Preventive Medicine 53 (2011) 250–252 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Preventive Medicine j o u r n a l h o m e p a g e : w w w. e l s ev i e r. c o m / l o c a t e / y p m e d Why the prevention paradox is a paradox, and why we should solve it: A philosophical view Stephen John Hughes Hall Centre for Biomedical Science in Society, Hughes Hall, University of Cambridge, Mortimer Road, Cambridge, CB1 2EW, UK a r t i c l e i n f o Available online 30 July 2011 Keywords: Ethics Risk Geoffrey Rose Prevention paradox a b s t r a c t This paper provides some philosophical comments on Rose's prevention paradox, suggesting why that paradox seems so difficult, and why policy-makers should care about solving it. The assumptions underlying the paradox section sets out two ways of understanding the notion of “benefit” in public health programmes, and shows how the prevention paradox arises from combining both understandings. Thinking through the paradox section argues that if we find the second understanding of benefit appealing, then we should rethink how we typically assess preventive public health measures. The implications section shows how these theoretical arguments imply that public health practitioners should care about solving the prevention paradox, rather than simply denying the legitimacy of one of the two views from which it arises. © 2011 Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved. In his classic The Strategy of Preventive Medicine, Geoffrey Rose outlines the “prevention paradox” (Rose, 2008). The problem arises from a “fundamental axiom of preventive medicine”, that “a large number of people exposed to a small risk [of some disease] may generate many more cases [of that disease] than a small number exposed to a high risk” (Rose, 2008, 59). This implies that “population strategies” which focus on reducing the risk of those already at low or moderate risk will often be more effective than strategies which focus on “high risk” individuals at improving population health. Hence the apparent paradox that to have the greatest possible impact on population health, “some way must be found to reduce the risk of large numbers of people who, more often than not, will not benefit from the change” (Rose, 2008, 60). This paper aims to establish which assumptions make the prevention paradox a paradox and why we should accept them, such that we should care about solving it. The assumptions underlying the paradox section sets out two ways of understanding “benefit” in public health programmes, and shows how the prevention paradox arises from combining both understandings. Thinking through the paradox section argues that if we find the second understanding appealing, then we should rethink how we assess preventive public health measures. The implications section shows how these theoretical arguments imply that public health practitioners should care about solving the prevention paradox, particularly if they appeal to “solidarity” concerns to motivate individuals. E-mail address: sdj22@cam.ac.uk. 0091-7435/$ – see front matter © 2011 Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved. doi:10.1016/j.ypmed.2011.07.006 The assumptions underlying the paradox That targeting interventions at the (few) members of high-risk groups will often be less effective a way of improving population health outcomes than targeting the (many) members of moderate- or low-risk groups is certainly important. However, it is not a paradox, but a slightly counter-intuitive fact which policy-makers can easily forget. Rose seems to think that what is paradoxical about his results is the implication that the most effective public health strategies have little benefit for the vast majority of those they affect (Rose, 2008, 47). However, there are two different ways of understanding how preventive public health programmes benefit individuals, which, arguably, Rose fails to distinguish. This section shows how it is only when we employ both senses simultaneously that we fully understand Rose's problem. Sometimes, Rose writes as if those targeted by public health campaigns benefit only if they do not die as a result. On this “actual outcome” understanding of benefit, the prevention paradox consists in two, inter-related phenomena. First, most people targeted by preventive measures will not benefit from those measures, but only suffer any related inconvenience (although when implementing the policy we will be unable to predict who). Second, often, the more effective a strategy at reducing overall mortality amongst those targeted by the intervention, the greater will be the ratio of not-at-all-benefitted to benefitted individuals. These are both important phenomena, related to debates about distributive justice. Furthermore, they clearly seem relevant to a key topic of Rose's book: how best to motivate individuals to comply with preventive strategies, given the low chance that they themselves will benefit (Rose, 2008, Chap. 4). However, on the actual outcomes understanding of public health policy, the situation Rose describes does not seem any more paradoxical than the fact that most people who enter a lottery will lose and only a very few gain. S. John / Preventive Medicine 53 (2011) 250–252 At other points, however, Rose formulates the prevention paradox in a different manner, adopting what I call an “ex-ante” understanding of the benefit of public health programmes, which assesses “benefits” in terms of changes in individuals' levels of risk of harm. Sometimes, rather than say that most people will not benefit from population strategies, he instead says that they will each benefit but only “negligibly” (Rose, 2008, 59), presumably by having their individual risk of harm reduced. On this interpretation, everyone who is targeted by a public health intervention does gain something from that programme, a very slight reduction in the risk that she will suffer harm (John, 2009). If we allow that the second, ex-ante interpretation of benefits is plausible, but also find the “actual outcome” understanding of benefit appealing, then population strategies can seem truly paradoxical. Imagine that we adopt a population strategy which reduces the risk of death of members of a low risk group slightly, thereby benefiting them a little (in the ex-ante sense), but that this programme also imposes a small hardship on each group member (say, remembering to take a pill every day). Imagine that, ex-ante, each member of the targeted population would rationally prefer not to take the pill and not to suffer the risk of death. Ex-ante, each individual seems to lose more than she gains from the policy. However, at the same time, we might know, from the (expected) “actual outcomes” perspective that at least some people will benefit from the policy, because they would otherwise have died. The very same policy both harms everyone and, yet, benefits some of them! Thinking through the paradox It is unclear whether Rose uses the term “prevention paradox” to describe the motivational and distributive justice problems which arise if we assume the “actual outcomes” understanding of the benefits of public health policy, or to describe the genuinely paradoxical situation which arises if we assume both the actual outcomes and ex-ante perspectives. This is not to criticise Rose, as the distinctions drawn above are both unfamiliar and not central to his own work. This section, however, suggests an important implication of the arguments above: if the ex-ante perspective is at least sometimes a legitimate way to think about policy, then the moral theory which normally structures discussion of public health policy, consequentialism, should be supplemented by an alternative, “contractualist” approach. One important approach to political philosophy is “consequentialism”: the view that we should choose actions on the basis of a function of their expected welfare consequences (Sinnot-Armstrong, 2006). There are well-known problems with using consequentialism for thinking about all public health policy; for example, consequentialist reasoning would seem to recommend that we should kill healthy people to harvest their organs for the sake of saving the lives of others! (Sinnot-Armstrong, 2006). Therefore, it is often claimed that consequentialist reasoning must be limited by consideration of rights. However, much writing on public health policy assumes that as long as rights violations are not at stake we should choose between policies on the basis of their expected consequences. As such, debates typically turn around two axes: first, whether some policy will violate individuals' rights; second, which consequences matter, such as whether we should assess consequences using QALYs or DALYs, and whether we should value equality of outcome (Nord, 1999). The broadly consequentialist approach to thinking about public health policy clearly relates to the “actual outcomes” understanding of public health benefit. On that approach, the prevention paradox is not, truly, a paradox, but simply the problematic fact that many people must all suffer a tiny deprivation for the sake of some other people enjoying a major benefit. For a consequentialist deciding whether we should go ahead with a population strategy which does not violate rights, then the question is simply whether aggregate small losses for a few outweigh aggregate great gains for a few. It seems plausible that, often, they do, such that consequentialists will, typically, be in favour of non-rights-violating population strategies. However, consequen- 251 tialist reasoning seems to miss out an important potential feature of policy choices, highlighted by the ex-ante understanding of benefit: that each individual might seem to be burdened more than she gains from a policy. In effect, consequentialist reasoning seems to overlook the possibility that individuals might, reasonably, want to take risks with their health. This seems a valid consideration in formulating policy goals, even if the policy would not actually violate anyone's rights. These comments suggest we need an alternative, or at least a supplement, to consequentialism. Such an alternative is offered by the approach to moral and political theorising called “contractualism”. To simplify, contractualists claim that policies are right if and only if noone affected by those policies could “reasonably reject” those policies. Individuals can reasonably reject policies if they can offer some complaint against that policy and propose an alternative, such that no-one else has a stronger complaint against her proposal than she has against the original (Scanlon, 1998, 153). In Rahul Kumar's crisper formulation: “a valid principle is one that is most acceptable to the person for whom it is least acceptable” (Kumar, 2003, 33). Central to contractualism is a focus on the standpoints and complaints of each individual, particularly those who are most burdened by a policy, and an associated refusal to “aggregate” costs and benefits to individuals. Of course, no-one thinks that we can actually ask every individual whether they object to a particular policy; rather, contractualism provides a framework for thinking through issues by asking how people might object to policies. The contractualist can provide an alternative account of the prevention paradox. She can assess whether we should adopt the population strategy by asking what objections members of the population could make against such a policy from the ex-ante perspective. From this perspective, each member of the population would, I have stipulated, prefer to suffer the tiny risk and not suffer inconvenience, rather than vice versa. Therefore, the contractualist can argue that, even if it does not violate anyone's rights to do so, the population strategy is “reasonably rejectable” in favour of the status quo. (Of course, this claim assumes that each member of the population values the risk-reduction less than avoiding inconvenience: this will not always hold true. However, at least when it does, contractualism can explain why population strategies seem problematic. Furthermore, contractualism can explain why cases where there is disagreement over which risks are tolerable are morally complicated. Consequentialist reasoning, by contrast, can make such concerns seem mysterious.) Furthermore, as well as explaining why some population strategies may seem paradoxical, the contractualist can also explain why “high risk” strategies sometimes seem preferable to “population strategies”, even though the former will, foreseeably, produce less overall benefit than the latter. When we think about the choice between population and high-risk strategies, each member of the high-risk group has a stronger complaint against adopting the population strategy than each member of the moderate risk group has against the high-risk strategy, because the gain for each high risk individual from the high-risk strategy is greater than is the gain of each moderate risk individual from the population strategy. (Of course population strategies will, often, benefit high-risk individuals, as I shall discuss below. My comments here are intended to illuminate what we might say when the gain members of the “high-risk” group will make from a “population strategy” are lower than those they would make from a high-risk strategy, in the hope of clarifying more complex real-life cases). In short, if we are faced with a strict choice between a population and a high-risk strategy in some prevention paradox cases, then our policy recommendations will be very different depending on whether we are consequentialists or contractualists. Consequentialists will tend to prefer population strategies, whereas contractualists will tend to prefer high-risk strategies. Therefore, recognising why the prevention paradox seems paradoxical—because we confuse two senses of benefit—also 252 S. John / Preventive Medicine 53 (2011) 250–252 suggests a broader problem, because the different senses of benefit relate to different moral theories with different normative implications for practice. Implications If we think that the ex-ante perspective on public health policies is sometimes legitimate, and interpret this claim in contractualist terms, then we can explain two puzzling facts: first, why (some) population strategies seem paradoxical; second, why high-risk strategies may seem preferable to population strategies. However, it might seem that there is an easy solution to the prevention paradox: we should simply reject the ex-ante perspective and the associated contractualist moral framework. This temptation may be particularly strong for public health professionals, familiar with the expected outcome consequentialist perspective. This section suggests two reasons why public health policy-makers should not try to dodge the paradox, but should, instead, recognise that the ex-ante perspective is valid, such that there is a genuine problem to resolve. One reason is purely strategic: when assessing public attitudes towards public health programmes, such concerns need not reflect a poor understanding of the facts behind such programmes or a selfish, immoral lack of concern for population outcomes. Rather, public attitudes might be shaped by a (largely) inchoate moral theory framed in ex-ante terms. Recognising this fact may facilitate communication between policy-makers and publics. A second, more positive reason for public health practitioners to be aware of ex-ante contractualism relates to Rose's concerns about motivation. Rose suggests that population policies will not only produce the greatest population benefit, but will also often benefit those in “high-risk” groups greatly (Rose, 2008, Chap. 6). For example, reducing the salt consumption of very many individuals at low risk of cardiovascular disease might not only benefit (some proportion of) that population, but also reduce the risk of those at high-risk, because as mean salt consumption decreases, the entire risk distribution will shift downwards. Rose often stresses that it will be hard to motivate most people to accept the minor privations associated with population policies. However, he appeals to the considerations just adduced as one way in which to resolve this problem: we should make people aware that there are “solidarity” based reasons to alter their behaviour, because, even such changes will foreseeably benefit those at the tail of the risk distribution (Rose, 2008, Chap. 6). This hope seems both plausible and appealing. However, it implicitly assumes that those who are at high risk are, in some sense, more needy than those at low risk, such that the decent thing for low risk people to do is to help their fellow high risk citizens. Such implicit assumptions require us to be able to articulate to members of the low and moderate risk groups that highrisk people have a stronger complaint against not implementing the population policy than the low/moderate risk individuals have against implementing that policy. That is to say, even if we value population strategies on consequentialist grounds, at least when contractualist reasons point in the same direction, we may have reason to formulate public discourse in the latter terminology. If policy-makers are willing to use Rose's attractive “solidarity” strategy in attempting to motivate others to follow population policies, then they face a problem: how to resolve the apparent paradox which arises when we combine the actual outcomes and ex-ante understandings of the benefits of public health policy. Even if policy-makers refuse to appeal to solidarity, it seems they should still be aware that ex-ante considerations shape how others might think about public health policy. This paper has not shown how to resolve the prevention paradox, but it has argued that we cannot hope to dodge that problem, but, rather, should accept the premises from which it emerges. Conflict of interest I have no conflicts of interest. References John, S., 2009. Why ‘health’ is not a central category for public health policy. Journal of Applied Philosophy 26 (2), 129–143. Kumar, R., 2003. Reasonable reasons in contractualist moral argument. Ethics 114, 6–37. Nord, E., 1999. Cost–value Analysis in Healthcare. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Rose, G., 2008. Rose's strategy of preventive medicine. In: Khaw, K.T., Marmot, M. (Eds.), Oxford University Press, Oxford. Scanlon, T., 1998. What We Owe to Each Other. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA. Sinnot-Armstrong, W., 2006. “Consequentialism” Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/consequentialism.