See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.net/publication/229450839 The Instrumentality of Music Article in Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism · February 2008 DOI: 10.1111/j.1540-594X.2008.00286.x CITATIONS READS 38 691 1 author: Philip Alperson Temple University 46 PUBLICATIONS 467 CITATIONS SEE PROFILE All content following this page was uploaded by Philip Alperson on 12 July 2020. The user has requested enhancement of the downloaded file. PHILIP ALPERSON The Instrumentality of Music Student: How do you count here, Maestro? Casals: With my soul. 1 Imagine that you were fortunate enough to have been in the sound room of the HMV recording studio in London in the 1930s for the legendary performances by Pablo Casals of Bach’s Suites for Unaccompanied Cello. You look through the soundproof glass and you see a man, transfixed, concentrating on his music as he plays his musical instrument. You see Pablo Casals with his cello. What could be clearer than this? The picture of a musician playing his or her musical instrument seems to be at the foundation of what we mean by the practice of music; and the idea of the musical instrument seems central to our understanding of the musical art. Of course we know that music may also include other kinds of practices such as dance, narration, verse, theatrical action, surtitles, and subtitles. But it is the musician playing the musical instrument that is at the core of practice. All other thoughts of music are parasitically or metaphorically based on this idea. If we want to talk about the music of the birds, lovers making beautiful music together, or the music of the spheres, we do so with an implicit reference to the kind of activity that Casals’s playing his cello epitomizes. It is hard to overestimate the importance of the idea of the musical instrument in our appreciation of music and our understanding of musical practice. We think of music as a performing art and, typically, we think of the performer as performing on a musical instrument. The notion of the musical instrument, as an object with sonic and musical possibilities and limitations and with its own history of development, shapes our understanding of the taxonomy and genres of music. We think, for example, of string music, organ music, music for winds, music for brass bands, and so on. The development of musical styles, particularly in the West, is tied in important ways to the use of instruments. To take a few examples and to speak in somewhat general terms, much medieval music consists of plucked, bowed, wind, and percussion instruments; seventeenth-century baroque music shows an increasing trend toward the use of stringed instruments; much music of late romanticism is characterized by huge instrumental resources, including large numbers of brass, reed, and percussion sections; much twentieth- and twenty-first-century music employs electronic instruments including synthesizers and record turntables. Musical instruments play a key role in our appreciation of many of the skills of music making. When we think of a musician’s virtuosity or even of her expressiveness or musicality, we think of these things as specifically tied up with what she does with the particular instrument she plays. Similarly, we think of “instrumentation”—the branch of musical composition dealing with the use of instruments in a composition—as an art in itself. Indeed, it might be said that musical experimentation with timbre, coloration, and different constellations of instrumental sound is one of the distinguishing features of modern music, certainly of music of the romantic period. In some cases a change in the traditional use of a single instrument can be striking, as in the case of Beethoven, who freed the tympani from its usual role as a rhythmic accompaniment to the trumpet and instead employed it thematically in the statement of a musical idea. In other cases, instrumentation becomes a major focus of attention for the whole orchestra, as in the cases of Berlioz and Debussy, whose mastery The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 66:1 Winter 2008 c 2008 The American Society for Aesthetics 38 of instrumental orchestration and color made instrumentation a central object of aesthetic appreciation. The idea of instrumental music is so central to our way of thinking about music that when people think of music in its purest form, they often tie the idea of absolute music (music without extramusical connotations) to the idea of “instrumental music,” that is, music made exclusively with instruments, excluding the human voice. Clearly, the idea of musical instruments has great importance to our thinking about music, to ways in which music is produced and performed, and to ways in which we appreciate music. In this paper, I would like to take a close philosophical look at the fundamental idea of music as a practice involving instruments. I want, first, to identify how we typically think about musical instruments, outlining the key features of the “commonsense” view of musical instruments. I then want to complicate that picture in a way that I hope is consistent with actual musical practice. I argue that, from an ontological perspective, musical instruments are, from one point of view, necessarily embodied entities in a sense that I shall defend. I also argue that the ontology of musical instruments must acknowledge an inescapably immaterial aspect of musical instruments that is usually overlooked by the commonsense view. I argue that the commonsense view of musical instruments also overlooks the possibility that composers and audiences have their own range of musical instruments. I argue for a more robust philosophical view of musical instruments that takes these matters into account. I conclude with a discussion of some key consequences of my view for several important issues in the philosophy of music. I discuss what I take to be the appropriate mode and object of attention in the appreciation of musical performances and consider the kind of musical ontology that this kind of attention suggests. I also discuss the idea of the instrumentality of music itself, by which I mean both the idea of “instrumental music” as well as the place of music in relation to large questions of social and cultural purposes that music might serve. i. musical instruments and the performer’s body Let us stake out first what we may take to be the commonsense view of musical instruments. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism On the commonsense view, musical instruments are devices that performers use to make music. Typically, we think of instruments as discrete, selfsubsisting material objects, intentionally crafted for the purpose of making music by performing musicians. Stradivari made violins, violas, and cellos; luthiers make lutes and guitars; teams of craftspeople at the Steinway and Bösendorfer corporations make pianos; and so on. Musical instruments are the sorts of things one finds for sale in music stores. Musicians take these objects and, by holding them, hitting them, blowing through them, plucking and scraping them, pressing on keys, and so on, produce the sounds of music. This much seems obvious. But some qualifications do seem to be in order. We have said that musical instruments are intentionally crafted for the purpose of making music. Certainly many instruments are created with such an intention. But do musical instruments need to be crafted by individuals for the express purpose of being used as a musical instrument? Some instruments that find themselves in musical practice are simply found in nature, as, for example, the coconut and conch shells, grass reeds, stones, and so on, that we hear in much folk music. Other instruments are human artifacts but artifacts that were not initially designed for use as musical instruments. Erik Satie’s ballet music, Parade, calls for a typewriter, a steamboat whistle, a roulette wheel, and a revolver. In such cases we would not find an intention to make a musical instrument on the part of an instrument maker. Nevertheless, in such cases we can still locate a human intention. “Natural” and “found” instruments are discovered and brought up into the artworld, so to speak, much in the way that found objects such as driftwood and bicycle seats may be taken up and deployed in the world of art. If we want to insist that musical instruments require instrument makers, what we would want to say is that the “making” of such instruments involves the intention to use the object as a musical instrument and that this intention might be had by a composer or a performer as well as by an instrument maker in the traditional sense of that term. What counts is that an object takes its place in the world of musical practice as something that can be used as a musical instrument. So far so good. We have also said that, on the commonsense view, musical instruments are discrete, selfsubsisting devices or material objects held or Alperson The Instrumentality of Music manipulated by the performer to produce musical sounds. Again we may take Casals’s situation as iconic. Casals’s cello is there for all to see in the world of extension. He holds that instrument and he plays it. The flautist blows across the blowhole of the head joint of the flute which she holds. The timpanist bangs on the drum in front of her. The pianist pushes down on the keys and steps on the pedals. But, here again, some qualifications are in order. It is misleading to say simply that musical instruments are discrete, self-subsisting objects held or manipulated by the performer. In some cases it is hard to tell where the body ends and where the instrument begins. Vocalists frequently speak of their bodies, or parts of their bodies, as their “instruments” (or their “pipes”—a play on pipes and windpipes), and a substantial amount of instruction for singers consists in training techniques and exercises for the control of the vocal chords, the diaphragm, the chest, and the mouth; techniques to control breathing, manage the degree of nasality, and alter vowel color; and methods to develop different registers of the voice, including the chest voice, the head voice, and falsetto. The startlingly clear sounds produced by members of Bulgarian women’s choirs, such as the Women’s Choir of Sofia, involve the focused use of the neck muscles in voice production, rather than the diaphragm, as in most professional singing in the Western tradition. Perhaps the most striking example of understanding the body itself as a vocal musical instrument comes in the non-Western traditions of throat singing practiced by Inuit people of the Arctic regions of Canada, Greenland, Alaska, and Siberia; Tibetan Buddhist monks; and the seminomadic tribes of Central Asia, especially in the Russian republic of Tuva. A Tuvan singer is able to achieve the remarkable feat of producing as many as four tones simultaneously, effectively singing synchronically with himself. There are many styles of throat singing, but the general practice is to generate a low fundamental tone (or drone) while simultaneously producing overtones—higher harmonic tones with frequencies that are multiples of the fundamental frequency—with timbres that may resemble the sound of a flute or a whistle. Normally, the sound of a singing voice is a mixture of fundamentals and harmonics that we hear as a single tonal sound where the fundamental tone identifies the 39 pitch and the harmonics contribute to the timbre of the sound. To achieve the throat singing effect, Tuvan throat singers master the difficult task of constricting various parts of the vocal tract and adjusting resonant cavities such as the mouth, sinuses, and lungs in order to tune and amplify particular harmonics so that they can be heard as discrete sounds, perceptually separable from the fundamental tone. The effect is striking.2 We find in the case of both the Tuvan throat singer and the Western vocalist that the techniques of controlling the body to produce musical sounds require subtle attention and practice that go well beyond the usual level of vocal sound production. We can see in these vocal practices a strong analogy with the kind of effort and training that goes into mastering a conventional musical instrument to produce musical sounds. We are clearly warranted, then, in calling at least part of a vocalist’s body her “instrument.” Some performers use their bodies to create percussive effects. Bobby McFerrin, the jazz and pop vocalist, is well known for percussing his own body, in effect simulating the pulse that a rhythm section might otherwise provide. Tap dancers tap with their feet. Flamenco dancers do the same and clap their hands in often complicated, intense, and virtuosic displays. These performers are doing more than simply making sounds in the course of their performances. In creating these rhythms with their bodies, they are contributing to the overall musicality of the piece by supplying rhythmic and timbral interest as well as by accenting and thereby bringing to attention particular melodic, harmonic, textural, and phrasal features of the music.3 What is less often noticed is that we may extend this insight about the embodied aspect of musical instruments to conventionally understood musical instruments, where the line between body and instrument also frequently blurs. A guitarist playing in the fingerpicking style may consider his fingernails part of the instrument, even to the extent of fashioning his fingernails in particular ways, painting them with Superglue, or wearing semipermanent acrylic fingernails in order to produce particular sounds on the strings and to facilitate playing. The tone and timbre of a woodwind player’s sound is as much a function of the way the player opens her throat as it is of the physical instrument. That is why a saxophone player, for example, can pick up a range of 40 instruments with different sonic characters and, to a great extent, still create the same identifiable, unique sound from instrument to instrument. Similarly, having control over the lips, tongue, and muscles of a brass or reed player’s jaw (the “embouchure”) is critically tied to the sound of the instrument and even to the musical capabilities of the instrument. When jazz trumpeter Chet Baker was fourteen years old, a boy threw a stone at him, damaging Baker’s upper left front tooth. The tooth eventually fell out, forcing Baker to adapt his technique and play only in the middle range horn. It was as if the change in his body cut the effective range of his trumpet by two-thirds. Twenty-three years later Baker had another unfortunate dental event, which, according to legends, was the result of either a severe beating or rotting teeth due to heavy drug abuse. Baker was forced to wear dentures. As a result, Baker switched from trumpet to the less physically demanding flugelhorn and adapted his playing style further, playing less taxing solos with shorter phrases, narrower ranges, lower dynamics, and so on. Left-handed guitarists face their own special challenges: if they simply turn the guitar upside down so that their left hands pluck the strings and their right hands make the chords on the fingerboard, they retain the strength and nimbleness of their left hand for the picking but at the expense of having to learn to play a guitar with a fingerboard having the treble strings on the top instead of the bottom. Some guitarists learn to play that way; others reverse the strings. The styles of lefthanded guitarists may vary as a result of this relationship between guitar and body.4 The relationship between the musician’s body and the instrument is so intimate that performers go to extraordinary lengths to find and keep the instrument that becomes one with them, an instrument that provides, for example, the right balance between ease and resistance to produce the quality of tone, the tonal attack, the variability of intonation, the speed and range of vibrato, and other aspects of musical production and expressiveness that best enable what it is that performer hopes to accomplish. We may speak of the relationship of the “fit” between the performer’s body and his instrument. Casals chose to play his Goffriller cello even when offered the opportunity to obtain a Stradivarius, not only for the tone and carrying power of the Goffriller, but also because he enjoyed managing the limitations of the The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism instrument. “I want to have to fight for my expression,” Casals said.5 All serious musical performers are sensitive to finding the musical instrument that most closely matches their own personal and bodily approaches to musical production. Woodwind players are notoriously fussy about the setup of mouthpiece and reeds that suits the physical dispositions they bring to their playing. Pianists are fussy about the action of the keys: Vladimir Horowitz brought his enormous nine-foot Steinway D piano from home on tour when he gave recitals. Discovering an instrument that opens up new musical possibilities is one of the great joys in the life of a musical performer. The point of all of these observations is that, when thinking of the ontology of musical instruments, we need to keep in mind the continuity, often the seamless continuity, between the physical instrument and the player’s bodily connection with the instrument. Many musicians put the matter clearly when they speak of their instruments as extensions of their bodies. The truth is that it is difficult to say where the instrument ends and the rest of the body begins. In this sense, musical instruments are embodied entities. ii. the immateriality of musical instruments There is a more profound ontological problem with the notion of instruments conceived simply as material objects. This problem has been brought to light by relatively recent developments in electronic and digital music making. Many performers nowadays play instruments whose sounds are in large part shaped by encoded information that reflects past or changing historical styles and traditions. A few examples will suffice. In the 1960s the Farfisa organ company transformed the accordion by adding to the traditional reed and bellows mechanism electronic key contacts, an internal microphone, a tone generator, an amplifier system, and other electronic modifications. The result was an instrument that could not only produce amplified accordion sounds but could also simulate the familiar sounds of organs, pianos, and wind and percussion instruments. The theremin, the Moog synthesizer, the fuzz and wahwah pedals, the circuitry of electric guitar pickups, and the entire development of digitized musical instruments in the last fifty or so years, including computer-generated music and MIDI (Musical Alperson The Instrumentality of Music Instrument Digital Interface) devices, with their accompanying software programs, have had an important role to play in invoking and recasting musical sounds of the past as well as providing additional resources for musical composition and performance.6 It is important to realize again that what we are talking about now are not material objects construed as mere hunks of physical stuff. In the cases mentioned above, we are speaking of objects whose creation and whose musical capabilities are infused with information and conceptual structures that reflect the history and styles of musical sounds. That is to say, the material objects we think of as musical instruments are culturally freighted right from the beginning. We did not really need the advent of electronic or digitized musical instruments to bring this lesson home. Musical instruments have always been created and used within the fabric of musical history. In some cases, technical developments for existing instruments have driven compositional practice. When, in the sixteenth century, flutes began to be made in two or more pieces instead of a single piece, the instrument’s intonation was dramatically improved, and when keys were added and the cylindrical bore was changed to a conical bore, the sound and playability of the instrument were enhanced. These changes attracted the attention of composers such as Michel Blavet and Johann Joachim Quantz, who then wrote concerti and sonatas featuring the flute. As the use of these musical instruments increased in the orchestral repertoire, particular instruments frequently came to be associated with various kinds of extramusical meaning. Flutes and oboes were often associated with pastoral scenes, trumpets with the hunt, trumpets and drums with the battlefield, and so forth. So the character, so to speak, of musical instruments—their typical uses, the way they have come to be played and thought of in the history of music—is often rooted in the technical development of the physical instrument and its corresponding musical possibilities.7 Conversely, the history and traditions of musical composition may prompt the invention of new musical instruments. When in the early 1960s Stan Kenton was experimenting with increasing orchestral complexity in his big band jazz group, he decided that the band needed a brass sound with a range somewhere between a low trumpet and a 41 high trombone and with an ability to cut through the already formidable brass section for which his band was famous. The result was the invention of the mellophonium, an instrument that combined the wraparound tubing of the French horn with the front-facing, flared bell of the mellophone and a large-diameter tubing (“bore”) and that, playing in the alto register, bridged the space between the saxophones and the trumpet/trombone brass section. The mellophonium had the tonal beauty of the French horn but, with its front-facing bell and large bore, it could cut through and soar over the massed sound of Kenton’s band. The instrument’s characteristics, the range of composition for which it was especially appropriate, and, indeed, its very existence, were the result of a felt compositional need within a genre.8 Another way in which musical instruments carry with them the history of their musical traditions is in their invention and use as provocative or subversive gestures. Bob Dylan was roundly and famously booed when he first used an electric guitar at the 1965 Newport Folk Festival, insulting those in the audience who thought that folk music could not abide the electronically amplified instruments of the hated world of rock and roll. Or, consider the case of Harry Partch. Partch composed for instruments of his own design that were in counterreaction to the tradition of the twelvetone chromatic scale that is the basis of the diatonic system upon which so much of Western music is based. In its place Partch proposed a 43-note scale based on a system of “just intonation,” a scale most Western ears would hear as microtonal, if not out of tune. He invented a number of musical instruments capable of operating in the system, including a 64-tubed bamboo marimba (the “boo”), a 43-tone pedal-pumped reed organ (the “chromelodeon”), a 13-glass gong assembly made from cloud chambers bowls that had been used to trace subatomic particles, a 72-stringed kithara (lyre), a “harmonic canon” (a 44-stringed zither), and an instrument he called “the spoils of war,” composed of tuned artillery shell casings. Here we have an example of the invention and use of musical instruments tied to the history of Western music but with the specific intent of undermining the harmonic system on which it is based.9 In fact, we may go further down the road of insurgency. Neil Feather eschews terms such as ‘composer’ or “performer,’ preferring the term ‘sound mechanic.’ Feather dispenses with the 42 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism norm of scalar music altogether. He has invented and has performed on such instruments as the “nondo,” a large sheet of steel strung with music wire hit with a mallet and whose pitch is infinitely variable, and the “melocycle,” a contraption that looks something like an exercise bicycle designed by Rube Goldberg whose strings pass by electronic pickups, causing the kind of Doppler effect we recognize in the falling pitch of the siren of an emergency vehicle as it speeds away.10 Perhaps at the upper limit of musical insurgency we have some of the music of John Cage, in which the musical instrument, depending on your point of view, is either the entire world of ambient noise or is done away with entirely. As we can see, if we are to have a rich understanding of musical instruments, we cannot regard them simply as material objects. The moment they are musical instruments, they are musically, culturally, and conceptually situated objects. The advent of computers and musical software simply reminds us of this fact in a particularly vivid way. iii. the instruments of composers and audiences To this point we have been concerned with the nature of instruments played by performers, and we have seen that, contrary to the commonsense view of the matter, performers’ instruments are not to be thought of simply as discrete, self-subsisting material objects external to the human body but rather, in an important sense, as embodied entities. We have also seen that there is an inescapably immaterial aspect to the performers’ instruments. The modern use of computers and software draws attention to another important ontological feature of musical instruments that goes unnoticed by the commonsense view. Consider for a moment the case of traditional composed music—the familiar situation in which a composer provides a score that is then read and performed by performing musicians for an audience. This is such a common state of affairs that we may call it the standard presentation situation of music. In the standard presentation situation we can identify five poles of musical production and reception: the composer, the score, the work (presumably stipulated in large part by the score), the performer, and the audience. Now there has been much philosophical discussion about the ontological status of the work, its relationship to the score and the composer, and other questions related to this scheme.11 We can set these debates aside for present purposes long enough to note that, as we observed earlier, musical instruments on the commonsense view are typically associated with the performer. It is the performer who plays the musical instrument. In the standard presentation situation the performer uses the musical instrument to perform the composer’s work and in so doing makes it available to the audience (see Figure 1). But composers have their musical instruments, too. We said earlier that orchestration—the stipulation of which instruments are used in a work and how they are used—is an important part of the skill set of the composer. It is less common, however, to think of the instruments that composers use. Again, it is interesting to start with the contemporary scene and work backwards. Consider the many musical software programs available now, such as Finale, Sibelius, and Band in a Box, that enable users to compose, record, and produce music. Let me say a few things about Band in a Box, concentrating on the compositional features of the program. The program allows users to compose music, with control over the usual musical variables: melody, harmony, rhythm, and tempo. The Work Composer Score Performer Musical Instrument Figure 1. The standard presentation situation. Audience Alperson The Instrumentality of Music program also enables the user to control for musical style; it comes loaded with a range of individual preset styles. There is also a “style-maker” function that allows users to create and modify styles, controlling for instrumentation, melody, harmony, rhythm, tempo, dynamics, and expressive markings within a style. The program can produce conventional scores as well as audio files of what has been composed.12 There are many reasons why one might chafe at the idea that a software program could be regarded as a legitimate tool in the compositional process. The program does not require that the user have a deep level of music-theoretical training, for example, and it might be objected that true musical composition requires of the composer a sophisticated theoretical grounding in music. Alternatively, it might be objected that, with its battery of supplied styles, the program imposes constraints on the artistic freedom of the composer to create. But these are matters of degree. Some composers have more theoretical knowledge than others and, as far as freedom of composition is concerned, composers have always composed against the backdrop of a historical tradition that favors certain genres, styles, and practices. No composer composes ex nihilo. It is also important to understand the range of compositional options open even to the novice user. There is a considerable array of rhythmic choices, for example. Perhaps you would like to select or adapt a drum style for a popular tune. Are you interested in composing a jazz rhythmic pattern to be played by the drummer with brushes instead of sticks? You have thirty-two basic options from which to choose, each of which can be altered for tempo and genre. You have the opportunity to control time signature, tempo, key signature, volume dynamics, and melodic, harmonic, and rhythmic variables, including accents, phrasing marks, bar lines, and expressive directions. You can print out complete musical scores or just lead sheets with chord progressions to study for future changes. Historically, many composers have composed at the piano, trying out various permutations of musical phrases, sections, and so on. Band in a Box has a computerized reharmonization option that allows users to take a given melody and reharmonize it, that is, generate alternate supporting harmonic accompaniments for the melodic line selected, from among hundreds of genre choices. In one demonstration in the package, the program 43 takes a melody from the first movement of Bach’s Brandenburg Concerto in F. The program analyzes the keys and scales implied by the melody. The user can impose any new key (G-flat, for example) on individual bars, composites of bars, or whole movements. The user can transpose entire compositions in a range of genres and styles, with a variable range of major and minor modalities. There is even an option to determine how wild the variations should be. So, for example, a moderately low wildness setting combined with one of the bossa nova styles would result in a bossa nova reharmonization of the first movement of the Concerto with a relatively tame harmonic substructure with hip-but-not-too-far-out turnaround chords. If you do not like the harmonies generated by the program, you can open up the options for each harmonic change and find dozens of other options, sorted alphabetically by root names of the chords or even by the program’s determination of what it calls “best to worst” choices. The program allows you to generate styles from earnumbing Muzak-like background music to musically advanced avant-garde harmonic stylings. Suppose you wish to compose a piece of music within a genre or style but you have not yet settled on a melodic subject. The program allows you to choose the genre or style category and then have the program generate melody options. You can, if you like, help the program out by choosing a specific number of bars, total duration of the composition, and so on. Or, suppose you have a candidate melody but you want to play around with it. The program can generate improvisations and variations on previously composed melodies. The improvisations can be generated in any of dozens of styles, levels of complexity, and percentages of deviation from the original melody. You can specify whether the improvisations should start or end on the same notes as in the original melody and what percentage of passing tones is acceptable. In short, the Band in a Box program invokes many of the same compositional habits, strategies, and techniques that Mozart or Beethoven might have used while experimenting at the piano keyboard, starting, say, with a relatively simple melody or harmonic pattern, substituting a more exotic harmony, trying another, experimenting with the instrumentation, working from the history of past compositional practice, and imagining new possibilities. And if you do not have quite the auditory imagination for which Mozart and Beethoven were famous—that is, if you 44 cannot hear complex music in your mind’s ear—all you have to do is save what you have composed to audio files and play them through your loudspeakers.13 Now imagine a relatively sophisticated composer who has enough mastery of the computer program so that her levels of musical productivity when using the program are on a par with what she was accustomed to doing at the piano keyboard instead of the computer keyboard. Imagine a modified Turing Test in which her work with Band in a Box is indistinguishable from her work at the piano.14 Here again, developments in digital computer design remind us in a vivid way of the fact that composers throughout history have relied upon enabling instruments in their compositional activity. Moreover, as with the case of musical instruments of performers, composers’ musical instruments may be understood as having physical, ideational, and historical components. The physical keyboard of the piano displays in a visual, spatial, and particularly graphic way the array of sounds as heard and, in a certain sense, many important elements of Western music, from the use of the diatonic scalar system, to justified music intonation, to the so-called horizontal temporal features of melody and rhythm, and to the so-called vertical features of simultaneous sounds in consonance and harmony and the relationships of parts or lines in a piece.15 The computer program does much the same thing. The program’s design logic and programming, combined with elements from the history of actual human musical production that the designers of the program have built in, is closely analogous to the piano keyboard. Both are compositional musical instruments. When we think about what we have been calling the standard presentation situation, we also realize that audience members have their range of instruments. Anything that can be utilized to bring the music to a listener can be regarded as a musical instrument. Radios, iPods, computers, high-fidelity stereo systems, in-store broadcast equipment, audio and video discs, and podcasts are all devices by means of which listeners may hear music. The ontology and technology of musical re-production is much discussed by philosophers. It is an interesting question what it is that is being reproduced, whether a performance or a work or something else. The role of producers, studio engineers, and audio technicians and the techniques of recording processes are also of great importance. It has The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism been argued by some that certain genres of music, such as rock, are primarily created in the studio, so that to speak of the recording as a re-production is somewhat misleading. The work is created in the studio.16 Recital halls also fall into the category of instruments that bring music to listeners. Of course there is the musically relevant matter of room acoustics. Every musician who has played in a concert hall knows that the acoustics of halls affect not only the sound but also the manner in which musicians play in order to accommodate the peculiarities of the acoustics of the room. The Philadelphia Orchestra is renowned for the deep silken warmth of its string section. Lore has it that an important factor in the development of the signature “Philadelphia sound” was the relatively dry acoustics of the Academy of Music where the orchestra played for its first hundred years. It is said that the acoustics of the hall required the string players to compensate by exerting greater force on the strings in order for their sound to project in the hall. Conductors Leopold Stokowski and Eugene Ormandy and generations of players developed this distinctive texture, which they were able to create wherever they played, even in their new home, the Kimmel Center, which has a very bright acoustical profile. Perhaps it is not even going too far to say that some concert halls can be “played” in the manner of musical instruments. Performance spaces may not only be designed for music, or for particular kinds of music, but they also may be tunable. In fact most contemporary recital halls are adjustable so that baffles, doors, risers, curtains, and other physical paraphernalia can be moved to enhance particular musical qualities for individual concerts or even for individual pieces of music within a concert. The acoustics of performance spaces also frequently involve electronic amplification that can modulate acoustic and musical variables. Concert halls also affect the presentation of music by allowing for a public space in which music can be performed. The advent of public music halls in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries not only provided physical space but also helped to establish a culture of listening in which music was presented in a way not unlike art objects are presented in a museum. This listening situation brought with it certain expectations and habits, not only about the ideal of listening to music for its own sake, but also concerning the place of music in society as a cultural emblem.17 The advent of Alperson The Instrumentality of Music 45 Work Composer Performer Audience Musical Instrument Musical Instrument Score Musical Instrument Figure 2. The standard presentation situation, version 2. the personal iPod also fosters certain sorts of listening habits within a social space, not the least of which is a kind of privatized musical experience that, I think can be argued, has its own advantages, disadvantages, and peculiarities, especially pertaining to the sociality of listening. One could argue that, while the iPod offers attractive opportunities in terms of the ready availability of music and the fidelity of musical sound, it is a technological and cultural development that encourages a kind of alienation in which listeners become foreign to others in the world around them.18 Finally, I mention in passing one especially interesting musical instrument that we might think of as a listener’s musical instrument, the Yamaha Disklavier. The Disklavier is a regular piano, with strings, sounding board, and the usual key and hammer mechanism, but it has been outfitted with an electromechanical system that can play the piano. In one sense, this is not such a new invention. Since the mid-nineteenth century we have had player pianos that have been able to read piano rolls and play the piano without a human pianist being present. What makes the Disklavier so interesting is its ability, by means of a software system that plays the piano, to present “live” performances, as it were, of previous performances by encoding in great detail performance variables from a recording of a performance. The software program infers from the recording at what force the key was struck, how far down the sustain pedal was pushed, how individual notes were weighted in chords, and so on. So, for example, at a display in Toronto, a Disklavier was tuned to approximate the voicing of Glenn Gould’s piano. The software was employed to encode Gould’s performance from Gould’s famous 1955 recordings of Bach’s “Goldberg” Variations. The playerless piano then re-performed Gould’s performance. And it doesn’t end there. A reperformance of Gould’s original recorded performance has been recorded onto a new CD so that it can now be re-reproduced in your home. Gould, who was notoriously shy about performing in public and who was famous for his use of studio technology to edit his own recordings, would have loved it.19 In view of what we have said to this point, it now appears that our picture of the standard presentation situation has gotten a little more complicated (see Figure 2). Indeed, if we hew closely to the position that anything that can be utilized to bring the music to a listener can be regarded as a musical instrument, we may, in the case where we have an ensemble with a conductor, think of the baton and the orchestra as the conductor’s instruments. So the picture gets even busier (see Figure 3). Work Composer Musical Instrument Score Performer Conductor Audience Musical Instrument Musical Instrument Musical Instrument Figure 3. The standard presentation situation, version 3. 46 At this juncture, one might wonder whether this account of musical instruments, which considerably extends the range of what might be thought to be a musical instrument, is overly generous. In so proliferating the number of things that might be considered a musical instrument, have we not multiplied entities beyond necessity? Have we arrived at the conclusion that anything could be— or everything is—a musical instrument? Surely, it might be thought, these would not be helpful suggestions. Occamites need not reach for their razors. While I have given wider latitude to the realm of musical instruments than we find in the commonsense view, the concept of a musical instrument is nevertheless constrained by the cultural embeddedness of musical instruments. Musical instruments are not mere artifacts. They are instruments whose classes and subclasses are underwritten by the actual practices of music whose intentions and histories shape and sustain the categories. From an ontological point of view, the concepts, classes, and subclasses of musical instruments may be thought of as norm kinds—classes that define correct and incorrect examples and in which the criteria for correctness are relativized to and established by the musical cultures in which they arise.20 If musical practice continues to foster the use of brass instruments including the trumpet, the trombone, and the tuba, these categories and entities will continue to have application within the practice. iv. the musicality of instruments and the instrumentality of music Let us take a moment to gather together what I have been saying to this point. I have been arguing that the commonsense concept of the musical instrument is foundational to our everyday understanding of the practice of music. In what I have called the standard presentation situation of music, musical instruments are generally associated with performers. The idea of a performer playing a musical instrument is iconic, capturing the idea that music is a performing art, and music is thought to be a performing art in virtue of the ability of performing musicians to play musical instruments to produce music. Furthermore, on the commonsense view, musical instruments are thought to be essentially discrete The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism and self-subsistent material objects, held or manipulated by performers, made expressly for that purpose by instrument makers. I have also argued that the commonsense understanding of musical instruments of performers is naı̈ve in certain respects. I have argued that the idea of construing musical instruments as essentially discrete, selfsubsistent material objects held or manipulated by performers needs to be qualified, for several reasons. Musical instruments are not objects divorced from performers’ bodies, but rather they are intimately tied to performers’ bodies, so much so that, in some cases, it is difficult to know where the body ends and where the instrument begins. This means that in some cases musical instruments must be understood in part as parts or as dispositions of the body. Because of this intimate relation between instrument and body, in the actual practice of music a hard and fast distinction between an external material object and the body of the performer is harder to maintain than the commonsense view would lead people to think. The performer’s musical instrument is better understood as an amalgam of material object, the performer’s body, and bodily dispositions as habituated by the developments of various musically related skills. Moreover, though the commonsense view has it right that, typically, some intentionality is involved in the causal chain that brings musical instruments into being and into use, that intentionality may come not only from an instrument maker but from a performer, a conductor or bandleader, an acoustician, a studio technician, and ultimately, even from an audience. I have argued that musical instruments can only be understood with respect to their intentional, ideational, and historical components, for example, as heuristic devices whose conceptual apparatuses play a role in the creation of music. I have argued that we can speak not only of the instruments of performers but also of the instruments of composers, conductors, listeners, and audiences. In arguing for this enlarged conception of musical instruments, I have emphasized that we must understand musical instruments as culturally freighted objects, that is, as objects that arise in the context of the history of musical practice. Just as the invention and development of musical instruments may come as the result of needs and forces in the history of music, so also can changes in the technical development of instruments affect the Alperson The Instrumentality of Music course of music history, musical composition, musical performance, and musical reception. In qualifying the commonsense understanding of musical instruments in these ways, I have sought to show that, ontologically, musical instruments need to be understood as musically, conceptually, and culturally situated. Or, to put the matter more formulaically, I wish to argue that musical instruments must be understood as instrumentalities in the context of human affairs. Let me now step back from the matter of musical instruments to make a few brief suggestions about the significance of this conception of musical instruments for several issues in the philosophy of music more generally. It seems to me, first of all, that there are important lessons to be learned about the nature of musical performance and that a deeper conception of what we mean by a musical instrument will help us better understand the achievement of musicians as performers and of music as a performing art. In the case of the standard presentation situation, where we think of the performer as in some sense enabling the actualization of the composer’s work, it is clear that the achievement of the performer goes well beyond simply using a material instrument to render the performed work in a public way. Of course it is true that in the standard presentation situation one does perform a work. A central feature of musical performances in the standard presentation situation is precisely the performance of composers’ works, making them audible in real time for audiences. In this context, musical performers work not only to get the notes right but also to present a compelling rendition of a work and to match the performer’s natural expressiveness with the expressive possibilities offered by the work. These are the sorts of issues that have been dealt with in the philosophical literature on interpretation and authenticity in music, especially with respect to questions about the appropriateness and faithfulness of a performance to the composer’s intentions, or to the score, or to a musical genre, style, or historical period, or to some combination of these, “covers” of previously recorded music, and more.21 I want to suggest, however, that our understanding of the performance of musical works would be enhanced by a greater attention to the role that instruments play in the presentation of musical works. To appreciate the performer’s performance, I would argue, is to appreciate a particu- 47 lar kind of human achievement. As we have seen, what the performer does is perform a work with an instrument that is at once both recalcitrant— insofar as it must be “mastered” so that the instrument can be utilized in the service of the production of musical works—and intimate—insofar as musical instruments are inevitably connected with the bodies and bodily actions of the performer. I want to suggest that the performance of musical works is a kind of musical practice in which the object of aesthetic appreciation is legitimately regarded as the work-in-performance. That is, there is a kind of double consciousness of the performance as a performance of the work as a musical entity and of the performer’s achievement in performing the work, an experience that may be characterized as having a certain kind of “twofoldness.” If, for example, we are listening attentively to a performance by Alfred Brendel of Mozart’s Sonata in F major K. 333–494 in which Brendel conveys a shimmering, graceful, singing quality in the Andante movement, we are, I believe, aware both of Brendel’s performance of that movement of the work and of Brendel’s extraordinary ability to produce fluid, melodic, voicelike music from what is, after all, a percussion instrument. To put the matter formulaically, we might speak of a double consciousness of the performance of the work and the performance in the work.22 Now it might be objected that, even if we grant that this twofold kind of appreciation I describe of performed music is possible, this account runs afoul of the view that the primary goal of musical performances in the standard presentation situation is precisely the performance of composers’ works, making them audible for audiences. My view, however, is that philosophies of art must in the end be driven by the beliefs and practices of people within the world of the art in question. Here I am in accord with philosophers such as Roman Ingarden, Joseph Margolis, Jerrold Levinson, Amie L. Thomasson, and Stephen Davies, who, in various ways, have stressed the importance of understanding art in the context of their relevant intentional activities and histories.23 It is my contention that the multifaceted approach to the performance of musical works I have described is in fact in close accordance with the way that most people listen to the performance of musical works. It is clearly the case in works of art whose performance is widely understood to 48 require an extraordinary level of achievement, as, for example, in the case of the bel canto tenor aria “Ah! mes amis” from Donizetti’s opera, La Fille du Regiment, which requires of the singer of the work great agility, not to mention the ability to hit nine high Cs. Some people come to Donizetti’s opera for the sole purpose of seeing and hearing this showpiece—often called the Mount Everest for tenors—performed. But I believe there is typically some consciousness of this sort of duality in the appreciation of the performance of most musical works. This is not to say that every listener is equally capable of appreciating all the nuances of this kind of double consciousness. With respect to the actual demands placed upon musical performances, it is possible that performing musicians are themselves most likely to have the fullest appreciation of what has been accomplished, since they are most familiar with the demands of the project from the inside, so to speak. In fact, it is likely that there is a natural segregation of listeners in this regard. French horn players are in a better position to understand the level of achievement of French horn playing than nonmusicians or even than musicians who do not play the French horn. Indeed, very good French horn players are likely to be in a better position to understand the level of achievement of very good French horn players than mediocre French horn players. But that is simply a feature of the appraisal of all human achievement. The same would be true for the appreciation of works in the centuries-old forms of classical Cambodian and South Indian dance—sophisticated dance traditions requiring of their performers the mastery of literally thousands of movements, gestures, and positions and extraordinarily demanding control over the entire body, including the face. We appreciate what we can, within the limits of our horizons. Greater attention to the role of musical instruments in the performance of music also gives us a deeper insight into performances in the musical performance outside of the standard presentation situation. In certain cases of musical improvisation there is no prior existing work created by a composer. In other cases, performers improvise on a previously composed work, but attention is traditionally directed less toward faithfulness to the work and more toward the evident spontaneity of the musical activity.24 In these cases, our appreciation of what has been accomplished is often tied to the specificities of the demands of the instru- The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism ment. The jazz pianist Bill Evans, for example, is widely admired for extending the range and complexity of harmonic texture that the piano keyboard makes possible. Maynard Ferguson was well known for his physically demanding command of the stratospheric range of the trumpet. Scott LaFaro, playing the upright bass more like a guitar than a traditional time-keeping bass accompaniment, showed that it was possible for the bass to play exceedingly lyrical and rhythmically complex passages. Clark Burroughs, the lead singer of the Hi-Lo’s who could hit a G above high C, and Yma Sumac, the Peruvian soprano with a four-and-ahalf-octave range from B below C to A above high C, are to the voice what Maynard Ferguson was to the trumpet. In each of these cases, I believe, listeners appreciate the human achievement with specific regard to accomplishment in the context of the demands of the particular instrument involved. I would, finally, also like to suggest that the conception of musical instruments I have been advancing has implications for our understanding of music itself as a particular human practice, or perhaps more accurately, as a set of musical practices. Again, because of space limitations, I can only sketch out the sort of thing I have in mind here. I have stressed throughout that the philosophical analysis of musical instruments must, in the end, be contextual, taking into account the entire range of human activity involved in the production and appreciation of music, rather than focusing only on the narrower concern with the work itself. It is in this spirit that my analysis of musical instruments moved from thinking about musical instruments as material objects seen as mere intermediaries between the performer and the performed work to an analysis of the ontology of musical instruments that takes into account a range of properties of instruments that pose challenges and demands that must be faced by performers and that offer musical possibilities for composers, performers, and listeners. I have argued that the ontological characteristics of musical instruments and the particular kind of human achievement that the use of these instruments represents are central to the appreciation of both works-in-performance as well as to musical performances that do not involve the presentation of previously composed works. I have also argued that in understanding these things, we need to take into account the historical and cultural forces that hold sway in the Alperson The Instrumentality of Music world of music. In this way we can see that the use of musical instruments may go so far as to call cultural trends into question, as I believe Dylan did in his performance at Newport in 1965. If there are such things as natural kinds—classes that denote naturally occurring materials or things such as chemical elements—music, as a human practice or as a set of practices, is not that sort of kind. That is not to say that music is not natural to human beings: some aspects of musical practice, if not universal, seem to be extremely widespread among societies worldwide. Nor is it to say that music is divorced from the natural world. Far from it: as I have indicated above, music is very deeply affected by its rootedness in the material world, especially in the case of the use and meaning of musical instruments. What I wish to stress rather is that music is a set of culturally and historically situated practices of human beings. Perhaps the most we can say about the overall coherence of this set is that they form something like a set of Wittgensteinian “family resemblances,” a range of activities that answers to a myriad of human possibilities and interests. And I believe that a deeper understanding of the nature and importance of musical instruments has something important to tell us about this range of practices so conceived. In 1991 Peter Kivy posed an intriguing question in an article entitled “Is Music an Art?”25 What Kivy had in mind in that article was pure instrumental (or “absolute”) music. Kivy argues that instrumental music is not an art in the sense of what we think of as the fine arts. The notion of the fine arts, as developed in the eighteenth century, rested on the notion of an essentially representational practice. Vocal music—specifically the “declamatory” music of composers such as Palestrina— made the inclusion of music in the category of the modern system of the fine arts plausible, but instrumental music never rested comfortably under the rubric of representation. On Kivy’s view, pure instrumental music is closer to the idea of a decorative art, an art that presents to us pure sonic design that we may value for its own sake. On Kivy’s view, absolute music is “a quasi-syntactical structure of sound understandable solely in musical terms and having no semantic or representational content, no meaning, making reference to nothing beyond itself.”26 Like all of Kivy’s writing, the scholarship is erudite and the argument is provocative. I applaud 49 Kivy’s effort to shine a light on a central value of instrumental music—the appreciation for the formal and expressive qualities of the music itself, an aspect of music that captures the imaginations of musicians and listeners alike. As Casals once said when rehearsing the second movement of Mozart’s Symphony No. 39 in E-flat Major, “We must follow the line of the music; we must find the design.”27 But as admirable as it is to take the purely musical aspect seriously, I cannot completely agree, as I have argued elsewhere, with Kivy’s assessment of absolute music. I believe, first of all, that there is, in fact, a well-established understanding of the fine arts, with a lineage going back to Plato, according to which the fine arts are linked to the notion of the arts of beauty and according to which absolute music, even construed as a “decorative” art, can be accommodated. But more fundamentally, I believe that even with respect to so-called absolute music, the decorative aspects of music are inseparable from the expressive dimension of music, a view that I believe Kivy’s version of “enhanced formalism” can accommodate. There is, on my view, a continuum of instrumental music that ranges from an art of pure decoration with a relative paucity of expression to instrumental music that approaches the limit of full-blown expressive imitation. If we admit that much, perhaps what we would want to say is that there is not an art of instrumental music, or even a fine art of instrumental music, but rather various arts of instrumental music.28 I also believe that, with respect to instrumental music, the expressive aesthetic value of music only begins to tell us about the range of significance that music has for human beings. We must distinguish, first, between the aesthetic value of music that focuses on a relatively narrow range of experience relating to sensual and structural properties— however profound that experience might be—and the artistic values of music, by which I mean the larger cultural and social significance of music that has been attributed to music from the time of the ancient Greeks, whether in terms of the connection between music and ethos, mathematics, cosmology, religious, or social and political thought and action.29 Or, if I may put the matter differently, if we are to come to a fuller understanding of the significance of music, we must do this with an understanding of a second sense of the instrumentality of music, one that is related to the instrumentality 50 of music we have been discussing in this article to this point. We must come to understand the instrumental value of music. The way forward, it seems to me, is to keep in mind two important strategies. The first is to take as our initial data the complexity of musical practices, examining the many functions that music does serve in the lives of people and in the various communities in which music is practiced. That is to say, the understanding of music must be contextualist and historical. The second strategy is to adopt a point of view we can call value pluralism, that is, to accept the premise that the value of music may reside in aesthetic values, generously construed, as well as in nonaesthetic values. In this, I think philosophers of music have much to learn from ethnomusicologists, anthropologists, and sociologists of music.30 This is an approach that will have much to say about matters concerning musical form, emotion in music, musical representation, the creation of music, and the various modes of using, appreciating, and valuing music—as well as about the nature and role of musical instruments. In this way I think we will be on the road to developing a robust understanding of the full instrumentality of music.31 PHILIP ALPERSON Department of Philosophy Temple University Philadelphia, Pennsylvania 19122 internet: alperson@temple.edu 1. David Blum, Casals and the Art of Interpretation (University of California Press, 1977), p. vi. 2. For examples, listen to Musique Traditionnelles d’Asie Centrale: Chants Harmoniques Touvas, Silex Y225222, especially selections 5 (“Kargyraa”) and 20 (“Uzlyau”). In the Inuit tradition, two women stand facing each other, generating an astonishing range of rhythmic vocal sounds that include lullabies and representations of the wind, water, dogs, seagulls, and other natural sounds. Listen to Katutjatut Throat Singing, Inukshuk Records, IPCD-0798. For an example of Tuvan fusion listen to Yat-Kha’s CD, ReCover, on which the Yat-Kha Tuvan punk band performs eerie covers of such rock classics as Iron Butterfly’s “InA-Gadda-Da-Vida” and Santana’s version of “Black Magic Woman” (World Village, 468061). 3. For examples, see the film clips of the great Flamenco dancer Yva Yerbabuena on www.youtube.com. Listen also to the contributions of clapping and tapping on Paco de Lucia’s CD Siroco (Verve, 830913-2), and, on the jazz fusion compilation FlamencoJazz (Nuba, KAR 101), listen to Chano Domı́nguez’s versions of Thelonious Monk’s tunes, “Well You Needn’t” and “Bemsha Swing.” 4. See John Engel, Uncommon Sounds: The Left The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism Handed Guitar Players That Changed Music. (Brussels, Belgium: Left Field Ventures sprl, 2006). 5. Blum, Casals and the Art of Interpretation, p. 133. 6. We might also mention in this regard the relatively recent phenomenon of nonsynchronous digital distance recording sessions in which performers at one physical location can create a virtual studio session, playing with other musicians at other physical locations in online recording sessions by trading, performing on, and altering MP3 files. See, for example, www.sessionplayer.com and www.esession.com. 7. Why are there virtually no jazz harpists or jazz bagpipists? Probably because the idiomatic harmonies, rhythms, and dynamic variations of jazz are so hard to achieve on these instruments. Readers are invited to listen to the music of jazz harpist Park Stickney and jazz bagpipist Rufus Harley, respectively, to determine whether these players are exceptions to the rule. Similarly, slide trombones are very cumbersome instruments that make rapid movement from note to note very difficult. Frank Rosolino was one of the very few slide trombonists who could match the dexterity of key-based instruments such as saxophones and clarinets or valve-based instruments such as trumpets and flugelhorns. If you want to keep up with the horns, you’re better off with a valve-trombone. 8. For an example of the Stan Kenton Mellophonium Orchestra, see Kenton’s version of Leonard Bernstein’s West Side Story, arranged by Johnny Richards, especially the exquisite ballads, “Maria,” “Tonight,” and “Somewhere,” Stan Kenton’s West Side Story, Capital Jazz, CDP 7243 B 2991427. 9. For examples of Partch’s music listen to The Harry Partch Collection, Volumes 1–4, New World Records, 80621 1–4. 10. See www.neilfeather.org. 11. See, for example, Stephen Davies, Themes in the Philosophy of Music (Oxford University Press, 2003), Part One, pp. 11–77. 12. I thank Jay Alperson for drawing this program to my attention. 13. The possibility that programs such as Finale, Sibelius, and Band in a Box can make up for a lack of musical imagination and skills is a matter of growing concern to schools of music. Gary Hagberg informs me that some music schools now require applicants to sign a statement affirming that they have not used these programs in preparing tapes submitted as part of the application packet. 14. “Modified” because in the original test we have a machine versus a human being. Here we have a human being versus the same human being with the aid of a machine. 15. That is one reason why keyboard facility is so important for musical understanding. Woodwind, brass, and, to a lesser extent, string players, do not enjoy this advantage. 16. See, for example, Theodore Gracyk, Rhythm and Noise: An Aesthetics of Rock (Duke University Press, 1996) and Andrew Kania, “Making Tracks: The Ontology of Rock Music,” The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 64 (2006): 402–414. 17. See Lydia Goehr, The Imaginary Museum of Musical Works (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992). 18. Compare Marx: “Activity and mind, both in their content and in their mode of existence, are social: social activity and social mind. The human essence of nature first Alperson The Instrumentality of Music exists only for social man. . . . Only through the objectively unfolded richness of man’s essential being is the richness of subjective human sensibility (a musical ear, an eye for beauty of form—in short, senses capable of human gratification, senses affirming themselves as essential powers of man) either cultivated or brought into being.” Karl Marx, Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844, trans. Martin Milligan (New York: International Publishers, 1964), pp. 137–141. 19. See Edward Rothstein, “Is It Live . . . or Yamaha? Channeling Glenn Gould,” New York Times, March 12, 2007. 20. On the concept of norm kinds, see Nicholas Wolterstorff, Works and Worlds of Art (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980). 21. See, for example, Stephen Davies, “Authenticity in Musical Performance,” The British Journal of Aesthetics 27 (1987): 39–50; Stan Godlovitch, “Authentic Performance,” The Monist 71 (1988): 258–273; Jerrold Levinson, “Authentic Performance and Performance Means,” in Levinson, Music, Art, & Metaphysics: Essays in Philosophical Aesthetics (Cornell University Press, 1990), pp. 393–408; and Peter Kivy, Authenticities: Philosophical Reflections on Musical Performance (Cornell University Press, 1995). 22. The notion that an experience can have a “twofold” dimension has been explored in other contexts. Richard Wollheim famously discussed the idea of twofoldness in connection with the perception of pictorial representation, a notion that has been discussed by many others in the field of aesthetics. See the symposium, “Wollheim on Pictorial Representation,” comprising Richard Wollheim, “On Pictorial Representation,” Jerrold Levinson, “Wollheim on Pictorial Representation,” and Susan L. Feagin, “Presentation and Representation,” The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 56 (1998): 217–240. See also Kendall Walton, “Depiction, Perception, and Imagination: Responses to Richard Wollheim,” The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 60 (2002): 27–35 and Bence Nanay, “Is Twofoldness Necessary for Representational Seeing?” The British Journal of Aesthetics 45 (2005): 248–257. In speaking of “double-consciousness” I also mean to refer to W. E. B. DuBois’s famous discussion of “double-consciousness” in his trenchant analysis of the dimensions of racism, in particular his treatment of the question, “How does it feel to be a problem?” DuBois writes, “It is a peculiar sensation, this double-consciousness, this sense of always looking at one’s self through the eyes of others, of measuring one’s soul by the tape of a world that looks on in amused contempt and pity. One ever feels his twoness,—an American, a Negro; two souls, two thoughts, two unreconciled strivings; two warring ideals in one dark body, whose dogged strength alone keeps it from being torn asunder.” W. E. B. DuBois, “Of Our Spiritual Strivings,” in The Souls of Black Folk: Essays and Sketches (New York: Bantam Classics, 1989 [1903]), View publication stats 51 pp. 2–3. I do not wish to press the reference to DuBois (or, for that matter, to Hegel’s discussion of the “unhappy consciousness” in the Phenomenology of Spirit, which likely influenced DuBois) further than to call to mind the notion that there are kinds of experience that can be characterized as being singular but with two aspects. A detailed analysis of the phenomenal character of the twoness of the experience of performed music is beyond the scope of the present article. 23. See Roman Ingarden, The Ontology of the Work of Art, trans. Raymond Meyer with Jon. T. Goldthwait (Ohio University Press, 1989); Joseph Margolis, What, After All, Is a Work of Art? (Penn State University Press, 1999); Jerrold Levinson, Music, Art & Metaphysics, cited above; Amie L. Thomasson, “The Ontology of Art,” in The Blackwell Guide to Aesthetics, ed. Peter Kivy (Oxford: Blackwell, 2004), pp. 78–92 and “The Ontology of Art and Knowledge in Aesthetics,” The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 63 (2005): 221–229; and Stephen Davies, The Philosophy of Art (Malden, Ma: Blackwell, 2006). 24. See Philip Alperson, “On Musical Improvisation,” The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 43 (1984): 17– 29. For other analyses of musical performance see also Stan Godlovich, Musical Performance: A Philosophical Study (London: Routledge, 1998) and David Davies, Art as Performance (Malden, MA: Blackwell, 2004). 25. Peter Kivy, “Is Music an Art?” The Journal of Philosophy 88 (1991): 544–554. 26. Peter Kivy, Music Alone: Philosophical Reflections on the Purely Musical Experience (Cornell University Press, 1990), p. 202. 27. Blum, Casals and the Art of Interpretation, p. 15. 28. Philip Alperson, “The Arts of Music,” The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 50 (1992): 217–230. 29. See Philip Alperson, “Instrumental Music and Instrumental Value,” Journal of Aesthetic Education 27 (1992): 2–10. 30. See Philip Alperson, “Value Monism, Value Pluralism, and Music Education: Sparshott as Fox,” Journal of Aesthetic Education 31 (1997): 19–30. 31. I would like to thank the faculty and students and the participants at a seminar on aesthetics sponsored by the Faculties of Logic and Philosophy of Science and Theory of Literature at the Universidad Autonoma de Madrid, where an earlier version of this essay was read. I am especially indebted to Lilian Bermejo, Noël Carroll, Jesús Vega Encabo, Paloma Atencia Linares, Margaret Moore, Paula Olmos, Mario Santos, and David Teira Serrano for their thoughtful questions and valuable suggestions at those meetings. I would also like to thank Susan Feagin, Mary Hawkesworth, and an anonymous referee for JAAC for excellent suggestions that helped me to sharpen the argument of this essay at a number of points.