էն€Հ٩ ٩ 乙 九 ルレ %«"フレん 1 shall argue in this essay that there is much wrong with speciesism: ί shall begin by examining the arguments made in defence of strong speciesism by Cohcn and Grg evaluaiing them with reference to Steinbock, Graft, and Lafollette and Shanks, before moving on to the arguments made by Holland in deilnce of weak speciesism, and evaluating them with reference to Kaufman. I shall 1se the conclusion to tie together and fUrther develop the evaluative remarks made throughout the essay. According to Singer, the speciesist believes that it is ijustifiable, to give ‘preference to beings' on the basis of their membership of a certain species (Singer, 2006、p.3). The strong speciesistjustifies Piscrimination or exploitation' (Ryder, 1998, p.320) on the basis of"species membership alone' (Horta, 2010, p.4), whereas the weak speciesistjustifies it on the basis that humans have 'certain characteristics' that make 'moral consideration appropriate', and that nonhuman animals lack (Holland,i984,p.284). 専2 Cohen argues that animals 'have no rights', because rights are 'claims' or ‘potential claims' within a 'commιmity of moral agents' (Cohen, 1986, p.94). The existence ofrights requires that they can be 'intelligibly defDnded' by beings who have 1he capacity to 'make moral claims against one another': humans can satisfy these requirements because they are ‘morally autonomous' and can understand 'rules of duty、and Teggnise possible confHct between what is in theirown interest' and 'what is just', but animals lack this capacity for 'fYee moral judgement' (Cohen, 1986. p.95). Gray argues that the empathy we feel for other human beings is an ،extension' ofthe、genetically based concerns' that we 'f3el forkin'. Morality is based on a 'biological' foundation, and ifwe act in Congmity with this foundation then we value the lives ofmembers of our own species above those of other species. This fact not only entitles us to prioritise the con81^ns of the human species, but gives us a、special duty' to ،members of our own species' that allows us tojustify discrimination against other species (Gray,1990, p.23). | ■3 Cohen's argument is unpersuasive: 'the fact that an entity does not have rights' does not mean that its interests 'count for less', or that we arejustificd in discriminating against it (Steinbock, 1978, p.250). Our behaviour towards others is influenced by factors other than a concern for their rights: the reason we refrain from assaulting others is not because it 'infringes' theirrights, but because we know that it 'hurts' them. The question is not ‘Can they reason?', nor ‘Can they talk?、,but 'Can they su∏erγ,: we know that animals can suffer, so the question ofrights is irrelevant (Bentham, 2000, p.l44). Furthennore, 'infants' and the 'mentally defective' are incapable ofmaking 'moral daims against one another', but this obviously does not mean that we treat them in ways in which、it would not be permissible to treat right-bearers'. Gray's argument is also unconvincing:just because something is namral does not mean that it is 'unavoidable' (Lafollette and Shanks, 1996, p.44). We also have 、biological tendencies towards aggression', but we certainly do not 'encourage, praise, or morally sanctify՛ this particular tendency. The very fact that non-speciesists exist proves 1hat speciesism 'cannot be natural' in the 'strong nomological sense': we have the power to resist our natural impulses, so we cannot use them as an excuse to discriminate against other species that are also capable of suffering. ⅛4 A fUrther objection to LOhen and Gray's arguments comes from Graft: species is a 'problematic concept', one that is difficult to define (Graft, 1997, p.109). The strong speciesist requires a species conceptwith clearly delineated boundaries between species to fhcilitate moral discrimination, but the reality is that these kinds of species concept — of which 'typism' might be considered an example — —are plagued by 'arbitrariness'. With typism for example, a 'broad partitioning' ofthe 'properties' that a group must possess in order 1O be considered a species could lead to a massive 'extension ofmorality', such as if we only distinguished 'animak from non-animals'. Conversely, a ،fine partitioning' could lead to a 'restriction of morality', such as if we included 'skin cobur' among our criteria and thus restricted morality to a 'single human "race'" (Graft, 1997, ρ.l 10). The speciesist might argue that these arguments are 'irrelevant' (Graft 1997, p.116), because we 'know which creatures are human”,but the fact is that over Molutionary time scales' human beings are 'virtually infants'. Ifhumans 8me to survive over ςevolutionari!y significanttime spans'. natural 'varEbility' and selection could gradually create new species within the original human species, or at the very least make it more difficult to define what a human is: the definition of the human species is 'contingent' rather than absolute, and the concept of species is thus unsuited to supporting a "generalisable, strong speciesist morality' (Graft, 1997, p,108). Ü Holland argues that a weak speciesism - based on the idea that morally relevant characteristics are present to a 'significantly greater extent' in humans — —allows the speciesist to take a Faturalistic' approach, and to incorporate the evolutEnary and scientific points that Graft raised (Holland, 1984, p.284). Holland believes thatweak speciesism can accommodate the fact that 'the determinants of a species are not clearly established‘: Holland recognises that the 'morally significant gap' between 'humans and other species' is partially based on 'empirically open questions', and that a consequence of this is that the Evolutionary affinities' between humans and other species require that some ofthe 'moral significance‘ attached to humans will be shared with other species (Holland, 1984, p.285). Holl&1d also argues that the existence of‰deficient humans' (Holland, 1984, p.283)is not problematic for the weak speciesist: even though deficient humans and nonhuman animals are 'alike' in that they 'lack' the ñdl range ofmorally relevant characteristics that a noπnal human is endowed with, the case ofthe deRcient humans is FiffbrenV, because they have been krobbed,. Nonhuman animals never had the potential to achieve the moral status of normal humans, while as deRcient humans had this moral stams stolen from them. 3 Holland's point regarding deficient humans is unconvincing: arguing that 'misfbrtune' is morally 'signihcand (Kaufo1an, 1998, p.l60) is oMy possible when the action in question will 'exploit、or 'take advantage、ofthat misfbrtune, but even then, one can still ask why expbiting a misfbrtune is morally wrong. The answer suld not be that 'misfortune makes one defbnceless' (Kaufinan, 1998, ρ.l61), because deficient humans and nonhuman animals are 'both equally defEnceless' by virtue ofthe1r shared 'in^ationality'. While it is true that the ibationality of a deficient human being is a 'misfortune' and the Fog's irrationality is not', they are both、equally vu^erable': misfbrtune is 'inelevant' when the action in question involves 'exploiting a shared vulnerability'. It is true that a Pue regard for misfortune| would prevent one from doing certain Ihings to de^cient humans that it would be perfectly acceptable to do to nonhuman animals, such as enticing them to perf”m circus tricks, but if this 'due regard Srmisfbnune' (Kaufhian, 1998. p.l62) prevents us from discriminating against deficient human beings, then a 'due regard fbrvulnerability' should prevent us from discriminating against nonhuman animals. φ7 It is clear that Cohen fails tojustify strong speciesism on the basis that animals do not have rights, and that Gray fhils to provide a compelling reason to simply abide by our supposed natural inclination towards species-based discrimination, but Holland also sails, because he cannot provide a coherent explanation for why а weak speciesism — one that is based on the presence of morally relevant characteristics — —should insist on giving deficient humans preferential treatment to nonhuman animals, even when we know that they do not possess a greater level of morally relevant characteristics than these nonhuman animals. In fact, the only element ofHolland's sρeciesism that is actually speciesist is the element concerning deficient humans, aside from this, one does not have to be a speciesist to believe that certain 'contingent facts, about human beings may grant them greater 'moral significance'. As Lafollette and Shanks point out, even if it is the case that the 'dif^rences between humans and nonhuman animals' are ‘morally relevant', the resulting 'diference in treatment' is not justified on the basis ofhumans belonging to a d^erent species, but on the basis ofhumans possessing、morally relevant characteristics' (Lafollette and Shanks, 1996, ρ.45): the only element of weak speciesism that is actually speciesist has been shown to be untenable, and the remaining elements simply do not constitute a speciesist approach. Having rebutted the arguments of Cohen and Gray, and having addressed this final concern, it is fair to conclude that there is much wrong with speciesism. 里風 Bentham, Jeremy, 1823. An Introduction to the Principles of Morais and Legislation Vol.2 (London: W. Pickering). Cohen, Carl, 2009, 'Why Animals Have No Rights', in Steven M. Cahn (ed.), Exploring Ethics: An Introductory Anthology (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 94-100. Graft, Donald* 1997 'Against Strong Speciesism', Joumal of Applied Philosophy, V01.14, No.2, 107-118 Gray, J.A., 1990 'In DefEnce of Speciesism', Behavioural and Brain Sciences, V01.13, No.l, 22-23 Holland, Alan J., 1984 'On Behalf of Moderate Speciesism', Journal of Applied Philosophy, Vol.l, No.2, 281-291 Horta, Oscar, 2010 'What is Speciesism?', Joumal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics, Vol.23,No.3,243-266 Kauflnan, Frederik, 1998 'Speciesism and the Argument from Misfbnune', Vol.l5, No.2, 155-163 Lafollette| Hugh and Shanks, Niall, 1996 'The Origin of Speciesism', Philosophy, Vol.71, No.275, 41-61 Ryder, Richard Dudley, 1998, The Political Animal: The Conquest of Speciesism (Jeffbrson: McFarland and Co. Inc.). Singer. Peter, 2006, In Defence ofAnimals: The Second Wave (Oxford: Blackwell Publishing Ltd). Steinbock, Bonnie, 1978 "Speciesism and the Idea ofEquality', Philosophy, Vol.53| No.204, 247-256 s there anything wrong with 'speciesism'? GRADEMARK REPORT GENERAL COMMENTS FINALGRADE Instructor © This is an excellent essay. You make some powerful criticisms of the notion ofspeciesism, and draw some important distinctions along the way. You address the topic at hand in an explicit yet very 8ncise mannerth2ughout, and present a sgent overall argument. You display a sound knowledge and understanding ofvarious articulations of speciesism, and are 2bust but fair in your criticisms. My one (minor) criticism is that, given the breadth of positions you seek to cover, you are sometimes too quick in making those criticisms, which 8uld at times have been explained and developed in a more careful and nuanced manner. OveraIl, an impressive essay. Well done. PAGE 1 Comment 1 Here, as elsewhere, you should give publication dates for the work of the authors you are planning to discuss. Comment2 A good introduction - you've set yourself an ambitious task here though, with lots of positions to cover in a relatively small number of words. PAGE2 C∙omment3 Good. A concise yet well-targeted summary. Comment4 Good. Robust argumentation, well supported with appropriate sources. PAGE3 Comment 5 Again, this is good - it is refreshing to see such strong and confident argumentation. PAGE4 Good, but try not to rely *too* much on quotation. Comment7 Good arguments, 8ncisely put. PAGE5 Üomment8 A very good essay. You have managed to harness a lot of material here, in constructing a spirited and - for the most part - persuasive argument. Well done. PAGE6 PAGE7 RIIRRIU PHILOSOPHY RUBRIC 15-16 RELEVANCE Very Good Relevance Gfdiscussion to aims stated VERY POOR Largely irrelevant P00R Displays only a limited sense of relevance AVERAGE Reievance satisfactory but room for improvement GOOD Mostiy relevant VERYGOOD AII relevant EXCELLENT Highiy re!evant and well directed throughout DEPTH Good Consideration of relevant Dositions/issues/debates VERY POOR Many important issues ignored POOR Some important issues ignored AVERAGE Covers an adequate range of reievant issues GOOD Covers a good range of relevant issues VERYGOOD Covers a very good range of Feievant issues EXCELLENT Covers the fuil range of relevant issues UNDERSTANDING Very Good Grasp of key concepts and arguments VERY POOR Faiiure to grasp key concepts and arguments P00R Limited grasp of key concepts and arguments AVERAGE Reasonable grasp Qf key concepts and arguments GOOD Solid grasp of key concepts and arguments VERYGOOD Very good grasp of key concepts and arguments FXCFMFNY Excelient grasp of key concepts and arguments Very Good DEVELOPMENT Development of arguments and critịcỉsms UERY POQR חחחח Littie or no discernible argument AVERAGE Arguments persuasive in Naces but room for improvement GOOD Mosily weil argued and persuasive VERYGOOD Verywell argued and persuasive throughout EXCELLENT Highly sophisticated and persuasive standard ofargument ORIGINALITY Good Tndepmndent thought and insight VERYPOOR No independent critical thinking. P00R Little evidence of independent critical thinκ∣ng ^VEWAGW Some evidence of independent critical thinking GOOD Good level of independent critical thinking VERYGCOD Ver|/ good tevel Qf independent critical thinking EXCFLLENT Outstanding level of independent critical thinking ORGANISATION Very Good SKucture of argument VERYPOOR LittIe or no discernible structure P00R Some serious structural problems AVFRACF Acceptable structure GQOD Good structure VERYGOOD Very good structure EXCELLENT Exempiary structure CLARITY Very Good Clarity and fluency of expression 'VERY POOR WhoHy unclear P00R Unciear in many places AVERAGE Reasonabiy ciear 匚:エコ Good daπty VERYGOOD Very good clarity EXCELLENT Exemplary clarity Standard of referencing and bibi!ography VERY POOR Littie or סהreferencing POOR Some serious referencing problems AVERAGE Referencing mostly adequate GOOD Good referencing VERYGOOD Very good referencing EXCELLENT Exempiary referencing LITERACY Standard Ofwriting (grammar, spelling etc.) VERY POGR Many serious grammatical and/or spelling problems P00R Some serious grammatical and/or spelling problems AVERAGE Acceptable literacy GC Good literacy VERYGOOD Very good literacy EXCELLENT Exemplary literacy Very Good