Uploaded by Preeti Phuskele

gilboa microecon theory i(3)

advertisement
Microeconomics
1
Is Economics a Science?
2
Issues
• Economics doesn’t predict well
• All its assumptions are wrong
• It isn’t even done in good faith
3
Economics doesn’t predict
Three replies:
• No one predicts
• Economics actually does (sometimes)
• Who needs to predict?
4
No one predicts
• Large, complex systems are hard to predict
• Chaos theory – even something as simple as
π‘₯𝑑+1 = 𝑓 π‘₯𝑑
with
𝑓 π‘₯ = 1 − 4 π‘₯ − 0.5
2
5
Chaos
𝑓 π‘₯ = 1 − 4 π‘₯ − 0.5
2
0
0.01
0.02
0.03
0.04
0.05
1
0.0396
0.0784
0.1164
0.1536
0.19
2
0.152127 0.289014 0.411404 0.520028
0.6156
3
0.515939 0.821939 0.968603 0.998395 0.946547
5
0.00406 0.970813 0.427388 0.025467
0.6457
10
0.795154 0.503924 0.524371 0.836557 0.999652
15
0.393686 0.015682 0.494768 0.466403 0.316366
20
0.079928 0.590364 0.027768 0.774441 0.069137
6
Chaos
• If a single variable with such a simple equation can
generate chaos…
• Just imagine what happens with the weather (the
butterfly effect)
• Or the entire global economy
• Or the geopolitical system
7
Two additional complications
In the social sciences:
• We don’t even have the basic rules
(no equivalents of flow equations in physics)
• We’re dealing with self-reflective systems
(a hurricane doesn’t change its mind if predicted correctly)
8
Economics actually does predict
• Sometimes it doesn’t do too badly
• Nice quantitative results on
•
•
•
Supply-and-demand in a single good market
Auctions
Matchings
• Many qualitative insights
9
It is easier to predict when
• The system is “small” and isolated
• There are many “repetitions” –
• similar examples that are causally independent
• Experiments are possible
• … Maybe we should learn when to expect a theory to
predict
10
Who needs to predict?
• Economics would surely like to be a predictive science
• But it can be useful even if it isn’t
• For instance, even if it can only critique reasoning
• Compare with history
11
All assumptions are wrong
• Well, yes
• But think of
• Robustness of findings?
• Relevance to economic decisions?
12
The Ultimatum Game
There is a sum of $100 to share between Players I and II
Player I offers a way to divide the sum (say, integer values)
Player II can say Yes or No
Yes – they get the amounts offered
No – they both get nothing
What will happen?
What does the theory say?
13
The Ultimatum Game
Bernd Schwarze (b. 1944)
Werner Güth (b. 1944)
Güth, Schmittberger, Schwarze (1982)
14
Reference
An Experimental Analysis of Ultimatum Bargaining
Werner Güth, Rolf Schmittberger, Bernd Schwarze
Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, Vol. 3, No. 4 (Dec., 1982), pp.
367-388
Abstract
There are many experimental studies of bargaining behavior, but suprisingly enough
nearly no attempt has been made to investigate the so-called ultimatum bargaining
behavior experimentally. The special property of ultimatum bargaining games is that on
every stage of the bargaining process only one player has to decide and that before the
last stage the set of outcomes is already restricted to only two results. To make the
ultimatum aspect obvious we concentrated on situations with two players and two stages.
In the ‘easy games’ a given amount c has to be distributed among the two players,
whereas in the ‘complicated games’ the players have to allocate a bundle of black and
white chips with different values for both players. We performed two main experiments for
easy games as well as for complicated games. By a special experiment it was
investigated how the demands of subjects as player 1 are related to their acceptance
decisions as player 2.
15
What does the theory say?
100
𝑦𝑒𝑠
100,0
π‘›π‘œ
0,0
𝑦𝑒𝑠
99,1
99
π‘›π‘œ
…
50
…
20
…
𝑦𝑒𝑠
…
0,0
80
50,50
…
π‘›π‘œ
0,0
0
…
…
…
16
Well,
We are tempted to predict:
100
𝑦𝑒𝑠
100,0
π‘›π‘œ
0,0
𝑦𝑒𝑠
99,1
99
π‘›π‘œ
…
80
…
20
…
𝑦𝑒𝑠
…
0,0
50
50,50
…
π‘›π‘œ
0,0
0
…
…
…
The “Backward Induction” solution
17
Backward Induction
In a finite game of perfect
information we can go down to
the leaves and work our way
backwards to find the players’
choices
Ernest Zermelo (1871-1953)
18
Backward Induction assumptions
• Rationality
• Common knowledge (or common belief) in rationality
• To be precise, as many levels of belief as there are
steps in the game
19
So in this case
The backward induction seems to be
100
𝑦𝑒𝑠
100,0
π‘›π‘œ
0,0
𝑦𝑒𝑠
99,1
99
π‘›π‘œ
…
50
…
20
…
𝑦𝑒𝑠
…
0,0
80
50,50
…
π‘›π‘œ
0,0
0
…
…
…
– But this assumes that the monetary sums are the “utilities”
20
Important
• In a game as simple as the Ultimatum Game, it is
impossible to test basic decision/game theoretic
assumptions (such as transitivity)
• We can only test them coupled with the assumption that
only material payoffs matter
21
Emotional payoffs
• Player II might be angry/insulted at a low offer
• Player II as well as Player I might care for fairness
• Player I might be altruistic
• etc.
• A way to tell some explanations apart: the Dictator
Game
22
Is it rational to respond to emotions?
In “Descartes’ Error” (1994) argued that it
is wrong to think of emotions and
Antonio Damasio (b. 1944)
rationality as divorced; rather, rationality
relies on emotions
23
Back to the Ultimatum Game
• Having said all that, emotional payoffs should not be
overstated
• In the Ultimatum Game, if the payoffs were in millions of
dollars rather than dollars, acceptance of low offers
would likely to be higher
• As well as when Player II has to wait before responding
24
The Ultimatum Game with delay
Let Me Sleep on It: Delay Reduces Rejection Rates in Ultimatum
Games
Veronika Grimm, Friederike Mengel
Economics Letters, Vol. 111, No. 2 (2011) pp. 113-115
Abstract
Delaying acceptance decisions in the Ultimatum Game drastically increases
acceptance of low offers. While in treatments without delay less than 20% of
low offers are accepted, 60-80% are accepted as we delay the acceptance
decision by around 10. min.
25
Not even in good faith
• Can science be objective?
• Aren’t we always affected by personal history, social class, our
incentives?
• If so, can we trust the “truths” that economists pretend to have
“established”?
• Should we check how many economists who believe in the free
market also benefit from it (serve on boards of directors etc.) ???
26
Can science be objective?
Path-breaking studies on the history
of madness, sexuality
Michel Foucault (1926-1984)
27
Shouldn’t we be suspicious?
• Well, yes
• But – we can try to be (more) objective
• Objectivity is a direction, not a place
• Let’s remind ourselves of the distinction between Positive
and Normative social science
• And then ask the question about Postmodernism
28
Positive vs. Normative
• Positive (~ descriptive)
IS
• Normative (~ prescriptive)
OUGHT
• Normative physics is called SciFi
• But in the social sciences it makes sense
29
How do we judge theories
• Positive
– How close to reality it is
• Normative
– ???
• The king in “The Little Prince”
30
The Little Prince
"It is contrary to etiquette to yawn in the presence of a king," the monarch
said to him. "I forbid you to do so."
"I can't help it. I can't stop myself," replied the little prince, thoroughly
embarrassed. "I have come on a long journey, and I have had no sleep ..."
"Ah, then," the king said. "I order you to yawn. It is years since I have seen
anyone yawning. Yawns, to me, are objects of curiosity. Come, now! Yawn
again! It is an order."
"That frightens me ... I cannot, any more ..." murmured the little prince,
now completely abashed. "Hum! Hum!" replied the king. "Then I—I order
you sometimes to yawn and sometimes to—" He sputtered a little, and seemed
vexed.
For what the king fundamentally insisted upon was that his authority
should be respected. He tolerated no disobedience. He was an absolute
monarch. But, because he was a very good man, he made his orders
reasonable.
"If I ordered a general," he would say, by way of example, "if I ordered a
general to change himself into a sea bird, and if the general did not obey me,
that would not be the fault of the general. It would be my fault."
Antoine de SaintExupery (1900-1944)
31
So what is a good normative theory?
• I suggest: one that captures the kind of people/society we
want to be
• Normative as second-order positive
• What type of a decision maker do I want to be?
• What kind of a society/economy do I want to live in?
32
Be that as it may
• Let’s not mix up positive and normative
• There may never be eternal peace (positive)
But this doesn’t mean we should start shooting each other
(normative)
• Our theories may never be perfectly objective (positive)
But this doesn’t mean we shouldn’t try (normative)
33
Utility Maximization
34
Who maximizes utility ?
Or rather, who behaves as if they did?
Logical positivism and the emphasis on observables
The revealed preferences paradigm
35
What’s observable ?
Choices: between pairs or out of sets?
Deterministic or stochastic?
If sets – all sets? Only budget sets?
These are all questions of modeling…
36
Binary relations
𝑋 − a set of alternatives
𝑅 ⊂ 𝑋 × π‘‹ – a binary relation
𝑅 is
reflexive if
π‘₯𝑅π‘₯ for all π‘₯
symmetric if 𝑦𝑅π‘₯ whenever π‘₯𝑅𝑦
transitive if
π‘₯𝑅𝑧 whenever [π‘₯𝑅𝑦 π‘Žπ‘›π‘‘ 𝑦𝑅𝑧]
complete if
π‘₯𝑅𝑦 π‘œπ‘Ÿ 𝑦𝑅π‘₯ (or both) for all π‘₯, 𝑦
37
Equivalence relations
𝑅 is a equivalence relation if it is reflexive, symmetric and transitive
For example: equality =
is
reflexive if
π‘₯ = π‘₯ for all π‘₯
symmetric if 𝑦 = π‘₯ whenever π‘₯ = 𝑦
transitive if
π‘₯ = 𝑧 whenever [π‘₯ = 𝑦 π‘Žπ‘›π‘‘ 𝑦 = 𝑧]
38
Equivalence relations – examples
𝑅 is a equivalence relation if it is reflexive, symmetric and transitive
For example:
π‘₯𝑅𝑦 iff π‘₯ and 𝑦 have the same (first) last name
π‘₯𝑅𝑦 iff π‘₯ and 𝑦 have the same height
π‘₯𝑅𝑦 iff π‘₯ and 𝑦 have the remainder after division by 3
39
Equivalence relations – examples
More generally, define π‘₯𝑅𝑦 iff 𝑓 π‘₯ = 𝑓 𝑦 for some function 𝑓: 𝑋 → 𝑍
Then 𝑅 is
reflexive if
𝑓 π‘₯ = 𝑓 π‘₯ for all π‘₯
symmetric if
𝑓 𝑦 = 𝑓 π‘₯ whenever 𝑓 π‘₯ = 𝑓 𝑦
transitive if
𝑓 π‘₯ = 𝑓 𝑧 whenever [𝑓 π‘₯ = 𝑓 𝑦 π‘Žπ‘›π‘‘ 𝑓 𝑦 = 𝑓 𝑧 ]
Are there others?
40
Equivalence classes
An equivalence relation 𝑅 divides the set 𝑋 into equivalence classes:
There is a partition of 𝑋, 𝐴𝑖 (finite or infinite) such that
π‘₯𝑅𝑦 iff both π‘₯, 𝑦 belong to the same 𝐴𝑖
This also means that 𝑅 is an equivalence relation iff there is some (set 𝑍 and some)
function 𝑓: 𝑋 → 𝑍 such that
π‘₯𝑅𝑦 iff 𝑓 π‘₯ = 𝑓 𝑦
41
Preference relations
≽ is a preference relation if it is complete and transitive
A fact: a complete relation is reflexive
42
Preference relations – weak and strict
For a relation ≽ define ≻ and ~ by
π‘₯ ≻ 𝑦 𝑖𝑓 π‘₯ ≽ 𝑦 𝑏𝑒𝑑 π‘›π‘œπ‘‘ 𝑦 ≽ π‘₯
π‘₯ ~ 𝑦 𝑖𝑓 π‘₯ ≽ 𝑦 π‘Žπ‘›π‘‘ 𝑦 ≽ π‘₯
(Define also β‰Ό and β‰Ί )
Facts:
If ≽ is transitive, then so is ~
If ≽ is transitive, then so is ≻
43
If ≽ is transitive, then so is ~
Recall that
π‘₯ ~ 𝑦 𝑖𝑓 π‘₯ ≽ 𝑦 π‘Žπ‘›π‘‘ 𝑦 ≽ π‘₯
If we have
π‘₯ ~ 𝑦 and 𝑦 ~ 𝑧
then
π‘₯ ≽ 𝑦 π‘Žπ‘›π‘‘ 𝑦 ≽ π‘₯
π‘₯≽𝑧
𝑦 ≽ 𝑧 π‘Žπ‘›π‘‘ 𝑧 ≽ 𝑦
π‘Žπ‘›π‘‘
𝑧≽π‘₯
So that we have
π‘₯~𝑧
44
If ≽ is transitive, then so is ≻
π‘₯ ≻ 𝑦 𝑖𝑓 π‘₯ ≽ 𝑦 𝑏𝑒𝑑 π‘›π‘œπ‘‘ 𝑦 ≽ π‘₯
Recall that
We need to show that
π‘₯ ≻ 𝑦 and 𝑦 ≻ 𝑧
Implies
π‘₯≻𝑧
Or: IF
π‘₯ ≽ 𝑦 𝑏𝑒𝑑 π‘›π‘œπ‘‘ 𝑦 ≽ π‘₯
and
𝑦 ≽ 𝑧 𝑏𝑒𝑑 π‘›π‘œπ‘‘ 𝑧 ≽ 𝑦
THEN
π‘₯ ≽ 𝑧 𝑏𝑒𝑑 π‘›π‘œπ‘‘ 𝑧 ≽ π‘₯
45
π‘₯≽𝑧
We have
π‘₯ ≻ 𝑦 and 𝑦 ≻ 𝑧
that is,
π‘₯ ≽ 𝑦 𝑏𝑒𝑑 π‘›π‘œπ‘‘ 𝑦 ≽ π‘₯
and
𝑦 ≽ 𝑧 𝑏𝑒𝑑 π‘›π‘œπ‘‘ 𝑧 ≽ 𝑦
then, by transitivity (of ≽)
π‘₯≽𝑧
46
π‘›π‘œπ‘‘ 𝑧 ≽ π‘₯
We have
π‘₯ ≻ 𝑦 and 𝑦 ≻ 𝑧
that is,
π‘₯ ≽ 𝑦 𝑏𝑒𝑑 π‘›π‘œπ‘‘ 𝑦 ≽ π‘₯
and
𝑦 ≽ 𝑧 𝑏𝑒𝑑 π‘›π‘œπ‘‘ 𝑧 ≽ 𝑦
Could it be that 𝑧 ≽ π‘₯ also holds?
No, because then we would have
𝑧≽𝑦
47
Utility representation
For a relation ≽ on a set 𝑋 and a function 𝑒: 𝑋 → −∞, ∞ we say that 𝑒
represents ≽ if, for all π‘₯, 𝑦,
π‘₯ ≽ 𝑦 𝑖𝑓𝑓 𝑒(π‘₯) ≥ 𝑒(𝑦)
48
Different notions of representation
For a relation ≽ on a set 𝑋 and a function 𝑒: 𝑋 → −∞, ∞
(i) for all π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘₯ ≽ 𝑦 𝑖𝑓𝑓 𝑒(π‘₯) ≥ 𝑒(𝑦)
(ii) for all π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘₯ ≻ 𝑦 𝑖𝑓𝑓 𝑒 π‘₯ > 𝑒(𝑦)
(iii) for all π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘₯ ~ 𝑦 𝑖𝑓𝑓 𝑒 π‘₯ = 𝑒(𝑦)
Fact: If ≽ is complete, (i) and (ii) are equivalent, and each implies (iii)
(but not the other way around)
49
Equivalence of (i) and (ii)
(i) For all π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘₯ ≽ 𝑦 ⟺ 𝑒(π‘₯) ≥ 𝑒(𝑦)
(ii) For all π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘₯ ≻ 𝑦 ⟺ 𝑒 π‘₯ > 𝑒(𝑦)
Given completeness, this is just using the contrapositive:
to say that
is equivalent to saying that
𝑝⇒π‘ž
¬π‘ž ⇒ ¬π‘
50
Contrapositives
The (“material”) implication
is equivalent to
𝑝⇒π‘ž
¬π‘ž ⇒ ¬π‘
In fact, the material implication 𝑝 ⇒ π‘ž is defined as ¬π‘β‹π‘ž
And the truth value of ¬π‘β‹π‘ž is
Value of
¬π‘β‹π‘ž
π‘ž
¬π‘ž
𝑝
∨
–
¬π‘
∨
∨
– the same as the truth value of ¬π‘ž ⇒ ¬π‘ which is (again) defined as
¬(¬π‘ž)⋁(¬π‘) = ¬π‘β‹π‘ž
51
Back to the equivalence of (i) and (ii)
(i) For all π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘₯ ≽ 𝑦 ⟺ 𝑒(π‘₯) ≥ 𝑒(𝑦)
(ii) For all π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘₯ ≻ 𝑦 ⟺ 𝑒 π‘₯ > 𝑒(𝑦)
Given completeness:
π‘₯ ≽ 𝑦 ⇒ 𝑒(π‘₯) ≥ 𝑒(𝑦) iff
𝑒 𝑦 > 𝑒(π‘₯) ⇒ 𝑦 ≻ π‘₯
𝑒(π‘₯) ≥ 𝑒(𝑦) ⇒ π‘₯ ≽ 𝑦 iff
𝑦 ≻ π‘₯ ⇒ 𝑒 𝑦 > 𝑒(π‘₯)
Hence (i) is equivalent to
For all π‘₯, 𝑦
𝑦 ≻ π‘₯ ⟺ 𝑒 𝑦 > 𝑒(π‘₯)
– which is (ii) with π‘₯, 𝑦 reversed
52
And (i) [hence (ii)] implies (iii)
(i) For all π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘₯ ≽ 𝑦 ⟺ 𝑒(π‘₯) ≥ 𝑒(𝑦)
(iii) For all π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘₯ ~ 𝑦 ⟺ 𝑒 π‘₯ = 𝑒(𝑦)
Because
π‘₯~𝑦 ⟺
π‘₯≽𝑦
⟺
𝑒(π‘₯) ≥ 𝑒(𝑦)
𝑦≽π‘₯
⟺
𝑒(𝑦) ≥ 𝑒(π‘₯)
⟺ 𝑒 π‘₯ = 𝑒(𝑦)
π‘₯~𝑦
53
Why doesn’t (iii) imply (i) ?
(i) For all π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘₯ ≽ 𝑦 ⟺ 𝑒(π‘₯) ≥ 𝑒(𝑦)
(iii) For all π‘₯, 𝑦
π‘₯ ~ 𝑦 ⟺ 𝑒 π‘₯ = 𝑒(𝑦)
Because representing indifference doesn’t guarantee that preference is
also “faithfully” represented
For a given ≽ and 𝑒 that represents it, consider 𝑣 π‘₯ = −𝑒(π‘₯)
54
Conditions for utility representation
For a relation ≽ on a finite set 𝑋,
≽ is complete and transitive
IFF
There exists a function 𝑒: 𝑋 → −∞, ∞ that represents ≽
55
Interpretation I: meta-scientific
For a relation ≽ on a finite set 𝑋
≽ is complete and transitive
IFF
There exists 𝑒: 𝑋 → −∞, ∞ that represents ≽
• What is “utility” ?
• The term derives its meaning from its usage (Ask not, “What?”, Ask, “How?”)
• We’ll explain what it means to maximize utility in terms of observables
56
Logical Positivism
• What is [good] “science”?
• Theoretical terms should be defined by
observations
• Culminated in the “Received View”
(Carnap, 1923)
Rudolf Carnap (1891-1970)
57
Logical Positivism +
Popper (1934)
• A theory is meaningful only if it is refutable
• It can never be verified, only refuted, or not-yetrefuted
• Famous targets of critic: Marx’s historicism,
Freud’s psychoanalysis
Karl Popper (1902-1994)
• (Evolution? Game theory?)
58
Logical Positivism and economics
• Popper (1934) criticizes psychology
• Samuelson (1938) pioneers “revealed
preference theory”
• Room for speculation…
Paul Samuelson (1915-2009)
59
Economics and psychology
Loewenstein (1988) suggested that,
maybe, in the 1930s, economics didn’t
think that psychology was such great
company
George Loewenstein (b. 1955)
60
Was it really Logical Positivism?
Moscati is a serious historian who argues
that I’m selling you fake history
But the story is too good to kill
Ivan Moscati (b. 1955)
61
Utility and marginal utility
Adam Smith (as Plato) thought that there is no
relationship between value and price
Cf. water and diamonds
Adam Smith (1723-1790)
The Marginalist Revolution
William Stanley Jevons 1835-1882
Carl Menger 1840-1921
Léon Walras 1834-1910
Alfred Marshall 1842-1924
Be that as it may
A theorem such as:
For a relation ≽ on a finite set 𝑋
≽ is complete and transitive
IFF
There exists 𝑒: 𝑋 → −∞, ∞ that represents ≽
endows “utility” with meaning
64
Interpretation II: normative
Suppose you ask me how to make a decision
And I ask you, would you like your ≽ to be complete ?
• Many would say yes
• Incompleteness is absence of decision (Kafka and his wedding engagements…)
And then: would you like your ≽ to be transitive ?
• Again, many would say yes
• An intransitive relation, let’s say a cyclical one (that’s more than just intransitive!)
isn’t very useful
65
The normative interpretation – cont.
And then I point out to you that
For a relation ≽ on a finite set 𝑋
≽ is complete and transitive
IFF
There exists 𝑒: 𝑋 → −∞, ∞ that represents ≽
And I can convince you that you would like to behave as if you were
maximizing a utility function, or maybe just maximize one (consciously)
66
Interpretation III: descriptive
Suppose I tell you that, when I analyze an economic problem, I assume
that agents are utility maximizing.
• Does it make sense?
• Do you know many such agents?
• What gives me the right to make predictions and give advice based on
such a preposterous assumption?
67
The descriptive interpretation – cont.
And then I point out to you that
For a relation ≽ on a finite set 𝑋
≽ is complete and transitive
IFF
There exists 𝑒: 𝑋 → −∞, ∞ that represents ≽
… and I may convince you that more agents might be described by my
analysis than you would have imagined
68
Comments
• Why do I need to convince you that this is how people behave?
• Why not just test?
• Indeed, if we test, it doesn’t matter which formulation we use
• The whole point is that they’re equivalent
• In fact, a characterization theorem is a sort of a framing effect
• If economics were a successful science, it would not need
axiomatizations
• But it isn’t so successful. So it leaves room for rhetoric.
69
Compare with Social Choice
For a relation ≽ on a finite set 𝑋
≽ is complete and transitive
IFF
There exists 𝑒: 𝑋 → −∞, ∞ that represents ≽
• Pareto domination: transitive but not complete
• Majority vote: complete but not transitive
70
Pareto Domination
• Basically, unanimity
(At least one has strict preference, the others – weak [or strict] )
• Transitivity seems obvious
(A bit involved because of this “at least one strict” issue)
• But completeness is utopian
71
Majority vote
Condorcet showed that even if all
individuals have complete and transitive
preferences, the majority vote of them
as a society might not be transitive
Marie Jean Antoine Nicolas de
Caritat, Marquis of Condorcet (1743-1794)
72
Condorcet’s Paradox
Individuals 1,2,3 ; alternatives π‘₯, 𝑦, 𝑧
Preferences are given by:
1
2
3
π‘₯
𝑦
𝑧
𝑦
𝑧
π‘₯
𝑧
π‘₯
𝑦
73
Condorcet’s Paradox – cont.
Majority vote:
π‘₯
2,3
1,3
1
2
3
π‘₯
𝑦
𝑧
𝑦
𝑧
π‘₯
𝑧
π‘₯
𝑦
𝑦
𝑧
1,2
74
The social choice perspective
Shows that it isn’t trivial to assume that a relation ≽ is complete and
transitive
Pareto domination
Majority vote
complete
transitive
−
+
+
−
75
Indeed, it can happen in one’s mind
• If we have different criteria for decision making, and we’re trying to
aggregate them
• Each can be thought of as an “individual”
• Looking for unanimity we may not get completeness
• Using majority – we may lose transitivity
• The representation result suggests we should aggregate by a numerical
trade-off
76
Is the utility unique?
…There exists and a function 𝑒: 𝑋 → −∞, ∞ that represents ≽
Can we say that we found the utility of the consumer?
Well, all we asked is
π‘₯ ≽ 𝑦 𝑖𝑓𝑓 𝑒(π‘₯) ≥ 𝑒(𝑦)
So 𝑣 π‘₯ = 10𝑒 π‘₯ could also work
77
How unique is the utility?
OK,
𝑣 π‘₯ = 10𝑒 π‘₯
is just a change of the unit of measurement – we’re used to that
And
𝑣 ′ π‘₯ = 10𝑒 π‘₯ + 15
Also involves “shifting” the zero; as in temperature
78
Cardinal utility
If the data allow for any transformation
𝑣 π‘₯ = π‘Žπ‘’ π‘₯ + 𝑏
where π‘Ž > 0 , but only those, we say that 𝑒 is cardinal
As in
9
𝐹 π‘₯ = 𝐢 π‘₯ + 32
5
𝐢 π‘₯ =
5
160
𝐹 π‘₯ −
9
9
79
But
For
π‘₯ ≽ 𝑦 𝑖𝑓𝑓 𝑒(π‘₯) ≥ 𝑒(𝑦)
to hold we can also use
𝑣 π‘₯ = 𝑒 π‘₯
3
𝑣 π‘₯ = π‘™π‘œπ‘” 𝑒 π‘₯
if 𝑒 π‘₯ > 0
And many others. The function 𝑒 π‘₯ is only ordinal.
80
Conditions for utility representation –
beyond finite
For a relation ≽ on a countable set 𝑋,
≽ is complete and transitive
IFF
There exists and a function 𝑒: 𝑋 → −∞, ∞ that represents ≽
81
Conditions for utility representation –
beyond countable
But: let π‘Ž, 𝑏 ≽ (π‘Ž′ , 𝑏 ′ ) iff
π‘Ž > π‘Ž′
or
[ π‘Ž = π‘Ž′ and 𝑏 ≥ 𝑏′ ]
It is complete and transitive
82
Lexicographic preferences
Complete?
(π‘Ž′ , 𝑏′ )
Transitive?
… but has no representation by any real-
(π‘Ž, 𝑏)
valued function
83
Why is there no representation?
If there were, we would need to have an entire
(positive length) interval of utility values
between
(π‘Ž′ , 1)
𝑒 π‘Ž, 0
π‘Žπ‘›π‘‘ 𝑒 π‘Ž′ , 1
For any
π‘Ž′ > π‘Ž
(π‘Ž, 0)
Which is a bit too much for the real line (as the
𝑒 range) to carry
84
Continuity
The relation ≽ is continuous iff π‘₯𝑛 → π‘₯ implies that
π‘₯ ≽ 𝑦 whenever (π‘₯𝑛 ≽ 𝑦 for all 𝑛)
and
π‘₯ β‰Ό 𝑦 whenever (π‘₯𝑛 β‰Ό 𝑦 for all 𝑛)
85
Continuity is very reasonable
If π‘₯𝑛 → π‘₯ then
π‘₯ ≽ 𝑦 whenever (π‘₯𝑛 ≽ 𝑦 for all 𝑛)
and
π‘₯ β‰Ό 𝑦 whenever (π‘₯𝑛 β‰Ό 𝑦 for all 𝑛)
Almost everything we can think of, in terms of physical and physiological
mechanisms, is continuous
An exception: a vegetarian’s preferences for the amount of meat
More generally, meaning may behave discontinuously
86
Lexicographic preferences
aren’t continuous
For any such π‘Ž,
π‘₯𝑛 ≽ 𝑦 for all 𝑛
But
𝑦 = (π‘Ž, 1)
π‘₯≽𝑦
does not hold – we have
π‘₯ = (π‘Ž, 0)
1
π‘₯𝑛 = (π‘Ž + , 0)
𝑛
𝑦≻π‘₯
87
Is continuity reasonable, then?
• I would argue that the lexicographic preferences don’t typically appear in
reality – apart from the case of endowing quantities with meaning
• They do appear in speeches (“we will never risk human lives, but, given that, we will…”)
• This may say more about the speeches than about real preferences
• Anyway…
88
Continuous utility representation
For a relation ≽ on π‘…π‘˜ ,
≽ is complete, transitive, and continuous
IFF
There exists and a continuous function 𝑒: 𝑋 → −∞, ∞ that represents ≽
89
Background:
Countable and uncountable sets
90
A puzzle
You run a hotel with infinitely many rooms
β„• = 1,2,3, …
They’re all occupied, and a new person comes along and asks to be
hosted
Can you give them a room?
91
Well, you can:
We start with
β„• = 1,2,3, …
And, say, person 0
The set
β„• ∪ 0 = 0,1,2,3, …
has “as many elements” as β„• = 1,2,3, …
92
“As many elements as’’
We can have a 1-1 mapping between
β„• = 1,2,3, …
and
β„• ∪ 0 = 0,1,2,3, …
β„•
1
2
3
4
5
…
β„•∪ 0
0
1
2
3
4
…
93
What about all the integers?
Again, we can have a 1-1 mapping between
β„• = 1,2,3, …
and
β„€ = 0, 1, −1, 2, −2, 3, −3, …
β„•
1
2
3
4
5
…
β„€
0
1
−1
2
−2
…
94
And the rationals?
π‘Ž
π‘Ž, 𝑏 ∈ β„• ∪ 0 , 𝑏 ≠ 0
𝑏
1
2
3
4
5
…
1
1
=1
1
1
2
1
3
1
4
1
5
…
2
2
=2
1
2
=1
2
2
3
2 1
=
4 2
2
5
…
be “counted” too.
3
3
=3
1
3
2
3
=1
3
3
4
3
5
…
Consider π‘Ž, 𝑏 > 0
4
4
=4
1
4
=2
2
4
3
4
=1
4
4
5
…
5
5
=5
1
5
2
5
3
5
4
5
=1
5
…
…
…
…
…
…
…
…
β„š=
𝑏
π‘Ž
And it turns out they can
95
For any table…
We can count the cells…
1
2
4
7
3
5
8
…
6
9
…
10
…
…
…
…
…
…
…
…
…
…
…
…
…
96
And thus
β„š=
𝑏
π‘Ž
𝑏
π‘Ž, 𝑏 ∈ β„• , 𝑏 ≠ 0 can be “counted”, too
1
2
3
4
5
…
1
1
=1
1
1
2
1
3
1
4
1
5
…
1
2
4
7
2
2
=2
1
2
=1
2
2
3
2 1
=
4 2
2
5
…
3
5
8
…
3
3
=3
1
3
2
3
=1
3
3
4
3
5
…
6
9
…
4
4
=4
1
4
=2
2
4
3
4
=1
4
4
5
…
10
…
5
5
=5
1
5
2
5
3
5
4
5
=1
5
…
…
…
…
…
…
…
…
π‘Ž
…
…
…
…
…
…
…
…
…
…
…
…
97
So it turns out that
The naturals
β„• = 1,2,3, …
the integers
β„€ = 0, 1, −1, 2, −2, 3, −3, …
and the rationals
β„š=
π‘Ž
𝑏
π‘Ž, 𝑏 ∈ β„€, 𝑏 ≠ 0
all have “as many elements as” each other
They are all countable
98
Admittedly, it’s weird…
That a set
β„• = 1,2,3, …
would have “as many elements as” supersets thereof
β„€ = 0, 1, −1, 2, −2, 3, −3, …
β„š=
π‘Ž
𝑏
π‘Ž, 𝑏 ∈ β„€, 𝑏 ≠ 0
But we simply don’t have a better definition of the (same) “number of elements”
for infinite sets
99
And it can also happen with intervals
That a set 0,1
has “as many elements as” its superset 0,2
In fact,
𝑓 π‘₯ = 0.5π‘₯
is a 1-1 mapping from 0,2 to 0,1
0,1
0,2
100
Any two intervals
would clearly have the same “number of
elements” (“cardinality”)
In fact,
𝑑−𝑐
𝑓 π‘₯ =𝑐+
π‘₯−π‘Ž
𝑏−π‘Ž
𝑐, 𝑑
is a 1-1 mapping from π‘Ž, 𝑏 to 𝑐, 𝑑
π‘Ž, 𝑏
101
Even infinite and finite
And even the non-negative part of the line
[0, ∞) has the same cardinality:
𝑓 π‘₯ = 1 − 𝑒 −π‘₯
is a 1-1 mapping from [0, ∞)
to [0,1)
102
And since we have
mappings from the entire line ℝ = −∞, ∞
into −1,1 , such as
𝑓 π‘₯ = π‘Žπ‘Ÿπ‘π‘‘π‘”(π‘₯)
103
All intervals
of positive length have the same
“number of elements” (“cardinality”)
Because
1
𝑓 π‘₯ = π‘Žπ‘Ÿπ‘π‘‘π‘”(π‘₯)+1
2
is a 1-1 mapping from ℝ = −∞, ∞
into 0,1
104
So maybe all infinities are the same?
Maybe the reals
ℝ = −∞, ∞
are also countable?
Is there a 1-1 mapping from the reals to
the naturals
β„• = 1,2,3, …
?
105
Well, they aren’t
Even
0,1 ⊂ ℝ = −∞, ∞
isn’t countable
There is no 1-1 mapping from the reals to
the naturals
β„• = 1,2,3, …
Georg Cantor (1845-1918)
106
0,1 isn’t countable
Assume it were
Then we’d have 0,1 = π‘₯1 , π‘₯2 , π‘₯3 , π‘₯4 , …
For each π‘₯ ∈ 0,1 there is 𝑛 ≥ 1 such that π‘₯ = π‘₯𝑛
Each π‘₯𝑖 can be written in a decimal expansion (not always in a unique way):
π‘₯𝑖 = 0. 𝑑1𝑖 𝑑2𝑖 𝑑3𝑖 𝑑4𝑖 𝑑5𝑖 …
Where 𝑑𝑗𝑖 ∈ 0,1,2, , … , 9
107
If 0,1 were countable
We’d have
π‘₯1 = 0. 𝑑11 𝑑21 𝑑31 𝑑41 …
π‘₯2 = 0. 𝑑12 𝑑22 𝑑32 𝑑42 …
π‘₯3 = 0. 𝑑13 𝑑23 𝑑33 𝑑43 …
π‘₯4 = 0. 𝑑14 𝑑24 𝑑34 𝑑44 …
We can construct
π‘₯ = 0. 𝑏1 𝑏2 𝑏3 𝑏4 …
with 𝑏𝑖 = 𝑑𝑖𝑖 + 2(π‘šπ‘œπ‘‘ 10) so that π‘₯ ≠ π‘₯𝑖 – for all 𝑖
108
Why
𝑖
𝑑𝑖
+2?
The decimal expansion isn’t unique
1
= 0. 500000 …
2
1
= 0. 499999 …
2
𝑗
so that fact that 𝑑𝑖𝑖 ≠ 𝑑𝑖 isn’t yet a proof that π‘₯𝑖 ≠ π‘₯𝑗
… but we get the point
109
Consumer theory
110
Consumer theory:
Basic concepts and preview
111
A basic distinction
What we can do and what we want to do are logically independent
• Aesop’s fox: “sour grapes”
• Groucho Marx: “I refuse to join any club that would have me for a member”
• The fox is psychologically healthier
• But they both commit the same “rationality sin”
• And a converse one is “wishful thinking”
112
What can we choose
π‘₯
𝑦
– quantity of good 1
– quantity of good 2
𝑝π‘₯
𝑝𝑦
– price of good 1
– price of good 2
feasible set – what are the possible values we
𝐼
– income
may choose for these variables
decision variables – what is up to us to control
113
The budget constraint
𝑦
𝐼
𝑝𝑦
𝑝𝑦 𝑦 + 𝑝π‘₯ π‘₯ ≤ 𝐼
π‘₯, 𝑦 ≥ 0
𝐼
𝑝π‘₯
π‘₯
114
The objective function
𝑦
Maximization of utility : π‘€π‘Žπ‘₯ π‘ˆ(π‘₯, 𝑦)
𝐼
𝑝𝑦
We thus ask, which of the points in the
feasible set has the highest π‘ˆ value?
𝐼
𝑝π‘₯
π‘₯
115
Indifference curves
Even with two goods, it’s hard to visualize the utility : π‘€π‘Žπ‘₯ π‘ˆ(π‘₯, 𝑦)
In fact, because utility is only ordinal, it’s not clear we want to
visualize it
The information we’d miss is not very meaningful anyway…
116
Indifference curves
𝑦
Connect points with equal utility
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = 𝑐
Each is an indifference class of ≽
π‘₯
117
Optimization
𝑦
𝐼
𝑝𝑦
Match the indifference curves with
the feasible set
Try to find the highest indifference
curve you can still be on
𝐼
𝑝π‘₯
π‘₯
118
Sneak preview
Optimality is often found at the equality of slopes which will be identified by the marginality
condition:
π‘ˆπ‘₯ 𝑝π‘₯
=
π‘ˆπ‘¦ 𝑝𝑦
or
π‘ˆπ‘₯ π‘ˆπ‘¦
=
𝑝π‘₯ 𝑝𝑦
119
The marginality condition
𝑦
A basic optimization tool: look for a point with
𝐼
𝑝𝑦
equal slopes
Generally, neither necessary nor sufficient, but
let’s see its logic first
𝐼
𝑝π‘₯
π‘₯
120
Why equate slopes?
𝑦
If the budget line is steeper than the
𝐼
𝑝𝑦
indifference curve…
π‘₯
121
Why equate slopes?
𝑦
If the indifference curve is steeper than the
𝐼
𝑝𝑦
budget line…
π‘₯
122
The slope of the budget constraint
𝑝π‘₯ π‘₯ + 𝑝𝑦 𝑦 = 𝐼
𝑝π‘₯ π‘₯ + π‘Ž + 𝑝𝑦 𝑦 − 𝑏 = 𝐼
𝑝π‘₯ π‘Ž − 𝑝𝑦 𝑏 = 0
𝑦
𝑏
π‘Ž
𝑏
=
𝑝π‘₯
𝑝𝑦
π‘Ž
π‘₯
123
The slope of the indifference curve
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = 𝑐
π‘ˆ π‘₯ + π‘Ž, 𝑦 − 𝑏 = 𝑐
π‘ˆπ‘₯ π‘Ž − π‘ˆπ‘¦ 𝑏 ≅ 0
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = 𝑐
𝑦
𝑏
π‘Ž
𝑏
π‘ˆπ‘₯
≅
π‘Ž
π‘ˆπ‘¦
π‘₯
124
… So, we want equality of slopes:
π‘ˆπ‘₯ 𝑝π‘₯
=
π‘ˆπ‘¦ 𝑝𝑦
or:
π‘ˆπ‘₯ π‘ˆπ‘¦
=
𝑝π‘₯ 𝑝𝑦
125
The economic meaning of
the marginality condition
$1 ≅
$1 ≅
1
𝑝π‘₯
1
𝑝𝑦
units of π‘₯ ≅
units of 𝑦 ≅
π‘ˆπ‘₯
𝑝π‘₯
π‘ˆπ‘¦
𝑝𝑦
utility
utility
126
Thus…
If:
π‘ˆπ‘₯ π‘ˆπ‘¦
>
𝑝π‘₯ 𝑝𝑦
And vice versa if
we’ll be better off moving $1 from 𝑦 to π‘₯
π‘ˆπ‘₯ π‘ˆπ‘¦
<
𝑝π‘₯ 𝑝𝑦
Unless…
127
Unless this is impossible, say
π‘ˆπ‘₯ π‘ˆπ‘¦
>
𝑝π‘₯ 𝑝𝑦
and
𝑦=0
… which can happen (“corner solution”)
128
Example
π‘₯ − # of six-pack of water bottles
𝑦 − # of single water bottles
𝑝π‘₯ = 15 − price for a six-pack
𝑝𝑦 = 3 − price for a single
𝐼 = 60 − budget for water
129
The budget constraint
𝑦
15π‘₯ + 3𝑦 ≤ 60
𝐼
60
=
= 20
𝑝𝑦
3
π‘₯, 𝑦 – a bundle
𝐼
60
=
=4
𝑝π‘₯ 15
π‘₯
130
Example: linear utility
For example
π‘ˆ(π‘₯, 𝑦) = 6π‘₯ + 𝑦
Which can happen:
π‘₯ = six-packs of bottles
𝑦 = single bottles
For such a function corner solutions will not be exceptional
131
Graphically
𝑦
π‘ˆ(π‘₯, 𝑦) = 6π‘₯ + 𝑦
The six-packs are a better deal:
𝑝π‘₯ = 15 < 6 ∗ 3 = 6𝑝𝑦
𝐼
= 20
𝑝𝑦
Comparing the slopes:
π‘ˆπ‘₯ = 6, π‘ˆπ‘¦ = 1
𝑝π‘₯ 15
π‘ˆπ‘₯
=
=5<6=
𝑝𝑦
3
π‘ˆπ‘¦
π‘ˆπ‘¦ 1
6
π‘ˆπ‘₯
= <
=
𝑝𝑦 3 15 𝑝π‘₯
𝐼
=4
𝑝π‘₯
π‘₯
132
What is exactly meant by π‘ˆπ‘₯ = 6, π‘ˆπ‘¦ = 1 ?
A partial derivative of a function is the derivative relative to one variable while
the others are held fixed
The partial derivative of π‘ˆ(π‘₯, 𝑦) relative to π‘₯:
πœ•π‘ˆ
(π‘₯, 𝑦)
πœ•π‘₯
πœ•π‘ˆ
(π‘₯, 𝑦)
πœ•π‘¦
=
πœ•π‘ˆ(π‘₯,𝑦)
πœ•π‘₯
= π‘ˆπ‘₯ (π‘₯, 𝑦)
=
πœ•π‘ˆ(π‘₯,𝑦)
πœ•π‘¦
= π‘ˆπ‘¦ (π‘₯, 𝑦)
and relative to 𝑦:
Partial derivatives graphically
Examples of partial derivatives
For
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = π‘Žπ‘₯ + 𝑏𝑦
The partial derivatives are
π‘ˆπ‘₯ π‘₯, 𝑦 = π‘Ž
π‘ˆπ‘¦ π‘₯, 𝑦 = 𝑏
And for
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = π‘Žπ‘₯𝑦
We get
π‘ˆπ‘₯ π‘₯, 𝑦 = π‘Žπ‘¦
π‘ˆπ‘¦ π‘₯, 𝑦 = π‘Žπ‘₯
The economic meaning of
π‘ˆπ‘¦
π‘ˆπ‘₯
<
𝑝𝑦
𝑝π‘₯
$1 ≅
$1 ≅
1
𝑝π‘₯
1
𝑝𝑦
units of π‘₯ ≅
units of 𝑦 ≅
π‘ˆπ‘₯
𝑝π‘₯
π‘ˆπ‘¦
𝑝𝑦
utility
utility
136
We could also have…
π‘ˆ(π‘₯, 𝑦) = 6π‘₯ + 𝑦
𝑦
And if 𝑝π‘₯ > 6𝑝𝑦
𝐼
𝑝𝑦
𝑝π‘₯
π‘ˆπ‘₯
>6=
𝑝𝑦
π‘ˆπ‘¦
Can 𝑝π‘₯ > 6𝑝𝑦 happen???
𝐼
𝑝π‘₯
π‘₯
137
Finally…
π‘ˆ(π‘₯, 𝑦) = 6π‘₯ + 𝑦
𝑦
If 𝑝π‘₯ = 6𝑝𝑦
𝐼
𝑝𝑦
𝑝π‘₯
π‘ˆπ‘₯
=6=
𝑝𝑦
π‘ˆπ‘¦
No unique solution
𝐼
𝑝π‘₯
π‘₯
(isn’t it a knife-edge case?)
138
Summing up
The solution to the water consumption problem is:
If
𝑝π‘₯
𝑝𝑦
If
𝑝π‘₯
𝑝𝑦
And if
𝑝π‘₯
𝑝𝑦
<6
π‘₯, 𝑦 =
𝐼
,0
𝑝π‘₯
>6
π‘₯, 𝑦 =
0,
= 6 – anywhere in
𝐼
𝑝𝑦
𝐼
𝐼
, 0 , 0,
𝑝π‘₯
𝑝𝑦
Decreasing marginal utility
•
In the water bottles problems, the marginal utilities were
constant
•
It might be more intuitive that the “extra utility” we get from a
good decreases as we have more of it
The utility from money
Back in 1738, Daniel Bernoulli wrote,
“And, because the marginal utility from
money is in inverse proportion to the amount
of money we have…”
Daniel Bernoulli 1700-1782
141
“The marginal utility is inversely
proportional…”
𝑒′ π‘₯ = 𝑐 ∗
1
π‘₯
𝑒 π‘₯ = 𝑐 ∗ π‘™π‘œπ‘” π‘₯ + 𝑑
𝑐>0
𝑐>0
π‘™π‘œπ‘”(π‘₯) = π‘™π‘Žπ‘›(π‘₯)
142
But what do you mean, Daniel?
Rudolf Carnap (1891-1970)
Karl Popper (1902-1994)
• Theoretical terms should be defined by
observations
• How do you measure this “marginal utility”???
143
Two possible answers:
• Look, guys, you’re going to talk about this
200 years after me. Com’n.
• In between us, there will be a psychologist
who will show that more is observable
than what these economists will choose to
admit
Daniel Bernoulli 1700-1782
144
Weber’s law in psychophysics
Ernst Heinrich Weber
1795-1878
βˆ†π‘†
=πœ†
𝑆
𝑆 – stimulus
βˆ†π‘† – increase in the stimulus (that can be discerned with a fixed
probability, usually 75%)
λ – a positive constant
Weber’s law – cont.
A person would notice, with probability 75% or more, that a change has
occurred, namely that
𝑆 + βˆ†π‘† > 𝑆
Only if the physical change is large enough
𝑆 + βˆ†π‘†
>1+πœ†
𝑆
Or:
π‘™π‘œπ‘” 𝑆 + βˆ†π‘† − π‘™π‘œπ‘” 𝑆 > π‘™π‘œπ‘” 1 + πœ†
– a constant
The π‘™π‘œπ‘” function
Hence, for physical
quantities, the π‘™π‘œπ‘”
function plays a special
π‘™π‘œπ‘”(π‘₯)
role
π‘₯
A comment re π‘™π‘œπ‘”
Unless otherwise stated, we’ll take the base
of π‘™π‘œπ‘” to be 𝑒
π‘™π‘œπ‘”(π‘₯) = π‘™π‘Žπ‘›(π‘₯)
π‘™π‘œπ‘”(π‘₯)
Recall that any other base π‘Ž > 1 is a positive
multiple thereof :
π‘™π‘œπ‘”π‘’ (π‘₯)
π‘™π‘œπ‘”π‘Ž (π‘₯) =
= π›Ύπ‘™π‘Žπ‘›(π‘₯)
π‘™π‘œπ‘”π‘’ (π‘Ž)
π‘₯
for
1
𝛾 = π‘™π‘œπ‘”
𝑒
=
(π‘Ž)
1
π‘™π‘Žπ‘›(π‘Ž)
>0
Cobb-Douglas Preferences
(After Charles Cobb, Paul Douglas)
We started with
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = 6π‘₯ + 𝑦
Or, more generally, a linear function:
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = π‘Žπ‘₯ + 𝑏𝑦 π‘Ž, 𝑏 > 0
We can now look at a simple function that allows for decreasing marginal
utility:
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = π‘Žπ‘™π‘œπ‘”(π‘₯) + π‘π‘™π‘œπ‘”(𝑦) π‘Ž, 𝑏 > 0
Indifference curves for Cobb-Douglas
π‘ˆ π‘₯,𝑦 = π‘Žπ‘™π‘œπ‘”(π‘₯) + π‘π‘™π‘œπ‘”(𝑦)
𝑦
For example, for π‘Ž = 𝑏 = 1
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = π‘™π‘œπ‘”(π‘₯) + π‘™π‘œπ‘”(𝑦) = π‘™π‘œπ‘” π‘₯𝑦
π‘ˆ = 𝑐2
π‘ˆ = 𝑐1
π‘₯
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = 𝑐
⟺
π‘™π‘œπ‘” π‘₯𝑦 = 𝑐
⟺
π‘₯𝑦 = 𝑑
Decreasing marginal utility
𝑦
Suppose
100
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = π‘™π‘œπ‘”10 π‘₯ + π‘™π‘œπ‘”10 𝑦
Consider the indifference curve
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = π‘™π‘œπ‘”10 π‘₯ + π‘™π‘œπ‘”10 𝑦 = 3
10
π‘₯𝑦 = 1000
10
100
π‘₯
and two points on it
10,100 , (100,10)
151
Indifference curves become less steep
(going from left to right)
𝑦
Imagine that at 10,100 we
reduce 𝑦 by 1. How much π‘₯
100
should we add to compensate for
this reduction?
10
10
100
π‘₯
152
Let’s use the partial derivatives
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = π‘™π‘œπ‘”10 π‘₯ + π‘™π‘œπ‘”10 𝑦
And thus
π‘ˆπ‘₯ π‘₯, 𝑦 = π‘™π‘œπ‘”′10
𝛾
π‘₯ =
π‘₯
π‘ˆπ‘¦ π‘₯, 𝑦 = π‘™π‘œπ‘”′10
𝛾
𝑦 =
𝑦
(For 𝛾 = 1/π‘™π‘Žπ‘›(10) )
153
At 10,100
The partial derivatives (marginal utilities) are
𝑦
𝛾
π‘₯
𝛾
=
10
𝛾
𝑦
𝛾
=
100
As 𝑦 decreases from 100 to 99 the utility loss is
100
approximately
𝛾
100
and in order to compensate fot that we
need extra π‘Ž of product 1 (increase π‘₯ ) that satisfies, roughly,
10
𝛾
π‘Ž
10
10
100
π‘₯
=
π‘Ž=
𝛾
100
1
10
154
By contrast, at 100,10
The partial derivatives (marginal utilities) are
𝑦
𝛾
π‘₯
𝛾
=
100
𝛾
𝑦
=
𝛾
10
As 𝑦 decreases from 10 to 9 the utility loss is approximately
100
𝛾
10
and in order to compensate fot that we need extra π‘Ž of
product 1 (increase π‘₯ ) that satisfies, roughly,
10
𝛾
π‘Ž
100
10
100
π‘₯
=
𝛾
10
π‘Ž = 10
155
A general point
𝑦
When the marginal utility of each
product is decreasing, we will
have indifference curves that are
less steep as we go from upper
left to lower right
π‘₯
156
Optimal solution for CD preferences
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = π‘Žπ‘™π‘œπ‘” π‘₯ + π‘π‘™π‘œπ‘” 𝑦
𝑦
𝐼
𝑝𝑦
π‘Ž
𝑏
π‘ˆπ‘₯ = , π‘ˆπ‘¦ =
π‘₯
𝑦
𝐼
𝑝π‘₯
π‘₯
π‘Ž
π‘ˆπ‘₯
π‘Žπ‘¦
π‘₯
= =
𝑏
π‘ˆπ‘¦
𝑏π‘₯
𝑦
157
The slope of the indifference curves for CD
𝑦
When π‘₯ tends to 0 (and 𝑦 doesn’t) they
become very steep
When 𝑦 tends to 0 (and π‘₯ doesn’t) they
become very flat
The slope is the same along any ray from
π‘₯
the origin (homothetic preferences)
158
Homothetic preferences
𝑦
Along every ray that starts at the origin
(0,0), the slope of all indifference curves
is the same
But it can change from one ray to another
π‘₯
159
Solving the CD problem – cont.
Looking for π‘₯, 𝑦 where:
𝑝π‘₯ π‘₯ + 𝑝𝑦 𝑦 = 𝐼
and
π‘ˆπ‘₯ 𝑝π‘₯
=
π‘ˆπ‘¦ 𝑝𝑦
or
π‘Ž 𝑦 𝑝π‘₯
=
𝑏 π‘₯ 𝑝𝑦
160
Solving the CD problem – cont.
π‘Ž 𝑦 𝑝π‘₯
𝑝π‘₯ π‘₯ π‘Ž
=
⟹
=
𝑏 π‘₯ 𝑝𝑦
𝑝𝑦 𝑦 𝑏
Let’s denote
𝐸π‘₯ = 𝑝π‘₯ π‘₯
𝐸𝑦 = 𝑝𝑦 𝑦
So that
𝐸π‘₯ π‘Ž
=
𝐸𝑦 𝑏
which has to hold for all 𝑝π‘₯ , 𝑝𝑦 , 𝐼 !
161
Solving the CD problem – nearly done…
𝐸π‘₯ π‘Ž
=
𝐸𝑦 𝑏
𝐸π‘₯ + 𝐸𝑦 = 𝑝π‘₯ π‘₯ + 𝑝𝑦 𝑦 = 𝐼
Hence
π‘Ž
𝐸π‘₯ =
𝐼
π‘Ž+𝑏
𝑏
𝐸𝑦 =
𝐼
π‘Ž+𝑏
162
(Was that too quick?)
𝐸π‘₯ π‘Ž
=
𝐸𝑦 𝑏
⟹
𝐸π‘₯ =
π‘Ž
𝐸𝑦
𝑏
Plug these in
𝐸π‘₯ + 𝐸𝑦 = 𝑝π‘₯ π‘₯ + 𝑝𝑦 𝑦 = 𝐼
to get
π‘Ž
π‘Ž
π‘Ž+𝑏
𝐸 + 𝐸𝑦 =
+ 1 𝐸𝑦 =
𝐸𝑦 = 𝐼
𝑏 𝑦
𝑏
𝑏
and thus
𝑏
𝐸𝑦 =
𝐼
π‘Ž+𝑏
and
𝑏
π‘Ž
𝐸π‘₯ = 𝐼 − 𝐸𝑦 = 𝐼 −
𝐼=
𝐼
π‘Ž+𝑏
π‘Ž+𝑏
163
Solving the CD problem – wrapping up
π‘Ž
𝐸π‘₯ = 𝑝π‘₯ π‘₯ =
𝐼
π‘Ž+𝑏
π‘Ž 1
⟹π‘₯=
𝐼
π‘Ž + 𝑏 𝑝π‘₯
𝑏
𝐸𝑦 = 𝑝𝑦 𝑦 =
𝐼
π‘Ž+𝑏
𝑏 1
βŸΉπ‘¦=
𝐼
π‘Ž + 𝑏 𝑝𝑦
164
Consumer theory:
Lagrange Multipliers
165
Or, using Lagrange multipliers
The “real” problem
π‘€π‘Žπ‘₯π‘₯,𝑦 π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
𝑝π‘₯ π‘₯ + 𝑝𝑦 𝑦 ≤ 𝐼
π‘₯, 𝑦 ≥ 0
166
Simplify our lives
𝑦
If π‘ˆ is monotone (the consumer
𝐼
𝑝𝑦
prefers more to less), it’s safe to
assume the solution will be on
𝑝π‘₯ π‘₯ + 𝑝𝑦 𝑦 = 𝐼
Can’t be
optimal
𝐼
𝑝π‘₯
π‘₯
167
Let’s simplify our lives even further
Let’s ignore the non-negativity constraints
π‘₯, 𝑦 ≥ 0
(Make a mental note not to forget these)
And then there’s only one constraint, which is an equality:
π‘€π‘Žπ‘₯π‘₯,𝑦 π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
𝑠. 𝑑.
𝑝π‘₯ π‘₯ + 𝑝𝑦 𝑦 = 𝐼
168
Lagrange’s idea
•
We’ll build the constraint into the utility function
•
As if it could be violated, though at a cost
•
At the optimal solution it won’t be violated after all
•
But the trick will also have an economic meaning
Joseph-Louis Lagrange 1736-1813
169
Solving using Lagrange multiplier
π‘€π‘Žπ‘₯π‘₯,𝑦 π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
𝑠. 𝑑.
𝑝π‘₯ π‘₯ + 𝑝𝑦 𝑦 = 𝐼
Becomes
π‘€π‘Žπ‘₯π‘₯,𝑦,πœ† β„’ π‘₯, 𝑦, πœ†
β„’ π‘₯, 𝑦, πœ† = π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 − πœ†[𝑝π‘₯ π‘₯ + 𝑝𝑦 𝑦 − 𝐼]
πœ† – a new variable, the cost of violating the constraint
170
Lagrange’s method – cont.
To find
π‘€π‘Žπ‘₯π‘₯,𝑦,πœ† β„’ π‘₯, 𝑦, πœ†
we take all partial derivatives and set them to zero
πœ•β„’(π‘₯, 𝑦, πœ†)
=0
πœ•π‘₯
πœ•β„’(π‘₯, 𝑦, πœ†)
=0
πœ•π‘¦
πœ•β„’(π‘₯, 𝑦, πœ†)
=0
πœ•πœ†
171
The partial derivatives
β„’ π‘₯, 𝑦, πœ† = π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 − πœ†[𝑝π‘₯ π‘₯ + 𝑝𝑦 𝑦 − 𝐼]
πœ•β„’
= π‘ˆπ‘₯ − πœ†π‘π‘₯
πœ•π‘₯
πœ•β„’
= π‘ˆπ‘¦ − πœ†π‘π‘¦
πœ•π‘¦
πœ•β„’
= − [𝑝π‘₯ π‘₯ + 𝑝𝑦 𝑦 − 𝐼]
πœ•πœ†
172
Setting them to zero
πœ•β„’
= π‘ˆπ‘₯ − πœ†π‘π‘₯ = 0
πœ•π‘₯
πœ•β„’
= π‘ˆπ‘¦ − πœ†π‘π‘¦ = 0
πœ•π‘¦
πœ•β„’
= − 𝑝π‘₯ π‘₯ + 𝑝𝑦 𝑦 − 𝐼 = 0
πœ•πœ†
173
The resulting equations
πœ•β„’
π‘ˆπ‘₯
= 0 = π‘ˆπ‘₯ − πœ†π‘π‘₯ ⟹ πœ† =
πœ•π‘₯
𝑝π‘₯
π‘ˆπ‘¦
πœ•β„’
= 0 = π‘ˆπ‘¦ − πœ†π‘π‘¦ ⟹ πœ† =
πœ•π‘¦
𝑝𝑦
πœ•β„’
= 0 = − 𝑝π‘₯ π‘₯ + 𝑝𝑦 𝑦 − 𝐼 ⟹ 𝑝π‘₯ π‘₯ + 𝑝𝑦 𝑦 = 𝐼
πœ•πœ†
174
Conclusions
πœ•β„’
= 0 ⟹ 𝑝π‘₯ π‘₯ + 𝑝𝑦 𝑦 = 𝐼
πœ•πœ†
πœ•β„’
π‘ˆπ‘₯
=0 βŸΉπœ†=
πœ•π‘₯
𝑝π‘₯
π‘ˆπ‘¦
πœ•β„’
=0 βŸΉπœ†=
πœ•π‘¦
𝑝𝑦
π‘ˆπ‘₯ π‘ˆπ‘¦
=
𝑝π‘₯ 𝑝𝑦
π‘ˆπ‘₯ π‘ˆπ‘¦
π‘ˆπ‘₯ 𝑝π‘₯
=
⟹
=
𝑝π‘₯ 𝑝𝑦
π‘ˆπ‘¦ 𝑝𝑦
175
And in the CD problem
We are again looking for π‘₯, 𝑦 where:
𝑝π‘₯ π‘₯ + 𝑝𝑦 𝑦 = 𝐼
and
π‘ˆπ‘₯ 𝑝π‘₯
=
π‘ˆπ‘¦ 𝑝𝑦
or
π‘Ž 𝑦 𝑝π‘₯
=
𝑏 π‘₯ 𝑝𝑦
176
And the solution is, again
𝐸π‘₯ = 𝑝π‘₯ π‘₯ =
π‘Ž
𝐼
π‘Ž+𝑏
𝐸𝑦 = 𝑝𝑦 𝑦 =
𝑏
𝐼
π‘Ž+𝑏
⟹π‘₯=
π‘Ž 1
𝐼
π‘Ž+𝑏 𝑝π‘₯
βŸΉπ‘¦=
𝑏 1
𝐼
π‘Ž+𝑏 𝑝𝑦
Clearly, we didn’t need Lagrange here, but in more complex problem
his method can really help…
177
Consumer theory:
Ordinality
178
Ordinality
Recall that the utility function is (only) ordinal
• We won’t take the specific function too seriously
• Any monotone transformation thereof is equally good
• We should better verify that we only discuss properties that
are common to all such transformations
179
“How unique” is π‘ˆ ?
We won’t be able to tell
𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = log π‘₯ + log 𝑦
from
𝑉 π‘₯, 𝑦 = π‘₯𝑦
or
log π‘₯ + log 𝑦 = 𝑑
π‘Š π‘₯, 𝑦 = 5π‘₯𝑦
or even
π‘₯𝑦 = 𝑐
π‘₯
𝑍 π‘₯, 𝑦 = (5π‘₯𝑦 + 10)3
180
Yet, the slope of the indifference curve
is the same
π‘ˆπ‘₯
=?
π‘ˆπ‘¦
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = π‘Ž ∗ π‘™π‘œπ‘” π‘₯ + 𝑏 ∗ π‘™π‘œπ‘” 𝑦
𝑦
π‘Ž
π‘ˆπ‘₯
π‘Žπ‘¦
= π‘₯=
𝑏
π‘ˆπ‘¦
𝑏π‘₯
𝑦
𝑉 π‘₯, 𝑦 = π‘₯ π‘Ž 𝑦 𝑏
π‘₯
𝑉π‘₯ π‘Žπ‘₯ π‘Ž−1 𝑦 𝑏 π‘Ž 𝑦
= π‘Ž 𝑏−1 =
𝑉𝑦 𝑏π‘₯ 𝑦
𝑏π‘₯
181
More generally:
If 𝑓 is monotonically increasing
𝑉 π‘₯, 𝑦 = 𝑓 π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦
𝑉π‘₯ = 𝑓 ′ (π‘ˆ) ∗ π‘ˆπ‘₯
𝑉𝑦 = 𝑓 ′ (π‘ˆ) ∗ π‘ˆπ‘¦
𝑉π‘₯ 𝑓′ ∗ π‘ˆπ‘₯ π‘ˆπ‘₯
=
=
𝑉𝑦 𝑓′ ∗ π‘ˆπ‘¦ π‘ˆπ‘¦
… a great relief
182
Hence the marginality condition
π‘ˆπ‘₯ 𝑝π‘₯
=
π‘ˆπ‘¦ 𝑝𝑦
Does not depend on the transformation
because the slope
π‘ˆπ‘₯
π‘ˆπ‘¦
is independent of 𝑓
183
But ...
How about
π‘ˆπ‘₯
𝑝π‘₯
=
π‘ˆπ‘¦
𝑝𝑦
?
• The transformation 𝑓 (𝑉 π‘₯, 𝑦 = 𝑓 π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 ) will modify both sides
in the same way: multiply by 𝑓 ′ > 0
• The values on both sides can change, but whether they’re equal
or not – will not change
• (Nor will the answer to the question, “which one is larger?”)
184
… Therefore…
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = π‘Ž ∗ π‘™π‘œπ‘” π‘₯ + 𝑏 ∗ π‘™π‘œπ‘” 𝑦
𝑉 π‘₯, 𝑦 = π‘₯ π‘Ž 𝑦 𝑏
π‘Š π‘₯, 𝑦 = 𝛼 log π‘₯ + 1 − 𝛼 log 𝑦
,
π‘Ž
𝛼=
π‘Ž+𝑏
𝑍 π‘₯, 𝑦 = π‘₯ 𝛼 𝑦1−𝛼
… all describe the same preferences, and we can switch among
them shamelessly
185
The normalized CD function
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = 𝛼 log π‘₯ + 1 − 𝛼 log 𝑦
𝐸π‘₯ = 𝑝π‘₯ π‘₯ = 𝛼𝐼
𝐸𝑦 = 𝑝𝑦 𝑦 = (1 − 𝛼)𝐼
1
π‘₯=𝛼 𝐼
𝑝π‘₯
1
𝑦 = (1 − 𝛼) 𝐼
𝑝𝑦
186
Consumer theory:
Monotonicity
187
Monotonicity of π‘ˆ
In bold strokes, “more is preferred to less”
But:
• What exactly is “more”? More π‘₯, more 𝑦,
more both?
• What exactly is “preferred to”? Strictly
better? Just not worse?
188
Basic monotonicity
π‘ˆ cannot decrease in any of the variables:
If
π‘₯ ≥ π‘₯ ′ and 𝑦 ≥ 𝑦′
then
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 ≥ π‘ˆ(π‘₯ ′ , 𝑦 ′ )
Typically justified by free disposal
189
Free disposal
If you don’t like it – throw it away
•
The quantities π‘₯, 𝑦 designate what’s legally yours, not
necessarily what went into your stomach
•
Used to be less of an issue when I was a student
•
Less obvious when we think about the environment
•
And can even be an emotional problem (if we cherish values
that are compromised by production/consumption of these
goods)
190
Basic monotonicity – cont.
Obviously allows
𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = π‘₯ + 𝑦
But also
20
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = min π‘₯, 10 + min 𝑦, 20
– the consumer can reach satiation
10
π‘₯
191
Satiation
• A type of nirvana
• Luckily, doesn’t happen too naturally
• Luckily?
192
A preview of the welfare theorem
We will discuss general equilibrium
And will find out that, under certain conditions, it is “nice” in
the sense of Pareto
The First Welfare Theorem: A general equilibrium yields
Pareto optimal allocations
193
Pareto efficiency/optimality
•
An allocation is Pareto
optimal/efficient if we can’t make
some people better off without
hurting others
•
Says nothing about justice or
fairness
Vilfredo Pareto 1848-1923
194
“Efficient” or “Optimal”?
• “Efficient” sounds like we only try to produce as
much as possible, and that’s not the case
• "Optimal” sounds like it’s the “best”, at least as
good as anything else – and it only means that
there’s nothing better
195
The First Welfare Theorem
•
In any event, Pareto optimality/efficiency is a nice property
to have
•
The First Welfare Theorem says that any allocation that is
the result of a general equilibrium has this property
•
But consumer who reach satiation can destroy it
•
That’s why, as economists, we see something positive in
the fact that people don’t reach satiation so easily…
196
Strict monotonicity
π‘ˆ is strictly increasing in each variable:
If
π‘₯ > π‘₯ ′ and
𝑦 ≥ 𝑦′
or
π‘₯ ≥ π‘₯ ′ and
𝑦 > 𝑦′
then
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 > π‘ˆ π‘₯ ′ , 𝑦 ′
– necessarily satisfies basic monotonicity as well
197
Is strict monotonicity plausible?
• How much water can you drink?
• In many good we will reach satiation
• Even if we still want something else (diamonds?)
198
Weak monotonicity
Basic monotonicity +
If
π‘₯ > π‘₯ ′ and
𝑦 > 𝑦′
then
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 > π‘ˆ(π‘₯ ′ , 𝑦 ′ )
There may be satiation in some goods, but not in all
199
Example: weak but not strict monotonicity
𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = min π‘₯, 10 + 𝑦
10
π‘₯
200
Weak monotonicity suffices
• For the consumer to be on the
budget line
𝑦
• …and wish to sell any extras in
the market
• For the equilibria to be Pareto
efficient/optimal
π‘₯
201
Consumer theory:
Convexity
202
Problems
• There are more complex feasible sets
• The marginality condition doesn’t always help
203
More interesting “budget” sets
Suppose you have to decide how many movies and how many
theater shows to watch
Good
Price
Minutes
π‘₯
movie
40
120
𝑦
theater
100
60
Budget
400
600
204
The budget(s) set
𝑦
40π‘₯ + 100𝑦 ≤ 400
10
120π‘₯ + 60𝑦 ≤ 600
π‘₯, 𝑦 ≥ 0
4
(3.75,2.5)
5
10
π‘₯
205
Let’s maximize utility
𝑦
Max 𝑉 π‘₯, 𝑦 = π‘₯ 0.3 𝑦 0.7
10
40π‘₯ + 100𝑦 ≤ 400
120π‘₯ + 60𝑦 ≤ 600
4
(3.75,2.5)
5
π‘₯, 𝑦 ≥ 0
10
π‘₯
206
Looking for a tangency point, say…
𝑦
Max 𝑉 π‘₯, 𝑦 = π‘₯ 0.3 𝑦 0.7
10
πŸ’πŸŽπ’™ + πŸπŸŽπŸŽπ’š ≤ πŸ’πŸŽπŸŽ
120π‘₯ + 60𝑦 ≤ 600
4
(3.75,2.5)
5
π‘₯, 𝑦 ≥ 0
10
π‘₯
207
Indeed,
𝑦
Max 𝑉 π‘₯, 𝑦 = π‘₯ 0.3 𝑦 0.7
10
πŸ’πŸŽπ’™ + πŸπŸŽπŸŽπ’š = πŸ’πŸŽπŸŽ
π‘₯=π‘Ž
4
(3,2.8)
(3.75,2.5)
5
1
1
𝐼 = 0.3 400 = 3
𝑝π‘₯
40
𝑦 = 1−π‘Ž
10
π‘₯
1
𝐼
𝑝𝑦
= 0.7
1
400
100
= 2.8
The tangency with the first line is within the
relevant range and we’re happy
208
But if preferences were different…
𝑦
Max 𝑉 π‘₯, 𝑦 = π‘₯ 0.8 𝑦 0.2
10
πŸ’πŸŽπ’™ + πŸπŸŽπŸŽπ’š = πŸ’πŸŽπŸŽ
π‘₯=π‘Ž
4
(3.75,2.5)
1
1
𝐼 = 0.8 400 = 8
𝑝π‘₯
40
𝑦 = 1−π‘Ž
1
𝐼
𝑝𝑦
= 0.2
1
400
100
= 0.8
(8,0.8)
5
10
π‘₯
The tangency point with this line is outside the
range and we’re very unhappy
209
Looking for tangency with the other segment
𝑦
Max 𝑉 π‘₯, 𝑦 = π‘₯ 0.8 𝑦 0.2
10
πŸπŸπŸŽπ’™ + πŸ”πŸŽπ’š = πŸ”πŸŽπŸŽ
π‘₯=π‘Ž
4
(3.75,2.5)
(4,2)
1
1
𝐼 = 0.8
600 = 4
𝑝π‘₯
120
𝑦 = 1−π‘Ž
1
𝐼
𝑝𝑦
= 0.2
1
600
60
=2
And again there’s tangency with one line that’s in
5
10
π‘₯
the relevant range (for this line) and we’re happy
210
Will this always work?
𝑦
Max 𝑉 π‘₯, 𝑦 = π‘₯ 0.5 𝑦 0.5
10
πŸ’πŸŽπ’™ + πŸπŸŽπŸŽπ’š = πŸ’πŸŽπŸŽ
π‘₯=π‘Ž
4
(3.75,2.5)
(5,2)
5
1
1
𝐼 = 0.5 400 = 5
𝑝π‘₯
40
𝑦 = 1−π‘Ž
10
π‘₯
1
𝐼
𝑝𝑦
= 0.5
1
400
100
=2
The tangency point with this line is again
outside the range and we’re again unhappy
211
On the other hand…
𝑦
Max 𝑉 π‘₯, 𝑦 = π‘₯ 0.5 𝑦 0.5
10
πŸπŸπŸŽπ’™ + πŸ”πŸŽπ’š = πŸ”πŸŽπŸŽ
π‘₯=π‘Ž
(2.5,5)
4
(3.75,2.5)
5
1
1
𝐼 = 0.5
600 = 2.5
𝑝π‘₯
120
𝑦 = 1−π‘Ž
10
π‘₯
1
𝐼
𝑝𝑦
= 0.5
1
600
60
=5
The tangency point with the other line is also outside
the relevant range and we’re very unhappy
212
So what’s going on?
𝑦
Max 𝑉 π‘₯, 𝑦 = π‘₯ 0.5 𝑦 0.5
10
40π‘₯ + 100𝑦 = 400
120π‘₯ + 60𝑦 = 600
4
π‘₯ = 3.75
(3.75,2.5)
𝑦 = 2.5
5
10
π‘₯
Well, we can’t call it tangency, but we
do have separation
213
More generally
𝑦
•
When there are several linear inequality and they all
have to be satisfied (“and”) we look for tangencies
•
If one of them is in the relevant range we’re happy
•
If not, we look at the extreme points
•
(We don’t need to look at all of them – if one of them is
“in between” slope we’re done)
•
(And something like this works in higher dimensions,
too)
π‘₯
214
Encouraged and cheered up,
Let us now assume that
𝑝π‘₯ = 𝑝𝑦 = 1,
𝐼 = 200
But there are discounts for large quantities: above 100 the
price of π‘₯ per unit goes down by 50%
𝑝π‘₯ =
1
2
if π‘₯ > 100
215
Which bundles are feasible
Distinguish between
𝑦
π‘₯ ≤ 100
and
200
150
𝑝π‘₯ = 1
π‘₯ > 100
𝑝π‘₯ = 0.5
100
100
200
300
π‘₯
216
The budget set
In the range
𝑦
π‘₯ ≤ 100
the price is
𝑝π‘₯ = 1
200
and the budget line:
150
π‘₯ + 𝑦 ≤ 200
100
And, as usual,
π‘₯, 𝑦 ≥ 0
100
200
300
π‘₯
217
The budget set – cont.
In the range
𝑦
π‘₯ > 100
the price is
𝑝π‘₯ = 0.5
200
and the constraint is
150
0.5 π‘₯ − 100 + 𝑦 ≤ 200 − 100 = 100
100
(Because we already spent 100 on the first 100 units)
or
100
200
300
0.5π‘₯ + 𝑦 ≤ 150
π‘₯
(and π‘₯, 𝑦 ≥ 0 )
218
The budget set, therefore:
𝑦
And we see we could also write
π‘₯ + 𝑦 ≤ 200
200
or
0.5π‘₯ + 𝑦 ≤ 150
150
and, as usual
100
π‘₯, 𝑦 ≥ 0
100
200
300
π‘₯
219
Let’s maximize
𝑦
Max 𝑉 π‘₯, 𝑦 = π‘₯ 0.45 𝑦 0.55
π‘₯ + 𝑦 ≤ 200
200
or
150
0.5π‘₯ + 𝑦 ≤ 150
100
100
200
300
π‘₯
(π‘₯, 𝑦 ≥ 0)
220
Looking for tangency
𝑦
Max 𝑉 π‘₯, 𝑦 = π‘₯ 0.45 𝑦 0.55
Let’s try tangency with
200
150
𝒙 + π’š = 𝟐𝟎𝟎
1
1
π‘₯ = π‘Ž 𝐼 = 0.45 200 = 90
𝑝π‘₯
1
1
1
𝑦 = 1−π‘Ž
𝐼 = 0.55 200 = 110
(90,110)
100
𝑝𝑦
100
200
300
π‘₯
1
We made it!
221
But there’s another tangency point
𝑦
Max 𝑉 π‘₯, 𝑦 = π‘₯ 0.45 𝑦 0.55
Tangency with
200
150
𝟎. πŸ“π’™ + π’š = πŸπŸ“πŸŽ
1
1
𝐼 = 0.45
150 = 135
𝑝π‘₯
0.5
1
1
𝑦 = 1 − π‘Ž 𝑝 𝐼 = 0.55 1 150 = 82.5
π‘₯=π‘Ž
(90,110)
(135,82.5)
100
100
200
𝑦
300
π‘₯
… and in this case
1350.45 82.50.55 = 102.96 >
900.45 1100.55 = 100.50
222
Generally
𝑦
•
If there are several linear inequalities and only
one should be satisfied (“or”), we will look for all
tangency points
•
We will need to compare them
•
And the intersection points
•
(We can save a bit: the intersection between two segments
will not be better than both tangency points on them)
π‘₯
223
An “or” condition between inequalities
𝑦
•
May appear when there are discounts
•
Or when we can buy in one of several
markets, but not to mix between them
•
Or to order from one of several
suppliers…
π‘₯
224
Convex sets
For every two points in the set, the entire interval
connecting them is also in the set
225
Non-convex sets
There exists at least one pair of points in the set, such
that some of the interval connecting them is outside
the set
226
The interval connecting two points
𝑦
For example, the interval connecting
1,5
5
1,5
and
3,1
3,1
1
1
3
π‘₯
227
The interval formula – cont.
𝑦
1,5
Consider, for example, the mid-point
5
What’s its π‘₯ value ?
1+3
=2
2
3,1
1
1
2
3
π‘₯
228
And, similarly
𝑦
The midpoint’s 𝑦 value is
1,5
5
5+1
=3
2
3
3,1
1
1
3
π‘₯
229
In short,
𝑦
The midpoint is 2,3
1,5
5
In other words, the average values:
2,3
3
1
1
1,5 + 3,1 = (2,3)
2
2
3,1
1
1
2
3
π‘₯
230
And what about other points?
𝑦
Their coordinates are weighted average of
1,5
those of the extreme points – while always
5
using the same weights
𝑦
π‘Ž 1,5 + 1 − π‘Ž 3,1
3,1
1
=(π‘Ž ∗ 1 + 1 − π‘Ž ∗ 3, π‘Ž ∗ 5 + 1 − π‘Ž ∗ 1)
π‘Ž = 1 we get
1,5
and for π‘Ž = 0 we get
3,1
For
1 π‘₯
3
π‘₯
231
Convex budget sets
𝑦
Obviously, the classic one:
𝑝π‘₯ π‘₯ + 𝑝𝑦 𝑦 ≤ 𝐼
π‘₯, 𝑦 ≥ 0
π‘₯
232
As well as…
𝑦
Anything we can get by
intersection (“and”) of linear
inequalities
(or, more generally, the
intersection of any convex sets)
π‘₯
233
But not…
𝑦
The union of convex sets need not
be convex
π‘₯
234
A non-convex budget set
𝑦
Can be problematic: the
marginality condition is no longer
sufficient for optimality
π‘₯
235
Non-convex preferences
𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = π‘₯ 2 + 𝑦 2
Increasing marginal utility (in each
variable):
π‘ˆπ‘₯ = 2π‘₯
π‘ˆπ‘¦ = 2𝑦
π‘₯
236
The marginality condition without
convexity
𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = π‘₯ 2 + 𝑦 2
The tangency point might be the
worst point on the line
π‘₯
237
Examples of increasing marginal utility
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = π‘₯ 2 + 𝑦 2
•
π‘₯, 𝑦 – minutes of watching a movie
•
π‘₯, 𝑦 – amount of heroin and cocaine
•
π‘₯, 𝑦 – practice time of two athletes for the
Olympic games
238
Convex preferences
𝑦
The “better than” sets
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 ≥ 𝑐
are convex,
(for every 𝑐)
π‘₯
239
How can we tell if preferences are convex?
𝑦
•
Drawing “better than” sets
•
Comparing the slope (marginal rate
of substitution) of the curve along it
•
And another useful rule:
π‘₯
240
A sufficient condition for convex preferences
If it so happens that
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = π‘ˆ1 π‘₯ + π‘ˆ2 𝑦
where each of π‘ˆ1 and π‘ˆ2 is concave (in its own variable)
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = π‘Ž ∗ π‘₯ + 𝑏 ∗ 𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = π‘Ž ∗ π‘™π‘œπ‘” π‘₯ + 𝑏 ∗ π‘™π‘œπ‘”(𝑦)
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = π‘Ž ∗ π‘₯ + 𝑏 ∗ π‘™π‘œπ‘”(𝑦)
… then the preferences are convex
241
How come that concave π‘ˆ1 π‘ˆ2
imply convex preferences?
𝑦
•
Assume they are concave
•
Decreasing marginal utility of each
product
•
And we get a less steep indifference
curve as we slide downwards (and to
the right)
π‘₯
242
The importance of convexity
•
As we just argued, it simplifies our lives as economists who
try to predict choices
•
But it also makes the optimization story more likely
•
How does the household “behave as if” it were maximizing a
utility function?
•
Under convexity: small improvements would lead to an
optimal solution
243
Consumer theory:
Comparative statics /
Sensitivity analysis
244
Consumer theory:
Changes in income
245
Changing income 𝐼
• ICC—Income-Consumption Curve
• Its habitat is the consumption bundles space
• Income isn’t represented graphically
•
Ernst Engel 1821-1896
Engel Curve
•
Lives in the Income-Good (quantity) space
•
The quantities of the other goods are not
represented graphically
246
The ICC for CD preferences
π‘₯=π‘Ž
1
𝐼
𝑝π‘₯
𝑦 = (1 − π‘Ž)
1
𝐼
𝑝𝑦
Recall that these preferences are
homothetic:
𝑦
ICC
The slope
π‘ˆπ‘₯
π‘ˆπ‘¦
is constant along any
ray that emanates from the origin
0,0
π‘₯
247
The Engel Curve
Consider the optimal solution
𝟏
𝒙=𝒂 𝑰
𝒑𝒙
π‘₯
1
𝑦 = (1 − π‘Ž) 𝐼
𝑝𝑦
Focus on the demand for one good
and observe how it changes as a
function of income
𝐼
248
The Engel curve and income elasticity
𝒙=𝒂
𝟏
𝑰
𝒑𝒙
1
𝑦 = (1 − π‘Ž) 𝐼
𝑝𝑦
πœ‚π‘₯𝐼 =
π‘₯
πœ•π‘₯
πœ•πΌ
π‘₯
𝐼
=
π‘Ž
𝑝π‘₯
π‘Ž
𝑝π‘₯
=1
For CD preferences,
income elasticity is 1
πœ‚π‘₯𝐼 ≡ 1 if and only if the demand for
π‘₯ is a linear function of income, that
is π‘₯ = 𝑐𝐼 for some 𝑐
𝐼
249
The general concept of elasticity
• Given a function 𝑧 = 𝑧(𝑀) we wonder how sensitive 𝑧 is relative to
changes in 𝑀
• We have the (partial) derivative
πœ•π‘§
πœ•π‘€
• But we want a “pure” measure, independent of measurement units:
πœ•π‘§
πœ‚π‘§,𝑀 = πœ•π‘€
𝑧
𝑀
250
Elasticity
πœ‚π‘§,𝑀
πœ•π‘§
πœ•π‘§
𝑧
= πœ•π‘€
=
𝑧
πœ•π‘€
𝑀
𝑀
Constant elasticity:
𝑧 = π‘Žπ‘€ 𝑐 , (π‘Ž > 0) ⟺ πœ‚π‘§,𝑀 = 𝑐
For instance:
𝑧 = π‘Žπ‘€ ⟺ πœ‚π‘§,𝑀 = +1
π‘Ž
𝑧 = ⟺ πœ‚π‘§,𝑀 = −1
𝑀
251
Constant Elasticity
If
𝑧 = π‘Žπ‘€ 𝑐
Then
πœ‚π‘§,𝑀
πœ•π‘§
𝑐−1
𝑐−1
π‘Žπ‘π‘€
π‘Žπ‘π‘€
= πœ•π‘€
𝑧 = π‘Žπ‘€ 𝑐 /𝑀 = π‘Žπ‘€ 𝑐−1 = 𝑐
𝑀
252
Constant Elasticity – cont.
And if
πœ‚π‘§,𝑀 =
πœ•π‘§
πœ•π‘€
𝑧
𝑀
=
πœ•π‘§
𝑧
πœ•π‘€
𝑀
=𝑐
Then
πœ•π‘§
𝑧
𝑑 log 𝑧
for
and
=cβˆ™
πœ•π‘€
𝑀
= 𝑐 βˆ™ 𝑑 log 𝑀
log 𝑧 = 𝑐 βˆ™ log 𝑀 + 𝑏 = log 𝑀 𝑐 + log(𝑒 𝑏 ) = log π‘Žπ‘€ 𝑐
π‘Ž = 𝑒𝑏
𝑧 = π‘Žπ‘€ 𝑐
253
Responses to income changes
πœ‚π‘₯,𝐼 > 0 – π‘₯ increases, a “normal” good
πœ‚π‘₯,𝐼 = 0 – π‘₯ doesn’t change, a “neutral good”
πœ‚π‘₯,𝐼 < 0 – π‘₯ decreases, an “inferior” good in a certain range
… why “in a certain range” ?
254
Further distinction among normal goods:
πœ‚π‘₯,𝐼 > 1
– a luxury good
πœ‚π‘₯,𝐼 = 1
– a proportional good
0 < πœ‚π‘₯,𝐼 < 1
– a basic/essential good
255
For CD preferences
We got
πœ‚π‘₯,𝐼 = πœ‚π‘¦,𝐼 = 1
And this makes sense: if there are only two goods, and one has
income elasticity of 1, so should the other one:
𝑝π‘₯ π‘₯ + 𝑝𝑦 𝑦 = 𝐼
Suppose we increase income by 1%
𝑝π‘₯ (1.01)π‘₯ + 𝑝𝑦 (1+? )𝑦 = (1.01)𝐼
256
More generally
Some weighted average of income elasticities (across all
goods) is equal to 1
α πœ‚π‘₯,𝐼 + 1 − α πœ‚π‘¦,𝐼 = 1
Hence it is impossible that all goods be luxury goods
Or that all be basic goods
257
The ICC for linear preferences
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = π‘Žπ‘₯ + 𝑏𝑦
Surely homothetic:
𝑦
The slope
π‘ˆπ‘₯
π‘ˆπ‘¦
=
π‘Ž
𝑏
is constant not
only along each ray (emanating
from the origin), but also across
rays
π‘₯
258
ICC for linear preferences – cont.
If we have
𝑝π‘₯ π‘Ž
>
𝑝𝑦 𝑏
𝑦
That is
ICC
𝑏
π‘Ž
>
𝑝𝑦 𝑝π‘₯
The solution is
π‘₯ =0
1
𝑦= 𝐼
𝑝𝑦
π‘₯
259
Engel Curve for linear preferences
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = π‘Žπ‘₯ + 𝑏𝑦
Say,
𝑝π‘₯
𝑝𝑦
>
π‘Ž
𝑏
The optimal solution is
π‘₯=0
1
𝑦= 𝐼
𝑝𝑦
π‘₯
𝑦
𝐼
𝐼
260
The ICC for linear preferences…
And if
𝑝π‘₯ π‘Ž
<
𝑝𝑦 𝑏
𝑦
That is
𝑏
π‘Ž
<
𝑝𝑦 𝑝π‘₯
The solution is
π‘₯ =
ICC
1
𝐼
𝑝π‘₯
𝑦=0
π‘₯
261
Engel Curve for linear preferences
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = π‘Žπ‘₯ + 𝑏𝑦
π‘₯ =
Say,
𝑝π‘₯
𝑝𝑦
<
π‘Ž
𝑏
The optimal solution is
1
𝐼
𝑝π‘₯
𝑦=0
π‘₯
𝑦
𝐼
𝐼
262
The ICC yet again
Wait, but what if
𝑝π‘₯ π‘Ž
=
𝑝𝑦 𝑏
𝑦
That is,
𝑏
π‘Ž
=
𝑝𝑦 𝑝π‘₯
ICC
?
Any point on the budget line is a solution
and the ICC becomes the entire orthant
π‘₯
263
Consumer theory:
Changes in price
264
Changing price 𝑝π‘₯
•
•
•
PCC (Price Consumption Curve)
•
Resides in the bundles space
•
Price isn’t represented graphically
Demand curve
•
Resides in the price-quantity space (for a given good)
•
The other quantities are not represented graphically
Demand and cross demand curve
265
The PCC for CD preferences
π‘₯=π‘Ž
1
𝐼
𝑝π‘₯
𝑦 = (1 − π‘Ž)
1
𝐼
𝑝𝑦
𝑦
𝐼
𝑝𝑦
PCC(1)
π‘₯
266
Demand curve
π‘₯
1
π‘₯=π‘Ž 𝐼
𝑝π‘₯
πœ‚π‘₯𝑝π‘₯ =
(πœ‚π‘₯𝑝π‘₯ ≡ −1
πœ•π‘₯
πœ•π‘π‘₯
π‘₯
𝑝π‘₯
=
π‘ŽπΌ
𝑝π‘₯ 2
π‘ŽπΌ
𝑝π‘₯ 2
−
= −1
hyperbola )
𝑝π‘₯
267
Cross demand curve
𝑦
(1 − π‘Ž)
1
𝑦 = (1 − π‘Ž) 𝐼
𝑝𝑦
1
𝐼
𝑝𝑦
πœ‚π‘₯𝑝𝑦 =
πœ•π‘₯
πœ•π‘π‘¦
π‘₯
𝑝𝑦
(πœ‚π‘₯𝑝𝑦 ≡ 0
=0
constant)
𝑝π‘₯
268
The slope of the demand curve
π‘₯
We’d expect
πœ‚π‘₯𝑝π‘₯ < 0
And this is indeed typical. Almost
always true. Why almost?
𝑝π‘₯
269
What happens when a price changes?
Suppose 𝑝π‘₯ ↑
𝑝′π‘₯ > 𝑝π‘₯
𝐼
𝑝𝑦
𝐼
𝑝′π‘₯
•
The budget line is “tighter”
•
Its slope changes, too
𝐼
𝑝π‘₯
270
Income and substitution effects
𝑝′π‘₯ > 𝑝π‘₯
Indeed
𝐼
𝑝𝑦
π‘₯𝐡 < π‘₯𝐴
Why?
A
B
π‘₯𝐡 𝐼 π‘₯𝐴
𝑝′π‘₯
•
The consumer is “poorer”
•
The price ratio has changed
𝐼
𝑝π‘₯
271
Trying to tell these apart
Budget line C goes through the old point, but with the
𝐼
𝑝𝑦
new slope
C
(π‘₯𝐡 −π‘₯𝐴 )
=
π‘₯𝐡 − π‘₯𝐢 + (π‘₯𝐢 − π‘₯𝐴 )
Overall change = income effect + substitution effect
A
B
π‘₯𝐡
𝐼
𝑝′π‘₯
π‘₯𝐴
𝐼
𝑝π‘₯
272
For example
𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = log π‘₯ + log 𝑦
60
𝐼 = 120, 𝑝π‘₯ = 2, 𝑝𝑦 = 2
π‘₯=
1 1
𝐼
2 𝑝π‘₯
𝑦=
1 1
𝐼
2 𝑝𝑦
=
1 1
βˆ™ βˆ™
2 2
=
1 1
βˆ™
2 2
120 = 30
A
𝑦𝐴 = 30
π‘₯𝐴 = 30
60
βˆ™ 120 = 30
π‘₯
273
Suppose the price has gone up
𝑦
𝑝π‘₯′ = 3 > 2 = 𝑝π‘₯
60
From budget line A
𝐴 2,2,120 → 30,30
We switch to line B
𝑦𝐴 = 30
B
A
π‘₯𝐡 = 20 π‘₯𝐴 = 30
𝐡 3,2,120 → 20,30
60
π‘₯
274
Introduce the third budget line
𝐢 3,2, ?
The price are the new ones 3,2
Which level of income would go through
𝐴 30,30 ?
𝐼 = 3 βˆ™ 30 + 2 βˆ™ 30 = 90 + 60 = 150
275
Hence we compare between…
𝐴 2,2,120 → 30,30
60
𝐡 3,2,120 → 20,30
C
𝐢 3,2,150 → 25,37.5
A
20 − 30
B
=
20 − 25
+ (25 − 30)
Overall change = income effect + substitution effect
π‘₯𝐡 = 20 π‘₯𝐴 = 30
π‘₯𝐢 = 25
60
276
The substitution effect cannot be positive
π‘₯
If the price of a good goes up, the
substitution effect will not make us
C
want more of it
A
𝑝π‘₯
277
The substitution effect can be zero
π‘₯
Say
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = min(π‘₯, 𝑦)
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = 𝑐
A,C
𝑝π‘₯
278
Income effect
Price increase
real income has gone down
The income effect is
•
negative for a normal good
•
zero for a neutral good
•
positive for an inferior good
For a normal good the income and substitution effects are in the same
direction
279
Giffen goods
•
For inferior goods, the income and substitution
effects are in opposite directions
•
Typically, the substitution effect is stronger (that’s
an empirical fact)
•
If this isn’t the case, the good is referred to as a
Giffen good.
Robert Giffen 1837-1910
πœ‚π‘₯𝑝π‘₯ > 0
280
Let us not confuse Giffen goods with
• Uncertainty about quality (a $10 Rolex)
• conspicuous consumption
281
Compensations: Slutsky and Hicks
Back to the example
60
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = log π‘₯ + log 𝑦
𝐼 = 120
C
37.5
𝑝π‘₯ = 2, 𝑝′π‘₯ = 3, 𝑝𝑦 = 2
A
30
B
Suppose that the consumer is compensated so
that she can consume bundle A
π‘₯𝐡 = 20 π‘₯𝐴 = 30
π‘₯𝐢 = 25
60
282
What’s the impact on utility?
𝑝π‘₯ , 𝑝𝑦 , 𝐼 → π‘₯, 𝑦 → 𝑉 π‘₯, 𝑦
𝑉 π‘₯, 𝑦 = π‘₯𝑦
[π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = log π‘₯ + log 𝑦 ]
𝐴 2,2,120 →
30,30
→
900
𝐡 3,2,120 →
20,30
→
600
𝐢 3,2,150 →
25,37.5 → 937.5
Evgeny Evgenievich Slutsky 1880-1948
150 – the compensated income, according to Slutsky
Slutsky compensation: 150-120=30
283
Neither shocked nor upset
𝑦
•
60
It’s natural that rotating the budget line
around a point (A) would change the
C
optimal bundle
•
A
60
And that’s perfectly fine with us…
π‘₯
284
However
𝑦
• Maybe the compensation shouldn’t be
60
that high?
• Maybe it’s enough to go back to the old
D
utility level, rather than the old physical
A
quantities (which are no longer
30
optimal)?
30
60
π‘₯
285
The compensation according to Hicks
Consider the table again
𝑝π‘₯ , 𝑝𝑦 , 𝐼
→
π‘₯, 𝑦
𝐴 2,2,120 →
30,30
→ 900
𝐡 3,2,120 →
20,30
→ 600
𝐢 3,2,150 →
25,37.5 → 937.5
𝐷 3,2, ?
→
π‘₯, 𝑦
→ 𝑉 π‘₯, 𝑦
John Hicks 1904-1989
→ 900
286
Hicks compensation – cont.
For 3,2, 𝐼 we have
1 1
1
π‘₯ = βˆ™ βˆ™πΌ = 𝐼
2 3
6
1 1
1
𝑦 = βˆ™ βˆ™πΌ = 𝐼
2 2
4
To get 𝑉 π‘₯, 𝑦 = π‘₯𝑦 = 900 we will require
1 1
𝐼 βˆ™ 𝐼 = 900
4 6
𝐼2 = 900 βˆ™ 24 = 21,600
𝐼 = 146.96
287
The compensations of Slutsky and Hicks
Slutzky: changes income to be able to be consume the
original bundle
Hicks: changes income to be able to be consume at the
original utility level
Hicks' sounds more fair, but requires knowledge (/estimation)
of the utility function
288
The PCC for linear preferences
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = π‘Žπ‘₯ + 𝑏𝑦
𝑦
𝐼
𝑝𝑦
If
𝑝π‘₯
𝑝𝑦
<
π‘Ž
𝑏
the solution is
If
𝑝π‘₯
𝑝𝑦
>
π‘Ž
𝑏
the solution is 0,
PCC(1)
If
𝑝π‘₯
𝑝𝑦
=
π‘Ž
𝑏
𝐼
,0
𝑝π‘₯
𝐼
𝑝𝑦
it's any point in between
π‘₯
289
The demand "function"
π‘₯
For 𝑝π‘₯ <
π‘Ž
𝑝
𝑏 𝑦
𝐼
𝑝π‘₯
it's π‘₯ =
For 𝑝π‘₯ >
π‘Ž
𝑝
𝑏 𝑦
it's π‘₯ = 0
π‘Ž
𝑏
(And for 𝑝π‘₯ = 𝑝𝑦 any value 0 ≤ π‘₯ ≤
𝐼
𝑝π‘₯
)
The elasticity is
πœ‚π‘₯𝑝π‘₯ ≡ −1
π‘Ž
π‘Ž
𝑝
𝑏 𝑦
𝑝π‘₯
in the range 𝑝π‘₯ < π‘π’š and not well
𝑏
defined outside it
290
The cross demand "function"
𝑦
π‘Ž
𝑏
For 𝑝π‘₯ < 𝑝𝑦 it's 𝑦 = 0
For 𝑝π‘₯ >
π‘Ž
𝑝
𝑏 𝑦
it's 𝑦 =
𝐼
𝑝𝑦
π‘Ž
𝑏
(And for 𝑝π‘₯ = 𝑝𝑦 any value 0 ≤ 𝑦 ≤
𝐼
𝑝𝑦
𝐼
𝑝𝑦
)
The elasticity is
πœ‚π‘¦π‘π‘₯ ≡ 0
π‘Ž
π‘Ž
𝑝
𝑏 𝑦
𝑝π‘₯
in the range 𝑝π‘₯ > π‘π’š and not well
𝑏
defined outside it
291
An example of a Giffen good
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = min π‘₯ + 𝑦, 100 + 0.5π‘₯
Both goods can satisfy hunger, but only good 1 has nutritional value
π‘₯ – amount of nuts
𝑦 – amount of Styrofoam
π‘₯ + 𝑦 – total amount that fills the stomach
0.5π‘₯ – amount of nutritional food
100 + 0.5π‘₯ – the addition of 100 guarantees that the consumer starts seeking
nutrition only after the hunger is somewhat satisfied
292
Describing the preferences
𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = min π‘₯ + 𝑦, 100 + 0.5π‘₯
Which need is the dominant one? Hunger or
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = 100 + 0.5π‘₯
nutrition? This depends on
π‘₯ + 𝑦 β‹› 100 + 0.5π‘₯
100
or
𝑦 β‹› 100 − 0.5π‘₯
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = π‘₯ + 𝑦
200
π‘₯
293
Indifference curves
𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = min π‘₯ + 𝑦, 100 + 0.5π‘₯
We distinguish between the two regions:
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = 100 + 0.5π‘₯
π‘₯ + 𝑦 β‹› 100 + 0.5π‘₯
100
𝑦 β‹› 100 − 0.5π‘₯
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = π‘₯ + 𝑦
200
π‘₯
294
Let’s get the budget line into the picture
𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = min π‘₯ + 𝑦, 100 + 0.5π‘₯
𝑝π‘₯ π‘₯ + 𝑝𝑦 𝑦 = 𝐼
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = 100 + 0.5π‘₯
And if
𝑝π‘₯ < 𝑝𝑦
100
The consumer will only buy the first good
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = π‘₯ + 𝑦
200
π‘₯
295
And this will be true for any income
𝑦
As long as
𝑝π‘₯ < 𝑝𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = 100 + 0.5π‘₯
Only the first good is consumed
100
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = π‘₯ + 𝑦
200
π‘₯
296
The interesting case
𝑦
If
𝑝π‘₯ > 𝑝𝑦
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = 100 + 0.5π‘₯
100
– for low income the optimal bundle is on
the 𝑦 axis
– for high income the optimal bundle is on
the π‘₯ axis
– and in between on the dotted line
π‘ˆ π‘₯, 𝑦 = π‘₯ + 𝑦
200
π‘₯
297
The ICC
𝑦
If
𝑝π‘₯ > 𝑝𝑦
– The ICC will first climb up the 𝑦 axis
– then it will slide down the dotted line
100
– and finally – flatten onto the π‘₯ axis
200
π‘₯
– along the dotted line the second
good is inferior
298
Next consider a change in price
Let’s start with
𝑝π‘₯ > 𝑝𝑦 ,
and increase 𝑝𝑦
𝑦
𝐼 < 200𝑝π‘₯
At low prices the optimal solution will be on the
dotted line
100
When 𝑝𝑦 is high enough, the optimal solution will
be on the 𝑦 axis
𝐼/𝑝π‘₯
200
π‘₯
And when 𝑝π‘₯ is higher (above 𝑝π‘₯ ) – on the π‘₯ axis
299
A possible PCC
𝑦
Importantly, there is a range in which it
goes down
In this range, an increase in the price of
100
good 2 (𝑝𝑦 ) results in an increase in the
demanded quantity 𝑦
200
π‘₯
300
Download