At the European Molecular Biology Laboratory in Heidelberg, Germany, Peer Bork’s research group has meticulously reconstructed a new tree of life – tracing the course of evolution. Russ Hodge explains. In the margins of one of Charles Darwin’s notebooks is a small, twig-like drawing – unimpressive until you realise that it represents an enormous intellectual leap, a milestone in human history. It is the first modern sketch of a tree of life, representing the fact that distinct species had common ancestors. For a century, naturalists had collected facts about species, naming them and grouping them according to their similarities. Darwin suddenly understood that the similarities represented familial relationships. Haeckel's Tree of Life The German biologist Ernst Haeckel (1834 - 1919) was a noted scientific illustrator and the first great popularizer of Darwin's Theory of Evolution. His "General Morphology - founded on the the Descent Theory" traced the origin of all life to Moneren, and first suggested that the ancestry of humans was among the Great Apes. Note the position of Menschen ("men") at the very top of the tree, among the Affen ("apes"). The first detailed evolutionary tree was published in 1866 in Haeckel's General Morphology of Organisms. Haeckel organized all creatures, including man, into families, genera, and species on the basis of progressive skeletonization. Rudolf Virchow applauded Haeckel's accomplishment: "anthropology has become part of zoology." However, Haeckel's arrangement of organisms on an ascending scale of development led to serious social and political misuse by Eugenicists and Nazis. Two decades later, another tree was meticulously composed by Ernst Haeckel, the great German naturalist and embryologist and a fanatical admirer of Darwin. Haeckel’s chart attempts to synthesize the plant and animal kingdoms into a single genealogical record of life on Earth. He got a lot of things right, but the tree goes back only so far. Once it reached one-celled organisms, he was stuck – scientists were only beginning to glimpse the amazing variety of such species alive on Earth; they certainly didn’t know enough to make a convincing phylogeny stretching back before the divergence of plants and animals. Since then, scientists have filled in branches and twigs, climbed down the trunk, and pushed deeply into the roots, drawing on the written record of evolution that is preserved in DNA. Still, questions remain, particularly with regard to the early history of life on Earth. Peer Bork’s group at the Haeckel’s tree of life from European Molecular Biology Laboratory in Heidelberg, The Evolution of Man (1879) Germany, has now finished the highest-resolution tree of evolution that has yet been made. It may never be final – millions of species surely remain to be found, and those we know will continue to evolve. But it fills in many of the gaps, and will help scientists sort out fragmentary clues of the existence of new organisms. It also sheds light on the very early history of life on Earth. Early in Earth’s history, there existed an organism that would give rise to all the species known today. In 1994, Christos Ouzounis and Nikos Kyrpides gave this shadowy creature a name: LUCA, for the last universal common ancestor. Studies of DNA sequences taken from plants, fungi, animals, bacteria, and another form of one-celled organism called Archaea proved that it must have existed. But until recently, scientists could say very little else about it. “Two things have changed,” Peer says. “First is the immense amount of information we have from DNA sequencing – over 350 organisms have been completely sequenced, spread across the entire spectrum of life. This gives us a huge amount of data that can be compared to make a good tree and also to answer some questions about LUCA. Certain key genes can be found in all of them, and the chemical ‘spelling’ of these genes permits us to group them into families and historical relationships.” It also allows researchers to reconstruct hypothetical ancestors. A fundamental principle of evolution, called the principle of common descent, states that if two organisms share features, it is almost always because they inherited the characteristics from a common ancestor. So by comparing existing species, scientists can obtain a picture of more ancient forms of life. "Over the past few decades, scientists have realised there is an important exception to this rule,” Peer says. “Bacteria can swap genes with each other, and sometimes they can even steal a gene from a plant or an animal. Once that has happened, they pass the gene on to their descendents. Such genes have a completely different profile to genes inherited the normal way. It’s like finding a branch from a tree that grows crosswise and fuses into another branch.” Peer says that attempts have been made to find such genes and eliminate them when building trees from DNA sequence data. But no one knew how often such events, called horizontal gene transfer (HGT), happened, or had developed a convincing method for finding them. “For a while, it was almost as if the amount of data was increasing the problem rather than solving it,” Peer says. “There were big debates, and the numbers of classifications were growing rather than reaching a consensus.” Part of the problem lay in the fact that the work could only be done by computer in a highly automated way, due to the incredible amount of genomic data that had to be sifted through. Francesca Ciccarelli, a postdoc in Peer’s group, decided to tackle the problem of the tree anew and find a solution to the problem of the HGTs. She started by combing the complete genomes of 191 species for unique orthologues – genes in different species that had evolved from a common ancestral gene. The task was difficult because it couldn’t be completely automated. Francesca found 36 cases, five of which seemed to have been shuffled around through HGTs and were thus discarded. Eliminating these from the analysis, the scientists could now build a complete tree by combining information from 31 genes. Peer was worried that some HGTs might have still have slipped in – a single mistake could spoil the quality of the tree. So the scientists put the computer to work doing some heavy lifting. The 31 genes were randomly divided into four groups. Trees were systematically drawn over and over again, for all of the genes in each group, with the exception of a single gene that was eliminated in each round. Then the results were compared. If the branches of the trees changed from pass to pass, an HGT was likely to be involved, and the gene was submitted to two more tests. In the end, the scientists found seven more candidates for HGTs, which they eliminated from their analysis. The remaining information was combined into a super-tree which was compared once again to trees based on individual genes in three different ways. “Any one of these methods on its own might have left a tree with some mistakes,” Peer says, “but by combining them, we’re confident that we have an extremely accurate picture of the evolutionary history of these molecules and the species.” The new tree of life includes all three domains of life: Archaea, Bacteria and The results clear up some old controversies, for example, a debate about the very early evolution of animals. Some trees in the past proposed that the vertebrates (which include humans) split off from another branch which would remain united for a while before splitting into separate branches leading to worms and insects. The new version groups things Eukaryota. There are so many species that the tree has to be drawn in a circle differently: vertebrate and insect ancestors split off from the worms together, and diverge from each other later. The higher resolution of the tree is also important, Peer says, because of metagenomic studies which are underway to sequence all the genes found in environments such as farm soil or ocean water. His group has participated in several such projects. ”Most sequencing approaches start with a given organism and work through its whole genome systematically,” he says. “Metagenomics is sequencing a place – like a global positioning system coordinate. In many cases we recover fragmentary traces of thousands of genes, and have no idea what organism they come from. Often these molecules represent creatures that have never been seen before.” The breadth and detail of the new tree will allow scientists to make much better guesses about where such fragments fit in and what types of living beings they belong to. Has the living world been fairly split up into major branches, limbs, and twigs, or have we overemphasized the prominence of our own lineage? A close look at the new tree shows that the latter seems to be the case. The eukaryotes, which include yeast, plants and animals such as ourselves, are so visibly different from one another that scientists have pushed them apart from each other on the tree. Genetically speaking, however, the species are often much more closely related than many single-celled forms of life. “Smaller genomes evolve faster,” Peer says. “There isn’t a single organism that has been sequenced that is both evolving fast and has a large genome. It suggests that some of the simplest species around have ended up that way because they have pruned things down. Evolution isn’t always about acquiring complexity.” The study also gives the scientists a closer look at LUCA. “One very big question has been what the earliest bacteria were like when they split off from the Archaea. Bacteria are grouped into two classes, called Gram-positive and Gram-negative, based on features of their membranes. The new tree reveals that Gram-positive bacteria evolved first. And if you look at their repertoire of genes, they seem to be suited to a very hot environment. The first Archaea were discovered in hot ocean vents, and most of the species alive today are thermophilic. It strongly suggests that LUCA was, too.” Definition Classification has been defined by Mayr as "The arrangement of entities in a hierarchical series of nested classes, in which similar or related classes at one hierarchical level are combined comprehensively into more inclusive classes at the next higher level." A class is defined as "a collection of similar entities", where the similarity consists of the entities having attributes or traits in common.[1] What makes biological classification different from other classification systems (e.g. classifying books in a library) is evolution: the similarity between organisms placed in the same taxon is not arbitrary, but is instead a result of shared descent from their nearest common ancestor. Accordingly, the important attributes or traits for biological classification are 'homologous', i.e., inherited from common ancestors.[2] These must be separated from traits that are analogous. Thus birds and bats both have the power of flight, but this similarity is not used to classify them into a taxon (a "class"), because it is not inherited from a common ancestor. In spite of all the other differences between them, the fact that bats and whales both feed their young on milk is one of the features used to classify both of them as mammals, since it was inherited from a common ancestor(s). Determining whether similarities are homologous or analogous can be difficult. Thus until recently, golden moles, found in South Africa, were placed in the same taxon (insectivores) as Northern Hemisphere moles, on the basis of morphological and behavioural similarities. However, molecular analysis has shown that they are not closely related, so that their similarities must be due to convergent evolution and not to shared descent, and so should not be used to place them in the same taxon.[3] [edit] Taxonomic ranks Main article: Taxonomic rank A classification, as defined above, is necessarily hierarchical. In a biological classification, rank is the level (the relative position) in a hierarchy. (Rarely, the term "taxonomic category" is used instead of "rank".) There are seven main ranks defined by the international nomenclature codes: kingdom, phylum/division, class, order, family, genus, species. "Domain", a level above kingdom, has become popular in recent years, but has not been accepted into the codes. The most basic rank is that of species, the next higher is genus, and then family. Ranks are somewhat arbitrary, but hope to encapsulate the diversity contained within a group — a rough measure of the number of diversifications that the group has been through.[4] The International Code of Zoological Nomenclature defines rank, in the nomenclatural sense, as: The level, for nomenclatural purposes, of a taxon in a taxonomic hierarchy (e.g. all families are for nomenclatural purposes at the same rank, which lies between superfamily and subfamily). The ranks of the family group, the genus group, and the species group at which nominal taxa may be established are stated in Articles 10.3, 10.4, 35.1, 42.1 and 45.1.[5] There are slightly different ranks for zoology and for botany, including subdivisions such as tribe. [show] v d e Taxonomic ranks [edit] Early systems [edit] Ancient through medieval times Aristotle, 384–322 BC. Current systems of classifying forms of life descend from the thought presented by the Greek philosopher Aristotle, who published in his metaphysical works the first known classification of everything whatsoever, or "being". This is the scheme that gave such words as 'substance', 'species' and 'genus' and was retained in modified and less general form by Linnaeus. Aristotle also studied animals and classified them according to method of reproduction, as did Linnaeus later with plants. Aristotle's animal classification was eventually made obsolete by additional knowledge and forgotten. The philosophical classification is in brief as follows:[6] Primary substance is the individual being; for example, Peter, Paul, etc. Secondary substance is a predicate that can properly or characteristically be said of a class of primary substances; for example, man of Peter, Paul, etc. The characteristic must not be merely in the individual; for example, being skilled in grammar. Grammatical skill leaves most of Peter out and therefore is not characteristic of him. Similarly man (all of mankind) is not in Peter; rather, he is in man. Species is the secondary substance that is most proper to its individuals. The most characteristic thing that can be said of Peter is that Peter is a man. An identity is being postulated: "man" is equal to all its individuals and only those individuals. Members of a species differ only in number but are totally the same type. Genus is a secondary substance less characteristic of and more general than the species; for example, man is an animal, but not all animals are men. It is clear that a genus contains species. There is no limit to the number of Aristotelian genera that might be found to contain the species. Aristotle does not structure the genera into phylum, class, etc., as the Linnaean classification does. The secondary substance that distinguishes one species from another within a genus is the specific difference. Man can thus be comprehended as the sum of specific differences (the "differentiae" of biology) in less and less general categories. This sum is the definition; for example, man is an animate, sensate, rational substance. The most characteristic definition contains the species and the next most general genus: man is a rational animal. Definition is thus based on the unity problem: the species is but one yet has many differentiae. The very top genera are the categories. There are ten: one of substance and nine of "accidents", universals that must be "in" a substance. Substances exist by themselves; accidents are only in them: quantity, quality, etc. There is no higher category, "being", because of the following problem, which was only solved in the Middle Ages by Thomas Aquinas: a specific difference is not characteristic of its genus. If man is a rational animal, then rationality is not a property of animals. Substance therefore cannot be a kind of being because it can have no specific difference, which would have to be non-being. The problem of "being" occupied the attention of scholastics during the time of the Middle Ages. The solution of St. Thomas, termed the analogy of being, established the field of ontology, which received the better part of the publicity and also drew the line between philosophy and experimental science. The latter rose in the Renaissance from practical technique. Linnaeus, a classical scholar, combined the two on the threshold of the neoclassicist revival now called the Age of Enlightenment. [edit] Renaissance through Age of Reason Rhinoceros in Conrad Gesner's Historiae animalium, 1551 An important advance was made by the Swiss professor, Conrad von Gesner (1516–1565). Gesner's work was a critical compilation of life known at the time. The exploration of parts of the New World by Europeans produced large numbers of new plants and animals that needed descriptions and classification. The old systems made it difficult to study and locate all these new specimens within a collection and often the same plants or animals were given different names simply because there were too many species to keep track of. A system was needed that could group these specimens together so they could be found; the binomial system was developed based on morphology with groups having similar appearances. In the latter part of the 16th century and the beginning of the 17th, careful study of animals commenced, which, directed first to familiar kinds, was gradually extended until it formed a sufficient body of knowledge to serve as an anatomical basis for classification. Advances in using this knowledge to classify living beings bear a debt to the research of medical anatomists, such as Fabricius (1537–1619), Petrus Severinus (1580– 1656), William Harvey (1578–1657), and Edward Tyson (1649–1708). Advances in classification due to the work of entomologists and the first microscopists is due to the research of people like Marcello Malpighi (1628–1694), Jan Swammerdam (1637–1680), and Robert Hooke (1635–1702). Lord Monboddo (1714–1799) was one of the early abstract thinkers whose works illustrate knowledge of species relationships and who foreshadowed the theory of evolution.[7] [edit] Early methodists Since late in the 15th century, a number of authors had become concerned with what they called methodus, (method). By method authors mean an arrangement of minerals, plants, and animals according to the principles of logical division. The term Methodists was coined by Carolus Linnaeus in his Bibliotheca Botanica to denote the authors who care about the principles of classification (in contrast to the mere collectors who are concerned primarily with the description of plants paying little or no attention to their arrangement into genera, etc.). Important early Methodists were Italian philosopher, physician, and botanist Andrea Caesalpino, English naturalist John Ray, German physician and botanist Augustus Quirinus Rivinus, and French physician, botanist, and traveller Joseph Pitton de Tournefort. Andrea Caesalpino (1519–1603) in his De plantis libri XVI (1583) proposed the first methodical arrangement of plants. On the basis of the structure of trunk and fructification he divided plants into fifteen "higher genera". John Ray (1627–1705) was an English naturalist who published important works on plants, animals, and natural theology. The approach he took to the classification of plants in his Historia Plantarum was an important step towards modern taxonomy. Ray rejected the system of dichotomous division by which species were classified according to a pre-conceived, either/or type system, and instead classified plants according to similarities and differences that emerged from observation. Both Caesalpino and Ray used traditional plant names and thus, the name of a plant did not reflect its taxonomic position (e.g. even though the apple and the peach belonged to different "higher genera" of John Ray's methodus, both retained their traditional names Malus and Malus Persica respectively). A further step was taken by Rivinus and Pitton de Tournefort who made genus a distinct rank within taxonomic hierarchy and introduced the practice of naming the plants according to their genera. Augustus Quirinus Rivinus (1652–1723), in his classification of plants based on the characters of the flower, introduced the category of order (corresponding to the "higher" genera of John Ray and Andrea Caesalpino). He was the first to abolish the ancient division of plants into herbs and trees and insisted that the true method of division should be based on the parts of the fructification alone. Rivinus extensively used dichotomous keys to define both orders and genera. His method of naming plant species resembled that of Joseph Pitton de Tournefort. The names of all plants belonging to the same genus should begin with the same word (generic name). In the genera containing more than one species the first species was named with generic name only, while the second, etc. were named with a combination of the generic name and a modifier (differentia specifica). Joseph Pitton de Tournefort (1656–1708) introduced an even more sophisticated hierarchy of class, section, genus, and species. He was the first to use consistently the uniformly composed species names that consisted of a generic name and a many-worded diagnostic phrase differentia specifica. Unlike Rivinus, he used differentiae with all species of polytypic genera. [edit] Linnaean taxonomy Main article: Linnaean taxonomy Carolus Linnaeus Carolus Linnaeus' great work, the Systema Naturæ (1st ed. 1735), ran through twelve editions during his lifetime. In this work, nature was divided into three kingdoms: mineral, vegetable and animal. Linnaeus used five ranks: class, order, genus, species, and variety. He abandoned long descriptive names of classes and orders still used by his immediate predecessors (Rivinus and Pitton de Tournefort) and replaced them with single-word names, provided genera with detailed diagnoses (characteres naturales), and combined numerous varieties into their species, thus saving botany from the chaos of new forms produced by horticulturalists. Linnaeus is best known for his introduction of the method still used to formulate the scientific name of every species. Before Linnaeus, long many-worded names (composed of a generic name and a differentia specifica) had been used, but as these names gave a description of the species, they were not fixed. In his Philosophia Botanica (1751) Linnaeus took every effort to improve the composition and reduce the length of the many-worded names by abolishing unnecessary rhetorics, introducing new descriptive terms and defining their meaning with an unprecedented precision. In the late 1740s Linnaeus began to use a parallel system of naming species with nomina trivialia. Nomen triviale, a trivial name, was a single- or two-word epithet placed on the margin of the page next to the many-worded "scientific" name. The only rules Linnaeus applied to them was that the trivial names should be short, unique within a given genus, and that they should not be changed. Linnaeus consistently applied nomina trivialia to the species of plants in Species Plantarum (1st edn. 1753) and to the species of animals in the 10th edition of Systema Naturæ (1758). By consistently using these specific epithets, Linnaeus separated nomenclature from description. Even though the parallel use of nomina trivialia and many-worded descriptive names continued until late in the eighteenth century, it was gradually replaced by the practice of using shorter proper names consisting of the generic name and the trivial name of the species. In the nineteenth century, this new practice was codified in the first Rules and Laws of Nomenclature, and the 1st edn. of Species Plantarum and the 10th edn. of Systema Naturae were chosen as starting points for the Botanical and Zoological Nomenclature respectively. This convention for naming species is referred to as binomial nomenclature. Today, nomenclature is regulated by Nomenclature Codes, which allows names divided into taxonomic ranks. [edit] Modern system Main articles: Evolutionary taxonomy and Phylogenetic nomenclature Evolution of the vertebrates at class level, width of spindles indicating number of families. Spindle diagrams are typical for Evolutionary taxonomy The same relationship, expressed as a cladogram typical for cladistics Whereas Linnaeus classified for ease of identification, the idea of the Linnaean taxonomy as translating into a sort of dendrogram of the Animal- and Plant Kingdoms was formulated toward the end of the 18th century, well before the On the Origin of Species was published. Among early works exploring the idea of a transmutation of species was Erasmus Darwin's 1796 Zoönomia and Jean-Baptiste Lamarck's Philosophie Zoologique of 1809. The idea was popularised in the Anglophone world by the speculative, but widely read Vestiges of the Natural History of Creation, published anonymously by Robert Chambers in 1844.[8] With Darwin's theory, a general acceptance that classification should reflect the Darwinian principle of common descent quickly appeared. Tree of Life representations became popular in scientific works, with known fossil groups incorporated. One of the first modern groups tied to fossil ancestors were birds. Using the then newly discovered fossils of Archaeopteryx and Hesperornis, Thomas Henry Huxley pronounced that they had evolved from dinosaurs, a group formally named by Richard Owen in 1842.[9] The resulting description, that of dinosaurs "giving rise to" or being "the ancestors of" birds, is the essential hallmark of evolutionary taxonomic thinking. As more and more fossil groups were found and recognized in the late 19th and early 20th century, palaeontologists worked to understand the history of animals through the ages by linking together known groups[10] With the modern evolutionary synthesis of the early 1940s, an essentially modern understanding of evolution of the major groups was in place. The evolutionary taxonomy being based on Linnaean taxonomic ranks, the two terms are largely interchangeable in modern use. Since the 1960s a trend called cladistic taxonomy (or cladistics or cladism) has emerged, arranging taxa in a hierarchical evolutionary tree, ignoring ranks. If a taxon includes all the descendants of some ancestral form, it is called monophyletic. Groups that have descendant groups removed from them (e.g. dinosaurs, with birds as offspring group) are termed paraphyletic, while groups representing more than one branch from the tree of life are called polyphyletic. A formal code of nomenclature, the International Code of Phylogenetic Nomenclature, or PhyloCode for short, is currently under development, intended to deal with names of clades. Linnaean ranks will be optional under the PhyloCode, which is intended to coexist with the current, rank-based codes. [edit] Kingdoms and domains Main article: Kingdom (biology) From well before Linnaeus, plants and animals were considered separate Kingdoms. Linnaeus used this as the top rank, dividing the physical world into the plant, animal and mineral kingdoms. As advances in microscopy made classification of microorganisms possible, the number of kingdoms increased, five and six-kingdom systems being the most common. Domains are a relatively new grouping. The three-domain system was first proposed in 1990, but not generally accepted until later. One main characteristic of the three-domain method is the separation of Archaea and Bacteria, previously grouped into the single kingdom Bacteria (a kingdom also sometimes called Monera). Consequently, the three domains of life are conceptualized as Archaea, Bacteria, and Eukaryota (comprising the nuclei-bearing eukaryotes).[11] A small minority of scientists add Archaea as a sixth kingdom, but do not accept the domain method. Thomas Cavalier-Smith, who has published extensively on the classification of protists, has recently proposed that the Neomura, the clade that groups together the Archaea and Eukarya, would have evolved from Bacteria, more precisely from Actinobacteria. His classification of 2004 treats the archaebacteria as part of a subkingdom of the Kingdom Bacteria, i.e. he rejects the three-domain system entirely.[12] Woese CavalierHaeckel Whittake Linnaeus Copeland et al. Smith 1866[14] Chatton r Woese et al. [17][18] [22] 2004[12] 1735[13] 1938 1990 3 1925[15][16] 1969[19] 1977[20][21] 2 4 3 6 kingdom 2 empires 5 6 kingdoms kingdoms kingdoms domain kingdom s kingdoms s s Eubacteria Bacteria Prokaryot Monera Monera Bacteria Archaebacteri a Archaea a (not Protista treated) Protozoa Protoctist Protista Protista Chromist a a Eukaryota Plantae Plantae Plantae Eukarya Plantae Vegetabili Plantae Protoctist a Fungi Fungi Fungi a Animalia Animalia Animalia Animalia Animalia Animalia [edit] Authorities (author citation) An "authority" may be placed after a scientific name. The authority is the name of the scientist who first validly published the name. For example, in 1758 Linnaeus gave the Asian elephant the scientific name Elephas maximus, so the name is sometimes written as "Elephas maximus Linnaeus, 1758". The names of authors are frequently abbreviated: the abbreviation "L." is universally accepted for Linnaeus, and in botany there is a regulated list of standard abbreviations (see list of botanists by author abbreviation). The system for assigning authorities differs slightly between botany and zoology. However, it is standard that if a species' name or placement has been changed since the original description, the original authority's name is placed in parentheses. [edit] Globally unique identifiers for names There is a movement within the biodiversity informatics community to provide globally unique identifiers in the form of Life Science Identifiers (LSID) for all biological names. This would allow authors to cite names unambiguously in electronic media and reduce the significance of errors in the spelling of names or the abbreviation of authority names. Three large nomenclatural databases (referred to as nomenclators) have already begun this process, these are Index Fungorum, International Plant Names Index and ZooBank. Other databases, that publish taxonomic rather than nomenclatural data, have also started using LSIDs to identify taxa. The key example of this is Catalogue of Life. In the next step in integration, these taxonomic databases will include references to the nomenclatural databases using LSIDs. The system that we still use today for giving scientific names to plants and animals has many founders, from the Greek philosopher Aristotle to the Swedish physician and botanist Carolus Linnaeus. Taxonomy is the study of scientific classification, in particular the classification of living organisms according to their natural relationships. Taxonomy's first father was the philosopher Aristotle (384-322 BC), sometimes called the "father of science." It was Aristotle who first introduced the two key concepts of taxonomy as we practice it today: classification of oranisms by type and binomial definition. Aristotle was the first to attempt to classify all the kinds of animals in his History of Animals (Historia Animalium in Latin). He grouped the types of creatures according to their similarities: animals with blood and animals without blood, animals that live on water and animals that live on land. Aristotle's view of life was hierarchical. He assumed that creatures could be grouped in order from lowest to highest, with the human species being the highest. Subsequent commentators on Aristotle interpreted this as a "ladder of nature" (scala naturae) or a "Great Chain of Being," but these were not Aristotle's terms. His system of classification was not evolutionary, and the various species on the ladder had no specific genetic relationship to each other. Aristotle regarded the essence of species as fixed and unchanging, and this view persisted for the next two thousand years. His other innovation was binomial definition. "Binomial" means "two names," and according to this system each kind of organism can be defined by the two names of its "genus and difference." The word "genus" comes from the Greek root for "birth," and among its meanings are "family" and "race." Aristotle's notion of definition was to place every object in a family and then to differentiate it from the other members of that family by some unique characteristic. He defined humans, for example, as the "rational animal." This, according to Aristotelian thought, defines the essence of what it is to be human, as opposed to such pseudo-definitions as "featherless biped." But what Aristotle did not do was methodically use binomial definition in his system of biological classification. This innovation had to await the development of modern science after the Rennaissance. Aristotle's influence was profound and long-lasting. Much of his work has not survived to the present day, so that we don't know the details of his study of plants, but his student Theophrastus (372-287 BC) continued it, becoming known as the "father of botany." He is believed to have planted the first botanical garden on the grounds of Aristotle's Lyceum. Most of the text of his two botanical works, On Plants (De Historia Plantarum) and The Causes of Plants (De Causis Plantarum) still exists, although only in Latin translations. The first describes the anatomy of plants and classifies them into trees, shrubs, herbaceous perennials, and herbs. The second work discusses their propagation and growth and served in part as a practical guide to farmers and gardeners. However, he introduced no new principles of classification. After Aristotle, there was little innovation in the fields of the biological sciences until the 16th century AD. At this time, voyages of exploration were beginning to discover plants and animals new to Europeans, which excited the interest of natural philosophers, as scientists were then called. There was great interest in naming these new species and fitting them into the existing classifications, and this in turn led to new systems of classification. Many of the botanists of this period were also physicians, who were interested in the use of plants for producing medicines. Andrea Cesalpino (1519-1603) was an Italian physician who created one of the first new systems of classifying plants since the time of Aristotle. He was a professor of materia medica, the study of the preparation of medicines from plants, at the University of Pisa, and was also in charge of the university's botanical garden. There, he wrote a series of works titled On Plants (De Plantis), detailing his system of classification. While his work was in large part based on the work of Aristotle and his successors, his innovation in basing his system of classifying plants on the basis of the structure of their fruits and seeds influenced subsequent scientists such as Linnaeus. One botanist who was influenced by Cesalpino was Gaspard Bauhin (1560-1620), a Swiss physician and anatomist. In his 1623 Illustrated Exposition of Plants (Pinax Theatri Botanica), he described about six thousand species and gave them names based on their "natural affinities," grouping them into genus and species. He was thus the first scientist to use binomial nomenclature in classification of species, anticipating the work of Linnaeus. By the time Carl (Carolus) Linnaeus (1707-1778) was born, there were many systems of botanical classification in use, with new plants constantly being discovered and named. This, in fact, was the problem — there were too many inconsistent systems, and the same plant might have several different scientific names, according to different methods of classification. During his childhood, Linnaeus was so fond of collecting plants that he was known as "the little botanist." He later became a physician, as so many other early taxonomists did, but returned to botany as his primary study. He published his most innovative work as a young man in 1735. The System of Nature (Systema Naturae) is notable for an overall framework of classification that organized all plants and animals from the level of kingdoms all the way down to species. The full subtitle of its tenth edition was: System of nature through the three kingdoms of nature, according to classes, orders, genera and species, with characteristics, differences, synonyms, places. This system of classification, although greatly modified, is essentially the one we use today. Linnaeus followed this work with The Genera of Plants and The Species of Plants, setting out a system of plant classification based on the structure of flower parts, in which he was influenced by Cesalpino. This method, in which plants were grouped together according to the number of stamens in their flowers, for example, was not accurate, but it was easy to use and thus readily adapted by scientists who were continually discovering more new varieties of plants. Linnaeus himself undertook much work in the field, and he was even more influential through his students, whom he sent around the world to gather specimens. His major works went through a great deal of revision in his lifetime, eliminating errors and coming closer to the system that was eventually adopted by taxonomists worldwide. His methods of classifying plants have been completely superseded by a deeper scientific understanding. Originally, Linnaeus had only used binomial nomenclature to classify plants, but he later extended this system to include animals and even minerals. There were also errors, subsequently corrected. At first, for example, he had placed the whales among the fishes, but later moved them into the mammals. He was also the first taxonomist to place humans among the primates (or Anthropomorpha) and to give them the binomen Homo sapiens. If Linnaeus is now considered the father of taxonomy, his success rested on the work of his predecessors. He was the first, in his System of Nature, to combine a hierarchical system of classification from kingdom to species with the method of binomial nomenclature, using it consistently to identify every species of both plants and animals then known to him. While he continued throughout his lifetime to revise and expand this great work, so his successors have continued to revise the principles of taxonomy, now according to genetic principles, informed by the analysis of DNA. So it always is with science: we stand on the shoulders of our predecessors, always reaching higher. Georges Cuvier was one of the most influential figures in science during the early nineteenth century. A self-appointed referee of proper science from his stronghold in the elite Académie des Sciences, Cuvier was as successful in creating his own image as a great man of science as he was in the many areas of science he studied. Cuvier was born on 23 August 1769, at Montbéliard, a French-speaking community in the Jura Mountains then rule by the Duke of Württemberg. Cuvier went to school at the Carolinian Academy in Stuttgart from 1784 to 1788. He was then a tutor for a noble family in Normandy. Here he first began to establish a reputation as a naturalist. In 1795 Geoffroy Saint-Hilaire invited Cuvier to come to Paris. Cuvier was first appointed an assistant and later a professor of animal anatomy at the post-French revolution Musée National d'Histoire Naturelle. When Napoleon came to power Cuvier was appointed to several government positions, including State Councillor and Inspector-General of public education. After the restoration of the monarchy Cuvier still managed to preserve his status. In 1831 he was made Baron and a Peer of France. Cuvier had a deep abhorrence against a popularization or democratization of scientific knowledge. Statue of Cuvier on the rear wall of the Royal Academy, London [Click on image for larger picture] Cuvier's scientific achievements are difficult to overestimate. It was widely recounted that he could reconstruct a skeleton based on a single bone. His work is considered the foundation of vertebrate palaeontology. Cuvier expanded Linneaun taxonomy by grouping classes into phyla. Cuvier arranged both fossils and living species in this taxonomy. Cuvier convinced his contemporaries that extinction was a fact- what had been a controversial speculation before. Cuvier strongly opposed Geoffroy's theory that all organisms were based on a basic plan or archetype and that they blended gradually one into another. Cuvier argued instead that life was divided into four distinct embranchements (life-vertebrates, molluscs, articulates (insects & crustaceans), and radiates). For Cuvier, it was function- not hypothetical relationships, that should form the basis of classification. This issue, which obviously could support or contradict a theory of evolution, was part of the famous Cuvier/Geoffroy debate in 1830. The debate has often been interpreted in the retrospect of a post-Darwin age as a debate over evolution. However the debate mostly revolved around the number of archetypes necessary to categorize all organisms. In his Essay on the Theory of the Earth (1813) Cuvier proposed that new species were created after periodic catastrophic floods. His study of the Paris basin with Alexandre Brongniart established the basic principles of biostratigraphy. Cuvier was a strong opponent of his colleague Lamarck's theory of evolution. (See Cuvier's Elegy of Lamarck) Cuvier believed there was no evidence for the evolution of organic forms but rather evidence for successive creations after catastrophic extinction events. Some of Cuvier's most influential followers were Louis Agassiz on the continent and in America, and Richard Owen in Britain. Term Node-based definition Monophyly A clade, a monophyletic taxon, is a Character-based definition A clade is characterized by one or more taxon which includes all descendants apomorphies: derived character states present in of an inferred ancestor. the first member of the taxon, inherited by its descendants (unless secondarily lost), and not inherited by any other taxa. Paraphyly A paraphyletic assemblage is one A paraphyletic assemblage is characterized by one which is constructed by taking a or more plesiomorphies: character states clade and removing one or more inherited from ancestors but not present in all of smaller clades.[28] (Removing one their descendants. As a consequence, a clade produces a singly paraphyletic paraphyletic assemblage is truncated, in that it assemblage, removing two a doubly excludes one or more clades from an otherwise paraphylectic assemblage, and so monophyletic taxon. An alternative name is on.)[29] evolutionary grade, referring to an ancestral character state within the group. While paraphyletic assemblages are popular among paleontologists and evolutionary taxonomists, cladists do not recognize paraphyletic assemblages as having any formal information content – they are merely parts of clades. Polyphyly A polyphyletic assemblage is one A polyphyletic assemblage is characterized by one which is neither monophyletic nor or more homoplasies: character states which have paraphyletic. converged or reverted so as to be the same but which have not been inherited from a common ancestor. No systematist recognizes polyphyletic assemblages as taxonomically meaningful entities, although ecologists sometimes consider them meaningful labels for functional participants in ecological communities (e. g., primary producers, detritivores, etc.).