2009). Nonetheless, and despite a plea by Irwin (1997), there has been almost no systematic study of a possible relation between dissociation and psi scoring in the last few decades. In a study from our lab (Cardeña et al., 2009), high dissociative/high hypnotizable individuals had stronger psi belief than low hypnotizables and marginally so than low dissociative/high hypnotizables (p = .06). With regard to actual performance on the precognitive task, those low on dissociation tended to have lower psi scores than those higher in dissociation and scored significantly in the opposite direction of the psi task. In a second study using a ganzfeld/telepathy procedure (MarcussonClavertz & Cardeña, 2011), although dissociation did not correlate significantly with the psi z-scores, low dissociatives had slightly negative scores whereas high dissociatives had slightly positive scores. A different approach has been to elicit dissociative experiences in the lab and measure their relation to a psi task. Following up on earlier work, Palmer (2011) devised an alphabet board modeled after the Ouija in which participants were asked to move around a pointer trying to select the letters of a target word that had been randomly chosen. The experience of an outside force moving the participant’s hand was correlated with scoring significantly higher than chance, and higher than those who did not have that experience, and a trait measure of dissociation correlated with the experience of outside force. A later study (Palmer, 2013) had similar results in that participants who experienced their hand being moved by an external force had better psi scores than those who did not, and measures of detachment also predicted positively psi scoring. Judging from the scant research literature, two conclusions can be reached. The first is that highly dissociative people clearly endorse having more psi experiences in their everyday lives, but have not shown in the few studies conducted so far that they can clearly perform well in psi tasks unless a dissociative process is summoned. The other conclusion is that there is some evidence that those low in dissociation may tend to score poorly in psi tasks. A caveat is that the couple of recent quantitative studies on the relation between dissociation and psi have used convenience, non-clinical samples, rather than pathological (e.g., people with dissociative identity disorder) or nonpathological (e.g., mediums) groups who routinely express dissociative processes. Furthermore, because dissociation is a complex construct that may involve different processes, future research would benefit from specifying further which aspects of dissociation correlate with which aspects of paranormal beliefs and experiences. Creativity The previous Handbook (Wolman, 1977) did not contain any discussion of creativity or art, yet this seems to be a strong predictor of psi performance. Targ et al. (1980) anecdotally mentioned it as an associated characteristic of successful remote viewers, and there seems to be an overrepresentation of artists among participants with a seeming talent for psi (Cardeña, Iribas, & Reijman, 2012). Some personality characteristics associated with being an artist, including being sensitive, independent, and nonconformist (Abuhamdeh & Csikszentmihalyi, 2004), could relate to psi. In agreement with this conjecture, Holt, Delanoy, and Roe (2004) found that ostensible psi experiences loaded on a factor associated with being an actor and including emotional creativity, internal awareness, and nonlinear cognition. Holt et al. (2004) also reviewed the literature on psi performance under experimental conditions and reported that artists had scored significantly higher than non-artists in four free-response studies, and their scoring rate in six additional ganzfeld studies was 40 percent, whereas the typical scoring rate in different meta-analysis hovers around 33 percent [see chapter 15, this volume]. Holt (2007) replicated a high scoring rate (44 percent) in a later study using an experience sampling technique. A striking result came from a small study with Julliard performing art students whose overall hit rate was 50 percent (75 percent among eight musical students; Schlitz & Honorton, 1992) although no comparison group of non-artists was tested. Moss (1969) had earlier found that the highest scores in one of her experiments came from artists who believed that they had earlier experienced psi. Of possible relevance, Van Kampen et al. (1994) found that openness for aesthetics (see the earlier discussion on openness to experience) was a significant predictor of performance in a ganzfeld psi task, and another study found correlations greater than .3 (although not significant after statistical correction) between three of four measures of creativity and psi scores (Roe, McKenzie, & Ali, 2001). Whether these results can be traced to a conglomerate of personality traits that artists share and/or to a long-term systematic practice in becoming attuned to subtle internal experiences remains to be elucidated. In any event, the results so far recommend including artists as participants and researchers in psi research. Beliefs Sheep-Goat Effect A commonly examined hypothesis is that people’s attitude towards the psi task at hand, or psi phenomena in general, is related to their performance on the task. Schmeidler (1943, 1952) introduced the term “sheep” to refer to those who accept the possibility of success on the given psi task and “goat” to those who reject it, but there are variants of the definition (Palmer, 1971). Palmer (1977) concluded that people who believe in ESP are more likely to perform well in the lab than those who do not. Lawrence (1993) reported a meta-analysis of 73 forced-choice studies on the sheep-goat effect, including over 4,500 participants, in which 24 percent of the studies were significant as compared with the expectable 5 percent by chance. The average standardized effect size (ES) was very small, ES = 0.03, but statistically very significant, p = 1.33 × 10–16, and did not covary with the study quality. An artifact similar to that in the extraversion–psi literature was evident in that out of the 65 studies that reported the order of measures, 15 administered the sheep-goat measure after the psi test. ES was slightly larger in these studies but not significantly so. The relation between believing in psi or success in a psi experiment and succeeding has been replicated by some more recent studies (e.g., Luke, Delanoy, & Sherwood, 2008; Marcusson-Clavertz & Cardeña, 2011; Parker, 2000; Smith, Wiseman, Machin, Harris, & Joiner, 1997) but not others (e.g., Broughton & Alexander, 1997; Cardeña et al., 2009; Hitchman, et al., 2012; Schönwetter, Ambach, & Vaitl, 2011). Given the very small overall effect-size of the sheep-goat effect, we recommend further process-oriented research on possible moderators or mediators of the effect. For instance, a study by Lovitts (1981) suggested that the sheep-goat effect can be reversed if participants think that the task is designed to disprove psi. Measures of Psi-Related Experiences and Beliefs A vast majority of measures of psi-related experiences and beliefs rely on explicit self-reports, as opposed to implicit measures in which attitudes are measured indirectly, such as by examining reaction times. In the psychological literature there is evidence that implicit measures exhibit predictive validity that exceeds that of explicit measures (Greenwald, Poehlman, Uhlmann, & Banaji, 2009), but implicit attitudes have received scant attention in parapsychology. Explicit measures. Most measures of psi-related experiences and beliefs include items on many other paranormal phenomena. For instance, the widely used Revised Paranormal Belief Scale (RPBS; Tobacyk, 2004; Tobacyk & Milford, 1983) includes the following subscales; Traditional Religious Beliefs, Belief in Psi, Superstition, Belief in Witchcraft, Extraordinary Life Forms, Spiritualism, and Precognition. The commonly used global Paranormal Belief Scale has shown satisfactory reliability but its dimensionality remains uncertain (Irwin, 2009). Lange, Irwin, and Houran (2000) proposed a two-factor solution based on Rasch scaling: New Age Philosophy (11 items mainly measuring beliefs in psi and survival of bodily death) and Traditional Paranormal Beliefs (5 items mainly measuring beliefs in witchcraft, devil, heaven and hell). The advantages of these scales are that they have shown unidimensionality, predictive validity, and minimal item response biases related to age and gender differences. A recent alternative to the RPBS as a global measure is the Survey of Scientifically Unaccepted Beliefs (SSUB; Irwin & Marks, 2013). The authors argued that this measure is an improvement over previous ones as it includes a substantial number of negatively-worded items, has negligible item response biases while retaining a broad sample of paranormal items, and satisfies criteria for being an interval measure, a high level of measurement. The factor structure is similar to, and converges with, the two-factor solution proposed for the RPBS, namely New Age Beliefs (15 items) and Traditional Religious Beliefs (5 items). Reliability estimates are high for both scales. For researchers interested in a narrower measure of beliefs in psi phenomena, the Australian Sheep-Goat Scale (ASGS; Thalbourne, 1995; Thalbourne & Delin, 1993) is one of the most popular alternatives. It features 16 items on beliefs in ESP and PK and 2 items on beliefs in survival of bodily death; the latter are sometimes excluded from the overall score (e.g., Lange & Thalbourne, 2002). Lange and Thalbourne showed that the scale has minimal age and gender biases and they recommended recoding the responses of the commonly used visual analog scale to 0, 1, and 2 to satisfy the assumptions of an interval level of measurement. Irwin and colleagues developed a new questionnaire that distinguishes between psi beliefs and experiences, the Survey of Anomalous Experiences (SAE; Irwin, Dagnall, & Drinkwater, 2013). The vast majority of the 20 items address experiences related to psi or survival of bodily death, but there are a few items on astrology and aura perception. Each item asks whether the respondents have had a certain anomalous experience (e.g., sense of being stared at) and, if so, whether they attribute it to paranormal events or not, with two scales: Proneness to Anomalous Experiences and Proneness to Paranormal Attribution. Irwin, Schofield, and Baker (2014) found that dissociative tendencies, sensory-processing sensitivity (low perceptual thresholds for both internal and external stimuli), and aberrant salience (interpreting as salient even subtle stimuli) correlated with both anomalous experiences and paranormal attributions. A strength of the questionnaire is that because it distinguishes between anomalous experiences and paranormal attributions, it allows non-believers (or skeptics) to acknowledge having had anomalous experiences without having to label them paranormal. A potential issue is that when asked to choose between the paranormal or normal explanation, the phrasing for the former option is that “it must have been” a paranormal event whereas the phrasing for the latter is “it was probably just” a normal event. A person who believes that the paranormal explanation is the most probable, but is not 100 percent certain may therefore choose the “normal” explanation. For additional measures of paranormal phenomena, see Irwin (2009) and Goulding and Parker (2001). Implicit measures. In the Implicit Attitudes Test (IAT; Greenwald, McGhee, & Schwartz, 1998) participants indicate as fast as they can whether a stimulus belong to a certain category (e.g., white or black face, positive or negative word). By combining categories it is purported to test how strongly different categories are implicitly associated. There are some versions adapted to measure paranormal attitudes (Irwin, 2014; Stieger & Hergovich, 2013; Weeks, Weeks, & Daniel, 2008). For instance, Irwin paired the category of paranormal (e.g., TELEPATHY) with synonyms for accept (e.g., ENDORSE) or reject (e.g., CONDEMN). Generally, these implicit measures have shown nonsignificant correlations with explicit measures, but have shown some other promising results. Stieger and Hergovich (2013) found a significant interaction between implicit and explicit beliefs on the criterion measure of knowledge of paranormal phenomena. Explicit New Age Belief, including psi, accounted for 4 percent of the variance in knowledge test scores, whereas the interaction between explicit and implicit accounted for an additional 6 percent of the scores, demonstrating the potential value of combining explicit and implicit measures. There are some conceptual problems with the IAT paradigm, though. One is that the reaction time measure may depend on individual differences in executive attention because participants are asked to quickly alternate between different stimulus–response schemes (e.g., using the same response keys for coding faces and words). Indeed, a study found that participants who performed well on tasks measuring task-switching and workingmemory showed smaller IAT effects than those exhibiting low scores on the executive tasks (Klauer, Schmitz, Teige-Mocigemba, & Voss, 2010). As executive attention decreases with age, it is plausible that individuals with equal implicit beliefs in paranormal phenomena will score differently on the IAT versions of implicit paranormal attitudes because of their age or executive attentional abilities. Although the implicit measures are an intriguing addition to the explicit self-report measures, further work is needed to understand their psychometric properties. It would be interesting to examine if implicit psi belief contributes significantly as a predictor in a regression model with explicit psi belief as another predictor and psi task performance as the dependent variable. Insofar as psi phenomena are valid, occur at an unconscious level, and serve unconscious motivations [see chapters 8, 16 and 17, this volume], it would be instructive to examine unconscious attitudes to psi phenomena in the context of psi testing (see also the discussion on fear of psi, Carpenter, 2012; Tart, 1984). Cognitive Correlates of Psi-Related Experiences and Beliefs Many studies on cognitive correlates of psi beliefs, or more generally paranormal beliefs, have been conducted on the assumption that psi phenomena do not exist and that attributing experiences to them reflect some kind of cognitive deficit. However, recent reviews (Irwin, 2009; Wiseman & Watt, 2006; Watt & Tierney, 2014) have concluded that research on associations between paranormal beliefs and measures of intelligence, academic performance, and critical thinking, among other cognitive variables, have yielded inconsistent results, failing to provide clear support for the cognitive deficit hypothesis. We will focus here on specific thinking styles or strategies that may be differentially used among people varying in paranormal beliefs. Processing Styles and Psi Beliefs Given the large proportion of psi experiences that take the form of intuitive impressions and are often reported with a high degree of conviction [see chapters 5 and 27, this volume], it is plausible that individual differences in trusting one’s intuitive impressions relate to belief in psi. Epstein and colleagues distinguished between two processing styles: the rational style, which is “conscious, relatively slow, analytical, primarily verbal, and relatively affect-free,” and the experiential-intuitive style, which is “preconscious, rapid, automatic, holistic, primarily nonverbal, intimately associated with affect” (Pacini & Epstein, 1999, p. 972; see also Epstein, Pacini, Denes-Raj, & Heier, 1996; Kahneman, 2011). They developed a measure known as the Rational-Experiential Inventory (REI) to examine individual differences in the prevalence of these thinking styles. The recent version of the REI (Pacini & Epstein, 1999) has two subscales for each processing style: Preference for Engagement, and Ability. For instance, one might prefer solving complex problems over simple problems without necessarily being particularly good at the former. Previous versions of the REI (e.g., Epstein et al., 1996) do not make this distinction, and they include more ability items for the experiential-intuitive (faith in intuition) processing style and more preference items for the rational (need for cognition) processing style. Aarnio and Lindeman (2005) found a moderate positive correlation between paranormal belief and experiential-intuitive processing, and a weak negative correlation with rational thinking. Genovese (2005) found that paranormal beliefs correlated with experiential-intuitive thinking, but not with the rational one. Wolfradt et al. (1999) administered a modified version of the Anomalous Experiences Inventory (Gallagher, Kumar, & Pekala, 1994) to a college sample and found that experiential-intuitive processing correlated weakly to moderately with anomalous beliefs, selfperceived abilities, and anomalous experiences. Surprisingly, anomalous beliefs and abilities correlated positively, albeit weakly, with a rational processing style, whereas anomalous experiences did not. They also found significant evidence that participants scoring high on both thinking styles were more likely to score high on anomalous beliefs, experiences, and abilities. Irwin and Wilson (2013) used the recent SAE and a version of the REI in which items on preference but not ability for the processing styles were included. The experiential-intuitive processing style correlated positively with both anomalous experiences and paranormal belief, whereas the latter two did not correlate with the rational processing style. Similar results were obtained in a study (Irwin & Marks, 2013) in which the SSUB was used. They found that the scale New Age Beliefs correlated positively with preference for experiential-intuitive, but not with rational, processing style. Beliefs in traditional religious phenomena did not correlate with preference for either processing style. Although the aforementioned studies examined psi beliefs and intuition processing style, it is worth mentioning that Houran and Lange (2013) found a marginally significant correlation between actual performance in a forced-choice psi test and a trait measure of business intuition in a sample of hospitality executives. Cumulatively, these studies support the notion that individuals who have a preference for the experiential-intuitive processing style tend to have anomalous experiences (see earlier sections) and attribute them to paranormal phenomena. It seems that preference for rational processing style is less clearly related to psi-related experiences and beliefs, with studies finding both weak positive and negative associations. The studies that have focused on the preference-subscale of the recent REI for rational processing have not found a relation with psi-related experiences or beliefs (Irwin & Marks, 2013; Irwin & Wilson, 2013), but investigations on the ability subscale together with behavioral tests of intuitive and rational processing would be a welcomed contribution to this literature. Signal Detection and Psi Beliefs A common psi experience is the sense of being stared at, which may make the person turn around and sometimes find that someone is indeed staring [see chapters 18 and 27, this volume]. This could be framed as a particular case of signal detection, in which a starer could be detected (hit) or in the case of a no-starer incorrectly identified (false alarm). Van Elk (2013) argued that on the basis of evolution humans may be especially geared at detecting the presence of others, because in scenarios in which a predator animal is hiding in the surroundings it would help survival to detect the threat but not cost as much to incorrectly perceive an agent when there is none [see chapters 7 and 11, this volume]. In some contexts it seems that humans indeed have a tendency to detect agents in the surroundings such as the 40 percent false-alarm rate reported in a study on detection of faces in random noise (Rieth, Lee, Lui, Tian, & Huber, 2011). Whether paranormal believers differ in their signal detection behaviors from skeptics has been put to test. One of the studies administered a task that consisted of photographs, shown for 1s, that depicted an artificial face or no-face (Riekki, Lindeman, Aleneff, Halme, & Nuortimo, 2013). Participants responded to whether they saw an artificial face or not, and if they claimed to see a face they had to indicate its location. As the authors expected, paranormal believers committed significantly more false alarms than skeptics, but believers also made significantly more hits by detecting the presence and location of the artificial face. The groups did not significantly differ in their overall performance or sensitivity. Thus, rather than one group being generally better than the other at signal detection, it seemed that believers were prone to making Type I errors (false alarms) and skeptics Type II errors (misses). Other studies have found similar preferences in the two groups (Blackmore & Moore, 1994; Krummenacher, Mohr, Haker, & Brugger, 2010), with psi believers having significantly lower response thresholds for responding “yes” to a trial compared to skeptics. A third study (Van Elk, 2013) also found lower response criterion in paranormal believers compared to skeptics in a sample of students and paranormal fair visitors, but unlike the other studies they found significantly better overall performance in skeptics than believers. In sum, the results of these studies indicates that psi believers and skeptics use different response criteria in signal detection tasks with believers tending to make more false alarms and skeptics more misses. It would be instructive to manipulate the cost of making a false alarm error or a miss to investigate whether the two groups adapt their strategies accordingly. Need for Control and Psi Beliefs An important function that psi experiences or beliefs may serve, whether accurate or not, is that they may provide a greater sense of control of external events, as information may be obtained through psi. Similarly, a belief in expressive psi experiences (psychokinesis, anomalous perturbation or force) could provide the individual with a greater sense of influence over events that would not be possible to influence by normal means. Irwin (2009) hypothesized that childhood experiences of low control leads to a greater need to feel control over external circumstances, and that paranormal beliefs may increase the sense of control. For instance, the ability to read people’s minds could help evade potential dangers. Greenaway, Louis, and Hornsey (2013) investigated whether changes in sense of control varied with changes in belief in precognition. In Experiment 1, induction of low control was related to higher precognition belief. In Experiment 2, participants reading a pro-precognition abstract subsequently reported higher perceived control over their life than participants reading a skeptical reply (perceived control was measured by three items with high reliability, e.g., “I am in control of my life”). In Experiment 3 they found that for participants who were asked to write about low control, those reading a pro-precognition abstract reported higher perceived control (expanded to five items) than those reading a skeptical abstract and a third group reading an unrelated abstract. Greenaway et al. concluded that when people are in a state in which they feel low control belief in precognition increases perceived control. Given that the precognition manipulation was immediately followed by the items on perceived control but no other control items—and it surprises us that a laboratory manipulation of reading an article abstract would substantially change individuals’ perceived control of their own lives—future work may benefit from examining potential demand characteristics of this approach and using previously validated measures of perceived control. Watt, Watson, and Wilson (2007) investigated retrospectively whether adults who believe in paranormal phenomena perceived that they had high or low control in childhood (e.g., “my parents tried to control everything I did”). There was a weak negative correlation between perceived childhood control and paranormal belief, but only the Traditional Religious Beliefs subscale was independently significant, whereas the New Age Philosophy scale was not. Another correlate of psi beliefs is whether individuals perceive that they typically can control events that occur to them (internal locus of control) or not (external locus of control). Irwin (2009) has reviewed this research and concluded that global paranormal beliefs, as well as psi-beliefs in particular, correlate positively with an external locus of control. Another measure of interest is tolerance of ambiguity. Individuals with high tolerance tend to find ambiguous events more desirable compared to those with low tolerance. Houran and collaborators found that those with high tolerance reported more paranormal experiences and beliefs (e.g., Houran & Lange, 1998). Similarly, a later study on precognition (Watt, 2014) did not support the hypothesis that being intolerant to ambiguity would predict correspondences between participants’ dreams and the later-viewed psi targets. In sum, findings suggest that psi beliefs are activated under induced or experienced conditions of low control. Longitudinal research would contribute greatly by assessing how this relation develops over time. Conclusions Our review of the literature does not reveal one or more psychological variables that can be used to consistently and strongly predict performance in psi tests, yet there is some regularity to the findings of various areas of research. With regard to traits, it seems advantageous to have participants who are generally more experientially-oriented, open to experience, creative, and perhaps at least extraverted enough to feel comfortable in some research situations. As for alterations in consciousness, despite promising historical precedents, parapsychology in general has been lax in actually evaluating them rather than assuming that they are present just because a procedure like ganzfeld or hypnosis was used. When actual measurements have been taken, an overall pattern of being in an altered state (including specific alterations such as those in the sense of time) has related to psi performance, whereas a rational, controlling stance seems to be counterproductive. This is an area in which far more investigation, including neurophenomenological projects tying brain dynamics to specific experiences, is called for. With respect to cognitive characteristics, there is some consistency in that belief in personal success in psi tasks does slightly increase the likelihood of doing well in them, but we need multivariate designs to find out if interactions between that and other variables can increase the small size effect explained by single variables. Research has shown that believers in psi overall do not exhibit cognitive deficits, and if they have a tendency to report false positives, this may be counterbalanced by a seeming tendency of anti-psi believers to report false negatives. Future studies may want to investigate under what circumstances one strategy is more advantageous, than the other, and include implicit measures in their designs. There are enough promising leads in our review to keep researchers busy for many years. References Aarnio, K., and Lindeman, M. (2005). Paranormal beliefs, education, and thinking styles. Personality and Individual Differences, 39, 1227–1236. Abuhamdeh, S., and Csikszentmihalyi, M. (2004). The artistic personality: A systems perspective. In R. J. Sternberg, E. L. Grigorenko, and J. L. Singer (Eds.), Creativity: From potential to realization (pp. 31–42). Washington, D.C.: American Psychological Association. Alexander, C. H., and Broughton, R. S. (2001). Cerebral hemisphere dominance and ESP performance in the autoganzfeld. Journal of Parapsychology, 65, 397–416. Alvarado, C. S. (1998). ESP and altered states of consciousness: An overview of conceptual and research trends. Journal of Parapsychology, 62, 27–63. Alvarado, C. S. (2014). Mediumship, psychical research, dissociation, and the powers of the subconscious mind. Journal of Parapsychology, 78, 98– 114. Barber, T. X. (1984). Changing “unchangeable” bodily processes by (hypnotic) suggestions. In A. A. Sheikh (Ed.), Imagination and healing (pp. 69–127). Farmingdale, NY: Baywood. Blackmore, S. (1987). A report of a visit to Carl Sargent’s laboratory. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 54, 186–198. Blackmore, S. J., and Moore, R. (1994). Seeing things: Visual recognition and belief in the paranormal. European Journal of Parapsychology, 10, 91– 103. Bower, K. S. (1973). Situationism in psychology: An analysis and a critique. Psychological Review, 80, 307–336. Braud, W. G. (1978). Psi conducive conditions: Explorations and interpretations. In B. Shapin and L. Coly (Eds.), Psi and states of awareness (pp. 1–41). New York: Parapsychology Foundation. Broughton, R. S. (2004). Exploring the reliability of the “presentiment” effect. Proceedings of Presented Papers for the Parapsychological Association 2004 Annual Convention (pp. 15–26). Broughton, R. S., and Alexander, C. H. (1997). Autoganzfeld II: An attempted replication of the PRL ganzfeld research. Journal of Parapsychology, 61, 224–226. Brugger, P., and Baumann, A. T. (1994). Repetition avoidance in responses to imaginary questions: The effect of respondents’ belief in ESP. Psychological Reports, 75, 883–893. Bunge, M. (1980). The mind–body problem: A psychobiological approach. New York: Pergamon. Cardeña, E. (2005). The phenomenology of deep hypnosis: Quiescent and physically active. International Journal of Clinical & Experimental Hypnosis, 53, 37–59. Cardeña, E. (2009). Beyond Plato? Toward a science of alterations of consciousness. In C. A. Roe, W. Kramer, and L. Coly (Eds.), Utrecht II: Charting the future of parapsychology (pp. 305–322). New York: Parapsychology Foundation. Cardeña, E. (2014). Hypnos and psyche, or how hypnosis has contributed to the study of consciousness. Psychology of Consciousness: Theory, Research, and Practice, 1, 123–138. Cardeña, E., and Carlson, E. (2011). Acute stress disorder revisited. Annual Review of Clinical Psychology, 7, 245–267. Cardeña, E., Iribas, A., and Reijman, S. (2012). Art and psi. Journal of Parapsychology, 76, 3–25. Cardeña, E., Krippner, S., and Lynn, S. J. (2014). Anomalous experiences: An integrative summary. In E. Cardeña, S. J. Lynn, and S. Krippner (Eds.), Varieties of anomalous experience: Examining the scientific evidence (2nd ed.) (pp. 409–426). Washington, D.C.: American Psychological Association. Cardeña, E., Marcusson-Clavertz, D., and Wasmuth, J. (2009). Hypnotizability and dissociation as predictors of performance in a precognition task: A pilot study. Journal of Parapsychology, 73, 137–158. Cardeña, E., and Pekala, R. J. (2014). Methodological issues in the study of altering consciousness and anomalous experience. In E. Cardeña, S. J. Lynn, and S. Krippner (Eds.), Varieties of anomalous experience: Examining the scientific evidence (2nd ed.) (pp. 21–56). Washington, D.C.: American Psychological Association. Cardeña, E., Reijman, S., Wimmelmann, C. L., and Jensen, C. G. (2015). Psychological characteristics of Danish practitioners of clairvoyance and other spiritual activities. Psychology of Consciousness: Theory, Research, and Practice 2, 170–184. Cardeña, E., and Spiegel, D. (1993). Dissociative reactions to the Bay Area Earthquake. American Journal of Psychiatry, 150, 474–478. Cardeña, E. and Terhune, D. B. (2014). Hypnotizability, personality traits, and the propensity to experience alterations of consciousness. Psychology of Consciousness: Theory, Research, and Practice, 1, 292–307. Cardeña, E., and Winkelman, M. (2011a). Altering consciousness. Multidisciplinary perspectives. Volume I. History, culture, and the humanities. Santa Barbara, CA: Praeger. Cardeña, E., and Winkelman, M. (2011b). Altering consciousness. Multidisciplinary perspectives. Volume II: Biological and psychological perspectives. Santa Barbara, CA: Praeger. Carpenter, J. C. (1991). Prediction of forced-choice ESP performance. Part III: Three attempts to retrieve code information using mood reports and a repeated-guessing technique. Journal of Parapsychology, 55, 227–280. Carpenter, J. C. (2004). Implicit measures of participants’ experiences in the ganzfeld: Confirmation of previous relationships in a new sample. Proceedings of Presented Papers: The Parapsychological Association 47th Annual Convention (pp. 1–11). Carpenter, J. C. (2012). First sight: ESP and parapsychology in everyday life. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield. Costa, P. T., and McCrae, R. R. (1985). The NEO personality inventory manual. Odessa, FL: Psychological Assessment Resources. Crabtree, A. (1988). Animal magnetism, early hypnotism, and psychical research 1766–1925: An annotated bibliography. New York: Kraus International Publications. Dalenberg, C. J., Brand, B. L., Gleaves, D. H., Dorahy, M. J., Loewenstein, R. J., Cardeña, E., … Spiegel, D. (2012). Evaluation of the evidence for the trauma and fantasy models of dissociation. Psychological Bulletin, 138, 550–588. da Silva, F. E., Pilato, S., and Hiraoka, R. (2003). Ganzfeld vs. no Ganzfeld: An exploratory study of the effects of ganzfeld conditions on ESP. Proceedings of Presented Papers: The Parapsychological Association 46th Annual Convention (pp. 31–49). Del Prete, G., and Tressoldi, P. E. (2005). Anomalous cognition in hypnagogic state with OBE induction: An experimental study. Journal of Parapsychology, 69, 329–339. d’Espagnat, B. (2006). On physics and philosophy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Dingwall, E. J. (Ed.) (1967–1968). Abnormal hypnotic phenomena: A survey of nineteenth century cases (4 vols.). London, UK: J. & A. Churchill. Epstein, S., Pacini, R., Denes-Raj, V., and Heier, H. (1996). Individual differences in intuitive-experiential and analytical-rational thinking styles. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 71, 390–405. Eysenck, H. (1967). Personality and extrasensory perception. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 44, 55–71. Ferenczi, S. (1955). Final contributions to the problems & methods of psycho-analysis. (M. Balint, Ed.). London, UK: The Hogarth Press. Foulkes, D., and Vogel, G. (1965). Mental activity at sleep onset. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 70, 231–243. Gauld, A. (1982). Mediumship and survival. London, UK: Heinemann. Gallagher, C., Kumar, V. K., and Pekala, R. J. (1994). The Anomalous Experiences Inventory: Reliability and validity. Journal of Parapsychology, 58, 402–428. Genovese, J. E. C. (2005). Paranormal beliefs, schizotypy, and thinking styles among teachers and future teachers. Personality and Individual Differences, 39, 93–102. Goulding, A. (2005). Participant variables associated with psi Ganzfeld results. European Journal of Parapsychology, 20, 50–64. Goulding, A., and Parker, A. (2001). Finding psi in the paranormal: Psychometric measures used in research in paranormal beliefs/experiences and in research on psi-ability. European Journal of Parapsychology, 16, 73– 101. Gow, K. M., Hutchinson, L., and Chant, D. (2009). Correlations between fantasy proneness, dissociation, personality factors and paranormal belief in experiencers of paranormal and anomalous phenomena. Australian Journal of Clinical & Experimental Hypnosis, 37, 169–191. Greenaway, K. H., Louis, W. R., and Hornsey, M. J. (2013). Loss of control increases belief in precognition and belief in precognition increases control. Plos One, 8(8), e71327. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0071327 Greenwald, A. G., McGhee, D. E., and Schwartz, J. L. (1998). Measuring individual differences in implicit cognition: The implicit association test. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 74, 1464–1480. Greenwald, A. G., Poehlman, T. A., Uhlmann, E. L., and Banaji, M. R. (2009). Understanding and using the Implicit Association Test: III. Metaanalysis of predictive validity. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 97, 17–41. Harley, T., and Matthews, G. (1987). Cheating, psi, and the appliance of science: A reply to Blackmore. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 54, 199–207. Hesse, E., and Main, M. (2000). Disorganized infant, child, and adult attachment: Collapse in behavioral and attentional strategies. Journal of American Psychoanalytic Association, 48, 1097–1127. Hilgard, E. R., and Tart, C. T. (1966). Responsiveness to suggestions following waking and imagination instructions and following induction of hypnosis. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 71, 196–208. Hinterberger, T. (2014). I am I from moment to moment: Methods and results of grasping intersubjective and intertemporal neurophysiological differences during meditation states. In S. Schmidt and H. Wallach (Eds.), Meditation—Neuroscientific approaches and philosophical implications (pp. 95–113). Cham, Switzerland: Springer. Hitchman, G. A. M., Roe, C. A., and Sherwood, S. J. (2012). A reexamination of nonintentional precognition with openness to experience, creativity, psi beliefs, and luck beliefs as predictors of success. Journal of Parapsychology, 76, 109–145. Hoffman, D. (2008). Conscious realism and the mind–body problem. Mind & Matter, 6, 87–121. Holt, N. J. (2007). Are artistic populations psi-conducive? Testing the relationship between creativity and psi with an experience-sampling protocol. Proceedings of Presented Papers: The Parapsychological Association 50th Annual Convention (pp. 31–47). Holt, N. J., Delanoy, D. L., and Roe, C. A. (2004). Creativity, subjective paranormal experiences and altered states of consciousness. Proceedings of Presented Papers: The Parapsychological Association 47th Annual Convention (pp. 433–436). Honorton, C. (1977). Psi and internal attentional states. In B. B. Wolman (Ed.), Handbook of parapsychology (pp. 435–472). Jefferson, NC: McFarland. Honorton, C. (1997). The ganzfeld novice: Four predictors of initial ESP performance. Journal of Parapsychology, 61, 143–158. Honorton, C., Ferrari, D. G., and Bem, D. J. (1998). Extraversion and ESP performance: A meta-analysis and a new confirmation. Journal of Parapsychology, 62, 255–276. Houtkooper, J. (2003). An ESP experiment with natural and simulated sferics: Displacement scores and psychological variables. European Journal of Parapsychology, 18, 49–64. Houtkooper, J. M., Schienle, A., Stark, R., and Vaitl, D. (2001). Atmospheric electromagnetism: Attempted replication of the correlation between natural sferics and ESP. Perceptual and Motor Skills, 93, 754–756. Houran, J., and Lange, R. (1998). Modeling precognitive dreams as meaningful coincidences. Psychological Reports, 83, 1411–1414. Houran, J., and Lange, R. (2013). Applying the theory of reasoned action to a computerized test of intuition, part II: Decision-making in a hidden test of psi. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 77, 236–251. Ioannidis, J. P. A. (2005). Why most published research findings are false. PLoS Medicine 2(8). doi: 10.1371/journal.pmed.0020124 Irwin, H. J. (1994). Childhood trauma and the origins of paranormal belief: A constructive replication. Psychological Reports, 74, 107–111. Irwin, H. J. (1997). Dissociative tendencies as a marker of psychological phenomena. Constructive observations with references to Michelson and Ray’s Handbook of Dissociation. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 91, 133–141. Irwin, H. J. (2009). The psychology of paranormal belief, Hatfield, UK: University of Hertfordshire Press. Irwin, H. J. (2014). Paranormal beliefs, spoken and unspoken. Australian Journal of Parapsychology, 14, 11–27. Irwin, H. J., Dagnall, N., and Drinkwater, K. (2013). Parapsychological experience as anomalous experience plus paranormal attribution: A questionnaire based on a new approach to measurement. Journal of Parapsychology, 77, 39–53. Irwin, H. J., and Marks, A. D. G. (2013). The Survey of Scientifically Unaccepted Beliefs: A new measure of paranormal and related beliefs. Australian Journal of Parapsychology, 13, 133–167. Irwin, H. J., Schofield, M. B., and Baker, I. S. (2014). Dissociative tendencies, sensory-processing sensitivity and aberrant salience as predictors of anomalous experiences and paranormal attributions. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 78, 193–206. Irwin, H. J., and Wilson, K. (2013). Anomalous experiences and the intuitive-experiential style of thinking. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 77, 65–71. James, W. (1890). The principles of psychology. New York: Henry Holt. Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking fast and slow. New York: Farrar, Strauss, and Giroux. Kallio, S., and Revonsuo, A. (2003). Hypnotic phenomena and altered states of consciousness: A multilevel framework of description and explanation. Contemporary Hypnosis, 20, 111–164. Klauer, K. C., Schmitz, F., Teige-Mocigemba, S., and Voss, A. (2010). Understanding the role of executive control in the implicit association test: Why flexible people have small IAT effects. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 63, 595–619. Krummenacher, P., Mohr, C., Haker, H., and Brugger, P. (2010). Dopamine, paranormal belief, and the detection of meaningful stimuli. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 22, 1670–1681. Kumar, V. K., and Pekala, R. J. (1988). Hypnotizability, absorption, and individual differences in phenomenological experience. International Journal of Clinical and Experimental Hypnosis, 36, 80–88. Lakoff, G. (1973). Hedges: A study in meaning criteria and the logic of fuzzy concepts. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 2, 408–508. Lange, R., Irwin, H. J. and Houran, J. (2000). Top-down purification of Tobacyk’s Revised Paranormal Belief Scale. Personality and Individual Differences, 29, 131–156. Lange, R., and Thalbourne, M. A. (2002). Rasch scaling paranormal belief and experience: The structure and semantics of Thalbourne’s Australian Sheep-Goat Scale. Psychological Reports, 91, 1065–1073. Lawrence, T. R. (1993, August). Gathering in the sheep and goats. A metaanalysis of the forced-choice sheep-goat ESP literature, 1947–1993. Paper presented at the 36th Annual Convention of the Parapsychological Association, Toronto, Canada. Lawrence, T., Edwards, C., Barraclough, N., Church, S., and Hetherington, F. (1995). Modeling childhood causes of paranormal belief and experience: Childhood trauma and childhood fantasy. Personality and Individual Differences, 19, 209–215. Lovitts, B. E. (1981). The sheep-goat effect turned upside down. Journal of Parapsychology, 39, 289–296. Ludwig, A. M. (1966). Altered states of consciousness. Archives of General Psychiatry, 15, 225–234. Luke D. P., Delanoy, D., and Sherwood, S. J. (2008). Psi may look like luck: Perceived luckiness and beliefs about luck in relation to precognition. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 72, 193–207 Luke, D. P., Roe, C., and Davison, J. (2008). Testing for forced-choice precognition using a hidden task: Two replications. Journal of Parapsychology, 72, 133–154. Lyons-Ruth, K., Dutra, L., Schuder, M. R., and Bianchi, I. (2006). From infant attachment disorganization to adult dissociation: Relational adaptations or traumatic experiences? Psychiatric Clinics of North America, 29, 63–86. Main, M., Van IJzendoorn, M., and Hesse, E. (1993). Unresolved/unclassifiable responses to the Adult Attachment Interview: Predictable from unresolved states and anomalous beliefs in the Berkeley– Leiden Adult Attachment Questionnaire. Presented at the 60th Anniversary Meeting of the Society for Research in Child Development, New Orleans, LA. Marcusson-Clavertz, D. and Cardeña, E. (2011). Hypnotizability, alterations in consciousness, and other variables as predictors of performance in a ganzfeld psi task. Journal of Parapsychology, 75, 235–259. May, E. C., Bányai, É., Vassy, Z., and Faith, L. V. (2005). Hypnotic susceptibility as a predictor of anomalous cognition performance. Paper presented at the 30 Simpósio da Fundação Bial: Aquém e Além do Cérebro (Behind and beyond the brain), Porto, Portugal, 417. McBain, W. N., Fox, W., Kimura, S., Nakanishi, M., and Tirado, J. (1970). Quasi-sensory communication: An investigation using semantic matching and accentuated affect. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 14, 281–291. Méheulst, B. (2013). The case of Alexis Didier. Mindfield, 4, 92–97. Milton, J., and Wiseman, R. (1999). Does psi exist? Lack of replication of an anomalous process of information transfer. Psychological Bulletin, 125, 387–391. Moss, T. (1969). ESP effects in “artists” contrasted with “non-artists.” Journal of Parapsychology, 33, 57–69. Murphy, K., and Lester, D. (1976). A search for correlates of belief in ESP. Psychological Reports, 38, 82. Pacini, R., and Epstein, S. (1999). The relation of rational and experiential information processing styles to personality, basic beliefs, and the ratio-bias phenomenon. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 76, 972–987. Palmer, J. (1971). Scoring in ESP tests as a function of belief in ESP. Part I. The sheep-goat effect. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 65, 373–408. Palmer, J. (1977). Attitudes and personality traits in experimental ESP research. In B. B. Wolman (Ed.), Handbook of parapsychology (pp. 175– 201). New York: Van Nostrand Reinhold. Palmer, J. (2011). Motor automatisms as a vehicle of ESP expression. Journal of Parapsychology, 75, 45–60. Palmer, J. (2013). Extrasensory perception, dissociation, and motor automatisms. Presented at the 2013 Parapsychological Association Annual Meeting in Viterbo, Italy. Palmer, J., and Carpenter, J. C. (1998). Comments on the extraversion–ESP meta-analysis by Honorton, Ferrari, and Bem. Journal of Parapsychology, 62, 277–282. Palmer, J., Khamashta, K., and Israelson, K. (1979). An ESP ganzfeld experiment with transcendental meditators. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 73, 333–348. Parker, A. (2000). A review of the Ganzfeld work at Gothenburg University. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 64, 1–15. Parker, A., and Beloff, J. (1970). Hypnotically-induced clairvoyant dreams: A partial replication and attempted confirmation. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 64, 432–442. Parker, A., Grams, D., and Pettersson, C. (1998). Further variables relating to psi in the Ganzfeld. Journal of Parapsychology, 62, 319–337. Parra, A., and Argibay, J. C. (2013). A free-response ESP test in two hypnotic susceptibility groups: A pilot study. Australian Journal of Parapsychology, 13, 27–35. Pekala, R. J., Kumar, V. K., and Marcano, G. (1995). Anomalous/paranormal experiences, hypnotic susceptibility, and dissociation. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 89, 313–332. Pérez Navarro, J. M., and Cox, K. (2012). Context-dependence, visibility, and prediction using state and trait individual differences as moderators of ESP in a ganzfeld environment. Europe’s Journal of Psychology, 8, 559.572. Pittenger, D. J. (1993). Measuring the MBTI … and coming up short. Journal of Career Planning and Employment, 54, 48–52. Rabeyron, T., and Watt, C. (2010). Paranormal experiences, mental health and mental boundaries, and psi. Personality and Individual Differences, 48, 487–492. Richards, D. G. (1991). A study of the correlations between subjective psychic experiences and dissociative experiences. Dissociation, 4, 83–91. Richards, D. G. (1996). Boundaries in the mind and subjective interpersonal psi. Journal of Parapsychology, 60, 227–240. Riekki, T., Lindeman, M., Aleneff, M., Halme, A., and Nuortimo, A. (2013). Paranormal and religious believers are more prone to illusory face perception than skeptics and non-believers. Applied Cognitive Psychology, 27, 150–155. Rieth, C. A., Lee, K., Lui, J., Tian, J., and Huber, D. E. (2011). Faces in the mist: Illusory face and letter detection. Perception, 2, 458–476. Roberts, B. W., Donnellan, M. B., and Hill, P. L. (2013). Personality trait development in adulthood. In H. Tennon and J. Suls (Eds.), Handbook of psychology. Volume 5: Personality and social psychology (pp. 183–196). New York: Wiley. Rock, A. J., Storm, L., Harris, K., and Friedman, H. L. (2013). Shamaniclike journeying and psi signal detection: II. Phenomenological dimensions. Journal of Parapsychology, 77, 249–270. Roe, C.A., Davey, R., and Stevens, P. (2005). Are ESP and PK aspects of a unitary phenomenon? The effects of deception when testing the relationship between ESP and PK. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 69, 18–32. Roe, C. A., Henderson, S. J., and and Matthews, J. (2008). Extraversion and performance at a forced-choice ESP task with verbal stimuli: Two studies. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 72, 208–221. Roe, C.A., Hodrien, A., and Kirkwood, L. (2012). Comparing remote viewing and ganzfeld conditions in a precognition task. Abstracts of Presented Papers: Parapsychological Association 55th Annual (pp. 36–38). Roe, C. A., Holt, N., and Simmonds, C. A. (2003). Considering the sender as a PK agent in ganzfeld ESP studies. Journal of Parapsychology, 67, 129– 145. Roe, C. A., McKenzie, E. A., and Ali, A. N. (2001). Sender and receiver creativity scores as predictors of performance at a ganzfeld ESP task. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 65, 107–121. Rosenthal, R. (1979). The file drawer problem and tolerance for null results. Psychological Bulletin, 86, 638–641. Sagi, A., van IJzendoorn, M. H., Joels, T., and Scharf, M. (2002). Disorganized reasoning in Holocaust survivors. American Journal of Orthopsychiatry, 72, 194–203. Sargent, C. L. (1980). Exploring psi in the ganzfeld. New York: Parapsychology Foundation. Schechter, E. I. (1984). Hypnotic induction vs. control conditions: Illustrating an approach to the evaluation of replicability in parapsychological data. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 78, 1–27. Schlitz, M. J., and Honorton, C. (1992). Ganzfeld psi performance within an artistically gifted population. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 86, 83–98. Schlitz, M., Wiseman, R., Watt, C., and Radin, D. (2006). Of two minds: Sceptic–proponent collaboration within parapsychology. British Journal of Psychology, 97, 313–322. Schmeidler, G. R. (1943). Predicting good and bad scores in a clairvoyance experiment: A preliminary report. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 37, 103–110. Schmeidler, G. R. (1952). Personal values and ESP scores. Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, 47, 757–761. Schönwetter, T., Ambach, W., and Vaitl, D. (2011). Does autonomic nervous system activity correlate with events conventionally considered as unperceivable? Using a guessing task with physiological measurement. Journal of Parapsychology, 75, 327–348. Siegel, R. K., and Jarvick, M. E. (1975). Drug induced hallucinations in animals and man. In R. K. Siegel and L. J. West (Eds.), Hallucinations: Behavior, experience and theory (pp. 81–162). New York: Wiley. Silverman, I. (1974). The experimenter: A (still) neglected stimulus object. The Canadian Psychologist/Psychologie Canadienne, 15, 258–270. Smith, M. D., Wiseman, R., Machin, D., Harris, P., and Joiner, R. (1997). Luckiness, competition, and performance on a psi task. Journal of Parapsychology, 61, 40–42. Sondow, N. (1986). Exploring hypnotizability, creativity, and psi. Conscious and unconscious components to psi success in the ganzfeld. Proceedings of Presented Papers: The Parapsychological Association 29th Annual Convention (pp. 367–381). Sorge, R. E., Martin, L. J., Isbester, K. A., Sotocinal, S. G., Rosen, S., Tuttle, A. H., … Mogil, J. S. (2014). Olfactory exposure to males, including men, causes stress and related analgesia in rodents. Nature Methods, 11, 629–632. Spiegel, D., and Cardeña, E. (1991). Disintegrated experience: The dissociative disorders revisited. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 100, 366– 378. Stanford, R. G., and Stein, A. G. (1994). A metaanalysis of ESP studies contrasting hypnosis and a comparison condition. Journal of Parapsychology, 58, 235–269. Stieger, S., and Hergovich, A. (2013). Together we are strong: Explicit and implicit paranormal beliefs predict performance in a knowledge test of paranormal phenomena better than explicit beliefs alone. Personality and Individual Differences, 54, 562–565. Storm, L., and Thalbourne, M. A. (1998–1999). The transliminal connection between paranormal effects and personality in an experiment with the I Ching. European Journal of Parapsychology, 14, 100–124. Storm, L., and Thalbourne, M. A. (2001). Studies of the I Ching: I. A replication. Journal of Parapsychology, 65, 105–123. Storm, L., Tressoldi, P. E., and Di Risio, L. (2010). Meta-analysis of freeresponse studies, 1992–2008: Assessing the noise reduction model in parapsychology. Psychological Bulletin, 136, 471–485. Targ, R., Puthoff, H. G., Humphrey, B. S., and May, E. C. (1980). Special orientation techniques (U). Report, SRI International. Tart, C. T. (1975). States of consciousness. New York: Dutton. Tart, C. T. (1984). Acknowledging and dealing with the fear of psi. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 78, 133–143. Thalbourne, M. A. (1995). Further studies of the measurement and correlates of belief in the paranormal. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 89, 233–247. Thalbourne, M. A., and Delin, P. S. (1993). A new instrument for measuring the sheep-goat variable: Its psychometric properties and factor structure. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 59, 172–186. Thalbourne, M. A., and Maltby, J. (2008). Transliminality, thin boundaries, unusual experiences, and temporal lability. Personality and Individual Differences, 44, 1617–1623. Thomson, P., and Jaque, S. V. (2014). Unresolved mourning, supernatural beliefs and dissociation: A mediation analysis. Attachment and Human Development, 10, 1–16. Tobacyk, J. (2004). A Revised Paranormal Belief Scale. International Journal of Transpersonal Studies, 23, 94–98. Tobacyk, J., and Milford, G. (1983). Belief in paranormal phenomena: Assessment instrument development and implications for personality functioning. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 44, 1029–1037. Tressoldi, P. and Del Prete, G. (2007). ESP under hypnosis: The role of induction instructions and personality characteristics. Journal of Parapsychology, 71, 125–137. Van de Castle, R. L. (1969). The facilitation of ESP through hypnosis. American Journal of Clinical Hypnosis, 12, 37–56. Van de Castle, R. (1993). Psi manifestations in multiple personality disorder. In L. Coly and J. D. S. McMahon (Eds.), Psi and clinical practice (pp. 84–114). New York: Parapsychology Foundation. Van Elk, M. (2013). Paranormal believers are more prone to illusory agency detection than skeptics. Consciousness and Cognition, 22, 1041–1046. Van Kampen, D., Bierman, D. J. and Wezelman, R. (1994). Personality and psi: Unravelling relations between extraversion, agreeableness, and openness to experience with ganzfeld performance. In D. J. Bierman (Ed.), Proceedings of the 37th PA Convention (pp. 175–181). Varga, K., Józsa, E., and Kekecs, Z. (2014). Comparative analysis of phenomenological patterns of hypnotists and subjects: An interactional perspective. Psychology of Consciousness: Theory, Research, and Practice, 1, 308–319. Vasiliev, L. L. (2002). Experiments in mental suggestion. Charlottesville, VA: Hampton Roads. (Originally published 1962). Velmans, M. (2009). How to define consciousness—and how not to define it. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 16, 139–156. Watt, C. (2014). Precognitive dreaming: Investigating anomalous cognition and psychological factors. Journal of Parapsychology, 78, 115–125. Watt, C., and Baker, I. S. (2002). Remote facilitation of attention focusing with psi-supportive versus psi-unsupportive experimenter suggestions. Journal of Parapsychology, 66, 151–168. Watt, C., and Brady, C. (2002). Experimenter effects and the remote facilitation of attention focusing: Two studies and the discovery of an artifact. Journal of Parapsychology, 66, 49–71. Watt, C, and Ramakers, P. (2003). Experimenter effects with a remote facilitation of attention focusing task: A study with multiple believer and disbeliever experimenters. Journal of Parapsychology, 67, 99–116. Watt, C., and Tierney, I. R. (2014). Psi-related experiences. In E. Cardeña, S. J. Lynn, and S. Krippner (Eds.) (2014). Varieties of anomalous experience: Examining the scientific evidence (2nd ed.) (pp. 241–272). Washington, D.C.: American Psychological Association. Watt, C., Watson, S., and Wilson, L. (2007). Cognitive and psychological mediators of anxiety: Evidence from a study of paranormal belief and perceived childhood control. Personality and Individual Differences, 42, 335–343. Weeks, M., Weeks, K. P., and Daniel, M. R. (2008). The implicit relationship between religious and paranormal constructs. Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion, 47, 599–611. Wickramasekera, I. (1993). Is hypnotic ability a risk factor for subjective (verbal report) psi, somatization, and health care costs? In L. Coly and J. D. S. McMahon (Eds.), Psi and clinical practice (pp. 184–197). New York: Parapsychology Foundation. Windt, J. (2011). Altered consciousness in philosophy. In E. Cardeña and M. Winkelman (Eds.), Altering consciousness. Multidisciplinary perspectives. Volume I. History, culture, and the humanities (pp. 229–254). Santa Barbara, CA: Praeger. Wiseman, R., and Watt, C. (2006). Belief in psychic ability and the misattribution hypothesis: A qualitative review. British Journal of Psychology, 97, 323–338. Wolfradt, U., Oubaid, V., Straube, E. R., Bischoff, N., and Mischo, J. (1999). Thinking styles, schizotypal traits and anomalous experiences. Personality and Individual Differences, 27, 821–830. Wolman, B. B. (Ed.). (1977). Handbook of parapsychology. Orig. pub. Van Nostrand Reinhold; repr. 1986, Jefferson, NC: McFarland. OceanofPDF.com CHAPTER 10 Ariadne’s Thread Meditation and Psi SERENA M. RONEY-DOUGAL History: In the Beginning The study of altered states of consciousness has been one of the central topics in parapsychology for the past 40 years. In the 1970s, Braud (1974, 1975, 1978) introduced the concept of the psi-conducive state. This model has driven much of the parapsychological research into altered states of consciousness and considers that psi functioning is enhanced when there is (1) cortical arousal sufficient to maintain conscious awareness, (2) muscular relaxation, (3) reduction of sensory input, and (4) internal attention. In other words, psi is enhanced when the receiver is in a state of sensory relaxation and is minimally influenced by ordinary perception. Just prior to this theoretical development, White (1964) had initiated a change in methodology from the forced-choice card guessing technique, introduced in the 1930s, to the free-response method. Some of the many states of consciousness explored were the effects of relaxation, dreaming, the hypnagogic state, hypnosis, and meditation, and with this development the free-response method thrived. In free-response sessions participants are asked to draw and/or verbally describe the target during their session. The target can be a picture, a video clip, or even a place being visited by another person. At the end of the session participants may have to decide for themselves from a pool of possible targets which was the target for that session, as in ganzfeld research, or the person may see only the target itself while another person has to independently try to correctly choose the target from the pool of possible targets, as in the remote viewing protocol. This can then be analyzed statistically, thus providing both quantitative and qualitative data [see chapter 15, this volume]. There are many different meditation techniques, but essentially meditation can be divided into two main types: concentration, or one-pointed awareness (known in Sanskrit as shamatta or dharana, and in Tibetan as shinay), and bare awareness (known in Sanskrit as vipassana or dhyana, and in Tibetan as lahtong), in which one is merely aware of whatever occurs, though in preliminary stages this can be combined with awareness of something, like the body, breath, or mind. Typically, one learns shamatta techniques first and the resultant calming of the mind enables the vipassana practices. Breath awareness is a classic yogic and Buddhist meditation practice. Transcendental meditation (TM) is a concentration meditation technique in which one chants a particular sound, or mantra. Mantra meditation, often combined with visualization, is used extensively in both yogic and Tibetan Buddhist traditions. Mindfulness is one of the methods used in shamatta practice to enable one to hold the focus by being vigilant to the wandering of the mind and bringing it back to awareness of the practice (Lamrimpa, 1995), which may be watching the mind itself, as in mahamudra or dzogchen. Early Research During the 1970s–1980s, several experiments suggested that meditation might help attain a state of consciousness conducive to psi awareness. Psi awareness is a useful term when describing free-response studies because in them the participants are asked to describe their impressions of the target prior to viewing it. Thus it is possible that, in line with yoga psychology theory, there is some subliminal level of cognitive awareness of the target, through psychic means, when the person accurately describes the target during the session [see chapters 8 and 16, this volume]. In early research, the hypothesis was that practicing meditation as part of the experimental session would enhance psi awareness. Most of that research used beginning meditators, some had done only a week of practice. Most experiments compared pre- and post-meditation psi scoring, in general finding that before meditation participants scored at chance or in the psimissing direction, and after meditation they were psi hitting. The first such study was by Schmeidler (1970), then three studies by Osis and Bokert (1971), and three more by Dukhan and Rao (1973). Stanford and Palmer (1973) monitored the EEG of the gifted participant Malcolm Bessent; Stanford and Stevenson (1972) also used EEG data. Matas and Pantas (1971) looked at psychokinesis (PK) in groups of meditators and Schmidt and Pantas (1972) reported three PK experiments; the final study assessed was by Honorton and May (1976) (Table 1). Honorton (1977b) conducted a meta-analysis of all the research by 1976 and found that overall there were nine significant meditation-psi experiments out of a total of sixteen (although Honorton only reported on fourteen of these), giving an overall p = 6 × 10–12. Since the Previous Handbook Around the time of the previous handbook, Honorton (1981) was developing his model of internal attention states from his readings of the classic yoga text known as Patanjali’s Yoga Sutras. These sutras (Satyananda, 1976/2000) state that, when one attains the state of consciousness known as samadhi, the siddhis (psychic powers) manifest. Meditation techniques may induce a state of consciousness that is considered traditionally to be a heightened, or even advanced, state of consciousness. In meditation there is internal noise reduction, as exemplified by studies on attention (Valentine & Sweet, 1999), and various psycho-physiological correlates (e.g., alpha rhythm, Cahn & Polich, 2006; decreased skin conductance, Shapiro, 1982). These have all been associated with greater psi awareness (Schmeidler, 1994). Fuller discussions of Patanjali’s yoga sutras in relation to psi research have been given by Braud (2002, 2006) and Radin (2013). Receptive Psi One of the first experiments reported after Honorton’s (1977b) chapter was by Rao and Puri (1978), who tested participants for both subliminal perception and psi before and after they had practiced TM for a week, with a significant negative correlation between the subliminal and psi scores. This study paved the way for Rao and Rao (1982), in which they also tested people who had trained in TM, again only for a week, on both subliminal perception and psi targets. They compared those who had done no meditation with those who had done the one-week course. The meditators scored above chance on both sorts of targets but only significantly so on the subliminal targets while the controls scored at chance on both types of target. In this study they found a significant positive correlation between the subliminal and psi scores. Roll, Solfvin, Krieger, Ray, and Younts (1980) continued the early line of research comparing pre- and post-meditation psi scoring. They hypothesized that meditation would enhance group psi, so that there would be more psi scoring on group targets after meditation than before it, and obtained significant scoring after one of the sessions for the group targets with a slight negative score on the pre-session group targets giving a significant difference between the two. Roll and Zill (1981) used the same method and obtained significant results, with the participants once again scoring nonsignificantly below chance before the meditation and significantly above after it. They did not specify the degree of meditation skill of the participants and considered that these results could better be explained by the participants’ conforming to the experimenters’ wishes than by the effect of meditation per se, because the significance of the study was primarily due to decreased scoring before the meditation. This was a common problem in early research. Compliance with experimenters’ wishes is an effect of which experimenters should always be aware. Nash (1982) compared hypnotic induction with TM in a classroom test of ESP and found that students’ self-rated impressions of a picture were more accurate during the hypnotic induction than during the meditation session. However, this was not a formal experiment so the results should only be considered suggestive. Some experimenters worked with both forced-choice and free-response methods. In forced-choice tests participants have to guess the target from a limited set of choices known to them in advance, whereas in free-response tests they have to describe the target in their own words or drawings, without any knowledge of the potential targets. Rao, Dukhan, and Rao (1978) used both methods testing participants both before and after a half-hour meditation session, working with beginners and more advanced meditators in an ashram in south India. The participants scored significantly higher on both types of test after meditation, though once again there was psi-missing prior to meditation. Harding and Thalbourne (1981) tested people trained in TM by comparing three groups: non-meditators, ordinary TM meditators, and siddhas (advanced TM meditators). They obtained null results with both methods and considered that this was because the meditators had not really wanted to participate and considerable persuasion had been used. Table 1: Honorton’s Database (1977) An experiment with more advanced meditators (Palmer, Khamashta, & Israelson, 1979) tested TM participants with from one to eight years of practice in a precognition ganzfeld design. Results from the participants’ judging were below chance, but not significantly so, whereas independent judges gave marginally significant positive results. Braud and Boston (1986) used a free-response design with a relaxation tape session, and obtained significant scoring (p = .025) with 25 meditators. They examined trained meditators from the Center of Healing and Enlightenment in Houston, but did not specify the extent or sort of meditation. Rao and Rao’s (1982) study suggests that in meditation one learns to become more aware of the contents of one’s mind at a subtler level—this awareness and openness being a generalized form of sensitivity to incoming information, whether of the subliminal or psychic form. Yogic teachings stress again and again that one learns to become more aware at all levels and that removing the noise of the internal dialogue allows greater sensitivity and awareness in general, of which psi awareness is an aspect that occurs at a certain stage in meditation attainment. Although meditation has been linked with other psi-conducive techniques, such as the ganzfeld, it may induce a very different state in that the person is being trained to go “beyond mind,” into a state of pure awareness in which there is very little or no thought. Bem and Honorton (1994), reporting on the ganzfeld database collected during the 1980s, found that practice of a mental discipline in daily life helped novice ganzfeld participants score better on their initial session. However, meditation was not separated out from hypnosis, relaxation, or biofeedback exercises, so it is not possible to discriminate the effect of meditation on participants. Broughton and Alexander (1997), in their replication of Honorton’s ganzfeld research, did not find better scoring for those who practiced a mental discipline and psi scoring was not significant. Schmeidler (1994) summarized the receptive psi research from 1978 to 1992 (Table 2a) and found that four of the six studies she looked at showed significantly positive results. She concluded that meditation may be psiconducive when the meditators accept the testing procedure. However, there were three studies, one that was not formal (Nash, 1982) and another that was published in a difficult to obtain Indian journal (Rao & Puri, 1978), which were not included in her summary. Psychokinesis Most of the experiments in this period looked at receptive psi. There were only a handful of experiments looking at meditation and PK research. Braud (1990) analyzed all the relevant studies reported between 1971 and 1988 (Table 2b), including those covered by Honorton (1977b): Matas and Pantas (1971), Schmidt and Pantas (1972), and Honorton and May (1976). Braud found that seven out of eight studies produced results in which meditation practitioners showed a stronger PK effect at some point in the experiment. Table 2a: Schmeidler’s Database (1992) + 3 studies Table 2b: Braud’s PK review (1990) (+ Honorton PK studies above) Braud and Hartgrove (1976) worked with TM practitioners who had practiced meditation for at least 18 months and a control group of nonmeditators, asking them to both influence a random event generator (REG) and do a free-response clairvoyance test of a picture in an envelope. Participants scored at chance on the PK test but significantly above chance on the clairvoyance test. The meditators did not score better than the controls. Honorton (1977a) worked with a long-term practitioner and instructor of TM, who obtained significant PK after meditation but not before or during meditation. Winnett and Honorton (1977) worked with meditators who were practicing the yogic meditation known as Ajapa Japa, which they had only recently learned. Unusually, they got significant PK scoring before the practice but not during or after the meditation! Schmidt and Schlitz (1989) did a PK study in which the participant attempted to influence pre-recorded targets of melodic tones and noises on a tape. The participants were asked to try and extend the length of time they heard the tone and shorten the time of the noise. There was an overall significant effect, with meditators showing the greater significance at p < .001, while the non-meditators scored at chance. In this study, the portioning out of meditators was done by asking people in a questionnaire whether or not they practiced meditation. Thus, there was no knowledge of the degree of expertise of the meditators or what sort of meditation they practiced. However, Braud (1990) noted that none of this research tells us anything about what is the psi-conducive factor, whether it was prior meditation history, the immediate effects of the meditation session, the meditator’s personality and reasons for meditating in the first place, or a combination of these factors. This is still the case. He further cautions that advanced meditators may not be positively disposed to doing psi research. Although both yogic and Buddhist traditions acknowledge that psi occurs as part of one’s progress along the spiritual path of self-development, these experiences are not to be cultivated for their own ends. The researcher’s and practitioner’s motivation for doing the research must be clear, that it is for the benefit of others and not for one’s own ego or self-aggrandizement. This can produce conflicts in some people that can be to the detriment of research. In conclusion, between 1976–1992 there were 14 meditation and psi studies of which nine tested receptive psi and five tested PK (one testing both receptive and PK). Five of the receptive psi studies gave significantly positive results and three of the PK studies did so. Therefore, meditation as a psi-conducive procedure was again clearly confirmed. Research Since the 1990s During the 1980s and 1990s there was relatively little research on the effect of meditation on psi. Interest has sparked once again in the new millennium, working with more advanced meditators as a potentially psi-conducive population has become more common, most of the research looking at PK in contrast to the earlier research which focused more on receptive psi. Psychokinesis Research The positive relation between meditation and significant REG deviations identified by Braud (1990) has continued. In an unpublished pilot study to determine a suitable protocol that would be beneficial for working with meditators, Bancel (1999) worked for two months with 18 Western practitioners of Tibetan Buddhist meditation who had meditated for at least 15 years. During the experimental sessions, participants were told not to meditate, but rather to watch a feedback display of the REG output while attempting to bias the REG in a given direction, as per the standard Princeton Engineering Anomalies Research (PEAR) protocol [see chapter 20, this volume]. The experiment thus allowed a comparison between a homogeneous group of meditators and the unselected contributors to the PEAR database. The protocol was adapted specifically to meditators by holding experimental sessions in the participants’ homes, in their normal practice setting, and by adjusting the rhythm of sessions to resemble that of a normal meditation retreat day. Data were collected from most of the participants on one day with three or four sessions, but for some participants sessions occurred over two days. A mean difference was obtained, similar to the normal PEAR data, but various factors (such as operator averages) indicated that meditators influenced the REG more than non-meditators. For example, the PEAR and the meditator data both showed a position effect in which the participants’ first sessions had the highest effect size, on average, compared to subsequent data sessions. A comparison of the first session data found the meditator effect size was three times that of the PEAR effect size for those sessions. The difference was significant. Nelson, Jahn, Dunne, and Dobyns (1998) of the PEAR laboratory did a series of experiments using a field REG (i.e., a portable REG) [see chapter 21, this volume], working with a variety of groups in different places. On one occasion they assessed a group who meditated and chanted at several temples and within pyramid chambers in Egypt. There is no mention of what type of meditation was practiced and it probably depended on each individual within the group. They obtained highly significant results, p = .0004. On another occasion the field REG was taken to a spiritual training course that included meditation among the various techniques being taught. There was no significant deviation. In a preliminary step to the Global Consciousness Project (GCP), data from several REGs around the world were gathered at the time that people around the world were meditating for world health and peace, the Gaia Mind Meditation, with an overall significant effect. Nelson (1999–2013), as part of the GCP, ascertained the effect of groups of people all concentrating at the same time. Between 1999 and 2013 there were 20 occasions when the GCP was alerted while groups of people meditated together for a variety of reasons, such as world peace. Not all of the experiments used formal meditation, and some of the studies involved large numbers of people worldwide practicing visualization, prayer, or meditation. They got mixed results: there were 4 events with significant deviations from chance, 3 of which were in the positive (high) direction. There were 5 events in the positive direction but non-significantly, with 1 giving positive significance during the peak period when 1,800 meditators were present; there were also 6 events that produced non-significant results in the negative direction. Therefore, although there was no clear outcome, a formal analysis might reveal an overall positive effect of meditation. Mason, Patterson, and Radin (2007) also looked at the effect of group meditation on an REG and found that the REG significantly deviated from chance output when the group, which involved hundreds of people at the same time and place, were meditating. Ivtzan (2008) collected REG data before group meditation and during meditation, as well as comparing groups that were or were not aware of the REG in the room. Groups that were not aware of the REG scored at chance while those who were aware of the REG scored significantly during the meditation session, but only with the local REG, not with a similar REG located at a distance. In an experiment on distant intention effects, Radin et al. (2008) used the Tibetan bodhicitta (compassion) practice of tonglen, in which one consciously attempts to take on the suffering of another and then send out positive energy to that person. In this study, partners of cancer patients were taught the tonglen practice (and some other intention techniques) at a workshop. They then practiced these daily for three months before the experimental session. There were two types of control groups: in one group (the wait group) the partners were taught the practices after the session, and in the other (the control group) the partners were not taught any technique, and neither person in the pair had cancer. The effects of the distant healing intention were recorded using skin conductance response (SCR) of the receivers, which increased during the healing epochs (p = .00009). The greatest effect was found in the group trained in tonglen meditation, but there was not a significant difference between them and the two control groups. This study was in many ways similar to the Bali studies discussed next, in that the meditator attempted to affect another person, but in this study the measure was an autonomic physiological response. A review by Schmidt (2012) discussed a new PK method termed attention focusing facilitation, which was used in a series of 12 conceptually similar studies between 1993 and 2006. This technique was pioneered by Braud, Shafer, McNeill, and Guerra (1995) and assesses the ability of someone to assist a distant participant to focus their attention on a candle flame. Learning to maintain attention on a focus is a basic condition for the meditation techniques that come under the general title of one-pointed, or concentration, meditation. Concentration on a candle flame is a classic type of pre-meditation technique that is very useful for beginners, although in these experiments none of the participants were meditators. The participants had to press a button every time they noticed that they had stopped concentrating on the flame. On some occasions they were helped from a distance by someone who was concentrating on them and assisting them to maintain focus. A meta-analysis of the 12 studies revealed a small but highly significant distant facilitation effect, in that the participants were able to hold their focus longer when the other person was concentrating on helping them from a distance (Schmidt, 2012). Four of the studies gave a significant positive effect; the remainder were not significant, but were all in the positive direction [see chapter 18, this volume]. Some of this research was conducted in Britain (Brady & Morris, 1997; Watt & Baker, 2002; Watt & Brady, 2002; Watt & Ramakers, 2003), some in the USA (Braud, Shafer, McNeill, & Guerra, 1995), and some in Bali (Edge, Suryani, & Morris, 2007; Edge, Suryani, Tiliopoulos, Bikker, & James, 2008; Edge, Suryani, Tiliopoulos, & Morris, 2004). In the Bali studies the distant facilitator was a meditator and the other participants were nonmeditators, as in the Western studies. Their initial pilot study found that the strongest results were obtained when the helper was trained in meditation (Edge et al., 2007), and so they continued using a meditator as the distant facilitator for the whole series of experiments. In the pilot study, some of the participants had two months of meditation training, but this was not found to affect the results strongly, and so in the remaining studies only the helper was a trained meditator. One interesting point to note is a clear difference in the number of button presses between the studies conducted in Bali and the ones conducted in the West. Participants in the Western world pressed the button almost five times more often than participants in Indonesia. This suggests a strong cultural difference: either that Balinese and Westerners differ in their thresholds for judging mind wandering, their willingness to admit to mind wandering, or their ability to maintain focus on the candle flame. “Meditative prayer is a part of daily life in Balinese Hinduism, but it may be that the Balinese are more adept through their cultural practices to be able to engage in focus meditation in the experiment, even if they have not been formally trained in meditation” (Edge et al., 2008, p. 38). Tibetan monks who spend a considerable amount of time chanting prayers and debating Buddhist scriptures consider that both of these practices prepare the mind for meditation, so this may be a key point in the cultural difference. Further, as noted by Schmidt (2012, pp. 532–533) “Many meditators report having more stable attention when meditating in a group compared to practicing alone (also called Sangha effect). While this might be explained by a conventional psychologic mechanism, there might also be an additional component through some type of distant intention effect. This is especially true if the positive intentions of the meditation are emphasized not only for oneself but, as is often done, also for others.” Eastern people who are familiar with the concept of sangha might be more influenced by it. In a series of studies looking at influence over quantum processes, Radin (2008) asked participants to imagine that they could intuitively perceive a low-intensity laser beam in a distant Michelson interferometer. If such observation were possible, it would theoretically change the pattern of light produced by the interferometer. Perturbation would produce a lower overall level of illumination, which was predicted to occur during the blocking condition. The light patterns were recorded once per second, and average illumination levels of these images were compared in counterbalanced mental blocking versus non-blocking conditions. The outcome was in accordance with the prediction (p = .002). This result was primarily due to nine sessions involving experienced meditators (p = 9.4 × 106); the sessions with non-meditators were not significant. In a similar type of design, Radin et al. (2012) used a double-slit optical system to test the possible role of consciousness in the collapse of the quantum wave-function. The ratio of the interference pattern’s double-slit spectral power to its single-slit spectral power was predicted to decrease when attention was focused toward the double-slit as compared to away from it. Six experiments testing this hypothesis led to a highly significant effect in the predicted direction (p = 6 × 10–6). In sum, in six experiments participants who practiced meditation were compared with those who had little or no meditation experience. Only the meditators gave significant results. In most of this research, no attempt was made to distinguish among different styles of meditation or to formally assess meditation expertise, but one experiment was conducted in a Zen Buddhist temple working with Zen meditators. A further series of experiments using this double-slit protocol (Radin, Michel, Johnston, & Delorme, 2013) was done with 21 participants, most of whom were meditators, but some of whom were musicians or other people high in absorption. No information was given as to what type of meditation practice the meditators used, nor were their results separated out from those of the other participants. A highly significant effect was found; during the concentration condition the photons displayed more of a particle type of behavior, resulting in a decline in interference. In a second experiment, the participants were not located near the double-slit system but were from around the world and interacted via the internet. Again, highly significant results were obtained: 685 people participated, of whom 451 stated that they meditated, but there was no information as to how long they had been meditating or with what type of practice. The meditators performed no better than the other participants. In a third experiment there were 10 participants, some of whom were meditators, and all practiced some form of mental discipline. Again significant results were obtained, but results from the meditators were not analyzed separately. Receptive Psi Research During this period there have been relatively few receptive psi studies and many of these are unpublished. For example, in 1994, while working with Honorton on the ganzfeld protocol, Bem (2013, personal communication) ran 25 meditators and 25 non-meditators as receivers in a study. Both receivers and two independent judges rated all the targets and decoys. There were strong results, particularly for males, with meditators scoring significantly better than non-meditators, using both receiver ratings and external-judge ratings. Much recent research in parapsychology has looked at subconscious processes, in particular physiological responses to stimuli. In an unpublished EEG study of visual evoked potential (Kozak et al., 2003), 15 participants were trained for a month in Primordial Sound Meditation (similar to TM), and both sender and receiver practiced meditation for half an hour prior to the session. Each pair did three sessions, and in each session both members of the pair acted as sender and receiver (two trials per session making a total of six trials per pair). The study evaluated whether brain activation in the receiver was higher when the sender was visually stimulated by a flickering black and white checkerboard pattern. EEG data were collected simultaneously from both sender and receiver, while the sender was presented with alternating flicker and control conditions. Three measures of EEG correlation, of recipient’s brain signal associated with sender’s flicker condition, were analyzed. Overall, 31 percent of the receivers seemed to be influenced during the flicker condition, a highly significant result [see chapter 17, this volume]. Lobach (2010) presented participants with two pictures, one of which would be chosen later as the target. Their heart rate was measured and found to be higher when looking at the non-target picture, opposite to her hypothesis. Some of the participants had experience with both yoga and meditation, though no details were given, and their results were similar to the others. In another method to test for non-conscious psi effects, the presentiment effect, researchers make physiological measurements prior to the participant consciously being exposed to a stimulus. It has been found that people respond differently depending on whether or not the later stimulus is emotional or neutral. In an experiment of this type, Radin, Vieten, Michel, and Delorme (2011) worked with both meditators, who had an average of 20.8 years of active Zen-type meditation practice, and non-meditators. They measured the EEG before, during, and after exposure to unpredictable light and sound stimuli. They hypothesized that pre-stimulus differences should be more apparent in meditators than in non-meditators. For the control group, no EEG channels showed significant pre-stimulus differences between light versus sound stimulus conditions, but for the meditator group five of the EEG channels showed significant differences. Comparisons between control and meditator groups showed significant pre-stimulus differences prior to audio tone stimuli in 14 of 32 channels, of which eight channels were significant. In an unpublished pilot study, Bierman (2007) used SCR as a measure of the participant’s presentiment to pleasant and unpleasant sounds. He also measured habituation to the stimuli and found that the meditators showed similar habituation levels irrespective of whether the person used a concentration or a mindfulness meditation. This is contrary to the teachings concerning these two types of meditation, which state that in concentration meditation one shuts out external stimuli and so should habituate faster, while with mindfulness one maintains awareness of stimuli and so should habituate slower if at all. The meditators had a normal waking condition compared to their meditation trials, the non-meditator participants had a relaxation condition compared to the normal waking condition. There was no difference between the meditators and the controls during the relax/meditation trials, whereas in the normal waking condition there was a significant difference in habituation, occurring much less for the meditators, especially for the pleasant stimuli. There was a strong interaction between state of consciousness and stimulus type; participants habituated to pleasant faster during meditation, and to unpleasant sounds faster during the normal waking condition. Although no presentiment main effect was found, some of the meditators did exhibit typical presentiment effects, and these participants were then asked to take part in the subsequent fMRI study. In that study (Bierman, 2007), meditators were chosen as participants on the hypothesis that they would be more likely to show a presentiment effect than non-meditators. Eight meditators participated and were initially prepared for the experiment by practicing meditation while playing a CD of the noise made by the scanner. The presentiment stimuli were violent, erotic, or neutral pictures and were presented both during meditation and in a resting state. Eight non-meditator control participants also participated in the resting state condition. Based on a qualitative analysis, only in the fMRI study was there a presentiment effect, with twice as many responses prior to the violent targets in the resting and control conditions. In the meditation condition there was stronger presentiment prior to the erotic stimuli. Bierman (2007; personal communication, 2014) reported that the meditators did not show a greater presentiment effect than the controls. Process-oriented research. In most of the above studies, meditators showed stronger psi effects than non-meditators, but there has been no research addressing what it is about meditation that makes it psi-conducive. The only process-oriented research to date is a series of four studies in India, conducted initially at an ashram with yogis (Roney-Dougal & Solfvin, 2006) and then with Tibetan Buddhist monks (Roney-Dougal & Solfvin, 2011; Roney-Dougal, Solfvin, & Fox, 2008). In this research, the yogic and Buddhist teaching that more-advanced meditators would be more consistently psychic than beginners was investigated. In Patanjali’s Yoga Sutras (Satyananda, 2000) it is stated that the siddhis manifest upon attainment of a certain level of samadhi. In the Buddhist teachings, it is stated that when one reaches a certain level of enlightenment, clairvoyance manifests (Conze, 1995). Therefore, the research question was whether enhancement of psi scoring occurs only after the meditator had reached a certain level of attainment, or whether this talent appears gradually. Each participant completed 6 sessions in the yogic studies and 8 sessions in the Tibetan studies. At the end of their series, each participant completed a yogic or meditation attainment questionnaire (MAQ), which detailed the types of practices they did, how often, and for how long. The questionnaire measured practices such as yoga asana, pranayama, as well as various types of meditation, such as mantra, visualization, mahamudra, bodhicitta, and factors such as years spent in retreat and number of hours of practice. All the studies showed a positive correlation between years of practice and psi-scoring in a ganzfeld type free-response task. The correlation between yogic attainment and psi was r = .57, p = .02 in Study 1, and non-significant in the same direction (r = .15) in Study 2 (Roney-Dougal & Solfvin, 2006). In a similar fashion, the significant correlation of psi score with years of meditation found in Tibetan Study 1 (rho = .80, p = .05; Roney-Dougal, Solfvin & Fox, 2008), was non-significant but in the same direction (rho = .28) in Study 2, which gives an overall finding for both Tibetan studies of rho = .74, p = .0005 (Roney-Dougal & Solfvin, 2011). The initial significant correlations in both yogic and Tibetan studies were partially due to psimissing by the beginners. These results support the interpretation that, as you practice meditation, the changes in consciousness occur gradually, rather than psi manifesting reliably only after attainment of a certain level. Using a different method of analysis to ascertain level of meditation attainment, the participants were separated into three different groups representing level of initiation. The advanced group of yogic monks and nuns (swamis) scored significantly better than those initiated into a yogic lifestyle (sannyasins), and than the students who had only just started yoga and meditation practice in study 1, and in study 2 these differences were in a similar direction but non-significant (Roney-Dougal & Solfvin, 2006). In the Tibetan studies, the most advanced group, the lamas who had all completed at least three years of retreat, was the only group to have independently significant psi-hitting and significantly higher scoring than the other two groups of monks (Roney-Dougal & Solfvin, 2011). Thus we found that the meditators with more than 15–20 years of practice showed the most consistent psi-hitting, averaging 33 percent direct hits and in some cases reaching 50 percent, where chance is 25 percent. For those who had practiced meditation for less than 15 years, the psi scoring was variable, sometimes psi-hitting sometimes psi-missing, in a similar manner to that found with non-meditators, but in those with more than 20 years of practice, the results were all in the psi-hitting direction, with stronger and stronger psi scoring as the years of practice increased. The Tibetan research also started to explore which types of meditation practice were most psi-conducive by comparing sessions in which participants used a mantra meditation with sessions in which they used a visualization practice. Years of practice of visualization, as measured by the MAQ, showed a positive correlation with psi scoring (rho = .49). However, no difference between the two techniques was apparent during the actual sessions. It appears that the most important thing is to practice every day for years rather than to use a particular technique. Sadly, this still does not tell us what it is about meditation practice that is psi-conducive, merely that years of continuous practice are required to make the change. However, recent research using a similar design over a four-year period with long term meditators at the Samye Ling Tibetan Center in Scotland did not replicate the Indian results, with no correlation between years of practice and psi score (Roney-Dougal, Ryan, & Luke, 2013). Summary There have been 43 meditation–psi experimental studies (see Table 3) reported since 1992, some including several experiments (such as the GCP research, which has 20 events counted as one study). Of these, 27 gave significant positive results in at least one analysis. There were 38 studies in which participants had practiced some form of meditation, sometimes over a number of years, and had been chosen to participate on the assumption that meditators are a psi-conducive group (“trait” studies); 22 of these studies compared the meditators with controls, or compared advanced meditators with beginners, of which 13 found that the meditators exhibited enhanced significant positive psi scoring. There were 25 studies in which the participants were asked to meditate as part of the procedure (“state” studies), under the assumption that a meditative state of consciousness would be psi-conducive. In 11 cases, these experiments gave significant positive results for at least some of the analyses. There were 14 studies in which both trait and state conditions were evaluated. Of these six gave significant positive results for at least some of the analyses. These results suggest that the continuous practice of meditation is more psi-conducive than meditating as part of the session. However, there is so far no way of knowing the degree to which the participant attained a meditative state of consciousness during any particular session (cf. Cardeña, 2009), nor is there any clear measure of what trait changes have occurred from practicing meditation over a number of years. These measures are in process of development but still leave a lot to be desired. As Cardeña (2009) also points out, personality traits, or in this case trait changes that have occurred over the years of meditation practice, and state of consciousness attained during a particular practice session are interactive processes. Still to Be Done The early work was primarily concerned with establishing that meditation is a psi-conducive condition. This has been done satisfactorily. Much of the more recent work has used meditators as a psi-conducive population for investigating other questions in parapsychology, rather than exploring what it is about meditation that makes it psi-conducive. There is the problem in knowing what the actual effect of meditating per se is. Transpersonal psychology research, which has started to look at the effect of aspects of meditation such as mindfulness, has so far not satisfactorily found any clear defining factors. Further, the term meditation has been used in a very loose way (Roe, 2010). The experiments outlined in this chapter have used many different forms of meditation, including mandala gazing, kundalini yoga (which is primarily concentration on the chakras and the energy channels between them), mantra yoga, which is sometimes known as transcendental meditation (TM) and in which you repeat certain words either mentally or out loud, karma yoga (which is where you are doing some activity while keeping a focused awareness), Zen meditation, which is primarily awareness of the mind, various Tibetan Buddhist practices, vipassana, as well as meditation practices developed by the researchers, or those known and preferred by the participants. Clearly, different techniques may result in different states of consciousness, and meditation research in parapsychology has been criticized for assuming that all meditation techniques are the same (Roe, 2010; Schmidt, 2012). Recent research looking at EEGs of meditators practicing a variety of techniques has found that different techniques result in different brain patterns and rhythms: TM is associated with alpha brainwave activity, concentration techniques with beta/gamma, and open awareness with theta (Cahn & Polich, 2006; Travis & Shear, 2010). Cahn and Polich (2006) caution that most EEG research has used too few recording sites, with a variety of locations for us to be definitive about this. Furthermore, most studies do not evaluate the various meditation techniques sufficiently. Table 3: Later Studies There is thus a lot of work still to be done. Meditation may give rise to a state of consciousness that may differ from other altered states that have been found to be psi-conducive. It may give rise to focused attention and stillness rather than the highly imaginative states found with psychedelics, or dreaming. In hypnosis there are some reports of meditation type experiences such as reduced awareness of the body, but this could be related merely to the fact that the body is relaxed, and some meditation techniques actually have the meditator focus on the body, as in some vipassana or yogic exercises. Cardeña (2005) discusses similarities between experiences of deeply hypnotizable people and some meditation experiences, such as increasing absorption, but again this is true only of some types of meditation practice, such as dharana, and not of others, such as dzog-chen. So we need to be careful, people have certain experiences in different states of consciousness but that does not mean that the state of consciousness is the same. The aim and end result of meditation is very different from the aim or end result of hypnosis despite there being certain similarities along the way. Subliminal Processing in the Mind One theoretical model of psi suggests that psi information is continuously present at a subliminal level and that various methods of accessing this information are similar to those used in accessing other subliminal processes (Carpenter, 2012) [see chapter 8, this volume]. This approach was studied considerably in the 1970s and 1980s (Roney-Dougal, 1986; Schmeidler, 1986). Comparison with subliminal perception research suggests that methods of accessing subliminal material are very similar to those that enable access to psi material. This research also found that participants who were able to successfully bring subliminal material into consciousness were best able to access psi material (Roney-Dougal, 1987; Carpenter & Simmonds-Moore, 2009). Recent research into subliminal perception and meditation found that meditation also appears to enhance awareness of subliminal information (Strick, van Noorden, Ritskes, de Ruiter, & Dijksterhuis, 2012). This may be why meditation enhances psi. It would be instructive to do research that directly compares subliminal and psi tasks by testing meditators. In yoga psychology the practice of meditation is considered to enhance one’s awareness of subliminal states of consciousness (Rao, 2014). According to the head of the Yoga Psychology department at Bihar Yoga Bharati University, yogis have a saying that the nighttime of the layperson is the daytime of the yogi, which implies that a yogi can become consciously aware while dreaming and in a deep sleep state of consciousness (L. I. Bushan, 2002, personal communication). As Bancel (1999, p. 7) has said: “When mindfulness and awareness come together, they provoke a sensitivity that, in various descriptions, often includes a feeling of communication or interaction with the environment. In a sense, the meditator’s goal is to develop this sensitivity to the environment, or, equivalently, to lived experience. Meditation exercises are designed to help the practitioner to integrate and hone these different qualities of keenness, openness, etc. The real occupation of the meditator, however, is to extend the sensitivity developed through exercises into his or her daily life.” In mindfulness/awareness meditation, mindfulness refers to keenness and stability of one’s attention, and awareness refers to an openness that is unbiased and curious. Increased Attention: Concentration and Focus Another possible avenue to explore is that meditation increases the ability to concentrate, with a concomitant increase in temporal attention (Kubose, 1976; Slagter, Lutz, Greischar, Nieuwenhuis, & Davidson, 2009), so that the meditator has more stable attention overall. Could it be this increased focus and concentration, together with increased awareness at all levels, that enhances psi scoring? As part of the Shamatta project, Wallace and collaborators (Wallace, 2006; Wallace & Shapiro, 2006) found that intensive meditation training resulted in improvements in perceptual discrimination and sustained attention (Maclean et al., 2010). In a review of mindfulnesstype meditation studies, Chiesa, Calati, and Serretti (2011) discriminated between different types of attention, and found that only 2 out of 7 randomized controlled studies showed significant improvements in sustained attention, whereas all 3 case-control studies found that long-term meditators showed significantly higher levels of sustained attention. In studies of selective attention once again it is the long-term meditators who show significant effects. A common problem with many studies is the use of novice meditators. Most significant results seem to be with long-term meditators. Four studies have looked at attention switching and once again only the study using long-term meditators produced a significant effect with meditators identifying more alternative perspectives of ambiguous images (Hodgins & Adair, 2010). Sauer et al. (2012) hypothesized that proficiency in mindfulness would result in the ability to stabilize an ambiguous percept and piloted a Necker cube test to measure this. Their findings suggest that meditators are more able than controls to slow down the switching of the bistable Necker cube image when asked to do so, but again we are measuring pre-meditation attainment rather than the ultimate meditation state of consciousness. Despite the present difficulties assessing the effect of meditation on attention, this is an avenue worth exploring in psi research. State and Trait Schmidt (2008) separated meditation-psi studies into two types: those that used meditation as part of the psi task to help the participant attain a psiconducive state of consciousness in the moment (state experiments)—and trait studies that used participants who were meditation practitioners but were not asked to meditate during the session. Of central importance in all the research studies mentioned here is that participants were considered as having “meditated” because they were given instructions to do so, or they stated that they practiced meditation, with no measurement of the degree to which they were proficient in meditation (Tart, 2013, personal communication). This is a huge problem, because, as mentioned earlier, no clear method of measuring meditation attainment has yet been devised. And, according to traditional teachings, most Westerners use concentration premeditation techniques (dharana) rather than meditation proper (dhyana) and although there may be some Westerners who have attained samadhi, they are keeping pretty quiet about it. As seen in the section above, most measures assess attention or concentration, which is dharana rather than dhyana. As Cardeña says, “Even within the ‘same’ state there are vast individual differences” (Cardeña, 2009, p. 311). An attempt to assess the participant’s meditation attainment was made in my yogic and Tibetan research (Roney-Dougal, Ryan, & Luke, 2013; RoneyDougal & Solfvin, 2011), for which a meditation attainment questionnaire (MAQ) was devised. But this was essentially a self-report questionnaire with all of the problems of inaccuracy, forgetfulness, and difficulty to ascertain the relation between the number of hours or years of practice and what effect that had actually had on changing the person’s state of consciousness. Walach, Buchheld, Buttenmuller, Kleinknecht, and Schmidt (2006) have also created a self-report questionnaire (the Freiburg Mindfulness Inventory) that shows some promise, but suffers from the fact that humility is considered in the East to be an essential aspect of meditation. Thus, the better the meditators, the more likely they are to report themselves as beginners, while beginners often overestimate their level of meditation attainment! This is a problem with all self-report scales. In the West we are at nursery school level where meditation attainment is concerned—nowhere near the levels that the Tibetans consider required for reliable psi. As reported in Roney-Dougal and Solfvin (2011), discussions with two Tibetan Gelugpa Rinpoches (one of whom was considered to be the top theoretician in the Gelugpa sect) revealed that they consider it necessary to first attain the highest level of concentration (shinay) before one can be fully mindfully aware (lahtong) enough to enter the meditation state proper, which is beyond the thinking mind (samadhi). Then one still has to overcome the obstacles of the realm of desires before psi can be considered reliable! Meditation-psi research will take a major step forward when there are reliable independent measures of how successfully a given meditation session actually affects the mind, and of the level of meditation the participant has attained. In discussions with participants in my meditation research they often stated that a session had or had not been a good meditation. But no one has addressed this issue yet in any experiment. Culture and Belief Some of the research reported above has highlighted cultural differences in the relation between meditation and psi. Is this another effect of belief, as in the classic sheep-goat research (Lawrence 1993), or some other characteristic of meditation? As already mentioned in the Edge et al. (2004) Bali research, the helpees were as much part of the psi process as the helpers—they were not merely their physiology, as in the classic DMILS protocol. In none of the studies were meditators used as helpees, even though they were employing a classic concentration technique. However, the Bali helpees showed a very different level of response to the practice from the Westerners who participated in the USA and Edinburgh trials. This suggests that their ability to focus, or to notice that the mind had wandered, or to admit noticing that the mind had wandered, as measured by the number of button presses, was very different from that of the Westerners. The helpers were key to the difference between the help and control conditions, but not to the overall number of button presses. The more one meditates, the more one becomes aware of the subtler levels of distraction. Beginners do not tend to notice the degree to which their mind is distracted. Edge et al. (2008) point out that the Balinese had, from childhood, taken part in daily pujas, and so on. When interviewing the Tibetans (Roney-Dougal & Solfvin, 2011), we found that the importance of prayer in training the mind for later meditation practice was highly rated. In fact, some of the Tibetans considered pujas to be a preliminary type of meditation. They also considered memorizing and debating their scriptures to be a preliminary form of meditation. Edge’s helpees had been practicing a preliminary to meditation since childhood, and thus it is possible that they had more focused minds than the Westerners, who most probably neither prayed, memorized scriptures, nor performed any other task to get their mental abilities trained and under control. It is also possible that the Balinese participants were conforming to the experimenter’s wishes and thought that fewer button presses were considered better and performed accordingly. In the East conformance to the one in authority is far stronger than it is in the West. This was very apparent with the students in my initial ashram research, and I think explains much of the early meditation-psi research where there was psi-missing or chance results prior to the meditation with above chance results after the meditation. Research involving mind wandering and button presses has recently received attention by meditation researchers, but only with regard to Westerners (Baird, Schooler, Mrazek, Fishman, & Smallwood, 2013; Hasenkamp, Wilson-Mendenhall, Duncan, & Barsalou, 2012). Karma yoga has a number of attributes that may be found to be psiconducive. Karma yoga is a form of meditation in action. Equanimity is one very important attribute in which one is not disturbed by either success or failure; absence of expectation and right motivation are considered vital for the correct attitude towards the tasks one is undertaking; and of course there must be egolessness, an essential humility, so that you are not affected emotionally by the outcome of the session. These are basic attitudes to life in both Buddhist and Yogic cultures that may facilitate psi experience. All of the Tibetan monks agreed to participate in our studies only on condition that the essential motivation was to benefit all, while they remained incognito. There has been no research on the relation between egolessness or humility and psi, so these are merely speculations based on observation. Further, in the East there is a different approach and attitude to experimental testing. The yogis and Tibetans were at ease with doing psi—it was the science that caused them concern (Roney-Dougal & Solfvin, 2011). Psi was used extensively in traditional Tibetan culture. Most villages had someone who practiced divination, and all the monasteries used to have an oracle, a monk who went into an altered state for divination, as well as a monk who practiced other forms of divination. Spiritual healing and astrology were common practices in both the villages and the monasteries (Roney-Dougal, 2006). On the other hand, for the Western Buddhist meditators (RoneyDougal, Ryan, & Luke, 2013) we worked with in Scotland, the science was no problem but the psi created much internal conflict. It is quite probable that this cultural attitude affected psi scoring. Setting Another important point to consider when working with participants as meditators is to create a setting that accords with their particular practice experience (Bancel, 2013, personal communication). In the research with meditators in India and in Scotland, all sessions occurred in a place that was familiar and comfortable to the participants, either their own room where they normally practiced, or a shrine room available for practice, or similar. Many researchers, such as at the PEAR laboratory, make their participants as comfortable as possible. But meditators find that doing their practice in a specific place on a daily basis helps enhance their practice, and so doing the experimental session in this place may well help to enhance psi. Conclusion All meditation traditions state that advanced meditators will exhibit reliable and strong psychic phenomena. Most cultures in the world studied by anthropologists are reported as having respected and honored their diviners and oracles. The Dalai Lama (2002) stated that all Tibetan monasteries in Tibet, prior to the Chinese invasion, had someone who practiced divination, and that these people were highly respected members of their communities. Western parapsychology research has, in the main, worked with relatively untrained people who show a minimal level of very unreliable psi. The research with meditators is very patchy and has not shown the levels of psi traditionally reported for advanced yogis and lamas. However, these initial tentative explorations into this area with Western practitioners, who by Eastern standards are just beginners, does show potential. It is a thread worth following. Acknowledgments Deep gratitude to all those who helped with this chapter: who sent me their unpublished studies; who contributed thoughts and ideas about meditationpsi research; who sent me references to articles; and the three reviewers who went through it with a fine tooth comb, and made many beneficial changes and suggestions; the mistakes and shortcomings are all mine. May this work be for the benefit of all beings. References Baird, B., Schooler, J. W., Mrazek, M., Fishman, D., and Smallwood, J. (2013). Unnoticed intrusions: Dissociation of meta-consciousness in thought suppression. Consciousness and Cognition, 22, 1003–1012. Bancel, P. (1999). Report on ICRL Internship at PEAR: REG Experiments with meditation practitioners. Unpublished manuscript. Bem, D. J. and Honorton, C. (1994). Does PSI exist? Replicable evidence for an anomalous process of information transfer. Psychological Bulletin, 115, 4–18. Bierman, D. (2007). fMRI and photoemission study of presentiment: The role of “coherence” in retrocausal processes. Final report for Bial Grant 34/04. Unpublished manuscript. Bierman, D. (2010). The potential anomalous component of intuition: Empirical evidence and an integrated theoretical approach. In F. Lopes da Silva, A. Castro-Caldas, C. Watt, D. Bierman, M. Cardoso, and R. M. Cardoso (Eds.), Behind and beyond the brain, Bial’s 8th Symposium (pp. 95– 109). Porto, Portugal: Fundaçao Bial. Brady, C. and Morris, R. L. (1997). Attention focusing facilitated through remote mental interaction: A replication and exploration of parameters. The Parapsychological Association 40th Annual Convention Proceedings of Presented Papers (pp. 73–91). Braud, L.W. and Boston, D.A. (1986). Target preference and clairvoyance in selected subjects following relaxation induction. In D.H. Weiner and D.I. Radin (Eds.), Research in parapsychology 1985 (pp. 25–28). Metuchen, NJ: Scarecrow Press. Braud, W. G. (1974). Relaxation as a psi-conducive state. Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society, 3, 115–118. Braud W. G. (1975). Psi-conducive states. Journal of Communication, 25, 142–52. Braud, W. G. (1978). Psi-conducive conditions: Explorations and interpretations. In B. Shapin and L. Coly (Eds.), Psi and states of awareness (pp. 1–41). New York: Parapsychology Foundation. Braud, W. G. (1990). Meditation and psychokinesis. Parapsychology Review, 21, 9–11. Braud, W. G. (2002). Psi-favourable conditions. In V. G. Ramohan (Ed.), New frontiers of human science (pp. 95–118). Jefferson, NC: McFarland. Braud, W. G. (2006). Patanjali yoga and siddhis: Their relevance to parapsychological theory and research. In K. R. Rao, M. Cornelissen, and J. Dalal (Eds.), Handbook of Indian psychology. Delhi, India: Motilal Banarsidass. Braud, W. G., and Hartgrove, J. (1976). Clairvoyance and psychokinesis in transcendental meditators and matched control subjects: A preliminary study. European Journal of Parapsychology, 1, 6–16. Braud, W. G., Shafer, D., McNeill, K., and Guerra, V. (1995). Attention focusing facilitated through remote mental interaction. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 89, 103–115. Broughton, R. S., and Alexander, C. H. (1997). Autoganzfeld II: An attempted replication of the PRL ganzfeld research. Journal of Parapsychology, 61, 209–226. Cahn, B.R. and Polich, J. (2006). Meditation states and traits: EEG, ERP, and neuroimaging studies. Psychological Bulletin, 132, 180–211. Cardeña, E. (2005). The phenomenology of deep hypnosis: Quiescent and physically active. International Journal of Clinical and Experimental Hypnosis, 53, 37–59. Cardeña, E. (2009). Beyond Plato? Toward a science of alterations of consciousness. In C. A. Roe, W. Kramer, and L. Coly (Eds.). Utrecht II: Charting the future of parapsychology (pp. 305–322). New York: Parapsychology Foundation. Carpenter, J. (2012). First sight: ESP and parapsychology in everyday life. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield. Carpenter, J., and Simmonds-Moore, C. (2009). ESP contribution to the unconscious formation of a preference. Paper presented at the 52nd Convention of the Parapsychological Association, Seattle, USA. Chiesa, A., Calati, R. and Serretti, A. (2011). Does mindfulness training improve cognitive abilities? A systematic review of neuropsychological findings. Clinical Psychology Review, 31, 449–464. Conze, E. (trans. and ed.) (1995). The large sutra on perfect wisdom, New Delhi, India: Motilal Banarsidass. Dalai Lama, H. H. (2002). Freedom in exile. London, UK: Abacus. Dukhan, H. and Rao, K.R. (1973). Meditation and ESP scoring. In W. G. Roll, R. L. Morris, and J. D. Morris (Eds.), Research in parapsychology 1972 (pp. 148–151). Metuchen, NJ: Scarecrow Press. Edge, H, Suryani, L. K. and Morris, R. L. (2007). Pursuing psi in a non– Euro American culture: Behavioural DMILS in Bali. Final report for Bial Grant 127/02. Edge, H, Suryani, L.K., Tiliopoulos, N., Bikker, A., and James, R. (2008). Comparing conscious and physiological measurements in a cognitive DMILS study in Bali. Final report for Bial Grant 116/04. Edge, H, Suryani, L. K, Tiliopoulos, N., and Morris, R.L. (2004). Two cognitive DMILS studies in Bali. Journal of Parapsychology, 68, 289–321. Harding, S. E., and Thalbourne, M. A. (1981). Transcendental meditation, clairvoyant ability and psychological adjustment. In W. G. Roll and J. Beloff (Eds.), Research in parapsychology 1980 (pp. 71–73). Metuchen, NJ: Scarecrow Press. Hasenkamp, W., Wilson-Mendenhall, C.D., Duncan, E., and Barsalou, L.W. (2012). Mind wandering and attention during focused meditation: A finegrained temporal analysis of fluctuating cognitive states, NeuroImage, 59, 750–760. Hodgins, H. S. and Adair, K. C. (2010). Attentional processes and meditation. Consciousness and Cognition, 19, 872–878. Honorton, C. (1977a). Effects of meditation and feedback on psychokinetic performance: A pilot study with an instructor of Transcendental Meditation. In J. D. Morris, W. G. Roll, and R. L. Morris (Eds.), Research in parapsychology 1976 (pp. 95–97). Metuchen, NJ: Scarecrow Press. Honorton, C. (1977b). Psi and internal attention states. In B.B. Wolman (Ed.), Handbook of parapsychology (pp. 435–472), New York: Van Nostrand Rheinhold. Honorton, C. (1981). Psi, internal attention states and the Yoga sutras of Patanjali. In B. Shapin and L. Coly (Eds.), Concepts and theories of parapsychology (pp. 55–68). New York: Parapsychology Foundation,. Honorton, C., and May, E. (1976). Volitional control in a psychokinetic task with auditory and visual feedback. In J. D. Morris, W. G. Roll, and R. L. Morris (Eds.), Research in parapsychology 1975 (pp. 90–91). Metuchen, NJ: Scarecrow Press. Ivtzan, I. (2008). Meditation on consciousness. Journal of Scientific Exploration, 22, 147–160. Kozak, L., Johnson, L. C., Richards, T., King, H., Standish, L. J., Schlitz, M. J., Simon, D., and Chopra, D. (2003). EEG evidence of correlated neural signals between physically and sensory isolated subjects who have undergone Primordial Sound Meditation (PSM) training. Unpublished manuscript. Kubose, S. K. (1976). An experimental investigation of psychological aspects of meditation. Psychologia, 19, 1–10. Lamrimpa, G. (1995). Calming the mind: Tibetan Buddhist teachings on cultivating meditative quiescence. Ithaca, NY: Snow Lion. Lawrence, T. R. (1993). Gathering in the sheep and goats…. A meta-analysis of forced-choice sheep-goat ESP studies, 1947–1993. The Parapsychological Association 36th Annual Convention: Proceedings of Presented Papers (pp. 75–86). Lobach, E. (2010). Somatic component of intuition and psi. In F. Lopes da Silva, A. Castro-Caldas, C. Watt, D. Bierman, M. Cardoso, and R.M. Cardoso (Eds.), Behind and beyond the brain, Bial’s 8th symposium (pp. 75– 85). Porto, Portugal: Fundacao Bial. MacLean, K. A., Ferrer, E., Aichele, S. R., Bridwell, D. A., Zanesco, A. P., Jacobs, T. L., … and Saron C. D. (2010). Intensive meditation training leads to improvements in perceptual discrimination and sustained attention. Psychological Science, 21, 829–839. Mason, L.I., Patterson, R.P., and Radin, D.I. (2007). Exploratory study: The random number generator and group meditation. Journal of Scientific Exploration, 21, 295–317. Matas, F., and Pantas, L. (1971). A PK experiment comparing meditating versus non-meditating subjects. Proceedings of the Parapsychological Association, 8, 12–13. Nash, C. B. (1982). Hypnosis and transcendental meditation as inducers of ESP. Parapsychology Review, 13, 19–20. Nelson, R.D. (1999–2013). Global Consciousness Project. Peace meditations. Available at: http://www.noosphere.princeton.edu Nelson, R. D., Jahn, R. G., Dunne, B. J., and Dobyns, Y. H. (1998). Field REG II: Consciousness field effect: Replication and explorations. Journal of Scientific Exploration, 22, 425–454. Osis, K., and Bokert, E. (1971). ESP and changed states of consciousness induced by meditation. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 65, 245–288. Palmer, J., Khamashta, K., and Israelson, K. (1979). An ESP ganzfeld experiment with Transcendental Meditators. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 73, 333–348. Radin, D. (2008). Testing nonlocal observation as a source of intuitive knowledge. Explore, 4, 25–35. Radin, D. (2013). Supernormal: Science, yoga and the evidence for psychic abilities. New York: Deepak Chopra Books. Radin, D., Michel, L., Galdamez, K., Wendland, P., Rickenbach, R., and Delorme, A. (2012). Consciousness and the double-slit interference pattern: Six experiments, Physics Essays, 25, 157–171. Radin, D., Michel, L., Johnston, J., and Delorme, A. (2013). Psychophysical interactions with a double-slit interference pattern, Physics Essays, 26, 553– 566. Radin, D., Stone, J. Levine, E., Eskandarnejad, S., Schlitz, M., Kozak, L., Mandel, D., and Hayssen, G. (2008). Compassionate intention as a therapeutic intervention by partners of cancer patients: Effects of distant intention on the patients’ autonomic nervous system. Explore, 4, 235–243. Radin, D., Vieten, C., Michel, L., and Delorme, A. (2011). Electrocortical activity prior to unpredictable stimuli in meditators and nonmeditators. Explore, 7, 286–299. Rao, K. R. (2014). Yoga: Theory and techniques for cultivating consciousness. In K. R. Rao (Ed.) Cultivating consciousness: An East-West journey (pp. 233–258). Visakhapatnam, India: Gitam University Press. Rao, K. R., Duckan, H., and Rao, P. V. K. (1978). Yogic meditation and psi scoring in forced-choice and free-response tests. Journal of Indian Psychology, 1, 160–175. Rao, K. R., and Puri, I. (1978). Subsensory perception (SSP), Extrasensory perception (ESP) and transcendental meditation (TM). Journal of Indian Psychology, 1, 69–74. Rao, P. V. K., and Rao, K. R. (1982). Two studies of ESP and subliminal perception, Journal of Parapsychology, 46, 185–207. Roe, C.A. (2010). The role of altered states of consciousness in extrasensory experiences. In M. Smith (Ed.), Anomalous experiences: Essays from parapsychological and psychological perspectives (pp. 25–49). Jefferson, NC: McFarland. Roll, W. G., Solfvin, G. F., Krieger, J., Ray, D. and Younts, L (1980). Psi scoring on individual and group targets before and after meditation. In W. G. Roll (Ed.), Research in parapsychology 1979 (pp. 172–174). Metuchen, NJ: Scarecrow Press. Roll, W. G., and Zill, R. (1981). Psi scoring on individual and group targets before and after meditation. In W. G Roll and J. Beloff (Eds.), Research in parapsychology 1980 (pp. 73–75). Metuchen, NJ: Scarecrow Press. Roney-Dougal, S. M. (1986). Subliminal and psi perception: A review of the literature. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 53, 405–434. Roney-Dougal, S. M. (1987). A comparison of subliminal and psi perception: Exploratory and follow-up studies. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 81, 141–182. Roney-Dougal, S.M. (2006). Taboo and belief in Tibetan psychic tradition. Journal of the Society of Psychical Research, 70, 193–210. Roney-Dougal, S. M., Ryan, A., and Luke, D. (2011). Preliminary study of the relationship between local geomagnetic activity, Tibetan Buddhist meditation and psychic awareness. Paper presented at the 54th Parapsychological Association Convention, Curitiba, Brazil. Roney-Dougal, S. M., Ryan, A., and Luke, D (2013). Follow-up study of the relationship between local geomagnetic activity and psychic awareness. Paper presented at the 56th Parapsychological Association Convention, Viterbo, Italy. Roney-Dougal, S. M., and Solfvin, J. (2006).Yogic attainment in relation to awareness of precognitive targets. Journal of Parapsychology, 70, 91–20. Roney-Dougal, S. M., and Solfvin, J. (2011). Exploring the relationship between Tibetan meditation attainment and precognition. Journal of Scientific Exploration, 24, 29–46. Roney-Dougal, S. M., Solfvin, J., and Fox, J. (2008). An exploration of degree of meditation attainment in relation to psychic awareness with Tibetan Buddhists. Journal of Scientific Exploration, 22, 161–178. Sauer, S., Lemke, J., Wittmann, M., Kohls, N., Mochty, U., and Walach, H. (2012). How long is now for mindfulness meditators? Personality and Individual Differences, 52, 750–754. Satyananda Saraswati, Sw. (1976/2000). Four chapters on freedom. Munger, India: Yoga Publications Trust. Schmeidler, G. (1970). High ESP scores after a swami’s brief instruction in meditation and breathing. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 64, 100–103. Schmeidler, G. (1973). PK effects upon continuously recorded temperature. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 67, 325–340. Schmeidler, G. (1986). Subliminal perception and ESP: Order in diversity? Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 80, 241–264. Schmeidler, G. (1994). ESP experiments 1978–1992. In S. Krippner (Ed.), Advances in parapsychological research, Vol. 7 (pp. 104–197). Jefferson, NC: McFarland. Schmidt, H., and Pantas, L. (1972). Psi tests with internally different machines. Journal of Parapsychology, 36, 222–232. Schmidt, H., and Schlitz, M. (1989). A large-scale pilot PK experiment with pre-recorded random events. In L. A. Henkel and R. E. Berger (Eds.), Research in parapsychology 1988 (pp. 6–10). Metuchen, NJ: Scarecrow Press. Schmidt, S. (2008). Aristotle’s fly—Remarks on anomaly research and a review on the relationship between meditation and psi. In F. Lopes da Silva, A. Castro-Caldas, C. Watt, D. Bierman, and M. Cardoso (Eds.), Behind and Beyond the Brain, Bial’s 7th Symposium (pp. 73–96). Porto, Portugal: Fundaçao Bial. Schmidt, S. (2012). Can we help just by good intentions? A meta-analysis of experiments on distant intention effects. Journal of Alternative and Complementary Medicine, 18, 529–533. Shapiro, D.H. (1982). Overview: Clinical and physiological comparison of meditation and other self-control strategies. American Journal of Psychiatry, 139, 267–274. Slagter, H. A., Lutz, A., Greischar, L. L., Nieuwenhuis, S., and Davidson, R. J. (2009). Theta phase synchrony and conscious target perception: Impact of intensive mental training. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 21, 1536– 1549. Stanford, R. G., and Palmer, J. (1973). Meditation prior to the ESP task: An EEG study with an outstanding ESP subject. In W. G. Roll, R. L. Morris, and J. D. Morris (Eds.), Research in parapsychology 1972 (pp. 34–36). Metuchen, NJ: Scarecrow Press. Stanford, R. G., and Stevenson, I. (1972). EEG correlates of free-response GESP in an individual subject. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 66, 357–368. Strick, M., van Noorden, T. H. J., Ritskes, R. R., de Ruiter, J. R., and Dijksterhuis, A. (2012). Zen meditation and access to information in the unconscious. Consciousness and Cognition, 21, 1476–1481. Travis, F. and Shear, J. (2010). Focused attention, open monitoring and automatic self-transcending: Categories to organize meditations from Vedic, Buddhist and Chinese traditions. Consciousness and Cognition, 19, 1110– 1118. Walach, H., Buchheld, N., Buttenmuller, V., Kleinknecht, N., and Schmidt, S. (2006). Measuring mindfulness—the Freiburg Mindfulness Inventory (FMI). Personality and Individual Differences, 40, 1543–1555. Wallace, B. A. (2006). The attention revolution. Boston, MA: Wisdom Publications. Wallace, B. A., and Shapiro, S. L. (2006). Mental balance and well-being: Building bridges between Buddhism and Western psychology. American Psychologist, 61, 690–701. Watt, C. A., and Baker, I. S. (2002). Remote facilitation of attention focusing with psi-supportive versus psi-unsupportive experimenter suggestions. Journal of Parapsychology, 66, 151–168. Watt, C. A., and Brady, C. (2002). Experimenter effects and the remote facilitation of attention focusing: Two studies and the discovery of an artifact. Journal of Parapsychology, 66, 49–71. Watt, C. A., and Ramakers, P. (2003). Experimenter effects with a remote facilitation of attention focusing task: A study with multiple believer and disbeliever experimenters. Journal of Parapsychology, 67, 99–116. White, R. A. (1964). A comparison of old and new methods of response to targets in ESP experiments, Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 58, 21–56. Winnett, R., and Honorton, C. (1977). Effects of meditation and feedback on psychokinetic performance: Results with practitioners of Japa yoga. In J. D. Morris, W. G. Roll, and R. L. Morris (Eds.), Research in parapsychology 1976 (pp. 97–98). Metuchen, NJ: Scarecrow Press. OceanofPDF.com Part Four: Biology and Psi OceanofPDF.com CHAPTER 11 Psi and Biology An Evolutionary Perspective RICHARD S. BROUGHTON When the previous Handbook was published there was a general consensus in the field that psi and biology were separate entities. Psi was the stuff of the mind, of consciousness, and biology was the material world. That these two entities might and probably did interact was assumed, and researching these interactions would help us understand psi, but that is as far as the relation could go. That view, I submit, seriously hampers our ability to understand psi and how it works, and I suspect just plain wrong. Consider this case from the collection of Louisa E. Rhine (1961) concerning a young man in California: One night in July of 1951 we had just finished supper, and my brotherin-law was getting ready to go to a meeting in San Jose, which is twenty-five miles from our house. For no reason I started crying, me, crying, twenty-five years old! I begged him not to go. Well there was quite a fuss and I got everyone upset. Mom kept saying, “He will be all right.” You know, the usual soft soap you give an upset person. This went on for about fifteen minutes. Then the feeling left me, and I said, “It’s all right for Bob to go now.” By this time the fellow he was to ride with had waited at their meeting place, but left before Bob got there, so Bob had to drive his own car down. He got as far as Bayshore and Charter Streets, when the traffic began to back up. A wreck, which is nothing unusual around here, but when Bob got to the corner, he said he almost passed out. There spread out on the highway was the man he was to have ridden with; his head was half gone. The car was a total loss. They found later that his brakes had locked on one side, and he flipped up in the air and came down on the other side of the road to be hit head-on by another car [p. 127]. What is noteworthy about this case? There are no images in the young man’s brain, no telepathic thoughts, no cognitive content at all. In this case it is all emotional feelings; it is his body “responding” to a future event. It is his biology that is responding. This is not a unique, unrepresentative case either. After dreaming, which accounts for the largest proportion of reported spontaneous ESP, the next largest category is that of intuitive impressions— sudden hunches, gut feelings, or “just knowing” without any imagery or reasoning process. I think this substantial subset (roughly one quarter) of spontaneous cases indicates something that we have been missing for too long. ESP is not simply a function of the mind or the brain, but it is deeply rooted in our bodies, in our biology. This chapter will cover similar territory to Morris’s chapter (1977), but there will be a different orientation. Although it would be stretching the point to say that the field has made many major advances in our understanding of the fundamental workings of ESP, there have been advances in our ideas about where we should be looking. The once dominant notion that psi is some sort of signal or even a non-physical type of communication between minds that are not necessarily embodied has given way, at least in part, to models in which psi is a correlational process between future and present, and the physiology of the brain (and perhaps body) may be very much part of that process. Thus the relation between psi and biology can be seen in a different light. This chapter starts with a brief review of its predecessor, focusing on the key elements that have carried research forward in the intervening years. Next, the chapter will review research that has focused on the biological aspects of psi in the years since the original book. Some topics are discussed in separate chapters in this volume, but their connections with Morris’s original perspective will be highlighted. In particular, I will look at research examining brain function and psi, as well as physical influences on brain and biology that may affect the utilization of psi. Next I will explore how ESP can be incorporated into current thinking on human evolution, arguing that ESP must be viewed within an evolutionary framework. Finally, I shall offer some suggestions as to where future research should be focused. Parapsychology, Biology and ANPSI in 1977 Morris began with a discussion of communication and information transfer with particular reference to the many channels of information flow with which nature has endowed humans and other animals. Reviewing the literature demonstrating that other species have sensitivities to environmental information that go far beyond the ranges used by humans, Morris highlighted the serious methodological challenges for those investigating possible psi abilities in animals. If the basic requirement of psi research is to eliminate all “normal” channels of communication, that requirement can be particularly difficult to meet if one does not fully understand all the possible channels of communication available to other species. In 1977 laboratory research on animal psi (or anpsi, a term largely fallen into disuse today) was very popular. As with human research, the animal research had its roots in a considerable literature of spontaneous cases of animals apparently exhibiting ESP in various forms (J. B. Rhine & Feather, 1962). In some instances it appeared that the animals attempted to warn their masters of impending danger, reacted to the death of the master at a distance, or anticipated their master’s return. Cases of left-behind pets tracking down their owners across considerable distances, called psitrailing, was thought to have a psi component, as was homing behavior, though Morris noted that the latter no longer needs a psi explanation. Along with the spontaneous cases were a very limited number of field experiments, primarily with “talented” animals, but Morris concluded that the totality of animal research provided little support for the notion of psi in infrahuman species [but see chapter 27, this volume]. Morris’s chapter then surveyed the considerable amount of lab research that was underway in the mid–1970s. Building on earlier research, the new wave of animal research benefited from computer automation and the development of digital random number generators (RNGs). Experiments were demonstrating that animals (mostly rodents) could seemingly bias the output of RNGs to increase rewards and reduce punishments, or that they seemingly could use precognition to avoid shocks or get food, or even just anticipate their own demise. Morris’s conclusion was that the animal psi research was encouraging but the data were weak and the interpretation that the animals were demonstrating psi was compromised by the growing recognition of the possibility that the data were actually revealing the psi of the experimenters rather than the animals. At the time the possibility of psibased experimenter effect had been recently highlighted in several key publications (Kennedy & Taddonio, 1976; White, 1976a, 1976b) and was supported by the newly emerging observational theories of psi [chapter 13, this volume]. The impossibility of ruling out experimenter psi effectively ended experimental animal psi research soon after the first Handbook was published. With regard to psi and human biology, at the time of Morris’s writing the principal lines of research were (a) examining physiological characteristics that may be correlated with psi performance, and (b) attempting to measure a psi effect through physiological responses. In the former category, most common were EEG studies that generally, though by no means universally, showed that ESP success was better when participants were producing an abundance of activity in the alpha brainwave frequency band. This, Morris noted, simply showed that participants did better when they were relaxed, something that was already known (more recent interpretations of the alpha band have become more nuanced, see, for instance, Cooper, Croft, Dominey, & Gruzelier, 2003; Klimesch, 2012). The latter category included a mix of studies generally of a telepathy design in which something was done to an agent while the recipient’s EEG or other physiological measure was being monitored. Results were also a mix of successes and failures, but at least one study is worth noting because it presaged a major research effort today. Levin and Kennedy (1975) managed to demonstrate that the contingent negative variation (CNV), an EEG response indicating preparation for action, significantly anticipated a participant’s response to a random stimulus (but only in one of two studies). Drawing his overall conclusions, Morris noted that although the results were mixed, the direct physiological measures that seemed to correlate with the onset of a target event were quite promising because they suggested more direct access to the psi information than verbal or behavioral responses [chapter 17, this volume]. Morris’s (1977) summary position was very cautious. He noted that little could be concluded from the research to that point, calling simply for more data before one can “truly assess the extent to which psi communication interacts with our presently known biological communication channels” (p. 710). Developments since 1977 Animal Research The considerable difficulties in interpreting the results of laboratory animal studies, combined with the general inability to confirm earlier findings in the wake of the discovery of data manipulation on the part of a leading animal researcher Walter Levy (J. B. Rhine, 1974) [see chapter 3, this volume], brought to a close any notions that animal research would be the quick road to reliable psi results. Animal research largely disappeared from the scene save for the efforts of a few individuals. French researchers Remy Chauvin and René Peoc’h reported several animal–PK studies in which mice (Chauvin, 1986) and chicks (Peoc’h, 1988, 1995) appeared to influence the behavior of a small self-propelled robot-like device called a tychoscope. The tychoscope’s movements were controlled by an RNG, and in the absence of influence it would describe a random path (within a defined area). Chauvin’s mice were afraid of the device and apparently influenced it to stay away from them to a statistically significant degree. In his first study, Peoc’h took advantage of a chick’s imprinting instinct by imprinting batches of chicks on the moving tychoscope. Subsequently the chicks would be constrained from following the device, but in that case the chicks apparently influenced the tychoscope to approach them significantly more often than chance would predict (Peoc’h, 1988). In a second study, Peoc’h mounted a candle on the tychoscope and found that chicks that were raised in the dark would influence the device to approach their cage to provide illumination (Peoc’h, 1995). As in previous laboratory animal studies, the possible influence of the experimenter could not be ruled out (despite some attempts). Efforts to replicate the imprinting work by other researchers were unsuccessful (Green & Thorpe, 1993; Johnson, 1989), thus leaving laboratory animal research in the same inconclusive state that it was in 1977. Field research with animals, by contrast, has made some progress, at least in terms of methodology, and some would argue in terms of results as well, largely through the efforts of Rupert Sheldrake. Drawing on extensive anecdotal reports of pets displaying apparently psychic abilities such as reliably anticipating an owner’s generally unpredictable return home. Sheldrake (1999) embarked on a variety of experiments to demonstrate such abilities under controlled conditions. This ongoing research program has generated a lot of data, as well as its measure of criticism, both of which Sheldrake discusses in more detail in chapter 27 in this volume. A recent comprehensive critical review of all the animal psi research to date concludes that the overall evidence for psi in animals remains scant, but a good case can be made for progress coming from studies looking for psi in the relation between humans and companion animals (Dutton & Williams, 2009). From Biology to Neuroscience When the biological literature was surveyed in 1977, the research focus was either on physiological states that might be associated with better scoring in behavioral psi tests, or on changes in ongoing physiological processes correlated with some target event, suggesting that ESP was being “received” directly by the body. This approach had the benefit of providing possible evidence of psi before it was subjected to cognitive processing, with its potential for creating bias and confusion. The intervening years have seen this useful, if somewhat simplistic, approach mature into a neuroscience-based search for the mechanisms that may underlie the processing of anomalous information and its mediation into conscious awareness. Presentiment The Levin & Kennedy (1975) study and subsequent replication efforts by Hartwell (1978, 1979) on CNV looked for evidence of precognition in a brain signal that anticipates action. Overall, the results were ambiguous, but the ideal of exploring whether human physiology could utilize future information anticipated one of the principal developments in research on psi and human physiology in recent years [see chapter 17, this volume]. The “orienting response” is a response to a change in the environment that has its roots in the emotional system’s preparation for possible action. It is the early stages of what can become the “fight or flight” response, which occurs when a threat is detected. It involves characteristic momentary changes in physiology, such as increased heart rate and an increased skinconductance response (SCR). The orienting response is commonly used to study the effects of emotional stimuli, for example, pictures, by monitoring SCR while the participant views pictures with varying levels of emotional or startling content. Typically, whenever the participant first sees a new picture, there will be an increase in SCR within a couple of seconds. If the picture is not particularly emotional, a chair for example, the response will be negligible, but if it is shocking, such as a close-up accident scene, the SCR will be large. In the 1990s, Dean Radin looked at the orienting response to see if there might be evidence of precognition in this fundamentally unconscious and life-preserving bodily reaction. To do this, he used the standard experimental design of presenting calm and startling pictures to participants. In addition to looking at the expected SCR after the picture was flashed, he looked at it just seconds before it was flashed. In a series of increasingly sophisticated studies controlling for anticipation and other artifacts, Radin found small but significant evidence that his participants’ physiology anticipated the shocking pictures (Radin, 1997, 2004a). This effect, called “presentiment,” has been replicated by other investigators and extended to other areas of physiology, becoming one of the more important research areas in parapsychology. Brain Activity and Psi The situation regarding alpha waves and psi remains ambiguous, with very little additional research to report. One single-subject study supported the relation between higher alpha wave production and more successful performance in psi tasks (Alexander, Persinger, Roll, & Webster, 1998). May (2000) reported that a study of three top remote viewers showed no increase in alpha during successful trials. Another brain-wave band, however, has attracted the attention of a small team of researchers. After noting that a special participant had displayed larger amounts of 40 Hz (gamma) waves while in a mental state that he identified as one of his “psychic” states, McDonough, Don, and Warren (1988) were able to classify correct versus incorrect guesses by the presence of these 40 Hz waves. This led to part of a broader study in which 20 frequent gamblers performed a forced-choice precognition test, in which greater power in the 40 Hz band was associated with the correct responses to a significant degree (McDonough, Don, & Warren, 2000). The role of gamma waves in the brain is not well understood, but they are thought to coordinate focused attention, particularly with visual stimuli, across the brain as a whole, and a recent overview suggests gamma activity may overlap with muscle activity, reviving the issue of relaxation and psi (Muthukumaraswamy, 2013). No other researcher has explored the relation between psi function and gamma waves, so nothing conclusive can be said about this, as Don himself notes in a recent overview of his team’s research (Don, 2010), but recent evidence that higher frequency brain waves are associated with deeper—and possibly psi conducive—mental states continues to make this an intriguing research topic (cf. Cardeña, Jönsson, Terhune & Marcusson-Clavertz, 2013). Recent years have seen a number of efforts to use brain waves to detect evidence of a telepathic “signal” from one person to another using the event-related potential (ERP), a measurable brain response to a specific stimulus. In a simplified version, a researcher might stimulate one member of a pair of isolated respondents with a light flash, which causes an ERP in that person’s EEG record, and then look for evidence of the ERP in the other non-stimulated participant’s EEG. A successful outcome would suggest a telepathic link. A study by Grinberg-Zylberbaum, Delaflor, Attie, and Goswami (1994) examined the EEG recordings from seven pairs of sensory isolated individuals, while one of the pair was being stimulated with randomly spaced flashes of light. In one condition, the volunteers did not know each other and in the other condition they were introduced to one another and asked to meditate together to become “connected.” The flashes produced the expected visual evoked response (VEP) in the stimulated volunteer. The researchers claimed that a morphologically similar VEP was found in the EEG of the non-stimulated person, but only in the “connected” condition and when the interaction was “deemed successful” by the researchers. The similar-looking wave-forms in the non-stimulated person was called the “transferred potential.” Aspects of the methodology raised serious questions and the method of analysis has been severely criticized (May, Spottiswoode, & Faith, 2001), but the results were sufficiently intriguing to spark efforts to replicate the findings. Using improved methodology and statistics, Sabell, Clarke, and Fenwick (2001) failed to confirm Grinberg-Zylberbaum’s findings. However, other studies have found evidence of event-related correlations. Radin (2004b) found very significant correlations in ensemble EEG variance between 13 pairs of friends when one was stimulated with the video image of the other. Standish, Kozak, Johnson, and Richards (2004) stimulated one member (in turns) of 30 pairs of volunteers with a reversing black and white checkerboard pattern (stimulus on), comparing it with a static checkerboard (stimulus off). Using a conservative statistical analysis, they looked for evidence that the EEG pattern elicited by the two conditions in the stimulated person was replicated in that of the non-stimulated participant. Five of the 60 non-stimulated “receiver” individuals provided significant evidence of higher brain activation during their partner’s stimulus-on condition when compared to stimulus-off condition. A combined analysis of all 60 participants in the receiver condition yielded highly significant results for the stimulus-on condition, whereas the stimulus-off condition yielded chance results. Four of the five significant pairs were able to return for a replication study, and one pair was able to replicate their significant performance. A team led by Wackermann (Wackermann, Seiter, Keibel, & Walach, 2003) conducted a very careful replication of the original Grinberg-Zylberbaum study using a standard reversing checkerboard stimulus with 38 volunteers, divided into two groups of 14 experimental participants each and one group of 10 controls (who had no visual stimulation). One of the experimental groups consisted of pairs of emotionally close individuals, and the other of strangers. Using a robust and sophisticated analysis the Wackermann team found significant evidence of an increase in EEG power in the nonstimulated participants during the periods when the other person was stimulated; however this was not interpreted as a replication of the Grinberg-Zylberbaum study as there was no evidence of VEP-like waveform (or “transferred potential”) in the non-stimulated individuals. This was true for both experimental groups, suggesting that emotional bonding is not a necessary condition for the observed increase in EEG power in the nonstimulated member of the pair. The publication of this study in a mainstream journal attracted some thoughtful criticism (Kalitzin & Suffczynski, 2003) that was incorporated in a replication study with 16 pairs of emotionally close participants. This replication produced somewhat contradictory results that failed to replicate the original study (Wackermann, Naranjo Muradás, & Pütz, 2004). Finally, Ambach (2008) attempted a close replication of Wackermann’s studies using 17 pairs of related individuals. Arguing that previous statistical methods were likely to lead to an overestimation of significance, Ambach modified the analysis and found no deviation from chance in his data (Ambach, 2008). In recent years, fMRI (functional magnetic resonance imaging) has been used in a few instances in an effort to detect psi-based correlated brain activity in separated individuals. In a small pilot study with two participants, Standish, Johnson, Kozak, and Richards (2003) found that flickering checkerboard stimuli produced observable differences in the fMRI response (blood oxygenation) in the non-stimulated individual. A later study (Richards, Kozak, Johnson, & Standish, 2005) used two selected volunteers from a previous EEG study who alternated in the roles of stimulated and non-stimulated participant. Three of four sessions showed significant differential activation in visual brain areas of the non-stimulated person, but the low number of participants and the researchers’ use of a non-random (alternating) stimulus sequence raise questions about the generalizability of their findings. It should be noted in this context that using fMRI to localize brain activity for any psychological behavior, let alone psi, has come in for severe critical scrutiny in the mainstream literature (Fiedler, 2011; Vul, Harris, Winkielman, & Pashler, 2009). One recent fMRI study ambitiously attempted to resolve the “psi debate.” Moulton and Kosslyn (2008) designed a study based on the assumption that any event-synchronized psi-related activity must reveal itself in fMRI scans. Testing 19 volunteers in an unusually designed psi-task, not previously used in the field, they were unable to detect any evidence of psi in the receiver participant’s fMRI record. Although the authors recognize the logical argument that “absence of proof is not proof of absence,” (p. 183), they nonetheless concluded in the abstract that their own absence of positive findings “…are the strongest evidence yet obtained against the existence of paranormal mental phenomena” (p.182), making their paper in a high-profile journal something of an “Exhibit A” for the argument that mainstream journals have uneven refereeing standards. Can we say that the efforts to find psi-based event-related correlations have made progress? Although there has been improvement in methods and analyses, the results remain inconsistent at best and, as Wackermann observes in his critical review of the research, “The absence of a theoretical background as well as the divergence of experimental designs and methods are rather frustrating” (Wackermann, 2004, p. 119). Positive results are offered as a “proof of principle” that brains or minds can communicate (or be “entangled,” to use Radin’s terminology) without sensory connections, but what does that mean in ordinary life? If an experimenter flashes a checkerboard pattern at one person and another person’s brain shows more EEG activity at the same time, are we to assume that everyone’s brain is similarly affected, or only that one chosen by the experimenter? Clearly future research could benefit from a more clearly articulated theoretical framework (for a comprehensive overview of evidence of psi in human physiology see Modestino, 2013). Brain Structure and Psi When the previous volume was published, studies of brain hemisphere specialization were very much in vogue. Such studies sought to identify the particular types of mental processing for which each hemisphere was specialized. This extended to ESP research, in which there was a general feeling that the constellation of specializations associated with the right hemisphere were likely to facilitate ESP, although some researchers favored the idea that any evidence of hemisphere preference in psi is task dependent. Reviewing the evidence in 1983, I concluded that there was insufficient evidence to confirm either view (Broughton, 1984). Since then, there has been only one study addressing the issue. Alexander and Broughton (2001) classified participants in a ganzfeld experiment according to hemisphere dominance, the tendency to prefer the processing mode associated with one or the other brain hemisphere. Although the overall results produced nearly significant scoring, there was no difference between the left and right dominant groups. Thus, the evidence for brain hemisphere differences in the operation of ESP remains suggestive at best. A number of researchers have explored the relation between dysfunction in the temporal lobes of the brain and the tendency to report subjective paranormal experiences (SPEs). SPEs are experiences that the person deems to be paranormal, but there is no implication that they are necessarily veridical. Following hints from earlier research, the first systematic investigation of SPEs and temporal lobe dysfunction (TLD) was conducted by Neppe (1983), who compared six members of the South African SPR who reported numerous SPEs with six other members who did not. The six who reported numerous SPEs displayed significantly more possible symptoms of TLD than the control group. Persinger used similar assessment tools with two groups of university students. In both samples he found a significant positive correlation between the scores on the TLD battery and the number and variety of SPEs (Persinger, 1984). Subsequently, Persinger, who has suggested that micro-seizures in the temporal lobes may contribute to SPEs, conducted a replication that incorporated a measure of complex partial epileptic signs (CPES), and both the TLD and CPES measures revealed significant positive correlations with SPEs (Persinger & Vaillant, 1985). Most recently Palmer and Neppe have been investigating the relation between TLD and SPEs with clinical patients. In a carefully devised study, 60 patients with TLD reported significantly more SPEs than 27 patients who did not have TLD, with females reporting significantly more SPEs than males (Palmer & Neppe, 2003, 2004). Although the work of Neppe and Persinger is intriguing, it is constrained by the fact that there is yet no experimental evidence that TLD is associated with measures of psi function, only the respondents’ reports of their SPEs, and even the researchers admit that many of these findings are not very robust (Palmer & Neppe, 2003). Nonetheless, Palmer and Neppe (2003) do note some promising circumstantial evidence in that people in the artistic professions score high on Persinger’s TLD scales and are also among the best participants in ganzfeld ESP experiments. Recently Cardeña and Alvarado sounded a cautionary note regarding research using purported questionnaires of TLD; for instance Persinger’s Personal Philosophy Inventory, defined as a measure of temporal lobe lability, contains such items as keeping a diary or reciting poetry, which are, to say the least, unlikely specific measures of TLD (Cardeña & Alvarado, 2014, p 186). An even more speculative connection between psi and brain structure concerns the pineal gland, long thought in folklore and yogic traditions to have a role in mystical or parapsychological experiences. Roney-Dougal (1989) notes that the pineal gland produces or regulates a number of neurochemicals, particularly the common neurotransmitter serotonin, which at night is converted by the pineal gland into melatonin and pinoline. Pinoline is a β-carboline, and the pineal gland may also make or store other β-carboline compounds, which are similar to the active ingredients in ayahuasca and other concoctions used by shamans for visions and divination. Such shamanic divination while under the influence of these substances often includes ostensible examples of psi according to anthropologists’ reports (Roney-Dougal, 1989). The circadian rhythm of the pineal gland might also play a role in the observation that the largest percentage of spontaneous cases of ESP come during the night in dreams. Although there has yet been no experimental research to test RoneyDougal’s conjectures, they remain important because they have the potential to link the long tradition of anthropologists’ reports of induced psi experiences among indigenous peoples to neurophysiological processes that may facilitate conscious awareness of psi information in normal states. Environmental Influences on Psi via Biology Over the eons of evolution, human biology has adapted to the changing environmental influences in which it is bathed. The regular ones are reasonably well understood, but even basic adaptations including circadian rhythms continue to throw up surprises such as the differing sensitivities to medical interventions according to those rhythms. There are as well some less obvious sensitivities being investigated by scientists, such as whether humans react to magnetic fields, as do some animals. In the 1980s scientists began to investigate whether changing levels in the ongoing geomagnetic activity of the earth might affect psi. The earth’s magnetic field is not a static field and its activity varies considerably, primarily due to variations in solar activity such as sunspots and solar flares. Variability due to solar influences is termed GMA (geomagnetic activity). Adams (1986, 1987) first reported a relation between GMA in remote viewing and ganzfeld research, namely that better psi scores were obtained when GMA was low (quiet magnetic field). This sparked a continuing flow of studies that examined the relation between GMA and various measures of laboratory and spontaneous psi. Despite much diversity in the studies and measures, the general finding was that better ESP is associated with quieter periods of GMA. There were also suggestions that higher GMA was associated with poltergeist cases. At best, the effects are very weak, but sufficiently persistent to warrant further attention [see chapter 14, this volume]. The Importance of an Evolutionary Framework It is probably an indication of the then prevailing view of psi that the 1977 edition of the Handbook contained the word “evolution” on only two of its roughly 900 pages, and those were in Wolman’s philosophical chapter on mind and body near the end of the book (Wolman, 1977). As I observed in 1987, few parapsychologists consider why humans should have those abilities we call psi, or how they would have come by them (Broughton, 1988), a notable exception being Rex Stanford, whose seminal thinking reflected in his psi-mediated instrumental response (PMIR) model and its successors (Stanford, 1974, 1990) was a primer for my thinking on the topic [see chapter 8, this volume]. For the purposes of this section I shall limit my discussion to ESP or “receptive psi.” Whether the large body of experimental PK research is a separate phenomenon remains an open question (May, Utts, & Spottiswoode, 1995), and I do not expect all the phenomena currently covered by the term parapsychology necessarily to be understood within one framework. If we are to take psi ability, however extraordinary it may seem, seriously as an ability, there is only one way humans could have acquired that ability—through evolution, which has endowed humans with all the other abilities that we take for granted. For psi ability to fit into an evolutionary model, it must serve to increase our fitness to breed and survive, and to help ensure the survival of our offspring. Can we support the argument that psi serves such an important function by looking at what could be its evolutionary building blocks? Looking at spontaneous cases, one might be tempted to think that a communication function is self-evident, but that does not stand up to close scrutiny, as the “communication” more often than not is very fragmentary and unreliable. According to Stanford’s PMIR model (Stanford, 1974, 1990), ESP is part of a system that gathers useful information to serve human needs, but what those needs are is not specified in the model. When, following Stanford’s initiative, I argued that ESP must be seen in an evolutionary context (Broughton, 1988), I was not able to be any more specific than Stanford about the needs it serves. Since then, there has been only limited interest in the usefulness of psi. Taylor (2003) offers a comprehensive analysis of “need-serving” theories of psi within an evolutionary context. He concludes that an evolved ESP ability would necessarily be limited or imperfect and would probably operate through an environmental scanning type of mechanism. Taylor’s scanning mechanism, however, is not an active one, but rather “being in a state receptive to any information that may serve the needs of the organism” (Taylor, 2003, p. 11). McClenon (2002), on the other hand, plays down what he calls “direct benefit” theories in favor of an evolutionary model based on indirect and largely psychological benefits that would arise from beliefs in the efficacy of healing and similar paranormal phenomena. To advance an evolutionary understanding of psi we must identify the specific and significant advantages that it might convey. For humans, this will be more than just knowing where food can be found or predators lurk. As early hominins gained mastery over their environment, social competition between and within groups generated selective pressures for increased intelligence, development of a theory of mind, and the memory capacity to entertain alternative future scenarios and predict others’ behavior (Finn, Geary, & Ward, 2005). Although an evolutionary advantage must be significant, it need not be a big advantage. Haldane (1927) has calculated that just a 1 percent advantage could spread throughout the population within the evolutionary time period for our own genus, homo. Among psi researchers there is a growing consensus that the fundamental form of receptive psi is precognition and other aspects of ESP can be subsumed within this. This derives not only from theoretical models of the phenomena (Bierman, 2010; May, Utts, & Spottiswoode, 1995) but also from the simple realization that any ESP experience is not really seen as anomalous until some point in the future when the experience is confirmed by an event or additional information arrives through normal channels. Thus, the fundamental extrasensory perception is that of seeing the future, but not just any future. It is seeing one’s own future. If psi has evolved to provide some information of the future, it need not produce miracles to provide sufficient evolutionary advantage for selection to work. The dramatic cases that attract our attention may not be at all typical of the “normal” operation of psi (Broughton, 1988; Taylor, 2003). More typical may be the hunches, feelings, or dreams that make sense only when some future event provides corroboration, and many more may go unnoticed. In the research realm, meta-analyses of the more successful research lines have shown the effect sizes to be very small. The famed Star Gate psychic espionage program was said even by its supporters to have yielded actionable intelligence in only about 15 percent of the real-world cases in which it was used (May, 1996), but when used as an adjunct to traditional intelligence methods it was valuable [chapter 29, this volume]. This same perspective can be applied to ESP within the individual—it is not a magic window into the future, but an occasional extra input to our normal information gathering systems. The operation of psi may not be useful all of the time, but it would have to be useful with sufficient frequency to be seen as an advantage by evolutionary selection. The result might be that psi would be virtually indistinguishable from normal intuition. Recent developments in evolutionary psychology have provided some important clues as to how psi fits into an evolutionary framework. Suddendorf and Corballis (2007) have highlighted the role of what they call mental time travel (MTT) in human evolution. Mental time travel is nothing more than our capacity to imagine the future. There is growing evidence that mental time travels into the past—memory—and into the future— planning—are closely related both behaviorally and neurologically (Viard et al., 2011). According to Suddendorf and Corballis (2007, p. 299), “the ultimate evolutionary advantage must lie with the capacity to access the future.” They make a compelling argument for the evolutionary importance of MTT. The increased behavioral flexibility that humans have by means of their ability to imagine, and therefore prepare for, the future seems selfevidently an evolutionary advantage of the utmost importance. They go so far as to argue that our capacity for revisiting our past in memory is essentially a by-product of evolution’s pressure to be able to predict the future (Suddendorf & Corballis, 2007, p. 302). There are important components common to both MTT and the little we know about psi. MTT uses episodic memories as the building blocks for its generated future scenarios. ESP has long been recognized to be based on episodic memory (Roll, 1966). I have argued, independently of MTT, that the experiences of ESP are assembled from memories and fragments of memories to convey the anomalous information (Broughton, 2006). The fragmentary and malleable nature of episodic memory may be crucial to its evolutionary adaptiveness by providing a flexible “vocabulary” of memory images from which possible futures can be assembled (Suddendorf & Corballis, 2007, p. 303). Another requirement for MTT, according to Suddendorf and Corballis, is the capacity for offline processing, the ability to disconnect mental representational space from constant sensory input so that memories can be brought forward and combined into future scenarios. Suddendorf and Corballis (2007, p. 307) offer dreaming and daydreaming as examples of the offline capacity to assemble memories and merge them with recent input to represent the future. Spontaneous case collections have shown that ESP is most likely to occur during dreaming, followed closely by daydream-like states. Parapsychology’s most successful research programs, the Maimonides dream studies (Ullman, Krippner, & Vaughan, 1989), ganzfeld experiments (Hyman, 2010; Storm, Tressoldi, & Di Risio, 2010a, 2010b), and the U.S. government’s remote viewing program (May, 1996) all explicitly cultivate offline processing. Offline processing seems fundamental to utilizing psi in both laboratory and life, and the role of psi seems less like a communication channel and more like an assistive technology for improved planning and decision making along the lines suggested by decision augmentation theory (May et al., 1995) [see chapter 13, this volume]. The emotional system plays a role in the MTT process as well. Research by D’Argembeau and Van der Linden (2007) suggests that the emotional weighting of memories contributes to their likelihood of entering the recombinatorial process that is MTT and, as proposed by Damasio (1994), to the emotional weighting relating to an individual’s goals. Considerable, though largely circumstantial, evidence suggests that a similar process generates psi experiences, especially through the emotional components of dreaming and the generation of anomalous feelings, including somatic ones such as those in the case that opened this chapter (Broughton, 2006). The presentiment studies described by Radin in this book provide more direct evidence for the involvement of the emotional system in ESP. The evolutionary framework sketched here covers only half of the process involved in psi. Understanding the other half of the process—how events in the future bring about what we recognize as psi in human behavior—is arguably more of a challenge, and one that most likely falls within the purview of physics. One such effort that neatly meshes with an evolutionary framework is Bierman’s consciousness induced restoration of time symmetry (CIRTS) model, which proposes that the brain processes that sustain consciousness amount to a special system that restores time symmetry (inherent in physics formalisms) and allows “advanced” waves (coming from the future) to occur (Bierman, 2010). What evidence is there of an evolutionary process for psi? The simple answer is, not much, but that is probably because hardly any parapsychologists have looked for it. There is a tradition of anecdotal reports suggesting heritability that are backed up by one large survey of Scottish “second sight” (Cohn, 1994). Several independent ganzfeld experiment data sets have shown substantially better results when relatives are used as the sender/receiver pairs, with parent-child and sibling pairs doing far better than others, including spousal pairs (Broughton & Alexander, 1997). The principal objection to evolved psi is the idea that if evolution were responsible for psi ability then it should be more highly developed and more effective than what we find. At least one philosopher sees this as a convincing argument for a dualist worldview (Levin, 1996). This sort of argument is not particularly strong, as it is based on the dubious assumption that evolution should produce something that conforms to our naïve notion of what effective psi should look like. Several answers can be offered to counter that objection. The first is that psi ability as we see it is the result of the optimum functioning that can be derived from the underlying mechanism. At present we have no idea what the underlying mechanism might be, but should it be along the lines suggested by the CIRTS model (Bierman, 2010) then we might be dealing with relatively weak correlational processes (between present and future states) rather than a direct causal process that evolution could have “scaled up” for strong effects. So, in effect, what we see of psi ability might be as good as it gets, but still enough to confer an evolutionary advantage. A second answer is that psi ability is functioning at a level appropriate to an evolutionarily stable strategy (ESS), which is a pattern of behavior (strategy) that, if employed by all members of society, cannot be bested by another strategy (see Broughton, 1988 for an elaboration in the context of ESP). A final possible answer is that anomalous information may not have been evolving so very long. Suddendorf and Corballis (2007, p. 312) argue that mental time travel may have evolved comparatively recently, principally as a result of an evolutionary “arms race” of cognitive and social abilities driven by intra-species and perhaps intra-genus competition. If psi ability amounts to a supporting subsystem of MTT, then its evolutionary history may be correspondingly short. Summary and Conclusions Unfortunately, a further three and a half decades of admittedly sporadic research on neurobiology and psi have not advanced the field any further than the cautious position of the earlier chapter by Morris. Methodology continues to improve, but few conclusions can be drawn. Much of the research continues to try to use physiological measures as an indicator that “psi happened” and typically yields ambiguous results about which a pessimistic observer may wonder if there really is any signal emerging from the statistical noise. Yet, some research lines have emerged that do hold promise. These are the presentiment research, covered by Radin in this volume, and the possible influence of geomagnetic variation on psi ability covered by Ryan in this volume, both of which have the potential to help understand the biological processes that underpin psi ability. To begin to understand the connection between biology and psi research, we must move from the “how does psi affect biology” approach of the past and look more for how biology begets psi, how what we term psi ability arises from human (and perhaps animal) biology, and to that end there is no scientifically viable alternative than to use an evolutionary framework to guide the search. Clearly research into the neurobiological processes that underlie psi ability must continue, but we must do more to avoid “spinning our wheels” with inconclusive findings. To be taken seriously, future research must adhere to the changing standards for experimental design and study preregistration that are sweeping the medical and psychological sciences (Cardeña, 2014; Eich, 2014). We know too little about the neurobiological mechanisms that must be investigated to be specific, so the particular research questions will depend on the ingenuity of the researcher. However, from my perspective the most profitable questions will be informed by a thorough consideration of the evolutionary context in which psi has emerged and the adaptive needs it serves. References Adams, M. H. (1986). Variability in remote-viewing performance: Possible relationship to the geomagnetic field. In D. H. Weiner and D. I. Radin (Eds.), Research in parapsychology 1985 (p. 25). Metuchen, NJ: Scarecrow Press. Adams, M. H. (1987). Persistent temporal relationship of ganzfeld results to geomagnetic activity, appropriateness of using standard geomagnetic indices. In D. H. Weiner and R. D. Nelson (Eds.), Research in parapsychology 1986 (p. 78). Metuchen, NJ: Scarecrow Press. Alexander, C. H., and Broughton, R. S. (2001). Cerebral hemisphere dominance and ESP performance in the autoganzfeld. Journal of Parapsychology, 65, 397–416. Alexander, C. H., Persinger, M. A., Roll, W. G., and Webster, D. L. (1998). EEG and SPECT data of a selected subject during psi tasks: The discovery of a neurophysiological correlate. In Proceedings of Presented Papers: The Parapsychological Association 41st Annual Convention (p. 3–13). Durham, NC: Parapsychological Association, Inc. Ambach, W. (2008). Correlations between the EEGs of two spatially separated subjects: A replication study. European Journal of Parapsychology, 23, 131–146. Bierman, D. J. (2010). Consciousness induced restoration of time symmetry (CIRTS): A psychophysical theoretical perspective. Journal of Parapsychology, 74, 273–299. Broughton, R. S. (1984). Brain hemisphere specialization and ESP: What have we learned? In R. A. White and R. S. Broughton (Eds.), Research in parapsychology 1983 (pp. 2–4). Metuchen, NJ: Scarecrow Press. Broughton, R. S. (1988). If you want to know how it works, first find out what it’s for. In Research in parapsychology 1987 (pp. 187–202). Metuchen, N.J.: Scarecrow Press. Broughton, R. S. (2006). Memory, emotion and the receptive psi process. Journal of Parapsychology, 70, 255–274. Broughton, R. S., and Alexander, C. H. (1997). Autoganzfeld II: An attempted replication of the PRL ganzfeld research. Journal of Parapsychology, 61, 209–226. Cardeña, E. (2014). A call for an open, informed study of all aspects of consciousness. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 8. doi:10.3389/fnhum.2014.00017 Cardeña, E., and Alvarado, C. (2014). Anomalous self and identity experiences. In E. Cardeña, S. J., Lynn, and S. Krippner (Eds.), Varieties of anomalous experience: Examining the scientific evidence (2nd ed.) (pp. 175–212). Washington, D.C.: American Psychological Association. Cardeña, E., Jönsson, P., Terhune, D. B., and Marcusson-Clavertz, D. (2013). The neurophenomenology of neutral hypnosis. Cortex, 49, 375– 385. doi:10.1016/j.cortex.2012.04.001 Chauvin, R. (1986). A PK experiment with mice. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 53, 348–351. Cohn, S. A. (1994). A survey of Scottish second sight. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 59, 385–400. Cooper, N. R., Croft, R. J., Dominey, S. J. J., Burgess, A. P., and Gruzelier, J. H. (2003). Paradox lost? Exploring the role of alpha oscillations during externally vs. internally directed attention and the implications for idling and inhibition hypotheses. International Journal of Psychophysiology, 47, 65–7. D’Argembeau, A., and Van der Linden, M. (2007). Emotional aspects of mental time travel. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 30, 320–321. doi:10.1017/S0140525X07002051 Damasio, A. R. (1994). Descartes’ error: Emotion, reason, and the human brain. New York: G. P. Putnam’s Sons. Don, N. S. (2010). Electrical activity in the brain and the extraordinary mind. In S. Krippner and H. L. Friedman (Eds.), Mysterious minds: The neurobiology of psychics, mediums, and other extraordinary people (pp. 113–127). Santa Barbara, CA: Praeger. Dutton, D., and Williams, C. (2009). Clever beasts and faithful pets: A critical review of animal psi research. Journal of Parapsychology, 73, 43– 70. Eich, E. (2014). Business not as usual. Psychological Science, 25, 3–6. doi:10.1177/0956797613512465 Fiedler, K. (2011). Voodoo correlations are everywhere—Not only in neuroscience. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 6(2), 163–171. doi:10.1177/1745691611400237 Finn, M. V., Geary, D. C., and Ward, C. V. (2005). Ecological dominance, social competition, and coalitionary arms races: Why humans evolved extraordinary intelligence. Evolution and Human Behavior, 26, 10–46. doi:10.1016/j.evolhumbehav.2004.08.005 Green, P. R., and Thorpe, P. H. (1993). Tests for PK effects in imprinted chicks. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 59, 48–60. Grinberg-Zylberbaum, J., Delaflor, M., Attie, L., and Goswami, A. (1994). The Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen paradox in the brain: The transferred potential. Physics Essays, 7, 422–428. Haldane, J. B. S. (1927). A mathematical theory of natural and artificial selection, Part V: Selection and mutation. Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society, 23, 838–844. Hartwell, J. W. (1978). Contingent negative variation as an index of precognitive information. European Journal of Parapsychology, 2, 83–103. Hartwell, J. W. (1979). An extension to the CNV study and an evaluation. European Journal of Parapsychology, 2, 358–364. Hyman, R. (2010). Meta-analysis that conceals more than it reveals: Comment on Storm et al. (2010). Psychological Bulletin, 136, 486–490. doi:10.1037/a0019676 Johnson, M. H. (1989). Imprinting and ANPSI: An attempt to replicate Peoc’h. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 55, 417–419. Kalitzin, S., and Suffczynski, P. (2003). Comments on “Correlations between brain electrical activities of two spatially separated human subjects,” Wackermann et al., Neuroscience Letters, 336(2003) 60–64. Neuroscience Letters, 350(3), 193–194. doi:10.1016/S0304– 3940(03)00872–3 Kennedy, J. E., and Taddonio, J. L. (1976). Experimenter effects in parapsychological research. Journal of Parapsychology, 40, 1–33. Klimesch, W. (2012). Alpha-band oscillations, attention, and controlled access to stored information. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 16, 606–17. Levin, J., and Kennedy, J. (1975). The relationship of slow cortical potentials to psi information in man. Journal of Parapsychology, 39, 25–26. Levin, M. (1996). On the lack of evidence for the evolution of psi as an argument against the reality of the paranormal. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 90, 221–230. May, E. C. (1996). The American Institutes for Research review of the Department of Defense’s Star Gate program: A commentary. Journal of Parapsychology, 60, 3–23. May, E. C. (2000). ESP and the brain: Current status. In Behind and beyond the brain: Exceptional experiences (pp. 321–352). Porto, Portugal: Bial Foundation. May, E. C., Spottiswoode, S. J. P., and Faith, L. V. (2001). A methodological issue in the study of correlation between psychophysiological variables. In Proceedings of the 44th Annual Convention of the Parapsychological Association (pp. 166–178). May, E. C., Utts, J. M., and Spottiswoode, S. J. P. (1995). Decision augmentation theory: Toward a model of anomalous mental phenomena. Journal of Parapsychology, 59, 195–220. McClenon, J. (2002). Content analysis of an anomalous experience collection: Evaluating evolutionary perspectives. Journal of Parapsychology, 66, 291–316. McDonough, B. E., Don, N. S., and Warren, C. A. (1988). EEG frequency domain analysis during a clairvoyant task in a single-subject design: An exploratory study. In Proceedings of the 31st Annual Convention of the Parapsychological Association (pp. 124–132). McDonough, B. E., Don, N. S., and Warren, C. A. (2000). Gamma band (“40 Hz”) EEG and unconscious target detection in a psi task. Journal of Parapsychology, 64, 247. Modestino, E. J. (2013). Physiological responses as unconscious measures of psi. In S. Krippner, A. J. Rock, J. Beischel, H. L. Friedman, and C. L. Fracasso (Eds.), Advances in parapsychological research 9 (pp. 126–157). Jefferson, NC: McFarland. Morris, R. L. (1977). Parapsychology, biology and ANPSI. In B. B. Wolman (Ed.), Handbook of parapsychology (pp. 687–715). Jefferson, NC: McFarland. Moulton, S. T., and Kosslyn, S. M. (2008). Using neuroimaging to resolve the psi debate. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 20, 182–192. doi:10.1162/jocn.2008.20009 Muthukumaraswamy, S. D. (2013). High-frequency brain activity and muscle artifacts in MEG/EEG: A review and recommendations. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 7. doi:10.3389/fnhum.2013.00138 Neppe, V. M. (1983). Temporal lobe symptomatology in subjective paranormal experients. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 77, 1–29. Palmer, J., and Neppe, V. M. (2003). A controlled analysis of subjective paranormal experiences in temporal lobe dysfunction in a neuropsychiatric population. Journal of Parapsychology, 67, 75–98. Palmer, J., and Neppe, V. M. (2004). Exploratory analyses of refined predictors of subjective ESP experiences and temporal lobe dysfunction in a neuropsychiatric population. European Journal of Parapsychology, 19, 44– 65. Peoc’h, R. (1988). Chicken imprinting and the tychoscope: An ANPSI experiment. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 55, 1–9. Peoc’h, R. (1995). Psychokinetic action of young chicks on the path of an illuminated source. Journal of Scientific Exploration, 9, 223–229. Persinger, M. A. (1984). Propensity to report paranormal experiences is correlated with temporal lobe signs. Perceptual and Motor Skills, 59, 583– 586. Persinger, M. A., and Vaillant, P. M. (1985). Temporal lobe signs and reports of subjective paranormal experiences in a normal population: A replication. Perceptual and Motor Skills, 60, 903–909. Radin, D. I. (1997). Unconscious perception of future emotions: An experiment in presentiment. Journal of Scientific Exploration, 11, 163–180. Radin, D. I. (2004a). Electrodermal presentiments of future emotions. Journal of Scientific Exploration, 18, 253–274. Radin, D. I. (2004b). Event-related electroencephalographic correlations between isolated human subjects. Journal of Alternative & Complementary Medicine, 10, 315–323. Rhine, J. B. (1974). Comments: A new case of experimenter unreliability. Journal of Parapsychology, 38, 215–225. Rhine, J. B., and Feather, S. R. (1962). The study of cases of “psi-trailing” in animals. Journal of Parapsychology, 26, 1–22. Rhine, L. E. (1961). Hidden channels of the mind. New York: William Morrow. Richards, T. L., Kozak, L., Johnson, L. C., and Standish, L. J. (2005). Replicable functional magnetic resonance imaging evidence of correlated brain signals between physically and sensory isolated subjects. Journal of Alternative & Complementary Medicine, 11, 955–963. Roll, W. G. (1966). ESP and memory. International Journal of Neuropsychiatry, 2, 505–521. Roney-Dougal, S. M. (1989). Recent findings relating to the possible role of the pineal gland in affecting psychic ability. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 55, 313–328. Sabell, A., Clarke, C., and Fenwick, P. (2001). Inter-subject EEG correlations at a distance: The transferred potential. In Proceedings of the 44th Annual Convention of the Parapsychological Association (pp. 419– 422). New York: Parapsychological Association, Inc. Sheldrake, R. (1999). Dogs that know when their owners are coming home and other unexplained powers of animals. London, UK: Hutchinson. Standish, L. J., Johnson, L. C., Kozak, L., and Richards, T. (2003). Evidence of correlated functional magnetic resonance imaging signals between distant human brains. Alternative Therapies in Health and Medicine, 9(1), 122–128. Standish, L. J., Kozak, L., Johnson, L. C., and Richards, T. (2004). Electroencephalographic evidence of correlated event-related signals between the brains of spatially and sensory isolated human subjects. Journal of Alternative & Complementary Medicine, 10, 307–314. Stanford, R. G. (1974). An experimentally testable model for spontaneous psi events: I. Extrasensory events. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 68, 34–57. Stanford, R. G. (1990). An experimentally testable model for spontaneous psi events: A review of related evidence and concepts from parapsychology and other sciences. In S. Krippner (Ed.), Advances in parapsychological research 6 (pp. 54–167). Jefferson, NC: McFarland. Storm, L., Tressoldi, P. E., and Di Risio, L. (2010a). A meta-analysis with nothing to hide: Reply to Hyman (2010). Psychological Bulletin, 136, 491– 494. Storm, L., Tressoldi, P. E., and Di Risio, L. (2010b). Meta-analysis of freeresponse studies, 1992–2008: Assessing the noise reduction model in parapsychology. Psychological Bulletin, 136, 471–485. Suddendorf, T., and Corballis, M. C. (2007). The evolution of foresight: What is mental time travel, and is it unique to humans? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 30, 299–313. Taylor, R. (2003). Evolutionary theory and psi: Reviewing and revising some need-serving models in psychic functioning. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 67, 1–17. Ullman, M., Krippner, S., and Vaughan, A. (1989). Dream telepathy: Experiments in nocturnal ESP. Jefferson, NC: McFarland. Viard, A., Chételat, G., Lebreton, K., Desgranges, B., Landeau, B., de La Sayette, V., … Piolino, P. (2011). Mental time travel into the past and the future in healthy aged adults: An fMRI study. Brain and Cognition, 75, 1–9. Vul, E., Harris, C., Winkielman, P., and Pashler, H. (2009). Puzzlingly high correlations in fMRI studies of emotion, personality, and social cognition. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 4, 274–290. Wackermann, J. (2004). Dyadic correlations between brain functional states: Present facts and future perspectives. Mind and Matter, 2(1), 105– 122. Wackermann, J., Naranjo Muradás, J. R., and Pütz, P. (2004). Event-related correlations between brain electrical activities of separated human subjects: Preliminary results of a replication study. In Proceedings of the 47th Annual Convention of the Parapsychological Association (pp. 465–468). Vienna, Austria. Wackermann, J., Seiter, C., Keibel, H., and Walach, H. (2003). Correlations between brain electrical activities of two spatially separated human subjects. Neuroscience Letters, 336, 60–64. White, R. A. (1976a). The influence of persons other than the experimenter in the subject’s scores on psi experiments. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 70, 133–166. White, R. A. (1976b). The limits of experimenter influence of psi test results: Can any be set? Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 70, 333–369. Wolman, B. B. (1977). Mind and body: A contribution to a theory of parapsychological phenomena. In B. B. Wolman (Ed.), Handbook of parapsychology (pp. 861–879). Jefferson, NC: McFarland. OceanofPDF.com CHAPTER 12 Drugs and Psi Phenomena DAVID LUKE This chapter investigates the relation between psychoactive substances and psi phenomena falling within the study of parapsychology. It is only concerned with so-called extrasensory perception (ESP)—telepathy, precognition, and clairvoyance as opposed to other non-psi phenomena, such as out-of-body experiences (which are reviewed in Luke, 2012). Psychokinesis (PK) makes only a very limited contribution to this review as it is seldom related to psychoactive drugs within the literature. The chapter borrows widely, but by no means exhaustively, from parapsychology as well as transpersonal studies, anthropology, ethnobotany, phytochemistry, psychiatry, psychotherapy, psychopharmacology, and neurobiology, particularly neurochemistry. It is organized into sections relating to: the discussion of the chapter on drugs and altered states in the original Handbook, an overview of the variety and effects of psychoactive substances; neurochemical models of psi experience; field reports of intentional and spontaneous psi phenomena incorporating anthropological, historical and clinical cases, and personal accounts; surveys of paranormal belief and experiences; experimental psi research with drugs; a methodological critique of the experimental research with recommendations for further work; and a summary and conclusions. Drug-induced States of Consciousness in the Earlier Handbook Originally written by Charles Tart, the chapter remit of the first handbook differs somewhat from that of the current text in that it was originally positioned within Part V of the book dealing with Parapsychology and Altered States of Consciousness, and yet it focused primarily on handling and mapping altered states of consciousness (drug states in particular) but dealt only very cursorily with the demonstration of psi in these states. Tart’s chapter essentially condemned the literature on drugs and psi up until that point (1977), based on the assessment that all the research was methodologically flawed due to a limited understanding of individual differences in (psychedelic) drug experiences, particularly those due to set and setting rather than substance. The present chapter will continue where Tart left off with his, albeit very brief, overview of the experimental literature on psi and drugs and present a condensed review of all the research literature, not just the experimental findings, from its inception until the present day (for a more expanded review see Luke, 2012). An Overview of the Variety and Action of Psychoactive Substances This chapter focuses primarily on the class of psychoactive substances that largely induce visionary and intense consciousness altering experiences. For the purposes of this review I include drugs and sacramentals such as mescaline, lysergic acid diethylamide (LSD), psilocybin, ayahuasca, N,Ndimethyltryptamine (DMT), cannabis (which is treated here as a psychedelic), and ketamine, but not opiates or cocaine. This class of visionary substances has been termed differently by diverse authors, usually depending on the connotation they wish to convey about the psychoactive effects or how the substance is used. Within the literature reviewed here, they have been termed “mind-expanding” (e.g., Palmer, 1979), “psychodysleptic” (Cavanna & Servadio, 1964), and “hallucinogenic” (e.g., Lee & Roth, 2012). Finally, there is the most frequently used term, “psychedelic,” created in 1956 by Humphry Osmond (1961, p.76) and meaning “mind manifesting.” Where specified, the original term used by the authors will be preserved to reflect their orientation to the issue. Elsewhere, where appropriate, the more widely used and neutral term “psychedelic” will be used. A psychedelic substance is defined as: one which, without causing physical addiction, craving, major physiological disturbances, delirium, disorientation, or amnesia, more or less reliably produces thought, mood, and perceptual changes otherwise rarely experienced except in dreams, contemplative and religious exaltation, flashes of vivid involuntary memory, and acute psychoses [Grinspoon & Bakalar, 1998, p. 9]. However, this may not be strictly accurate as some substances that would otherwise fit in this group can be somewhat addictive—though perhaps not physically—such as ketamine, or some produce delirium, such as the nightshade plants. There are numerous substances (chemicals or biological matter) currently known to have psychedelic effects, with estimates of those that have been tried and tested running to about 350, and these have been increasing by an approximate factor of 10 every 50 years since 1900, when there were only two such substances known within academia (Shulgin, 2010), so this is an ever expanding field of study. Among these numerous substances there are several classes of known psychedelics, usually classified by their nearest neurochemical relative, main receptor site of action, or basic chemical structure. The most typical are the classical tryptamine and lysergamide drugs, which have a core structural profile like that of the neurotransmitter serotonin, including LSD, psilocybin, and DMT. The current broadest class of psychedelics, comprising some 2000+ chemicals (many untested), are the phenethylamines (Shulgin, Manning, & Daley, 2011), which are structurally more like dopamine and include mescaline, MDMA, amphetamine, and the 2C family of chemicals (e.g., 2CB). Then there is a class of dissociatives such as ketamine, phencyclidine (PCP), and dextromethorphan (DXM), which primarily act by binding to the N-methyl-D-aspartate (NMDA) receptor. Some of the oldest known European psychedelics belong to a class of tropane alkaloids, such as atropine, scopolamine, and hyoscyamine, derived from the Solanaceae (nightshade) family of psychedelic plants (e.g., henbane, belladonna, mandrake, and datura) and with anticholinergic neurochemical effects. There are also several other psychedelics that do not easily fit within these categories, such as the recently discovered salvinorin A, which is a kappaopioid agonist. An agonist activates a neurotransmitter receptor to produce a response, whereas antagonists, such as ketamine, which is an NMDA antagonist, block the action of an agonist. In some cases, the neurotransmitter systems targeted by particular drugs are well-known, as with the classical tryptamine psychedelics such as psilocybin, which are apparently selective 5HT2A partial agonists (Lee & Roth, 2012). The neural mechanisms involved continue to be debated, but a recent BOLD fMRI study (Carhart-Harris et al., 2012) showed that, contrary to expectations, psilocybin does not increase blood flow anywhere in the brain but decreases cerebral blood flow to key regions, specifically the thalamus, anterior and posterior cingulate cortex (ACC & PCC), and medial prefrontal cortex (mPFC), the latter two of which are crucial regions in the default mode network. Significantly, the usual positive coupling between the mPFC and the PCC is reduced during the intake of psilocybin. Not all drugs that have psychedelic effects are selective 5HT2A partial agonists, however, and some chemicals, known as promiscuous drugs, modulate a variety of neurotransmitters, or their mode of action remains uncertain—a good example of both types (Ray, 2010; Wallach, 2009) is N, N-dimethyltryptamine (DMT). Thus, the specific systems that possibly mediate the induction of psi and related parapsychological phenomena may be difficult to identify. However, a neurochemical taxonomy of action may be possible once more is known about the action of these chemicals and the specific types and features of paranormal experience that they induce (Luke & Kittenis, 2005). An Overview of Neurochemical Models of Psi Experience At least 18 different reasons have been documented for why the states induced by psychedelics may be conducive to parapsychological phenomena. These reasons include increases in mental imagery, empathy, absorption, attention, awareness, spontaneity, suggestibility and openness, access to unconscious thoughts or memories, and transcendence of space and time (for a review see Luke, 2012). Nevertheless, these factors remain entirely speculative as no systematic research on this has been conducted. In addition to these hypothesized state factors there a number of somewhat more elaborate neurochemical models of psi experience that are extant and are discussed in the following subsections. Brain as Filter The oldest, and indeed the simplest of these models pertains to the action of psychedelics in a general sense and was proposed by the writer Aldous Huxley following his mescaline experience with the psychiatrist Humphrey Osmond—the man responsible for coining the term psychedelic. Osmond also maintained that ESP was a proven fact and believed that psychedelics could be used to induce the phenomena, having had such experiences himself (Osmond, 1961; Osmond & Smythies, 1952). Huxley (1954) was prominent in promoting Henri Bergson’s (1896/1990) theory of the brain as a filter of memory and sensory experience that reduces the wealth of information available to awareness, lest people become overwhelmed by a mass of largely useless and irrelevant data not needed for survival. Bergson suggested that if these filters were bypassed, humans would be capable of remembering everything that had ever been experienced and perceiving everything that has happened everywhere in the universe (as in clairvoyance). Nevertheless, it was Huxley who applied this theory to psychedelics by suggesting that these mind-manifesting drugs override what he called the “reducing valve” of the brain (Huxley, 1954, p.12), allowing humans access to both psychic and mystical experiences. Huxley (1954) eruditely paraphrased this notion with the quote by the English poet and mystic William Blake (1793/1906): “If the doors of perception were cleansed, every thing would appear to man as it is, infinite.” Huxley’s (1954) rather basic conception never received a more formal operationalization of the specific drug actions that might be involved, but research into the neurochemistry of psychedelics lends some support to his notion. For instance, Vollenweider and Geyer (2001) proposed that information processing in cortico-striato-thalamo-cortical (CSTC) feedback loops is disrupted by psychedelics via 5-HT (serotonin) receptor agonism (specifically 5-HT2A receptors). This disruption thereby might inhibit the “gating” of extraneous sensory stimuli and inhibit the ability to attend selectively to salient environmental features. Furthermore, psychedelics are also thought to induce presynaptic release of glutamate from thalamic afferents, leading to a simultaneous overload of internal information in the cortex. It is thought that these combined information overload effects are at least partly responsible for the “hallucinogenic” experience with these drugs, which are known to induce greatly altered or amplified incoming sensory information, as is indicated behaviorally by an increased startle effect (Vollenweider, 2001). Furthermore, the results of brain-imaging research discussed above (CarhartHarris et al., 2012) indicate that under the influence of psilocybin there is no single brain region that increases in activity, but the brain’s activity is reduced overall. Significantly, the usual positive coupling between the mPFC and the PCC—which forms part of the default mode network thought to be important in introspection and high-level constructs such as self and ego—was reduced, leading to “a state of unconstrained cognition” (CarhartHarris et al., 2012, p. 2138). This psychedelic disruption of the sensory gating function discussed by Vollenweider (2001), and the reduction of activity in the default mode network discussed by Carhart-Harris et al. (2012), could also underpin the neurobiology of ESP. Such neurobiological processes may apply whether elicited by any number of psychedelics or without the intervention of such exogenous chemicals, though perhaps via endogenous chemicals such as DMT. Some support for this is starting to emerge as brain imaging studies have begun to explore exotic mental states, with no increase overall and similar reductions in brain activity being found, for instance, in the ACC and mPFC with experienced automatic writing trance mediums (Peres et al., 2012), and a reduced global functional connectivity across the cortex associated with transcendental experiences in deep hypnosis without suggestion (Cardeña, Jönsson, Terhune, & Marcusson-Clavertz, 2013). Indeed, like psychedelics, psi experiences and events have variously been conceptualized in relation to an inhibition of the ordinary sensory inhibition, such as with latent disinhibition (Holt, Simmonds-Moore, & Moore 2008), transliminality (Thalbourne, 1998), boundary thinness and schizotypy (Simmonds & Roe, 2000), and self-expansiveness (Friedman, 1983). It may be noted that psychedelics have also been long associated with both creativity (e.g., Krippner, 1985) and psychotic experiences (Osmond & Smythies, 1952), although, as with paranormal experience (for an overview see Irwin, 2009), the use of psychedelics is not related epidemiologically to poor mental health (Krebs & Johansen, 2013). Ultimately, despite the simplistic appeal of the anti-reducing valve action of psychedelics as a neurochemical model of psi, considerable gaps remain in our current understanding of the neuropharmacological action of psychedelics in humans. Since the early 1970s and until relatively recently, practically all psychedelic research had been conducted with animals, and no definitive generalizations can be made about the main neurotransmitter receptor sites involved, as psychedelics vary considerably in their chemical makeup and their ligand affinity (Ray, 2010). However, electrophysiology and receptor studies have revealed that both NMDA antagonists (e.g., ketamine) and classic serotonergic psychedelics (e.g., LSD) may actually enhance glutamatergic transmission via non– NMDA receptors in the frontal cortex. Such dual action may indicate a common mode of chemical action in the brain, responsible for similar experiences with such divergent molecules (Vollenweider, 2004). This serotonin/glutamate receptor-complex model of drug action is receiving high-profile attention. Despite the lack of understanding of the neurobiology of psychedelic action, and the lack of generalizability across so many diverse substances, recent advances would appear to support the Bergson-Huxley notion of the brain as a filter capable of being deactivated by chemicals. Furthermore, this notion, including the parts pertaining to ESP, is now gaining ground once more among theorists of consciousness (e.g., Kastrup, 2012). Indeed, recent theoretical developments (Smythies, 2011) suggest that NMDA antagonism, such as via ketamine, bypasses the reducing valve/filter action of the brain. Pineal Gland Neurochemistry Model Advancing on earlier suggestions about the pineal gland’s involvement in psi (e.g., Miller, 1978), Roney-Dougal (1986, 1989, 1991, 2001) has developed an endogenous neurochemical perspective of psi based on the action of the pineal and several hallucinogenic substances found in ayahuasca, the visionary Amazonian brew reported to induce a range of paranormal experiences. The common neurotransmitter serotonin is known to be most active in the pineal gland, where it follows a circadian rhythm and is converted at night into melatonin (5-methoxy tryptamine, or 5MT), and the β-carboline, pinoline (6-methoxy tetrahydro-β-carboline, or 6-MeO-THβC), which regulate sleep cycles. The pineal gland may also create other β-carbolines, that block the neuronal uptake of serotonin, making it available for use, and inhibit the enzyme monoamine oxydase (MAO). Certain tryptamines, such as N,N-dimethyl tryptamine (N,N-DMT, or simply DMT) and 5-methoxy tryptamine (5-MeODMT), are broken down by MAO. MAO inhibiters, such as pinoline or the harmala alkaloids, make serotonin available at the pineal gland. Strassman (2001) speculated that there, with the aid of methyl transferase enzymes, serotonin can also be converted into 5-MeO-DMT, DMT, and bufotenine (5hydroxy-N,N-dimethyltryptamine, 5-HO-DMT), endogenous visionary substances also found in certain ingredients (such as Psychotria viridis) of ayahuasca brews and other shamanic visionary substances. In vivo biosynthesis of DMT might also occur through the conversion of the common, nutritionally essential amino acid tryptophan (Jacob & Presti, 2005; Shulgin & Shulgin, 1997). However, these endogenous visionary tryptamines are not orally active, as they are denatured by the MAO enzymes present in the stomach; but ayahuasca brews also contain plant additives (such as Banisteriopsis caapi) containing a range of harmala alkaloids that inhibit MAO and allow the complementarily ingested visionary tryptamines to be active in the brain. It is this action of the β-carbolines (particularly harmine) in ayahuasca that is considered their primary purpose as admixtures in the brew (e.g., McKenna, 2004), though this may not always be the case as subjectively potent ayahuasca decoctions occasionally do not contain DMT when analyzed (Callaway, 2005). Nevertheless, the harmala alkaloids are also known to induce visions themselves, and Roney-Dougal (1986, 1989, 1991, 2001) originally implicated β-carbolines, such as the endogenous pinoline and the exogenous harmala alkaloids, as inducing psi-conducive states, either naturally during dreams (Callaway, 1988) or artificially by causing waking dream states. She (2001) also later acknowledged that the β-carbolines may exert their visionary effects by potentiating the effects of ingested visionary tryptamines like DMT or 5-MeO-DMT when consumed in combination with them, as in ayahuasca. In essence, ayahuasca contains two types of visionary chemicals, one type (β-carbolines, e.g., harmine) that helps to both create and potentiate the effects of the other type (tryptamines, e.g., DMT), potentially mimicking the nocturnal chemistry of the pineal gland and its supposed control over natural visionary states such as dreams (Callaway, 1988), mystical experiences, and NDEs (Strassman, 2001). Roney-Dougal (1989, 1991, 2001) suggested that the pineal gland and its neurochemistry is important in the occurrence of psi phenomena and points to the association made by yogis between the pineal gland and the ajna chakra, the proposed yogic psychic center that controls psi-experiences in those with awakened kundalini (Miller, 1978; Satyananda, 1972). Naranjo (1987) noted that both kundalini and ayahuasca experiences, being similar in many respects, also feature the same serpentine imagery, further speculating that they probably have the same neurochemistry and result in the same “bioenergetic” activation, although this term is somewhat vague. Furthermore, manifestation of very specific body vibrations said to be classic kundalini symptoms are supposedly quite reliably induced with substances such as DPT (N,N-dipropyl-tryptamine) and 4-Acetoxy-DIPT (N,N-diisopropyl–4-acetoxy-tryptamine), which are even more obscure psychedelic tryptamines than DMT, but close relatives of it (Toad, 1999a, 1999b). Similarly, Grof (2001) has reported spontaneous kundalini arousal occurring during psychedelic psychotherapy sessions and surveys of kundalini experiences indicate that they are related to drug use (DeGracia, 1995; Thalbourne, 2001). Roney-Dougal (1989, 1991, 2001) has also indicated that the pineal gland is sensitive to the same fluctuations in geomagnetic activity that appear to be associated with spontaneous psi-activity (for a review see Roney-Dougal, Ryan, & Luke, 2013) [chapter 14, this volume]. That the pineal gland is central to psi is further supported by anthropological research—although experimental evidence is lacking—that suggests that DMT and the harmala alkaloids found in ayahuasca are psi-conducive, along with clinical research that suggests that pinoline and melatonin regulate sleep cycles and dreaming, during which spontaneous psi experiences most often occur (Roney-Dougal, 1986, 1989, 1991, 2001) [see chapter 15, this volume]. Some tentative support for the notion that ESP performance is directly predicted by pineal gland activity is also evident from experimental research that demonstrated that prepubescent children score better on ESP tests at 3 a.m. than at 9 p.m. when the pineal’s nocturnal chemicals (melatonin, etc.) are supposedly at peak concentrations in the brain (Satyanarayana, Rao, & Vijaylakshmi, 1993), This effect was not evident with a comparable group of pubescent children, which the authors suggest might be expected because the pineal gland is less active after infancy. A more extensive follow-up investigated dream–ESP and circadian pineal rhythms among young adults, finding a significant improvement in dream precognition scores at 3 a.m. compared to 8 a.m. (Luke, Zychowicz, Richterova, Tjurina, & Polonnikova, 2012), with scores in the same direction but non-significant in a replication study (Luke & Zychowicz, 2014), providing some tentative support for the notion that ESP may be linked to circadian pineal rhythms. Roney-Dougal (2001) also draws parallels between the ostensibly psiconducive nature of the shamanic, psychotic, psychedelic, and dream states, which she suggests all belong to the same continuum—perhaps somewhat akin to Thalbourne’s (1998) concept of transliminality, the proclivity for psychological material to cross thresholds in or out of consciousness—and that they all show suggestive evidence of being regulated by the same neurochemical processes. Recently, the discovery of trace amine receptors in the brain, for which DMT shows greater affinity than does serotonin—its more common neuro-amine cousin—has lead to a resurgence of interest in endogenous DMT in the mediation of mental health (Jacob & Presti, 2005). Nevertheless, the use of psychedelics generally is not related to poor mental health (Krebs & Johansen, 2013) Evaluation of the Pineal DMT Hypothesis In evaluating the role of the pineal gland and endogenous psychedelics in the activation of psi, it has yet to be shown that psi can be produced with these substances under controlled conditions. In addition, psi experiences may be induced with other psychoactive substances, as shown in the following sections. This criticism was countered by Strassman (2001) with the argument that other psychedelic substances may also stimulate the pineal and endogenous DMT by their action. However, this proposal is little more than conjecture. Furthermore, although the hypothesis that DMT is made in the human pineal is reasonable, it remains speculative. According to Strassman (2001), although the lungs, liver, blood, and eye all contain the enzymes necessary to convert tryptamine to DMT, the pineal gland is especially rich in them and also has high concentrations of serotonin ready to convert to tryptamine. So although the pineal–DMT hypothesis is currently unproven, it is certainly feasible, especially when it is considered that the chemical conversion of tryptamine to DMT can be demonstrated in vitro. The only attempt thus far to support the hypothesis directly has been Strassman’s attempt to isolate DMT from 10 human pineal glands extracted from cadavers. No DMT was detected in the glands; however, neither the bodies nor the glands were freshly frozen and any chemicals present may have degraded before analysis (Strassman, 2001). Thus far DMT has been found to be naturally occurring in the brain (Kärkkäinen et al., 2005), most recently in the pineal glands of rodents (Barker, Borjigin, Lomnicka, & Strassman, 2013), and in the highest concentrations in humans in the cerebrospinal fluid (for a review, see Barker, McIlhenny, & Strassman, 2012), but not the human brain, let alone the pineal gland, as yet. Furthermore, although the pineal gland contains methyltransferase enzymes, as Strassman (2001) indicated, the particular one thought to be crucial for in vivo DMT production (indolethylamine Nmethyltransferase, or simply INMT) has as yet not been found in the human brain or pineal gland although, curiously, DMT was found in rabbit brain tissue, despite the absence of INMT (Kärkkäinen et al., 2005), perhaps indicating that INMT is not necessary for the production of DMT after all. Furthermore, most INMT mapping research only establishes where enzyme translation is occurring, as it is based solely on INMT mRNA studies. A recent study (Cozzi, Mavlyutov, Thompson, & Ruoho, 2011) using a fluorescent INMT antibody found indication of the presence of INMT in three Rhesus macaque nervous tissues samples, including the pineal gland. Evidence of INMT in primate pineal glands potentially provides support for Strassman’s human pineal–DMT production hypothesis. However, absence of evidence is not evidence of absence, and the pineal gland is difficult to research in vivo, and DMT is an under-researched substance, particularly in humans. DMT is also difficult to detect (Barker et al., 2012) and belongs to the most controlled category of drugs in most countries, so currently the jury remains out on the pineal–DMT hypothesis. Dopamine and Paranormal Beliefs and Experiences Taking a purely materialist reductionist view of paranormal experiences by attempting to account for them exclusively in terms of beliefs arising from faulty cognitions—what Irwin (2009) calls the cognitive deficits hypothesis —a loose neurobiological model for the explanation of paranormal beliefs posits the dopamine neurotransmitter system as the primary facilitator. Put forward by Krummenacher and colleagues (Krummenacher, Brugger, Fahti, & Mohr, 2002; Krummenacher, Mohr, Haker, & Brugger, 2009), the theory suggests that although activity of the neurotransmitter dopamine is classically implicated in enhancing cognitive and perceptual decisions by improving the signal to noise ratio of neuronal transmission, paradoxically hyperdopaminergic activity is associated with psychotic symptoms, schizophrenia, and schizotypy (for a brief review, see Krummenacher et al., 2009), and so excess dopamine may account for delusional thinking stemming from an increased tendency to find patterns in apparently random data—what the psychiatrist Klaus Conrad (1958) called apophenia. According to Brugger and colleagues (e.g., Pizzagalli, Lehmann, & Brugger, 2001) paranormal believers—and so most likely paranormal experiencers too—have been shown to be more inclined towards apophenia than skeptics, thereby accounting for the increased creativity apparently associated with paranormal thinking and its similarity to some psychotic symptoms: because a combination of creative and delusional dimensions are indicative of the positive phenomenology of schizotypy (Eckblad & Chapman, 1983) [see chapters 9 and 25, this volume]. Direct research into what might be most accurately called the hyperdopaminergia-apophenia hypothesis is somewhat limited at this time, consisting of only two studies, with somewhat mixed results. The first study (Raz, Hines, Fossella, & Castro, 2008) attempted to relate paranormal belief as a phenotype to hyperdopaminergia as a genotype via what Raz et al. (2008) call the “COMT dopaminergic gene.” COMT (Catechol-O- methyltransferase) is an enzyme that degrades catecholamines such as dopamine, and the COMT protein is encoded by the COMT gene. Using questionnaires of paranormal belief, 107 psychology students were genetically screened for three COMT allelic forms, Raz et al. (2008) successfully identified approximately one quarter of the sample with high COMT activity, a quarter with low activity, and half with intermediate activity. However, failing to support the hyperdopaminergia-apophenia hypothesis, the authors found that those with decreased COMT activity, and hence greater hyperdopaminergia, reported no more paranormal beliefs, abilities, or experiences than the higher COMT activity participants. Undeterred, they pointed to the observation that attempting to unravel links between single gene polymorphisms that influence neurochemical function, and consequently individual differences in cognitive function, may be difficult when using distal phenotypes such as questionnaire measures, and that more proximal measures such as brain imaging might be more promising. Indeed, behavioral genetics is in a state of epistemological crisis after the lack of hard findings from the recently completed Human Genome Project (e.g., see Maher, 2008), so it may well be too soon to expect good data relating paranormal beliefs to genes, particularly single genes, even if they are related. The second study, by Krummenacher et al. (2009), sampled 20 paranormal believers and 20 paranormal non-believers and administered levodopa—an active precursor to dopamine in the brain—in a randomized placebo controlled between-subjects study. Participants were given two signal detection tasks, one with words (tapping left hemisphere processes) and one with faces (right hemisphere), that presented either word/non-word or face/non-face stimulus pairs tachistoscopically for just 140 ms. Participant responses were assessed for both their tendency to make correct guesses relative to incorrect ones: their sensitivity index (d’), and their tendency to respond with a positive or negative bias, or their response tendency (C). The two measures were independent of each other. Findings indicate that skeptics had significantly greater sensitivity to signal detection than believers in the placebo condition but, contrary to expectations, increased dopamine led to a significant decrease in sensitivity in skeptics but had no effect on believers. These findings challenge the view that dopamine generally assists in signal detection, and Krummenacher et al. (2009) suggested that the opposite may actually be true in some cases, especially with presumed hypodominergic individuals (i.e., skeptics). Additionally, the authors argued that the lack of change in sensitivity in believers administered levodopa may be due to a plateau effect caused by high cerebral dopamine baseline levels; however, such a suggestion is somewhat post hoc and, even if it were true, the authors do not comment on why the dopamine-enhanced skeptics had lower sensitivity (i.e., greater sensory apophenia) than either believer group. Whereas the sensitivity measure findings are puzzling, the response bias measure results are somewhat more straightforward, in the control scenario at least. As was expected, in the placebo condition believers had a greater tendency to respond in the affirmative (favoring a Type I error strategy), whereas skeptics had a greater tendency to respond in the negative (favoring a Type II error strategy), the difference between the groups being significant. However, against expectation, in the levodopa condition these tendencies in each group were diminished so that there was no significant difference between skeptics and believers, although the trend remained. Specifically, compared to their placebo controls, dopamine-enhanced believers were more cautious in making false positive decisions (i.e., more conservative), and skeptics were less prone to make false negative decisions (i.e., more liberal), so that in effect both believer groups were less polarized in their responses. Contrary to the linear dopamine-apophenia relationship originally proposed, these results may indicate differing baseline dopaminergic activity in skeptics and believers and the possibility that there is a non-linear relationship between task and dopamine levels, perhaps an inverted U-shape modulated by individual differences in belief. However, these findings should be replicated first and more direct measures of baseline dopamine (e.g., spinal dopamine metabolic marker assays) should be made before these findings and post hoc interpretations are given much weight. Furthermore, as the authors noted, use of a between- rather than withinsubjects design is far from ideal, leaving too much faith in the randomization of the small groups and no certainty in equivalence of baselines in dopamine responsivity and behavioral performance. Aside from the current lack of research on the hyperdopaminergia-apophenia hypothesis and the somewhat confusing mixed results, this line of research seems worthwhile pursuing further, although it suffers from additional limitations. One is that it aims to boil down paranormal experiences to misperceptions and misjudgments of the pattern recognition type. Even if we allow for the fact that the authors a priori preclude the possibility of genuine paranormal phenomena, this approach does not account for the swathe of other cognitive deficits that are also given to account for paranormal beliefs, such as poor judgments of probability and randomness, egocentric bias, selective remembering, confirmation bias, and more (Brugger & Mohr, 2008). Indeed a study investigating probability inferences in those under the influence of ketamine, versus matched controls and schizophrenic patients, showed that the ketamine group was no different from the placebo group, whereas the patients exhibited a jump-to-conclusions response concerning probability inferences (Evans et al. 2012). Although ketamine is primarily an NMDA-antagonist, it also has direct effects on dopamine receptors (Kapur & Seeman, 2002), so the lack of probability inference effect with ketamine does not complement a dopamine explanation for paranormal experiences within the cognitive deficits paradigm. Other psychological factors supposedly related to paranormal experiences, such as the propensity for false memories, also show no relation with self-reported recreational drug use generally (Wilson & French, 2006). In this respect the dopaminergic approach does not currently incorporate many of the multitudinous psychological explanations for paranormal beliefs and experiences. Furthermore, the wealth of evidence, to follow, relating increased paranormal experience—and to some extent experimentally controlled production of ESP—to the ingestion of psychedelic substances does not particularly support a dopamine-based theory of paranormality either, as dopamine activation is neither primary nor ubiquitous with psychedelic substances. Typically, classic tryptamine psychedelics (such as LSD and psilocybin) are thought to exert their effects via serotonin receptors, particularly the 5-HT2A receptor subtype (Lee & Roth, 2012). Nevertheless, it is thought that 5-HT2A receptor stimulation can activate dopamine release (Diaz-Mataix et al., 2005), and Previc (2011) has asserted that all the various psychedelic neurochemical pathways to “altered states of consciousness with distorted reality” (p. 43) ultimately lead to elevated levels of dopamine in the brain, although such reasoning rather ablates the intricate nuances of psychopharmacology and disregards primary neurochemical pathway activation as in any way important. Furthermore, although some psychedelic substances (e.g., LSD, psilocin, DMT) do have relatively high affinities for certain dopamine receptors (Ray, 2010), dopamine is rarely considered to be a primary neurotransmitter site for psychedelic effects. Indeed, the primarily dopaminergic recreational drugs, such as amphetamine and cocaine, have been found to be either unrelated or negatively related to paranormal experiences and beliefs (Luke, 2012), contradicting the dopamine-paranormal belief/experience hypothesis. Indeed, if Previc were right about psychedelics exerting their effects via the dopamine system, we would expect amphetamine and cocaine to be psychedelic too, which they are not. Furthermore there are various psychedelics strongly associated with paranormal experiences that do not have dopaminergic action, such as the kopioid agonist salvinorin A (Ray, 2010) and anticholinergic agents like scopolamine and hyoscyamine, found in nightshade family plants like datura (Katzung, Masters, & Trevor, 2012). Overall—with scant direct research, mixed and complex findings, and poor generalizability of the hypothesis to (a) other psychological explanations, and (b) most of the psychedelicparapsychology literature—at present, the dopamine-apophenia conjecture remains very much rudimentary and unsupported. Overview of Psychedelics/Neurochemical Models of Psi The preceding sections outline several neurochemical models germane to explaining psi experiences, namely the brain as filter, pineal gland neurochemistry, and dopamine. The first two models draw upon the action of psychedelic substances in particular and remain open to the possibility that psi experiences may be genuine. Two other models, not reviewed here (but see Luke, 2012), are sympathetic to the psi hypothesis but are primarily concerned with near-death and mystical experiences and pertain to ketamine and DMT as the key chemicals. It should be noted, however, that no one psychedelic model might ultimately be the correct one, as psychedelics may work in many ways (e.g., dissociatives are both NMDA antagonists, as well as mu-opioid agonists). Nevertheless, these models provide important avenues for future research and development of more complete neurobiological models of apparent paranormal cognition or merely paranormal belief, and, indeed, of more complete models of consciousness itself. The importance of understanding the apparent psi-inducing effects of psychedelics is clear and the evidence in support of this relationship is reviewed and evaluated in the following sections. Field Reports of Intentional and Spontaneous Psi Phenomena Despite apparent traditional prejudices by anthropologists against reporting such phenomena (Winkelman, 1983), the anthropological and ethnobotanical literature remains replete with examples of ostensible psi phenomena occurring with the indigenous use of psychoactive plants (Luke, 2010). Archaeological evidence suggests that such practices have existed for millennia (see Devereux, 1997). Since the discovery of psychedelic compounds by the academic community and their popularization among the intelligentsia, there has been a steadily growing number of reports of paranormal experiences occurring with the use of these compounds. Several parapsychologists and psychical researchers, primarily from the 1950s and 1960s when psychedelic research was at its peak, endorsed the research of psi with psychedelics (Luke, 2012). Even J. B. Rhine, the father of modern parapsychology, ran some informal psychedelic sessions in 1961 at the Foundation for Research on the Nature of Man, in collaboration with then Harvard psychologists Timothy Leary and Richard Alpert (Black, 2001), although there was apparently too much spontaneous laughter erupting for anyone to credibly test for anything (S. Abrams, personal communication, August 14, 2006). Notably, several other parapsychologists have reported personal ESP experiences with the use of psychedelics (see Luke, 2012). Krippner’s apparent precognitive vision of President Kennedy’s assassination while on psilocybin serves as a good example. Krippner (1970) took the substance while visiting Timothy Leary and his psychedelic research team at Harvard in 1962, and reported a vivid trip including the following: I travelled to the nation’s capital. I found myself gazing at a statue of Lincoln. The statue was entirely black, and the head was bowed. There was a gun at the base of the statue and someone murmured, “He was shot. The President was shot.” A wisp of smoke rose into the air. Lincoln’s features slowly faded away, and those of Kennedy took their place. The setting was still Washington, D.C. The gun was still at the base of the black statue. A wisp of smoke seeped from the barrel and curled into the air. The voice repeated, “He was shot. The President was shot.” My eyes opened; they were filled with tears. In 1962, when I had my first psilocybin experience, I gave this visualization of Kennedy relatively little thought, as so many other impressions came my way. However, it was the only one of my visualizations that brought tears to my eyes, so I described it fully in the report I sent to Harvard. Nineteen months later, on November 23, 1963, the visualization came back to me as I mourned Kennedy’s assassination [p. 38]. Similar reports of frequent ESP experiences with such substances from various consciousness researchers, chemists, anthropologists, and psychonauts are available elsewhere in the literature (for a review see Luke, 2012). A review of the clinical literature reveals surprisingly few published psychiatric inpatient reports relating to psychedelics and paranormal experience. This may be due to a number of factors, such as the lack of spontaneous phenomena within the psychiatric population, or the medicalization within psychiatry of paranormal experiences as delusions or hallucinations. Indeed, Mogar (1965) noted that early psychoanalytic and behaviorist researchers using LSD were prejudiced against ESP phenomena. Yet, there is one study, a psychiatric-interview survey with users of LSD (Abraham, 1983), that mentioned precognitive experiences as one of the symptoms of the LSD flashback phenomena, now called hallucinogen persisting perception disorder (American Psychiatric Association, 2013). On the other hand, there are many accounts of paranormal experiences with psychoactive drugs coming from psychedelic-assisted psychotherapy, with every therapist in this field who has written about their work reporting such experiences, and which tend to occur with greater frequency than in nonpsychedelic therapy (Luke, 2012). The psychiatrist Stanislav Grof, generally credited with the greatest expertise in this field, having conducted more than 4,000 psychedelic therapy sessions over a two decade period, reported observing patients experiencing ESP (particularly precognition) and accurate remote viewing on a daily basis (Grof, 1975, 2001). The occurrence of extraordinary coincidences or synchronicities was the most frequent type of experience but, curiously, these occurred only among those clients who experienced transpersonal breakthroughs within the psychedelic session (Grof, 2001). There is a wealth of reports of the spontaneous occurrence of ostensible psi phenomena with the use of psychedelic substances, but such experiences are not necessarily genuine psi events. Aside from the usual arguments for and against spontaneous phenomena as evidence for the paranormal (e.g., see Cardeña & Pekala, 2014; Stokes, 1997), the fact that respondents had consumed a visionary substance may be reason to question their perception and interpretation of the experiences, at least for those cases that are not substantiated by evidence or independent observers. Nevertheless, Shanon (2003) pointed out that the usual definitions of hallucination in the psychological literature fail to adequately encompass the diverse and complex nature of experiences that occur with psychedelics, nor can assumptions be made about the ontology of such psychedelic-induced visions. Indeed, many people who have had ostensibly paranormal psychedelic experiences reported how real the experience seemed, often being felt as more real than the ordinary waking experience (Shanon, 2003). Further empirical research is needed to validate these claims. Surveys of Paranormal Belief and Experience in Relation to Drug Use Reviewing the survey research one immediately notices two trends. First, virtually all of the 16 surveys reviewed were published since the 1970s, after the period when most direct experimental psychedelic research was conducted, although such research is now slowly resuming after a long hiatus. Second, most of the surveys primarily focused on paranormal experiences (9 surveys) and/or belief (7 surveys) and tended to record drug use information as one of many possible co-variables (10 surveys), often omitting to distinguish among the different substances. Only six studies approached users of psychoactive substances as the target sample (for a review see Luke, 2012). The findings from the survey research indicate a small but consistent, and typically significant relation (r = .16 to .25) between belief in the anomalous/paranormal and drug use, with the size of this relation being most pronounced for the marijuana users in Tart’s 1993 study. Furthermore, these studies support the hypothesis that psychedelics can induce some paranormal phenomena, although the same arguments for and against the genuineness of field reports are also relevant here. Of the reviewed surveys, correlations between the occurrence of paranormal experiences (including psi and mystical experiences) and the use of all drugs (excluding prescription drugs) ranged from r = .13 to .46 and were typically significant, and/or those reporting ESP and anomalous/paranormal experiences were found to be significantly more likely to use psychedelics. One study found the same for recurrent spontaneous PK as well, although only tentatively (Palmer, 1979). Furthermore, of those reporting the use of psychedelics, between 18 and 83 percent reported ESP experiences—most commonly telepathy but also precognition—actually occurring during drug use, with heavier users reporting more experiences. Yet, conversely, the occurrence of PK during drug use was only reported to occur by between 13 and 22 percent of those using psychedelics. Weak relations between paranormal experiences, the use of psychedelics, and kundalini experiences has also been found in two studies, and there is also a weak, but repeated, correlation between transliminality, drug use, and paranormal experience with Australian psychology students. Where specified, the relation with paranormal experiences, belief in the paranormal, transliminality, and tolerance of ambiguity is much reduced with cocaine, heroin, and alcohol, compared to psychedelics, perhaps reflecting Metzner’s (2005) classification of these former substances as consciousnesscontracting drugs. The same is also true for the negative relation with the fear of psi and use of psychedelics, which is not apparent with heroin and actually reversed with alcohol, although replication and analyses for specific classes of drugs is necessary. Correlations between self-reports of cannabis use and “thought transmission” in psychiatric research are apparent, often indirectly, though such experiences are also more widely reported in the apparent absence of pathology, with or without cannabis. Most of the surveys failed to adequately identify which substances lead to which experiences, although a switch to such taxonomic research is now evident (Luke & Kittenis, 2005). Substances particularly favorable to the experience of telepathy were cannabis, MDMA and DXM. No one substance was particularly generative of precognitive experiences, and possible candidates for clairvoyance were cannabis, LSD, and psilocybin. As yet no research has explored state and personality dimensions in relation to substance-induced psi experiences, although such research is encouraged (Cardeña, 2009; Luke, 2011a). Experimental Psi Research with Drugs Published between 1943 and 1961, the earliest parapsychology experiments with psychoactive substances were conducted with simple stimulants and depressants, such as caffeine, amphetamine, alcohol, amytal, and quinalbarbitone. This work, which had mixed results, is not included here (for a review see Palmer, 1978) as this overview is instead focused on the visionary (i.e., psychedelic) substances, which are seemingly more favorable to the production of psi. So far there have been only 18 published papers, comprising 23 separate experiments, on the efficacy of psychedelics for inducing ESP, primarily with LSD or psilocybin, but also with mescaline, cannabis, Amanita muscaria, and ayahuasca (for a summary see Table 1). The results of these experiments, which began in the 1950s, varied in their degree of success, most likely in relation to the methodology involved (for a review see Luke, 2012). The most successful experiments tended to have participants experienced with the use of psychedelics, and also utilized free-response testing procedures, with open-ended mentation regarding their internal state, rather than forced-choice guessing scenarios, which tend to be repetitive and thus rather boring “under the influence.” In retrospect it is easy to see how the more naïvely-designed projects lost any hope of sensibly testing for anything, let alone psi, once their inexperienced participants began succumbing to the mystical rapture of their first trip. These few experiments were also reported quite differently, sometimes as entire monographs in excess of 100 pages or at other times as footnotes within another published report, often without useful details and statistics. The majority of these experiments were essentially pilot studies and were mostly conducted during the psychedelic research period of the 1960s. Table 1. Summary of All ESP Controlled Research with Psychedelics Due to the exploratory nature of most of these experiments, it is difficult to fully assess their efficacy in using psychedelics to produce ESP (no PK experiments having been attempted). In most cases the study could have largely been improved with an adequate control condition for order effects (Palmer, 1978), and the masked use of decoy targets in the judging process. Procedures using subjective probability estimates by experimenters (such as Asperen de Boer, Barkema, & Kappers, 1966) are now virtually obsolete in parapsychology because they are so difficult to assess and are prone to bias (Parker, 1975). Of 10 ESP-card experiments, in the one that used a control condition the scores in the psilocybin condition were significantly different from chance and were also superior to the control condition, although not significantly so (Asperen de Boer et al., 1966). Nevertheless, it is apparent that experiments using forced choice ESP-card type symbol guessing procedures were largely unsuccessful compared to chance expectation. Indeed, the use of the symbol-guessing procedure has been widely criticized for being far too mundane under the influence of psychedelics (Luke, 2012). Even so, using Amanita muscaria, Puharich (1962) showed that forcedchoice procedures could be successful with picture-sorting tasks, although there are concerns that his experiments were not well controlled for possible sensory leakage. Alternatively, more engaging, free-response procedures have demonstrated at least some success in all but one of the four studies that used psychometry —the supposed ability of psychically determining the provenance of a given object—although rarely with any control condition for comparison. A clearer indication of possible psychedelic-induced ESP, at times in comparison to a control condition, comes from the four clairvoyance and four telepathy designs, which were mostly positive (see Luke, 2012). Despite some promising trends, however, replication is needed and, in some cases, with better methodology and pre-planned analyses. It remains curious that no formal explicit experiments with precognition or PK have been performed, particularly the former because powers of divination are traditionally attributed to many plant psychedelics. A Methodological Critique of the Experimental Research and Suggestions for Future Study When consideration is given to what has been learned from these largely pilot studies, experimenters and commentators alike have highlighted the difficulties involved in attempting to test for psi with participants who have taken a psychedelic. Asperen de Boer et al. (1964) suggested that participants’ willingness to perform in the task was important, but given the difficulty to maintain alertness, self-control, focus, interest, and orientation to the task (Millay, 2001; Rogo, 1976), it seems much more important to consider the participants’ capability to perform in the experiment rather than their mere willingness. Parker (1975) notes that a participant’s increased sensitivity to subtle influences under psychedelics is both a boon and a bane to research. Indeed, using psychedelics to induce psi is a double-edged sword, chiefly because all of the reasons listed previously that make such research alluring also may have the participants neglect the psi task while they become absorbed in their aesthetic experiences (Osis, 1961; Smythies, 1960), the quest for philosophical knowledge (Osis, 1961), a deep soulsearching self-examination (Blewett, 1963), one’s own personal drama (Millay, 2001; Parker, 1975), or flow of thoughts (Ryzl, 1968). In addition, participants may have difficulty communicating because of the lack of adequate language (Lilly, 1969), the overwhelming flood of ideas and emotions (Ryzl, 1968), and the speed of change of the internal experience (Blewett, 1961, 1963). The experience of dissociation (e.g., with ketamine) can also hinder communication when participants are no longer present or aware of their physical environment and, as Huxley (1961) pointed out, there is a need to assure participants of their identity once constructs of space and time disappear. However, it is apparent that these obstacles to research may be greatly alleviated or even eliminated if participants are experienced with the use of psychedelics, as noted by Tart (1977) and others (Blewett, 1963; Parker, 1975). Indeed, about a quarter of inexperienced participants are expected to have intense spontaneous mystical experiences during their first trip (Wulff, 2014). Yet, only 3 (Bierman, 1998; Masters & Houston, 1966; Wezelman & Bierman, 1997) of the 19 studies reviewed here specifically reported the use of participants experienced with these psychedelics, and it is worth noting that those studies were relatively more successful at getting above chance psi scores than those that used inexperienced participants. Further, it has been suggested that experienced psychedelic participants can be trained more easily to stabilize their experience (Levine, 1968; Millay, 2001; Tart, 1977). Regardless of training, it has been strongly advised that participants be allowed to stabilize their experience before testing begins (Blewett, 1963; Millay, 2001; Parker, 1975; Tart, 1977). Stabilization of the experience may even be expedited by inducing hypnosis prior to drug administration (Parker, 1975; Tart, 1968) in what has been called the “hypnodelic” state (Ludwig 1968). Alternatively, Ryzl (1968) reported re-inducing LSD states through hypnosis, as is also reported elsewhere, although it was uncertain how successful this was (Ludwig, 1968), though success inducing other drug states (e.g., MDMA, heroin) has been reported (Hastings, 2006; Ludwig & Lyle, 1964). Perhaps, the entire psychedelic experience can be later hypnotically re-induced in experienced users so that no psychedelics are actually taken during the test procedure. Testing for psi under such “controlled flashbacks” may overcome most of the stipulated problems, and have the added advantage of investigating Rogo’s (1976) question of whether it is the neurochemical action of the drugs or the state induced that can seemingly produce psi. Nevertheless, this research approach somewhat restricts participants to those who are both experienced and comfortable with psychedelics and are highly suggestible. Some researchers (e.g., Smythies 1960; Tart, in Levine, 1968) have suggested that using good-psi scorers, psychics, and mediums in drug studies would improve scoring, but Eileen Garrett (1961) noted that although LSD enhanced her mediumistic experience it did not improve her forced choice test-scores. Echoing this, Osis (1961) found that mediums did not prove any more successful than normal participants in the other psychometry experiments. This may be explained by all the problems that occur more with inexperienced psychedelic users, indicating that sample selection should primarily seek to identify experienced users over psi-effective participants, although, presumably, ideal participants would be both. It is also noted that among traditional shamanic cultures the use of psychedelics and mediumship are seldom mixed (Luke, 2014). Considering aspects of timing, several authors have offered advice, though no formal studies have been conducted. Both Ryzl (1968) and Grof (2001) suggested that the optimum period for testing psi during the LSD session was towards the end when the effects were leveling off, as in the Masters and Houston (1966) experiments, yet Pahnke (1971) disagreed. As regards to the duration of the psi-task, rather than the extended test periods favored by some researchers (e.g. Asperen de Boer et al., 1964; Tinoco, 1995), Osis (1961) suggested 20 minutes should be the maximum for optimum performance. Some consideration has also been given to the optimal substance. Pahnke (1971) recommended combining stimulants with psychedelics, whereas Asperen de Boer et al. (1966) chose psilocybin over LSD, due to it being milder, with which Cavanna and Servadio (1964) agreed. Indeed, LSD has a much longer duration of action than psilocybin and, as Blewett (1963) noted, 10-hour trips are hard to staff. Ryzl (1968) also questioned the utility of LSD in psychedelic psi testing and proposed that the ideal substance, if it can be synthesized, should inhibit cortical activity to suppress the stream of thoughts, depress sub-cortical activity to block incoming stimuli and excite spheres of the cortex involved in ESP production, yet maintain rational insight, and increase suggestibility. Such a designer drug is far in the future; moreover, there is an increasing number of ethnobotanical substances that have traditionally been used for psychic purposes, which have not yet been thoroughly tested, or even tested at all (e.g., Salvia divinorum). Tart (1993) further suggested that marijuana was an ideal substance for psi experimentation because of its wide familiarity within the public, its mild psychedelic qualities, and its reputed ability to induce psi, experientially at least. Puharich’s (1962) apparent repeated success with Amanita muscaria also needs replicating. Furthermore, other non-psychedelic chemical psi research, such as de Pablos’s (2002) unsuccessful first-person precognitivedream drug-study, could also be replicated with the use of psychedelic substances that have actually been reported to induce psi in dreams. For instance, there are reports of precognitive dreams, by both traditional users and by modern consciousness researchers, with substances such as Calea zacatechichi (e.g., Devereaux, 1997; Díaz, 1979), Silene capensis (e.g., Hirst, 2000; Sobiecki, 2012), and tree datura (Brugmansia, e.g., Metzner, 1992). Other substances seem best suited to other experimental designs too, for example, telepathy-like experiments might also benefit from the empathogenic effect of substances such as MDMA, as the one participant under its influence in a remote detection experiment did exceedingly well (Brown, 2012), and reports of telepathy are fairly typical with this substance (Luke & Kittenis, 2005). Group telepathy with people under the influence of DXM has also been independently reported by numerous survey respondents (Luke & Kittenis, 2005). The use of a placebo in a double-masked or masked control condition, as in Cavanna and Servadio (1964), is of questionable utility in this type of experiment because at anything less than sub-threshold doses the participant is likely to detect the effects of the drug; nevertheless, researchers should be aware that placebo drug effects have been demonstrated in ESP research when coupled with positive false feedback on task performance (Pitman & Owens, 2004). One way in which researchers have attempted to circumnavigate the poor disguise of psychedelics and reduce expectancy effects in non-parapsychological research is to tell the participant in advance that they may receive a placebo or one of a number of different drugs, only one of which is a psychedelic, though ultimately participants can usually tell when they get a psychedelic. Several researchers have also commented on the importance of dosage (e.g., Levine, 1968). Indeed, Blewett (1961) warned that giving participants low doses of LSD may not be sufficient to break through the barrier between the normal and the full-blown psychedelic state and can be merely disorientating rather than transformative. Support for this logic is also evident in escalating dose research with DMT (Strassman, 2001). It was also advised in the original Handbook that experienced participants control their own dosage (Tart, 1977), as in the experiment by Wezelman and Bierman (1997). Participants’ self-reports of the depth of the altered state were also considered better than dosages as indicators of subjective effects (Tart, 1977). Self-reports using the Hallucinogenic Rating Scale were also considered better indicators of dosage than physiological measures (Strassman, Qualls, Uhlenhuth, & Kellner, 1994), though the use of a scale of transpersonal experience, such as the Self-Expansiveness Scale Form (Friedman, 1983), would also likely be fruitful in discerning the relevant depth of the psychedelic ASC. Furthermore, some researchers (e.g., Parker, 1975; Tart 1968, 1977) have noted that the issue of dosage is largely irrelevant in comparison to the influence of the psychological factors of set and setting, as originally noted in psychedelic research by Leary, Litwin, and Metzner (1963). Vayne (2001) suggested that the influence of psychological factors on psychoactive drugs vary their effects so much that the drug can be thought of primarily as an experience composed of set, setting, and substance. Factors considered important in determining psychological set include the participants’ expectations, attitudes towards themselves, idiosyncratic perceptions, and emotional orientation to the experiment (Levine, 1968; Tart, 1968). It is also deemed imperative to engender a sense of self-surrender, acceptance, and trust (Blewett, 1963). Factors considered important in determining psychological setting include those that are ordinarily considered under demand characteristics (Parker, 1975; Tart, 1968, 1977), particularly the experimenter’s attitude, which should be warm, friendly, and supportive (Blewett, 1963). Psychological issues induced through interpersonal relations within the laboratory become magnified when participants are on psychedelics (Blewett, 1963; Parker, 1975). Indeed, Cavanna and Servadio (1964) highlighted this when one of their participants had an anxiety attack concurrent with their own anxiety, which led them to advise that experimenters themselves should be experienced users of the substance under investigation, as echoed by Strassman (2001). Tart (1968) also recommended that the experimenter should guide the experience towards the goal of the study, and has criticized previous work for assuming psychedelic states to automatically induce psi, because, as noted by Tart, Osmond, and Beloff (in Levine, 1968), in traditional scenarios the shamans who use these substances usually have extensive training and experience. It is further suggested that the experimental task be shaped to the state of the participant, not vice versa (Tart, 1977), and utilize the strong motivation, directed awareness, and complex ritual that is found in shamanism (Grof, 2001; Tart, 1968). Grob and Harman (1995) have also urged the integration of aspects from shamanic practices into scientific procedure so that there is attentiveness to factors of set and setting, such as intention, expectation, preparation, group identification, and formalized structure, as well as the integration of the experience in the following months. Indeed a multi-method approach to studying psychedelic shamanic practices is advised, so that ethnography can inform suitable experimentation (Giesler, 1984; Luke, 2010). Nevertheless, Storm and Rock (2011) pointed out that, in psi research with psychedelics, researchers need to be aware of the difference between shamanic techniques and merely shamanic-like techniques; for example, the latter may lack the purpose of serving one’s community. Furthermore, Tart (1977) recommended the implementation of mutual research, where participants are considered as co-investigators, to reduce experimenter bias and enhance a sense of participation, trust, and motivation. One way to ensure such congenial factors in the experimental setting may be to have an experienced psychedelic user and parapsychologist as both the experimenter and participant (Luke, 2011b), concerns over placebo effects notwithstanding. General Summary and Conclusions Even though the subjective paranormal experiences, clinical observations and anthropological reports are subject to all the usual criticisms and rebuttals that apply to non-experimental cases (e.g., see Cardeña & Pekala, 2014) there is a growing body of reports, rooted in thousands of years of traditional psychedelic use, that supports the notion that genuine psi phenomena do occur in psychedelic states. Nevertheless, as evidence, these data are not scientifically rigorous yet have great value in mapping the phenomenological terrain of psi experiences with psychedelics. This body of reports is further supported by correlations from surveys linking psychedelic use with the increased reporting of psi experiences and belief in psi and the paranormal, although self-reports have more phenomenological merit than evidential value. Furthermore, even though it can be considered little more than exploratory at this stage, the experimental evidence is more positive than not and proves promising so far, illuminating both methodological pitfalls and possibilities. It is apparent that parapsychopharmacology is a multidisciplinary endeavor pooling expertise from anthropology, ethnobotany, phytochemistry, neurobiology, psychopharmacology, psychiatry, psychotherapy, transpersonal psychology, and indeed parapsychology. It also owes much to the non-academic explorers of consciousness, be they shamans, occultists, or psychonauts. It is a branch of research that is still very much in its infancy and, along with other fields conducting research with the use of psychedelics, has been operating very quietly since the late 60s, until a gentle turn in the tide during the last decade or so has seen experimental research resume (Grob & Harman, 1995). Nevertheless, further experimental research continues to need strict ethical and often governmental approval before it can proceed, requiring lengthy applications (McKenna, 2004; Strassman, 2001). Tart (1977) recommended bypassing these difficulties by casually enrolling participants who were already using psychedelics, rather than having the experimenter administering the substances directly. An example of this kind of experiment involved several thousand Grateful Dead fans, renowned for their psychedelic consumption, who acted as senders in a series of dream telepathy experiments with some success (Krippner, 1999). Indeed, taking what Giesler (1984) calls a psi-in-process approach and keeping naturalistic variables intact, group experiments may be one way to access the kind of group telepathy experiences that people tripping in groups sometimes report (e.g., Stevens, 1989) especially on DXM (Luke & Kittenis, 2005). However, without the grounded and controlled atmosphere of a concert or shamanic ceremony, psychedelic group ESP experiments run the risk of turning into bacchanalian scenes, as reported by Puharich’s wife (Hermans, 1998). Direct parapsychological research with psychedelics needs expanding beyond the Netherlands and Brazil—the only places where experimental psychedelic parapsychology research has been conducted since the 1970s. Furthermore, treating these substances like any other drug worthy of investigation within a medical or therapeutic context has recently proven a fruitful means of inquiry for many researchers (Grob & Harman, 1995), although psi research does not readily attract such funding at the present time. Nevertheless, we should note that psychedelics are considered sacramental by the spiritual and religious groups that use them and must be treated and researched with respect. It is also clear that besides trying to replicate the promising free-response studies, further experimental psychedelic research should utilize protocols that maximize psi effects, and this work can then simultaneously enhance process research methodology by indicating optimal conditions for psi through the psychologically magnifying effects of these substances. For instance, Bierman’s (1998) psychedelic psi research may have revealed the apparent psychic blocking of negative images, and from earlier experiments, forced-choice tasks are clearly too mundane. Research should also seek to study these substances in the shamanic context, in which they have most effectively been used, designing appropriate test protocols for traditional settings. Additionally, following in the footsteps of William James, there has already been some return to self-experimentation with psychoactive drugs by Pablos (2002), who developed a viable protocol for testing one’s own precognitive dreaming abilities with drugs, which might easily be adapted to waking experimentation as well. All experimental research should also be designed and conducted with an appreciative consideration of Tart’s proposals for the creation of state-specific sciences (Tart, 1972). In the future, parapsychologists might ask their participants about their drug use and researchers investigating the use of psychedelics might once more include questions relating to paranormal experiences (e.g., Echenhofer, 2005). Furthermore, with an ever growing number of substances being discovered and a large natural participant pool of psychedelic users, there is a need for more thorough and focused phenomenological research that investigates and identifies the types of paranormal experience that occur through the use of each of these diverse psychedelic substances. References Abraham, H. D. (1983). Visual phenomenology of the LSD flashback. Archives of General Psychiatry, 40, 884–889. American Psychiatric Association (2013). Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders (5th ed.). Arlington, VA: American Psychiatric Association. Asperen de Boer, S. R. van. Barkema, P. R., and Kappers, J. (1966). Is it possible to induce ESP with psilocybin? An exploratory investigation. International Journal of Neuropsychiatry, 2, 447–473. Avramopoulos, D., Stefanis, N. C., Hantoumi, I., Smyrnis, N., Evdokimidis, I., and Stefanis, C. N. (2002). Higher scores of self reported schizotypy in healthy young males carrying the COMT high activity allele. Molecular Psychiatry, 7, 706–711. Barker, S. A., Borjigin, J., Lomnicka, I., and Strassman, R. (2013). LC/MS/MS analysis of the endogenous dimethyltryptamine hallucinogens, their precursors, and major metabolites in rat pineal gland microdialysate. Biomedical Chromatography, 27, 1690–1700. Barker, S. A., McIlhenny, E. H., and Strassman, R. (2012). A critical review of reports of endogenous psychedelic N, N-dimethyltryptamines in humans: 1955–2010. Drug Testing and Analysis, 7–8, 617–635. Bergson, H. (1990). Matter and memory (N. M. Paul and W. S. Palmer, Trans). New York: Zone Books. (Original work published 1896). Bierman, D. J. (1998, October). The effects of THC and psilocybin on paranormal phenomena. Paper presented at Psychoactivity: A multidisciplinary conference on plants, shamanism, and states of consciousness, Amsterdam. Black, D. (2001). Acid: A new secret history of LSD. London, UK: Vision Paperbacks. Blake, W. (1906). The marriage of heaven and hell. Boston, MA: John W. Luce and Company. (Originally published 1793). Blewett, D. (1961). LSD in psychiatric treatment. In Proceedings of two conferences on parapsychology and pharmacology (pp. 56–58). New York: Parapsychology Foundation. Blewett, D. (1963). Psychedelic drugs in parapsychological research. International Journal of Parapsychology, 5, 43–74. Brown, D. J. (2012). LSD & ESP: Scientists study psychic phenomena and psychedelic drugs. Santa Cruz Patch (online), posted on 9 June 2012, at http://santacruz.patch.com/articles/lsd-esp-scientists-study-psychicphenomena-and-psychedelic-drugs. Brugger, P., and Mohr, C. (2008). The paranormal mind: How the study of anomalous experiences and beliefs may inform cognitive neuroscience. Cortex, 44, 1291–1298. Callaway, J. C. (1988). A proposed mechanism for the visions of dream sleep. Medical Hypotheses, 26, 119–24. Callaway, J. C. (2005). Various alkaloid profiles in decoctions of Banisteriopsis caapi. Journal of Psychoactive Drugs, 37, 151–155. Cardeña, E. (2009). Beyond Plato? Toward a science of alterations of consciousness. In C. A. Roe, W. Kramer, and L. Coly (Eds.), Utrecht II: Charting the future of parapsychology (pp. 305–322). New York: Parapsychology Foundation. Cardeña, E., Jönsson, P., Terhune, D. B., and Marcusson-Clavertz, D. (2013). The neurophenomenology of neutral hypnosis. Cortex, 49, 375–385. Cardeña, E. and Pekala, R. (2014). Researching states of consciousness and anomalous experiences. In E. Cardeña, S. J. Lynn and S. Krippner (Eds.), Varieties of anomalous experience: Examining the scientific evidence (2nd ed.) (pp. 21–56). Washington, D.C.: American Psychological Association. Carhart-Harris, R. L., Erritzoe, D., Williams, T., Stone, J. M., Reed, L. J., Colasanti, A., … and Nutt, D. J. (2012). Neural correlates of the psychedelic state as determined by fMRI studies with psilocybin. Proceedings of the National Academy of Science, 109, 2138–2143. Cavanna, R., and Servadio, E. (1964). ESP experiments with LSD 25 and psilocybin. A methodological approach: Parapsychological monographs 5. New York: Parapsychology Foundation. Conrad, K. (1958). Die beginnende Schizophrenie: Versuch einer gestaltanalyse des Wahns [The onset of schizophrenia: An experimental analysis of creative madness]. Stuttgart, Germany: Thieme. Cozzi, N. V., Mavlyutov, T. A., Thompson, M. A., and Ruoho A. E. (2011). Indolethylamine N-methyltransferase expression in primate nervous tissue. Society for Neuroscience Abstracts, 37, 840.19. DeGracia, D. J. (1995). Do psychedelic drugs mimic awakened kundalini? Hallucinogen survey results. Retrieved October 27, 2004, from http://www.csp.org/practices/entheogens/docs/kundalini_survey.html de Pablos, F. (2002). Enhancement of precognitive dreaming by cholinesterase inhibition: A pilot study. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 66, 88–105. Devereux, P. (1997). The long trip: A prehistory of psychedelia. New York: Penguin/Arkana. Díaz, J. L. (1979). Ethnopharmacology and taxonomy of Mexican psychodysleptic plants. Journal of Psychedelic Drugs, 11(1–2), 71–101. Diaz-Mataix, L., Scorza, M. C., Bortolozzi, A., Toth, M., Celada, P., and Artigas, F. (2005). Involvement of 5-HT1A receptors in prefrontal cortex modulation of dopaminergic activity. Journal of Neuroscience, 25, 10831– 10843. Don, N. S., McDonough, B. E., Warren, C. A., and Moura, G. (1996). Psi, brain function, and “Ayahuasca” (telepathine). Proceedings of Papers Presented at the 39th Parapsychology Association Annual Convention, San Diego (pp. 315–334). Echenhofer, F. (2005). Ayahuasca/EEG research progress report and invitation to donate. Bulletin of the Multidisciplinary Association for Psychedelic Studies, 15(1), 19–20. Eckblad, M., and Chapman, L. J. (1983). Magical ideation as an indicator of schizotypy. Journal of Consulting and Clinical Psychology, 51, 215–225. Evans, S., Almahdi, B., Sultan, P., Sohanpal, I., Brandner, B., Collier, T., Shergill, S. S., Cregg, R., and Averbeck, B. B. (2012). Performance on a probabilistic inference task in healthy subjects receiving ketamine compared with patients with schizophrenia. Journal of Psychopharmacology 26, 1211. Friedman, H. (1983). The Self-Expansiveness Level Form: A conceptualization and measurement of a transpersonal construct. Journal of Transpersonal Psychology, 15, 37–50. Garrett, E. J. (1961). Psychopharmacological parallels to mediumship. Proceedings on two conferences on parapsychology and pharmacology (pp. 61–63). New York: Parapsychology Foundation. Giesler, P. (1984). Parapsychological anthropology: I. Multi-method approaches to the study of psi in the field setting. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 78, 287–328. Grinspoon, L., and Bakalar, J. B. (1998). Psychedelic drugs reconsidered (2nd ed.). New York: The Lindesmith Centre. Grob, C., and Harman. W. (1995). Making sense of the psychedelic issue: Federal approval for research into psychedelics resumes. Noetic Sciences Review, 35, 4–19. Grof, S. (1975). Realms of the human unconscious: Observations from LSD research. New York: Viking Press. Grof, S. (2001). LSD psychotherapy (3rd ed.). Sarasota, FL: Multidisciplinary Association for Psychedelic Studies. Hastings, A. (2006). An extended nondrug MDMA-like experience evoked through posthypnotic suggestion. Journal of Psychoactive Drugs, 38, 273– 283. Hermans, H. G. M. (1998). Memories of a maverick. Maassluis, Netherlands: Pi. Hirst, M. (2000). Root, dream and myth. The use of the oneirogenic plant Silene capensis among the Xhosa of South Africa. Eleusis: Journal of Psychoactive Plants and Compounds, 4, 121–149. Holt, N. J., Simmonds-Moore, C. A., and Moore, S. L. (2008). Psi, belief in the paranormal, attentional filters and mental health. Presented at the Bial Foundation Convention, Porto, Portugal. Huxley, A. (1954). The doors of perception. London, UK: Chatto & Windus, Ltd. Huxley, F. (1961). States of suggestibility. In Proceedings of two conferences on parapsychology and pharmacology (pp. 19–21). New York: Parapsychology Foundation. Irwin, H. (2009). The psychology of paranormal belief: A researcher’s handbook. Hatfield, UK: University of Hertfordshire Press. Jacob, M. S., and Presti, D. E. (2005). Endogenous psychoactive tryptamines reconsidered: An anxiolytic role for dimethyltryptamine. Medical Hypotheses, 64, 930–937. Kärkkäinen J., Forsström T., Tornaeus J., Wähälä K., Kiuru P., Honkanen A., Stenman U.-H., Turpeinen U., and Hesso A. (2005). Potentially hallucinogenic 5-hydroxytryptamine receptor ligands bufotenine and dimethyltryptamine in blood and tissues. Scandinavian Journal of Clinical and Laboratory Investigation, 65(3), 189–199. Kastrup, B. (2012). A paradigm-breaking hypothesis for solving the mindbody problem. Paranthropology, 3(3), 4–12. Katzung, B. G., Masters, S. B., and Trevor, A. J. (2012). Basic and clinical pharmacology (12th ed.). New York: McGraw-Hill Medical. Krebs, T. S., and Johansen, P-Ø. (2013). Psychedelics and mental health: A population study. PLoS ONE, 8(8): e63972. Krippner, S. (1970). Psilocybin: An adventure in psilocybin. In B. Aaronson and H. Osmond (Eds.), Psychedelics: The uses and implications of hallucinogenic drugs (pp. 35–39). Garden City, NY: Anchor. Krippner, S. (1985). Psychedelic drugs and creativity. Journal of Psychoactive Drugs, 17, 235–245. Krippner, S. (1999). A pilot study in dream telepathy with the Grateful Dead. In R. G. Weiner (Ed.), Perspectives on the Grateful Dead: Critical writings (pp. 11–17). Westport, CT: Greenwood Press. Krummenacher, P., Brugger, P., Fahti, M., and Mohr, C. (2002). Dopamine, paranormal ideation, and the detection of meaningful stimuli. Poster presented at the 3rd Forum of European Neuroscience, Paris, France. Krummenacher, P., Mohr, C., Haker, H., and Brugger, P. (2009). Dopamine, paranormal belief, and the detection of meaningful stimuli. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 22, 1670–1681. Kugel, W. (1977). Call-time as a new parameter in statistical ESP experiments. In J. D. Morris, W. G. Roll, and R L. Morris (Eds.), Research in parapsychology 1976 (pp. 138–140). Metuchen, NJ: Scarecrow Press. Langdon-Davies, J. (1961). On the nature of man. New York: New American Library. Leary, T., Litwin. G. H., and Metzner, R. (1963). Reactions to psilocybin administered in a supportive environment. Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, 137, 561–573. Lee, H-M., and Roth, B. L. (2012). Hallucinogen actions on human brain revealed. Proceedings of the National Academy of Science, 109, 1820–1821. Levine, J. (1968). Psychopharmacology: Implications for psi research. In R. Cavanna and M. Ullman (Eds.), Psi and altered states of consciousness: Proceedings of an international conference on hypnosis, drugs, dreams, and psi (pp. 88–106). New York: Parapsychology Foundation. Lilly, J. C. (1969). Inner space and para-psychology. Journal of Parapsychology, 33, 349. Ludwig, A. M. (1968). The hypnodelic state. In R. Cavanna and M. Ullman (Eds.), Psi and altered states of consciousness: Proceedings of an international conference on hypnosis, drugs, dreams, and psi (pp. 68–87). New York: Parapsychology Foundation. Ludwig, A. M., and Lyle, W. H. (1964). The experimental production of narcotic drug effects and withdrawal symptoms through hypnosis. International Journal of Clinical and Experimental Hypnosis, 12, 1–17. Luke, D. (2010). Anthropology and parapsychology: Still hostile sisters in science? Time and Mind: The Journal of Archaeology, Consciousness & Culture, 3, 245–266. Luke, D. (2011a). Anomalous phenomena, psi and altered consciousness. In E. Cardeña and M. Winkelman (Eds.), Altering consciousness: A multidisciplinary perspective. Volume: Biological and psychological perspectives (pp. 355–374). Westport, CT: Praeger. Luke, D. (2011b). Experiential reclamation and first person parapsychology. Journal of Parapsychology, 75, 185–199. Luke, D. P. (2012). Psychoactive substances and paranormal phenomena: A comprehensive review. International Journal of Transpersonal Studies, 31, 97–156. Luke, D. (2014). Psychedelic possession: The growing incorporation of incorporation into ayahuasca use. In J. Hunter and D. Luke (Eds.) Talking with the spirits: Ethnographies from between the worlds (pp. 231–257). Brisbane, Australia: Daily Grail Publishing. Luke, D. P., and Kittenis, M. (2005). A preliminary survey of paranormal experiences with psychoactive drugs. Journal of Parapsychology, 69, 305– 327. Luke, D., and Zychowicz, K. (2014). Working the graveyard shift at the witching hour: Further exploration of dreams, psi and circadian rhythms. International Journal of Dream Research, 7(2), 105–112. Luke, D., Zychowicz, K., Richterova, O., Tjurina, I., and Polonnikova, J. (2012). A sideways look at the neurobiology of psi: Precognition and circadian rhythms. NeuroQuantology, 10, 580–590. Maher, B. (2008). The case of the missing heritability. Nature, 456, 18–21. Masters, R. E. L., and Houston, J. (1966). The varieties of psychedelic experience. London, UK: Turnstone. McKenna, D. (2004). Clinical investigations of the therapeutic potential of ayahuasca: Rationale and regulatory challenges. Pharmacology and Therapeutics, 102, 111–129. Metzner, R. (1992). Divinatory dreams induced by tree datura. In C. Rätsch (Ed.), Yearbook for ethnomedicine and the study of consciousness (pp. 193– 198). Berlin, Germany: VWB. Metzner, R. (2005). Psychedelic, psychoactive and addictive drugs and states of consciousness. In M. Earlywine (Ed.), Mind-altering drugs: The science of subjective experience (pp. 27–48). New York: Oxford University Press. Millay, J. (2001). The influence of psychedelics on remote viewing. Bulletin of the Multidisciplinary Association for Psychedelic Studies, 11(1), 43–44. Miller, R. A. (1978). The biological function of the third eye. http://www.nwbotanicals.org/oak/newphysics/thirdeye.htm Mogar, R. E. (1965). Current status and future trends in psychedelic (LSD) research. Journal of Humanistic Psychology, 5, 147–166. Naranjo, C. (1987). “Ayahuasca” imagery and the therapeutic property of the harmala alkaloids. Journal of Mental Imagery, 11, 131–136. Osis, K. (1961). A pharmacological approach to parapsychological experimentation. In Proceedings of two conferences on parapsychology and pharmacology (pp. 74–75). New York: Parapsychology Foundation. Osmond, H. (1961). New techniques of investigation. In Proceedings of two conferences on parapsychology and pharmacology (pp. 76–78). New York: Parapsychology Foundation. Osmond, H., and Smythies, J. (1952). Schizophrenia: A new approach. Journal of Mental Science, 98, 309–315. Pahnke, W. N. (1968). The psychedelic mystical experience in terminal cancer patients and its possible implications for psi research. In R. Cavanna and M. Ullman (Eds.), Psi and altered states of consciousness: Proceedings of an international conference on hypnosis, drugs, dreams, and psi (pp. 115– 128). New York: Parapsychology Foundation. Pahnke, W. N. (1971). The use of psychedelic drugs in parapsychological research. Parapsychology Review, 2(4), 5–6 and 12–14. Palmer, J. (1978). Extrasensory perception: Research findings. In S. Krippner (Ed.), Advances in parapsychological research: 2 Extrasensory perception (pp. 59–243). New York: Plenum Press. Palmer, J. (1979). A community mail survey of psychic experiences. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 73, 221–251. Parker, A. (1975). States of mind: ESP and altered states of consciousness. London, UK: Malaby. Peres, J. F., Moreira-Almeida, A., Caixeta, L., Leao, F., and Newburg, A. (2012). Neuroimaging during trance state: A contribution to the study of dissociation. PloS ONE, 7(11), e49360. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0049360 Pitman, J. A., and Owens, N. E. (2004). The effect of manipulating expectations before and during a test of ESP. Journal of Parapsychology, 68, 45–63. Pizzagalli, D., Lehmann, D., and Brugger, P. (2001). Lateralized direct and indirect semantic priming effects in subjects with paranormal experiences and beliefs. Psychopathology, 34, 75–80. Previc, F. (2011). Dopamine, altered consciousness, and distant space with special reference to shamanic ecstasy. In E. Cardeña and M. Winkelman (Eds.), Altering consciousness: A multidisciplinary perspective. Volume 2: Biological and psychological perspectives (pp. 43–61). Westport, CT: Praeger. Puharich, A. (1959). The sacred mushroom: Key to the door of eternity. Garden City, NY: Doubleday. Puharich, A. (1962). Beyond telepathy. Garden City, NY: Doubleday & Co. Ray, T. S. (2010). Psychedelics and the human receptorome. PLoS ONE 5(2), e9019. DOI:10.1371/journal.pone.0009019 Raz, A., Hines, T., Fossella, J., and Castro, D. (2008). Paranormal experience and the COMT dopaminergic gene: A preliminary attempt to associate phenotype with genotype using an underlying brain theory. Cortex, 44, 1336–1341. Rogo, D. S. (1976). Exploring psychic phenomena: Beyond mind and matter. Wheaton, IL: The Theosophical Society in America. Roney-Dougal, S. M. (1986). Some speculations on a possible psychic effect of harmaline. In D. H. Weiner and D. H. Radin (Eds.), Research in Parapsychology 1985 (pp.120–123). Metuchen, NJ: Scarecrow Press. Roney-Dougal, S. M. (1989). Recent findings relating to the possible role of the pineal gland in affecting psychic ability. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 55, 313–328. Roney-Dougal, S. M. (1991). Where science and magic meet. London, UK: Element. Roney-Dougal, S. [M.] (2001). Walking between the worlds: Links between psi, psychedelics, shamanism, and psychosis. Unpublished manuscript, Psi Research Centre, Glastonbury, UK. Roney-Dougal, S. M., Ryan, A., and Luke, D. (2013). The relationship between local geomagnetic activity, meditation and psi. Part I: Literature review and theoretical model. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 77, 72–88. Rouhier, A. (1925, May-June,). Phénomènes de Matagnomie expérimentale observés au cours d’une expérience faite avec le “peyotl” (Echinocactus Williamsii) (Experimental Matagnomie phenomena during an experience with “peyotl” (Echinocactus Williamsii). Revue Métaphysique, 144–154. Rouhier, A. (1927). La plante qui faite les yeux émerveillés: Le peyotl (The plant that marvels the eyes: Peyotl). Paris, France: Doin. Rudgley, R. (2000). The encyclopedia of psychoactive substances. New York: Thomas Dunne. Rush, J. H., and Cahn, H. A. (1958). Physiological conditioning for psi performance Journal of Parapsychology, 22, 300. Ryzl, M. (1968). Training methods for psi induction. In R. Cavanna and M. Ullman (Eds.), Psi and altered states of consciousness: Proceedings of an international conference on hypnosis, drugs, dreams, and psi (pp. 55–67). New York: Parapsychology Foundation. Satyananda, S. S. (1972). The pineal gland (ajna chakra). Bihar, India: Bihar School of Yoga. Satyanarayana, M., Rao, P. V. K., and Vijaylakshmi, S. (1993). Role of pineal activity in ESP performance: A preliminary study. Journal of Indian Psychology, 11, 44–56. Shanon, B. (2003). Hallucinations. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 10(2), 3–31. Shulgin, A. [T.] (2010). Chemistry and memory. In J. Millay (Ed.), Radiant minds: Scientists explore the dimensions of consciousness (pp. 190–197). Doyle, CA: Millay. Shulgin, A. T., Manning, T., and Daley, P. F. (2011). The Shulgin index (vol.1): Psychedelic phenethylamines and related compounds. Berkeley, CA: Transform Press. Shulgin, A. T, and Shulgin, A. (1997). TIHKAL: The continuation. Berkeley, CA: Transform Press. Simmonds, C. A., and Roe, C. A. (2000). Personality correlates of anomalous experiences, perceived ability and beliefs: Schizotypy, temporal lobe signs and gender. Proceedings of Presented Papers from the 43rd Annual Convention of the Parapsychology Association, 2000 (pp. 272–291). Smythies, J. R. (1960). New research frontiers in parapsychology and pharmacology. International Journal of Parapsychology, 2(2), 28–38. Smythies, J. R. (1987). Psychometry and mescaline. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 54, 266–268. Smythies, J. R. (2011). Ketamine, Bergson and NDEs. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 75, 148–150. Sobiecki, J. F. (2012). Psychoactive ubulawu spiritual medicines and healing dynamics in the initiation process of southern Bantu diviners. Journal of Psychoactive Drugs, 44, 216–223. Stevens, J. (1988). Storming heaven: LSD and the American dream. London, UK: William Heinemann. Stokes, D. M. (1997). Spontaneous psi phenomena. In S. Krippner (Ed.), Advances in parapsychological research 8 (pp. 6–87). Jefferson, NC: McFarland. Storm, L., and Rock, A. J. (2011). Shamanism and psi: Imagery cultivation as an alternative to the ganzfeld protocol. Gladesville, New South Wales: Australian Institute of Parapsychological Research. Strassman, R. [J.] (2001). DMT: The spirit molecule: A doctor’s revolutionary research into the biology of near-death and mystical experiences. Rochester, VT: Park Street Press. Strassman, R. J., Qualls, C. R., Uhlenhuth, E. H., and Kellner, R. (1994). Dose-response study of N,N-dimethyltryptamine in humans. II Subjective effects and preliminary results of a new rating scale. Archives of General Psychiatry, 51, 98–108. Tart, C. T. (1968). Hypnosis, psychedelics, and psi: Conceptual models. In R. Cavanna and M. Ullman. Psi and altered states of consciousness: Proceedings of an international conference on hypnosis, drugs, dreams, and psi (pp. 24–41). New York: Parapsychology Foundation. Tart, C. T. (1972). States of consciousness and state-specific sciences. Science, 176, 1203–1210. Tart, C. T. (1977). Drug-induced states of consciousness. In B. Wolman (Ed.), Handbook of parapsychology (pp. 500–525). New York: Van Nostrand Reinhold. Tart, C. T. (1993). Marijuana intoxication, psi, and spiritual experiences. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 87, 149–170. Thalbourne, M. A. (1998). Transliminality: Further correlates and a short measure. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 92, 402– 419. Thalbourne, M. A. (2001). Measures of the sheep goat variable, transliminality, and their correlates. Psychological Reports, 88, 339–350. Tinoco, C. A. (1994). Testa de ESP em pacientes sob efeito da ayahuasca [Controlled ESP test in patients under the influence of ayahuasca]. Revista Brasileira de Parapsicologia, 14, 42–48. Tinoco, C. A. (2011). Teste de persepção extrassensorial com respostas livres em pessoas sob efeito da ayahuasca [Free response extrasensory perception tests with people under the effects of ayahuasca]. Unpublished manuscript, Department of Parapsychology, UniBem, Curitiba, Brazil. Toad (1999a). DPT primer. The Entheogen Review, 8(1), 4–10. Toad (1999b). 4-Acetoxy-DIPT primer. The Entheogen Review, 8(4), 126– 131. Vayne, J. (2001). Pharmakon: Drugs and the imagination. London, UK: Liminalspace/El Cheapo. Vollenweider, F. X. (2001). Brain mechanisms of hallucinogens and entactogens. Dialogues in Clinical Neuroscience, 3, 265–279. Vollenweider, F. X. (2004). Brain mechanisms of hallucinogens. Consciousness research abstracts from the Toward a Science of Consciousness Conference, Tucson, Arizona (pp. 91–92). Vollenweider, F. X., and Geyer, M. A. (2001). A systems model of altered consciousness: Integrating natural and drug-induced psychoses. Brain Research Bulletin, 56, 495–507. Wallach, J. V. (2009). Endogenous hallucinogens as ligands of the trace amine receptors: A possible role in sensory perception. Medical Hypotheses, 72(1), 91–94. Wezelman, R., and Bierman, D. J. (1997). Process orientated ganzfeld research in Amsterdam. Proceedings of the 40th Parapsychology Association Annual Convention held in conjunction with the Society for Psychical Research (pp. 477–492). Whittlesey, J. R. B. (1960). Some curious ESP results in terms of variance. Journal of Parapsychology, 24, 220–222. Wilson, K., and French, C. C. (2006). The relationship between susceptibility to false memories, dissociativity, and paranormal belief and experience. Personality and Individual Differences, 41, 1493–1502. Winkelman, M. (1983). The anthropology of magic and parapsychological research. Parapsychological Review, 14(2), 13–19. Wulff, D. M. (2014). Mystical experiences. In E. Cardeña, S. J. Lynn, and S. Krippner (Eds.), Varieties of anomalous experience: Examining the scientific evidence (2nd ed.) (pp. 369–408). Washington, D.C.: American Psychological Association. OceanofPDF.com Part Five: Physics and Psi OceanofPDF.com CHAPTER 13 Quantum Theory and Parapsychology BRIAN MILLAR Those who talk about Psi without a theory literally don’t know what they are talking about! —Millar, 2012a The topic of this essay is not entirely parapsychology, but emphasizes rather what Carr (2008) calls paraphysics. The complication is that psi occurs in people, not in simple physical systems. From the physical point of view, the task of parapsychology is the pragmatic one of learning how psi can be produced with sufficient strength and reliability. Once that is done the (para)physicist can plumb its properties. The approach taken here distances itself from the “search for the soul” goal that Alcock (1987) claims underlies much of parapsychology: It is much nearer to mainstream science and attempts to integrate psi within this larger picture. Here psi research is not regarded exclusively as a “psychological science,” but is importantly also a “physical science.” Psi research is interdisciplinary. It is not possible within the limited compass of this essay to embrace all quantum-inspired and related theories of psi. Most appear in the literature once and are then never heard of again. Primary here are the Observational Theories (OTs) (Houtkooper, 2002; Millar, 1978; Stokes, 1987). I also consider Decision Augmentation Theory (DAT) (May, Radin, Hubbard, Humphrey, & Utts, 1985, May, Spottiswoode, Utts, & James, 1995; May, Utts, & Spottiswoode, 1995), despite it not being quantum-based. Detailed evaluation of pure physics lies outside the scope of this essay, but the work of Shoup (2011) is particularly close to the underlying theoretical position taken here. Rather, the focus is on applied physics, the consequences of practical relevance for the working parapsychologist. The reader should be aware that the account given here is very much this writer’s own take. Roots: Precognition and Quantum Theory There are two main root sources for the theories discussed here: the empirical evidence for precognition and the Measurement Problem in quantum physics (OT only). Precognition From the very early days in parapsychology, it was recognized that it is not possible experimentally to distinguish the various types of psi. Telepathy could actually be clairvoyance, precognition could actually be psychokinesis (PK). Virtually any experimental result could be a form of PK. Questions of this type were put aside in favor of the more tractable examination of psychological factors. But ask a parapsychologist of the Rhine school what the core phenomenon is and he is likely to answer one of the real-time sort: Although precognition may occur, it is in conflict with common sense and may with impunity be ignored until later. The non-local theories (NLT) consider this (temporally local) approach a denial of the essential nature of psi. Precognition (and/or the logically [nearly] equivalent retro–PK) seems to be experimentally as well established as any other psi effect. The choice is open whether all apparent manifestations of psi are equally artifactual (the standard scientific view) or if precognition is the distinctive manifestation of psi that sets it aside from (most) other physical phenomena. If forced to come to grips with precognition anyway, why not make a virtue of it and consider it central? In the framework of the NL theories, all psi effects are actually at root disguised precognition. Something, which looks a lot like retro-action (but isn’t quite), lies at the core of psi effects. Measurement problem. In New Age accounts of Quantum Mechanics (QM) it is often said that human observers bring the universe into being by observing it. Their myth is that each person is a little God, moment by moment creating his/her own universe in his/her own image. In the very beginning of Quantum Mechanics, Bohr’s people tried to make sense of the field and their loose consensus has become known as the Copenhagen interpretation(s). The central problem was at what point does a system cease to be described as a superposition of quantum waves and where do classical laws take over. In this jargon, the wave changes to an event with the “collapse” of the wave function. Most took refuge in ideas of thermodynamic irreversibility. This was certainly rather vague and unsatisfactory to mathematical sticklers such as Wigner (1961). Where, indeed, does the buck stop? He asked what happens if we not merely have a human observer who observes a quantum process, but we have a second “over-observer” looking at the result obtained by the first (the paradox of “Wigner’s friend”). Wigner did, initially, think that humans have some special “consciousness” magic that is employed in “observation”: The first human observer “collapses the wave function” to an event, which is observed classically by the over-observer. Although he later abandoned this idea the attribution has stuck. Those days are gone: decoherence rules now. Although there are a few holdouts most physicists today consider “observation” by a photocell to be no different than “observation” by a human. In the formalism of QM, when a quantum system interacts with anything macroscopic (and noisy), the spooky (off-diagonal) terms in the density matrix very rapidly get “randomized” out, leaving only the classical behavior on the diagonal. The decoherence process is something physically real: it can be described in terms of ongoing physical processes, in contrast to the “collapse of the wave function” which cannot. Decoherence does not account for actual collapse but only the appearance of collapse. Although not all physicists are totally sold on decoherence, there is widespread agreement that it forms an important part of the solution of the measurement problem (Schlosshauer, 2004). A photocell is then in the same sense as a human, a little God! There is, however, some truth in the New Age canard: observation (whether machine or human) brings about decoherence and turns a wave function into an event. Potentiality becomes reality, probabilities become events. Although observation (by a human) may conjure up an event, in current QM we are quite impotent to influence the nature of that event. Consider a quantum system that will produce either a left (L) or a right (R) polarized photon (light particle) with 50 percent chance of each. Observation produces either L or R events but the observer cannot make it either L or R: this is determined by pure random chance, beyond the observer’s control. In conventional QM, the little human (or photocell) God says only: “Let there be events!” Observation in PK. It is evident that the measurement problem may have direct relevance to psi. Parapsychological experiments suggest that, contrary to standard QM, observers (a chosen few anyway) can at will slightly influence the 50:50 distribution of L and R towards, say, more R. If the experiments are correct, the question becomes how can QM best be extended to incorporate PK? [see chapter 20, this volume]. Walker suggested the addition of a nonlinear (information) term to standard QM. Because an event only comes into existence when observed, an influence in the present seems to have an effect on the past (the precognition connection). However, physical experimenters have looked in vain for non-linear effects in QM. At first sight, the change from collapse to decoherence seems to eliminate the possibility of PK because now a human observer is, in principle, no different than a photocell. However, the reverse is actually the case, as decoherence (Gell-Mann, 1994) opens up new vistas for PK. If the observer is structureless (a heat-bath or “reject” photocell), then standard QM holds. But organisms are anything but random; they are highly structured, right down to a (sub)molecular scale, and they do make surprising use of quantum effects (Ball, 2011). Direct investigation of the quantum physiology of psi is currently infeasible and another more immediate approach will be considered. EPR and proposed Walker-Schmidt coupling. The first proposal for nonlocal coupling of a quantum system to a measurement was in a paper by Einstein, Podolsky, and Rosen (1935; EPR), written while the first author was tilting at the windmills of QM. Decades went by before it gave rise to practical implementations. A system breaks into two similar particles going in different directions, subject to the various conservation laws. What EPR showed was that systems of (two) particles that have interacted in the past can continue to behave, in some respects, as a single entangled state even though the two constituent particles are now far apart. Whenever the experimenter chooses to measure an entangled property of one particle, the corresponding property of the other one turns out also to be determined. This looks initially very odd, because a quantum particle does not have a property until it is measured. It gives the impression that the particles are somehow in communication (Einstein’s “spooky action at a distance”). There are correlations between the measurements of the two particles, quantified in the Bell inequalities. However no message can be passed between them. The two retreating particles have to be treated gently, for instance a good vacuum must be maintained; if they interact with gas molecules along the way, the entangled state rapidly decoheres into two classically separate particles. It is instructive to see how far one can go towards a theory of psi based on the (now) conventional physics of EPR. EPR alone does not cut it. The investigation yields indications about the kind of physical interaction “missing” in current QM that is needed for a proper theory of psi. Consider giving both A and B a “box” containing one of a pair of entangled photons on which they can make measurements. Each goes to a separate room. The simplest two-player game would take up too much space to describe here, but with a quantum assist they can make a match even though there is no communication between them. This has become known as quantum pseudotelepathy (Brassard, Broadbent, & Tapp, 2005). The “pseudo” here signifies that it just looks like a signal even though there is only a correlation. In laboratory tests of telepathy, the “senders” cannot be allowed to send whatever they like, because of possible shared behavior. Targets must be determined by a (physically) random process, and to generate them a Random Number Generator (RNG) is used. The purest kind uses radioactive decay as the random source. The RNG is designed so that its output cannot be affected by any past influence: it “insulates” the output from the past. The RNG cannot be affected by non-locality introduced by an interaction in the past. Lab-type telepathy consequently cannot be simulated using just EPR. The RNG is designed so that (processed quantum noise) information can freely be read out. The processing goes: quantum system → detector → electronics → display → human observer. But this is in the wrong temporal order. For psi to be able to “get at” the internal quantum process, a new kind of non-locality is needed, induced by a future interaction that “propagates” from future to past—in short, a kind of time-reversed EPR. I have elsewhere (Millar, 1988) called this the Walker-Schmidt (WS) coupling. If this hypothetical WS coupling should exist in nature, the RNG would be wide open to influence from the future. It is ideally suited to detect any such effect, because it is isolated from interference by the past and the chance distribution is conveniently known. The idea of WS coupling is attractively simple and it may underlie the observed properties of psi but is there hard evidence of it in physics? Only while writing this did I come upon a recent paper (Ma et al., 2012) that builds upon an earlier proposal by Perez (2000). This purports to demonstrate that non-local coupling can in fact be induced by a future interaction. In this experiment the time was small by human terms (less than half a microsecond) and a great deal more work needs to be done on these lines before much can be said. Nonetheless, WS coupling is no longer entirely an unsupported assumption. There has been a great deal of loose talk about QM: a few enthusiasts have gone so far as to embrace entanglement as a kind of (spurious) diplomatic immunity, which ensures that “anything goes.” It should be realized that psi is either classical signaling or a kind of quantum entanglement: the two are mutually exclusive. Parapsychology cannot have non-local cake and eat signals too. NLT Guide for the Perplexed It is useful, at this point, to set out in plain words what the NLTs actually have to say. What varieties do they come in and how do they differ? The NLTs are in agreement that the basic psi effect is that the future influences (but does not change) the past: there exists a troubling non-local coupling between future and past that is not explained within current physical theory (Non-Local in time). The principal collection is known as the Observational Theories (OT). I (contentiously) include Decision Augmentation Theory (DAT), which is neither quantum nor observational, but nonetheless displays deep philosophical as well as practical similarities. The OTs came originally from the physics measurement problem in QM, albeit tackled in substantially different ways by Walker (1976) and Schmidt (1975). Both used the concept of PK, which can trivially be converted to ESP (see below). The active element in the future influences the past by PK. This element in the future cannot, however, work its magic on any random system it wants to in the past; rather, it can only affect a system about which it (later) gets information by normal means (through a feedback channel). In the OTs, the world is not seen directly by ESP; rather, feedback about the world is seen. Aristotle’s dictum (There is nothing in the mind that was not earlier in the senses) may be neatly inverted for psi: There is nothing psiaffected that is not later in the senses. More crudely stated: to be able to PK or precognize something you must later see how it turned out. But just what information has to be given as feedback: does it have to be trial by trial or is a total score sufficient? The traditional “peek and poke” models (see later) of signal-based parapsychology suggest that only trial-bytrial feedback is likely to be effective. This impression was so dominant that many parapsychologists apparently neglected to inform themselves what the OTs have to say on the matter (e.g., Targ & Tart, 1985). The quantitative models of Schmidt and Walker predict somewhat different relative sizes of effect on different feedback levels. I am unimpressed by the mathematical “guesses” of both theorists and take (for now) the merely qualitative view that the amount of psi influence on a system is dependent upon the amount of feedback information. As the feedback information degrades, psi scoring drops off: less detailed information results in a psi effect which may be less than if the feedback were trial by trial, but certainly not zero. From a psychological point of view the OTs operate upon the global unit that is meaningful for the (actual) agent. The basic ideas of DAT are found in Stanford’s (1974a, 1974b) psychologybased Psi Mediated Instrumental Response (PMIR) model [chapter 8, this volume]. Mathematical consequences were developed by May et al. (1985) as Intuitive Data Sorting (IDS) and later as Decision Augmentation Theory (DAT) (May, Spottiswoode, et al., 1995a; May, Utts, et al. 1995b). DAT is based on the intuitive idea of precognition. However, precognition is not likely to emerge as anything overt, such as a vision: much more frequently, “precognizers” just unconsciously adjust their behavior in the present so that “something good” happens in the future or “something bad” does not. Suppose the precognizer must choose between two routes home (left or right) and, unknown to her, the road to the right harbors an escaped lion: the precognizer automatically turns left. Such unconscious (precognition-based) behavior often involves timing, for example the precognizer may start out for home only after the lion is recaptured. This principle may be applied to a standard PK experiment: the participant/experimenter unconsciously chooses to switch on the RNG at just the right moment when the total score will be “something good.” The precognizer may be influenced by anything at all in the future, without any physical restriction. Both NLTs decisively reject the fundamental sensorimotor analogy that dominates parapsychology: for DAT this is often expressed as “No Force,” while OT formulates it as “No Message.” It is NLTs together versus the rest of the parapsychological world. The theories agree that the basic effect is some kind of time reversal. For OT, this is (retro-)PK and for DAT, precognition. On OT, ESP can be built from PK: for DAT, PK can be built from ESP (precognition). The NLTs spurn the assumption that the unit affected by psi is (necessarily) the subject trial, but is rather of a more global nature. The psi effect is (often) exerted on the experiment as a whole: this is radically different from the standard sensorimotor model. For both NLTs the source of psi is not necessarily the nominal individuals and (psychologically) is likely more often the experimenter instead: in contrast, the standard model automatically fingers the participants as responsible unless there is very good reason to doubt it. There is a whole field of similarities and differences between OT and DAT that lie outside the scope of this essay. The defining difference between them is the necessity for feedback (observation) for OT alone. It is necessary to tie the magic of psi to the physical world that includes the RNG. If some such feature is not present, then psi becomes untethered from the physical. For the OTs the “binder of domains” is the (physical) feedback channel. The situation envisaged for DAT is much more weakly specified than for OT. For OT two specific physical systems are related—the guess and the feedback. With DAT, in contrast, behavior may be coupled with any psychologically relevant situation in the future, with no necessary physical connection between them. DAT may be thought of as an incomplete OT, shorn of observation. The OTs are potentially more powerful than DAT because the OTs make the restrictive assumption that a feedback channel is necessary. We may never know if this is true unless parapsychologists vigorously try out OT in practice. If this shows that feedback is not, in fact, necessary, we can always fall back on the less powerful DAT. In what follows, I have attempted to use “OT” in the text where the necessity for feedback is clear and “NLT” otherwise. OTs: Formal Structure At the center of Walker’s (1976) system was a theory of long distance quantum coupling in the brain, which is no longer tenable: the strictly OT part was just an offshoot. Schmidt’s model is pure OT, while Walker’s system is a mixture of OT with extraneous material. Here I follow the road sketched by Schmidt (1975).The thrust of this section is that, while the physical background lies within QM, the OTs may be represented as a purely (formal) logical system without any explicit mention of quantum mechanics. A single OT axiom can be formulated: the quantum nature of the world is then merely implicit in the elements of the theory. This is important for the practical worker, who just wants to doodle a few lines, without constantly going back to QM. Furthermore, this approach provides a convenient framework to discuss properties. A logical system is most rigorously expressed in symbolic logic, but this would severely vex most readers. Instead, the various elements are reified as inanimate devices. The term “machine” or “machine-like” is used to convey this. Psi, at first sight, seems to occur only with humans, or at least with living systems, but most of the properties of living systems are likely irrelevant to psi. Furthermore, it is by no means certain that rudimentary psilike phenomena do not occur in purely inanimate systems. It is only possible to detect psi in humans because it can (to some degree) be directed: “Wish that more 1s than 0s are generated by this RNG.” It is just not possible to do this with a crystal, even if it were, on the sly, teleporting atoms between galaxies. Starting from human PKers everything is removed that makes them human so that only the hard psi core of precognition or retro–PK remains. It is not necessary to worry acutely about this radical amputation. In the next section a start is made on reattaching the severed organs. Schmidt invented diagrams useful for OT. It is no coincidence that these resemble the schematics of electronics, since they effectively represent elementary psi circuits. The diagrams used here are somewhat modified from Schmidt’s originals, but most of the changes are purely cosmetic. The only difference of importance is that the psi-source is shown as a two terminal device, whereas Schmidt depicts only a single terminal, with the “ground” line implicit. The change serves to make explicit that the psisource is an observer (in the physics sense). A psi source changes probability distributions: to do so it needs to “see” the (binary) distribution at its terminals, not just the “hits” but the “misses” as well. (This formulation too limits human errors that tend to creep in when working without an explicit “ground”). It should be noted that although now two terminals are used there is still only a single information channel. One cable connects a light bulb to the electricity outlet, but it comprises twin wires. At this point, like Schmidt, the diagrams show only discrete (trial by trial) feedback. It should be clearly understood that this is for simplicity only, to illustrate the underlying ideas clearly. The diagrams are generally (much) more complicated for realistic feedback, but this is a matter of engineering detail. The first element, representing chance, is the Random Generator (RG), a discrete binary RNG based on pure quantum noise without any bias at all; modern state-of-the-art machines are not far behind. In general these come with different output probabilities, but as this is not important here we take the simplest (symmetrical) case, with p = .5. The Schmidt representation is a triangle with face right: here there are two outputs “0” and “1.” The novel non-conventional element is the psi source (PS), which represents “magic” without intelligence, a naked psi machine. It is modeled after an idealized successful PKer, but unlike a real PKer the PS scores at a constant rate. The PS has two input terminals, which we label plus (+) and minus (-). The PS is represented by a pair of interlocked triangles, suggesting its “Janus face” to time. The nature of the PS is to change probability distributions. Specifically, the probability of a signal on the + terminal is increased (- is decreased): and this is expressed here by the term “+hunger,” which is used in much the same impersonal sense as a black hole has “matter-hunger” (see later). The PS changes the probabilities of any RG to which it is connected. It is often useful, however, to think about this from the point of view of the PS itself: it acts locally (at its own terminals) to appease its blind +hunger. If this is connected to an external RG this has no choice but to “follow” (one end of a wire cannot be a logical “high” while the other end is “low”). This is a loose description of an a-temporal whole in the (unsuitable) language of causality and should not be taken too literally. On this way of thinking, though, it is easier to see that from the point of view of the psi source it is irrelevant what random elements in the external world are connected to it. All the PS-machine does is to unbalance its own inputs and it neither “knows nor cares” what (quantum noise) it is connected to. The psi-affected probability of a + input is no longer p = .5, but (say) p1 = .51. This is not directly observable, only the unbalancing effect on the external RG can be seen. OT Axiom: When the PS is connected to a quantum-based RG the psi source inputs are unbalanced and consequently the RG too becomes unbalanced. But what is an appropriate connection? The third element in the OT scheme, which represents (largely) deterministic systems, is the feedback channel, a one-way communication channel from RG to PS. The feedback channel is the business element of the OT circuit. Although it often masquerades as a humble pair of wires, it is in general of some complexity and is usually an information-processing device in its own right. Because of its diverse construction the feedback channel is usually represented as a plain rectangle, with indication of its function: sometimes hardware is explicit. Here it has two inputs and two outputs. For the purpose of illustrating the basic operation, a couple of wires (and a wire-cutter) are adequate. It is clear that if the PS functions as advertised, according to the OT axiom we can “magically” alter the output probability of the RG as desired: RG “1” output connected to PS + (and 0 to -) : p(1) = .51 RG “0” output connected to PS + (and 1 to -) : p(1) = .49 [Wires cut (disconnected) : p(1) = .50] This is illustrated in Figure 1: at the top is shown the straight-through channel (1s are enhanced) and at the bottom the cross-over channel (0s enhanced): the psi-affected probabilities are shown as (small) vertical bars on the RG outputs. Positive Definition of Psi The OT axiom directly yields a positive definition of PK, rather than a vague negative definition “not this … not that.” If the wires of the simple feedback channel above are swapped, the scoring excess follows whichever RG output is connected to the +input of the PS. The defining feature of OT psi is just that it follows the feedback rather than the more distal external world. Since the OTs are based on PK, the definition generalizes to psi in general. Probability—Not Events The key concept of QM is probability. QM is a probability calculus: The OTs are likewise a probability calculus. The prior (chance) distribution is changed (usually just shifted) by psi to a posterior distribution. It is important to note it is the probability distribution as such which is shifted, not because it represents something: it may be anything at all provided it is quantum-based. If the chance distribution is the same, all quantum-based physical systems are equally susceptible to psi influence. What the probability represents is irrelevant to the psi source: what it means to the world is the work of the feedback channel (see later). +Hunger was introduced above as a way of illustrating the probabilitychanging nature of PK. Physically this corresponds to the correlation term introduced by the (hypothetical) physical process of WS coupling. Many other possible formulations are logically equivalent; the +hunger formulation is used only because it is particularly simple. The OT structure is inspired by the basic experiment of QM, diffraction. Consider a beam of (monochromatic) light that passes through a slit so that it casts a thin vertical light bar on a screen, a single peak. Now insert a (closely spaced) double slit in the light beam after the single slit: the single peak on the screen breaks up into a whole series of peaks, due to successive constructive and destructive interference between the light waves at different angles (path length). The introduction of the double slit changes the light pattern on the screen. Figure 1. PK with Straight-Through and Crossed Feedback Channel. Microscopically, the pattern consists of flashes in which individual photons hit the screen. According to QM what the introduction of the double slit does is change the probability distribution of photons hitting at a particular angle. About an individual photon nothing more can be said. It is not like classical physics in which, in principle, every particle can be followed individually; in QM photons do not have individual trajectories. Events (flashes) are no more than (noisy) markers of the underlying probability distribution. In OT the probability distribution of RG outputs is likewise affected as a whole through connection of a feedback channel to a PS. The effect of PK is on the global probability distribution, or actually on its underlying quantum representation. PK affects the quantum state directly (non-locally) and events are merely indirect markers of the changed quantum state. For the OTs psi is always global, even when, as here, it appears to work on a discrete sequence of bits: there are no individual bits that are true psi-hits and true psi-misses. This is hard going for naive intuition. For my part (after the initial shock) the OT picture now seems quite natural. From Logical System to Physical Theory More is required of a scientific theory than a formal logical system. Axioms become laws. Laws predict empirical consequences in the real world, and these predictions must turn out to be correct. The real world version of the OT axiom is the OT Law. This is used in the same sense as Newton’s Laws —assumptions about the world, which on mathematical development allow (quantitative) predictions. Psychology, understandably, makes little use of this term. The theoretical RG becomes a physical RNG. The theoretical PS becomes a physical “black box” somewhere in the individual’s head. The feedback channel splits into two. There is the external feedback channel (the wiring or programming), which is accessible to direct manipulation. People are not PSs; they may contain PSs. The internal feedback channel between the senses and the PS lies within the brain. A large part of the internal feedback channel is what is known to psychologists as the “cognitive system,” embodied in the wet-ware of the brain. The psychology of psi is the work of the cognitive system (internal feedback channel). The quantum weirdness embodied in the PS is exploited by the cognitive system. Most of the discussion here consequently involves the feedback channel of the OTs. Probability Shifting: Quantum-like OT Mechanism In classical physics an effect can only be obtained by the push/pull of each individual bit by the application of a force. The conventional sensorimotor idea of parapsychology is that PK is a kind of “astral finger” that pokes at individual RNG bits, while ESP is an “astral eye” that peeks in turn at each Zener card. This classical, almost atomistic viewpoint has been called the “peek and poke” model (Burns, personal communication, 2014). The OTs are something completely different. The basic mechanism is “Probability Shifting.” How can something so apparently abstract as a probability distribution be shifted directly? It is not possible to make an intuitive model of that, the whole idea just does not make sense outside of QM. But classical physics is (by definition) not adequate for the paranormal. Figure 2 diagrams the very heart of OT—probability shifting. Figure 2. Probability Shifting (+Hunger in Action). “No Signal” Is the Message If a signal is transferred via a communication channel, it is possible to use the information of the message received in any desired way. This is the way a radio works. The same information is received regardless of what happens later. In the OTs, in contrast, the very existence of a (pseudo-psi) correlation depends on later feedback (quantum observation). The information associated with the correlation is of a purely formal nature: it cannot be used consistently. Any attempt to use it as if it were a standard communication channel tends to couple it to the “noisy” external world (observation in the physicist’s sense), destroying the coherence on which the effect depends; psi is labile. Messages cannot routinely be sent by this means, nor is it possible consistently to make money by using psi to guide investments [but see chapter 29, this volume]. Psi is just robust enough to produce (some) impressively low p-values; but even here it may be best to keep it “under the hat” and not tell too many people! The Feedback Channel Is Physical On hearing “feedback channel,” the psychologist involuntarily thinks of the feedback loop involved in learning, but it is not psychological at all. The term is borrowed from communications theory: Shannon’s math is a gift for the psi theorist. The way it is used in the OTs goes somewhat beyond its usual technical usage. The feedback channel in the OTs is a one-way communication channel from RG to PS that couples the two together to form a (temporary) single system. This total system displays properties that neither of the two parts has when apart: in addition to its normal duties it also functions as a quantum connection. The feedback channel is the link between the randomness of the RG and the “magic” of the PS. The provision of a feedback channel is not the same as listening to a radio station. There can be a connection even if one does not hear anything (though not the other way around). In fact, meeting the OTs’ requirement for a feedback channel for psi is more like saying the (old fashioned) radio must first be plugged in. Though at first sight it does not look like it: The feedback channel is physical. Psi Sources for Pleasure and Profit The thrust of discussion here is that while the OT Law is physically simple, the very complex human being takes every advantage of this little bit of quantum weirdness to achieve his ends, by use of his internal feedback channel. This is illustrated by a number of thought experiments, which initially involve a hypothetical bare PS and work up to complicated human agents. Can anything interesting be done with a bare PS? Perhaps the engineer wants a statue to levitate, so he sets it on an electric jack controlled by an RNG: a 1 output raises the statue 1cm, while a 0 lowers it an equal distance. He then connects the RNG to the PS such that the 1 output gives a pulse to the +input of the PS (0 to the -input). Depending on the strength of the PS, it may take an awfully long time reliably to raise the statue an appreciable distance by (machine) PK. If he switches the connection over (0 output to +PS) the statue slowly lowers. It looks as if he can send a message by choosing the way he connects the PS. Now, connect 10 different RNGs to the inputs of a computer (programmable external feedback channel) and connect an output to our bare PS. Any programmer may change the program of the external channel to determine what effect the PS has on the external world. If he wants to use (machine) PK to obtain an excess of 1s on RNG3, the feedback channel computer is programmed so that a pulse is sent from the 1 output of RNG3 to the +terminal of the PS (and RNG 0 output to the -terminal of the PS): if the programmer wants excess 0s on RNG5, it is programmed so that a pulse is sent from the 0 output of RNG3 to the +terminal of the PS (1 to the terminal). If the programmer wants to do ESP instead of PK he may program “Schmidt’s mechanical paragnost” (Figure (3): this uses an RG to generate the target, as well as a pseudo-random generator (P-RG) to make the “guess.” Both the guess and the target are input to the feedback channel computer; if they match, the program sends a pulse to the +terminal of the PS (if no-match, a pulse to the -terminal). In this way, to satisfy its +hunger, the PS magically enforces matches (hits) in the external world. The PS now effectively works upon a (composite) RG, made from the target and guess RG: this composite RG represents “hit” or “miss.” The PS unbalances its own input terminals without reference to what it represents, a hit/miss RG is no different from a standard 0/1 RG. It is worthy of note that this circuit causes pure correlation, without biasing either RG, something quite different to peek and poke models. Figure 3. Schmidt’s “Mechanical” Paragnost. Now connect the computer to the world wide web. In this way the programmer can select any random process (or combination of random processes) desired to PK-influence anything at all in the entire (internet) observable universe. The programmer may, for example, choose that the PS “observe” microscopic fission traces in 5 billion-year-old zircons or distant quasars relayed from the Hubble telescope. (A programmable psi system is not the ultimate secret weapon with which history can be changed: in fact the programmer cannot change anything whatever, all he can do is introduce correlations between apparently separate systems). The feedback channel program can be changed by the programmer to cause any qualitative PK effect required on any (combination of) external QM-noise based systems. The program is designed so that it transforms success at the desired task into pulses at the +input (and failure at the -input) of the PS. In this way the blind “+hunger” of the PS is harnessed to influence the world in the manner desired by the programmer. But suppose the programmer works in Silicon Valley and wants an easier way to do the programming rather than writing boring old code. She will have to “make do” with a successful human participant who has an internal channel/cognitive system and PS. In this case things are simple for the (ex-) programmer: it is only necessary to instruct the participant: “Here is an RNG: I want you to wish for an excess of 1s.” Internally the participant associates (feelings? of) success with 1s (or failure with 0s) and a pulse corresponding to each success is (unconsciously) sent to the +terminal of his internal PS (and failure to the –terminal). Likewise for ESP the “programmer” instructs the human participant: “Here is an (open) pack of Zener cards, guess which symbol is on the top and I’ll turn it over and see if you’re right.” To make the guess the participant (unconsciously) consults a (p = 1/5) internal RNG and when the top card is shown compares guess and target to see if there is a hit or miss (success or failure). This success/failure information is passed on to the internal PS as before, with success connected to the +input. This is just the same setup as before with the external feedback channel, only now everything is internal. Suppose the programmer tries to find out whether he can do the psi thing himself and, somewhat to his surprise, finds that he can. He is now simultaneously both programmer and programmed. The conscious part decides what he wants to do and then (unconsciously) programs his own internal feedback channel appropriately. But humans do not split neatly into just two parts (conscious and unconscious): rather there may be multiple levels of semi-independent processing. The decision as to what psi effect is “wanted” does not need to be conscious but can itself be the result of unconscious processing (another level of control). This multi-level structure of human processing effortlessly lends itself to much more complex psi tasks, such as (unconsciously) making experimental outcomes conform to a cherished theory. There is negligibly more processing required for a complex as compared to a simple psi task. There remains the important question of just what makes one PKer successful while a neighbor scores at flat chance. No purely physical theory deals with the psychological (and physiological) variables. A complete theory of psi must comprise both physical and psychological components. The NLTs provide a convenient framework (see below) into which the psychology can be fitted: the differences between participants are to be sought in the internal feedback channel and its programming, the individual’s cognitive system. The NLTs Meet Psychology The basic problem of the application of psychology to psi is that it attempts to tackle a 20th (or 21st) century problem (temporal non-locality) with 19th century conceptual tools. NLT is a product of thinking outside this limited psychological box. There is a visceral clash between the non-local NLTs and signal-based experimental psychology. The Logical Problem and Lack of Performance The methods of experimental psychology are based on the assumption that adequate controls on information leakage can be implemented. But this is true only if information can leak via sensory channels alone. Parapsychologists postulate a (physically) new kind of (psi) interaction that is (largely) independent of space and time limitations, it is nonlocal. The psychologist does not know how to insulate against psi leakage: psi is consequently able systematically to circumvent any control and multiple blinding she can devise. On purely logical grounds psychology alone is impotent to deal with psi. Psi can get round all the normal safeguards of psychology, but does it? This is the postulate of passive psi, the domain of the truthful. The alternative is that psi scatters in all directions, like a flock of birds trying to evade the hunter. This is the postulate of evasive psi, the domain of the “trickster” (Hansen, 2001). Psi is an unconscious process, like dreaming, and dreams are rarely ethical. Evasive psi is overwhelmingly more plausible (Kennedy, 2003). The psi pioneers pressed on regardless, possessed by the spirit of psychology. Very rapidly the orthodox view in parapsychology became that the expression of psi is primarily determined by a constellation of subtle and largely unconscious psychological factors. By identifying and manipulating the psychological factors, psi scoring could surely be brought under control, but this increase in control did not materialize. Most experiments since Rhine have looked at the effect of some psychological factor on psi [chapter 9, this volume]. Significant results have indeed been found (Palmer, 1979, 1982), but seem curiously limited to a few virtuoso experimenters. Despite all this effort no psychological variable has (yet) been found that parapsychologists agree has noticeably altered the overall proportion of successful psi experiments. The early promise of psychology in understanding psi has proven just that … promissory. Experimenter Psi and the NLTs It simply would not occur to any right thinking (signal-based) psychologist to question who does the psi-ing: it is obviously the nominal participants. The physics-based NLTs can hardly disagree more! There is no difference in principle between all the personnel involved in the experiment provided they get feedback of the results, all are observers. They may be participants, experimenter, data analyst, etc., or conceivably even the lab dog, who is petted and fed more treats when things are going well (Schmidt, 1984). According to the NLTs there are just a collection of people who are interested in the behavior of a random generator. Who is called “participant” or “experimenter” is theoretically unimportant. There are, however some practical differences between them: a) E is usually considerably more motivated than P. b) P is usually a first-time psi-er, while E is someone with a previous track record in psi experiments. c) P sees only a small part of the experiment (usually at the trial level), while E sees it all, at each level up to the final statistic. On the basis of the NLTs it comes as no surprise if Es typically have more psi-influence on the results than Ps. Percipients may be expected to apply psi at the level of the feedback they get (trial or sometimes total scores). The experimenter is interested primarily in the whole experiment and gets the total result directly as feedback, a random experiment generator. Further, in a process-oriented experiment, E’s (implicit) goal is not merely to find evidence of psi, but to confirm the hypothesis: to this end E may apply psi to the end result as a whole, a random test statistic generator. Experimenter psi goes together with NLT like peaches and cream. On these theories experimenter psi is expected to dominate experimental results: consequently a heavy experimenter psi contribution is evidence for the NLTs. And if there is much experimenter psi the standard methods of experimental psychology are undermined, experimenters may be systematically fooling themselves. In this case application of the OTs offer (perhaps the only) way out of the experimental impasse, by methods involving feedback manipulation (see later). Signal in Noise (SIN) ESP is often described as a communications anomaly. The psychologists’ standard model of communication is that of Weaver and Shannon (1963), which may be applied if information is already present in the central nervous system but it says nothing about how it gets there. For psychologists the mechanism can be none other than some unknown signal, as this is the only possibility in 19th century physics. But as noted above, a major logical assumption (only sensory leakage) on which experimental psychology is based is blown away by the very existence of psi. So entrenched, however, has the SIN model become in psychological thinking that it represents the central dogma in current psychological theories of psi. Most standard statistical methodology is based on the SIN model and it is almost impossible to avoid using theory-loaded terms such as signal, message, transmission, and information transfer. The standard effect size and standard power are also implicitly based on the Shannon model. Psychology—A Mixed Blessing Parapsychology is indebted to psychology for most of its basic methodology. It has, moreover, contributed considerably to the much needed professionalization of the field. However, quite debatable assumptions have been taken over, without due consideration of whether they are in fact applicable to psi. Academic parapsychology has been largely dominated by psychology, which held the purse strings. Most parapsychologists are experimental psychologists by training. With this background it seems selfevident that the psychology of psi can be understood even if its mechanism is unknown. The opposing view, subscribed to here, is: The psychology of psi cannot be understood in the absence of reference to its physics. Spontaneous cases involve large effects that are explicitly experienced by the participant. Typical lab procedures reveal small effects that are significant only when summed over participants, though no single individual scores beyond chance level. This kind of result may be (partly or perhaps principally) due to the nominal experimenter. It is usually assumed that laboratory psi is in principle just a collection of artificially captured tiny spontaneous cases. But spontaneous cases may well have a different nature than experimental psi. For one thing, they seem to involve a greater amount of information than is typical even for an entire successful lab experiment. No one, as far as I know, has yet attempted to quantify this. J. B. Rhine’s original intent in bringing the paranormal into the laboratory was to shed light on the mechanism of real life spontaneous psi by investigating it under simplified conditions. In most science the introduction of an experimenter and evaluation by pooling have negligible effect on the system studied. Ironically, in parapsychology the imposition of these normally innocuous conditions may have radically altered the system being observed to produce an artificial (pathological) field of study not found in nature. Perhaps the important factors in the manifestation of psi in the laboratory are not the (hypothetical) delicate constellation of psychological variables in the participant usually assumed. The basic problem is rather who does it— participant or experimenter? This is unlikely to be resolved using the methods of psychology alone, because the very existence of psi invalidates a basic assumption of experimental psychology. Empirical Evidence For work in an established area it is possible to examine detailed experiments. This can hardly be done for the NLTs since it is just that groundwork that is in question. Very little experimental work has been done in this area. Much of that was done by Helmut Schmidt: his results regularly came out just as he believed and promptly changed when he changed his mind. It is consequently hazardous to take his work at face value. Instead, more general (and vaguer) criteria are necessary. Is the general picture of experimental research consistent with the NLTs? The ecological validity of the NLTs is first on the agenda; I note that although in the first instance it is directly applicable to experimental psi only, it has considerable potential for extension. The two things Rhineans are most reluctant to confront are the experimenter psi effect and uselessness. These are “cornerstone” evidence for the NLTs. Ecological Validity The OTs first came to the fore with the experiments initiated by Schmidt, in which a PK volunteer sits in front of a display that shows prerecorded RNG outputs (the individual typically believes the targets are being generated in real time). This setup is sometimes referred to as “retro–PK.” This highly technological type of experiment represents only a small part of experimental parapsychology. It is natural to ask if this restricted and experimenter-distorted area is at all worth getting hot and bothered about. Is there any indication in the wider world that precognition/retro-PK might lie at the core of psi? In the current jargon, do the NLTs have any “ecological validity”? Dunne long ago examined his own precognitive dreams. He dreamed of the eruption of a volcano on a South Sea island in which 4,000 people died (Dunne, 1929, p. 34). This seemed to correspond with a newspaper report within a short period after the dream that reported an event then dubbed the worst volcanic disaster of the 20th century, Mount Pelée on Martinique, in 1902 (Anonymous, 2014) with just this number of deaths. It later turned out that Dunne had misread the newspaper, which reported 40,000 dead. Dunne’s conclusion was that he precognized the newspaper report rather than the event itself. There are a few similar cases in the literature. There is, at least, a bit of ecological evidence for the core OT “handshake.” (Restricted) Area of Application The area of application of the NLTs is limited to statistical laboratory experiments. It may (reasonably) be urged by those impressed by spontaneous cases or mediumistic phenomena that these are quite unrepresentative of the great mass of psi effects. It has been argued above that lab psi may be essentially induced, artificially created by the very methods of study. All the strong effects that suggest real message transmission and real forces do not fit neatly into the NLT framework. We may speculate that (if real) these are second tier effects, with further layers of mechanism built on top of quantum level correlations. The policy adopted here is “one step at a time”; we concentrate on lab psi and hope that if this can be understood within the context of the NLTs, it may provide a basis for further expansion. Experimenter Proteus Effect Experimenter effect is dealt with in more detail elsewhere [chapter 22] and here I give no more than a few comments. It has often been felt, particularly by skeptics, that the results of psi experiments just do not look like mainstream psychological topics. A mere handful of experimenters regularly report large effects and roundly significant statistics. The majority of experimenters (and published studies) report inconsistent “so-so” results that, even if sometimes nominally significant, are not really convincing. The impression is of a small band of virtuosos who stand out from a chorus-line of wannabes. Alarmingly, these virtuoso experimenters typically get just the results they expect: the experiment seems to function as a kind of “crystal ball” in which the objective external world mirrors the (otherwise private) internal psychology of the experimenter. This character accommodation to experimenter expectation is here dubbed the Proteus effect, after the shapeshifting Greek god. The single best predictor of the outcome of a parapsychological experiment is not the topic of research nor the hypothesis tested but most likely the identity of the principal investigator. That experimenter effects are more common and powerful in psi experiments than in psychology is a major indication in favor of NLT. Experimenter effect is entirely natural within the NLT framework, where it is simply experimenter-psi due to being an observer of results. Planned experimental comparison of experimenters is a rarity and most apparent experimenter effects are just incidental observations. Whether the mechanism is psi or sensory has received still less attention. Parapsychogists have (with a few courageous exceptions) conspicuously avoided looking at experimenter effect in the eye and there are weighty social reasons for this. Stanford long ago asked “Are we shamans or scientists?” (Stanford, 1981). If the answer is “shamans” then how many parapsychologists relish vacating the halls of academia to nail up a “Psychic Readings” shingle instead? This fear is, I believe, to some extent justified: it is given concrete form by the career of Martin Johnson. It was based on a correlation between DMT (perceptual defense) and ESP scores. Largely on this basis, Johnson became professor of parapsychology in Utrecht. Only after his retirement did reexamination establish that these results were due to an experimenter effect by Johnson (Haraldsson, Houtkooper, Schneider, & Bäckström, 2002). What if this had come out earlier? Scenarios such as this illustrate the powerful disincentive to examine too closely “the goose that lays the golden eggs.” An important observation concerns the size of the experiment. If psi enters at the level of the subject trial then clearly the more trials the better (z-score increases linearly with the square root of the number of trials). If, on the other hand, the experimenter (or someone else) has a psi influence on the experiment as a whole, then the participants (and the number of their trials) are irrelevant. The significance of an experimental result depends only on the experimenter: the z-score is then roughly constant regardless of the number of trials. This, above all, is the empirical background of DAT. Current evidence is generally in favor of constant z, which implicates the experimenter as the primary source of psi. That the psi effect is on the experiment as a whole supports the global mechanism of the NLTs rather than the conventional peek and poke model on the trial-by-trial level. Are Applications of Psi Possible?—The Atlas Problem According to OT lab ESP is actually a kind of pseudo–ESP, no signal—just correlation. On this basis it is impossible (consistently) to send messages. In an experiment technically beyond its time, Carpenter (1991) attempted to transmit a five-letter word by ESP, using information theory techniques, particularly a majority vote. The target word “PEACE” was apparently successfully transmitted by this means. Given that this work was done during the “hippy” years when PEACE was the slogan, the choice of target word raises some doubt about the validity of the outcome: perhaps only “BANTHEBOMB” could have been more likely. Perhaps the most disturbing consequence of OT is that, if true, psi is nearly useless (Bierman & Spottiswoode, 2012a, 2012b). This is in marked contrast to signal theories that seem to offer unlimited possibilities for a psi technology. If psi consists exclusively of nonlocal correlations it can hardly be of more than theoretical interest: look too hard at it and it vanishes! Any attempt to apply it to the world seems necessarily to involve some decay of the coherent quantum state upon which the psi effect is supposed to depend. The PS has not only to change the target quantum process but also has to carry a chunk of (noise from) the external world with it, an “Atlas” overload for a PS. If there is no possibility of applications, no sustained external financial support for parapsychology can be expected. It may be hoped that some way may be found around this “Atlas Problem.” Perhaps techniques analogous to those employed in QM to minimize measurement disturbance, such as “interaction-free measurement” (Elitzur & Vaidman, 1993) or even conceivably “weak measurement” (Aharonov & Vaidman, 2007) can be adapted for psi use. Selectivity Point selectivity is characteristic of both NLTs: for OT this is primarily determined physically by the feedback channel, while for DAT it is said to be psychological (the result has to be “just right”). If such “Goldilocks” selectivity is found in selected experiments, rather than a scatter around the target, it argues for NLT. No systematic literature search has been undertaken but one relevant experiment is known to me (May, Humphrey, & Hubbard, 1980), in which scoring appeared only on the bits designated as target and not on adjacent bits which were generated within a few milliseconds. This bull’s eye selectivity is sufficiently impressive to command attention and is a strong argument for NLT against signal-based theories. Complexity Independence Although the terms “goal-oriented” and “complexity independence” are of relatively recent coinage, the basic idea goes back to the early Rhine work. It was originally called the unitary or diametric hypothesis (Foster, 1940; Pratt et al., 1940). The idea is that psi goes for the goal without bothering with all the intermediate steps of normal information processing. Because of their precognition core, the NLTs are as goal-oriented as can be: psi works directly on the final outcome (although each individual experiment/participant construes that). The experimental work in this area has been thoroughly reviewed by both Stanford (1977) and Kennedy (1978, 1979, 1995). They agree that psi shows considerable evidence of being goal oriented. In the specific context of RNG machines, the term “complexity independence” is used. Schmidt was the first to ask the question of whether internally different RNGs with the same display give rise to different PK scores. He rather consistently found no difference between them (provided they were pure quantum devices). There have, however, been a few reports by other experimenters (particularly those who doubted complexity independence) of differences between machines (e.g., Ibison, 1998). OTs Falsified? Experiments have been carried out to detect “pure clairvoyance” (e.g., Targ & Tart, 1985), which is not physically possible in OT. Typically a random physical process is used to determine targets, which are guessed. The guesses are compared with targets by machine, which outputs only the total hits. These studies suffer fatal weaknesses from the viewpoint of OT: the principal of these is that it is assumed that no psi effect can be exerted via a total score. On the basis of OT, on the contrary, most psi is likely exerted on the total. The second weakness is one common to almost all psi experiments: experimenters may have privileged access to more detailed information at some point and exert their own psi effect then. The DAT group does not spell out an explicit mechanism for the nonlocal step, save that it is precognitive in nature. These theorists found experimental reason for reticence about the OT handshake. The key novelty in the experiment (May, Lantz, & Piantineda, 1996) was that feedback was not all-or-nothing but instead graded over a fairly wide range by means of tachistoscopic presentation at different intensities. If the OTs are correct, the psi scoring rate should increase with the intensity of the (feedback) presentation (how well it is observed). A key element in these studies was that each of the small number of participants was an individually-selected high scoring “remote viewer”; this was decidedly not the prototypical big pot experiment. Only two of the participants were able to score significantly overall under these conditions. For the more successful one there was a nonsignificant increase in scoring with presentation intensity, but unexpectedly there was a significantly negative slope for the less successful. It would be interesting to know if perhaps this low-scoring person strongly disbelieved in the importance of feedback and rather overdid it, in the same kind of way as “goats” (disbelievers in psi) are believed to score below chance. Although the first feedback was well controlled, no information is given about any subsequent debriefing. Likewise, no information is given about feedback to the experimenters or their expectations. It is public knowledge that these experimenters were involved in psychic spying for the U.S.: the dollar value of such activities would be severely curtailed if success were possible only about events that are later verified in a normal way. The May/Spottiswoode duo have themselves been suspected of harboring a psi strength of the same order as their volunteers (Parker & Millar, 2014), and it is conceivable that their failure to find evidence of the OT handshake is actually a (negative) instance of the Proteus effect. The Universal Key of the NLTs—ESP/PK Equivalence Laboratory psi consists of a number of apparently very different effects, telepathy, clairvoyance, precognition, retrocognition and micro–PK, to name but a few. At first sight, it seems that each of these needs a novel physical principle of its own to account for it: each psi mystery needs its own key. But the NLTs unify all lab psi effects into minor variants of one single basic mechanism, though that mechanism is somewhat different for OT and DAT. The OT Law is a universal “skeleton” key that opens all lab psi locks. According to the OTs, ESP is PK. The characteristic difference is that the RNG worked upon at the earlier time the participants made their guesses is not an external electronic device, but internal “wet-ware” in the brain. In this case the participants’ intentions (at feedback) are not to get a 0 or 1 but to get their wet-ware RNGs to produce (earlier) the right target. According to DAT, PK is basically precognition and the ESP/PK equivalence is expected to be strict if the external RNG is good. However, in the OTs it seems quite implausible that a wet-ware RNG in the brain is as good as a sophisticated electronic device, with which pains are taken to assure that the output is (as nearly as possible) of pure QM origin. It is known that human guessing does not produce a theoretically random sequence (e.g., there is a strong tendency to avoid repeats). It might then be expected from the OTs that ESP should produce a somewhat lower scoring rate than PK. Walker (1975) made much of this difference and attempted to explain the distribution of ESP in the population on this basis. Rhine (1964, p. 98) remarked that in his experience PK ability (dice) seemed rather more common than ESP (cards), but he himself seems to have been fairly good at PK. In the “wild country” that exists outside the lab, paranormal practitioners seem to have specialized either in ESP or PK; but typically at least traces of the other have been reported as well. Schmidt and Pantas (1972) did elegant experiments with (hidden) internally different machines to test the idea, which panned out just as Schmidt expected. Interim Verdict: NLT or Not? The amount of experimental work done to look directly at NLT has been very limited, especially when the data of Schmidt are disallowed. Few have been moved to work in this area. The pure clairvoyance experiments to date have been methodologically flawed. However the underlying idea is worth pursuit, with manipulation of feedback on both trial and total to both participants and experimenter. The biggest black mark against the OTs is the lack of feedback dependence found by May et al. (1996). This, however, is a single experiment, which should be repeated in simplified form by other experimenters. There are also a few suggestions that signals can occasionally be sent and money made, contrary to NLT. The paucity of proper scientific reports of such effects is, however, striking. These are all isolated episodes, more like the initial studies in a new line of research rather than (as yet) sustainable techniques. My general impression is that parapsychological data correspond strikingly to the NLT picture and rather poorly to signal-based orthodoxy. Prospective Research The major question raised by the NLTs is where is the psi coming from— participants or experimenter? Until this can be resolved parapsychology can say little more than that psi effects seem to occur. To that end a number of suggestions for prospective research are treated in chapter 22. Here we consider exclusively prospective investigations that use the OTs as a tool to tease out participant from experimenter. A few remarks are added on the more general question of building a new psychological framework appropriate to the NLTs, in place of the conventional signal-based model. Routine Feedback Prespecification and Reporting If feedback marks the handshake point for nonlocal coupling, as the OTs maintain, then this provides a conveniently accessible handle to get a grip on psi. Two otherwise identical experiments with different (unreported) internal feedback arrangements may be expected to give quite different results. Such feedback differences may erroneously be attributed to psychological factors. Feedback to the various participants in psi experiments has typically not been specified in advance, nor even formally reported. The OT requirement for psi is the connection of a feedback channel. The simplest way to set things up is to specify up front, as part of the experimental design, exactly what set of data will be given as feedback to what participant at what preplanned stage. The moment perhaps most susceptible to (experimenter) psi on the OTs is when the data are all collected together and the results of the critical statistical test are first seen. The unwritten psi-lab lore is that the experimenter should preferably be in a calm, non-striving but expectant state when he first views the final result of his labors. This is strikingly like the advice sometimes given to participants in psi tests. Research conducted within the NLT framework should routinely include a chronological record of feedback at different levels to the various participants, in particular the experimenter, as well as the nominal participants. Particular attention should be paid to the initial feedback of the final statistic to experimenter/analyst. Feedback Splitting and Manipulation Consider an ESP test in which 20 participants each guess through 4 (open) packs of Zener cards, with immediate trial-by-trial feedback. Split these into odd and even trials and total the number of hits in each set A and B. Send total A to a virtuoso-experimenter and total B to a psi-challenged investigator to observe. If the conventional signal model is true, then the two parts are the same (within statistical fluctuation) and any psi score is due to the participants. But if the major source is E-psi, exerted via the feedback channel (by observing the total), as the OTs claim, then A will be significant while B will be at chance level). Straightforward feedback splitting is a very simple method that can be incorporated in virtually all existing experimental designs, with little additional labor. It is offered with the warning that it is only a very crude initial survey method. If it should be found from a sufficiently extensive application of systematic feedback splitting with successful experimenters that this makes no difference whatever, then it may be concluded that in practice OT is not to be taken seriously. I strongly suspect, however, that splitting differences will turn out to be ubiquitous. This provides a means (simple if imperfect) to detect where (who) the psi is coming from. As such, it does not cure the repeatability problem, but if application of the procedure suggests that the (primary) psi source is the experimenter, then the OTs might just prevent announcing the (latest) “repeatable experiment.” Simply splitting the data is not logically sufficient to identify the psi source unambiguously, because even after observation of two sets by two different observers the data remain susceptible to psi input by still later observers. There seems nothing to stop such a later observer from (say) psi-ing B greater than A. Is there some way to eliminate (or minimize) the effect of later observers? We need to be able to fix the data at some point, just as after developing a photograph, residual light-sensitive material is washed away with fixer. The OTs do have something to say about how this might be achieved but this goes beyond the bounds of this essay. To get meaningful and consistent results the OTs suggest experimenter feedback must be as rigidly curtailed to known channels. That feedback to the experimenter herself should be controlled and manipulated has little precedent in the tradition of experimental psychology. Deliberately planned feedback manipulation is discussed above. However, inadvertent feedback manipulation may already have left characteristic “fingerprints” in existing data. I published a number of “forensic” tests for experimenter psi (Millar, 2012b). One class concerns mathematical consequences if the experimenter inputs psi at the level of the whole experiment, specifically if feedback is not a simple total but a statistic, such as t or F. As illustration consider an experiment in which the hypothesis is that 2 groups differ: the relevant final statistic is t. This is an (inadvertently) manipulated form of the mean difference between the groups (delta): specifically delta is divided by an estimate of the empirical sampling error (SE). A large t can be obtained in two ways—increase delta or reduce SE (which is normally impossible). Calculation shows that if the psi input is via the feedback unit t, then both happen: as delta goes up standard error goes down (in a mathematically known way). It looks superficially as if variance is converted to deviation. This generalizes to ANOVA designs: psi input on the F-statistic results not only in increase in the between-groups variance (effect) but simultaneously decreases the within-groups variance (error term). Richard Broughton long ago drew my attention to a (then) mysterious experimental result of his, where the within groups variance had nearly vanished. According to the OTs, reduction of within groups variance is expected in general where psi is applied via feedback of the F (or t) statistic (to the experimenter). Reduced within-groups variance is a fingerprint for experimenter psi. Furthermore, if this effect is real it may yield quantitative evidence for the OTs. Meta-analyses of suitable existing data may confirm or refute the theory, though this has not yet been done. Psychology of the NLTs The NLTs are incompatible with the “smuggled” importation of mainstream psychological assumptions into the specialized area of parapsychology, where they may or may not be relevant. The day of the unfettered dominance of signal-based psychology is over once there is an established physical theory. Bem (2012) already feels the future bastion shaken by decline and experimenter effects: I must admit that my nightly prayer as a mainstream social psychologist is that both these effects will be found to rest upon mundane “psychological” factors that we can eliminate, isolate, or incorporate into our designs in ways already familiar to us. But I am increasingly persuaded that one or both of them may well be intrinsic anomalous properties of psi [pp. 11–13]. For a proper theory of psi it is necessary that both physical and psychological factors be integrated. It may be suspected that many of the apparent correlations of psychological variables with psi found to date are not intrinsic but a mere Proteus Effect. However, there are surely also real effects of psychological variables (though perhaps of the experimenter rather than the nominal participants). In contrast to the conventional signal-based peek and poke model, the NLTs are relatively global: experiments are typically psi-influenced as a whole. The quasi-mechanical concepts of the peek and poke model no longer suffice: the corresponding psychology concentrates on discrete processes, at a cognitively low level. A high level global psychological system seems a more appropriate controller for a global psi. A nightly familiar candidate is the “stage-manager” of dreams. This brings us back with a bump into the area of dreams, fantasy, automatisms, etc., in short, all these processes which are less than fully introspectable and which were in the beginning of the 20th century brought together in terms of the notion of the subconscious, subliminal, or psychodynamic processes. This kind of “theory” was too easy to spin and did not lend itself to rigorous investigation with the instrumentation of the day. Myers’s (1903) formerly fecund but now severely outmoded model of the subliminal self may be extended with the newer insights of the NLTs. Carpenter (2004, 2005) has recently emphasized unconscious processing in psi, but this is not yet emancipated from the standard SIN model of psychology. The possible role of (experimenter) imaginal processes have been remarked. Only now has an armamentarium of research techniques and machinery become available that would have boggled Myers. Philosophers have asked why Nature did not take the road of the unconscious “philosophical zombie,” rather than a conscious human. Motor automatisms seem to be almost that, directing the Ouija board but without (full) consciousness of doing it! Brain scans of conscious pushing versus unconscious automatism may shed light on consciousness. The area of unconsciousness/consciousness research is of interest far outside the circumscribed area of parapsychology. Parapsychology becomes again, to an important degree, an investigation of just those unconscious (and semi-conscious) processes that have been neglected by parapsychologists since the period of psychical research. Thus, the rallying cry of parapsychology might well be unconscious processing. If, as the OTs suggest, ESP requires sensory feedback of the target, then an elementary consequence is that ESP must bear all the earmarks of that sensory perception (or the same confusion matrix), so-called top-down processes. ESP is considered by the OTs to have a two-step mechanism. Guessing is first done by a random mentation generator (RMG) played upon by a PKer who gets feedback of the actual target at some time in the future. (For the ganzfeld we may perhaps talk about a “random fantasy generator” or RFG). There is no physical reason, apart from convenience, that