Marx on Freedom and Necessity RODGER BEEHLER University of Victoria In a famous passage in volume three of Capital, Karl Marx distinguishes between a "realm of freedom" and a "realm of necessity".1 The passage has attracted attention as seeming to register a dismal perception by Marx of the productive labour that will be necessary even under communism. "Dismal perception" is G. A. Cohen's verdict in his lucid essay "Marx's Dialectic of Labour".2 Cohen has now softened the charge to "a somewhat gloomy perception".3 But he continues to hold that the passage reveals Marx viewing even post-capitalist labour "as bound always to be unsatisfying",4 a marked shift from Marx's optimistic 1840s view that under communism labour would be unalienating. The debate has recently been joined by James Klagge, who has argued against Cohen (and others) that the volume three passage does not disclose a shift in view, and so does not register a "deep pessimism" or "negative appraisal" by Marx of post-capitalist labour.5 I offer here a reading of the passage which, if correct, also absolves it of Cohen's charge, but for reasons different from those urged by Klagge. I then consider briefly some statements by Marx in the 1875 Critique of the Gotlia Programme," which both Cohen and Klagge judge to be incompatible with the 1864 passage in Capital. I propose an interpretation of the Gotha remarks that reconciles the two passages. 1 Karl Marx. Capital, vol. 3 (New York: International Publishers, 1977), 820. 2 G. A. Cohen. "Marx's Dialectic of Labour", Philosophy and Public Affairs 3 (1974), 235-261. The expression occurs at 260. 3 G. A. Cohen, History, Labour and Freedom (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1988), 207. 4 Cohen, "Marx's Dialectic", 260: Cohen. History, Labour and Freedom. 207. 5 James C. Klagge. "Marx's Realms of'Freedom' and "Necessity' ", Canadian Journal of Philosophy 16 (1986). 769-777. 6 David McLellan. ed.. Karl Marx: Selected Writings (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977). 569. Dialogue XXVIII (1989), 545-552 https://doi.org/10.1017/S0012217300012506 Published online by Cambridge University Press 546 Dialogue The practical interest of this controversy lies in its potential influence upon contemporary assessments of the place of work in human communities. If Karl Marx shifted about in appraising the potential of work to constitute a part of what is good in human life, this may seem to justify scepticism toward any suggestion that productive labour could be a more humane and fulfilling activity in a future socialist, or non-socialist, world. My argument, if sound, tends to stem scepticism on that ground. 1. The sentences from volume three of Capital that are in question (hereafter denoted CIII) are these: [T]he realm of freedom actually begins only where labour which is determined by necessity and mundane considerations ceases; thus in the very nature of things it lies beyond the sphere of actual material production. Just as the savage must wrestle with Nature to satisfy his wants, to maintain and reproduce life, so must civilized man, and he must do so in all social formations and under all possible modes of production. With his development this realm of physical necessity expands as a result of his wants; but, at the same time, the forces of production which satisfy these wants also increase. Freedom in this field can only consist in socialized man, the associated producers, rationally regulating their interchange with Nature, bringing it under their common control, instead of being ruled by it as by the blind forces of Nature; and achieving this with the least expenditure of energy and under conditions most favourable to, and worthy of, their human nature. But it nonetheless still remains a realm of necessity. Beyond it begins that development of human energy which is an end in itself, the true realm of freedom, which, however, can blossom forth only with this realm of necessity as its basis. The shortening of the working day is its basic prerequisite.7 I believe that to understand what Marx is affirming here, we need to distinguish between two different kinds of "compulsion" in economic activity; two different senses in which economic activity might be described as freely or M«freely done. Consider the difference between these three propositions: 1. Human beings, because they are material organisms, are compelled by physical necessity to labour, no matter what the form of their social organization. 2. In labouring under capitalism, each labourer is directly subjected, within the enterprise owned by his or her employer, to the dictates of a coercive structure of capitalist production relations, and all labourers are subjected to the unregulated workings of the market and of the capitalist organization of the economy. 3. In labouring under communism, each labourer exercises in direct association with other labourers a rational regulation of their immediate economic activity within some specific work situation, and all labourers exercise together in a society-wide association a rational regulation of the society's overall "interchange with Nature, bringing it under their common control". 7 See note I above. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0012217300012506 Published online by Cambridge University Press Marx 547 The difference between (2) and (3) is the difference between being controlled and being in control. Nevertheless, both (2) and (3) are consistent with (1). To put it differently, both (2) and (3) fall within the realm of necessity. But, to repeat, "the realm of freedom actually begins", according to Marx, "only where labour which is determined by necessity and mundane considerations ceases". Why? As I understand Marx's reasoning in CIII, it can be summarized as follows: 1. That activity alone is truly "an end in itself" which is done solely because of its attractions. No activity is describable as an end in itself if, however attractive it may be in some of its aspects, the activity is one that human beings cannot not choose to engage in. 2. Human beings cannot choose not to labour, even in post-capitalist society. "Civilized man", as much as "the savage", is confronted by the "physical necessity" of engaging in labour. 3. Labour in post-capitalist society will, however, be characterized by freedom, up to a degree. For while human beings in post-capitalist society cannot choose not to labour, but must labour, under the constraint of physical necessity, still, such labour will be free in two senses, (i) The labour will be willingly done by "socialized man", working with others as "associated producers", (ii) The labour will not be a case of human beings being "ruled" by the process which is "their interchange with Nature" (as "by... blind forces"), but will consist, instead, of their "rationally regulating" their production through a self-directed, autonomous exercise of their powers in which they achieve "common control" of their interchange with nature, rather than are controlled by it. 4. Nevertheless, socialist labour, though free in the above senses, remains activity that human beings must perform. It is activity they are compelled, out of necessity, to undertake. In that sense, then, it is not freely undertaken, but is done because necessity exacts it of them. Even in post-capitalist society, the labour of human beings, however much it is now done in a manner and under conditions that are "most favourable to and worthy of [my emphasis] their nature", is still activity they are forced to perform out of "physical necessity". 5. By contrast, the "true realm of freedom", begins with activities which human beings undertake not from necessity but wholly from choice. These activities alone constitute "true" freedom, because there is no compulsion, no necessity, in acting. One acts only for the sake of being active in that way. The activity is an end in itself, whose motivation lies wholly within itself. It is done from free choice, not from necessity. 6. Therefore, a prerequisite of human beings inhabiting (to any significant degree) the true realm of freedom is leisure: extensive respite from https://doi.org/10.1017/S0012217300012506 Published online by Cambridge University Press 548 Dialogue labour. This entails for the overwhelming number of persons (most especially at the time Marx is writing) a shortening of the working day. I submit that this is the correct reading of CM. I shall now try to show that it does not constitute a pessimistic view of human labour. 2. The distinction on which the passage turns is between activity which it is necessary that human beings engage in, and activity which there is no necessity for them to engage in. If "the nature of things" is such that human beings must, of necessity, engage in an activity L, then L lies outside the true realm of freedom. Nevertheless, because, given the nature of things (which includes the kind of things human beings are), it is necessary that human beings engage in L, it does not follow that human beings must be unwilling to engage in L. It is necessary that persons eat and sleep. But most persons willingly, even eagerly, do both. Whether persons will willingly do what it is necessary that they do must depend on the nature of the activity and the conditions under which it is to be done. Marx envisages under communism conditions of labouring such that the activity involves "the least expenditure of energy" necessary to accomplish its object, and is carried out in association with others in a manner that is "most favourable to and worthy of their human nature". Could labour be, in such conditions, congenial to human beings; even if not as congenial as activity in the true realm of freedom? G. A. Cohen, as noted above, claims that in CHI Marx conceives of labour "as bound always to be unsatisfying". Cohen even goes so far as to assert that Marx's view of such labour is that "it cannot be wanted".8 But to claim that a kind of activity is bound always to be necessary is not to claim that it is bound always to be unsatisfying. (This holds even if one regards other kinds of activity as bound always to be more satisfying.) Nor does the claim that a kind of activity is bound always to be necessary entail the claim that it cannot be wanted. (Cohen himself interpolates in the HLF version of his essay the observation: "Some eating is enjoyable."9) True, Marx holds that human beings cannot be related to such activity as to what is "an end in itself", on Marx's construction of that phrase. But the activity may still be wanted, and be satisfying. Cohen at one point asserts: "Granted, [A] there will always be a set of operations on whose completion the provisioning of the race depends. But it does not follow, and it is not equally undeniable, that [B] there will 8 Cohen, "Marx's Dialectic", 261; Cohen, History, Labour and Freedom, 207. 9 Cohen, History, Labour and Freedom, 208. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0012217300012506 Published online by Cambridge University Press Marx 549 always be tasks which men perform against their inclinations because they have to." 10 I do not see why must we accept that Marx's asserting (A) involves him in asserting (B). From (A) all that follows is that, on Marx's stipulated sense of "true" freedom, these operations cannot be said to be an exercise of true freedom. Cohen also asserts: "That a task must be and is fulfilled does not imply that the motive for its performance is that its performance is necessary. But Marx accepts this implication when he says that the realm of freedom, first glossed as activity not determined by mundane requirements, must "in the very nature of things' lie beyond the sphere servicing those requirements."11 I do not see that Marx does accept the implication. Nothing in CHI rules out some part of the motivation for engaging in labour being that it is affirming of one's sense of community with the other members of society, that it is satisfying of one's need for social intercourse and fellowship, that it is (in some of its tasks) challenging and exercising of sophisticated human powers, that it gives some scope for selfexpression, and so on. All CHI asserts is that whatever else is true of human labour, it is always physically and socially necessary activity. It always lies, therefore, outside the true realm of freedom. Marx's relegation of labour to the realm of necessity does not entail either that it must always be unsatisfying or that human beings cannot want it. It entails only that (to repeat) labour cannot be truly described as freely done. True, Marx also judged that communist labour could not, as a consequence, be as satisfying or as desirable as activity that lies in the realm of freedom. But this does not commit him to regarding it as bound always to be unsatisfying, or incapable of being wanted. It does not, then, justify Cohen's charge. 3. James Klagge's reading of CHI also finds Marx undeserving of Cohen's charge. But while Klagge rightly stresses that CHI allows labour under communism to be "unalienated",12 he gives too little attention to the opposition between freedom and constraint in the passage. According to Klagge, the reason why Marx calls for the realm of necessity to be minimized as much as possible is because Marx is "here being influenced by some perfectionistic value"; possibly the conviction that "" activities that are ends in themselves, which mainly consist of activities that are constitutive of all-round development of the individual, are 10 Cohen. "Marx's Dialectic", 261; Cohen, History, Labour and Freedom, 208. 11 Cohen. "Marx's Dialectic", 261; Cohen, History, Labour and Freedom, 208. 12 Klagge, "Marx's Realms", 771. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0012217300012506 Published online by Cambridge University Press 550 Dialogue more suited that necessary productive activity for the development of human potential".13 Now there is evidence that Marx did hold that some activities which are ends in themselves are more suited to develop human potential than labouring activity. But this does not amount to holding that activities that are ends in themselves mainly consist of such potential-developing activity. In any case, Marx does not, in CIII, define activities that are ends in themselves in terms of their suitability to developing human potential. He defines them in terms of their being inescapable or optional. The assumption activating the passage is that human beings are potentially autonomous, se//-choosing creatures, for whom labour (however satisfying or developing of human powers it may possibly be), "still remains a realm of necessity", and is, therefore, strictly speaking, unfree activity. It is, consequently, less appropriate to human beings than "that development of human energy which is an end in itself" (my emphasis). Note that it is the realm of freedom that Marx refers to in the passage as "blossom[ing] forth"; not the richness of actualized potential. The emphasis throughout is on the opposition between being constrained and being unconstrained: between enjoying complete freedom of choice of activity, and being hedged by necessity. Cohen and Klagge, while disagreeing about CIII, do agree in seeing an incompatibility between CIII and the following remarks by Marx a decade or so later: In a higher phase of communist society, after the enslaving subordination of the individual to the division of labour, and therewith also the antithesis between mental and physical labour has vanished; after labour has become not only a means of life but life's prime want: after the productive forces have also increased with the all-round development of the individual, and all the springs of co-operative wealth flow more abundantly—only then can the narrow horizon of bourgeois right be crossed in its entirety and society inscribe on its banners: from each according to his ability, to each according to his need!14 "If we take this passage seriously", Klagge asserts, "it must be said that Marx changed his view of labour ... between 1864 and 1875", though to "a more optimistic view of labour", in contrast to the pessimistic change frequently alleged to have occurred between 1844 and 1864. Klagge's reasoning is that in the Gotha passage, "Marx holds that materially necessary labour may be not only a means to life, but iife"s prime want' ... an end in itself, and not only an end in itself, but the central or highest end in itself'.15 Cohen, similarly, opposes the description of labour as life's prime want to the CIII denial that labour can be an end in itself.16 In what follows I propose, somewhat diffidently a reading of the Gotha passage that reconciles it with CIII. But I wish to stress that here 13 14 15 16 Ibid., 774. See note 6 above. Klagge, "Marx's Realms", 776. Cohen, "Marx's Dialectic", 260-261; Cohen, History, Labour ami Freedom. 207-208. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0012217300012506 Published online by Cambridge University Press Marx 551 my thesis is tentatively put forward as a not implausible reading of Marx's words. I am conscious that others may think it a strained construction of the passage.17 When Marx asserts that in "a higher phase of communist society" labour becomes "life's prime want", he may mean, I suggest, simply that labour becomes each person's first and foremost want. It becomes so for two reasons. First, labour under communism, being free in senses 3(i) and 3(ii) above, can admit, in some instances at least, of challenging and satisfying activity. But secondly, the members of such a society are fully "species beings", who want the good life not only for themselves but for one another. They therefore want to labour before they do anything else, because by labouring each contributes to producing what is necessary for all members of the society to be alive in a way that fulfills their human nature. There are no "free-riders" in the society imagined by Marx, as evidenced by the fact that each contributes according to his or her ability, but receives (and accepts) reward only according to his or her need. For these persons, whose powers, sensibility, and purposes have developed within this "higher phase" of social life, labour is the "prime want" of each, just in being the first and foremost want of each. Now, as we have seen, labour being life's prime want may partly consist in its being wanted because it is one more opportunity for unalienated activity "worthy" of "human nature". In a passage from the Grundrisse which Klagge quotes in his paper, Marx speaks of the obstacles to its achievement that have to be overcome by labour. But ... the overcoming of such obstacles may itself constitute an exercise in liberty, and ... these external purposes lose their character of mere natural necessities and are established as purposes which the individual himself fixes. The result is the self-realization and objectification of the subject, therefore real freedom, whose activity is precisely labour.18 But that this degree of freedom is now present in labouring still does not make one's labouring an end in itself, as Marx defines these words in CIII. One now finds in labouring things that are fulfilling of one's nature. Yet that does not make labouring an end in itself. Nor does it make it the case that one's motivation in labouring must be to engage in this activity solely for its own sake. Other activities may be recognized and experienced as more fulfilling of one's nature. The same holds for the second feature entering into labour being "life's prime want": its being wanted because it contributes to the fully human existence of all members of the society. That labour is wanted for either of these reasons does not make it an end in itself, on the CIII definition. Neither must it make labour an end in itself on a more ordinary, motivational construction of these words. This is because what is a prime want is not necessarily an ultimate end. 17 James Klagge and William H. Shaw both found it to be so in reacting briefly to a shorter version of this essay. 18 McLellan, ed.. Karl Marx: Selected Writings, 368. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0012217300012506 Published online by Cambridge University Press 552 Dialogue I suggest that in the society envisaged by Marx, what is especially wanted as an end in itself is the fully human existence of each and all. Labour, therefore, is the prime want of these persons—their first and foremost want—because each sees labouring as not only the means by which his or her own life is continued ("a means of life"), but as the necessary means of continuing in existence a valued kind of human community benefitting all. What I want first and foremost to do I may not do for its own sake. Nevertheless, it is my first and foremost want. Among human beings in the highest phase of communism, as Marx envisages them, continued reproduction of the economic conditions under which all are able to enjoy a fully human existence claims each as having a value so high that to contribute to that reproduction is the prime (but by no means the only) want of each. That is an intelligible priority, and one consistent with CHI. (Or so it seems to me.) 4. I conclude with a substantive, as distinct from exegetical, question. If I am right, Marx, in CHI, conceives of the true realm of freedom as that in which there is no compulsion or necessity in acting. He regards genuine freedom as cancelled by natural necessity. This is not (in my view) a very helpful way to characterize freedom, because it focusses attention too much upon human relations to nature and too little upon intra-human relations. Yet it is the position expressed by Marx in CIII (though not, or not very often, elsewhere). At the same time, one of the views for which Marx is most famous is his insistence that a human being has a natural need to be active in ways that are appropriate to his or her human nature. Failure to be so active will be experienced as loss (when such activity has been experienced but is now denied), and/or as lack of fulfillment (both when such activity has been experienced, and even when it has not been experienced or is not even recognized to be possible). Furthermore, it seems clear that the activities that Marx regards as most especially appropriate to human nature are those which CHI assigns to the true realm of freedom. On such a view, then, "the nature of things" is such that it is necessary that human beings engage in activities that are in the true realm of freedom. That is, to live a fully human life it is necessary to be active within the true realm of freedom. At the same time, it was (on at least one occasion) Marx's view that what it is necessary that human beings do lies outside the true realm of freedom. Does this introduce into "the true realm of freedom" a kind of necessity that makes it less distinct from "the realm of necessity" than Marx in CHI allows? https://doi.org/10.1017/S0012217300012506 Published online by Cambridge University Press