HeyJ LVI (2015), pp. 454–546 BOOK REVIEWS The Hemlock Cup: Socrates, Athens and the Search for the Good Life. By Bettany Hughes. Pp. xl, 486, London, Jonathan Cape, 2010, £25.00. The Ironic Defense of Socrates: Plato’s Apology. By David Leibowitz. Pp. ix, 194, Cambridge University Press, 2010, $64.00/£50.00. Bettany Hughes’ new book is a work of popular or journalistic history, rather than of scholarship sensu stricto. Written both by and for the enthusiast, it has the strengths and weaknesses of its kind. On the plus side, it is well enough written to draw readers in to the narrative and well enough structured to make a good read; on the minus side, there are exaggerations (often resulting from no more than her breezy style), occasional inaccuracies, unsupported assertions, philosophical naivety and a bit of repetition (the book is written in a deliberately sprawling fashion). The information is, on the whole, reliable, but, for instance, she trusts the sources far more than any academic would. The book purports to be a ‘biography of Socrates’, but it is far more than that. It sets Socrates and his trial in their historical and cultural contexts, with plenty of information, even of a microhistorical kind, about ancient Athens both before and during Socrates’ lifetime. She focuses particularly on his relation to Alcibiades, and on the devastating effects of the Peloponnesian War on Athenian spirits before the trial. There are other books that successfully do exactly this, however, for the same or similar audience, and one wonders whether the book is really needed. She is fascinated by the material culture of Athens, and some of the best bits of the book report recent archaeological discoveries with enthusiasm (but she goes too far when she claims that Socrates can be revealed by the material remains). Throughout, the narrative is supported by plenty of excerpts from ancient authors. Naturally, Hughes’ book revolves around the central facts of Socrates’ life – his trial and death. Plato’s Apology – the defence speech he put posthumously into his mentor’s mouth – is the sole focus of Leibowitz’s book. His thesis is that the speech is far more ironic than is usually noticed, and that this leads one inevitably to some startling conclusions. The first chapter, nominally about the prooemium of the speech, is actually a justification of his approach. He finds the jury and Socrates so far apart that Socrates is bound to lie to them; he finds that Socrates will speak on two levels at once, for the uninitiated jury and for the more enlightened, or ‘careful’, members of the audience (see e.g. p. 59); this is irony, and the method of leaving a trail of hints is a good teaching method because it allows us to discover for ourselves. In other words, Leibowitz has cleverly found a way of justifying his Straussian agenda, to read Apology as a text with subterranean layers that can only now be revealed. Subsequent chapters proceed by minute interrogation of the text, in such an orderly fashion that it reads like an extended commentary. Sometimes the questions Leibowitz asks are fresh and interesting; sometimes, they are not the kinds of questions an author could conceivably expect to be asked of his text, and therefore come close to the documentary fallacy of asking questions from outside the universe of the text. The same goes for his frequent reference to other dialogues as aids to understanding Apology. But in actual fact, despite his somewhat tortuous approach, most of Leibowitz’s conclusions are unsurprising. Mainly, he rediscovers the defects that others have found in the speech as a defence: that Socrates never really replies to the charge of failing to worship the city’s gods; that the entire defence is designed to work only if the dikasts were already convinced Socratics; that he explains away rather than answering the corruption charge; that he appears to scorn and provoke both the dikasts and his prosecutors. For Leibowitz, the first defect is a deliberate hint by Socrates that he is in fact a natural scientist, while the second and third are part and parcel of Socrates’ speaking at two levels at once. It is interesting to see how his Straussian approach reaches the same point as more conventional methodologies. There is a good deal of over-interpretation and explicit speculation in the book, but it is intelligent, C 2015 Trustees for Roman Catholic Purposes Registered. Published by JohnWiley & Sons Ltd, 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK and V 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA. BOOK REVIEWS clearly written, and thought-provoking. Plato’s Apology perennially disturbs its readers; used with caution, Leibowitz’s commentary will enable readers to discover some of the subtleties and delights 455 of the text, and to puzzle over exactly what kind of defence speech it was supposed to be. Lakonia, Greece Robin Waterfield Eros and Socratic Political Philosophy. By David Levy. Pp. ix, 202, New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2013, £57.50/$90.00. The book is essentially a study of Plato on eros. Levy devotes a chapter each to Symposium and Phaedrus, the two main dialogues on love, but also to Republic, because it seems to disparage love, while the other two dialogues praise it. The political dimension promised by the book’s title emerges as Levy considers Plato’s position on the family in Republic, which appears to involve a suppression of erotic attachments, and the role of eros in a tyrant’s soul. Levy’s overall intentions are to reconcile the apparent discrepancies between Plato’s accounts of eros, and to show the relation of eros to political life. The reconciliation he seeks is not that of developmentalism, such that Plato’s views on eros evolved over time. He believes that there is a common core to the various passages on eros, and in fact that Plato restricts the term eros to interpersonal relationships, leaving the philosophic life ‘profoundly unerotic’ (8). This is because eros opens us to the gods, and religious beliefs may, in their irrationality, oppose philosophy and so threaten the rule of the philosopher kings. It seems to me that certain aspects of this project are radically ill-conceived. Levy’s attitude towards love is post-romantic. He claims (2) that ‘lovers for millennia have believed that Plato understood the depths of their own hearts’, when a highly influential paper by Vlastos took Plato to task precisely for the impersonality of his approach to love; he claims (4) that the family is an arena for eros, which is very far from clear in a preHellenistic Greek context. And Levy’s original claim, that the philosophic life is unerotic, clashes with a number of passages in the dialogues where eros and philosophy are linked, such as Gorgias 481d. At Republic 474c-475c, 485a-e, 490b and 499c Plato says explicitly that his philosopherrules must be gripped by eros for philosophy. So far from being threatened by eros, they make use of its energy. Levy pays insufficient attention to these passages. So, his study of Republic (Chapter 1) concludes by attempting to detach eros from the philosophic life and by connecting it instead to irrational religious beliefs. But what is this connection? Levy finds the answer in Phaedrus (Chapter 2): thanks to its eros, the soul grows wings that take it up to the gods. But this conclusion again operates in something of a vacuum: yes, granted that the soul’s wings take it up to the level of the gods, but they also allow it to see the Forms. In other words, in Phaedrus too, eros is central to the philosophic life. Levy’s study of Symposium (Chapter 3) faces the problem that the ascent passage, in which the ascent is apparently motivated by eros, is surely a philosopher’s ascent. So how will he detach eros from the philosophic life this time? He does so by restricting the domain of eros, properly speaking, to interpersonal relationships, and then noting that during the ascent the aspirant moves away from interpersonal relationships (which is in itself a controversial interpretation). But, again, it seems to me that this position can be maintained only at some distance from the text, for it seems explicit that eros governs the entire ascent from beginning to end. Even if the term does not appear for a page or two of the text, the ascent passage begins, obviously, with a strong emphasis on eros, and ends with the general conclusion that ‘in the business of acquiring immortality [i.e. becoming a philosopher] it would be hard to find a better partner than eros’ (212b). While I disagree fundamentally with much of this book, it must be said that, unlike the wilful obfuscation practised by many of its postmodern peers, it is at least well written. But the main theses seem to me to be so flawed that I can only recommend caution in approaching the book. Lakonia, Greece Robin Waterfield New Essays on Plato: Language and Thought in Fourth-century Greek Philosophy. Edited by Fritz-Gregor Herrmann. Pp. viii, 227, Swansea: The Classical Press of Wales, 2006, £45.00. The essays in this volume stem from an unthemed Plato conference in Glasgow in 2002. The editor points out that all the contributors take words, phrases and concepts as the foundation of their studies, but that is hardly a unique tactic, and the book is best approached simply as a collection of 456 BOOK REVIEWS good essays, by some of the best (mainly younger) scholars working on Plato today. R.F. Stalley considers how Plato handles the issues surrounding the familiar distinction between law and justice in four early dialogues. He finds that uncertainties and unclarities in Euthyphro, Apology and Crito are all resolved in Gorgias: while recognizing a higher order of justice which human laws could violate, Plato also recognizes that some laws embody principles that are fundamental to legal order of any kind; it is in one’s interest to observe proper laws because doing so maintains good order in one’s soul. Verity Harte teases some useful insights into Plato’s epistemology out of his analogy of mistaking something for something else which it resembles. In what amounts to little more than an extended footnote, Herrmann then traces the history of the word ousia in Plato’s early dialogues, distinguishing its usage as a metaphysical term, referring to what something really is, from a usage that is closer to its everyday meaning as ‘property’. The former usage Herrmann claims derives from Philolaus. In a packed, interesting paper, Stefan B€uttner revisits the tripartite soul. He finds that the three parts are aspects of a single soul; that the soul’s essential cognitive function is to distinguish things (which it therefore does in three different ways); that the distinction between feeling and thinking is modern and should not be imposed on Plato, for whom all forms of cognition involve feeling; and that the three parts of the soul therefore desire their appropriate pleasures. Antony Hatzistavrou tackles the old question of whether rulership compromises the philosopher-king’s happiness and argues that it doesn’t, because a philosopher-king is at least in part fulfilled by rulership. This is not an original conclusion, but he approaches the matter by finding an implicit distinction in Plato’s use of the word physis, as ‘natural capacity’ or ‘developed personality’. Patricia Clarke conducts a largely linguistic enquiry into Theaetetus 152a, and concludes that it would be wrong to restrict Protagoras’s view to beliefs, rather than perceptions, or some combination of the two. Against the run of recent commentary, Vasilis Politis defends a ‘tiered’ interpretation of Sophist 248e-249d, that makes it at least compatible with Plato’s middle-period ontology. Of course, if correct, this raises more questions than it answers, but the paper is well argued. Andrew Mason introduces the curious, but possibly correct notion of ‘degrees of eternity’ to solve a puzzle in Timaeus: how Plato can think of both the changing world as a whole and the changeable forms as eternal. Finally Stephen Halliwell challenges the view (powerful support for the traditional way of reading Plato’s dialogues) that Aristotle regarded the views put forward by Socrates (and others) in Plato’s dialogues as Plato’s own. Much of the paper considers a single sentence in Aristotle (Politics 1265a10-13), and concludes that while Aristotle was impressed with Plato’s style, he was less inclined to attribute the ideas to the author, rather than just to engage with them as ideas. One of the contributors mentions in a note that her paper had been given at, among other venues, the ‘Old Chestnuts’ Greek philosophy seminar at King’s College, London. By and large each of these papers revisits well-trodden territory. This makes the volume as a whole seem solid rather than exciting – but ‘solid’ has a lot to commend it in times when so much flaky stuff is being written about Plato. Lakonia, Greece Robin Waterfield The Painter of Constitutions: Selected Essays on Plato’s Republic. Edited by Mario Vegetti, Franco Ferrari and Tosca Lynch. Pp. 344, Sankt Augustin, Academic Verlag, 2013, e54.00. Within the scholarly community, the strongest argument for the adoption of Esperanto, or (better) the revival of Latin as a common language, is based on the frustration of being unable to read others’ work, communicate freely at conferences, and so on. Many English-speaking scholars are admirably fluent in one or more modern languages, but there are always languages with which one struggles, resulting in the uncomfortable feeling that one has missed nuances intended by the writer or speaker. In ancient philosophy, in addition to all the European languages, there is good work going on in Japanese and I have heard that the field is opening up in China too. The frustration is increased, naturally, the more important the foreign-language work. One of the most impressive projects in ancient philosophical studies in Italy over recent years has been the publication, in seven fat volumes, of a multi-authored commentary on Plato’s Republic, that perennial source of scholarly interest, under the general editorship of Mario Vegetti. Each of these volumes contains an introduction, an annotated translation of whichever book or books are covered by that volume, followed by a BOOK REVIEWS series of interpretative essays by various hands. The book here under review is a selection of fifteen of these essays (not always quite under their original Italian titles), culled from all seven volumes. The book consists of a very brief preface, the essays, and then a combined bibliography. The essays tend to be introductory rather than arguments for abstruse theses, and so should in theory be good for students, but density of expression, combined with the occasional grammatical error and infelicity in the translations somewhat hinder comprehension. Vegetti demonstrates the importance of Thrasymachus’ contribution; the entire dialogue is a response to him. Gastaldi gives us a thorough evaluation (in 45 pages) of Plato’s criticisms of poetry as imitative and his project to revise such work for the purposes of his ideal city. Calabi (in 7 pages) reads the Noble Lie as Plato’s attempt to provide the city with a founding myth. De Luise and Farinetti tackle the question of ‘the unhappiness of the guardians and the happiness of the polis’; they grasp the nettle and accept that the guardians must sacrifice some of their happiness, or learn to redefine their happiness, for the sake of the greater good. Vegetti next gives us a sound response to the question whether Plato intended his ‘ideal city’ to be practicable: it is not in itself practicable, but as a paradigm it has practical effects. In a similar mode, Ferrari argues that the apparent uselessness of Forms for guiding politicians working in the real world is offset by their acting as paradigms (and so that the two-world theory remains valid). Next, Vegetti surveys the multiple functions of the Form of the Good in Republic, and then Ferrari focuses on its role as cause – as final cause of human action, but also as responsible for knowledge of Forms and the being of Forms. In the course of his discussion, Ferrari considered the Sun metaphor; next Repellini turns to the Line and the 457 Cave, in a speculative attempt to align the different phases or stages of the two images. Vegetti next considers ‘dialectics’ as a methodical ascent to the Idea of the Good and descent to its application, via the interrelated network of Forms now seen as good. Its function is not just epistemological – guaranteeing the veracity of beliefs – but also ethical, in that it provides a basis for connecting truth with value. Cattanei next surveys the state of mathematics (arithmetic, geometry, stereometry) in Plato’s time and the reforms he was proposing so that the mathematical sciences would not just draw philosophers away from contemplating the material world, but would also be useful in warfare. Plato’s remarks on harmonics receive their own chapter, with an essay by Meriani, highlighting Plato’s disdain for an empirical approach to the subject. Bertelli considers Plato’s criticism of democracy and oligarchy, against the background of Plato’s own experiences as a citizen of Athens, and snippets of information from other dialogues. Against a trend of recent scholarship, he finds Plato totally opposed to democracy, as well as oligarchy. Gastaldi rightly sees the happiness of the just man (proof of which is the whole point of Republic) as lying in his psychic harmony. Finally (in a rather better translated contribution than most), Fronterotta considers Plato’s language in Book 10 in so far as it seems to imply that the Forms are created by some demiurge and concludes that this is a metaphor, useful to persuade ordinary, nonAcademic readers. There is enough here to whet the appetite, and make those of us who struggle with Italian wish we could now go on to the main course, the sevenvolume version. Lakonia, Greece Robin Waterfield Ancient Approaches to Plato’s Republic. Edited by Anne Sheppard. Pp. v, 137, London: Institute of Classical Studies, 2013, £24.00. Confining itself strictly to the reception of Plato’s Republic by ancient authors (rather than Byzantine or medieval authors, say), this slim volume contains seven disparate essays arising from a London seminar series some years ago. The introduction is brief and uninformative, then there are the seven chapters, then an index of passages cited. John Finamore surveys the passages of De anima where Aristotle criticizes the Platonic idea that the soul has parts. He concludes that Aristotle’s fundamental notion is that, given the range and complexity of psychic faculties, the soul is too complex to be encapsulated in just three parts. Jed Atkins shows that, rather than seeing, as the majority of modern scholars do, some deep incompatibilities between Republic and Laws, Cicero acknowledged their differences but saw them as complementing each other, as Aristotle and a few modern scholars do. He took Republic 458 BOOK REVIEWS to be largely about constitutions (and of course especially the ‘best’ one, Kallipolis), and Laws, being largely about laws, as the completion of Republic. J.G.F. Powell argues that Cicero’s engagement with Plato in De re publica and De legibus is far more than ‘ornamental’. So far from rejecting Plato’s whole approach, his engagement was substantive and profound, and he believed that he was fundamentally involved in the same project as Plato: hence the homage of the book titles. The Middle Platonist view of how much of life is predetermined was heavily influenced by their reading of the Myth of Er that ends Republic. Taking Alcinous’ Didascalicus as a representative text, Erik Eliasson shows that the situation is not quite so straightforward, arguing that Alcinous reflects two different readings of the myth and gives two different versions of how much or little of life is ‘up to us’. James Wilberding also considers the Myth of Er, but now we are among the Neoplatonists. On Porphyry’s interpretation of the myth, souls do not specify their next incarnation in detail, but only in broad outline. Wilberding approves of this interpretation and recommends it to us as satisfying what we have been led to expect from the myth given its role in Republic. Anne Sheppard supplies some brief prolegomena to Proclus’ little-studied commentary on Republic, which comes in the form of a series of seventeen essays. She outlines their content and speculates that twelve of them were delivered as a course of lectures, and that the rest, with disparate contents, were added later. Finally, Sebastian Moro Tornese reflects on the role of music in Proclus’ commentaries on Timaeus and Republic. He pulls Proclus’ comments together and argues that they are essentially triadic – that music has the power to lead the soul from the sensible to the intelligible via an intermediary stage where nous is awoken and the soul is oriented (attuned) towards intelligible harmony. Lakonia, Greece Robin Waterfield Plato: Republic 1-2.368c4. Edited, with an introduction and commentary, by Chris Emlyn-Jones. Pp. vi, 194, Oxford, Oxbow (Aris & Phillips Classical Texts), 2007, £18.00. For many years now, Aris & Phillips have published a series of editions of classical texts, philosophical or otherwise, consisting basically of introduction, text with facing English translation, and commentary. The series broadly seems to be aimed at undergraduates and graduates with some knowledge of the relevant language, though the quality of the series is such that scholars working in the field always profit as well. This new edition of the opening moves of Plato’s Republic fits perfectly into the series, and will, I am sure, prove just as valuable as many of its shelf-fellows. Emlyn-Jones’s choice of text makes good sense, but an unusual book title! The first book of Republic approaches the topic of justice gradually, in the fashion of a typical ‘Socratic’ dialogue, or dialogue of search, by asking more or less amenable interlocutors what they think it might be. Once Socrates has demolished the first couple of replies, however, he is faced with a far more formidable opponent, the sophist Thrasymachus of Chalcedon, who not only challenges Socrates’ working methods, but also produces a radical definition of justice. The movement of the dialogue is thus reminiscent, as Emlyn-Jones points out (p. 9), of the earlier Gorgias. The dialogue is also rich in Plato’s dramatic flourishes, to which Emlyn-Jones is sensitive, while sensibly falling short of basing entire interpretations on just this. Thrasymachus, anyway, is made to express his position with such force and bluster that it has proved hard to extract a coherent position from his words. But whatever else he says, he claims that it is injustice, not justice, that benefits agents – justice being a position of subservience to the superior man or stronger government, who dictate what justice is. This is indeed an important point, and so when the first book ends inconclusively (and, again, typically of the dialogues of search), a fresh set of interlocutors begin the second book by restating at least this aspect of Thrasymachus’s case, and by challenging Socrates to prove that justice benefits agents in and of itself, even apart from its consequences. And this is the challenge Plato takes up in the rest of Republic. So Emlyn-Jones’s book, which finishes at the end of Glaucon and Adeimantus’s restatement, serves as a general introduction to Republic as a whole. In the introduction, he discusses general questions of style and composition and cultural background, before turning to an analysis of the arguments. He gives us a charitable interpretation of Cephalus, and a good analysis of the argument with Polemarchus, which leads him to wonder whether Plato is not having certain doubts about BOOK REVIEWS the Socratic method in general, or at least some of the arguments he typically deploys. Certainly, later in Republic Plato has Socrates express dissatisfaction with his performance in Book I. But the meat of the introduction lies in Emlyn-Jones’s attempt to unravel Thrasymachus’s position. He does a good job. He finds Thrasymachus to be generally consistent, holding that justice disadvantages its practitioner, and suggests, interestingly, that at least some of the apparent coherence is due to the way Socrates himself is made to pose the problem, so that Thrasymachus is doing no more than responding to Socrates on his own terms. He also makes the plausible suggestion that, in a sense, Socrates and Thrasymachus are arguing at cross-purposes (p. 24). The introduction ends with the easier task of clarifying Glaucon’s and Adeimantus’s speeches. The text is Slings’s Oxford Classical Text, with minimal apparatus. Emlyn-Jones lists a very few textual variants, and sometimes just for the sake of information, in that not all the variants are not dis- 459 cussed in the commentary. The translation is plain and modest; for instance, at a couple of points in the commentary, he expresses approval of slightly more racy versions of this or that phrase, but does not adopt them in his own version. This in a sense summarizes the approach of the whole book, which aims not so much to set the world alight, as to be useful. It succeeds admirably. The commentary, then, contains further analysis of arguments (those not already covered in the Introduction), and also discusses points of philosophy, philology, drama, history, mythology, and general background. We are rarely taken deep into the text, but we are given a good basis on which to think for ourselves about the issues raised by these opening arguments of what many regard as Plato’s greatest work. This will be a very useful edition for students, and scholars will profit from the introduction and some acute remarks in the commentary. Lakonia, Greece Robin Waterfield Plato’s Laws: Force and Truth in Politics. Edited by Gregory Recco and Eric Sanday. Pp. vii, 248, Indiana University Press, 2013, $25.00/£16.99. The intention of this volume is to provide a multi-authored commentary on Laws as a whole, or the most ‘fruitful’ aspects of it. So, of the fourteen chapters, the first two give us synopses, and the remaining twelve tackle some topic in Laws, starting with Book 1 in Chapter 3, and proceeding to Books 11 and 12 in Chapter 14. But, in their introduction, the editors pinpoint, as a common theme, the balance between coercive and consensual politics. Hence the book’s subtitle. In the first of the two synopses, Mitchell Miller stresses, via certain key passages, the secondbestness of Laws. Nevertheless, Miller believes that Plato still hopes to inspire his readers, and he goes on to reveal something of the artistry and structuring of this rather awkward dialogue. Next, Mark Munn relates the dialogue to its historical context. While acknowledging that, as a work of Plato’s, the dialogue has a certain timelessness, he sees the mood and some details as products of their times in the fourth century. Eric Salem guides us through Book 1, seeking to explain what he calls the ‘murkiness’ of the work. He attributes this to the non-Athenian setting (not conducive to philosophy), to the subject-matter, and to the Athenian Stranger’s need to get his interlocutors to trust him. John Russon tackles Book 2, which is concerned with education. Though the educational system seems quite ‘repressive’ (60), Russon believes that an alternative picture lurks beneath the surface. His delving for this alternative, less repressive, more flexible form of education seems to me somewhat strained. For instance, if in Book 1 everyone is treated as equal, and yet Book 6 talks of proportional rather than simple equality, I cannot see that this passage points to an alternative educational system in which an individual student’s character and needs are taken into consideration. Just as Plato sees new beginnings after cataclysms in human history, John Sallis, in a meandering, reflective chapter (which lacks notes and bibliography), sees Book 3 as a new beginning, a restatement of the question of the dialogue: what is the origin of constitutions? He traces four stages from primitivism to polis life. As well as surveying the main elements of Book 4 (the location of the foundation, its population, and the need for a primary source of authority) Michael Zuckert focuses on drama and rhetoric, not always plausibly. It is implausible, for instance, to read the Athenian’s criticism of Athenian sea-power as merely a rhetorical strategy, when Isocrates was saying the same at much the same time. I missed 460 BOOK REVIEWS discussion of what seems to me the most important aspect of Book 4, namely the important theme of finding the balance between ideal and realistic legislation. Patricia Fagan continues with Book 4. She asks how terrain affects the polis, and what role the gods play. She constructs a very negative picture of the foundation, as a closed, xenophobic, inflexible society. Robert Metcalfe analyses the great preamble of Book 5 and finds that it would have been more persuasive, less dictatorial, if it had been dialogue rather than monologue. Book 6 is concerned with the city’s administrative apparatus. Gregory Recco returns to the distinction between simple and proportional equality, shows how it is put to use in the establishment of the city’s offices, and argues that it maintains the city in a balance between democracy and monarchy, and so avoids factional disputes, but does so at the cost of coerciveness, since it is designed to dupe both monarchists and democrats. At 803b, in the course of Book 7, the Athenian claims, surprisingly after all these pages, that human affairs are not worth treating seriously, but still must be treated seriously. David Roochnik investigates this paradox, and finds a kind of ‘oscillation’ between play and seriousness, details and abstractions. Human life is worth only qualified seriousness, and recognition of the divine is needed to maintain a proper perspective. Francisco Gonzalez investigates a stretch of Book 8, 835b-842a, on how legislation is to restrain lust. He finds that lust has the potential to derail the entire legislative project, since it cannot be entirely regulated by legislation and coercion must be employed. Catherine Zuckert argues, reflecting on Book 9, that, given human nature, laws themselves are insufficient to inculcate virtue or the common good; education is also needed. In fact, she claims, Plato draws near to the Republic position that, ideally, philosophers should rule, not the laws. Sara Brill, considering the preludes on atheism in Book 10, argues that the soul is not only a natural product, but has the ability also to transcend nature. The city’s laws on atheism are to be the means of bringing order to a disordered soul (if it is not incurable) by embedding it within the right psychological and political structure. Finally, Eric Sanday provocatively argues that the city founded in Laws is bound to degenerate, and that its health can be measured by how it copes with that breakdown. The function of the Night Assembly of Book 12 is to turn this weakness into a strength – to use it to educate the citizenry in virtue. I found the quality of these essays patchy. The two synoptic essays seem sounder than many of those that engage more closely with the text, where occasional insights are offset by rather rambling ‘readings’ of the text, throwing up issues of dubious philosophical value. For a deeper and more fruitful engagement with the philosphical issues of Laws, I recommend the collection of essays edited by Bobonich and reviewed in HJ 53, 508. Lakonia, Greece Robin Waterfield Plato, Aristotle, and the Purpose of Politics. By Kevin Cherry. Pp. xiii, 232, Cambridge University Press, 2012, £60.00. Plato and Xenophon were attracted by the idea that all forms of rule are essentially identical: the same knowledge is involved whether one is ruling a household, an army, or a state. Aristotle, by contrast, held that politics was special, and not to be assimilated to other forms of knowledge. This is the contrast that lies at the core of Cherry’s stimulating book. He develops the implications of the two positions to widen the gap between the two thinkers and to sharpen up their views. But, first, a quibble: since Cherry belongs to the Straussian school, which holds, among other things, that it is important that Plato wrote dialogues, keeping himself and his own views in the background; and since Cherry consistently adheres to this principle throughout the book (never writing ‘Plato says’, for instance), then the book’s title is a misnomer, because Cherry would have to say that we learn nothing about ‘Plato’. Still, Aristotle clearly rejects Plato’s position at the start of Politics. This position of Plato’s is found most clearly in Statesman, at 258b-259d. In Chapter 1, Cherry develops the contrast between the two positions. For Plato (or ‘Plato’) the knowledge is the same, and the communities differ only in size. For Aristotle, communities differ in kind, not just in size, because they have different goals. The goal of politics is to maximize the good for all citizens, and for this knowledge is not the only factor: a person’s moral character is also relevant. Besides, a politician’s knowledge is not, or not only, theoretical knowledge, as Plato would have it, but practical knowledge. BOOK REVIEWS In Chapter 2 Cherry further heightens the contrast by arguing that, at bottom, Plato and Aristotle are operating with different conceptions of ‘nature’. For Plato, nature is hostile (Cherry’s reading of the cosmological myth), communities form for selfpreservation, and therefore stability is the ultimate political goal. For Aristotle, nature is benign, and shows the way for humans to form political communities and work towards attaining the good life. The stability that for Plato is the end of politics is for Aristotle just a stepping-stone towards the attainment of goodness. This chapter raised concerns in my mind about Cherry’s use of the idea of ‘nature’: the ancient Greeks very rarely thought of Nature as a unified force, but as the aggregate of all individual natures, with their own teleologies, but at times Cherry seems to come close to regarding it as a reified global force. Chapter 3 develops a related contrast, concerning knowledge and power. For Plato, knowledge is a rarity, and strict adherence to the rule of law is a necessary safeguard against the inevitability of rulers who lack knowledge. Since Aristotle is concerned with practical knowledge, however, not the theoretical knowledge of Plato’s rulers, political knowledge is more easily obtainable, even by the majority. This in turn (Chapter 4) shows that Aristotle is inclusive, whereas Plato limits political knowledge to very few; Aristotle encourages political investigation as a way to keep improving things, Plato effectively denies its value. 461 Cherry has done an excellent job of highlighting the differences between Plato and Aristotle, with illuminating insights into both thinkers along the way. In Chapter 5, against the background (see above) of his Straussian views, he develops a contrast between what he calls Socratic politics (where the value of inquiry and investigation is fully recognized) and the position of the Eleatic Stranger in Statesman, and locates Aristotle somewhere between the two, disagreeing with Socrates that politics has only to do with individuals, and disagreeing with the Stranger about the relative worthlessness of inquiry. Finally, in Chapter 6, Cherry widens his scope and considers the relations of all this to modern political thinkers. Plato’s position resembles that of Hobbes, Machiavelli, and Locke, with their emphasis on stability and on politics as a cure for brute nature. Aristotle should therefore, Cherry argues, be brought in to help us critique political views that are based on those of these early modern thinkers. This is a brave book, and its bravado has led Cherry on a few occasions not to devote quite enought space to an interpretation or argument to be persuasive. But the basic tactic of comparing Aristotle’s Politics with Plato’s Statesman proves a very effective way of illuminating the political positions of both thinkers. Lakonia, Greece Robin Waterfield Aristotle on the Nature of Community. By Adriel M. Trott. Pp. xiii, 239, NY/Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2014, £60.00/$95.00. Trott gives us a sophisticated defense of Aristotle’s political thinking against those who would criticize it as reactionary for legitimating the exclusion of certain groups, such as women and slaves, from access to political power; she does so, however, by going to the opposite extreme and transforming him into a radical democrat and fanatical inclusivist as a matter of principle, as the only means whereby the political community can both decide upon the best type of ‘constitution’, given its particular geographical, historical, and economic situation, and the best means to get there (‘deliberation’). Maintaining such an ‘open’ process becomes the state’s main concern until it reaches Fukuyama’s ‘end of history’, with something like democratic capitalism as the official policy with a strong socialist ‘safety-net’ to catch the weak and vulnerable who ‘fall through the slats’ in the dominant meritocratic competition. Such a process may be a valid criterion by which to measure a state’s success at achieving political justice, but what happened to Aristotle as the cool, nonideological political scientist, strategist, and physician who recognizes the ‘polis’ or communal living as the inevitable fate of any group of humans who want to advance to the stage of division of labour so that they can offer themselves a version of the ‘good life’ better than each person or family doing everything for itself? Aristotle’s discussion of the strengths and weaknesses of the different types of political ‘constitution’ was more shrewd and disinterested, preferring to avoid the worst, in the form of political revolution and public violence, than to achieve the best, for which all he felt the state could do was to supply the proper conditions, including a reliable material base and political stability, leading to a reasonable amount of leisure allowing for the development of good habits, education, and political discussion. One misses with Trott any discussion of Aristotle’s awareness of the difficulty for a state to flourish without a large middle class, which allows a 462 BOOK REVIEWS majority of its citizens to adopt a point of view in their deliberations that seeks what is best for the state as a whole, as distinct from their personal class or economic interest (the difference between a ‘polity’ and a ‘democracy’, the latter being only ‘the best of the worst’). Without that, even a fully ‘inclusive’ democracy cannot save itself from descending into a partially-camouflaged and undeclared ‘civil war’ between two ‘states’ that exist beneath the cover of one, each with a radically different ‘end’ for the constitution to aim at, with ‘deliberation’ taking the form of a struggle over who becomes ‘qualified’ to exercise the franchise. Trott’s strength is in showing Aristotle’s consistency in invoking ‘nature’ as an internal source of movement at every level from the lowest biological specimen, through the human person with their use of reason (whose products are thus not merely ‘conventional’ or ‘artificial’ as in the regnant Social Contract interpretation, but fully ‘natural’ as well), up to the political community as it debates its own primary institutions. The latter remain ‘open’, negotiable, and flexible as Trott emphasizes, but in the subsidiarity that Aristotle recognizes as conditioning the human development towards excellence, there is no ‘formula’ the state can adopt to guarantee success, but only maxims and recipes for avoiding disaster. Heythrop College Patrick Madigan Politeia in Greek and Roman Philosophy. Edited by Verity Harte and Melissa Lane. Pp. xv, 399, Cambridge University Press, 2013, £65.00/$110.00. The majority of the papers in this prestigious volume stem from a 2011 conference in honour of Malcolm Schofield, on his retirement. Anyone working in any field of ancient philosophy knows Schofield’s work and will immediately have an idea of the stellar cast of fifteen colleagues and former students who contributed to the conference. The extra two papers were written after the conference by the two editors. Of the seventeen papers, two are on Presocratics (Alcmaeon and Xenophanes), ten focus chiefly on Plato (although one of those is on Protagoras in Plato), two are on Aristotle, and three are on post-Aristotelian thought. The chapters are divided among four sections, which reflect Republic 591e-592b: the first section (five papers) concerns the ‘vocabulary of politics’; the second (four papers) the ‘practice of politics’; the third (four papers) the ‘politics of value’ (i.e. ethics); and the fourth (four papers) an extension of politics to a human being’s relations to the gods and the cosmos as a whole. Following an introduction, the chief purpose of which is to suggest that the papers in the volume owe their inspiration directly to Schofield’s work, Long (A.G., not A.A.) argues that in Republic Plato changes the terms of political debate in a nonpolitical direction, so as to claim that philosophy, not politics itself, is what counts. In Chapter 2, Farrar argues that Plato does not disdain historical reality, and compares his view with that of the historian Thucydides, to whom she sees Plato responding. In Chapter 3, Lane argues that when Plutarch, in his Lycurgus, claims that ancient Sparta did without written law, he was writing as a Platonist (and therefore an unreliable historian), for whom the rule of the sage was superior to written law. In Chapter 4, Mansfeld shows how Alcmaeon’s definitions of health and disease were influenced by political discourse, particularly Herodotus’ constitutional debate. In Chapter 5, Griffin argues that Roman philosophers (such as Cicero and Seneca) drew on the language of Roman law to help them assimilate Greek philosophy in a Roman environment. Part II: The first two papers, by Wardy and Harte, focus on the Noble Lie of Republic. Wardy argues that not only practical politics, but even political philosophy, is bound to involve such compromises; and Harte shows that the problem is not so much the falsehood of the lie as that it appeals to ignorance, which elsewhere it is the philsopher’s concern to remove. In Chapter 8, Denyer argues that Protagoras had a distinct political philosophy, in which conventional standards replace natural ones, which allows for criticism (for its utility, at least), and which is designed to produce social harmony by producing consensus on the ‘wholesomeness’ of those values. In Chapter 9, Barnes attacks the idea that Proclus (or any other late Neoplatonist) was politically active. Part III: Rowett (formerly Osborne) argues that many of the peculiarities of Protagoras are comprehensible if we understand Socrates to be using Protagoras’ own tactics back at him. She ties this in to the theme of the volume by claiming that this makes Socrates ‘more of a political animal’ (193) than Protagoras. In Chapter 11, Burnyeat argues against the Sachsian fallacy: an ideal citizen has respect for the rule of reason in his soul and this is equivalent to respect for the laws of the city; therefore, someone with his soul in the right condition will obey the rules and regulations of his BOOK REVIEWS community. In Chapter 12, Kraut seeks to restore the original meaning of to kalon, that is ‘beauty’, in the Nicomachean Ethics, thus giving ethics an aesthetic dimension. In Chapter 13, McCabe tries to accommodate the notion of impartiality within Stoic ethics; she finds that oikei osis, since it involves self-perception, creates an understanding within the Stoic sage of the similarity of his interests with those of others, and hence a sense of what we can recognize as social justice. Part IV: In Chapter 14, Lloyd explores the application in Aristotle’s thought of cognitive and political properties to non-human animals and finds a tension in that non-human animals do indeed have humanlike cognitive abilities, and yet Aristotle wants to drive a wedge between their sociability and ours. In Chapter 15, Warren considers the common ancient philosophical tendency to think of human perfection as assimilation to God in the context of Xenophanes’ abstract deity, and 463 shows that Xenophanes is an outsider to the tradition, in that there can be no assimilation to such a deity. In Chapter 16, Rowe places Aristotle’s remarks on serving god in Eudemian Ethics within the Socratic-Platonic tradition whereby traditional notions of piety are intellectualized, and attributes his caution in doing so to the memory of Socrates’ trial for impiety. Finally, in Chapter 17, Sedley argues that the atheistic position criticized by Plato in Laws 10 was not a product of Plato’s imagination, but was held by certain thinkers, who remained ‘underground’ because of the dangers of being atheists at the time, and was based on the science of the day. This is an excellent collection of essays, several of which are destined to become important within their field, and therefore a worthy offering to Schofield. Lakonia, Greece Robin Waterfield A Companion to Greek and Roman Political Thought. Edited by Ryan K. Balot. Pp. xxviii, 659, WileyBlackwell, 2009, £110.00. This is a boom time for ancient political thought. No longer the domain of classicists, historians, and ancient philosophers, in the past twenty or so years political scientists, especially in America, have rediscovered ancient theories and views. This new interdisciplinary work looks both ways, backward and forward. As ancient philosophers have known for ages, modern theories and perspectives, when carefully handled, can afford good insights into the ancient world; and ancient political thought has enlivened modern thinking in much the same way as the rediscovery of ancient ethical thought has stimulated a new wave of ethical theory (‘virtue ethics’). The virtues of this cross-fertilization are stressed in Balot’s slightly evangelical introductory chapter. There are thirty-four essays in the book, divided among eight sections, with the criterion of division being theme rather than chronology or individual thinkers. The only exception to this is that, for obvious reasons, Plato and Aristotle get their own section. The sections are: ‘The Broad View’ (8 essays); ‘Democracies and Republics’ (6 essays); ‘The Virtues and Vices of One-Man Rule’ (3 essays); ‘The Passions of Ancient Politics’ (3 essays); ‘The Athens of Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle’ (6 essays); ‘Constructing Political Narrative’ (3 essays); ‘Antipolitics’ (3 essays); and ‘Reception’ (2 essays). Apart from the obviously historical section on Plato and Aristotle, all the other essays are explicitly or implicitly involved in the programme of cross-fertilization. The starting-point is always historical: this is a book about the ancient world, not in the first instance about modern political thinking. But the very choice of structuring the book by topic rather than thinker invites involvement in that programme. The authors are sensitive (some more than others) to ancient texts and contexts, but on the lookout for the more universal lesson. And, if the essays in this volume are anything to go by, this is a productive approach. On the face of it, there are enormous differences between the political life of ancient Europeans and us: for instance, we believe in, or pay lip service to, the ideal of universal human rights, which an ancient Greek or Roman would have struggled to understand (‘You mean slaves too?’). Nevertheless, the essays in this volume suggest the lesson that there are timeless truths embedded in all societies, just by virtue of the fact that all societies involve human beings living and working with one another, and raise at least some of the same questions, such as whereabouts on the spectrum of individual freedom and state authority it is best to be positioned. The programme of cross-fertilization explains some oddities. There is a section, for instance, on the ‘passions’ of ancient politics. Ancient political thinkers paid far more attention to human emotions, and their role in making people model or aberrant citizens, than their modern counterparts have generally done. By creating a three-essay 464 BOOK REVIEWS section on this aspect, Balot is inviting modern political scientists to take more account of human feelings. And two of the three essayists expressly issue the invitation. In the ‘Broad View’ section, Balot’s introduction is followed by essays that expose and discuss the fundamentals of ancient political theory: what politics was like in the ancient world, ideas on citizenship, how secular or infused by their religions ancient political practice was, and so on. Kurt Raaflaub’s essay positioning ancient Greek political thinking within its wider Mediterranean context stands out, and Josiah Ober as usual puts modern social models to good use in his study of Athens and Rome. ‘Democracies and Republics’ explores the differences between ancient and modern concepts, but also contains some more historical essays (including one provocatively entitled ‘Roman Democracy?’, by W. Jeffrey Tatum, which, in imitation of Polybius, brings out the democratic elements to the ‘mixed’ constitution enjoyed by Rome). Two essays discuss the important topic of how different the ancient Greek idea of personal freedom and rights was from nowadays. ‘The Virtues and Vices of One-Man Rule’ selfevidently discusses ancient views on tyranny and monarchy. The section ‘Constructing Political Narrative’ is particularly interesting, with its accounts of how writers of all hues, from historians to dram- atists, participated in the political theorizing of their communities. Philip Stadter’s ‘Character in Politics’ is especially valuable: a study of how various ancient authors attributed success or failure in politics, and even civic catastrophe, to the character of their leaders, as much as to his policies. ‘Antipolitics’ has an essay on that philosophical fancy, cosmopolitanism; on the reasons and strategies for dropping out of political life in ancient Athens; and a brilliant essay by Todd Breyfogle on how Augustine made use of political ideas developed in earthly communities to point us towards membership of the heavenly city. In ‘Receptions’, Christopher Nadan follows ancient republican ideas through Aquinas, Machiavelli, and Montesquieu; and Catherine Zuckert considers the work of Hannah Arendt and Leo Strauss, two (very different) political thinkers who have openly looked back to ancient political thinking in developing their own ideas. This is an extremely valuable volume, a must for every library; perhaps the paperback will be priced within the reach of at least some individuals. There is a similar volume available: The Cambridge Companion to Ancient Greek Political Thought (2009), with some coincidence of authors; but the Blackwell Companion is both better and more thorough. Lakonia, Greece Robin Waterfield Reason and Analysis in Ancient Greek Philosophy: Essays in Honor of David Keyt. Edited by Georgios Anagnostopoulos and Fred D. Miller, Jr. Pp. xvii, 329, Springer, 2013 (Philosophical Studies Series 120), $179.00/£117.00. David Keyt has played a long and substantial role in ancient philosophy, especially ancient political philosophy, and this collection of fifteen essays is a worthy tribute. The book is topped and tailed by a personal memoir by Keyt of his ‘life in the Academy’ and by a list of his publications to date. The essays begin with Brickhouse and Smith reprising one line of their 2010 Socratic Moral Psychology by arguing, based on certain passages of Plato’s Apology, that Socrates is not the strict intellectualist he is usually made out to be: even if our thinking is primarily and directly responsible for what we do, emotions and appetites can affect our thinking. The next three essays address Socratic politics. Jean Roberts tackles the old chestnut of the alleged clash between Apology and Crito on disobeying the laws. She argues, in effect, that Socrates holds the Aristotelian distinction between equity and legal justice, and so that there is no real clash because even if he is obliged to obey the law of Athens, his moral obligation to avoid injustice is not exhausted by this law. Next Stephen Gardiner argues that Socrates’ basic political concern was with the very possibility of a reasonable politics. His pessimism about this explains the naivety of his reported political views. Much of the essay is taken up with interesting criticism of alternative views, especially Kamtekar’s. Merrill Ring argues, to telling effect, that Socrates’ argument in Crito for the wrongness of any attempt on his part to escape is seriously flawed, in that neither premiss (Retaliation is wrong; escaping would be retaliating) is properly secured. The final essay on Socrates, by Nils Rauhut, argues that Socrates was not a moral exemplar, in that, as Alcibiades’ speech in Symposium shows, he had to struggle against lust. This is so obvious that BOOK REVIEWS it was stated in a single sentence by G.M.A. Grube eighty years ago. Turning to Plato, Allan Silverman, in an essay that is likely to be controversial, argues that the Principle of Specialization in Republic does not depend entirely on a citizen’s ‘antecedent nature’, but is a product of nurture as well; that Plato allows for a higher degree of social mobility than is usually recognized; and that all the citizens, of whatever metal, are educated for their moral improvement and happiness. C.D.C. Reeve surveys the passages in Republic on the tripartite soul, to conclude, as others have before, that only the rational part is truly a soul, or a person, while the other parts are accretions on to the rational soul. He finds this view confirmed by some passages from other dialogues. Gerasimos Santas revisits Republic’s analogy between city and soul. Arguing that the parts of the soul are faculties (not agents), he concludes that they can perform their functions better or worse. Even reason has a virtue, which is wisdom. From this Santas concludes that every member of Kallipolis, not just the philosopher rulers, can be just in their own way. This paper dovetails nicely with that of Silverman. Still on Republic, Mark McPherran focuses on the Myth of Er, and finds a new way to charge the dialogue with radical inconsistency. That is, throughout the dialogue justice has been due to the agent herself, but the myth seems to introduce other pressures on a soul in Hades, such as chance, which push it towards a just or an unjust life in its next incarnation. Christopher Shields discusses Plato’s assertion that logos arises out of the interweaving of forms 465 (Sophist 259e). He rejects the standard interpretation, that the forms are meanings, and suggests that they form the deep metaphysical structure of the universe, which is reflected in a meaningful sentence. We do not interweave the forms ourselves by forming sentences, but the mind requires already existing forms for rational discourse. The final five papers are on Aristotle. S. Marc Cohen discusses the peculiar concept of ‘accidental beings’ and their place in Aristotle’s ontology. Frank Lewis discusses Metaphysics Z6, and in particular why Aristotle uses Platonic forms as examples when he does not believe in their existence. It is because forms do play a suitable role in Plato’s metaphysics, as the kind of primary entities that Aristotle is searching for. Cass Weller argues, from a consideration of Metaphysics Z11, that Aristotle thought of a human being chiefly in terms of function and only secondarily in terms of his material parts; that the material parts must be such as to support the function. Fred Miller elaborates a theory of the importance of belief for Aristotle, based on a survey of his use of relevant terminology. Finally, Charles Young discussed kharis in NE book 5: he sees it as ‘grace’ rather than ‘gratitude’, because it involves some return on a favour, not simply its acknowledgement, and he develops the concept accordingly, concluding that it is fundamental to the health of a community. It is a pity that this highly rewarding collection of essays comes with a price tag that will keep it out of the reach of many libraries, let alone individuals. Lakonia, Greece Robin Waterfield Christian Origins and the Ancient Economy. By David A. Fiensy. Pp. xvi, 231, Cambridge, James Clarke, 2014, £22.50/$45.00. Fiensy has canvassed all the scholarship on economic conditions in Palestine in the first century CE, weighed and carefully sifted the evidence that comes to us from different sources, including more recently archaeology, and presents, almost inadvertently, a devastating indictment of the Jewish upper classes, including the high priestly families, as exploiting, disenfranchising, and ruining the Jewish peasant farmers, creating an army of impoverished and bitter former free holders and renters who had been thrown off their land because they could not pay their debts, who became tinder waiting for a spark to rise up against their oppressors that led to the rebellion of 66-70 CE and to the subsequent destruction of Temple and Jerusalem with Jews excluded from the city. As Josephus reports, almost the first thing the mobs did was burn down the archives where the tax and debt records were kept. What made the deterioration of conditions more difficult for the peasant farmers to accept was the vision of the sacredness of the land, which was to be each tribe’s permanent possession and which could not be alienated, regularly presented to them through readings from the scriptures; the ‘sabbatical’ and ‘Jubilee’ cancellation of all debts and return of land to its original owners, however, had been suppressed upon the return of the exiles from Babylon. The ‘prosbul’ was enacted by Hillel during the first century BCE precisely to counter the provision in the Torah for the cancellation of debts every seven years. Land was the only investment in which to place extra wealth, and one had to have more land to acquire wealth. This unleashed a ruthless competition among the upper 466 BOOK REVIEWS classes of ‘possessive individualism’ that effectively shredded the social justice and national solidarity that was the cornerstone of the vocation of the chosen people, who through the gift of the Law were supposed to function as a ‘light to the nations’. Not only were the high priestly families no exception to this mad scramble; they became the chief offenders. The Talmud has nothing good to say about ‘the houses of Boethus, Hanan, Phiabi, and Kathros (Kadros)’. However, this process began just after the execution of Jesus; during his lifetime economic conditions in Galilee, if not in Judah, were positive and equitable. There seems to have been modest prosperity all around, and the amalgamation of small holdings into larger estates had not really begun. Jesus was calling for justice within the system, rather than a revolutionary replacement of the system. His ‘Kingdom of God’, however, was also inspired by a return to the traditional scriptural ideal of the ‘Jubilee’, which the messiah was to restore. The Jewish leaders were unfortunately unfaithful to their own traditions; with each seeking more, the nation as a whole lost everything. Heythrop College Patrick Madigan Leo Strauss and the Problem of Political Philosophy. By Michael P. Zuckert & Catherine H. Zuckert. Pp. xii, 387, Chicago/London, The University of Chicago Press, 2014, £31.50. In 2008 the Zuckerts published The Truth about Leo Strauss primarily to defend Strauss against the charge of being the ideological source behind unpopular initiatives within American foreign policy. This book seeks rather to explain Strauss’ political philosophy from within by showing the various influences to which he was responding and to test his philosophy for completeness and coherence. In this second project they succeed admirably. Strauss’ view of the history of philosophy may be described as a variation of the familiar pattern available in text books with certain unusual emphases and consequent tensions that led him to both striking insights and to possible contradictions. Before there was philosophy, mankind was served by pre-philosophical explanations of the cosmos and how to behave, primarily in terms of ‘ways’ or ‘laws’ which an entire community was expected to follow and which were traced back to a divine or semi-divine source. This is the realm of ‘opinion’ from which philosophy inevitably begins and with which it maintains a prickly relationship, as it attempts to rise from opinion to a higher level of knowledge or science. Philosophy is unavoidably perceived as subversive by the ‘city’, which is the only home it can have due to the increased education and leisure that the city affords and by the very project to develop an alternative explanation to that already available through the orthodoxy of the ‘opinions’. Strauss sees philosophy as a ‘way of life’ characterized, as in Lessing’s famous dream, by a perpetual search rather than a definitive ‘finding’ or ‘system’, which is reserved for God alone; this itself is controversial, for he is clearly opting for a modern view of philosophy rather than a classical one, the latter of which he is ostensibly urging us to return to. The first philosophers tried to give a naturalistic explanation for the universe based on reason, which made their accounts reductive; the differences between them, however, meant that they were not much of a challenge to the traditional domination of opinion in the city. Things changed with Socrates who interrogated his fellow citizens about civilized values such as the ‘good’, the ‘noble’, the ‘just’ and the ‘true’, and raised the possibility that these may have only a human, conventional basis rather than an objective one. At the same time, however, he overcame the reductive tendencies of his predecessors by ‘pulling up’ philosophy to the human level and opening up a place for teleology, and thereby the personal, in the realm of the objective. Finally his fate showed the limits to which ‘philosophy’ as a way of life can challenge ‘opinion’, and the limited extent to which philosophers can expect a ‘conversion’ by the city in response to or as a consequence of their teachings. This mutual hostility was particularly marked in societies whose ‘opinion’ took the form of a law which had been ‘revealed’ and would not suffer challenge, as in Judaism and Islam; here philosophy was still the most noble life and could be maintained privately in subsidiarity permitted by the state. However, its practitioners frequently had to resort to ‘esoteric’ writing to conceal beliefs that ended up conflicting with the official view so as not to outrage public opinion. Ironically the possibility of an authentic philosophical way of life has been lost in modern period, primarily because ‘modern’ philosophy, which has been officially granted unlimited freedom of expression, has also ‘lowered its sights’ with regard to the knowledge, science, or ‘conversion’ it proffers so as to render the latter more BOOK REVIEWS palatable, less difficult, and consequently less offensive to the city’s ‘opinion’, thereby undermining or denying the possibility of the uniquely valuable way of life it was supposed to be instantiating for the benefit of the state - as in the currently influential positions of positivism and historicism. 467 So in freeing itself from all restriction or correction by ‘opinion’, philosophy compromised, diluted, and finally killed itself. This is a fascinating study. Heythrop College Patrick Madigan A History of Political Ideas: From Antiquity to the Middle Ages. By Philippe Nemo, translated by Kenneth Casler. Pp. ix, 665, Pittsburgh, PA, Duquesne University Press, 2013, $36.00. First published in French in 1998, this book summarizes twenty centuries of ‘western’ writings on political theories in their historical context. He does not claim specialized expertise in all that he treats and relies heavily on other authors for his material. Specialists may disagree with his interpretations of the primary sources but all readers will profit from his clearly written overview of the development of political thought. Following a general introduction on anthropology and politics, the book is divided into three parts: Ancient Greece, Rome and the Christian West. The introduction gives the author’s requirements for political theory – the existence of a state and of rational thought – and describes the gradual emergence of these conditions from pre-state societies and sacred monarchies to their fulfilment and subsequent decline in Athens. Although the best-known and most influential works of Greek political thought were Plato’s Republic, Statesman and Laws and Aristotle’s Politics, they were preceded and influenced by several centuries of political developments and criticism in three phases: ‘1. The formalization of notions on justice (themis, dike) and social order (eunomia), in contrast with “feudal” violence and excess. . .; 2. A realization that justice can only be ensured by a law (nomos) which is equal for all (isonomos) and that the law must be explicit and written, therefore, in the hands of men. . .; 3. Then it is realized that the law itself can be tyrannical and that, consequently, it can be criticized; to provide a basis for such criticism, a distinction is made between what is natural (physie) and what is conventional (nomo)’ (p. 22). These developments can be seen from the works of Homer, Hesiod, Solon, Cleisthenes, Heraclitus, Pericles and Herodotus. Although the Athens of Socrates, Plato and Aristotle is usually considered to be the epitome of democracy in the ancient world, according to Nemo, ‘Plato’s political thought is essentially a long argument against the very principle of democracy’ (p. 74). The principal failings of democracy are its tendency to degenerate into mob rule and the susceptibility of the common people to demagogy. Of the other types of government – timocracy, oligarchy, tyranny and aristocracy – only the latter can ensure justice and therefore the wellbeing of all citizens. Plato’s Laws provides a detailed blueprint for an ideal state governed by an aristocratic Nocturnal Council. In Nemo’s estimation, ‘Plato imagined that political science was aprioric, like mathematics, whereas his pupil, Aristotle, and most of the great political thinkers after him, imagined political science to be experimental’ (p. 109). Having observed different forms of government, Aristotle settled on a variation of aristocracy that he named simply a politeia. It borrowed some features from the government of the few and others from the government of the many. To avoid any one faction abusing power, he called for a three-fold division of state functions, in modern parlance, the legislative, executive and judicial. Given the different interests of the rich and the poor, compromise is necessary to provide stability and ensure justice for all. Plato and Aristotle were not the only critics of 4th century Athenian democracy; their contemporaries, Xenophon, Isocrates and Demosthenes, also rejected this form of government. Xenophon advocated ‘a reactionary Spartan-type political program. A return to the virtues of the ancestors. . .’ (p. 145). Isocrates favoured a mixed form of government, a nonegalitarian democracy run by a Council of the Areopagus for which the membership criterion is wisdom (p. 168). Demosthenes echoed the criticisms of Athenian democracy of the other thinkers but Nemo says little about his preferred alternative. The city-state for which these Greek thinkers provided models of government was not to last beyond the fourth century BCE. Beginning with the conquests of Alexander the Great (336-332), empires swallowed up city-states and destroyed what remained of democracy. The philosophies of Cynicism, Stoicism and Epicureanism flourished in these circumstances. With the spread of the Roman Empire, Greek political philosophy gave way to a very different Roman brand. Since ‘in Rome, political ideas rarely achieved expression in the form of general theories; more often than not, they were commentaries on Roman political life’ (p. 198), Nemo begins with an overview of Roman history, followed by discussions of Roman public law and political institutions and 468 BOOK REVIEWS civil law, and only then treats Roman political doctrines. The four periods of Roman history are the kingdom (mid-eighth century to 509 BCE), the republic (509-31 BCE), high empire (31 BCE-285 CE) and Low Empire/Late Antiquity (285-565 CE). The republic experienced a series of reforms that enabled its long survival and the enormous expansion of its territory. Its last years saw power struggles and civil war and following his defeat of Antony’s forces at Actium, Octavian became the first Roman emperor and consolidated in his person and his successors all the powers of an absolute monarch. From 285 onwards the empire became divided into two, East and West; the latter effectively ended in 565 with the invasion of Rome by the Lombards. Following his descriptions of Roman political institutions and private law, Nemo concludes, ‘If Roman law was so innovative. . ., it was because the Roman Republic, followed by the Empire, was the first truly “multi-ethnic” state in the history of humankind. Legal expedients had to be invented to create a social bond between people originating in many different ethnic groups, and so that throughout the empire there could exist an equality before the law, which until then was found only in smaller monoethnic communities’ (p. 256). The result was a concept of ‘natural law’ or ‘law of nations’. The principal Roman political philosopher was Cicero. His contributions included doctrines of society, humanity and human dignity, of law as founded in human nature, of the state, of private property and contract and of mixed government (pp. 266-7). Like the Stoics, he emphasized the dignity and autonomy of individual humans. The preservation of individual human nature is the purpose of law, both natural and positive, and the state’s role is to uphold the law. The three forms of government – monarchy, aristocracy and democracy – can all fulfil this role, but Cicero preferred a mixture that combines the advantages of each. Although most of Cicero’s doctrines proved enduring, his critique of absolute monarchy had no effect. Instead, the emperors took on the trappings of Oriental monarchs, encouraged by Virgil and others. As time went on, ‘the monarchic “legal person” became indistinguishable from the private holder of the charge, and accordingly the imperium of the former became indistinguishable from the dominium of the latter. The state belonged to the king like his personal property or his family’s patrimony’ (p. 325). Seneca aproved this development although he encouraged his emperor, Nero, to show mercy. Dio Chrisostom, Tacitus and Pliny the Younger also approved of absolutism as long as the emperor observed the rule of law. Absolutism accorded well with the divinization of the emperor which, during the Low Empire, was modified under the influence of monotheism so that ‘the emperor was no longer a god but the supreme earthly servant of a single heavenly God, that is, a “vicar of God” ’ (p. 356). Eusebius of Caesarea was an eloquent Christian proponent of this doctrine. Nemo’s account of the Christian West begins with the political ideas of the Bible which, however, do not constitute political thought in the GrecoRoman scientific sense (p. 406). In their concern for transforming society in order to achieve social justice, ‘Hebrew prophets introduced something totally different in the art of government. Henceforth, politics becomes inseparable from eschatology and messianism’ (p. 412). The state is not the instrument of justice; God is, working through individuals of all social status. If the righteous do not receive justice in this life, they will in the messianic era. When the New Testament identified Jesus as the messiah, it became clear that his reign of justice will not occur within history but afterwards. For Nemo, the two major contributions of the Bible were ‘the eschatological “energizing” of historical time [as linear rather than cyclical] and the discrediting of temporal power,’ both of which were unknown to the GrecoRoman world (p. 445). By far the most important early Christian political analyst was St. Augustine. His two key concepts for understanding the role of the state vis-a-vis the church were political authority as punishment for sinners and the action of Providence in history (p. 456). With the fall of the western Roman empire, political thought virtually disappeared for several centuries, although churchmen filled the void with canon laws attempting, often without success, to assert the authority of the church over secular rulers, whether feudal lords or the new Holy Roman Emperors. From the 11th to the 13th centuries several unitary states came into being, at the same time that the church was undergoing reform and reviving the study of old Roman law. Although there were inevitable conflicts over jurisdiction between church and state, both benefitted from the establishment of a rational basis for laws and the separation of morals and law (sins and crimes): ‘Henceforth, the state would be concerned only with crimes and misdemeanors. It would have no legitimacy in matters of conscience and, in general, in the private lives of individuals’ (p. 533). Although Thomas Aquinas acknowledged the theological genius of St. Augustine, the two differed significantly in their political thinking. For example, ‘Aquinas undoubtedly continues the ancient Greco-Roman tradition and disagrees with the Pauline and Augustinian idea of a direct Godgiven authority to certain individuals because of sin’ (p. 550). Thus, he rejected both absolutism and BOOK REVIEWS government based on secrecy. Moreover, human law must be in accordance with natural law for it to be legitimate; this provides an additional safeguard against despotism. However, the natural law is open to misinterpretation and so God has revealed the divine law to provide certainty on doctrinal and moral issues. During the 14th and 15th centuries the supremacy of the church over the state was successfully challenged by writers such as Dante, Marsilius of Padua and William of Ockham and by the heads of increasingly powerful states in France, Germany, Spain and Italy. Although attempts by the advocates of conciliarism to restrict papal absolutism ultimately failed, in several states (e.g., England) political absolutism met with at least partially successful resistance. This period also saw the rise of millenarian movements in many parts of Europe 469 that rejected, often violently, the political and intellectual developments that were taking place in both church and state. Nemo’s history ends rather abruptly, likely because it has been followed by an even longer companion volume, A History of Political Ideas in the Modern Era and Contemporary Times (2002). Some of the secondary sources on which he relies heavily were written many decades ago but he does refer to contemporary authors (e.g., Rene Girard) as well. Although the common practice of multiple authorship on topics such as this can provide more specialized treatment, an important advantage of a single authored volume like Nemo’s is its unity of style and approach. University of Ottawa John R. Williams Advice for the Sultan: Prophetic Voices and Secular Politics in Medieval Islam. By Neguin Yavari. Pp. vii, 197, London, Hurst, 2014, £35.00. Yavari is offended with the current state of Western political science, especially the ‘Cambridge School’ represented by Quentin Skinner and J.G.A. Pocock, which posits the separation of religion and kingship that occurred in the Enlightenment West as the terminus ad quem that all forms of society and all stages of political development are working their way towards. These secular values are held to have universal validity; this consigns the Muslim world, which has not gone through such an ‘Enlightenment’ and is wary of much of what it notices in this supposedly ‘eschatological’ stage of world history, to a stubbornly, perplexingly, and deliberately arrested or ‘un-modern’ phase of development. She joins Armando Salvatore in arguing that ‘[t]he purportedly anti-modern, or at least modernity resistant, role of Islam’ is a symptom of the reluctance of Western sociological discourse ‘to attribute a transformative potential to non-Western social formations, with a corresponding devaluation of their religious and more broadly cultural traditions.’ (quoted pp. 150-1) She puts forth a rich banquet from the genre known as ‘Mirror of Princes’ or advice given to rulers to argue the contrary, that Islam had and has its own way of giving instruction and imparting corrections to rulers who are failing to rule correctly, and that such correction is done in the name, not of religious orthodoxy, but of a Reason fully as secular as anything known in the West, a Reason that specifies the order and place of religion rather than the other way around, and that is operating out of a different, but fully respectable model of political develop- ment that is not inherently inferior, but sees itself rather as superior, to the social breakdown, individual aimlessness, and moral decay it notices accompanied the ‘triumph’ of the abstract values of the rights of man, democracy, and liberalism in the West. All this can be conceded, as well as the grace and artistry of the ‘anecdotes’ (or ‘parables’) told about rulers and viziers who are deliberately posited as living long in the past or far away (to allow a disinterested approach to the lesson), and of the ‘animal fables’ which again leave it to the ruler – or potential reader – to interpret the story in a way that best fits their own situation – thus imparting correction in the gentlest, most respectful, and self-initiated way possible, rather than delivering a thunderous moral in an external, heavy-handed fashion. Further, the political ruler must always operate in tandem with the religious authority, even if he specifies the latter’s proper ‘place’; banishing the latter completely would immediately deprive his dynasty of legitimacy in the eyes of the population. Still the ruler, even if he makes mistakes, is to be borne patiently, in Lutheran fashion; his errors will themselves lead to his downfall, and man should not presume to do what only God’s inscrutable Will can bring about. Strong-man rule is the only game in town, the only system known or indeed deemed possible; anything else is a non-starter and falls below the radar screen. In fact, the ideal prince is in many ways the ‘stronger’ man. The ‘Reason’ Yavari celebrates is a Machiavellian skill in 470 BOOK REVIEWS survival and triumph over one’s enemies, typically through asking for advice but never trusting completely even the ‘wisest’ counselor. Islam does not suspect concentrations of power, but rather expects and even longs for such, because such is preferable to its opposite - chaos. The price one pays is dynastic competition and turbulence in transition – ‘when the elephants fight, the grass gets trampled’; and the attempt to ‘educate’ any particular ruler is inevitably an activity fraught with anxiety and thus an attempt at ‘damage control’. The West has opted for a system of checks and balances that limits concentrations of power; we pay our distinctive price in an evaporation of cultural values unless individually chosen. By default, the reason for the difference can only be that in the dominant myth of the West, the ‘Son’ goes beyond the ‘Father’ to accomplish what the Father wanted to do but was unable to achieve himself. Heythrop College Patrick Madigan Narratives of Islamic Legal Theory. By Rumee Ahmed. Pp. 176, Oxford University Press, 2012, £50.00. This book focuses on medieval Islamic legal theory (usul al-fiqh) focusing on Dabusi who died in 430/ 1038 and Sarakhsi (who died probably in the final decade of the 11th century C.E.). Both jurists were part of the Baghdad Hanafi tradition, which greatly influenced the classical and post-classical Hanafi legal tradition. Most medieval legal theory manuals have the same structure, the same topic headings, and even draw the same conclusions. In other words, the manuals functioned fundamentally as a venue for jurists to prove that their legal school was intellectually superior to other, competing legal schools. Rather than apologizing for the law by giving reasons for its inclusion in the canon, medieval jurists used legal theory to justify the law, i.e., to argue for its definition, application, and contemporary relevance. The author then takes a page out of the playbook of Charles S. Pierce who coined the term, ‘abduction,’ or a study of the facts and devising a theory to explain the facts. In ‘abduction’ facts are accepted, explained, and justified, rather than created or presupposed. Justification tries to show why the axioms and injunctions of one’s legal tradition, e.g., the Hanafi, are applicable in a particular case. At this juncture Ahmed makes the important point that Islamic jurisprudence represents the will of Allah, hence it impinges on every aspect of communal and individual life. The author notes that the works of both Dabusi and Sarakhsi are based on their predecessor, Abu al-Hasan al-Karkhi (d.340/ 951) and Abu Bakr al-Jassas (d.370/981). For example, both jurists use the identical terms and arguments of al-Jassas to make their case. How then do Dabusi and Sarakhsi differ? They justify the same term differently, hence demonstrating that the application of the shariah can change without affecting the principles or injunctions. Medieval jurists like Dabusi and Sarakhsi have a larger perspective or Weltanschauung in mind into which the shariah functions as a Gestalt or whole. In short, Dabusi and Sarakhsi differ concerning the function of Islamic law as a whole. In Chapter One Ahmed examines the thought of Dabusi and Sarakhsi in their use of the Qur’an. He notes that the Hanafi traditions stressed the absolute superiority of the Qur’an vis-a-vis other sources of Islamic law such as the sunna or the normative practice of the Islamic community (ummah). In regard to the Qur’an, Sarakhsi views the shariah as both transcendent and universally applicable. He felt that one must submit to the Qur’an uncritically, rather than interact with it creatively. For him the Islamic law aims to engender belief in the hearts and minds of the Muslim faithful. In Sarakhsi’s eyes the faith perspective colors the justification of both the principles and the injunctions of the shariah. In contradistinction to Sarakhsi, Dubasi believed in only using definitive, authoritative sources, as opposed to basing divine law on sources of questionable origin. Context, purpose, and circumstances count for everything for Dubasi in regard to the application of Islamic law. In Chapter Two Ahmed argues that the hadith (or the words and actions of Muhammad) abrogated the sunna of pagan Arabia before the time of the Prophet. For the Hanafi legal tradition Muhammad possessed infallibility in the sense that Allah protected him from error. The sunna of Muhammad then became available to future generations as the hadith that defined normative practice for Muslims. Chapter Three deals with the limits of ra’y or ‘considered opinion’ in Sarakhsi and Dubasi. For Dabusi jurists can never quite know the divine truth fully, but only approach this truth asymptotically. The divine truth remains basically detached from the jurist’s purview, hence no individual jurist’s view of ‘considered opinion’ is binding on another jurist. Sarakhsi takes another tack arguing that the individual jurist does know the divine BOOK REVIEWS truth. While Dabusi cared deeply about the context and circumstances that accompanied the application of the shariah, Sarakhsi, appealing to the transcendence of God, opted for a ‘less critical application of inherited injunctions in pursuit of perfection.’ What takes Ahmed’s monograph to the next level is his ability to transcend legal theory qua legal theory as such. He does this by noting that legal theory texts must understood in the context of religious devotion and obligation. In other words, legal theory texts may best be understood as religious ritual enacted by faithful, pious practitioners 471 and that the basic concern of Sarakhsi and Dubasi has to do with the application of legal texts to the life of their respective communities. The manuals of legal theory attempt, then, to compensate for the failure of the Muslim community to apply Islamic law correctly. The author comes to these conclusions by a careful and rigorous study of the text of Dubasi and Sarakhsi. In sum, this book is absolutely first-rate and it is difficult for me to praise this book too highly. It augurs well for the future of the Oxford Legal Studies Series. Auburn University, Alabama Richard Penaskovic Inevitable Democracy in The Arab World: New Realities in An Ancient Land. By Wissam S. Yafi. Pp. xiv, 207. Palgrave Macmillan, 2012, $28.00. Yafi is a Harvard scholar who chairs the MENA Democracy Group which concerns itself with the contemporary dynamics in the Arab world and their world-wide consequences. He divides his subject into two main parts. In Part 1, New Realities, four chapters focus on economic, geosocial, technological, and geopolitical realities in the Arab world. Part 2, Inevitable Arab Democracy, looks at the paradox of Arab weakness, change, and potential outcomes, misconceptions about Arab democracy, and the complex relationship between Islam and democracy. The book includes an epilogue, a brief glossary of commonly used terms, a bibliography and a helpful index. In Part 1 Yafi argues that because of globalization, a stagnant economy, a burgeoning population explosion, and high unemployment, the Arab nations, in particular, have had enormous difficulty in keeping pace with other countries, externally, while internally, these countries have had massive unrest, as seen in the ‘Arab Spring.’ Another element that has to be factored into the equation has to do with the various governments in the Arab world that were or are ruled by autocratic leaders, as seen in Egypt, Libya, Saudi Arabia, Bahrain, and Tunisia. Although the number of people who are literate in the Gulf, for example, has risen dramatically in recent years, this has not translated into an increase in economic prosperity and growth. Why not? First, the various governments in the Arab countries play too dominant a role in their economies, hence crowding out private investments. In Egypt, for example, there are over six million jobs in the public sector, while in the United States there are but three million jobs in the federal government. The Egyptian government cannot afford to hire any more graduates from their universities without going into bankruptcy. Meanwhile, the young become restless and disillusioned. Second, we have in the Arab world a veritable population explosion, ever since the oil boom. When these young children mature and graduate from college, jobs are few and far between, particularly for women. Third, in the Arab countries many items like electronics, cars, and food are imported, at great expense, along with foreign workers who take jobs away from native workers. Fourth, the Arab nations like Saudi Arabia have invested heavily in expensive weaponry to protect their oil wells, thus contributing to the depletion of their wealth. Moreover, technology has had a huge effect on life in the Arab countries. Until recently, news reporting in the Arab world involved micromanagement by the government. Censorship was widespread. Thus a tight lid was kept on any information that dare criticize the regime. With the advent of cell phones, the Internet, satellite T.V., and videoconferencing, government censorship is, for the most part, a thing of the past. Governments have little defense against these technological ‘weapons,’ which have sufficient power to topple any regime. Because of these economic, demographic, and technological realities, autocratic governments will have an extremely difficult time remaining autocratic. The train to democracy will win out, since its momentum will make it unstoppable. How does Islam the religion factor into this equation? Yafi sees Islam as a grassroots voice for the Arab world and perhaps the most powerful force ‘pushing the region toward reform.’ According to the Western media, Islam constitutes the problem with the Islamic world. Yafi argues 472 BOOK REVIEWS that this is a fundamental error that the Western media makes, along with thinking that the Muslim law, shariah, is at loggerheads with secular law. The West feels there should be a sharp separation between church (mosque) and state, whereas in some Islamic countries like Iran, mosque (church) and state are one. However, one can ask whether there is really a sharp separation between church and state in the West? Has not the British monarch headed the Church of England for almost five hundred years? Have not the Jewish lobby and the Christian right heavily influenced the political process in the U. S., particularly in regard to moral issues like abortion and gay marriage? Finally, it should be noted that shariah, has existed along with secular law in the Islamic world ever since the genesis of Islam in the seventh century. In Jordan, Syria, and Lebanon, the shariah is consulted in regard to personal issues, but civil, constitutional, and criminal issues are settled in accordance with the Napoleonic Code. Finally, Yafi sheds a bright light on the new economic, demographic, and technological realities in the Arab world today. He realizes that once the autocratic regimes are replaced by democracies, political and economic structural change must occur, but the ride will be neither smooth, nor easy. It will take one or more decades to accomplish the necessary changes. The international community must be there to assist the move toward democracy. Billions of aid must be forthcoming from the international community, including the oil-rich Arab countries themselves. In sum, Yafi has penned a brilliant book, one that theologians should read carefully in order to understand the Arab world at a time when an Arab Spring beckons. Auburn University, Alabama Richard Penaskovic Toward an Islamic Enlightenment: the G€ ulen Movement. By M. Hakan Yavuz. Pp. 300. Oxford/NY, Oxford University Press, 2013, £21.53. It is a mistake, the author tells us, to treat ‘Islam’ as though it were a single monolithic entity; rather it is a series of interpretations of the Qur’an and the traditions which derive from it. The Qur’an itself, in spite of the often willful denials of some ‘literalists’, like the highly influential and vocal Wahhabists, ‘consists of very general and poetic exhortations toward faith and virtue’; ‘specific political and social legitimacy and practice’ were ‘always fiercely contested’ by the Prophet’s immediate followers and their successors (2). One of the most remarkable of the movements constitutive of Islam in recent times is that which is spearheaded by the Turkish author Fethullah G€ulen, himself a follower of Said Nursi. The claim of the writers of this school is that a renewed Islam may and should embrace science and what one might call enlightenment values, including democracy; and that the Qur’an should be interpreted to this effect. They are radically opposed to the stark opposition often insisted upon between science and democracy on the one hand, and loyalty to Islam on the other. The Turkish revolution brought about by Kemal Atat€urk (surely, by the way, one of the most remarkable leaders in the whole of human history) took the former way out; the influence of Islam was to be at worst eliminated, at best radically restricted, in public affairs. ‘Kemalists’ are apt to interpret science in positivistic terms; the G€ulen movement, on the contrary, sees the enthusiastic practice of science and pursuit of democratic ideals as themselves aspects of the service of God. G€ulen reproaches the Arabs for ‘generating a negative image of Islam by reducing Islam to Wahhabism and Gulf Arab norms and practices’; and makes a sharp distinction between ‘urban Ottoman’ and ‘tribal Arab Islam’ (58). I myself wish that all Muslims were followers of G€ulen’s movement, which I take to be wholly admirable; but there are considerations which make me uneasy. In spite of confident assertions to the contrary by influential contemporary atheists, it is easy to be convinced that essential theism (our author would say ‘deism’) on the one side, and the worldview of natural science on the other, fit together perfectly; positivist atheism is no corollary of science, however often it is stated or assumed to be so. Essential theism explains what natural science at once assumes and demonstrates; that we live in an intelligible universe, the divine intelligence explaining its intelligibility as such, the divine will explaining why it has the particular kind of intelligibility that science progressively finds it to have - in terms of ninety-two naturallyoccurring chemical elements rather than four, of mutation and natural selection of life-forms rather than special creation of each species, of the arcana of quantum theory rather than a less zany set-up at the microphysical level, and so on and so on. Among the many splendours of the Qur’an are passages which may clearly be interpreted as praise of such a Creator. It is not absurd to suppose that this BOOK REVIEWS Creator is in general on the side of co-operative rather than anti-social behaviour - though it must honestly be acknowledged that faith in God can have a very different effect. It is when one comes to alleged special revelations of this Being, and their specific features, that difficulties are apt to arise. There are shocking passages in the Judeo-Christian scriptures, as when God deprives Saul of his kingdom for not committing genocide thoroughly enough (1 Samuel 15), or commands people not to let any medium stay alive (Exodus 22.18). But (non-fundamentalist) Christians have some freedom of manoeuvre in relation to their sacred book, which may be seen in terms of an emergent trend, represented by the Old Testament, leading to full realization in the New. The frequent divine injunction to war in the Hebrew scriptures can be disturbing; yet Christians may properly remind themselves that they are indeed called to a kind of warfare, but that it consists in a struggle against the powers of evil, within oneself as well as without, which impede the realization of the Kingdom of God. (Enlightened Muslims do well to speak in this connection of the ‘inner jihad’.) As well as the magnificent generalities, there are some specifics in the Qur’an too; if Dr. Yavuz can accuse Wahhabists of some disingenuousness in neglecting the former, they may fling back the charge in regard to the latter. A few of the specifics are a source of concern to non-Muslims. (Others are of course excellent, and sometimes astonishingly advanced for their time. According to the Qur’an, women are to retain the property which they bring to a marriage rather than automatically making it over to their husbands; Western countries did not catch up with Islam on this matter until the Enlightenment. And it should never be forgotten that, in the early centuries of its existence, Islam led the world in philosophy and science.) The typical Enlightenment view, that convicted thieves should at worst be imprisoned, and in the course of their incarceration be humanely advised to take up a less anti-social way of making ends meet, is not so much an interpretation as a contradiction of the plain 473 words of the Qur’an, to the effect that they should have their right hands cut off. There are other disturbing features still which seem to cling to the religious, moral, legal and political traditions which derive from the Qur’an, and to societies which pride themselves on being Islamic. There is what one might call a consensus of Enlightenment values. These may be a somewhat ill-defined bunch, but one may safely say that they imply the following: that adulteresses should not be publicly stoned to death; that women should be allowed access to education and medical resources; that they should not be subjected to genital mutilation; and that apostates from one’s religion have not thereby necessarily made themselves worthy of death. Whatever the ultimate outcome of recent reformist tendencies, these values are at present flouted as a matter of course in many Islamic societies. On the value of religious toleration, there is a verse in the Qur’an, to be sure, which says that no compulsion should be exerted on people in matters of religion; but there are other passages, like the notorious ‘sword Sura’, which seem to tell a very different story. And most schools of Sharia law agree that a Muslim commits no sin if she or he puts to death an apostate from Islam. It is difficult for a sympathetic non-Muslim to be quite happy with the recent statement of a spokesman for Islam, in response to the aspersions of a well-known atheist, that this fact is ‘unimportant’. It has sometimes been remarked that Islam has ‘bloody borders.’ I have read of a district in western Africa, where churches are routinely damaged and Christians assaulted, being told that they will have no peace until they convert to Islam. I wish the G€ulen movement success with all my heart; but I think that it has a hard row to hoe. On the other hand, there has been very good news recently of members of the Muslim community in Britain and Canada, including some imams, actively discouraging ‘radical Islamic’ terrorism, and helping to bring to book those who engage in it, or are plotting to do so. Calgary, Canada Hugo Meynell The Mystical as Political: Democracy and Non-Radical Orthodoxy. By Aristotle Papanikolaou. Pp. x, 238, Notre Dame, IN, University of Notre Dame Press, 2012, $27.00. A blistering attack on liberalism, both in its theological and political forms, is a key element of the agenda pursued by Radical Orthodoxy, beginning with the early development of that movement in the 1990s. In contrast to Radical Orthodoxy, Papanikolaou argues that a clear understanding of Eastern Orthodox theology embodies valuable resources for a defense of liberal democracy, for the justification of talk about human rights, the common good and free speech, as well as about the separation of church and state. The most important of these resources, identified at the outset of his argument, is the traditional Orthodox mystical theology of divinehuman communion. Against the background of such a theology, the importance of certain liberal principles can be illuminated, with the Radical Orthodox 474 BOOK REVIEWS critique of those principles being exposed as problematic. This book represents a productive retrieval of certain traditional religious ideas for contemporary theological purposes. In the process, Papanikolaou develops a compelling account that stands in tension, not only with Radical Orthodoxy, but also with some standard Eastern Orthodox perspectives on the relation between religion and politics. Rather than regarding liberalism as a ‘political philosophy that was constructed as part of the modern critique against religion’ (46), Papanikolaou perceives it as being ‘grounded in the love of God’ (35). His is an account that emphasizes Christian ascetic practices for the role that they play in removing obstacles to love, as the ‘kinds of practices that one needs to perform so as to make oneself available to God’s love’ (3). This is the very heart of his argument. While not rejecting a eucharistic ecclesiology—i.e., one that identifies the eucharistic assembly as church and the Eucharist itself as the ‘space of divine-human communion’ — Papanikolaou argues that such an ecclesiology must be ‘tempered by the ascetical tradition within Christianity,’ moreover, that doing so ‘leads to an endorsement of modern liberal democracy’ (56). Divine-human communion is a eucharistic event, not something limited to the experience of individuals, but one that has public, political implications; ‘the mystical is the political’ (70). That event is not something that has been realized, once and for all, in any particular eucharistic gathering; rather, ‘the movement toward that mode of existence is through practices that allow for the divine presence to be more fully manifested’ (82). Papanikolaou proceeds to argue further that liberal human rights talk makes perfect sense only against the Trinitarian background of an Orthodox theology that conceives of personhood as being essentially relational. Similarly, he argues that the democratic notion of a common good cannot be identified with but nevertheless must be ‘analogically related to the eschatological good of divinehuman communion’ (157). In a qualified defense of free speech, Papanikolaou envisions how conversations conducted in freedom can potentially deepen understanding and reduce the risk of demonization; but this ‘power to shape relationships’ can also be misused with hateful and destructive consequences (194). Divine-human communion is not achieved apart from God’s love, and depends fully on God’s initiative. But from the human side it is a struggle to realize, enjoy and fully participate in the love that God always already offers. Fulfilling the love commandment, on Papanikolaou’s view, is not simply a matter of volition, not simply something that one decides to do; it takes practice. Because the political community is always removed at some distance from the reality of perfect communion, Christians must speak in a prophetic voice, engage continuously in a critique that measures the gap and marks the differences. But they are also a part of that imperfect community and so their politics must somehow be ‘reconceived as an ascetical practice’ (197). On his account, ‘Christian politics must be a performance of practices that either emerge from or attempt to contribute to the Christian struggle to learn to love’ (197). As already indicated, I judge this account to be persuasive and compelling. I do not regard it, however. as completely unproblematic. I worry, for example, about Papanikolaou’s apparent hostility to voluntarism. There is certainly some truth to the claim that one cannot simply will to love, but rather that ‘one must learn how to love’ (the author’s central claim in this book). Yet there might still be some important role that volition plays in the ascetic struggle, so that one wills to engage in this rather than that sort of practice, to become this rather than that sort of person. Here volition is not something that operates just in the moment to shape some decision immediately at hand, but has the long term effect, mediated by praxis, of producing determinate outcomes. It is volition nevertheless, a kind of choosing to love, to engage in love’s practices, even to remain constant in love. I also worry about the extra burden that Papanikolaou places on his argument, not merely to show that Orthodoxy is compatible with liberal democratic principles, but rather, that it alone can provide a fully adequate rationale for such principles. What would be wrong with Christians forming an overlapping consensus with others who endorse democracy for a whole variety of non-Christian reasons? Why might there not be reasons other than Trinitarian ones, for example, (the pragmatic reasons articulated by George Herbert Mead come to mind) leading one to conclude that personhood ‘must be defined in terms of relationality’ (99)? But these are minor worries that in no way serve to undermine Papanikolaou’s achievement in this admirable book. Lehigh University Michael L. Raposa BOOK REVIEWS 475 Henry VIII and His Afterlives: Literature, Politics, and Art. Edited by Mark Rankin, Christopher Highley, and John N. King. Pp. 285, Cambridge University Press, 2013 (paperback). £19.99/$29.99. ‘It is difficult,’ say the editors, ‘to describe Henry VIII wholly as a “tyrant”.’ (p.1). ‘Nor,’ they add, ‘was Henry’s exercise of violence sufficiently extreme to turn him into a compelling “portrait of evil”.’ (p.10) Evidently, they have written their Introduction without a glance at the contents of the very volume they have edited. Well, let’s take a glance. ‘There can no longer be any doubt,’ says Dale Hoak, ‘that Henry VIII was ‘the greatest of English tyrants.’ (p.62) ‘He hath been known,’ declares a contemporary Protestant, ‘and noted over all, to be the greatest tyrant that ever was in England.’ (p.76) The name of Henry VIII, adds the Catholic Reginald Pole, ‘is notorious throughout the Christian world like no other for centuries.’ (p.83) He is described by the Puritan Anthony Gilby as ‘that tyrant and lecherous monster’. (p.87) Even the Whig historians, Edward Herbert, Gilbert Burnet and David Hume, agree ‘that Henry was a cruel, capricious, and despotic king’ (p.128). Reflecting on their opinions, Swift sees him as ‘one of the worst princes of any age or country’ (p.129), as ‘that monster and tyrant’ and ‘among all the princes who ever reigned in the world’ as ‘never so infernal a beast’ (p.130). Dickens, too, dismisses him as ‘a disgrace to human nature, and a blot of blood and grease upon the history of England’. (p.262) Finally, to all these descriptions one may add the glaring omission of the famous words of Sir Walter Raleigh in the Preface to his History of the World, ‘If all the pictures and patterns of a merciless prince were lost in the world, they might all again be painted to the life out of the story of this king.’ Then how, we may ask the editors, can they condone what the more recent historian Sir Charles Oman has condemned as ‘the cold-blooded deliberate cruelty’ of such a tyrant ‘that marked not only his advancing years but his whole reign’? (p.253) Well, wasn’t he ‘England’s last great medieval prince’? (p.3) Wasn’t he moved by a desire ‘to display magnificence in peace and war’? (p.55) Mayn’t he be seen as ‘the last of the troubadours and the heir of Burgundian chivalry’? (p.55) Mayn’t he be admired as ‘the heavy Holbein figure, legs outspread like the Colossus of Rhodes’, as ‘the jolly, bluff Harry, the gormandizer, hunter, and womanizer’? (p.115) Doesn’t he mark what historians like J.J. Scarisbrick recognize as “England’s transition to modernity’? (p.54) Mayn’t he even be hailed, as the AngloCatholic Maynard Smith hails him, as ‘the Maker of Modern England’? (p.255) Even the abovementioned Whig historians, who condemn him as a tyrant, admit that ‘in the long run his acts were justified by the triumph of English Protestantism’. (p.128) Only, Swift can’t agree with them, on seeing such a tyrant ‘celebrated as an instrument in that glorious work of the Reformation.’ (p.129) To put it very crudely, as a contemporary author put it, ‘the Reformation here in England’ might be attributed to ‘Henry VIII’s codpiece’ (p.176), or what Shakespeare calls ‘the rebellion of a codpiece’ (Measure for Measure iii.2). ‘Poor Henry VIII!’ one feels like exclaiming, ‘Was he really such a bad man?’ ‘Yes,’ says Scarisbrick, ‘Henry VIII was not only a bad man but an egregiously bad king as well’, and insofar as he may have achieved anything, it was ‘a disunity from which (we) have not yet fully recovered.’ (p.259) AL Rowse, as another recent historian, goes so far as to affirm that Henry was ‘the nearest thing the English have ever had to an Ivan the Terrible or a Stalin’ (p.254). Such an affirmation is qualified by a reminder of ‘that historian’s proclivity for provocation and controversy than indicative of any deep groundswell of historical opinion’, but this whole volume is precisely indicative of just such a groundswell, extending over so many generations. On the other hand – for in such matters of moral judgment there has always to be an other hand – what about, we may well ask, poor Stalin, and poor Ivan the Terrible, not to mention poor Hitler? Weren’t they all human beings? Didn’t they all show a certain tenderness towards women and children? Weren’t they variously moved by a patriotic desire to spend their lives, their money, and their people, for the good of their nation? It is so reminiscent of a certain old lady, who had nothing but good to say about others. ‘Then what about the devil?’ she was challenged. ‘Well,’ she said, ‘you must admit he does his job very efficiently.’ Now, I feel prompted to add, poor editors! Evidently they set out with the commendable desire to celebrate the fifth centenary of Henry VIII’s accession to the throne of England in 1509, and I imagine them farming out the requisite contents to the appropriate contributors. Only, what have they reaped but a whirlwind of condemnation instead of commendation, or at least condonation? And mayn’t I be accused of having made matters worse for them, by picking out the plums of condemnation? But that isn’t all. Now, I feel further promptings to point out other plums I was looking for in a book of this kind, but which I have failed to find. Even in their Introduction the editors excuse themselves for their omission of ‘any sustained 476 BOOK REVIEWS treatment of Henry VIII among English Catholics’ (p.4). Why is this? I ask. Because Catholics are certain to condemn him, they may answer. But, as I have shown with all the plums I have pulled out of the pie, almost all of them are Protestant plums. Apparently, Protestants have been no less loud in their condemnation of Henry as a tyrant than Catholics, even though it was he who set afoot the whole process of Reformation in England – when they would have preferred another to have done so. At least, in the subsequent discussion of the old Whig historians or the later modern historians, they might have made mention of John Lingard, if only in contrast to Lord Macaulay. Then, on the Protestant side, why have they omitted all mention of John Milton, who is one of the few Protestant advocates of Henry VIII, if only for Henry’s advocacy of divorce and implicitly of pro-choice? And then, delving further into ‘the dark backward and abysm of time’, if they admit mention of Reginald Pole (p.83), why do they omit all mention of the book that drew down Henry’s ire more than anything else, his Pro Ecclesiasticae Unitatis Defensione? Not only was that book the immediate Catholic response to Henry’s claim to be Supreme Head of the Church in England, but it also drew down the royal revenge on Pole’s mother, the saintly Countess of Salisbury. Above all, what about Shakespeare? He is only glanced at towards the end of this volume, and only for the play of Henry VIII to which he merely contributed some minor scenes in conjunction with John Fletcher, and for which he can hardly bear full responsibility – least of all the final Act with its dependence on Foxe’s Book of Martyrs and its fulsome praise of the future Elizabeth put into the mouth of Cranmer. Yet it isn’t only over this play but over not a few of the preceding Jacobean plays, that the shadow of Henry VIII is cast – not only in the characters of Cymbeline as king of Britain and Leontes as king of the three-cornered island of Sicilia (as England), but even in the earlier characters of Othello and Lear. After all, if Henry’s reign has, in the words of Scarisbrick, ‘left deeper marks on the mind, heart, and face of England than did any event in English history’ from the Norman Conquest till the Industrial Revolution (p.54), how could it have been ignored by England’s dramatist – apart from his plaintive description of ‘bare ruined choirs where late the sweet birds sang’ (in Sonnet 73), and a romance at the very end of his dramatic career which is pock-marked by collaboration with the Protestant John Fletcher? Finally, I have a complaint to make not only against this book but against so many academic books published in these postmodern times. What, I wonder, is the need of a sub-title, when a wellchosen title should be sufficient? Isn’t ‘The Afterlives of Henry VIII’ apt enough as a description of the contents of this book, without the unnecessary addition of ‘Literature, Politics, and Art’? Or even if, as sometimes happens, a cryptic title is chosen, why does it have to be explained in the sub-title? Why not keep the reader guessing, as Shakespeare loves to keep his spectators guessing, so as to oblige them to open the book and read the explanatory preface? Then, of course, they may well find it is just ‘much ado about nothing’/ Sophia University, Tokyo Peter Milward Rethinking Shakespeare’s Political Philosophy: From Lear to Leviathan. By Alex Schulman. Pp. 227, Edinburgh University Press, 2014, £70.00. Why, oh why, must postmodern scholars choose to relapse into an incomprehensible academic jargon? Why must they feel obliged to refer again and again to the writings of their various academic colleagues to prove that they are abreast of all the latest books and articles and even unpublished doctoral theses on their chosen subject? And why must academic editors and university publishers require the use of such jargon before consenting to edit or publish such books? Such a book by such an author is, needless to say, the present book now under review, dealing though it does with such a fascinating subject as the political theory implicit in the plays and poems of Shakespeare. (Yet again one may wonder about the need of such a sub-title as “From Lear to Leviathan”, considering that King Lear is but one of the many plays and Hobbes’ Leviathan offers but one of the many political theories discussed in these pages.) After all, Shakespeare was living and writing in an age when political theory had become inextricably linked as well with religious controversies as with the consciences of common people, and he himself draws attention to the fact that his plays are presented not just for the entertainment of his audiences but also as ‘the abstracts and brief chronicles of the time’ (Hamlet ii.2). In particular, in his assessment of the political philosophy of Shakespeare, the author draws an apt distinction between the impact of antiquity on the Roman plays and that of modernity on the tragedies and problem plays. Only by ‘antiquity’ he refers chiefly to the dialogues of Plato, in which he is far better versed than Shakespeare could have been, and by BOOK REVIEWS ‘modernity’ he draws comparisons between the plays and modern political thought from Hobbes to Marx, while omitting the millennium of medieval Christian tradition, which was after all much more familiar to the dramatist than either Plato or those modern thinkers. True, Shakespeare was by no means ignorant of classical antiquity, but his knowledge came to him not only through the Renaissance with its revival of Platonic studies in Florence, but also through the Aristotelian philosophy studied at all the universities. In either case, however, the knowledge was largely filtered through the Catholic faith of the medieval scholars. As for the modern thinkers from Hobbes onwards, concerning whom the author is again far better versed than Shakespeare could possibly have been, they could hardly have exercised any influence on him, though on many of them, notably on Karl Marx and Sigmund Freud, it was the dramatist who exercised his profound influence – as G.K.Chesterton humorously remarked in an essay ‘On Writing Badly’, ‘How can we discuss how we should have written Shakespeare? Shakespeare has written us.’ As for the medieval tradition which Shakespeare inherited as his birthright, though it was already in process of strangulation under the long rule of the Protestant ‘Virgin Queen’, there is no doubt – and the author graciously admits it – that both in his poems (such as Sonnet 73, with its sad mention of ‘bare ruined choirs’) and in his plays (such as especially As You Like It, with its setting in the Forest of Arden) we cannot help recognizing a deep undercurrent of nostalgia, as when the sorrowing father laments over the dead body of his dear daughter, ‘Thou’lt come no more,/ Never, never, never, never, never!’ Yet in spite of it all, the author makes the bold assertion at the end of his Introduction, ‘I cast my vote with modernity, and with Shakespeare the modern.” (p.19) Needless to say, the author goes on to present his detailed reasons for making this assertion, in terms of what he sees as ‘the interaction between emergent English nationalism and the Protestant Reformation’ (p.138), and the ‘novel religious energy’ of the Protestant reformers rather than a ‘backward-looking religious tradition’ – and he concludes, without the shadow of a proof, that Shakespeare was (as we say) ‘with it’. In order to maintain this negative, however, I can hardly be expected to consider all the plays, whether standing for antiquity or for modernity, and so I may be pardoned for concentrating my attention on two of the plays chosen by the author for his discussion of ‘modernity’, the tragedy of King Lear, which receives special mention in the sub-title, and the problem play of Measure for Measure, which 477 comes in for longest discussion over some 40 pages. Concerning King Lear in general, the author makes the unnecessary negation that the play ‘is not a journey from Old Testament legalism to New Testament agape’ (p.106) – as if there were anyone making such an affirmation. Obviously, it is a journey of the old king from the lack of selfknowledge as originally noted in him by his daughter Regan through a progressive growth of selfknowledge in ‘the school of adversity’ till he comes to the full knowledge of himself in Cordelia. Secondly, concerning the connection between Cordelia and Edgar, he proposes that ‘hers is the moral apotheosis, his the secular inheritance’ (p.105), while going so far as to suggest the further possibility of ‘aligning Cordelia with Edmund’ (p.114). Evidently, however, Cordelia and Edgar are the two ‘saints’ of the play leading their long suffering parents to their salvation. From the beginning Cordelia is welcomed by France with words that, so far from being restricted to what is called ‘a Gospel last-shall-befirst flavour’ (p.106), are a tissue of Messianic prophecies, implying that she is a Christ-figure. As for Edgar, in his flight from his father’s house and his decision to have resort to disguise, so far from being a ‘sadomasochist’ (p.114), he is clearly the pattern of a hunted priest against whom anachronistic ‘proclamations’ are published, ‘intelligence’ is given, and all ports are watched. As for Edmund, what on earth, one wonders, is there in common between his villainy and Cordelia’s sanctity? Finally, as for the sad ending of Act V, it is here interpreted as a transition ‘not from Paganism to Christianity, but from religious enchantment to materialism’ (p.116) – as if anyone had hitherto seriously proposed either of these alternatives. Rather, out of a succession of ‘broken hearts’ and ‘side-piercing sights’ in Act IV, recalling the Biblical piercing of the side of Christ on the Cross (John xix.34), there comes the nonBiblical climax of the Pieta, when the sorrowing father is seated on stage holding the dead body of his innocent daughter to the accompaniment of Albany’s exclamation, ‘O see, see!’ from the Lamentations of Jeremiah (i.12), ‘Behold and see, if there be any sorrow like unto my sorrow!’ Next, as for the problem play of Measure for Measure, the author comments that ‘the disturbance to order is novel religious energy rather than backward-looking religious tradition’ (p.158), whereas it rather, and more obviously, consists in the contrast between Catholic tradition, represented by the duke turned friar and by the would-be novice seeking admission to the convent of Poor Clares, and the Puritanical judge Angelo – for which reason it has been called, by Christopher Devlin in his Hamlet’s Divinity (1983) ‘the most 478 BOOK REVIEWS Catholic of Shakespeare’s plays’. As for Isabella, the author speaks twice of her hoped for ‘progress towards holy orders’ (pp.183,198), whereas the sacrament of ‘holy orders’ in the Catholic Church is only for priests, not nuns. He also ascribes to the mind of the dramatist a see-saw ‘between Isabella’s valuation of purity as admirable and as absurd’ (p.175), whereas this is his own imagination – if also the imagination of all too many unsympathetic critics. Lastly, it is again his imagination that sees Isabella accepting the twice repeated proposal of Duke Vincentio, as if she is choosing ‘the secularpolitical world of marriage and procreation’, whereas the dramatist leaves an ambiguity between what may be seen as a realistic refusal and an allegorical acceptance. Much more remains to be said about the strange, yet sophisticated, interpretations of this author, but sapienti satis. It is enough for me to have given a taste of his arguments on behalf of Shakespeare’s ‘modernity’, whereas, in contrast to what I would rather emphasize as the dramatist’s pervasive nostalgia, the author fails to admit his commitment to those whom he himself seems to criticize as ‘the new political technicians of the age of Bacon’ (p.57). Sophia University, Tokyo Peter Milward Revolutionary Ideas: An Intellectual History of the French Revolution from The Rights of Man to Robespierre. By Jonathon Israel. Pp. viii, 870. Princeton University Press, 2014, £27.95/$39.95. Israel here recounts the history of the French Revolution in light of the ideas behind the events. Without entirely discounting the role played by other social, material, cultural, political, and economic factors, Israel argues that radical Enlightenment thought was the chief cause of the Revolution. Israel describes his work as filling ‘the gaping, causal void’ left all too often by a purely social or socioeconomic interpretations. (6) That this void gapes even in other ‘revisionist’ literature available about the French Revolution is the reason why this book was written and should be read. (29) Israel supports his claims with 25 chapters in addition to a prologue. These are researched with attention to primary sources. The first chapter is an introduction, identifying the central role played by ‘la philosophie’ in propelling the Revolution forward. Israel admits that even within French thought traceable to the Enlightenment there were multiple philosophical stances. The true Revolution was sparked by a strain traceable to Rousseau, Diderot, and Helvetius, and generally opposed to that of Montesquieu, Locke, Voltaire and Hume, especially in their approval of moderate British government. (23) The core of revolutionary thought was characterized by a commitment to rationally knowable human rights with a strong focus on the radical equality of all men. The following chapters proceed with a joint historical and thematic movement. In reasonable short chapters, Israel gives a careful narration of the events of the Revolution. He places the beginning of the French Revolution in the cultural ‘Revolution of the Press’ in 1788 (Chapter 2) and its close in the ratification of the New Constitution of 1799, identified as the ‘Failure of the Revolution’ (Chapter 24). Chapter 23 looks abroad to consider the impact of the Revolution on Holland, Italy and the Levant. Throughout these chapters, Israel co-relates the dissemination of ideas with historical events. The detail with which he writes means that this book could serve as an introductory history, although the intricacy of his treatment will probably appeal most to those who already have an interest either in the historical events or their propelling ideas. In several of the chapters, Israel pauses the forward motion of his account to clarify particular submovements within it. Such pauses include Chapter 7: ‘War with the Church,’ Chapter 11: ‘Republicans Divided’, Chapter 14: ‘Education: Securing the Revolution’, Chapter 15: ‘Black Emancipation’, and Chapter 18: ‘De-Christianization’. These chapters are still written as historical narrations, but deal with subsets of events and themes. While they supply needed considerations to the work as a whole, they could be enjoyed individually by anyone familiar with the outline of the Revolution. Since it falls under the theme of equality, Israel is careful to trace the role of women in the philosophy and action of the Revolution but does not devote a unique chapter to this issue. In the concluding Chapter 25, Israel reaffirms his thesis in the light of the evidence he has amassed. He clarifies the three main ideological movements present in the Revolution: radical Enlightenment thought, moderate Enlightenment thought, and an authoritarian populism. The first of these was the true spring of the Revolution, and the reason for its enduring relevance. As an instance of why such clarification is of crucial importance, Israel distinguishes the bloody Reign of Terror from the Enlightenment center of the Revolution. The Terror was a temporary undoing of the Revolution. It was caused by peripheral authoritarian currents and quickly reversed, submerged again by the dominant BOOK REVIEWS humanistic philosophy. The French Revolution proved the power of a secular egalitarian conception of human life, which, although it was eclipsed in France, has had an impact on almost all modern systems of government. Israel’s sorting, tracing and classifying of the various strains of thought present in the French Revolution results in several provocative conclusions. Among these could be placed the idea that certain strains thought which were influential during the French Revolution should not be considered as truly belonging to it. Israel himself recognizes that many of his theses cut across conventional ideas. His interpretation of the Reign of Terror is one of the most obvious instances of this. Israel also rejects the idea that the Revolution, at its core, was compatible with Christianity so that 479 the de-Christianizing impulse in the movement was non-essential. (28) He maintains that radical equality based on the grounds of reason alone is inimical to both the doctrines and structures of Christianity as it was known in France in the 1700s. This seems to be a valid historical claim. Israel, however, speaks as though real concern for the good of the people belongs exclusively to secular democracies. Help in navigating through the multitude of names and dates referenced in the work is provided by a glossary-type ‘Cast of Main Participants’ with 167 short entries. 22 illustrations depict mostly these figures or revolutionary emblems. The book includes a Bibliography and Index. Ave Maria University Sr. Albert Marie Surmanski The Dark Side of Church/State Separation: The French Revolution, Nazi Germany, and International Communism. By Stephen Strehle. Pp. xviii, 383, New Brunswick/London, Transaction Publishers, 2014, £38.11. Strehle has patrolled the Church/State frontier in four previous books. Basically he thinks the separation of spheres is a good thing, but in this book he shows that since the Enlightenment this separation has gone too far and become a hostility. Specifically, from Rousseau, Voltaire, and the French Revolution onwards, left-wing and sceptical thinkers have indicted the Judaeo-Christian tradition as a thinlydisguised ideology and tissue of lies used by the Ancien R egime to stay in power. The Catholic Church made the mistake of resisting reform movements towards the dismantling of hereditary privilege and the promotion of a more egalitarian society that has been the chief social dynamic of the West since the Renaissance, and has paid a terrible price. An equally extreme counter-position has as a consequence repeatedly come to power and erected a ‘wall’ between church and state, developed a Deist (or atheistic) natural religion and philosophy to provide a foundation for morals (the only recognized socially useful role for religion), feigning a false ‘respect’ for the Judaeo-Christian tradition by hypocritically guaranteeing it a separate sphere where it is effectively marginalized and prevented from having any real impact on society or politics, and insisting on controlling the educational system, whereby this alternative and openly-hostile view of nature and history counters any religious influence young people are exposed to on the Sabbath or at home, so as to gradually wean them away from the religion of their ancestors. Strehle considers three famous cases: the French Revolution, Nazi Germany, and International Communism (with a fourth case, the United States, where Thomas Jefferson dupes Bap- tists in Virginia and Congregationalists in New England to achieve the same result). ‘Only connect’ said E. M. Forster, and Strehle connects all the dots, supplies a mountain of data, and basically builds an unanswerable case. A surprising thesis Strehle establishes is that the Enlightenment, rather than being a ‘friend’ to the Jews (after all, Jewish Emancipation occurred as a result of Napoleon spreading the results of the French Revolution to the rest of Europe) was actually the source of virulent and rabid modern antiSemitism. Earlier the latter was a baseless prejudice repeatedly countered by the Church; the Enlightenment established a ‘ground’ for this hostility by tracing their objections to the Christian god back to the ‘god’ of the Jewish Old Testament, whose irrational, egotistical, exclusivist, territorial, cruel and materialistic tendencies they held the Jewish people themselves took on. The Jews were ‘liberated’ from their ghettos, but only if they gave up their entire previous identity and assimilated, not to their ‘daughter’ Christianity, but to the new hostile and disfigured portrait of their previous selves and their god – a feat Enlightenment ideologues themselves thought was impossible. There could therefore be only one ‘enlightened’ solution to this social problem – a ‘final’ solution. Strehle ratifies Theodore Herzl’s insistence on the necessity of Zionism: the Enlightenment has turned the modern ‘liberal’ nations of Europe more anti-Semitic than they ever were before, despite their protests to the contrary. Don’t believe them: Sal si puede. Get out while you still can. Heythrop College Patrick Madigan 480 BOOK REVIEWS Statecraft and Salvation: Wilsonian Liberal Internationalism as Secularized Eschatology. By Milan Babık. Pp. x, 267, Waco, TX, Baylor University Press, 2013, £39.44. In this expansion of his doctoral dissertation, Babık succeeds in establishing Wilson’s liberal internationalism as a movement to ‘immanentize the eschaton’, which in a sense is true of all utopian thought, deriving ultimately from the heterodox philosophy of history of Joachim of Fiore. Unlike St. Augustine, who held that the ‘City of Man’ could never coincide with the ‘City of God’, that ‘salvation’ happens along an axis distinct from secular ‘progress’, and thus that good and evil will be with us until the final judgment, no matter how many scientific and technological breakthroughs we make, Joachim fused the two and engaged in Biblical and theological exegesis in an attempt to read God’s purposes within secular and political history. Babık overreaches, however, in attempting to lift Wilson’s program to the same level of urgency and ruthless, uncompromising dedication to an abstract ‘vision’ or ‘scheme’ that must be realized at all costs, as was true of the ‘totalitarian’ programs of Nazism and Bolschevism, trampling the rights of individuals and entire nations in desperate and single-minded pursuit of an all-consuming ‘dream’. What is disappointing about this book is that the evidence the author musters does not support his thesis. As Babık shows, Wilson’s program with regard to both democracy and capitalism was reformist at heart, not revolutionary; he was a gradualist who worked from the ‘bottom up’ to improve existing institutions, rather than from the ‘top down’, razing everything and rebuilding according to an ideal scheme. Babık has Wilson opposing a Biblicalmatrix approach to the ‘salvation’ of social problems to one predicated on rational study and secular analysis. The ultimate sources of Wilson’s psychology were certainly his Presbyterian Christianity, but there is nothing to suggest that he thought this excluded reason or secular analysis of the ills that afflict society. Further, he correctly saw that the only rhetoric that could move Americans (and hold them together) at this time to make the painful but necessary changes was one that harked back to the Puritan Fathers, invoking Biblical and Gospel images extolling America’s vocation in world history. Babık’s thesis is further unsupported by his reading of history. What fell into crisis during the latter half of the 19th century was not only religious faith, but crucially as far as statecraft is concerned, the Enlightenment faith that reason and Stateinterest could somehow produce both domestic peace and a ‘concert of nations’ internationally. In the face of the apparent collapse of these assumptions, the ‘secular’ option of the totalitarian thinkers was to ramp up the intensity and rigor of Enlightenment critique to produce a ‘hyperrational’ vision that alone, they believed, could save us from the abyss that threatened to swallow the earth. The ‘religious’ response was to confess our sinful abuse of existing institutions and work to purge corruption so that they could serve everyone. In the wake of the First World War, the League of Nations could never bring ‘salvation’ or ‘the end of history’ in the form of a guaranteed peace, nor could it enforce ‘conversion’, personal or corporate; what it could do, which its successor the United Nations is attempting to do, is to supply mechanisms that allow every other option to be explored before two groups become belligerants. Babık’s thesis stumbles over its own inflated, hyperbolic rhetoric. Heythrop College Patrick Madigan Politics and Faith: Reinhold Niebuhr and Paul Tillich at Union Seminary in New York. By Ronald H. Stone. Pp. xix, 486, Macon, GA, Mercer University Press, 2012, £39.95/e47.00. Stone was a student of both Niebuhr and Tillich at Union Seminary and draws upon extremely thorough research to produce this, the seventh book he has authored or edited on his mentors, and almost certainly the definitive statement on the political theology they cooperated in producing, as they both – from German backgrounds on opposite sides of the Atlantic – came out of the First World War and in their despair saw Europe falling impotently into yet another World War. They both protested the social inequities and economic injustice the capitalist order had engendered, which led them to jointly propose a Christian Socialism; they did not believe, however, that the ‘captains of industry’, even in democratic countries, would ever allow such an agenda to be voted into effect. Protest, struggle, and suffering – as on the model of Gandhi’s ‘nonviolent resistance’, strikes (even if officially ‘illegal’), boycotts, etc. would thus be the order for the day for Christians if, accepting their bit of the cross, they choose to be BOOK REVIEWS true to the prophetic strand in their faith and respond to the ‘kairos’ or ‘season’, as the needs and opportunities of the time are disclosed to them. In this they vastly underestimated the capacity of capitalism to respond to the socialist agenda; not under that name in America, the home of ‘rugged individualism’, but in effect in such measures as civil rights, equal educational opportunities, minimum wage, progressive income tax, unemployment compensation, pensions, medical care, etc., that gradually transformed America in the post-World War II era. What impresses a Catholic reader is the pessimism of these two thinkers about human nature, their effectively Marxist indictment of liberalism’s ‘optimism’ and ‘naivete’ about individual egoism and corporate venality. This bespeaks a deeper difference in the kind of ‘spirituality’ they claim Christianity calls one to. For these thinkers it is impossible to appropriate the traditional neo-Platonic model of individual growth towards holiness, moving through conversion, penance, then purification and contemplation, culminating in union (to some extent) with the divine. Having imbibed instead the secular ‘masters of suspicion’, these two effectively hold that such ‘purification’ (and consequent ‘union’) can never take place, at least not until universal justice is achieved – which incidentally never arrives. To move towards personal holiness ‘prematurely’ is to escape into ‘false consciousness’ and to shirk or evade one’s obligation to participate instead in the social struggle. Human nature is so infected with sinfulness that all ideas are polluted from their source with self-interest, and all institutions are inherently distorted by a desire for increased power. No amount of ‘conversion’ can remove this. 481 A Catholic could of course participate in the same struggles for social equality and economic justice as ‘spinoffs’ from having moved towards greater union with the deity, but not as a guiltobsessed, embarrassed long-term preparation for such, nor as a compensatory substitute for having failed to achieve – or even having failed to try for – such union. One could cynically suggest that these thinkers excuse their lack of personal conversion on the grounds that it’s impossible anyway – so why make the effort? The amazing cornucopia of the post-WWII industrial output challenges their blanket discounting of the capacity of capitalist entrepreneurship to supply the material means for a fulfilling life to the entire world’s population. More seriously, given Protestantism’s claim to return to a pristine, pre-institutional ‘authentic’ Christian position, both St. Paul and St. Augustine (and all the early Church Fathers) lived in a world where slavery was an accepted social institution, whose eventual overthrow they did not envisage. Paul advises slaves to obey their masters; more importantly he does not consider their condition an impediment to their becoming good Christians, nor does he see their embrace of Christianity as a ‘flight into false consciousness’ or an ‘opiate of the proletariat’ as Marx would later brand it. These two Protestant thinkers make justice a precondition for turning to the agenda of personal holiness – which conveniently never arrives – rather than a consequence and practical offshoot of such - which should, and to some extent must, come first. Heythrop College Patrick Madigan The Protestant Ethic or The Spirit of Capitalism: Christians, Freedom, and Free Markets. By Kathryn D. Blanchard. Pp.xxi, 239. Eugene, Oregon, Cascade Books, 2010, $29.00. Business as Usual: The Economic Crisis and the Failure of Capitalism. By Paul Mattick. Pp. 126. London, Reaktion Books, 2011, £12.95. One of the keystones of Kathryn Blanchard’s argument is that there is no inevitable antagonism between capitalism and Christianity. To be sure, capitalism can take noxious forms against which Christians should protest but, Blanchard opines, it also comes in more humane varieties which Christians can embrace. The trick is to develop economic theories with a robust moral content. This, Blanchard suggests, is what Calvin did by placing his musings on freedom and law and a commitment to ‘neighbour love’ at the heart of his analysis of work, consumption, and exchange. And it is apparently what Adam Smith did, too. Smith was all for a free market but he held that it could ‘flourish only within his ideal community — one guided by honesty, self-limitation, and [that phrase again] neighbour love’ (xv). ‘Sympathetic self-interest’ may look like a contradiction in terms but we’re told that it was the lodestone of Smith’s theories. The crucial point is that someone like Smith insisted on the moral bearings of economic theorising but many of his successors failed to follow his example and this, on Blanchard’s account, is when the rot began to set in. The so-called ‘Chicago School’ is top of her list of targets and figures such as George Stigler, Gary Becker and Milton Friedman are accused, with considerable justification, of allowing ethics to drop out of economic 482 BOOK REVIEWS analysis. The capitalism that ensued is precisely the kind with which Christians are bound to have problems but other theorists have seen the sense in returning ethical considerations to their rightful status. Blanchard tackles, among others, Deirdre McCloskey, Julie Nelson, and Muhammad Yunus, and suggests that Christians can enter into fruitful dialogue with their ideas. Blanchard’s book is unapologetically anachronistic and it imposes a false unity on five centuries of economic thought but it is passionately written and opens up some intriguing avenues of enquiry. Those who take a bleaker view of capitalism and believe that it is beyond moral redemption will be more sympathetic to Paul Mattick’s angry volume, in which Marx looms much larger than Christ. Inspired by the recent economic downturn, Mattick argues that most analysts are looking for excuses when they should be admitting to capitalism’s fundamental flaws. It is not enough, he argues, to blame our present woes on a series of strategic mistakes and irresponsible practices. Trying to ‘fix’ the system is a pointless exercise, because this assumes that the system can be repaired, and it is ’hard to imagine a more stunning demonstration of the theoretical bankruptcy of economics as a putative science’ (67). This is an old tune, but whistling it again is at least timely and Mattick does a decent job of exposing the historical cycle of boom and bust and some of his predictions will presumably come true: when the oil runs out and when the consequences of climate change hit home capitalism will find itself in quite a pickle. Unfortunately, for all the rousing rhetoric, no concrete solutions are supplied. All we really get is an invitation to establish new forms of organised activity and a new social system and a rehashing of the old imperative to abolish the distinction between those who control and those who perform the work of production. Fabulous ideas, no doubt, but how exactly are they to be achieved? Reading these books in tandem obliges us to confront the question that shows no sign of going away: is capitalism one of the worst ideas that humanity ever came up with or, with a lot of tinkering, could it prove to be a workable and sustainable system that doesn’t obliterate human dignity? Time, one imagines, will tell. University of Durham Jonathan Wright The Subject, Capitalism, and Religion. By Jung Mo Sung. Pp. 171, London, Palgrave Macmillan, 2012, £55.00. Pentecostalism and Prosperity. Edited by Katherine Attanasi and Amos Yong. Pp. xii, 261, London, Palgrave Macmillan, 2012, £55.00. The first book is part of a series on New Approaches to Religion and Power with a preface by the series editor Joerg Rieger. The book is based around six papers given around 2001. Jung Mo Sung’s first chapter helpfully gives some memories that shape his theology. His family arrived in Brazil from South Korea in 1965. When he was 15 he began to participate in a young people’s group with the Catholic Church doing aid work to protect rural migrants in Sao Paolo. Though his group did not have a social or political conscience, but simply played with poor children, the face-to-face encounter was an experience of grace which was the only thing that got him up in the morning without complaining. Later, however, as the eldest child of an immigrant family himself, he had to take on responsibilities in the family business. He quickly learned that ‘good words do not solve concrete problems.’ These cold, hard practical lessons complemented and contradicted what he was learning about the mystery of gratitude. However, it was not only good words that were incapable of solving problems. Sung relates his encounter with the ‘science’ of economics, and the day to day concrete reality of business. He found the former theoretical and unreal. In fact, as he discovered, there is something ‘spiritual’ about marketing in particular. The most important aspects of a product are what the consumer things about it, and what others come to think of him or her for consuming it. Moreover, he found that unless you are a consumer (not ‘excluded’) you do not exist. Leaving business school for seminary he was first thrilled by new arguments, then unsettled by a crisis of faith. What survived for Sung was not doctrinal belief assimilated by the catechetical process but a foundation in a spiritual experience of grace, especially that grace that comes when we are indignant at the suffering of the innocent, a foundation, however, which must be reasonable. With Gramsci he discovered that history was not so much the unfolding of God’s will but the conflict of social classes. Realising that one need not be a priest to do theology he left and then passionately pursued the new theology of liberation and the option for the poor. From Dussel he learned of the intrinsic relations between the economy (production and exchange) and the Eucharist; and from Hinkelammert, of the fetishism and idolatry, not only of capitalism, but of a utopianism unable to recognise limits. With Julio de Santa Ana he began to realise that liberation theology had a theme missing – the economy – and argued this in his doctoral BOOK REVIEWS research. A further critique of the idolatry of the market is found in Assmann, but Sung points out that this does not mean doing away with markets, or leaving the Left uncritiqued. With Segundo he leaned of God’s revelation as a pedagogical process and with Girard the theme of mimetic desire in consumption. Sung is torn between the urgent need to respond now to the cry of the poor and the far off goal of thinking painstakingly through the many theoretical issues, which are never resolved to his own satisfaction. I shall pass over his complex chapter on the Subject, Transcendentality within Real Life, and simply suggest that, for Sung, the Subject might almost be defined as ‘an exigence for indignation’ and attend to an issue that is related to the complex notion of structural sin, namely that of self-organisation. Sung considers the accounts of self-organising systems with the market in mind. Apologists such as Samuelson record how the market ‘just evolved,’ without being designed. This is Adam Smith’s ‘invisible hand.’ Biological evolution, too, has been invoked in support of neoliberalism. Sung is bound, now, to concede with Assmann, (once so critical of the market in the 1970s) that there is some (partial) self-regulation. But this problematizes the moral subject: the market does not need morality to be efficient– indeed, family values writ large may positively hinder efficiency and he makes the point with Sen that without anyone’s property rights being infringed, the most extreme famines can still occur. This leads him to a distinction taken from George Soros between rule-making and playing by the rules. Hence the need: ‘to place the economic system itself with its institutions and rules as the object of analysis’ (108). The agent must understand structures so that she can change them. Sung, then, is a second generation liberation theologian, clinging without certainty to his dreams, living in hope, but honestly and anxiously seeking to respond with solidarity to the human condition. Some very different responses to the cry of the poor are on display in the second book. In recent decades there has been increasing awareness of the phenomenon of ‘World Christianity,’ prompting the publishers to commission a series of monographs on Christianities of the World. Thirteen contributors to a conference on ‘Pentecostalism and Prosperity,’ held at Regent University in 2011 present their research. Representing diverse disciplines and perspectives and presenting case studies from around the globe, a striking series of portraits is given of the ‘renewal’ movement which can trace its roots to the Azusa Street Revival of 1906 and which now accounts for 483 a quarter of the world’s two billion Christians. The theme of the volume is the prosperity gospel. God has promised not only the salvation of souls but divine healing and material prosperity. Christ’s ministry is to the whole person, and such a message engenders hope in impoverished situations, a fact that has economic consequences, especially for the poor who are typically the ‘consumers’ of such good news. This, of course, is not the only understanding of the biblical message, and in introductory sections various typologies are discussed and respondents conclude with calls for discernment. Some insight into the pluralism and tensions involved can gleaned from the seven case studies that form the heart of the book. One contrast is that of South Africa and Eastern Europe. The contributors to a South African think tank (CDE), with the assistance of Peter Berger, strike an optimistic note of the possibilities of energising civil society by the entrepreneurial spirit of the Pentecostal movement which has tended to slip underneath the secular radar screen. Max Weber’s thesis that Protestantism has given spiritual sanction to the rational pursuit of economic gain now has added force. On the other hand, Daniela C. Augustine, after discussing the way that the prosperity gospel can be viewed as a spiritual platform for neoliberal capitalist values, charts the ways that the transition to a market economy after 1989 has been worse than even many Communist leaders had predicted. Accordingly, in a region marked by communitarian values (whether from Orthodoxy or Marxism) the prosperity gospel has not taken root. Secular Europe, however, is an exception. Eloy H. Nolivos examines the neoliberal transitions in Latin America and discusses the Weberian thesis. Is Pentecostalism a resource for development? In one respect it helps as an anchor for the dislodged masses of the globalised continent. The dislodged of Los Angeles can be found in the Oasis Christian Center, a converted cinema located blocks away from Hollywood’s Walk of Fame. Gerardo Marti interviews those seeking uncertain success in the entertainment industry. He explores the tremendous role religion has for those navigating their ‘life plan’ in a labour market requiring individualisation and the acquisition of a variety of work skills. The anxieties of the financial crisis are in the minds of those attending the Southwest Believers’ Conference in Texas. Five evangelists in rotation urge the believers to stop worrying and start sowing. ‘This is not our crisis’ affirms Creflo Dollar to great applause. The appeal is simple, have faith, tithe and you will reap sevenfold. The luxury car must be ‘named and claimed.’ Jonathan L. Walton 484 BOOK REVIEWS asks Earl whether this is his recession. He is 57, laid off from his construction job and broke. ‘Shoot, if I didn’t know Jesus, I would have shot myself in the head.’ Despite the obvious lack of prosperity (the plush hotels are empty) the pious devotion to authoritative, simple, Biblical truths is found compelling and convincing. Wenzhou is on the East coast of China, about three hundred miles North of Taiwan, and three hundred miles South of Shanghai. As China has opened up, trade has brought sudden wealth. Wenzhou Christians regard their city as the Jerusalem of China and Nanlai Cao gives an illuminating insight into the significance of the purchase of real estate for the sake of erecting church buildings by ‘boss Christians.’ The desire for large emotion-filled spaces has led to the funding of widespread church building by wealthy entrepreneurs. Property acquisition is vital for the revival, and donors are often highly regarded and their testimonies circulated widely. The display of wealth and celebration of success is often as important as evangelism (and once built the churches are soon filled). The contrast is with the rural Christians who attained their charisma and authority by suffering under Mao. El Shaddai is one of many Catholic Charismatic groups in the Philippines. It began as a radio station in 1984 and within fifteen years accumulated a followership of millions. Founded by a businessman turned preacher, Brother Mike Velarde, whose entertaining and evocative style is pitched at poor, aspiring classes, it is famous for its open air Saturday night ‘prayer and healing’ rallies in Manila attracting up to a million and broadcast throughout the country. Miraculous healing is stressed, as is the ‘positive confession’ whereby what is articu- lated in public prayer is expected to happen. Members are encouraged to open bank accounts and advised to tithe at 10%, save at 10%, and so on, with suggestions for how to spend the remainder. They are not cast as victims but rather sing, Let the weak say, ‘I am strong,’ let the poor say, ‘I am rich.’ Katharine L. Wiegele contextualises El Shaddai in the post-Marcos People Power movement with its ultimate disappointment at ineffective leadership as regards corruption, human rights abuses, poverty and land reform. El Shaddai helps self-reliance, whilst at times is criticised for its capitalist morality and materialistic motivations. Its mass appeal caters for private rather than collective concerns. In the light of such diversity Amos Yong, a Malaysian minister of the Assemblies of God seeks a range of typologies. Asking whether it is possible to develop a balanced argument for prosperity, one that is not a stumbling block to others, but which emphasises responsible stewardship, he turns to Economy of Communion. The group argues that the modern economy’s preoccupation with selfinterest is an aberration, and engages with the poor through a loosely organised network of business communities embedded in the market economy deeply informed by a form of solidarity in which profits are reinvested into the community for the common good. It was founded in 1991 by the Catholic activist Chiara Lubich in Sao Paolo. Both books will interest those imbued with sociological imagination and concerned with how the Church responds to the poor in the context of a modern market economy. Maryvale Institute Christopher Friel The Economy of Desire: Christianity and Capitalism in a Postmodern World (The Church and Modern Culture Series). By Daniel M. Bell Jr. Pp. 224, Grand Rapids, MI, Baker Academic, 2012, $19.99. The Wound and the Blessing: Economics, Relationships and Happiness. By Luigino Bruni (trans. by N. Michael Brennen). Pp. xxiv, 123, Hyde Park, NY, New City Press, 2012, £12.50. The 2008 economic crisis and its aftermath laid bare the shortcomings of market capitalism which most governments and economists have considered the best, if not the only, credible economic system. Now that their previously unquestioned faith in this system has been shaken, they may attend to the critics whom they had previously dismissed on both ideological and pragmatic grounds. Religion is an important source of these critiques, and the two books reviewed here, one by a theologian and the other by an economist, exemplify this faith-based approach to the subject. Daniel Bell’s principal criticism of market capitalism is its dependence on and encouragement of consumerism. In theological language, consumerism ‘deforms human desire and so warps relations with oneself, others and God’ (p. 29). Following Gilles Deleuze and Michel Foucault, he considers capitalism to be a discipline or economy of desire. Deleuze describes how capitalism’s ‘liberation and disciplining of the fundamental dynamic creative power that is desire’ (p. 67) gradually pervaded the entire world. Foucault shows how desire ‘is enslaved to the axiomatic of production for the market not merely by the disciplinary capacity of the state but also through the pastoral power operative in all dimensions of life, from the social and civil to the personal and familial’ (p. 78). BOOK REVIEWS Despite the current economic crisis, Bell does not argue that capitalism does not work. Instead, he asks what work does capitalism do? Or, in theological language, ‘With our economic lives ordered by capitalism, are we able to worship God truly? Are we able to desire God and the gifts of God as we ought?’ (p. 89). His answer to both these questions is a firm no: ‘Christianity [is[ an economy of desire that does not discipline desire so that it is distracted and distorted from its true end but rather heals desire of its capitalist corruption, aiding desire in finding its true home in God, where it enjoys communion with all’ (p. 93). Bell justifies this assertion by exposing the anthropology of capitalism, according to which human beings are autonomous and isolated individuals who value choice above all else, for whom self-interest is paramount, whose desires are unlimited, who compete with others for limited resources and for whom justice is personal, not social, and its theology, with its conflation of divine providence and the hidden hand of the market, its denial of sanctification and quest for holiness, its assertion of resource scarcity and the salvific role it assigns to the corporation. In exploring whether there can be a Christian alternative to capitalism, Bell takes issue with theologians like Michael Novak who argue that, despite its faults, capitalism is the best available economic system. They consider that the system is so entrenched that no human efforts can make any significant changes to it. For Bell this is heresy: ‘the alternative to capitalism is not something that we construct; rather, it is something we confess that God is doing here and now’ (p. 127). Christians need not be prisoners of consumerism and the desire for market ‘goods’ that it inculcates. Nor do they have to renounce all desire. Rather, they can and should reorder their desires towards God and the things of God. Bell cites medieval monasticism as an example of how desires can be so reordered. Unfortunately, the Christian churches, which Adam Smith criticized as an obstacle to the emergence of a capitalist economic order, eventually succumbed to its allure. Bell’s alternative to the capitalist economy is what he calls an economy of salvation. Christ’s atoning work is ‘a movement of the divine economy of plenitude, ceaseless generosity, and superabundance. As such it runs counter to every economy that operates on the basis of scarcity, debt, desert, and a strict accounting of what is due’ (p. 152). The divine economy does not condemn private property, contracts or profits but these must be employed for the common good, with special consideration for the needs of the downtrodden and oppressed. Whereas the driving force of capitalism 485 is greed, the insatiable desire for more than enough, the divine economy privileges voluntary poverty, charity and the works of mercy, both corporeal and spiritual. Examples of the divine economy include the Jubilee campaign, Catholic Worker Movement, L’Arche and the Mondragon Co-operative Organization. The title of Luigino Bruni’s book comes from the Genesis account of Jacob’s struggle with the angel, which reveals ‘the unbreakable link between “wound” and “blessing” in every authentic human relationship’ (p. xx). Like Bell, he is not opposed to markets and contracts, but a society that regulates human relations only through markets and contracts is intolerable. The radical individualism of modern capitalism developed, at least in part, as a means of avoiding the wounds that can result from social intimacy: ‘Market relationships allow us to satisfy our needs without having to depend on others’ love; by all depending impersonally and anonymously on the “Invisible Hand” of the Market (with a capital “M”), we do not personally depend on anyone else, nor do we have to encounter anyone personally (and potentially painfully)’ (p. 15). What seemed to Adam Smith and his followers as a great step forward for humankind has turned out to be at best a mixed blessing: an increase of personal freedom on the one hand and a loss of community and the happiness it brings on the other. Moreover, personal freedom has always been constrained in both industry and governments and is increasingly restricted for everybody in the name of efficiency and security. Bruni discusses some recent attempts to mitigate the self-interested and anti-social behaviour of corporations, such as the corporate social responsibility (CSR) and Italian cooperative movements. The former is tenuous because the sole goal of the corporation is profit and corporate philanthropy generally reduces profits. The cooperative movement is superior in this respect because of its communitarian basis. Taking his cue from Pope Benedict XVI, Bruni calls for an economics based on love in all its forms, eros, philia and agape. Capitalism priorizes eros and includes philia to a limited extent but has no place for agape, i.e., gratuitousness, and is thus joyless. Although economists and other social scientists have rediscovered happiness as an important measure for economics, he criticizes their definition of happiness because of its subjectivity and identification with pleasure. Adopting another set of terms, he argues that capitalism has promoted (not very successfully) liberty and equality but has completely ignored fraternity. Without that, there can be no true happiness. But 486 BOOK REVIEWS fraternity involves risk of hurt and rejection (the wound) as well as the prospect of happiness (blessing). He concludes, ‘Only in “hand-to-hand” relationship with the other in flesh and blood, and accepting the wound that we may receive in this struggle, can we re-establish a new social bond, a new fraternity, which we do not yet know how to foresee’ (pp. 112-3). Although these two books are similar in many respects, they will attract different readerships. Bell writes for Christians with an interest in theology. However, he says little about the unquestioned acceptance of capitalism by most churches and their adherents. Nor is there any reference to Max Weber’s thesis on the relationship of Protestantism and capitalism, however disputed that might be. Bruni’s readers will be his fellow social scientists although his eclectic use of Biblical terminology concepts will likely puzzle, if not alienate, them. Moreover, his book reads like a collection of loosely related articles rather than a unified whole. Despite these shortcomings, the two authors will hopefully achieve their common goal of contributing to the emergence of an alternative economic system based on the common good. University of Ottawa John R. Williams Does the Richness of the Few Benefit Us All? By Zygmunt Bauman. Pp. viii, 101, Cambridge, Polity Press, 2013, £40.00/£9.99/£6.99 (E-book). The Locust Effect: Why the End of Poverty Requires the End of Violence. By Gary A. Haugen and Victor Boutros. Pp. xxii, 346, Oxford University Press, 2014, £18.99. ‘You have the poor among you always (Mt. 26:11). That may be true but poverty is widely considered an evil from both religious and secular perspectives. These two books analyse the causes of global poverty and discuss whether there are solutions. Zygmunt Bauman has published extensively on globalization, modernity and postmodernity, consumerism and morality. In this extended essay he attacks the growing disparity in wealth between the very rich and everybody else. This has been justified on many grounds, including natural law (human nature), predestination and the superiority of capitalism in producing wealth. Apologists for capitalism claim, as per the title of this book, that inequality is not a problem because everybody benefits from the increased wealth for which rich people are largely responsible. As producers of wealth, the rich feel entitled to most of it. Moreover, they have been successful at convincing national governments and international financial institutions that restrictions on their ability to generate wealth would hurt ordinary people who depend on economic growth for their livelihood. According to Bauman, none of these justifications is valid. The rewards of economic growth accrue almost exclusively to those who are already very rich, leaving everybody else no better or even worse off. Why do the vast majority accept this injustice? Either because they realise they are powerless to change the situation or they are too caught up in consumerism to take action to improve their lot. The pernicious effects of consumerism are largely invisible but nonetheless powerful; they include defining happiness as hav- ing rather than being, priorizing the acquisition of things over inter-personal relationships and encouraging envy and rivalry rather than cooperation. Bauman offers no solutions to the problems he describes. His conclusion is pessimistic: ‘It seems that one needs catastrophes in order to recognize and admit (retrospectively, alas, only retrospectively. . .) their coming. A chilling thought, if ever there was one’ (p. 96). Haugen and Boutros contend that both academics and policy makers have overlooked the most important obstacle to reducing poverty, which is violence. For example, the 15 U.N. Millennium Development Goals make no mention of violence against poor people. All of the programs aimed at improving the lot of the poor – foreign aid, land reform, education, etc. – are useless in situations where there is no rule of law to protect individuals and communities from violent attacks on their persons and property. The authors provide numerous examples of such failings, which can be as destructive as a swarm of locusts. They include sexual attacks on girls and women, forced prostitution, slavery and bonded labour, abusive police and arbitrary detention. Unlike in the developed world, poor people in the developing world have very little protection against violence because of dysfunctional justice systems. When colonized countries achieved their independence, they inherited systems that were designed to protect the colonizers from the common people. The systems have never been changed and in most of these countries the role of the police is to protect the elites from the ordinary people. BOOK REVIEWS Moreover, the systems are seriously underfunded, resulting in police forces that resort to extortion and corruption to compensate for low pay, overcrowding of prisons and a drastic shortage of judges and lawyers. As a result, laws designed to protect the poor are rarely enforced. Those who can afford it obtain protection from violence by private, not public, means. This compounds the problem of lawlessness: ‘Business, commerce, and the wealthy in the developing world would know that the public justice systems don’t work – and so they don’t use therm. As a result. . . elites have little or no incentive to build public criminal justice institutions that work’ (p. 190). The obstacles to creating effective justice systems in developing countries appear overwhelming. Neither the World Bank nor the U.S. Agency for International Development provides funding for this purpose and most international aid for law enforcement is targeted at terrorism and drug trafficking. However, the authors note that barely a 487 century ago criminal justice systems in most countries were similar to those in developing countries today. In a short period of time massive changes occurred, thanks to local leadership and popular support of reforms. International Justice Mission, the faith-based N.G.O. of which Haugen is founder and president, has achieved similar successes, though on a smaller scale, since it began in 1997, on issues such as child sex trafficking in the Philippines, slavery in Brazil, police corruption in Brazil and impunity for rapists in Peru. The authors make specific recommendations for addressing the problem of violence in developing countries: all discussions of poverty reduction must recognize the role of violence; economic development agencies must have recourse to law enforcement and criminal justice expertise; and pilot projects such as those undertaken by International Justice Mission should receive high priority for funding. University of Ottawa John Williams God’s Reign & the End of Empires. By Antonio Gonzalez; translated by Joseph V. Owens SJ. Pp. 378, London, Convivium, 2012, £19.54. Gonzalez draws on social theorists from the Marxist tradition for a diagnosis of modern globalization but offers a bold remedy that is unashamedly biblical. Speaking from the Mennonite tradition he recommends a radical, non-violent alternative emerging from the grassroots and based on the communities portrayed in the Acts of the Apostles. Social theory is necessary to highlight problems and give diagnosis. The globalized empire now presents us with crises of tax-avoidance, debt, poverty, inequality, prostitution, migration, ecological disaster, criminality and an absence of global democracy. G. notes how the exercise of power requires violence: the hidden hand of capitalism is enforced by a hidden fist. Drawing on Mandel, the Marxist theory of value is assumed: capitalists do not have to pay the workers the full value of their labour so that the system (and not simply the greed of politicians or bankers) exploits and impoverishes. Keynesian and socialist solutions are rejected: ‘we must turn, perhaps to the surprise of some, to the testimony of the Bible.’ Beginning with Genesis, the roots of evil extend further and deeper than Marxian exploitation. G. refers to the ‘Adamic logic.’ In essence this involves self-justification. We seek to ‘eat the fruit,’ that is, appropriate the consequences of our actions. As a result we are fearful: humankind has never been as afraid of God as we are today. This is despite atheism – in fact, atheism is a symptom of such fear. Like Cain we have more guilt than we can bear. Adamic logic leads to the logic of Babylon. The victim is to blame, and in many ways there is a profoundly unhappy state of domination that all empires bring. Genesis too, sees the call of Abraham, and a new history is created in the midst of human history, but G. will refute the notion that only the Old Testament has social relevance. There are many interesting openings on familiar texts in a chapter on the strategy of the Messiah to reverse the Adamic logic. The Roman soldier who is legally permitted force you to go one mile is put in an awkward position when forced to choose between violating his own norm and beseeching the oppressed people not to help if you go the extra mile; the whip Jesus made was used only to drive out animals about to be sacrificed (not people), thus undermining the centre of economic power based on sacrificial logic. When asked whether to pay tax Jesus, after inspecting the coin, did not say ‘give’ but ‘return’ to Caesar the things that are Caesar’s. That is to say, we return not simply the few denarii that are ‘owed’ in tax, but all denarii – a wholesale rejection of the system to the consternation of those who benefited from it. We are to escape from Egypt once more. The reign of God announced by Jesus arrives in the Messianic communities. G. examines the social class of the early church. It is not, as was first thought, that the churches were made up of the 488 BOOK REVIEWS lowest classes. There is some truth in the later view that better off Christians (centred on the household, the economic unit that became the basis of local churches) were among the faithful (though these were not from the ruling class). But G. accepts the view that in fact the churches were predominantly poor with a minority of wealthy Christians sharing goods so that absolute poverty was eliminated. Thus the reign of God is not spiritualised but results in a voluntary communism. The key is faith in Christ, who though divine, is truly human. Constantinianism, however, saw a Christian empire in which Christians could assume power and use force, which of course they did when put to the test by Islam. (Gandhi pointed out that the only people who didn’t realise that Christ taught non-violence were Christians). Although that time has passed, Christians hanker after the good old days by influencing the consciences of those in power, and lose much sympathy as a result. To discern the signs of the times and make his own distinctive contribution G. turns to social theory and the idea of the ‘network society.’ Manuel Castells writes of our postindustrial, information society. Society is structured, so to speak, the way a PC is structured in computer network, with flows of capital and information (and hence domineering power) forming a global net which individuals feel the need to resist in the affirmation of their identity. Identity, then, becomes crucially relevant in such a society. Having a special identity that it is not universally shared is no longer a barrier to relevance. With this context set, the section on Latin American Pentecostalism (pp. 292-9) is at the heart of what the book advocates. Distinguishing sharply from Neo-Pentecostalism (a middle class movement that regards its influence as a sign of millennial rule according to Rev 20:4 that has been ‘quite worrisome’ in Guatemala) G. retains the insights of liberation theology to the effect that the poor are in a privileged position to hear the word of God. Pentecostals believe that Christian salvation is not purely spiritual, but brings health and wealth. When the poor believer is asked for money, by risking the little he has, the believer is no longer subjectively poor. G. does not discuss whether the ‘prosperity Gospel’ of ‘name it and claim it’ is a species of Adamic logic; or whether the requests for donations in order to be blessed is akin to capitalist logic; or whether wealthy preachers who flaunt their wealth (as a sign of God’s blessing) are true to the Gospel. He does not explore the extent that Pentecostalism, being in the ‘business of the self,’ imbues entrepreneurs with the skills to live in a capitalist economy (as neo-Weberians might argue) – for he wants to read the movement as a protest against the global empire. G. would concede, I think, that the movement he valorises does not quite share his social concern: after all, this must be why he thinks that the social theology he presents needs to be written. He continues to draw on Castells (a sociologist in the Marxist tradition who is scathing on fundamentalism as a negative reaction to the global network) and the need to move from ‘resistance identity to project identity.’ For example, feminism has moved from the trenches of resistance to transforming social structures in challenging patriarchism. The project recommended is the emerging reality of the ‘new popular economy.’ Economic relations of reciprocity and cooperation operating within the economic system are deemed viable and efficient – G. draws on Razeto and also Schweickart. Interestingly, G. affirms both pluralism and what, in effect, is the doctrine of ‘anonymous Christianity.’ There is no discussion of Adamic logic, however. I find three faults in this book. It seems to me that the severity of the Adamic logic is exaggerated here and downplayed there when it suits the author’s purposes; in several places he overstates cases that are ‘clearly proven’ without further argument, when in fact, further argument is desired; it lacks an index. God’s Reign is a manifesto. But there are many acute insights, no Biblicism, much generosity with alternative views, great nobility (on non-violence) and the translation is very readable. It recommends itself to those who rage prayerfully against the machine. Maryvale Institute Christopher Friel Social: Why Our Brains Are Wired To Connect. By Matthew D. Lieberman. Pp. x, 374. Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2013, £18.99. Matthew Lieberman’s new book can be viewed in two ways. First, it is a work of popular science; an expert in social neuroscience shares some of his most interesting findings with the general public. Secondly, it can be viewed as a contribution to broader philosophical debates about human nature, and the implications of scientific work for public policy. As a work of popular science, the book is undoubtedly a success. There can be no doubt about Lieberman’s credentials and his book, which is a pleasure to read, should find a large audience. Lieberman is careful to present scientific research as a series of on-going debates rather than a set of settled conclusions. For example, he describes how whereas once it was thought that autistic people BOOK REVIEWS were insensitive to the social world, it now appears that the root cause of autism may be oversensitivity leading to withdrawal (pp. 161-177). He discusses a range of opinions about the importance of mirror neurons, admitting that some scientists may have attached too much significance to their discovery, while allowing that they do play an important but subtle role in our understanding of others (p. 134). Naturally, he is able to present us with new and interesting facts about the brain, for example, he points out that there is evidence that the phrase ‘I feel your pain’ need not be a metaphor. Some people’s brains respond to the sight of a loved one receiving an electric shock just as if they themselves were the ones receiving the shock (p. 155). Social pain should be taken just as seriously as physical pain – and, surprisingly, both can be treated with Tylenol (p. 65). Considered as a contribution to debates about human nature and public policy, the book is somewhat flawed. Lieberman seems to think that, until now, the fact that we are social creatures has been neglected. He notes that Jeremy Bentham asserted that pain and pleasure govern our lives, and, taking for granted that Bentham meant physical pain and pleasure, chastises him for overlooking social pains and pleasures (p. ix). In fact, Bentham’s list of pleasures includes the pleasures of amity and a good name, which are clearly social pleasures (An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation, Chapter V). He states that according to most accounts of human nature we are special not 489 because we are social, but because we have language or reason (p. 9). For Aristotle, language matters because it enables us to be political animals, by which he means that we are the most social animals (Politics,1, 1253a). It is true that, in recent years, economists, who have had more influence over public policy than philosophers, have had to be taught that we are natural co-operators, rather than egoists rationally pursuing our own interests. Lieberman is making an important and worthwhile point, but he writes as though he is taking on the whole philosophical tradition. His practical suggestions can be somewhat trite. He suggests that teachers of English could better motivate their students by emphasizing that good grammar enables communication (p. 288), and that history teachers should discuss why events happened, treating history as a great soap opera, rather than asking students to memorize dry and tedious facts (p. 287). Will he also tell pilots that they should avoid crashing their aeroplanes? Lieberman has Aristotle and common sense on his side; he need not write like a lone voice in the wilderness. On balance though, the book’s virtues outweigh its flaws. There is no trace of arrogance in Lieberman’s writing, he is content to be one voice participating in a conversation about what it means to be human. After all, not only is he a scientist, he is above all a social animal. Florida State University, Panama Benjamin Murphy Up With Authority: Why We Need Authority to Flourish as Human Beings. By Victor Lee Austin. Pp.172, London, T&T Clark, 2010, $23.29. It seems appropriate that Victor Lee Austin’s Up With Authority is dedicated to ‘the Reverend Andrew C. Mead and the People of St. Thomas Church’. Austin is an Episcopal priest and describes himself as a ‘philosophically-minded theologian’ (19), rather than a professional philosopher. The style of the book is earnest and preacherly. Austin calls our attention to a certain slackness in social life: ‘It seems to me that people in our time are trying to live without authority. There used to be authority but (we think) we have outgrown it; so that our world is after (i.e. ‘post’) authority.’ (19) The principal motivation behind Up With Authority is accordingly to bring the concept of authority back into the general discussion of ethics and social theory. Austin takes real pleasure in adumbrating the different facets of concept, which vindicate its role in secular and religious life. The design of the book is thematic: the first chapter, an introduction, is followed by chapters on ‘Social Authority’, ‘Epistemic Authority’, ‘Political Authority’ and ‘Ecclesial Authority’. These chapters are followed by a chapter on the ‘fallibility’ of authority and a chapter on ‘Authority in Paradise’. Austin has gone through a large literature and reviews the position set out by authors like Yves Simon, who wrote A General Theory of Authority (Notre Dame: 1962), Michael Polanyi, and Oliver O’Donnell. Simon argued that authority determines the ‘form’ of the common good and carries it into our personal lives, where it is willed, individually and materially. Austin accepts Simon’s argument that authority accordingly ‘exists in order that human persons may flourish as self-governed members of society who somehow contain their society (societies) in themselves.’ (29) Knowledge requires authority. Austin follows Polyani, in Personal Knowledge: Towards a PostCritical Philosophy (University of Chicago, 1958), 490 BOOK REVIEWS who argues that epistemological skills are learnt from a master, which requires submission to an authority. It is only because a judge has epistemic authority that the judge can discover the truth in a particular case. Outsiders, who lack the judge’s authority, are not able to find the truth, and are thus more easily tempted to bypass the epistemological question and replace it with assertions of will or self-interest or raw power.’ (44) Austin’s discussion of political authority in the book is far less searching. One of the reasons for this is that Austin seems more interested in the place of Christ in such a discussion. ‘There is no person whom the Gospel does not address,’ he writes. ‘This includes persons who have political authority.’ (90) Those who are believers will ‘acknowledge the higher political rule of Christ’. (90f) Austin turns to music to illustrate the authority of the church. Although Johannes Sebastian Bach and the conductor of the Saint Matthew Passion exercise authority in the production of such music, the Passion is a representation ‘that holds before us the church together—the church assembled’. (95) A soloist therefore sings an aria with authority ‘only because the church provides ‘the communal identity and structure’ (99) that makes such a representation possible. The ‘fallibility’ of those who exercise authority does not diminish the need for authority in human society. There is no following the common good, without authority: ‘. . . let us not back away from the truth. At times, the human good requires that we submit to social authority that we believe is wrong.’ (145) Austin tries to place limits on such a prescription by asserting that authority cannot be separated from obedience; and obedience is rational and voluntary. It follows that authority does not extend to coercion and blind obedience. This takes Austin into a rather summary discussion of civil disobedience. Austin follows the example of Aquinas in taking philosophical positions, which are followed by objections, and replies to the objections. This suits the homilectic style of the book. tone is lively and colloquial: Austin writes about the “moronic part of my sophomore essay” (13); ‘My way or the highway’ (145), he interjects, in discussing pride. One of the confusing elements is that Austin switches unpredictably from the masculine to the feminine form of the third person. The book has a religious and rather eccentric bibliography, but offers leads for anyone interested in its subject matter. There is also a list of scriptural citations, a brief subject index, and ten blank pages, presumably for one’s own meditations on the subject. The book contains a brief conclusion, really a crescendo of sorts, in which Austin takes up the subject of authority in heaven. Austin sees authority as something integral to what we are, and rejects the lapsarian idea that authority has become necessary because of sin. It follows that authority ‘perdures among human beings’ (159), even in paradise. ‘Heaven is a state of activity of people who are undiminished by sin, whose activities will have to be decided upon, which decisions entail the ongoing provision of authority.’ This authority is social and epistemic, rather than political, and is ‘exercised by redeemed persons over redeemed persons and under redeemed persons, for the joy of all.’ (160) St. Francis Xavier University, Nova Scotia, Canada Paul Groarke A World Without Why. By Raymond Geuss. Pp. xvi, 264, Princeton/Oxford, Princeton University Press, 2014, $27.95. Geuss cultivates a graceful style that combines intrigue with charm. This is a tour de force that, through disparate essays, presents a deeply thoughtout and coherent naturalistic position that grounds a subversive liberation ethic of exposing the lack of foundation behind most of the basic concepts, notably for institutions, on which our culture rests, in the interests of dismantling unnecessary authoritarian repression and manipulation through psychological pressure that leads to alienation, passivity, and anomie, to allow us to respond positively to the ‘invitation’ that is the lightest of social intrusions and the only legitimate pressure, the exposure to great art and excellent activity in general, to which we may respond through imitation, expressing our gratitude by excelling and ‘playing the game’ even better. Our excellent cultural activities continue very well although gutted of their mistaken substantive foundations (invoked to give others a ‘club’ to beat us with to command obedience or conformity, which measure their own insecurity) because they were never more than a ‘constellation’ of practices that have at best a Wittgensteinian ‘family resemblance’, that resist a common definition because they have no common essence, that survive in each case through a paradigmatic instance of excellence that provides a context-dependent criterion for evaluation, which is all we ever needed and is what we are doing now. BOOK REVIEWS There is nothing beyond matter and energy which evolve into complicated forms with more specialized and sophisticated techniques for survival. Some needs are healthy, but others are faulted on two grounds: some involve unhealthy reactions to social pressure (Rousseau is the father of this suspicion, and Geuss should have done more with him), and some involve projections of an independent substantive reality, typically daunting and intimidating, behind the loose constellation of practices that is the only social reality, to enforce obedience and conformity. The latter are unnecessary bogeymen that should now be dismantled, and Geuss spends the majority of his text exposing the empty pretensions behind such proper nouns. Here Nietzsche is his champion, but also such contemporary thinkers as Richard Rorty and especially Bernard Williams. Philosophy reduces to practical philosophy: politics and ethics, which properly consist in identifying and resisting the temptation to construct the discredited branch of speculative philosophy or metaphysics, which is a ‘Who’s Who’ of fraudulent and criminal concepts used to scare and stampede people to someone else’s benefit. Even the last two could be replaced by ‘law’ and ‘administration’, so that ‘philosophy’ as a whole joins the rogue’s gallery of unwarranted impostors that should be eliminated in the interests of slimmed-down cultural baggage promoting liberation and empowerment. Almost, but not 491 quite. For critical activity or dialectic, revealed at the start of philosophy as the profoundly disturbing and enjoyable, wildly unpredictable and ‘out of control’, distinctly human activity, the intellectual catnip, ambrosia or ‘narcotic of the intellectuals’ which the West at least decided it could not do without (its attempted confinement, curtailment, or elimination was the reason for the collapse of the otherwise well-functioning and sustainable Marxist economies of eastern Europe) cannot be eliminated; indeed, Geuss is a past master at it and means to take it to its conclusion. He allows his own wildly-slicing critical machine to reduce our world to a fideistic universe where we really know very little, primarily because there is very little to be known. Most of reality is in flux and uncertain. We would have it otherwise, but in our mature moments we must learn the discipline of doing without such false consolations - not only because they are false but because they too easily become tools of repression. Geuss himself keeps open the possibility, however, that he has allowed his machine to slice away too much and that like the regimes of eastern Europe our civilization will consequently collapse – or retrieve at least part of metaphysics. Perhaps that was always the ‘ambrosia behind the ambrosia’. Heythrop College Patrick Madigan Ministers of the Law: A Natural Law Theory of Legal Authority. By Jean Porter. Pp. xvi, 368. Emory University Studies in Law and Religion, Grand Rapids, MI/Cambridge, UK, Eerdmans, 2010, £21.00. Porter’s Ministers of the Law quickly runs aground. The first chapter sets out the ‘paradox’ of legal authority, which apparently holds that the reliance on authority in the natural law and legal tradition precludes the use of personal judgement in making ethical decisions. I say ‘apparently’ for good reason, since the paradox remains remarkably unclear. Philosophically, it seems simpler to say that the book is a response to the suggestion in so much of the contemporary moral, social and political literature that authority must be justified. The purpose of the book is also unclear. Porter describes her book as ‘an essay in systematic theological jurisprudence.’ (7) She set out to provide ‘a theological analysis of the authority of law, according to which legal authority is construed as a natural relation of authority, resting ultimately in God’s wisdom as expressed in the free act constituting us as creatures of a specific kind.’ (5) The book reads more like a philosophical exercise, however, and sets out Porter’s position on a series of issues in philosophy of law and social theory. Although Porter’s account of legal authority is based on ‘early scholastic theological and legal thought’, it is ‘responsive to contemporary exigencies of legislation and judicial interpretation, particularly as these are experienced in the Anglophone societies with which I am most familiar.’ (5) The underlying argument in the book is that political power must be subject to legal constraints. The work of the ‘scholastic jurists’ is significant because they ‘developed a workable account of the legislative and executive power of the prince’ (47) based on the natural law. Porter relies heavily on Kenneth Pennington (The Prince and the Law; University of California, 1993), who argues that the scholastics developed a natural law jurisprudence that provides ‘an account of natural rights and relations that the lawgiver is bound to respect.’ (48) She singles out Gratian’s Harmony of Discordant Canons, or the Decretum, which appeared ‘sometime around 1140’ (71), as a pivotal text, since it unified the divergent sources of the canon law into a single, coherent system of law based on the natural law. 492 BOOK REVIEWS The scholastics recognized the constitutional character of the natural law, which set out the limits in which the legislative and executive power could be exercised. The natural law also had a procedural side, and governed the trial process, like the modern doctrines of natural justice and due process in our own law. The scholastics, like the Roman jurists and the canon lawyers, believed that political power was legally limited. The natural law gave the courts their own sources of authority and guaranteed the independence of the judiciary. A judge’s ultimate responsibility was to the law, and the standards of reason and justice inherent in the law, rather than to the political order. It follows that the judge was a ‘minister of the law’. Porter does not seem to appreciate that the historical sources which interest her lie in the civil tradition, rather than the common law, and were based on a much older legal view. The primary virtue of Ministers of the Law is nevertheless that it recognizes the jurisprudence of the past has a great deal to offer us, in thinking our way past the problems posed by the regulation of political power. The major problem with the book is that Porter does not confine herself to such a project, and her narrative is full of theoretical digressions and understated arguments, which professional philosophers will find frustrating. Porter is determined to show that the natural law is compatible with the current round of theories in ethics, philosophy of law, and political theory. There are traces of H.L.A. Hart and Ronald Dworkin, and even the social contract, in Porter’s rendition of the natural law. This is part of a relatively recent Christian tradition, in authors like John Finnis, who has worked so hard to convince us that the natural law can be formulated in a manner that accommodates contemporary moral tastes. Porter limits the reach of the natural law by arguing that justice is largely a matter of social norms. Although the natural law gives rise to certain normative principles, which inhere within the law, that is not enough to establish norms, which are an expression of a community’s authority over its members. This is a nod towards political authority. The common good, Porter writes, ‘looks a great deal like the political morality endorsed in broad terms by Dworkin and others, qualified in such a way as to give greater weight to economic and other positive rights.’ (203) Thus, she says, ‘there are many, to some extent incommensurable ideals of the common good, just as there is a plurality of natural moralities.’ Porter is constantly temporizing. She seems to be determined to save the theory of the natural law by demonstrating that it produces the same ethical and social choices as the liberal and procedural views in the mainstream of philosophy. She accordingly borrows many of the terms and concepts in the conventional literature: the common good within a particular community is ‘a thick ideal’ (203). Human laws are, in ‘Andrei Marmor’s illuminating analysis’, ‘constitutive conventions’ (80). Although Porter gives us her position on a number of ethical controversies, she confesses that her account of human rights may look like ‘a baptized version of secular liberalism’ (337), and indeed it does. The critical question in a legal context is more functional. From a practical perspective, it is hard to believe that Porter’s version of the natural law has enough grist to resolve contentious legal and ethical issues. Anyone, she writes, ‘can appreciate that life, health, sexual pleasure and intimacy with one another, children and immersion in one’s family and community life are legitimate aims for action and salient concerns for assessing social policies’. (181) If we agree with this, it is ‘precisely because these are among the natural objects of the will, goods towards which each human being is naturally and properly oriented.’ (182) It is not evident that this says very much. The nagging question is why we need the natural law, if it is simply going to reproduce the conventional liberal position, particularly when other theories take us there, poste haste? There is very little in Porter’s book that is going to convince philosophers outside her camp to adopt such an approach. The book suffers from a number of inaccuracies, but the most troubling is plainly that it assumes the concepts of law and positive law are philosophically fungible. This problem resides in the English use of the word “law”, which was essentially expropriated by the legal positivists. As a result, there is a tendency among many Anglo-American theorists to assume that the law obtains its authority from the fact that it is a product of the exercise of political power. Porter falls into the usual error, without realizing it, and the narrative weaves in and out of legal positivism during the course of her arguments. There are theological and religious reasons behind Porter’s position, since she bases her view of the law on the Christian idea of community, which gives society authority over the individual. There is no doubt, moreover, that the authority of the law has its provenance in the community at large. The problem lies in thinking that there is no need to trace the authority of the law any further back than the political process and the machinery of government. Although this probably explains BOOK REVIEWS Porter’s interest in the civil jurisprudence, it ignores the customary sources of the law, which have ethical and social roots. All one can say is that her omission seems surprising in a book that is 493 supposed to be reasserting the authority of the natural law in the legal order. St. Francis Xavier University Paul Groarke The Foundations of Natural Morality: On the Compatibility of Natural Rights and the Natural Law. By S. Adam Seagrave. Pp. ix, 174, Chicago/London, The University of Chicago Press, 2014, $29.82. When Jacques Maritain helped to compose the United Nations’ Universal Declaration of Human Rights in the immediate post-war period, he pointed to the classical natural law tradition as the only foundation for such a doctrine that would rescue humanity from subjectivity by anchoring such principles more deeply and securely than in a shallow source of wilful and arbitrary pronouncement, and that could distinguish between essential and valid claims on the one hand versus extravagant, arbitrary, and frivolous claims on the other. Leo Strauss responded that the modern ‘natural rights’ tradition, a la Rousseau who wrote an earlier version of the same document, constituted a sharp rejection, indeed, a departure and rebellion against classical natural law; whether one likes it or hates it, the modern natural rights tradition begins in a different place, the atomistic individual and his claims against an encircling society he views with suspicion as a threat to his survival and well-being, rather than the unique space where his personal limitations may be overcome and his completion and fulfilment secured. To use language that Seagrave deploys, Maritain maintained that the modern theory was historically continuous with classical natural law tradition and is therefore compatible with it, whereas Strauss counters that the modern theory of natural rights is psychologically a completely different ‘beast’ that comes to us from and presupposes a contradictory metaphysical universe - specifically an opposed relation between the individual and the state, so that ultimately it is neither continuous nor compatible with the earlier social discourse. Seagrave splits the difference or tries to go between the horns of the dilemma by conceding to Strauss that the modern theory of natural rights is historically discontinuous with the inspiration and outlook of classical natural law, while retrieving for Maritain and his followers like Finnis, Sandel, MacIntyre and Tierney the thesis that it nevertheless it is compatible with the latter. The two can cohabit, we can have it both ways, we need not choose between them, and the ship of state will stay afloat. The basis for this unexpected and fortuitous reconciliation is the novel and intriguing theory of personal identity proposed by that pivotal, Janus-faced thinker, John Locke. Rather than getting hung up on ontological issues coming through the substance-based metaphysics of Aristotle, Locke retreated to an epistemologically-based theory that leaves contentious philosophical issues in the shade for individuals to ponder at their leisure. Locke comes at the notion of personal identity through the Biblical question of how legitimate it is for God to punish our resurrected body at the final judgment for sins committed while alive – and in a different body. Aren’t we two different people? What is essential to secure personal identity between them? Locke decides it is self-consciousness and memories that secure personal identity, which God can attach to any body, so that it is fair for God to punish our resurrected version. More broadly, self-consciousness gives rise to a sense of self-ownership which in turn, Seagrave points out, provides the foundation of our claim to natural rights. Our unique selfconsciousness also makes us aware, however, of a common human nature, which thereafter serves as an unavoidable constraining frame for these claims - and an adequate foundation for classical natural law principles. Through this common source in the Lockean psychology, the two, law and rights, although independent, achieve congruence and compatibility although it is a dialectical relationship. Seagrave shows how this genealogical theory sheds a dialogic light and may contribute today to the discussion on controversial issues such as universal health care, same-sex marriage, and the death penalty. This is an innovative and powerful theoretical contribution that merits serious examination and study. Heythrop College Patrick Madigan The Perspective of Love: Natural Law in a New Mode. By R.J. Snell. Pp. xii, 207, Eugene, OR, Pickwick Publications, 2014, $24.00. R.J. Snell defends natural law against ‘the Protestant Prejudice’ against it, a critique that objects to natural law theories on the grounds that they (1) wrongly posit the autonomy of an order of pure 494 BOOK REVIEWS nature and reason, (2) are not sufficiently Christocentric, and (3) overlook the noetic effects of sin. (190) While Snell is in agreement with the concerns that motivate these criticisms, he does not think they apply to natural law theory at its best, which is worked out on the basis of ‘interiority.’ This ‘mode of meaning’ differs from the mode of ‘common sense,’ in which things are described according to how they ‘relate to us,’ as well as from the mode of ‘theory,’ which ‘explains things in relation to other things.’ (10) Snell thinks the typical objection to natural law is directed against natural law theory performed in the theoretical mode, which conceives nature in terms of ‘theoretical anthropology and its concomitant metaphysics of the person.’ (11) While Snell thinks the Protestant Prejudice may or may not successfully refute such third-person, often abstract accounts of natural law, it does not rule out a natural law performed in the mode of interiority, which makes a first-person account of the human person in all its concreteness the site of a reflection on human nature. Despite disagreements, ‘particularly in application,’ among John Paul II, Martin Rhonheimer, the ‘new natural law’ theorists, and Bernard Lonergan, all understand natural law in this mode, which ‘is quite able to include the effects of sin on intellect and will, the role of grace, the importance of community, history (including salvation history), and the centrality of the gospel.’ (12) Thus, after discussing natural law in a theoretical mode— exemplified by interpreters of Aristotle and Thomas such as Maritain—and the Protestant critique of this account in Part 1, and treating the new mode of natural law according to interiority in Part 2, Snell provides his own proposal for a natural law theory from ‘the perspective of love’ in Part 3, which is heavily influenced by Lonergan. The starting point for Snell’s understanding of natural law is what Lonergan calls ‘selfappropriation,’ which involves reflexively experiencing, understanding, knowing, valuing, and deciding for myself as an experiencer, understander, knower, valuer, and decider. Natural law can be found in the dynamism of my own questioning, the desire to know that leads me to attend carefully to my experience in an effort to understand the world, and to examine my understanding in order to figure out whether that understanding is correct, and to further examine whether what I come to know is good, and to decide what I must do in response. Very simply, I discover that ‘I am the natural law and its first principles,’ which are not propositions but the dynamic structure of the consciousness. (147) The norm of this structure is the desire to know, value, and love, and it is the presence or absence of further questions regarding truth and value that indicates the successful operation of this structure. However, Snell thinks investigation of oneself in the concrete also reveals the ways in which this drive to know and love is derailed by selfishness, bias, and sin. Still, to make the argument ‘that the noetic effects of sin either damage or render nonfunctional the capacity of reason to know the truth confirms the power of reason to know the truth and the self-evident goodness of truth, for there could be no other reason to make the argument than a commitment to the goodness of truth.’ (148) Thus natural law is not only concretely affected by sin, but also by grace. While sin competes with our natural orientation towards being attentive, intelligent, reasonable, responsible, and loving, the gift of ‘total being in love’ transforms our valuing, deciding, believing, knowing, understanding, and experiencing for the better. (158-162) From the Christian perspective, this love is named ‘the missions of the Son and Spirit, as the Word made flesh who sends both his disciples and Spirit into the world to remake loves and allow for progress and authentic humanity once again.’ (195-196) In other words, Snell’s account of natural law in the mode of interiority becomes natural law in the mode of transcendence, since attention to the data of consciousness reveals the way in which God’s love in Christ enables us to live out the orientation to truth and goodness that we are. Snell’s approach, because of its refusal to abstract from human life as concretely lived, meets the Protestant demand to emphasize the noetic effects of sin on human nature and the role of Christ and the gift of the Spirit in redeeming human nature, all the while insisting on the ‘integral structure of the human spirit’ that can only be denied by enacting that very same spirit. (197) Boston College Brian Traska Truth Matters: Knowledge, Politics, Ethics, Religion. Edited by Lambert Zuidervaart, Allyson Carr, Matthew Klaassen, & Ronnie Shuker. Pp. xi, 349, Montreal & Kingstron, McGill-Queen’s University Press, 2014, $100.00. The proceedings of an interdisciplinary, international Conference held in Toronto in August 2010, this vol- ume presents a variety of positions on truth and the practical consequences of these differences in the BOOK REVIEWS academic and public spheres. While it does not attempt to argue for a unified conception of truth, or promote either analytic or continental thought, the volume as a whole argues that truth has a ‘more-thanpropositional character’ that is ‘crucial for understanding why truth matters, not simply in the academy, but throughout culture and society’ (x). The work contains four sections that touch on different topics related to truth. The first, entitled ‘Truth and Knowledge,’ focuses on theoretical questions related to truth and our knowledge; the most interesting is by Lambert Zuidervaart, ‘How not to be an Anti-Realist: Habermas, Truth, and Justification’ in which he attempts to move beyond the realist/anti-realist debates by discussing truth as ‘life-giving disclosure’. Zuidervaart emphasizes the interdependence and intersubjectivity between human agents and the events and entities they encounter. It is a thought-provoking essay which serves as the foundation for the volume’s other articles to develop in various ways. The first section also contains essays by Clarence Jodersma, Matthew Walhout, and Olaf Ellefson. Jodersma develops Zuidervaart’s concept of truth as life-giving disclosure in an attempt to move beyond an impasse in educational theory, Walhout searches for an account of truth along analytic Hegelianism lines that respects findings in quantum physics, and Ellefson seeks to defend Donald David’s intuitive or primitive account of truth from the attacks of Stephen Stich. The rest of the work focuses on practical issues. The second section, ‘Truth and Politics,’ examines the importance of truth for public discourse and political life. Drawing on Gadamer, Ricoeur, and Habermas, the essays in this section argue that truth is something reached through mutual dialogue and is vital for the survival of democracy. Darren Walhof uses Gadamar’s thought to argue that democracy can survive only when one dares to engage in open and honest dialogue with those who differ with you; Adam Smith examines Habermas’s discursive theory and encourages an appeal to the experience of discourse, rather than assuming its legitimacy when addressing opponents 495 of pluralism; Amy Richards looks at the role that suffering can play in authenticating the claims of journalists; and drawing on Ricoeur, Jon Van Rys studies how historical fiction often implicitly explores the nature of truth through narrative. Part three is entitled ‘Truth and Ethics’ and contains essays by Gerrit Glas, Jay Gupta, John Park and Doug Blomberg. Glas draws on Zuidervaart and Kierkegard’s account of truth to examine the existential importance of truthfulness; Gupta argues that Kierkegaard’s ‘subjectivism’ can be an ally in affirming truth’s existential significance; Park criticizes noncognitivist and subjectivist views of moral reasoning using recent findings in moral psychology, to argue that at least some moral concepts must be based on objective truths; finally, Bloomburg exposes the implications of truthfulness and other virtues for higher education’s arguing that curriculum and pedagogy should be focused on promoting justice for all creation. The fourth and final section deals with ‘Truth and Religion.’ In this section, Gill Goulding examines Balthasar’s account of truth as God’s act of disclosure and the role of mystery and relationality in his Trinitarian thought; Pamela Reeve compares the thought of Aquinas with that of Charles Laughlin, coming up with a new verb, ‘trueing,’ to describe the ontological relationship between the cosmos and the human experience; Using the account of demonic possession in Scripture, Jeffrey Dudiak advocates a ‘representational’ account of truth that subordinates it to human flourishing as lived in different historical contexts; and finally, Calvin Seerveld studies the concept of ‘artistic truth’ found in Biblical Wisdom Literature. Due to the nature of the topic and the variety of positions taken, no one will agree with every essay. However, all can agree that the aim is noble, and the practical issues are important, making this volume a worthwhile read, especially for those interested in politics and the peaceful flourishing of democracy. Ave Maria University Luke Murray The Ethics of Capital Punishment: A Philosophical Investigation of Evil and Its Consequences. By Matthew H. Kramer. Pp. xii, 353, Oxford University Press, 2014, This is a fascinating book in that Kramer, professor of legal and political philosophy at Cambridge, is able to generate a counter-cultural justification for the death penalty as the uniquely appropriate penalty for flamboyantly wicked crimes (Hannibal Lecter type crimes of abduction, torture, and murder, as well as crimes against humanity) from purely secular premises; that is, against the liberal sweep of the past fifty years in most developed first-world countries which has banished the death penalty as a last indulgence in barbaric revenge in favour of life-long incarceration without possibility of parole for the worst cases as an ‘advance’ in civilization, humanity, disinterested imposition of justice, and compassion, and agreeing with the ‘least intrusion principle’ that holds that a court should always impose the ‘least severe’ measure that will achieve a desired result or satisfy the 496 BOOK REVIEWS demands of justice, Kramer nonetheless argues that there are certain crimes which show a contempt, not only for the victim(s) of the offense but for humanity as a whole (Hitler, Goebbels), such that the imposition of anything less than the death penalty would seriously tarnish the standing and respect of that particular community with the rest of the world by in effect ‘backing into’ a collective responsibility and complicity with the criminal by default, thereby rendering it deserving of protest, sanction, and exclusion. In other words, not only do communities have the permission, they have the obligation to execute perpetrators of such crimes. Our gut-wrenching revulsion in the face of such extreme acts of wickedness is accurate, and the best liberal principles and most determinedly secular reasoning demand the maximum penalty. Ironically or consistently, however how you look at it, only societies which are themselves based on liberal democratic principles have this dual permission and obligation. Kramer first scrutinizes the standard justifications for capital punishment – the deterrence-oriented, incapacitative, and denunciatory rationales – and finds them all defective. These are consequentialist, and fall foul of the standard objections that follow from the principle that ‘the end justifies the means’. The retributivistic argument is closer to Kramer’s own; it seeks to restore the ‘balance’ or equity of justice, and specifically to reassert the moral dignity of those who have been harmed by serious crimes. But Kramer’s novel ‘purgative’ way goes beyond this: it defends the death penalty as a uniquely appropriate penalty because it brings to an end the ‘defilingly evil existence’ of someone who has committed outrageously offensive crimes. His theory thus combines a shocking return to our most primitive intuitions concerning the nature of justice, argued on the basis of the most modern, liberal, and secular platform. Specifically, we are not thereby removing from the community someone who has broken a divine taboo, and thereby brought down God’s anger and punishment upon the community as a whole. Civilized, liberal society, with respect for equality and the dignity of the individual, now substitutes for God. Through modern media and communication, the world has truly become a ‘global village’; crimes launched half-way around the globe can have an immediate and direct impact upon us. We no longer have the luxury of being indifferent to each other’s observation and respect for justice. Liberal society has paradoxically produced previously-unheard of acts of extreme wickedness that display a gratuitous contempt for the principles of a free and secure society that are so personally ‘defiling’ that the persons committing them must be executed by their societies on pain of that particular society otherwise falling into collective responsibility and complicity with the criminal in his crime with regard to the rest of the world, which makes it deserving of a similar response by other states. Kramer’s ‘purgative’ justification for the death penalty is a novel, unsparing, and courageous attempt to do ‘justice’ to the outrageous blights against humanity that modern society, through an improper use of its expanded freedom and with its desperate, exaggerated emphasis on the unique worth of individual achievement and originality, not only produces but has rendered defiantly distinctive of our era. Heythrop College Patrick Madigan The Moral Dynamics of Economic Life: An Extension and Critique of Caritas in Veritate. Edited by Daniel K. Finn. Pp. 166, Oxford University Press, 2012, £18.99. A year after Pope Benedict had published his social encyclical, a symposium, ‘Caritas in veritate and the United States’ met in 2010 to critique and extend its themes. Emerging from the symposium, this slim volume contains 48 short contributions from 23 contributors in 11 chapters on topics such as markets and government, economic relations, reciprocity, development and implications, for example, on welfare policies. Most write from the American horizon, which as John L. Allen points out, is severely polarised. Liberal commentators hail what Benedict had to say about trade unions, redistribution of wealth, and a planetary form of governance, but largely gloss over the life issues. ‘Theo-cons’ such as George Weigel divide the work into the truly Benedictine golden passages, and the red passages from the ‘social justice crowd’ that do not merit what canon law describes as a ‘religious submission of mind.’ On the right Michael Novak, writing on sin, finds refreshing the fact that ‘long neglected lessons from Augustine are being included in social teaching.’ Greed is always there, but less so with capitalism, and capitalism redistributes more than any other system. What are the most practical forms of defeating sin? Here, ‘wise Pope Benedict’ puts too much stress on caritas, virtue, justice and good intentions BOOK REVIEWS and needs to learn from the Reformers. The solution is that checks and balances must be written into the institutions. (Novak never actually references the encyclical, but he is correct that the word ‘sin’ is indeed mentioned: on both occasions with regard to social and economic conditions (CV,34)). Amelia J. Uelmen, a consultant for Focolare’s Economy of Communion project, wonders whether Americans, who define freedom as self-definition will hear what Benedict has to offer about interpersonal relations as a ‘source of the self.’ Matthew J. Slaughter takes a look at the economic situation and finds the data sobering. The top 1% get 21% of the wealth and the gap is rising. He explains his deep concern at the hardship that families face and has built ethics and social responsibility courses into his Business School curriculum, and looks to the ‘logic of gift’ to understand business as a community of persons. Katherine Marshall, has spent a long career with the world bank with a focus on issues facing the poorest countries. She calls for a robust commitment akin to a (what else?) Marshall Plan. John H. Coleman thinks that Benedict lack imagination in calling for world government. More to the point is governance by a variety of networks (such as the International Campaign to Ban Landmines). Daniel K. Finn notes the unfortunate resonance for Americans of Benedict’s appeal to fraternity – putting him in mind of ‘stereotypically immature males on college campus.’ Mary L. Hirschfeld points to some lacks in contemporary economic thought. The market is the institution in which the logic of exchange (we give to acquire) is governed by commutative justice. But sometimes markets fail, and in order to attain distributive justice we must decide how and when governments should intervene. Such intervention is merely technical; policy reduces to control. A better way is to influence culture (the place where we pose questions about true human flourishing) and foster trust (if bankers had been concerned with making sound loans rather than trying to squeeze out cash from customers the financial crisis would not have been possible) and so encourage the 497 hybrid commercial entities that embody virtues of gratuitousness. Hirschfeld seeks authentic development (do our literacy programs help people in the pursuit of truth? Do we feed the poor so as to befriend them at supper?) and criticises mainstream thought on its own terms (although economic logic suggests that firms who do not maximise profit go out of business, there is no comparison with households, who will not be driven out of business if they fail to maximise utility). Benedict is defended by an Italian economist Stefano Zamagni, presumably an influence on the encyclical. Several ideas are explained. The principal of reciprocity can be compared with the principal of exchange. In the latter A gives to B. But B then has to give something back, which in a market economy is determined by the price. This price logically precedes the transfer of value from A to B, and after receiving, B will be compelled by law to fulfil the agreement. But with reciprocity, neither of these conditions apply. There is no agreement as to the price, and no compulsion to return – though when we hold the door open for someone, usually we expect these favours will be returned someday. In stressing reciprocity Benedict hopes to overcome the dichotomy of the economic and the social: entrepreneurs are not required simply to maximise profit; they can act for prosocial reasons. Indeed, capitalism is simply one form that the market economy can take. Benedict endorses the ‘civil economy,’ whereby one can live the live the experience of human sociality (and be influenced by solidarity, subsidiarity, and values that affirm the centrality of the person and the common good) within the economy. This is an alternative to the tradition that stems from Adam Smith: markets must not ignore the disadvantaged. The aim is to go beyond the liberationist who sees the market as the locus of exploitation, and the libertarian who thinks that the market is the place where all the problems of society can be solved. Maryvale Institute Chris Friel Political Theology: A Guide for the Perplexed. By Elizabeth Phillips. Pp. vi, 200, London/NY, T. & T. Clark, 2012, $15.00. The author is to be congratulated on providing a useful and readable survey of this extremely important and ever-pressing topic. The Subject Index has long entries on ‘pacifism’ and ‘oppression’, just as it should. I suppose that every Christian who is not a pacifist must frequently and seriously ask herself whether she ought not to be one. Pacifism is a noble stance; but it will not do, for all that it is often done, to make its consequences appear easier than they are by dint of shoddy arguments and blindness to facts. Ought Neville Chamberlain really to have continued with his policy of appeasement when Hitler invaded Poland in 1939? (‘The situation 498 BOOK REVIEWS ought never have been allowed to reach that point’, a pacifist told me. But we have to act in the situation that actually obtains, not the one we would prefer to be in; no doubt it would be nice if Adam had never eaten the apple, but the fact is that he has, and we have to live with the consequences.) It would be convenient if diplomatic initiatives were always successful by themselves, but they are not. And when it comes to those bent on genocide --- are they really to be persuaded to cease and desist without the use of force, and lethal force at that? No doubt some of their representatives will be glad to talk to you, while others get on with business as usual. Peace, as Aquinas says, is more than the mere absence of war, and the question may occasionally arise of whether a state of so-called ‘peace’ is so flagrantly unjust, due typically to oppression of some people by others, that resort to war is the lesser evil. Of course, it must always be stressed that war for the Christian is at best the very last resort. Augustine is presented by the author as emphasizing the role of government in ‘holding the lid on human destructiveness.’ He will have it that, give or take a little, human beings since the Fall are thoroughly selfish, and have to be prevented by a more or less officious state from destroying one another and ultimately themselves. Aquinas, however, was enough influenced by Aristotle to maintain that, in spite of the ravages of sin, we retain some natural disposition to cooperate with one another; this leaves room for a state which is somewhat more benign and less intrusive. While it does not do, as the author rightly reminds us, to exaggerate either the pessimism of Augustine or the optimism of Aquinas (34), their overall views do provide ideal types, benchmarks between which to place viable Christian accounts of the nature of the state, and of the proper scope and limits of its coercive power. There are equal and opposite dangers in exaggerating and underestimating the effects of sin; and it has been well said that there is no more embittered reactionary than a disappointed liberal. I found particularly helpful the author’s summary of Reinhold Niebuhr’s somewhat Augustinian position, as he himself acknowledged it to be. He wrote, ‘A simple Christian moralism counsels people to be unselfish. A profounder Christian faith must encourage men (sic) to create systems of justice which will save society and themselves from their own selfishness.’ Dr. Phillips describes Niebuhr’s ‘scathing critiques of pacifists and advocates of non-involvement in the years leading up to World War II’ (84). But as John Howard Yoder sees the matter, Niebuhr’s cynicism sells the Christian witness lamentably short. The Church ought to display ‘a counter-politics of the gathered, believing community of God’s people which is marked by visible faithfulness to God’s sovereignty instead of grasping for political power’; and to practise ‘non-violent servant leadership in response to the life and teachings of Jesus and in anticipation of his coming kingdom ‘ (18). I was also impressed by Dr. Phillips’s account of the work of Jean Bethke Elshtain, who is influenced by both Augustine and Niebuhr. Elshtain told an aquaintance, in the immediate aftermath of 9/11, ‘Now we are reminded of what governments are for’ (99). Her reasoned defence of the war in Afghanistan may be mistaken, but it is certainly not despicable. She has also given us the brilliant epigram, ‘Muhammad was his own Constantine.’ She remarks that the distinction drawn by Jesus between the realm of Caesar and the realm of God has sometimes appeared to justify quietism. But that would be to abdicate responsibility. At the other extreme Islam has earned itself the reputation, whether justly or not, of being the religion of the sword. ‘Not that Christianity has no knowledge of the sword. But within Christianity the sword always has to justify itself’ (100). Yet there ought to be no question but that it has often ‘justified’ itself too easily. Cardinal Ottaviani doubted whether any armed conflict in modern times really met the criteria of justice in war. ‘Is the church ordained to be an instrument of peace, living in the already of the kingdom, while the state is ordained to be an instrument of violence within the realities of the not yet? How do we respond to the nearly opposite theory that secular states are the protectors of peace while religion is particularly prone to cause violence?’ (156) These are good questions indeed. As the lives of Christians are hid with Christ in God (Colossians 3.3) they can fearlessly seek out and proclaim the truth on such awkward questions as these, however unpopular or unpalatable it may be. Indeed, if we are to believe the prophet (Ezekiel 33.6), it will be the worse for them if they do not do so. Calgary, Canada Hugo Meynell BOOK REVIEWS 499 The Future of Political Theology: Religious and Theological Perspectives. Edited by P. Losonczi, M. LuomaAho and A. Singh. Pp. xiv, 210, Ashgate, 2011, £58.30. There is a spectrum of thinking from different conceptions of the political and the theological and depending of where one lands depends of how political theology proceeds. This book subscribes to Cavanagh and Scott’s definition, given in the Blackwell Companion Political Theology of a ‘discipline’ (their quotation marks) that considers political arrangements from the perspective of different interpretations of God’s way with the world. Authors in this book think that the above does not exclude what political theology can say about the political as a realm of human beings under God (their itals) but want to distance themselves from any fundamentalism. They accept what Jean-Luc Nancy proposes as the preference of the democratic process as where power is exercised and where justice is incommensurable. Political theology can make this latter more obvious and so criticize the political and seek correction but not domination of the political. More than domination, however, is the relative autonomy of politics and its concern with the media and the rise, as George Walden has stated, of a political-media elite who serve one another’s interests. The essays here propose new cultural imaginaries that are theologically permeated but resist attempts at domination. The book is in three parts: the past with its concepts and challenges; new theological trends and the final part on contexts and future prospects for the subject. The editors are aware that some approaches can mitigate against theology and religion becoming an interruptive force on politics and especially the Nancy version of direct power by theology, which they see as prohibitive on representations of the infinite and ask why it should be excluded. Indeed they go further is asking how such a prohibition can be made meaningful without theology being able to function since it involves an understanding of humans and sets limits which are somewhere between theology and politics. The authors also see this book as giving alternative ways of doing theology in a broad and pluralistic way to inform humans about the political as a realm of humans subsumed to God (or some other form of higher or alter reality). (This last bracketed phrase is their own). Although the book is about the future it begins with the past and three essays which about it. Riedl considers the secular in Western theology from a historical viewpoint beginning with the origins of (North) African Christianity and he delineates certain periods of conflict and cooperation in that long history. He attempts to construct an understanding of an underlying spiritual dimension to the formation of modern European culture so as to root its diverse phenomena in that domain thus providing a more comprehensive discourse for PT now and in the future. Hoelzl is on the particular episode of the Jewish Holocaust under the National Socialists in Germany up to and during the Second World War and the issues raised about the function of politics and religion, especially Christianity, seems to him and enormous problem for humanism as a political idea and for the identity of Europe. He states that this episode has been forgotten and yet it was a central event which requires reflection on how we understand ourselves and the identities, personal or national, that we prefer to construct without its inclusion. Lanczi wants to distinguish between political knowledge and wisdom and to ascertain the gap between them, preferring the latter as the preferred way of proceeding. The second Part of the book looks at the subject through the lens of new trends in theology in the hope of a reorientation of the subject. Karl Rahner’s pupil, JB Metz, and his idea of theology being interruptive to current discourses and practices is given ample consideration by Lieven Boeve since this is less a conventional systematic theology and more a constant critique of attempts at excluding suffering. Boeve illuminates and expands Metz’s approach by contrasting it with superficial understandings of how to speak about development, even in the case of the documents of the Second Vatican Council, where naive optimism and a prediliction for the success of a project can override and exclude the pervasive experience of suffering at all its levels. He argues persuasively that this interruptive theology is a necessary feature of the epistemological primacy of any and all narratives, political, theological and religious but doesn’t say where the interruption comes from, that is, the basis of its thinking. The Radical Orthodoxy movement is well articulated by Catherine Pickstock with particular emphasis placed on participation in politics and religion and thus restating the essentially social dimension of a creative personal faith. Levinas and the exclusion of the Holocaust already referred to is examined by Losonczi. The last essay in this Part by William Desmond looks at terms such as ‘cosmopolis’, ‘ghetto’, ‘intimate’ and ‘universal’, ‘singularity’ and suchlike to provide a new vocabulary for political theology by trying to, if not eliminate, then at least spatially partnering words which at first glance appear poles apart. 500 BOOK REVIEWS Whether or not this attempt can be actually effective remains to be seen but he does at least draw attention to the limitations of conventional and unreflective uses of words as devices for reinforcing distance in theory and practice and for the need to rethink their usage as ignored or forgotten references. The final part of the book deals with contexts and future prospects. The context in Europe, considered by Kornel Zathureczky, considers Pope Benedict’s Rosenberg Lecture which she thinks offers an attempt at a PT for Europe in Christian terms as opposed to a competing version by Islam which sees itself as having a universal reach in an insistent way based upon its own legal reasoning. Andras Csepregi looks at the work of the Hungarian thinker, Istvan Bibo, and his use of sociological and socio-psychological elements. The chapter on Iranian marriage and family law considers that Islam discriminates against women and their rights because of a particular interpretation of the Quire’s which needs now to be set in a different context for the future since this is the scope of its political theology. The essay on Buddhism deals with ‘Navayana’ which is the version adopted by the untouchables or dalit and which can be seen as a kind of liberation theology but which is generally absent from academic consideration. Aakash Singh thinks that this version is very political and given that it comes from the poorest has a distinctive and urgent contribution to make. Mika Luoma-aho considers the political theology of the UN and of the 2000 Millennium Declaration which underpins the UN’s approach until 2015. He regards this as important because, he argues, these approaches have their basis in Christian covenant theology although of a secular nature. This is a good range of essays which goes into certain themes in considerable detail whilst calling into question the existence of political theology itself as having a future at all. Sacred Heart Parish, Wimbledon James Campbell Language Use in the Public Sphere: Methodological Perspectives and Empirical Applications. Edited by Ines Olza, Oscar Loureda, and Manuel Casado-Velarde. Pp. 564, Bern/Oxford, Peter Lang Since the turn of the new millennium religion has entered fully into identity politics. Debates and controversies surrounding religion abound all over the world. Ongoing geopolitical circumstances mean that this is sure to continue. The questions of how religions are treated, and how they should be treated, in media, education, and public life are therefore of great significance that merit thorough consideration by scholars, professionals, and the general public. This edited volume provides fascinating insights into the mechanisms of communication and how they are related to the issues surrounding religion and public life in several national contexts. From astute analyses of media portrayal of religions in Britain, to the issue of the European Court’s ruling on the crucifix in Italian classrooms, and the reporting of debates over public wearing of the Islamic veil in Spain and Quebec, the essays in this book inform, entertain, and examine judiciously pressing problems concerning communication and religion in today’s world. In an area of study that is often partisan and sensationalist, this tome is methodologically rigorous. It would serve as an excellent introduction to the general reader interested in understanding further the relatively new field of discourse studies. Part One consists of nine scholarly articles that together give an overview of the main methods used in this field. This makes the book invaluable to researchers and graduate students in the social sciences. The variety of approaches suggested and the dis- cussion offered by different authors linking innovative ideas with other scholarly traditions, such as Philosophy, also make this handy edition readable, relevant and accessible to the non-specialist. The volume is the result of the collaboration of an international group of scholars from Spain, Britain, Belgium, Italy, Canada and Germany who are interested in the study of religion in public discourse. Consequently it offers pioneering research and methodological reflection that are otherwise unavailable in English-language publications. The ten articles in Part Two will be of particular interest to the general reader wanting to understand media reporting on religions, and the contribution discourse analysis can bring to understanding these issues. For example, in a fascinating chapter, Ruth Breeze problematises the treatment of religion in British media by presenting a fine-grained analysis of the reporting of religious controversies in four national daily newspapers: The Guardian, The Telegraph, The Sun, and The Daily Mirror. Her analysis reveals the complexities of reporting about the wearing of religious symbols, suggesting that some newspapers can at times ‘frame’ minority religions more favourably than when reporting Christianity. In three separate essays utilising different methodological approaches, Ines Olza, Sira Hernandez Corchete, Beatriz Gomez-Baceiredo, Ramon Gonzalez and Damaso Izquierdo Alegrıa consider similar issues in Spain. They too suggest BOOK REVIEWS the ideologies of national newspapers can affect their treatment of religions and give a detailed account of how narratives and texts are subtly manipulated and produced in order to reinforce political positions. This is a timely, scholarly edition that will have an impact beyond the academic community. As everyone has a vested interest in the fairness and sincerity of debates about religion in the public 501 sphere, this volume is to be welcomed as a thorough, detailed scientific examination of what can be often emotive issues. Its dispassionate and rigorous style serves as a prompt to remind us that we ignore truth at our peril in an age when religious controversies will persist. University of Navarra, Pamplona, Spain Daniel Moulin Justice: The Biblical Challenge (Biblical Challenges in the Contemporary World). By Walter J. Houston. Pp 150, London, Equinox, 2010, £15.99. In the present volume, Walter Houston unfolds a biblical conception of justice as fairness. He does so by weaving together contemporary theories of justice from notable political theorists, such as John Rawls and Amartya Sen, with contextual research on both the present day and biblical times. Houston uses this approach as a foundation to write about three modes of justice that can be discerned in the biblical texts, which he feels hold special significance for not only Christians, and in the case of Hebrew scriptures, Jews, but also for people of other faiths and even concerned secular readers. The first of these modes is ‘justice as cosmic order’, which centres on Houston’s analysis of the created order as depicted in the bible and invoked by the prophets. In a chapter devoted to that mode, Houston includes a stimulating discussion on the merits of reading certain biblical texts as departing from images of God’s justice based upon kingship to one of God’s justice centred on patronage, notably in favour of the people of Israel. According to Houston, those images can even be mixed in the same stories, so that, for example, YHWH’s kingly justice is felt by Pharaoh in the Exodus narrative even while the Hebrew people benefit from God’s patronage. The second mode of biblical justice identified by Houston is ‘justice as faithfulness’. In his ensuing discussion, the theme of patronage, with reference to the Exodus narrative, is further developed. This idea of patronage, for Houston, encourages the proper and just treatment of those for whom one has a special responsibility as per the law codes in the book of Leviticus that address actually existing inequality. An an example in this regard he cites the law codes provisions addressing the proper treatment of slaves held by the Israelites. A third mode of justice delineated by Houston is ‘justice as a community of equals.’ Here, Houston notably references the economic and social equality amongst the community of Israel as evidenced in jubilee provisions in Leviticus. Further, he makes use of Pauline images of equality that transcend blood relationships and prohibit people in power positions benefiting from the suffering of others. In this regard, he rather awkwardly argues for the conclusion that brotherhood and sisterhood in Christ along the former lines ‘must surely apply to everybody’ (p. 91). After his discussion of these three modes of biblical justice, Houston then offers a chapter which asserts that the biblical images of justice are put into practice by Jesus, including, in a somewhat of a departure from the prophetic tradition, in ways that separates the fates of oppressor and oppressed in favour of the former. Next, Houston’s penultimate chapter consists of a ‘justice audit,’ which names several worldly injustices and comments on them in light of the afore-mentioned three modes of biblical justice. A specific example mentioned is the failure of more economically developed countries to meet their portion of the funding for the United Nations Millennium Development Goals, which is discussed under the rubric of (lack) of justice as ‘right order.’ In a similar manner, Houston makes the assertion that ‘political equality is largely illusionary when economic equality does not exist’ (p. 108) made in a section titled ‘a community of equals?’. His overall conclusion in this chapter is that an audit exposes a general lack of justice in the world today, which can be sourced to imbalances in resources and power. Building on such analysis, in his concluding chapter, Houston offers specific recommendations for Christians to respond to biblical imperatives for justice, with a particular focus on the UK context. Here, for example, he cites the faith-based mobilization for the Jubilee 2000 debt-reduction campaign and fair-trade activism as important instances of Christian concern for justice in the world that serve counter a tendency to retreat into overly internal church matters. Houston suggests that a similar campaign ought to be undertaken to address the maltreatment of asylum seekers in the UK. He also builds on earlier materials to suggest that the Green Party has the policies that best reflect biblical values of justice for a concerned UK voter. Alternatively, Houston posits that the Labour party might be (justly) galvanized by influx of members 502 BOOK REVIEWS committed to its foundational principles of equity and fairness. He further upholds the value of intentional communities striving to live in solidarity with the poor, naming the Iona Community as an example of a group committed to peace, justice and the integrity of creation. As may be already evident, this monograph’s author does not hide his normative commitment to a more equitable world. The result is certainly some stimulating reading but there are also instances of overly sweeping statements and the resultant arguments are sometimes muddled. For instance, Houston places the World Health Organization (WHO) on a list international bodies that ‘most of the time..[work] against the interests of the poorest people in the less developed part of the world’ (p. 122). While the WHO is far from perfect, this seems a rather unfair characterization of the organization and its activities, which do strive to better the health of people who are marginalized in the global community. Further, the ‘justice audit’ chapter does little to explicitly link the preceding material and foreshadow the conclusion. Yet, despite such tensions, Houston’s work does succeed in its goal of raising a series of challenges to status quo lifestyles in the UK and the USA, often from a biblical perspective centred on justice. As such, although not always logically rigorous, Justice – The Biblical Challenge, nonetheless serves to raise significant questions about Western Christian complicity in both unjust structures and oppressive ways of being. Saint Thomas More College, University of Saskatchewan Christopher Hrynkow Reason, Tradition, and the Good. By Jeffrey L. Nicholas. Pp. 250, Notre Dame, Indiana, University of Notre Dame Press, 2012, $38.00. The sleep of reason produces monsters. This famous etching by Francisco de Goya is covering Nicholas’ thought-provoking book. The readers get aware how well this picture is chosen by familiarizing themselves with the two main theses of this work: The first, developed in chapters 1 and 2, claims that reason in modernity is asleep and that it has produced an ugly monster: a capitalist or rather a market society, as Michael Sandel has formulated it recently. In such a society it is impossible to evaluate ends. Chapters 3 to 5 demonstrate that the fight against this monster can be won once reason has been woken up. The upshot of the first two chapters is that the Frankfurt School Critique of Reason with its prominent figures Adorno, Horkheimer and Habermas gave the correct diagnosis of the problems of modern-capitalist society but were unable to offer the effective cure. Adorno and Horkheimer were right in identifying ‘subjective rationality’ as the main cause that made a reification of human beings possible and which led to domination and oppression (p. 19). According to the analysis of the early Frankfurt School, a ‘substantive’ conception of reason is missing. Only with such a new conception of reason, it is possible to formulate a critical theory of society, a society which is just and free of oppression (p. 221). To rely on substantive reason means to accept that reason is constituted by and constitutive of tradition (p. x). The social practices of giving and asking for reasons, the evaluation of these reasons and consequently the evaluation of the ends is only possible within a tradition and on the background of the set of evalua- tive standards and beliefs which it provides. The basic failure of the Enlightenment was therefore its belief in the possibility of a tradition-independent form of reasoning, its illusion that it is possible to establish a ‘neutral’ standpoint which enables a critical evaluation of society and an ongoing emancipation of human beings from oppressive and manipulating forces. Chapter 2 shows that the work of Habermas and his notion of ‘communicative rationality’ represents an important development of the Frankfurt School. According to Nicholas, Habermas moved in the right direction dissociating himself from the underlying philosophy of consciousness of Horkheimer and Adorno and advocating a conception of reason which is aware of its rootedness in historic forms of social interaction. Although representing a considerable improvement, this step is not sufficient. Nicholas demonstrates convincingly that Habermas’ conception of communicative reason is still too formal. With its claim to be able to derive substantive values or evaluative standards for judging ends from a purely procedural form of communicative action, it still tries to establish a ‘neutral’, tradition-independent standpoint of reasoning and is therefore not capable to propose a substantive conception of reason which could serve as a basis for a critical theory of society either (p. 12). In chapter 3 Nicholas turns to MacIntyre’s work with the intention to demonstrate two things: Firstly, he wants to illustrate that there is much common ground between MacIntyre and the Frankfurt School with respect to their analysis of the problems of modern society. Secondly, vital resources to BOOK REVIEWS formulate a critical theory of society can be found by relying on MacIntyre’s arguments for a traditionconstituted and tradition-constitutive conception of reason. Of course, such a conception of reason is charged frequently of leading to relativism. Although much ink has been spoiled on that issue, Nicholas is able to confront and debunk some of the more recent arguments that a commitment to MacIntyre’s traditionconstituted and tradition-constitutive conception of reason implies necessarily a commitment to relativism. The most creative and thrilling part of the book is chapter 4 which argues that the concepts ‘reason’, ‘tradition’ and ‘good’ are interrelated and that a reflexion on how they depend on each other leads to a substantive conception of reason which is able to provide a critical theory of society. Especially this chapter does not just display the stunning familiarity of Nicholas with MacIntyre’s, but additionally it proves that a ‘MacIntyrean tradition of enquiry’ has the capacity to clarify and solve some of its inherent tensions and problems. Although Nicholas presents in sum a convincing defence of his thesis, I would like to mention a critical point which concerns the insufficient social and cultural contextualization of the tradition of moral enquiry which is called ‘Frankfurt School’. At least a German reader of this book is astonished that Nicholas tries to interpret the thinking of Adorno and Horkheimer without considering their Jewish background and the traumatic German experience of the Third Reich. Nicholas’ presentation conveys the impression that the Frankfurt School is just an intellectual reaction to the frustrated promise of Enlightenment. However, such a presentation is biased. Adorno and Horkheimer were searching for an explanation how the rise of Hitler and the Nazis and how the horrific reification of human beings in the concentration camps were possible despite the long philosophical German tradition with its emphasis on reason. In this context, they speak of the ‘Verblendungszusammenhang’ (context of delusion) as one of the necessary conditions of the rise of the Nazi regime. Their criticism 503 of the Enlightenment conception of reason is a philosophical explanation and answer to the question which historic and social process enabled such a collective delusion. It can be said that the Nazi ideology is ‘Nietzsche put to practice’ and in this sense it revealed the final social and political consequences of a philosophical error which is rooted in an Enlightenment conception of reason. In accordance with MacIntyre one could argue that the sociological impact of this wrong turn in philosophy lead to the erosion of an ‘educated public’ which made a collective delusion possible and consequently enabled the rise of the Nazi regime. This missing or insufficient historicisation of the Frankfurt School, is, at least in my opinion, responsible for the fact that Nicholas has not detected even more common ground between these two traditions of thought. For example, the two do not just present a similar critical diagnosis of modernity, but both argue to provide a philosophical standpoint which is superior to competing philosophical traditions. Like MacIntyre in After Virtue, the protagonists of the Frankfurt School claim that they are able to provide a standpoint which allows to recast the historic narrative in such a way that it can be understood how the catastrophe of Nietzscheanism at the political and social level became possible. Despite this particular criticism, the merit of this book is beyond any doubt. It represents an important constructive proposal how the contributions of MacIntyre’s work in moral philosophy can also make a difference in the field of political philosophy. This is much needed because MacIntyre’s own proposal of ‘politics of local communities’ has proven up so far to be insufficient to formulate a full scale political philosophy and critical theory of society. Therefore, we should hope that Nicholas will soon fulfil his promise to further elucidate his Thomistic-Aristotelian critical theory of society which he sketches briefly at the end of his book. University of Bonn Patrick Zoll Christian Faith and Social Justice: Five Views. Edited by Vic McCracken. Pp. x, 207, London, Bloomsbury, 2014, £17.99. There is a great idea behind this book. The idea was to bring representatives of various ethical stances together to engage in conversation. The five ethical positions are labelled libertarianism, political liberalism, liberation theology, feminism, and virtue ethics. The structure of the book reflects the idea of conversation: each spokesperson presents a short summary of her or his position and the other four reply from their respective stances. These encounters provide the core five chapters of the book, to which along with an introduction a concluding chapter is added, allowing each participant to provide a summing up from her or his standpoint. Given the difficulties faced by students and practitioners in coming to terms with the great variety 504 BOOK REVIEWS of ethical theories and practical stances on important issues, this project is crucial and timely. However, the present volume represents only a first step in realization of the idea, and that should not be surprising, given that each of the stances can adduce a considerable literature devoted to the articulation and defence of its position. The idea remains a great one, and what is learned from this attempt may help to guide further steps in the realization of the project. The comments offered here in review, while giving a flavour of the book’s contents, are intended also to help develop the project. They are shaped around three questions. Assuming this a conversation, what is the conversation about? Who are the participants in the conversation? And are they agreed on the rules of the game? Already in the introduction the editor notes the selectivity involved in the choice of five positions and the exclusion of possible other candidates, such as the natural law tradition, or utilitarianism. Since the topic is social justice from the perspective of Christian Faith, one might also list Catholic Social Thought (not to be identified completely with natural law) and the Social Gospel tradition among possible participants. This inevitable limitation is not as such a problem, except in one regard, and that is in the specification of the topic of conversation: what are they talking about? The title suggests that ‘social justice’ is the focus of attention. The introduction opens the discussion by identifying three practical issues: the criminalization of homosexual acts by a Texan law, the exclusion of non-insured patients from health care, and the French ban on Muslim girls wearing headscarves in class. Are these intended to illustrate the concept of social justice? If so, there is a serious gap in the specification of the topic. In the tradition of Catholic Social Thought it has become commonplace to say that ‘work is the key to the social question’. The absence of fundamental economic issues from the perspective of social justice means that the conversation is distorted from the beginning. Of course, given the importance of the issues around the production and distribution of what is needed for human existence, the relevant concerns cannot be ignored in practice. They arise in Miguel A. De La Torre’s defence of liberationist stances, in Daniel A. Dombrowski’s presentation of Rawls on inequality, in Laura Stivers’ noting of the relative impoverishment of women, and in Jason Jewell’s endorsement of property rights from a libertarian perspective. Another related question provoked by this opening listing of concrete issues is whether the conversation is about the five stances which might be taken on such concrete issues, or whether the conversation is about the defence of those stances in general? The book follows the latter path, but the former might have been more productive. On the second question, who are the participants in the conversation, there is the obvious answer in terms of names. Along with the four listed above, Elizabeth Phillips represents virtue ethics. Each is a protagonist on behalf of her or his chosen stance, so it is more the positions rather than the persons which are brought into dialogue with one another. This is a difficult trick to pull off for a number of reasons. One reason is that they are not all the same kind of thing. For instance, political liberalism is a theoretical construct on the basis of several presuppositions, as was its earlier and related theory of justice. Liberation theology, on the other hand, is a practical stance, which, while it must address some theoretical issues, for example in relation to hermeneutical method, is pre-eminently an engaged advocacy stance. To bring theory in a strict sense into conversation with an engaged practical standpoint is difficult and requires careful reconstruction so that positions encounter each other on the same basis. As is reflected in some of the contributions to the book, it is not unknown for a position to create a positive profile for itself by caricaturing the alternatives. As for instance, as ideological, or as concealing class interest, or as reflecting patriarchy, or as remote and abstract theory. In further development of the project it is to be hoped that this tendency will be completely overcome and the engagement can be fair as well as honest. In the present chapters and conclusion there are many signs of willingness to cooperate. Feminism and virtue ethics find many points of similarity, libertarianism does not understand itself as excluding virtue ethics, and in being opposed to all uses of aggression is in harmony with the concerns of feminism. The tentative indications of agreement have to be explored further in order to discover if they are fruitful. Here is a point at which a focus on concrete issues rather than theoretical clarification might have been more productive. The discovery that on certain real cases the practical conclusions supported by divergent positions actually converge in endorsing the same recommendations might encourage acceptance of the complementarity of positions which to date have profiled themselves by contrast with each other. And this is the third question provoked by the book: what is or might be the shared theoretical foundation on the basis of which complementarity might be acknowledged and the tolerance of divergence accepted? This question alone deserves a monograph. Of the positions on the table, perhaps it is political liberalism following Rawls which has most directly faced this question and provided an articulation of the reality of a plurality of comprehensive doctrines along with the desirability of finding an overlapping consensus between them to sustain a public and political common life. The BOOK REVIEWS concrete issues listed in the opening of the conversation all had to do with matters of policy, whether of legislation or social practices. They belong, therefore, in that public realm in which solutions might be supported by representatives of divergent comprehensive doctrines. It should not be forgotten that no overlapping consensus is possible without persons and communities who hold 505 with conviction the content of their own comprehensive doctrines. This conversation begun in this book will also be useful to those attempting to refine their own commitments and convictions, since it presents arguments for and against the various stances. Heythrop College Patrick Riordan Toward a Generous Orthodoxy: Prospects for Hans Frei’s Postliberal Theology. By Jason A. Springs. Pp. x, 234, Oxford University Press, 2010, $74.00. During the last few decades of the twentieth century, postliberal thinkers dramatically reshaped the theological landscape, developing their own carefully nuanced perspectives, eliciting critical responses from both liberals and conservatives, while also (at least in some respects) setting the stage for the emergence of Radical Orthodoxy. Now in the second decade of the twenty first century, serious questions might be raised about the present status and future of the postliberal movement. Jason Springs’ book poses and attempts to answer some of those questions, focusing attention most specifically on the work of the Yale theologian Hans Frei, whose major writings were published in the 1970s and who died in 1988. This is the most important commentary on Frei’s theology, among numerous article-length and several book-length treatments, produced to date. The book has three primary objectives. In the first place, Springs executes a close reading and analysis of Frei’s work, ranging from his Yale dissertation to several important collections of essays published posthumously. His announced intention here is to demonstrate the continuity of Frei’s thought, to undermine standard accounts that distinguish between an ‘early’ and a ‘later’ Frei. In the middle sections of the book, Springs struggles to distinguish between Frei’s theology and that of his Yale colleague George Lindbeck, with whom he is often closely linked as a founding father of the postliberal movement. Finally, the twenty first century ‘prospects’ for a postliberal theology are explored in the book’s closing chapters, with some of Frei’s central claims being re-evaluated in the light of contemporary philosophical developments. Springs succeeds admirably in achieving his first objective here, carefully linking Frei’s early meditations on the ‘realistic narrative’ embedded in Scripture with his later attentiveness to that narrative’s ‘cultural linguistic context.’ The difference in emphasis, Springs argues convincingly, does not signal a fundamental shift in theological perspective, since a Barthian refusal to articulate the meaning of basic Christian beliefs in anything other than explicitly Christian terms guided Frei’s deliberations throughout his career. (Wittgenstein’s continuing influence was crucial for Frei as well, but always in a way, Springs insists, that is logically parasitic on his Barthian theological commitments.) Springs seems somewhat less successful in his attempt to show that the similarities between Frei and Lindbeck ‘have tended to get overemphasized’ (83). The result is not so much a problematic interpretation of Frei’s theology, but rather, the risk of caricature in summarizing Lindbeck’s position. Springs’ observation that Lindbeck’s bold talk about scripture ‘absorbing’ the world ‘has proven to be rhetorically unfortunate’ is balanced by his admission that Lindbeck later made attempts to clarify such talk (64). But the force of this admission is blunted by his strategy of identifying the ‘absorption’ trope as one of the salient features distinguishing Lindbeck’s from (what he regards as) Frei’s slightly more palatable perspective (82). I think that Springs is also unnecessarily rigid in the extent to which he portrays Lindbeck’s argument as entailing the absolute incommensurability or untranslatability of different religious perspectives on the one hand (68ff.), and as precluding the possibility of articulating propositional truth claims on the other (118). Interreligious dialogue is certainly a far more challenging task for someone defending the cultural linguistic theory of religion that Lindbeck proposed than it might be for some liberals, but it is hardly an impossible one. (Indeed, many of the insights recorded in The Nature of Doctrine were the precipitate of Lindbeck’s own decades-long engagement in such dialogue.) Moroever, to say that doctrinal utterances as doctrine should be conceived as rules rather than as propositional truths does not mean for Lindbeck that religious persons never make truth claims; it does mean that their making of such claims, much like their liturgical practices, is a form of religious behavior that ought to be ‘ruled’ by specific doctrines, one that should conform to a certain ‘grammar.’ Early in the book, Springs contends that ‘Frei’s semantics presupposes a pragmatics’ (13). His 506 BOOK REVIEWS exploration in the book’s later chapters of the pragmatic dimension of Frei’s postliberal theology—as well well as of its future prospects and possibilites when contemplated from a pragmatic point of view— give firm substance to that contention. The argument in these chapters deserves careful consideration from readers as well as further development by Springs. Frei’s gradually increasing attentiveness to the ecclesial practices that shape Christian discourse is evaluated by Springs against the background of a philosophical pragmatism first articulated by Wilfrid Sellars and then refined in Robert Brandom’s more recent work. The result is consistently iluminating as Springs avoids the distortive simplicity of any hermeneutic that emphasizes the significance of a given text’s contents while de-emphasizing its context, or vice versa. Now Peter Ochs has for several decades, and in numerous publications, carefuly delineated the affinities between postliberal theology and Charles Peirce’s pragmaticism. Moreover, Richard Bernstein has clearly traced the origin of important claims made by Sellars and others to their roots in several essays published by Peirce in the 1860s in the Journal of Speculative Philosophy. Intriguingly, Springs book suggests that, despite the canonical status of Barth, Wittgenstein, Geertz and others in the any narrative that describes the genesis of postliberalism, the future of such a theological perspective may emerge in this blossoming conversation with the philosophical pragmatists, not only contemporary but also classical ones. Lehigh University Michael L. Raposa The Future of Love: Essays in Political Theology. By John Milbank. Pp. xxii, 382, London, SCM, 2009, £25.00. This collection brings together a wide range of essays, eighteen in total, written after the last twentyfive years. Many of them are rewritten, at least in part, to reflect developments in Milbank’s thought and so it provides a valuable contribution to the study of his ideas. It is common place to note the vast erudition and tremendous intellect that characterizes all of Milbank’s work, and the range and scope of these essays give ample opportunity for the appreciation of both aspects of this. Moreover, for people with some general familiarity with his thought this is an excellent place to gain a wider overview. Indeed, as someone who has come to Milbank primarily through his more theological writings, and engaged with him on this level, I found it very useful to see his more politically inclined writings and understand why, in this field, he is often accorded great respect. Indeed, I found much that was appealing and inspiring within this; nevertheless, I still find Milbank’s work deeply troubling. It is almost impossible to offer an overview in the space of a review for the essays here. In six sections he develops themes on: Theology and English Culture; Theology and British Politics; responses to responses on Theology and Social Theory; Political Theology Today; Theology and Pluralism; and, Theopolitical agendas. Many of the themes overlap, and there is often no clear division, which is not a criticism in itself because Milbank’s work seeks to provide a grand theory, a theological holism, that encompasses all realms of thought. Indeed, before turning to particulars in this review, it would be useful to address this grand metanarrative that runs throughout the essays and which finds explication at various points. I would suggest this is necessary because a piecemeal approach would not do justice to the discourse that holds all this together. This great explanatory thesis which centralizes theology is something many find inspiring, however, it is one area where I find great problems with his work for at least four reasons which I will detail below. First, Milbank has a vision of a certain form of Platonic Augustinianism as providing not only the best but the only satisfying solution to the world’s problems, and the only adequate form of theology. However, his reasoning is often circular, given his presuppositions he sets out what must be, as he interprets it, the answer, and then shows his starting point gives us that answer. Certainly, given the sophistication of Milbank’s thought it is presented in a far more nuanced way, nevertheless it is inescapable. This results in his degrading comments on other religious traditions, and while at times he is quite generous in allowing that Judaism and Islam may have much in common with his own preferred tradition, he is often at pains to point out that they fail to provide an adequate explanation of the world, at least as he sees it. This brings us to a second point, which is that Milbank’s master discourse leads him to insist that everything is at root theological in explanation. Continuing with the notion of the Abrahamic religions, Milbank, for instance, claims that while the ‘Christian genius’ allowed it to blend reason and faith (i.e. the revelatory narrative and Greek philosophy), Islam by contrast tried and failed to achieve this. Leaving aside Milbank’s tunnel vision that only Greek philosophy is the world’s true intellectual heritage (a typical postliberal theological aporia that BOOK REVIEWS seems to think that ignoring India, China and other cultures is quite legitimate because Christianity must think within its own petite narrative – based on an appallingly limited understanding of world Christianity!), for someone who claims to deal with political theology it is remarkably na€ıve that he does not recognize that many factors beyond simply ‘theological’, narrowly understand, led to this. Certain groups of thinkers had support from the reigning powers, trends in intellectual thought and social formation benefitted various expressions of thought, etc. As such, Milbank’s thesis that everything else in world history is formed by (Christian) theological presuppositions, while cleverly argued by himself and others in the Radical Orthodox camp is patently nonsense. Thirdly, Milbank’s meta-narrative means that his thought remains, essentially, enwrapped within an imaginative bubble. At places he makes reference to Tolkien and others who, he says, by using imagination and literature were far more able to engage and actively spread an orthodox Christian worldview than those who used more prosaic theological and philosophical methods. Leaving aside the correctness of his assumptions, it has been noted by critics that he does engage in a very rhetorical style where stylistics take centre stage. In this regard I can see a parallel between Tolkien and Milbank, both are tremendous intellectuals who through their sheer power of imagination have created selfcontained worlds with their own internal coherence and logic (commentators on the fantasy novel genre often suggest Tolkien stands supreme in this regard for creating an entire universe with a history, languages, races, etc.), but, as I have suggested above, we have reason to doubt the viability of Milbank’s schema. If one wishes to buy into it, as his Radical Orthodoxy acolytes have done, you can create a theological vision of a world with its heroes and villains, a compelling central narrative that relates the way to a fall and return to grace; however, I suggest we do not need to buy into it (one reason for this would simply be that there are better ways of doing theology and better theologies than that he provides). Finally, my last assessment is that what Milbank gives us is, in various ways, bad theology, even within his own terms. Despite Milbank’s reference to ‘an entire Christian logic’ there is simply no such thing, and his work is throughout riven by a tension. On the one hand he wants to see everything as subservient to theology, yet one the other he wants to acknowledge the value of human endeavour and reason – and he sees incarnation and a universal divine presence, or indwelling, as grounding this. However, given this, and here I think he has good theological sense, it becomes increasingly untenable to suggest 507 that only one interpretation which in his system continues a quasi-Barthian dialectic of truth and error, spiritual right vs. secular error, becomes difficult to maintain. Other systems of thought besides his own can maintain such a synthesis (of valorising a divine inspired ideal yet accepting human reason and experience as worthwhile), and can do it without the polemical rhetoric he continually displays which seeks to divide the world between truth and error. To turn to some particular issues, Milbank’s political theology, for which I have noted he receives high praise, includes some very sound and praiseworthy aspects. His social vision is often strong and contains a clear insistence on justice and equality. In particular, he provides a sound explication of what can be found of use within Marx’s work, but also offering insightful critique. However, throughout his political essays while I often found myself endorsing his analysis he returned, repeatedly, to the meta-narrative which we have discussed above insisting that only one particular theological worldview could provide a sound basis for this. While he cogently showed, within his imaginative framework, why his own theology could ground his social vision, it is far from clear that it is the only vision that could do this. Moreover, his dismissal of liberation theology as inadequate seems to be based on a particular reading and analysis of it as essentially Marxist inspired, which is certainly not true of all liberation theology, and neglects the biblical sources it draws upon. Again, within his own theological viewpoint, it is unclear why he must reject that grounded in human reason or secular sources (Marxism) if this draws its inspiration (or may potentially do so) from a divine indwelling; an issue further compounded when he himself is willing to see Marxism as the best analysis of social issues. I would also note that while I find much of Milbank’s social analysis as very good it seems inadequate, both in theological and practical terms, certainly compared to recent liberation theological critique found in such figures as Jung Mo Sung. Continuing to focus on his political theology, it seems, at times, that Milbank’s theological imagination leaves him lost in the realms of fantasy with no coherent or realistic vision to offer. For instance he advocates ‘the gradual end of human self-government, a kind of ordered anarchy’ which he seems to think will come about if people devout themselves to his particular theological vision. While we may deem the pursuit of a high-minded idealism admirable, and certainly as an ultimate vision or idealistic utopia we may endorse what he wishes, yet it leaves us with no practical suggestions to counter the problems of the world. There seems to be a certain 508 BOOK REVIEWS naivety at work, similar to that of some very conservative social commentators, that if we all went back to church, sent children to Sunday School and advocated a theological leadership, etc. then the world would be a better place; however, it is clearly the case that this did not instil in society a greater moral fibre in the past, and leaves us wondering, if Milbank is right, why institutions like the Catholic Church (which he sees as a great focus of his theological vision) have not been above scandal, abuse and exploitation – I would suggest that Milbank’s idea that a correct metaphysical vision/ theology as grounding a certain social view is no bar to a great many actual abuses of people that could equally well be grounded in such a vision. Despite his pretensions to write political theology his thought seems often ungrounded in reality. Other issues of agreement or contention could be picked out from these essays, however, due to space I will devout myself briefly to just two more. One of these is Milbank’s very clever deconstruction of evangelical piety arguing that it offers a commoditisation of souls akin to the workings of a market based capitalism. While sympathetic to his critique, and I can see myself employing it, I nevertheless feel that he wants it to do too much. The entire evangelical movement cannot be written off as an ideology that has developed from employing a single approach linked to the rise of capitalism. As ever, ignoring historical, political and social factors Milbank seems to think that all comes eventually down to ideology, or, more correctly, theology; nothing else can impinge upon his all encompassing narrative. As such, his critique loses some of its force by being too doctrinaire in its assessment. The second point is his focus on the English context, or ‘Englishness’. This clearly looms large in his writings, and much of the first section has essays looking to figures he sees as precursors to his worldview like Coleridge. Leaving aside that Coleridge’s immediate successors and interpreters were often of a liberal theological disposition far from Milbank’s own tastes, his employment of these figures becomes part of a very suspect pseudo-Hegelian narrative. Making vast generalizations about the Anglo-Saxon character and disposition (for such a sophisticated thinker Milbank seems entirely unaware that any characterization of the English as Anglo-Saxon is deeply suspect), he seeks to show that in some fundamental ways the English way of approaching the world, which balances he suggests in a perfect match, metaphysics and empiricism, is the finest and truest epitome of all that he holds most worthy. While not quite employing a fully Hegelian sense of evolution, the cultural chauvinism that ensues in his view is clear: in his country, in the thinkers he admires, in the way of doing things and thinking of his native homeland, the highest pinnacle of Christian civilization (which, as he constantly tries to show, and as we have discussed above, is supreme beyond all others) has been reached. Moreover, his eulogies of the English way of life become, at times, almost absurd, where he extols the village church and its parish as what all truly aspire to and the true essence of Church as embodiment of Christ – a cursory glance through history would show that what this entailed is far from what ecclesiology should mean with the practical outworking of it where the local priest was effectively in the service of the local landowner; this presumably would betray a political power structure utterly at odds with Milbank’s own Marxist inspired thought. This leaves us really wondering what we can learn here. As stated at the beginning, Milbank’s erudition and brilliance are clear, but almost as if blinded by this he can at times present ideas which seem totally out of touch with reality and lacking any credibility. His Tolkienesque masterpiece of a total narrative theology that encompasses everything begins to unravel as it is made to do too much, and especially as it has to grapple with the actuality of the world, history, politics and society. I have no doubt that the ideology Milbank sets out will be studied and employed by theologians for many years to come, and certainly at its best it has depth, a mystery, an insight which few can match, however, to take Milbank’s work as one of the great works of theology would, I suggest, be mistaken. What we have is one man’s dream, but to take too much of it would entail a nightmare. The University of Winchester Paul Hedges Hauerwas: A (Very) Critical Introduction. By Nicholas Healy. Pp xii, 142, Eerdmans, 2014, £16.99. Healy subjects Hauerwas’s though to a careful systematic Theological appraisal. Focusing on his arguments rather than his personality, Healy produces a brilliant critique. Beginning with an uncontroversial outline of Hauerwas’s thought in which, drawing on social theory, the church should perform Christ’s narrative in a social ethic over and against the world, he then criticises his method, social theory and theology. Offering a compelling interpretation of Hauerwas as paralleling Schleiermacher, BOOK REVIEWS Healy claims both understand Christianity as an ecclesiology ordered on social-philosophical lines in which any doctrines of God take a back seat. Unlike traditional theologians such as Aquinas, whose understanding of the Church and Christian ethics was by an understanding of God’s provenience and independence, both Schleiermacher and Hauerwas, in different ways, understand God essentially along functionalist and utilitarian lines. Citing Kelsey, Healy claims that his attempt to ground Christianity in community practices reduces it to those practices at the expense of the Divine reality that is immanent yet also transcendent of them. Apologetics and ethics are conflated with God. Moreover, Hauerwas’s emphasis of ecclesial authority over the individual undercuts his own authority to challenge the church, as he is hardly an ecclesial authority as such. What right has he to demand that Scripture be solely read from within the Church, yet insist as an individual layman that most of the Church has misread Scripture, as with Pacifism? If he is to assume a prophetic authority against most church authorities then he needs to develop a Theology more accepting of the Holy Spirit working outside and to some against most of the Church. He needs to properly acknowledge that Scripture may be misread communally as well as individually and develop clear safeguards against the abuse of ecclesial authority. Turning to Social theory, Healy shows how ethnographic studies suggest that individuals are formed less passively by their communities than Hauerwas argues. People choose to be part of a community and influence it, as when homosexuals choose a parish tolerant of their practices, leaving less hospitable communities rather than simply being moulded by them as clay. Furthermore even individuals in traditionalist Catholic communities do not monolithically adhere to the beliefs embodied in their practices, a significant minority regarding such doctrines as the Real Presence as inessential to Catholicism. Hauerwas repeatedly extols “peasant Catholicism” but this is rooted in a misunderstanding of “peasant Catholics”. Healy appreciates Hauerwas’s concern that Christianity be seen as socially embodied, but fears that its reductionism leaves no room for the individual and the intellect in religion. Chris- 509 tians rarely behave in a manner sharply distinguishable from others. It is in fact debatable whether the Christian tradition should be so distinguished, Macintyre’s exclusivist understanding of tradition which influenced Hauerwas being considered too clear cut. Finally Hauerwas’s thought is criticised as theologically lacking. His stress on community practices leaves little place for the Grace of God. Christianity cannot be considered along Macintyrean lines as a community operating on certain tradition-specific lines of human excellence because it has excellence is at all primarily through God’s grace rather than by anything of our own. There is little sense in Hauerwas of God’s strength made perfect in the Church’s weakness, of the prevenience of Christ’s person and works on the Cross and by the Resurrection triumphing against even the wickedness of his closest disciples. Nor is the role of the Holy Spirit in the Church and in the world in general, sufficiently explored. Hauerwas is so busy telling Christians how to live that he pays little attention to the God revealed in Christ through the Spirit who makes life worth living in the first place. There is no Theology of failure, little consolation for those who, perhaps not though their entire fault may be too weak for the rigorist ethical communities Hauerwas envisions. How, if at all, these people may hope for salvation is not explained by him. Even when he wrote a commentary on the Gospel according to St Matthew, it is as a series of sermons on applied ethics rather than any concession that Christianity might involve contemplating God and what God has done even more than doing things in his name. Healy does not dismiss Hauerwas’s Theology entirely; he simply believes that it must be made more Theological. Kelsey is again invoked; the church is conceived as a worshipful response to the Triune God, with ethics grounded in Christ rather than the reverse. Healy is perceptive and provoking, those interested in Hauerwas must read it – as should Hauerwas himself. Braunton, UK Christopher Villiers Just War: Authority, Tradition, and Practice. Edited by Anthony F. Lang Jr., Cian O’Driscoll, and John Williams. Pp. viii, 328, Washington, DC, Georgetown University Press, 2013, $26.50. This collection of 16 papers plus an introduction and conclusion is the outcome of a workshop held in August 2010 in Washington, DC hosted by the US Institute of Peace. As the title suggests, the central theme is authority – both the contested authority of the just war doctrine for contemporary 510 BOOK REVIEWS nation states and non-state warriors and, for those who accept the doctrine, the authority to declare war and to determine how war should be conducted. In addressing the second meaning of authority, James Turner Johnson notes that following the Peace of Westphalia treaties (1648) nation states were acknowledged as the only legitimate wagers of war. In recent years, however, this position has been challenged by non-state armed forces fighting against repressive governments and by the emergence of the ‘Responsibility to Protect’, both of which limit the immunity of sovereign states from outside interference in domestic affairs. Nevertheless, Johnson concludes that ‘Classic just war thinking was right to hold that the use of arms is just only when authorized by a ruler responsible for the common good’ (p. 33). Chris Brown argues that neither sovereign states nor the U.N. Security Council possess the moral authority to declare war; rather such authority resides in ‘some notion of international public opinion, amorphous though this notion may be’ (p. 41). However, his main point is that just war theorizing, with its emphasis on legalistic rules, should give way to prudential consideration of the questions (not the answers) that just war doctrine raises. In his specifically Christian account of just war thinking, Nigel Biggar agrees with Brown that it ‘requires the prudential consideration of circumstances. . ., albeit within the terms set by moral norms of conduct’ (p. 57). These include right motive and intention as well as a favourable ratio of benefits to costs. John Williams (not this reviewer) discusses the popular opposition in Britain to the impending decision to invade Iraq in 2003. Although he would not allow such protests to be the determining factor in government decision making about war, ‘just war needs to engage with the challenge posed by the claim that war is “Not in my name”’ (p. 76). For Laura Sjoberg, the just war doctrine had done more to legitimate wars than to prevent them. One of the principal justifications for waging war has been ‘to protect “our” way of life, “life back home,” “innocent women and children,” and other proxies for the beautiful soul’ (p. 85), but the logical corollary of this motivation has been to target the enemy’s women and children, both to punish the enemy and because of the difficulty distinguishing between innocent noncombatants and those offering material support to enemy fighters. She concludes that ‘the just war tradition is itself a net cause of public harm that ought to be discarded and replaced not only in scholarly circles but also in policymaking circles’ (p. 92). Among the many non-state warrior groups operating today, Al-Qaeda is probably the best known and arguably the most effective. Nahed Artoul Zehr describes its model of war, as formulated by Abu Mas’ab al-Suri in his treatise on jihad, The Global Islamic Resistance Call. al-Suri distinguishes offensive jihad, which requires authorization by the political head of the community, and defensive jihad, for which the individual Muslim is the legitimate authority as regards both when and how (including terrorist tactics) to wage war. Tarik Kochi criticizes James Turner Johnson’s defence of the traditional just war position on legitimate authority, and just war theory in general, because of its use to justify colonialism and neo-colonialism and its neglect of the origin of sovereign authority: ‘When a theory does not, or cannot, explain how the bearer of the sword got the sword, and whether it got the sword by use of the sword, then it is not in a strong position to dictate to others the moral conditions under which a particular act of violence should or should not take place’ (p. 130). Against the contributors who would jettison just war doctrine altogether, Anthony F. Lang Jr. defends it as the best means for deliberating about war in democratic states, but like Chris Brown and Nigel Biggar, he rejects its legalistic use. Instead, he proposes a narrative approach and suggests that religious institutions are places where narratives about war can be effective. However, his reasons why this might not work are more persuasive than those in favour of his approach. Gregory M. Reichberg explores the place of punishment in classical theories of just war but does not deal with the question of authority. Joseph Boyle addresses authority only indirectly in focussing on right intention as a moral condition for making war. He notes that this condition has virtually disappeared from contemporary discourse but in his view it is essential for a just war. Brent J. Steele defends the role of revenge in pursuing war with specific reference to the murder of Osama bin Laden: ‘authority in global politics, when it is challenged, leads to not only a motive of revenge but also an expectation that such revenge must occur in a public setting. . .. The squaring of the circle between the two – revenge and just war principles – occurs because revenge gets transformed into “authoritative punishment” or “justice” when it is linked to rules’ (p. 199). Michael L. Gross contends that some non-state groups can claim legitimate authority to conduct guerrilla warfare against states under certain conditions, especially just cause. The basis of such authority is twofold: ‘a modicum of representation and the capability to improve the lot of their people’ (p. 223). Neta C. Crawford reveals that in the U.S.A. the authority to determine how to wage war rests almost entirely with the military and that ‘military BOOK REVIEWS necessity’ outweighs ‘noncombattant immunity’, resulting in widespread civilian causalities. Martin L. Cook argues that international law must evolve both to prevent states from oppressing their citizens and harbouring terrorists and to discourage powerful states from unilaterally intervening in other countries for their own self-interest. John Kelsey notes the differences between traditional just war theory and Muslim teachings on jihad and identifies the characteristics of what he calls ‘good’ just war thinking, including careful attention to the facts of particular conflicts and to the dynamic nature of conflicts: ‘one might judge an initiative as just at the outset, unjust at some point in the course of fighting, and just at the end’ (p. 277). For Nicholas Rengger, contemporary 511 just war doctrine priorizes the elimination of perceived injustices over the restraint of force, the result being the militarization of states and easy recourse to war: ‘Where injustice is everywhere, the reasons to use force to oppose it are not hard to find’ (p. 289). In a collection such as this, it is good to see that the contributors interact with one another, resulting either in agreement or disagreement. Of disagreements there are plenty, but each position is well argued. Whether and in what form just war theory should be preserved remains an open question. Further thinking about this will be enriched by careful attention to this book. University of Ottawa, Canada John R. Williams After the Smoke Clears: The Just War Tradition and Post War Justice. By Mark J. Allman and Tobias L. Winright. Pp. xii, 220, Maryknoll, N.Y., Orbis Books, 2010, $20.00. There are many books that concentrate on the rationale for going to war and on the conduct of war. After the Smoke Clears, as its title suggests, examines the period after the conflict and asks the question, ‘What must be done to restore justice?’ Allman and Winright, both associate professors of ethics at the time of writing (Allman at Merrimack College in North Andover, Massachusetts, Winright at St Louis University) and both writers on just war theory, offer their readers a balanced and informed piece on the issue of moral duties in a post war situation. After a brief yet useful introduction, which focuses on the hard lessons learnt from Afghanistan and Iraq, the book falls into two parts. In the first the writers examine the just war theory and the jus post bellum, which, until recently, has largely been ignored by ethicists. They first look at historical developments from Ancient Greek and Roman times, through Ambrose, Augustine, Gratian and Aquinas to Vitoria, Suarez, and Grotius and beyond the World Wars, and then present an overview of the traditional categories of jus ad bellum and jus in bello. They explore the jus post bellum as an emerging category in the ancient world, the Christian tradition and Kant and end the first part by summarising the elements of philosophy, political science, international law and military science as discussed by Brian Orend, Gary J. Bass, Doug McCready and Mark Evans. Building on the writing of Adrian Pabst (University of Kent), Allman and Winright conclude that although the just war tradition has developed in Christian circles, ‘theologians and church leaders have for the most part, but not altogether, ignore post bellum ethics’ (81). With this in mind they go on to propose ‘four main criteria, each consisting of a number of considerations and practices, to promote justice in the post war period .. [believing] that the right intent of restoring a just and lasting peace requires serious and systematic attention to jus post bellum by Christian theologians and the church’ (81). The second part begins by considering the Just Cause Principle, posing the question, ‘Can you get good fruit from a bad tree?’ and presents a critique of Orend’s position on Just Cause and jus post bellum. We then move to the reconciliation phase, which reflects on the immediate post conflict period, acknowledgment, apologies, punishment, forgiveness and amnesty. A chapter on punishment follows, focusing on compensation and war crimes trials. The fourth main criterion is the restoration phase, which I found the most compelling (probably because this was not written from an ‘ivory tower’ perspective but came to grips with the grittiness of war), not a return to the pre war status quo but addressing security and policing, political reform, economic recovery, social rehabilitation, environmental cleanup, depleted uranium, and cluster bombs and land mines (a development of Winright’s ‘Community Policing as a Paradigm for International Relations,’ in Just Policing, Not War: An Alternative Response to World Violence, ed. Gerald W. Schlabach, Collegeville, MN: Liturgical Press, 2007, 130-52). The writers conclude by stating that although they expect a general consensus on what they have written, they acknowledge that ‘there exists legitimate 512 BOOK REVIEWS room for differences of opinion with regard to their concrete applications on the ground’ (174-75). I was impressed by the fact that although Allman and Winright write from their Catholic backgrounds and pay special attention to the moral methodology of the U.S. Catholic bishops in their statements on socio-ethical issues, this book is not written primarily for a Catholic – or even Christian – audience. Monastère Sainte Presence Luke Penkett The Political Problem of Religious Pluralism And Why Philosophers Can’t Solve It. By Thaddeus J. Kozinski. Pp. xxvi, 268. Lanham, Maryland, Rowman and Littlefield, 2010, £44.95. Kozinski is an assistant professor of philosophy and humanities at Wyoming Catholic College. He is on the Board of Advisors for the International Etienne Gilson Society. This is his first book. Here he takes three philosophers, John Rawls, Jacques Maritain, and Alasdair MacIntyre, all theorists of religious pluralism and offers critiques on each. His argument is that ‘the only philosophically defensible end of any overlapping consensus political order must be the eradication of the ideological pluralism that makes it necessary.’ Put another way, ‘a pluralistic society should have as its primary political aim the creation of political conditions for the communal discovery and political establishment of that unifying tradition within which political justice can most effectively be obtained.’ It is a delightfully astute and provocative book. In Part 1 Kozinski analyzes the central idea of Rawls’s Political Liberalism. He begins by looking at Michael Sandel’s anti-Kantian and communitarian and Richard Rorty and Thomas Bridges’s postmodern and antifoundationalist critiques of Rawls’s A Theory of Justice, which Rawls completely revised. Kozinski then points out the flaws in his Political Liberalism. Part 2 opens with a contextualisation of Maritain’s ‘democratic charter’ (which differs radically from Rawls in its ‘absence of moral and political restrictions and pressure on both the mode of and motivation for public political discourse’ and its ‘historical and philosophical explanation of why an overlapping political consensus is possible and desirable in the present day’ (xxiii)). Chapter 4 then examines Robert Kraynak, Aurel Kolnai, and William Cavanaugh’s criticisms of Mauritain’s at times incoherent, at times na€ıve, thought, most notably when he attempts a hybridization of Catholic and non-Catholic, Thomistic and non-Thomistic philosophical and theological principles. The third part explores MacIntyre’s theory of ‘tradition-constituted rationality’, starting with his early thinking, then tracing his treatment through four of his main works, After Virtue, Whose Justice? Which Rationality?, Three Rival Versions of Moral Inquiry and Dependent Rational Animals. Kozinski critiques MacIntyre’s thought, contrasting him with Jeffrey Stout and Gary Gutting, pointing out the absence in MacIntyre’s thought of political theology. Kozinski then adumbrates a theologically informed MacIntyrean model for political community. Kozinski concludes that the political problem of religious pluralism cannot be solved by philosophy alone. It must be theologically informed, the result of a co-operation between political philosophy and political theology. The Political Problem of Religious Pluralism is a fine first book. Originating as a dissertation, its analyses are comprehensive yet readable and engaging. Interdisciplinary by nature, it will attract readers well-versed in the writings of Rawls, Maritain, and MacIntyre, as well as those for whom these names are little more than encyclopaedia entries. There is a foreword by James V. Schall SJ, until recently Professor of Political Philosophy in the Department of Government at Georgetown University. The bibliography and index serve Kozinski well. Monastère Sainte Presence Luke Penkett Religion, Intolerance, and Conflict: A Scientific and Conceptual Investigation. Edited by Steve Clarke, Russell Powell, and Julian Savulescu. Pp. cclxxxii, 282, Oxford University Press, 2013, £30.00. In May 2010 Steve Clarke, Russell Powell, and Julian Savulescu organized a conference at the Old Indian Institute in Oxford on the general theme of the relationship between religion and tolerance. This book contains thirteen essays that engage this theme from a diversity of perspec- tives. While ten of the essays are revised versions of papers presented at the conference, three of them (chapters 1, 8, & 13) were added during the publication process. The book is exemplary in that it successfully brings together a variety of diverse intellectual positions regarding a rather BOOK REVIEWS difficult and extremely relevant question, namely, whether religion is a force for the promotion of tolerance or intolerance. The book’s success in coherently engaging with such a complex and contested question from such different perspectives owes a good deal of debt to the preface that clearly lays out the question, indicates the general methodology, and provides a preview of the book’s contents. As regards methodology and content, the essays investigate the question empirically from the disciplines of evolutionary anthropology (chapters 2 to 4), experimental psychology (chapters 5 to 7), and analytic philosophy (chapters 8 to 13). One of the results of such a variety of approaches is that most readers will probably be drawn to one particular section of the book. In addition to their empirical approach, the contributions are descriptive and sometimes prescriptive. One of the most noteworthy prescriptions is the recommendation by Persson and Savulescu (chapt. 13) that children should only be allowed to go to schools that teach religious doctrines if they are also exposed to at least an equal amount of science. The conspicuous absence of theological insights certainly says something about the editor’s views towards theology’s ability to participate in “rigorous empirical investigation” and its relationship, or lack thereof, to science. This view comes into clear relief in Chapter 13 when Persson and Savulescu affirm that the ubiquity of religion affirms nothing about the truth or the credibility of religion. The lack of theological reflection certainly does not mean that the book is not of interest to theologians. On the contrary, it contains some valuable research material, perhaps most especially for those who question the nature and role of religious traditions in contemporary culture. For example, theologians dealing with issues of interreligious dialogue and theology of religions are likely to find some of the essays extremely worthwhile. In this regard, Chapter 11 by Owen Flanagan stands out. Flanagan examines the intriguing question of whether belief in the Abrahamic God of the monotheistic traditions makes a difference in terms of tolerance. He concludes his essay with some helpful suggestions for further investigations, including the importance of teach- 513 ing children the positive value of different ways of being human in terms of different religious traditions and their diverse understandings of ways of being human. The general theme of religion and tolerance is certainly highly problematic and creates some serious challenges that the book more-or-less confronts successfully. One of the persistent problems that plagues this theme is the semantic confusion surrounding the meaning of the terms involved. To the book’s credit, this problem is squarely acknowledged (thought not resolved) in Chapter 1 with Powell and Clarke’s reflection on the meanings of religion and tolerance. In regard to the ‘tolerance’, they propose that it is manifest when (i) one considers an action or practice to be objectionable, (ii) possesses the ability to put a stop to it, but (iii) due to overriding reasons, decides to allow the action or practice to take place. As regards ‘religion’, the task seems to be decidedly more difficult and it is taken up in one way or another in Chapters 8 through 10. The difficulty of arriving at a clear understanding of ‘religion’ is acknowledged in the concluding ‘Commentary A’ by Perry and Biggar who point out the difficulty of defining religion. Perhaps a theological reflection on the nature of religion from the perspective of a particular tradition could have been helpful in filling-out the meaning of this central concept. In addition to ‘Commentary A’, the book also has a ‘Commentary B’ in which the editors masterfully synthesize the different contributions. This is not to say that they simplify the complexity of the discussion by reducing their inherent differences. They do, however, arrive at the general conclusion that a basic awareness of the tendency of religions to generate intolerance, under certain conditions and towards certain people, is of vital importance if conflict is to be assuaged and possibly even avoided altogether. In the current climate in which hostilities among different people and communities run high, this edited volume provides a valuable resource that can help us to understand the nature of the conflict and in this way, deal with it more effectively. Katholieke Universiteit Leuven John Friday Is Critique Secular? Blasphemy, Injury, and Free Speech. By Talal Asad, Wendy Brown, Judith Butler, and Saba Mahmood, with a new preface by the authors. Pp. xxii, 154, New York, Fordham University Press, 2013, £12.99. This book was first published in 2009. This new edition, sparkedby the Danish cartoon controversy of 2005, is an answer to the question posed in the title. A dozen editorial cartoons, most of which 514 BOOK REVIEWS satirised the Islamic prophet Muhammad, were published in the Danish newspaper Jyllands-Posten on 30 September 2005, and re-published by several European and North American newspapers in 2008. Jyllands-Posten stated that this publication had been an attempt to contribute to the debate on criticism of Islam and self-censorship. Muslim groups in Denmark complained and the issue led to protests and riots around the world, including violent demonstrations in some Muslim countries. The question set by the authors here is whether a secular worldview is radically different from a religious one; if so, does each have its own epistemology, so that one is irreconcilable with the other? The title was also intended to challenge the presumption that critique is inherently secular. The reader is invited to reflect on whether secularism is, by definition, the condition of critique and self-criticism, unlike religious orthodoxy, which is considered to be dogmatic. During the autumn of 2007 a symposium ‘Is Critique Secular?’ was held at the University of California, Berkeley; it is from this symposium that the papers published here are taken. Any current discussion of secularism has a number of significant epistemological and political consequences, some of which are examined here. First, the writers ‘explore the way a particular conception of secularism is central to the identity of the West (liberal, democratic, tolerant, critical), juxtaposed against its imagined other, which in this historical moment has become coextensive with Islam’ (viii). Second, the writers ‘call into question the standard normative account of secularism as a principle of state neutrality toward religion, including a resolute separation of church and state, religion and law, ecclesiastical and political authority’ (ix). After an Introduction contextualising the symposium by Wendy Brown, Class of 1936 First Professor of Political Science at the University of California, Berkeley, Talal Asad, Professor of Anthropology at the CUNY Graduate Center, shows in his wide-ranging and erudite ‘Free Speech, Blasphemy, and Secular Criticism’, how ‘different conceptualizations of belief, freedom, and truth produce different possibilities for action in the world’ (9). He asks two basic questions, ‘Does the modern liberal aversion to the category of blasphemy derive from a suspicion of political religion?’ and, ‘Why is it that aggression in the name of God shocks secular liberal sensibilities, whereas the act of killing in the name of the secular nation, or of democracy, does not?’ (9-10). Saba Mahmood, Associate Professor of Anthropology at the University of California, Berkeley, addresses in her ‘Religious Reason and Secular Affect: An Incommensurable Divide?’ the significant differences in what she calls ‘reading practices ‘flowing from Islamic piety (a tradition of interpretation that is challenged by many Muslims) and secular Protestantism’ (10) before moving on to regard different semiotics of iconography and representation, in particular those pertinent to religious deities and prophets. Judith Butler, Maxine Elliott Professor of Rhetoric at Berkeley, then provides a ‘Response’ to these two papers. Focusing on the question of ‘why outrage against the cartoons by Muslim populations across the globe was of a certain kind, and of what specific meaning that injury had and has’(95), drawing out their writers’ conclusions, affirming their challenges to Western representations of blasphemy, injury, and freedom by emphasising the fact that there will always be a normative framework regulating the semantic areas in which such terms work. Further, she concludes, these frameworks stimulate our own critical perspectives. Asad and Mahmood then reply, briefly, to Butler, Asad considering the distinction between critique and criticism, critique as ‘the indispensable foundation of knowledge’ (138), and the interface between power and critique, Butler ends with a question that points to a possible way forward, ‘What [are] the cultural, ethical and sensible means by which ... relations [are] affected and transformed?’ (147). A challenging and thought provoking book that moves beyond questions of whether the Dutch cartoons constituted a substantial injury, whether the cartoonists were exercising their freedom of speech, or whether the offence of religious sensibilities ought to be prohibited, this work offers much on the nature of blasphemy, on how injury such as that incurred by the Islamic protesters as a result of the Dutch cartoons ought to be addressed - and on the price paid for an antiintellectualism brought about by legal proscriptions of speech. Dorset Luke Penkett BOOK REVIEWS 515 The Leap: How to Survive and Thrive in the Sustainable Economy. By Chris Turner. Pp. vii, 360, Toronto, Random House Canada, 2011, £3.25. This extraordinary book could hardly be more timely. It begins with a parable. Two trains are running on adjacent tracks, one running towards an abyss of incalculable depth, the other, which has far fewer travelers on it, towards a fairly commodious destination. Up to now, far more people are on the first train than on the second. It is still possible, with some resolution and at the cost of some immediate inconvenience, to make a leap from the first train to the second. Some passengers in the first train are standing and gesticulating, earnestly telling the rest how important and urgent it is to make the leap; others are trying to shout these down or shut them up. Others still are remaining impassive and imperturbable in their seats. It is not difficult to interpret the parable in terms of present-day humanity at large, particularly those fortunate enough to enjoy the standard of living which prevails in North America and Europe. We should perhaps be somewhat concerned at the prospect of every fish in the Great Lakes being rendered unfit for human consumption, due to the belching of mercury into the atmosphere by installations for the extraction and refinement of coal for our electrical grids; by the 34,000 or so American lives significantly shortened by direct involvement in the coal business; or by the apparently inevitable periodic devastations of marine life by accidents to tankers and oil rigs. We have acidifying oceans and consequently disappearing coral reefs; and small islands, till recently inhabited, inundated by oceans rising due to melting ice caps. (How safe is London, by the way?) We, or at least the more fortunate among us, can simply turn our eyes in another direction. Others among us are committed, whether financially or by sheer force of habit, to the unrestricted exploitation of conventional but dwindling sources of energy, and will lobby to prevent governments from undertaking radical change. But a Swedish climatologist has compared our predicament to persons about to fall a considerable distance; they may either construct a cushion at some inconvenience to themselves, or do nothing and suffer the full and fatal consequences. (In defense of the status quo, I believe that I have heard worse arguments than I ever have on any other subject, especially from Albertans; but there is no pace to go into them here.) Germany, perhaps not always the best model for national behaviour over the past century or so, has proved exemplary in its commitment to renewable energy as provided by such devices as solar panels and wind turbines. Many thousand family residences actually contribute electricity to the grid, due to encouragement by far-sighted legislation. (Unfortunately similar attempts in Britain have largely failed, due to let-outs which were deemed to make them more palatable to the electorate.) The success of the new German technologies has spectacularly exceeded all forecasts, and has been achieved in the teeth of vigorous opposition, accompanied by dire prognostications, on the part of their political opponents, who often have strong financial interest in supporting the status quo. Extra coal-based installations, which were deemed necessary by the government to make up for the largescale abandonment of nuclear-based energy, have largely proved unnecessary. Manufacture and servicing of the new technology has incidentally turned out to be a boon in meeting the problems of unemployment in the formerly communist East Germany. Fortunately, many American jurisdictions provide heartening examples of towns and firms which have resorted to renewable energy, for all the busy and vociferous political opposition that they encounter. Evidently, this book does not fall under the concept of either philosophy or theology. But I urge that it is of significance to the practitioners of both disciplines, as indeed to all educated citizens of a democracy. It is still, in spite of widespread trivialization of the subject, not absurd to maintain that a principal concern of philosophy, and in particular of moral philosophy, is how a person ought to live. This book argues from a mountain of evidence, and as cogently as any which I have come across, that, if we care a jot about our (great-) grandchildren and subsequent generations, we most of us have to make radical changes in the way we live, and encourage others to do so. The theologian may add that this is the most central and pressing consequence of the command of God as it bears on the more fortunate people living at present in the West; and that we will be answerable to the divine Judge if we do not heed it (cf. Ezekiel 33.6 ). Since our lives as Christians are hid with Christ in God (Colossians 3.3), we may fearlessly proclaim and strive to implement what appears on the best evidence to be the truth, however inconvenient or unpalatable it may be. Calgary, Canada Hugo Meynell 516 BOOK REVIEWS Walter Lippmann: Public Economist. By Craufurd D. Goodwin. Pp. ix, 414, Cambridge/London, Harvard University Press, 2014, £25.95. Walter Lippmann was the most respected political journalist in the United States from 1931 until 1967. He wrote columns for the New York Herald Tribune and then the Washington Post, initially four days per week, then three, and finally two. Ultimately the column was syndicated in more than two hundred papers across the country and abroad. At his peak Lippmann wrote for an audience that approached eight million in a standard format of approximately a thousand words. He also produced ten books, some of which have become classics: A Preface to Politics (1913), Public Opinion (1922), A Preface to Morals (1929), and The Good Society (1937). Goodwin, for forty years the ‘dean of economic thought in America’, has written a superb intellectual biography; in the final quotation from the book, Alastair Buchan, for many years correspondent for the London Observer in Washington, links Lippmann with Reinhold Niebuhr as part of ‘the great tradition of Christian pessimism.’ But Lippmann was Jewish, and he brought to the job of defending the secular gospel of western intellectual, political, and economic liberties a fierce intelligence, personal discipline and restraint, avoidance of rancor, and unfailing courtesy; he also brought a prophetic sense of realism, an even proleptic or anticipatory caution and warning, alert to any danger signal, against easy complacency and in particular the inveterate, and even encouraged contraction of concentration within capitalist society away from the common good towards individual self-interest. Guiding America through the Great Depression, he tried every ingenious device that could be invented for damage control and social engineering to preserve a liberal system that paradoxically poisoned itself and plotted its own demise by encouraging as dominant motivations greed and the subsequent panic at the prospect of loss and catastrophe; at the end Lippmann admitted it was an open question whether he could save the system from itself. Lippmann took as his life vocation what he thought everybody – but especially the educated elite – should be doing: studying the complex problems that strangely bedevil the free enterprise system and which keep the free flow of goods, labor, and credit from bringing prosperity to everyone. Self-interest at every stage may clog the system, and – short of rule by an ‘elite’ that would be isolated from the temptations the system encourages and thus beyond corruption, which is impossible – proper education of the voters and public at large could provide a clear view of what was happening and widen their vision and sympathy to do what should be done for the common good. This requires ever more precise and updated information about an ever-evolving problematic economic situation. Lippmann was repeatedly disappointed, however, at the failure of every sector of the society to rise to embrace this enlarged concern he was advocating; the ‘gambling instinct’ at the core of capitalism, especially the banking, stock market, and financial sector of investments in general, and the self-protection behind stereotypes of a demonized ‘other’, prohibited the development of the common concern and breadth of interest he was conspicuously demonstrating. Eventually he realized the irreplaceable need for a change of character in economic man if the system is to survive; but the system did not encourage this – to the contrary. Build in as many checks and balances as you will, the devil you have left at the center of the system will always outwit them. The gospel Lippmann was defending was the only, or the best one he knew, but it was not good enough. Heythrop College Patrick Madigan Why Marx Was Right. By Terry Eagleton. Pp. xiv, 258. New Haven/London, Yale University Press, 2011, £28.91. Someone ought to conduct a university course on ‘The Great Half-Rights.’ Marx would unquestionably be a main attraction; Freud and Hobbes, with their views of human nature and human prospects in many ways antithetical to his, would probably feature as well. It was high time for a counterblast in favour of Marx in defiance of contemporary fashion, and Dr. Eagleton is just the person to supply it. For one thing, he writes with a combined elegance and panache which are such as to drive at least one rival author to the verge of despair. What was it that happened in the crucial decade between about 1976 and 1986, he asks, at the start of which Marx was all the rage, and at the end of which he was almost universally decried? (It was towards the beginning of that decade that a certain rash person gave a visiting lecture at an English university, at BOOK REVIEWS which he praised Marx for many aspects of his thought, but ventured to suggest that some oversights might be attributed to him as well. He was promptly, publicly and insultingly denounced for presuming to say that Marx was wrong on any matter whatever; though two people told him afterwards in the pub that they largely agreed with him, but did not dare say so openly.) Eagleton wonders ironically whether it was that those young hotheads who had espoused Marxism became submerged under heaps of toddlers; or that a manuscript in Marx’s hand had turned up in a Highgate attic to the effect that it was all a joke; or that some genius had published a tome refuting all Marx’s principal arguments. On the widely-circulated cliche to the effect that Marxism is out-of-date, Eagleton adroitly comments that to make it out-of-date ought to be the main ambition of every Marxist worth her salt. But who could deny that contemporary conditions in the slums of Lima or Nairobi are frighteningly reminiscent of what Engels reported of Manchester in the early 1840s? (To differentiate Engels’s contribution from what is properly original to Marx is not, as the author says, his concern in the present work.) He points out that one can legitimately call oneself a Marxist while admitting that the great man was wrong about this and that; as he says, confessed enthusiasts for the films of Alfred Hitchcock may with consistency concede that their hero occasionally nodded. His strategy, an excellent one, is to take ten fundamental contentious issues on which he provides firm grounds for believing that Marx was substantially right. On each issue, the author follows the admirable practice, inherited from medieval Scholastic writers, of first setting out what his opponents would say, in terms that would so far as possible be acceptable to themselves. According to the presently fashionable opinion, writes Eagleton, Marxism may be all very well in theory; but in practice it leads to terror, tyranny and mass murder, as history has by now abundantly shown. It may look well enough to comfortable Western academics who take for granted freedom and democracy; but, given the clear evidence, one must be ‘obtuse, self-deceived or morally contemptible’ to be a Marxist today. What is more, failure to accept the dictates of the market finally results in a lack even of material goods. Well, replies Eagleton, capitalism isn’t all roses either. ‘Modern capitalist nations are the fruit of a history of slavery, genocide, violence and exploitation every bit as abhorrent as Mao’s China or Stalin’s Soviet Union.’ In the nineteenth century, millions died as the result of easily-preventable famine or 517 disease, often as the result of free-market dogma which put staple foods beyond the means of ordinary people. Even today, ‘(o)ne in three children in Britain . . . lives below the breadline, while bankers sulk if their annual bonus falls to a paltry million pounds.’ It is not to be denied, as Marx readily admitted, that capitalism has bequeathed to us some precious goods along with its abominations --- the heritage of democracy, civil rights, and feminism, in spite of its ‘history of slumps, sweatshops, fascism, imperial wars and Mel Gibson.’ And it should not be forgotten that ‘so-called socialist’ states have their positive achievements too; ‘cheap housing, fuel, transport and culture, full employment and impressive social services for half the citizen of Europe’ (12-14). Marx himself hoped for a future of diversity, not uniformity; he envisaged socialism as a deepening of democracy, not an abrogation of it; ‘(h)is model of the good life was based on the idea of artistic self expression.’ In spite of his notorious endorsement of violent revolution - who would expect those in power willingly to relinquish their unjust privileges? - he admitted that some proletarian revolutions might well take place without violence. Was ever a thinker so misrepresented? (238-9) The reviewer, for his part, finds immensely impressive Marx’s depiction of what non-alienated labour might be in the society of the future, with head and hand working together, and human beings in enthusiastic cooperation one with another. Given our evolutionary inheritance of instinct (underestimated in my opinion by Marx and Marxists with their extreme ‘environmentalism’), it is perhaps too much to hope that, with post-industrial society properly organized, we would entirely be able to dispense with such coercive instruments of the State as army and police, as prophesied by Marx and Engels in The Holy Family. But is it not a reasonable and commendable aim for people of good will, to try to achieve a socio-political set-up where such human predispositions as may remain to engage in destructive and anti-social behaviour are encouraged as little as possible? Marx’s famous account of religion, as offering a comforting illusion to render bearable for the oppressed classes a life which was otherwise unbearable, may have been exaggerated; but can one really lay one’s hand on one’s heart and say there is absolutely nothing in it, and never was anything? Nicholas Berdyaev stated roundly that the only thing wrong with Marxist socialism was its atheism. He added that those who thought capitalism the more Christian option needed their heads looking into. Calgary, Canada Hugo Meynell 518 BOOK REVIEWS Theology and Marxism in Eagleton and Zizek: A Conspiracy of Hope. By Ola Sigurdson. Pp. x, 243, Basingstoke/NY, Palgrave Macmillan 2012, £58.00. This useful and exciting book compares two favourable assessments of Marxism from Christian perspectives, one Catholic, one Protestant. Among the most surprising intellectual developments of recent years has been the revival of interest in religion among those who think seriously about politics, especially from a Marxist point of view. Eagleton’s Catholic background, enhanced by the profound influence upon him of the work of the late Dominican scholar Herbert McCabe, leads him to think in terms of Thomas Aquinas; while Zizek’s Protestant origins make him reflect rather the influence of Hegel. Both are unashamedly unreconstructed Marxists, and both preoccupied with ‘ideology’, which they think of in a pejorative sense as essentially ways of thinking which hinder human emancipation. In this sense the Hebrew prophets and Jesus may well be thought to have been opposed to ‘ideology’ (20), for all that they did not envisage it quite in the manner which has become usual since Marx. The kind of ‘religion’ whose main function is to sanctify and so to stabilize the more or less unjust and oppressive socio-political situation which happens to prevail at present (I like Robert Musil’s expression, ‘the utopianism of the status quo’) is certainly ‘ideological’ in this sense; but it is possible to regard it as still an open question whether this is of the essence of religion. While most of Marx’s followers have been at one with him in hostility to Christianity and to religion in general, as obscurantist and reactionary forces, it is obvious to anyone with eyes in her head that the two worldviews have a great deal in common, both in their active revolutionary fervour, and in their hopefulness for a better future for humankind. Whatever their differences, they are at one in having a great deal to say about human hopefulness and emancipation, and what we are to do about the human situation. It does not strain credulity to suggest that what Marx called ‘the classless society’ is close to one aspect of what Christians have proclaimed as ‘the Kingdom of God’. And surely Nicolas Berdyaev had a point, when he suggested that those who really thought capitalism closer to Christian ideals than Marxism needed their heads looking into. Zizek makes much of the contrast between ‘faith’ and ‘belief’; in his view, what was significant about the Hebrew prophets was rather ‘trust in the Lord’ than ‘conviction there exists only one instead of a number of gods’ (98). He is surely right to rail against those who would make objectivity a pretext for lack of moral and political commitment. But I am uneasy with his polemic against supposedly ‘objective’ discourse which does not directly involve such commitment. Admittedly, appeal to objectivity can be a sham, a cloak for evasion of the search for greater social justice or emancipation. But it has a place, and an important place, all the same. Its neglect leads straight to the re-writing of history in deference to the party line, rather than in accordance with the evidence, to Lysenkoism and the repeated wholesale revisions of the Soviet Encyclopedia. The main task facing us may be, in deference to the eleventh of Marx’s Theses on Feuerbach, changing the world rather than merely describing or explaining it; but to change the world for the better rather than for the worse, you have to have as accurate as possible an account of the facts as they are. One would have thought that the actual history of State-sponsored Marxism during the twentieth century provided abundant corroboration of this point. As Eagleton sees it, following McCabe, it is helpful to see God rather as ‘being itself’ than a being among beings; as they see it, this may draw much of the sting from the atheist critique. For my part, I am inclined to sympathize with those who maintain that modern Thomists are better advised to interpret ‘being’ in terms of ‘understanding’ (with ‘being’ in the last analysis as what is to be understood) rather than vice versa. On this account, our limited and fallacy-prone human understandings advance slowly and haltingly, through our morality and our science, towards the ‘unrestricted act of understanding’ that is God - whose understanding explains the intelligibility of the world, and whose will explains the actual kind of intelligibility that it is progressively found by scientists to have. I fear that to envisage God primarily as ‘being’ is too apt to lead to excessive abstraction, and, as modern analytical philosophers have pointed out to us ad nauseam, nonsensical abstraction at that. Perhaps, in spite of a tendency in the thought of Aquinas, contemporary Christian theorists have to stress positive analogies between the divine and the human --- if one is to face properly the criticisms of Hume and his multitude of twentieth-century followers. Certainly, it is idolatry or ideology - that the one is apt to be identical with the other is often pointed out in this book and by our two authors - to treat God as one among God’s creatures; but, for all my great admiration for McCabe, I do not think that, among the many competing interpretations of Aquinas, the one that BOOK REVIEWS makes him appear as a kind of proto-Tillich is the most enlightening or convincing. Eagleton will have it that God creates ‘for the hell of it’ (115). I like that, but don’t take it quite au pied de la lettre. Can’t God have created Eagleton for the sake of Eagleton, and for the rest of us? I for my part am glad of his existence and activities as an extraordinarily entertaining, invigorating and instructive author. Both Eagleton and Zizek, at least as presented by Sigurdson, seem to me to lack, and very much to need, an epistemology adequate to provide a convincing account of just what ‘ideology’ is, at least in its common pejorative sense, and of what genuine ‘emancipation’ would amount to. A comprehensively critical epistemology would reveal the best of Freudianism and Marxism as partial viewpoints (Zizek is right to regard them as complementary); both our socio-economic position 519 and our personal psychic history are liable to impose limitations on the evidence to which we are apt to attend, the possibilities which we are easily able to envisage, the judgments which we are willing to affirm, and the decisions that we are prepared to make. Such a theory does exist, but it takes one beyond the limits of anything that can usefully be called ‘Marxism’. Eagleton is quite correct in insisting that a thoroughgoing postmodernist relativism renders all serious and non-arbitrary political criticism impossible (31-32). The author’s (or translator’s) frequent lapses in English grammar and syntax are a pity, but do not make this fine book less worthy of reading and, indeed, of careful study. Calgary, Canada Hugo Meynell The Economy of Desire: Christianity and Capitalism in a Postmodern World. By Daniel M. Bell, Jr. Pp. 224. Grand Rapids, MI, Baker Academic, 2012, £9.40. This is a very silly book. Its object, certainly a worthy one in itself, is to determine what of positive value is to be learned by Christians from postmodernism (‘What has Paris to do with Jerusalem?’ (15)). With this in mind, it concentrates particularly on two subjects as treated by two wellknown authors, Michel Foucault on ‘power’ and Gilles Deleuze on ‘desire’. The author rightly says that members of the Churches should not be deterred by the fact that both writers were declared Marxists, as Marxism comes in any number of shapes and forms. I for my part am sure that there is a great deal of worth to be learned from Foucault (are not common assumptions about sexuality, prisons and punishment too largely determined by the power some people are trying to exert over others?); if it is not taken to the self-destructive extreme apparently implied by Foucault himself (Foucault’s convictions, on his own showing, appear invalidated by the very motive of power which he attributes to his adversaries). I am prepared to be persuaded that there is also something useful to be got from Deleuze, an author with whom I am less familiar. The ‘Occupy Wall Street’ farrago began as a serious political protest against the grossly unjust state of affairs, where CEOs and popular entertainers ‘earn’ by noon on January 3rd what the average shop-floor worker gets for the whole year. But it soon degenerated, as did its offshoots elsewhere, into a mass orgy of narcissism and selfindulgence, where most participants had apparently forgotten the original object of the whole exercise. There is a time and place for carnivals, and a time and place for serious socio-political protest; but they are not the same. I cannot agree with the author’s apparent view, though this is never clearly expressed, that that this development was an improvement, characteristically ‘postmodern’ as no doubt it was. The quasi-lyrical language in which he describes such goings-on (cf. 31-5 and elsewhere) evidently impresses him himself more than it does his reviewer. It seems quite sensible for Christians to take ‘desire’ as a starting-point for assessment of the human condition. At least since Augustine, theologians have been inclined to the view that the main practical business of Christian living is to redirect desire from ‘concupiscence’ (love of self and indulgence of the senses) to charity (love of God and of one’s neighbour). It would be fruitful to follow this up; but the author does not do so. He makes surprising reference to Duns Scotus’s recondite but profound doctrine of that the concept of ‘being’ is univocal as between God and creatures; if it is admitted to be ‘equivocal’, as between ‘bow’ as a weapon for shooting arrows and a knot for securing a lady’s scarf, surely the reality of God is rendered deeply problematic. Aquinas’s ‘analogy of being’ between God and creatures struck Scotus as dangerously agnostic. Scotus’ doctrine of the univocity of being is here referred to in quite a different context, as exerting an influence on Deleuze. Postmodernists are wont to emphasize ‘difference’ and to extol it; ‘(i)f being is univocal, then what could the difference between beings be?’ Deleuze will have it, we are told, that ‘difference is a matter of degrees of power, or, rather, degrees of desire . . . Univocal being, desire, is 520 BOOK REVIEWS differentiated by degrees of intensity’ (43). This, so far as the reviewer can judge, is sheer sententious verbiage; and there is a lot more where that came from. There are so many urgent problems facing humanity, which the Church should take the lead in addressing. What restrictions on our habits of consumption, how much of a fall in our standard of living, must we accept if our grandchildren, and all subsequent generations (assuming there are any), are to inherit a habitable planet? The ‘capitalism’ identified and deplored by the author is, as Deleuze argues, the situation where ‘not only is the market central to everything, but everything is also subject to the rule of the market’ (23). So far as such a state of affairs obtains, it is certainly proper for Christians to denounce it. But the fact remains that, to survive and flourish in industrial or postindustrial society, we have to respect the laws of the market; and the question to be asked here is, how is a proper deference to them to be reconciled with elementary justice, not only between first and third worlds, but between groups and classes within both? How much should be expected of the State, and what should rather be demanded of the enterprise of individuals and small groups? (The book does point out, it is fair to say, that much desirable change is better brought about on a small scale, than by trying to exert influence over the State apparatus; but this is hardly news.) One might have expected the author and his authorities to shed light on questions like these, but they do not, and they have confirmed me in my conviction that the same applies to postmodernism in general. Modernism had coherent standards, which may have been deficient, of what counted as improvement of the human condition; postmodernism is essentially subversive of all such standards. I do not always see eye to eye with Sir Richard Dawkins; but his expression ‘fancophonyism’ would seem to be apt as applied to such material as this. Calgary, Canada Hugo Meynell Nozick’s Libertarian Project: An Elaboration and Defense. By Mark D. Friedman. Pp. x, 212, London/NY, Continuum, 2011, $120.00. Friedman sets out to provide a detailed, rigorous, up-to-date defence of Robert Nozick’s famous argument in favour of libertarianism as presented in his classic text Anarchy, State and Utopia (1974). He reconstructs what he takes to be the most plausible rendition of Nozick’s original position and presents it in the form of a deductive ‘proof,’ composed of five premises that lead to a conclusion that is intended to be robustly (not mathematically) persuasive. He moves on to defend Nozick’s general thesis from common objections and then teases out and extends the general implications of his theory on a wide range of issues. We might distinguish between two schools of libertarianism. On the one hand, there are the ‘consequentialist’ libertarians who argue that absolute protections of individual liberty will produce the greatest happiness or ‘preference-satisfaction’ for the greatest number. On the other hand, there are ‘deontological’ or ‘natural rights’ libertarians who argue that absolute protections of individual liberty have a moral basis in a Kantian conception of human beings as ends-in-themselves. Friedman champions the second alternative. Even if one could uncover empirical evidence that indicates that serious restrictions on liberty could somehow benefit the common good, these findings could not undermine a basic right to freedom of choice, which is based on a primary moral principle that derives from the deep nature of human beings. Friedman’s version of libertarianism translates into a moral interpretation of John Stuart Mill’s noharm principle. He explains: ‘the use of force or coercion against persons who are not violating or unreasonably threatening to violate others is wrong, full stop’ (p. 5). Autonomy, our freedom to choose for ourselves, is, on this account, of paramount importance. At one point, Friedman approvingly cites Shelly Kagan’s paraphrase of Nozick: ‘Interference with another’s autonomy is the form of harm that is most fundamental from the moral point of view’ (p. 129). A very strong claim, indeed! In the light of this primary moral injunction not to interfere with others, Friedman (unsurprisingly) defends F. A. Hayek’s lassez-faire economics, Nozick’s ‘entitlement theory’ of property (illustrated by his original Wilt Chamberlain example) and the hotly contested analogy libertarians draw between taxation and forced labour. He also argues for a minimal state, for negative (liberty) rights instead of positive (welfare) rights, for an understanding of private property based on a Lockean account of original acquisition, and so on. Readers who wish to ‘get inside’ the mind-set of contemporary liberalism will find this offering an informative read. At the same time, the book really does not amount to a defence of BOOK REVIEWS libertarianism. There are several problems. To begin with, Friedman’s informative and artful marshalling of arguments seems to beg the question. The author writes, ‘I am going to ignore the unfortunate fact that the best minds in academic philosophy have been unable to resolve in any convincing way our most basic ethical concerns, such as the objectivity/subjectivity of moral values, the existence of free will in a deterministic universe, the possibility of moral knowledge and related matters’ (p. 6). Friedman, rather too quickly, takes this as a licence to ignore any need for a more in-depth consideration of our most fundamental moral ideas. But the arguments that fill the book seem to hinge on libertarian moral intuitions. Arriving at libertarian principles by relying on libertarian intuitions ably illustrates where the position comes from but it does not provide an adequate defence against critics who will dispute, at the very least, libertarian interpretations of our moral intuitions. A second problem has to do with public assistance to innocent needy. Friedman does not shy away from the obvious moral conclusion that we should be able to force unwilling others, at the risk of some very small sacrifice, to help those ‘facing imminent death by starvation or from an easily curable disease’ (p. 143). But this does not easily square with the libertarian conviction that individual autonomy, freedom of choice, is the first value. The distinction he draws between per- 521 fect and imperfect duties in a Kantian sense (which is itself questionable) does not get to the root of the problem. Starving people or the fatally ill do not need negative (non-interference) rights but the urgent active intervention of other people. If anything, they need positive rights, the very existence of which, libertarians do their best to contest. A third problem involves externalities, inevitable negative effects on third-party bystanders to agreements. Friedman insists that we can use ‘Cost Benefit Analysis’ (CBA), ‘to quantify, in terms of monetary value, all costs and benefits associated with a particular decision or policy’ (p. 152). On this basis, we can determine the acceptability of imposed risks on the public (say from a neighbouring nuclear power plant or from the fluoridation of water). But this strategy seems to substitute a utilitarian calculus based on what we think agents ought to choose for a libertarian model based on what individual agents actually choose. Reconciling the libertarian emphasis on the priority of individual liberty with pressing demands about the welfare of the disadvantaged and the common good would requires a more in-depth consideration of moral first principles. St. Francis Xavier University Nova Scotia, Canada Louis Groarke Rawlsian Political Analysis: Rethinking the Microfoundations of Social Science. By Paul Clements. Pp. 248, Notre Dame, IN, University of Notre Dame Press, 2012, £26.93. In this interesting and very informative book, Clements aims to establish that both rational choice theory and neoclassical economics are incomplete as models of social and political analysis, and need to be incorporated into a broader Rawlsian paradigm. Clements understands the ‘Rawlsian paradigm’ to be a cluster of central ideas that go back to Kant’s notion of the uniqueness of human beings as rational agents – uniqueness that is determined by our ability to choose, and to make choice itself the object of further reflection and consideration. Rawls stands in this tradition, and gives it a boost by providing it with new methodological and analytical tools by reconceptualising Kant’s insight regarding the categorical imperative in terms of the veil of ignorance, thereby making it relevant and useful for social theory and political economy. Rawls also recasts the essential Kantian distinction between the hypothetical imperative and the categorical imperative in terms of the rational and the reasonable, thereby providing the grounds for clearly distinguishing the Kantian tradition from rational choice theory, but also demonstrating how the two traditions are linked. The point of agreement is the rational – cast as primary goods in Rawls; the reasonable is the point of difference, thus giving rise to the contentions between the two traditions. Clements adds a third element to this conceptual mix, by searching for the foundations of Kantian and Rawlsian insights into both the natural sciences and human evolution. Here, he finds two phenomena that give credence to the Kantian tradition and its claims. The first is that, although language is a natural phenomenon, it differentiates human beings from other animals; it also provides the arena for claims and counter claims, which have more than passing affinity with the reasonable. The second is that modern neurology also points towards – even though it does not decisively establish – an understanding of morality which is more in tune 522 BOOK REVIEWS with the Kantian tradition. For example, some investigations seem to suggest that our conception of right is grounded in neurons that are distinct from those that govern our sense of natural desires, and trigger different parts of the brain. The different locations of activity in the brain suggest a difference in nature between the two. Thus Clements’ Rawlsian paradigm emphasizes the sense of human agency; the ability to revise choices; feelings of sympathy and disgust; and our sense of right, not just the consequences of action. Rational choice theory and neoclassical economics, on the other hand, represent for Clements means-end rationality, where it is not the choices themselves, but only the best ways to realize them, which are in view. Rational choice theory does not have any conceptual repertoire to judge or to appraise choices or ends. What Clements aims for is a unified moral theory in which the insights of the Kantian and the Rawlsian traditions are combined, together with insights from rational choice theory. In other words, for Clements, pursuit of material goods – Rawls’ primary goods – and not simply their just distribution, has moral relevance. This should be combined with the Rawlsian and Kantian insights regarding human agency and our sense of right and justice. In a nutshell, interests and principles are an integral part of any moral theory, and any social analysis that does not invoke them in a unified manner falls short of the desired standards. In pursuit of this goal, Clements has written a wide-ranging book. One can find here not only useful summaries of the main approaches, but also very readable summaries of some important case studies by rational-choice theorists in political economy and related fields. Also, one can learn a great deal about the application of these theories to economic, political, and environmental issues. Moreover, the reader can gain an informative introduction to the famous Grameen bank; the history of its formation and its operations; the history of the conflict in one of the largest states in India, Bihar; the anti-colonial struggles in Kenya; the conflicting attitudes of French and English populations of Canada towards volunteering and the draft during the two world wars; and the current global environmental crisis. This is no small feat for a book of moderate length. Despite all those worthwhile elements of the book, there are some things I have some misgivings about. At the outset, Clements arbitrarily excludes sophisticated versions of classical utilitarianism, on the pretext that the model of choice in rational choice theory and the neoclassical economic model is much narrower than that in classical utilitarianism, and that it’s the latter which has currency in policy analysis in its established forms, and not classical utilitarianism. It seems to me that throughout the book, and especially at the crucial juncture in his argument, he treats rational choice theory as a straw man, and attributes things to it that more sophisticated rational choice practitioners would certainly deny. The second, and more important, point is that he does not present any unified theory, nor does he specify any mode of unification between Kantian Rawlsian theory and rational choice theory. Crucially, since he is developing an alternative paradigm for policy analysis, he should have – even if briefly – stated a general modus operandi for such unification. Furthermore, Clements does not seem to be very specific about the relation between interests and principles, and at times is very vague about the whole matter. On occasion, he says that the senses of right and the good are ‘somewhat’ independent of each other. He needs to be more specific about what this ‘somewhat’ exactly means – or amounts to – given his own standards of precision. He is clear that one function of principles is to exclude certain interests which are not compatible with certain principles. However, he also has a positive conception of principles, in which case principles lead directly to certain choices – without reference to interests – and this, he thinks, is foreign to rational choice theory. Nevertheless, Clements offers no specification of a procedure for how to discern the exact relation between – and the precise weight of – principles and interests. Given that he rejects certain welldeveloped rational choice models on the grounds that no ‘unified’ account of principles and interests is found in them, the lack of specification also speaks against his own model. The final point is quantification. Clements is rightly impressed by rational choice theory’s developed quantification methods and its ability to quantify policy imperatives. He thinks that he has developed a quantification method for his own Rawlsian model that should impress the skeptical crowd on the other side. As far as I can see, however, he has done no such thing, and perhaps, here, he has ignored his own insight. Policy analysis is an explanation of reality, as well as a construction of a new reality: the creation of new institutions, etc. The latter cannot be scientific; it is an art, and in trying to make this art into a science he makes the same mistake that he accuses rational choice theory of making. In fact, his criticism of the rational choice theorists who have developed social analysis by combining rational choice theory with historical narratives and principle-based approaches might have ignored his own point. It would seem that some rational BOOK REVIEWS choice methods might be better examples of what Clements preaches in his book. To finish, I must reiterate that, although I have used more space for criticism than for praise, I do not want to give the misleading impression that the book isn’t worthwhile; and I do think it is well 523 worth reading. It is a superb introduction to the ongoing debate between the Kantian/Rawlsian model and rational choice/neoclassical economics model, without being the final word on the issue. La Trobe University, Melbourne Ali Rizvi Freedom after the Critique of Foundations: Marx, Liberalism, Castoriadis and Agonistic Autonomy. By Alexandros Kioupkiolis. Pp. vi, 276, Basingstoke, Palgrave Macmillan, 2012, £60.00. This book recommends agonistic autonomy, according to Cornelius Castoriadis. Castoriadis was a left-leaning opponent of Stalinism and an influence on the May 1968 student protests. He opposed Sartre, who once claimed that C. had been right, but at the wrong time – Sartre, came the retort, had the honour of being wrong at the right time! As a first approximation to the central idea of the book we can recall Sartre’s existentialist account of freedom. There is no God and no luminous realm of values. To the young man in a quandary about whether to support his mother or fight for the resistance Sartre considers only to dismiss Christian, Kantian and romantic counsel: you are free, choose; that is to say, invent. Alexandros Kioupkiolis would certainly distance C. from the Sartrean ideal of the free floating chooser who fashions his life from scratch – the subject must pass through the agony of psychoanalytic soulsearching and engage in a care of the self. However, the atheistic denial of all objective values – save the value of freedom itself – makes the comparison with Sartre pertinent to any reader new to Castoriadis. In reality, there is never any time in which we are ever right or wrong. The original sin, then, is essentialism. The first two chapters (which despite the complexity of the theme are at times models of lucidity) detect the sin in Marx and Kant. For both thinkers liberty had been positive – it involves the idea that freedom is for something. Marxian essentialism sees freedom as the development of all potentialities and is traced to Aristotle. Kantian self-mastery by reason results in unchanging principles that are ultimately arbitrary. A third chapter argues for relativism: knowledge and practice are in trouble. Here, the reader may be in trouble, for on nearly every page value judgements and judgements that there actually is objective knowledge abound. For example, we are warned against the possibility of objective grounding in science but two chapters later the causal mechanisms of nature are recognised. So, in the introduction K. tackles the criticisms of another opponent of C., Habermas. Scepticism commits the fallacy of performative contradiction. The critique of objective and universal reason makes much of the plurality of standards and ways of reasoning, but it presupposes the general validity of its arguments and assumes that indefinite others will be able to see their logical force. K. has two responses. Firstly, he will concede just so much scope for universal reason so long as particular options are not specified. Thus, I think, it is clearly only a ‘strong’ essentialism he rejects. It’s clear, I think, that the third chapter must be seen as winnowing away the Marxian and Kantian chaff of the first two chapters. Secondly, the Habermasian response is found guilty of begging the question: it upholds universal reason against sceptics by postulating the existence of universal reason. Here, an admirer of Lonergan will be quick to note that K. gives himself an easy time of it. He never considers that we might find foundations in the normativity of our intelligence (we ask intelligent questions, seek to judge critically, pose the question for deliberation: is this truly worthwhile?) rather than in the products of our intelligence. Trying not to be stupid is hardly begging the question! We can arrive at foundations by explicating what is implicit in such performances. The assumption present in the title that the critique of foundations has met with success can be contested. The result, however, is this: K. gives himself permission to flout the censure of performative contradiction liberally. For example, the whole book argues that the truth that he presents is a truth that will set us free; that we are to question everything; that such questioning will emancipate us from narrow paths. But the truth (which the author will reason for, and so propose to our decision) is that freedom is not for truth – or for any good thing. And the broad path on offer is one that is open to all possibilities save only those that really matter, such as asking: what is really worthwhile, what is freedom for? Having rejected positive liberty, K. takes issue with Berlin and Mill. Negative liberty is doing what we please. The problem is that our desires may be preprogrammed by all sorts of unconscious motivations (seeds sown by our exploiters, perhaps) and what is needed is a struggle with our depths – the care of the self that will be our salvation. The fifth chapter draws on C. to explore agonistic subjectivity. We are to 524 BOOK REVIEWS plunge into the psyche with Freud, and K. cites The Essay on Freud to the effect that in such affective struggle previously unnoticed mental contents can become available to deliberation and choice. Psychoanalysis can free us from self-deception. Here, an admirer of Paul Ricoeur, the author of the essay, will be quick to note that besides the archaeology that discovers traces of the past in the present, the therapeutic situation also reveals a teleology that moves from the present to the future: accordingly, Ricoeur, in these dialectical sections in the third part of the essay upon which K. draws, did not conclude that God was dead. The nature of the acting subject – our essence, in the weak sense – is enlighteningly portrayed. Aware of the criticism that the subject is the plaything of unconscious forces a nuanced account of freedom is offered that steers a middle course between determinism and voluntarism. A section on initiating the new draws on intuitions from creative practice: it is unlikely that an algorithm could codify inspiration. We are a combination of passivity and activity. An admirer of St Thomas might be pleasantly surprised, for Thomas had held the will to be a mixture of nature and freedom. I am not quite certain, however, whether all issues are resolved. At times freedom is equated with sovereignty, but elsewhere such sovereignty is denied. I must pass over the sixth chapter which explains a key term of art, the social imaginary. The upshot is that agents need not be determined by structures. The seventh chapter continues illuminatingly with the theme at the heart of the book, the autonomy of the subject and the care of the self. By self-reflection we are to adopt a new attitude to the unconscious. We are to get in touch with the inner drives and rework them, for in the struggle for autonomy we must be liberated from being the plaything of heteronomous forces. I am not sure how K. holds this to be possible given his preference for a balanced position rather than voluntarism. Indefinite deliberation must come to an end, and so eventually we will be at the mercy of external forces. Of course, for Thomas, this limitation on our liberty is one of the ways in which operative grace is reconciled with freedom; under the influence of grace the will wills a new end, (voluntarily, but not strictly speaking, freely) and so freely chooses the means to the end (so that grace then becomes cooperative). Such an idea must be anathema, though, to K. To recognise the divine initiative must be to acquiesce to hegemony. Subsequent chapters grapple with the vexing question of whether the account of freedom so outlined is egotistical. The context of the book is always secular. The diktats of God are demeaned, but infinity is frequently valorised. In fact, K. often rails against idolatry. Now, for the Thomist, it is because we are free that we can criticise any finite good. Only an infinite good, a good that is incapable of being criticised from any point of view can draw the will infallibly. So, if the will is attached to a finite good as if it were divine, idolatry results. For the Thomist, then, K. appears to draw on valid intuitions. It is almost as if he adopts a Christian anthropology whilst denying the theology. In particular, it is as if he valorises the dark night of the soul in an agonistic care of the self, whilst denying any possibility of mystical union. As a result, of course, the reader is free to reject his proposal. Everywhere the bleakness of an atheistic horizon rules out possibilities. For example, despite 53 pages on liberty, and 41 pages on equality, there are precisely zero pages on fraternity. Again, the care of the self is centre stage, but nowhere, save in political struggle, is there any care of the other. There is no possibility that freedom might be the freedom to make a gift of oneself – and so love, joy, peace, compassion, hope, sacrifice and gratitude are never on the radar screen. Nevertheless, I have no choice but to be grateful to the author who has shed much light on his hero who, he tells us, changed the trajectory of his thought as a teenager during a hot, Greek summer when he happened upon The Imaginary Institution of Society. Kioupkiolis’ filial piety is another (very welcome) performative contradiction. Maryvale Institute Christopher Friel Redeeming History: Social Concern in Bernard Lonergan and Robert Doran. By Gerard Whelan, SJ. Pp. 253, Rome, Gregorian and Biblical Press, 2013, e27.00. The most exciting chapter of this book is the last one before the concluding chapter, chapter 11, in which the author applies the analysis presented in the earlier chapters to two real-life situations. In the first Whelan narrates how the Lonergan-Doran approach to theology animated his pastoral strategy while working as pastor in a parish in Kangemi, on the outskirts of Nairobi, Kenya. The complexities of pastoral engagement in such a situation required working on several levels, including the personal faith development of volunteer parish workers, and social analysis of the difficult and sometimes conflicted social and political environment. Where more simplistic conflict models had tended to exacerbate the problems, a considered approach guided by theory proved fruitful in various BOOK REVIEWS development strategies which were also ecumenically attractive to partners from other faith communities. Summarizing the approach in terms of the familiar ‘see, judge, act’ pioneered by Young Christian Workers in Belgium, Whelan outlines his inductive theological approach as he has learned it from Lonergan and Doran. So vibrant and rooted is the narrative in this section that I really wanted to know more. Perhaps Whelan will write more direct inductive theology in the future, but at least this application will be a headline for his students who may be encouraged to write their own stories of their attempts to do inductive theology. The second application which strikes a heart chord is the comment on the style of teaching adopted by Pope Francis. In particular the orientation to the evangelization of cultures and social structures is noted as potentially benefiting from Doran’s theory. The first eight chapters trace the steps of Bernard Lonergan’s intellectual biography. While drawing on important work done by other Lonergan scholars such as Fred Crowe and William Mathews Whelan contributes a new aspect by drawing attention to the persistence of social concern as a key motivator for Lonergan’s philosophy and theology. Observing the devastation caused by the 1929 crash and great depression of the 1930s Lonergan wanted his work in philosophy and theology to be relevant to analysis and solution of the great social problems of the day. This social concern persisted through his life, and Whelan points out the peaks along the way. The early essay on circulation analysis, the common sense chapters in Insight, and the return to economics and to the examination of progress and decline in history in the late essays signal this persisting concern which also animated Lonergan’s mainstream work in theology. The scope of Method in Theology is such that it is not only theology as a science which is under review as regards its methods, but also the other sciences of human affairs to the extent that they deal with meaning. In particular, Lonergan’s exploration of the importance of dialectic enables Robert Doran to develop and expand this theme, making it more useful for application to social and political situations. Chapters nine and ten are devoted to this topic, and Whelan maintains that Doran’s work notably in Theology and the Dialectics of History (Toronto, 1990) completes Lonergan’s project. Among Doran’s contributions is the addition of 525 psychic conversion to the levels of conversion already examined by Lonergan, namely, intellectual, moral and religious conversions. This idea came from Doran’s doctoral work on Jung and was developed in his book Psychic Conversion and Theological Foundations (1981). Whelan suggests that it was the absence of such a level of conversion in Lonergan’s own biography which explains why he was not able to deliver the full impact of his social concern. Without an effective option for the poor in his own life, coupled with illness in later life, the social concern which was a constant motivation in his life’s work did not fully deliver on its promise (246). Doran’s main contribution to the culmination of Lonergan’s method is the expansion of dialectic to explore its functioning at the various levels of both the subject, and history. Whelan documents the refinements offered by Doran in adding the distinction between contraries and contradictories. This enables a further distinction between healthy and unhealthy dialectics. The former as for instance where there is a tension between the unconscious psyche and the conscious spirit allows for possible healing and progress. Unhealthy dialectic is where contradictions are so entrenched that all resolution is blocked. Method is best exemplified in its application, in practice, and its usefulness is best demonstrated by results. Nevertheless, primers are needed for the instruction of neophytes who have to be trained in the mastery of methods, and this book adds to the literature available for that purpose. It does so in a significantly integrated way, from the focus on social concern, and presents the challenge to students and practitioners who wish to follow Pope Francis’s example of contextual theology. They are challenged not just to talk about ‘option for the poor’ but to engage in the subjective dialectic of confronting the resistances in themselves. Then they will be equipped to engage in the praxis in the pursuit of solutions which presupposes change and development – conversion – in the theologians. This very welcome study of social concern in the thought of Lonergan and Doran reaffirms the promise of fruits to be gained by the adoption of their approach. Those fruits are exemplified in the chapter on the application of Doran’s method. They too are a promise of valuable work in future from this author. Heythrop College Patrick Riordan 526 BOOK REVIEWS An Awareness of What is Missing: Faith and Reason in a Post-Secular Age. By J€urgen Habermas et al. Pp. 87, Polity Press, $14.95. In his recent writings Habermas has focused his attention on the role of religion in the public sphere, as is evident in his 2001 essay entitled ‘Faith and Knowledge’ in The Future of Human Nature, his debate with Cardinal Joseph Ratzinger in Munich in 2004, and most recently in a series of essays on the relationship between religion and the public sphere in Between Naturalism and Religion (Polity 2008). This collection consists of a series of essays initially presented at the Jesuit School of Philosophy in Munich in 2007 and represents an important contribution to ongoing reflections on religion in a post-secular context. This volume opens with a helpful introduction by M. Reder and J. Schmidt, S.J. that contextualizes Habermas’s approach to religion in relation to his own philosophical development and broader currents in modern philosophy and theology. Habermas’s primary contribution is a nine-page chapter entitled, ‘An Awareness of What is Missing,’ which rehearses his basic ideas about the role of religion in a post-secular context. This essay is followed by a series of critical engagements with Habermas’s reflections by four scholars from the Jesuit School of Philosophy in Munich (N. Brieskorn, M. Reder, F. Ricken, and J. Schmidt) and concludes with a 12-page epilogue in which Habermas responds to his critics. The four essays by the scholars from the Jesuit School of Philosophy in Munich raise critical questions about the significance of religion for secular reason (Brieskorn), the role of translation in Habermas’s philosophy of religion (Ricken), and the difficulty of negotiating the proper relationship between faith and reason (Reden and Schmidt). In his opening essay Habermas argues that the relationship between reason and religion needs to be reconceived in view of the rise of religious fundamentalism, the postmodern intensification of the dialectic of Enlightenment, and the hegemony of capitalist principles of exchange in a globalized world. Habermas suggests that it is necessary to rethink the genealogy of postmetaphysical reason and to draw from religious resources in order to respond to these challenges. For Habermas, the explicit contribution of religion to secular reason is that it cultivates ‘an awareness of what is missing.’ As Reder, Schmidt, and Brieskorn suggest the genealogy of this phrase can be traced to various thinkers in the Frankfurt School (Bloch, Adorno, and Brecht), but Habermas himself points to Johann Baptist Metz’s Memoria Passionis (2006) as the source for his own use of the phrase. Habermas argues that secular reason is deficient because of its diminished capacity to cultivate a sense of what is missing and to engender resistance to the violations of basic human rights in the contemporary world. Religion constitutes a resource that possesses the capacity to counteract this deficit by articulating a vision of the moral whole (the kingdom of God) that serves to sensitize individuals to the experience of loss, failure, and catastrophe in history. In this sense, Habermas views religion as an important moral supplement to secular reason. But the critical question in a context of cultural and religious pluralism is the most effective means for bringing the moral resources of religion into the public realm. In Awareness of What is Missing Habermas gives broad guidelines for the interaction between secular reason and religion among believers and nonbelievers. Habermas argues that secular persons must recognize that religion possesses a cognitive content that cannot be dismissed as irrational. Religious persons also must accept the legitimacy of scientific reason and the egalitarian principles of modern law and morality. Furthermore, it is necessary for both religious and secular persons to engage in the work of translation in order to redescribe the semantic content of religion in a rational language accessible to non-believers. Habermas’s proposal, therefore, involves a critical rejection of strands of modern secularism as well as a call for believers and theologians to engage in constructive dialogue with postmetaphysical thinking. It is in relation to this dialogue between theology and postmetaphysical thinking that Habermas offers a series of sharp criticisms of Benedict XVI’s Regensburg Address. While the exchange between Habermas and Benedict XVI (then Joseph Cardinal Ratzinger) in Munich in 2004 was largely conciliatory, in An Awareness of What is Missing Habermas takes issue with Benedict XVI’s ‘unexpectedly critical’ analysis of modernity in the Regensburg Address in 2006. Against what he interprets to be Benedict XVI’s totalizing criticism of modernity as a period of decline that shattered the medieval synthesis between faith and reason, Habermas defends the emergence of modern reason as creating the conditions for the possibility of both the natural sciences and the modern understanding of law and democracy. Independent of whether one thinks that Habermas or Benedict XVI has the better side of the argument, in these essays Habermas voices serious reservations about the suitability of Benedict XVI’s theological approach to the task BOOK REVIEWS of post-secular dialogue between believers and non-believers. By way of contrast, Habermas’s affirmative statements about the prioritization of praxis and responsibility over belief and metaphysics in Metz’s political theology point to the style of theology that Habermas views as most adequate to the task of post-secular dialogue. Overall, this volume offers not only a succinct, readable presentation of Habermas’s reflections on the role of religion in post-secular society, but also 527 contains a series of important analyses of the relationship between Habermas’s postmetaphysical philosophy and contemporary theology. As such, it represents essential reading for those interested in the ongoing debate about the proper relationship between religion and politics in this increasingly post-secular moment. College of the Holy Cross, USA Matthew Eggemeier Making Sense of the Secular: Critical Perspectives from Europe to Asia. Edited by Ranjan Ghosh. Pp. viii, 226, New York: Routledge, 2013, $140.00. This edited collection by Ranjan Ghosh removes the secular/sacred straight jacket imposed by much Western thinking through expanding the discussion beyond North America and Western Europe. What this entails is the softening of any definitive, agreed-upon understanding of the secular as it manifests itself differently in the often overlooked locales included here; namely: Pakistan, Sri Lanka, Malaysia, South Korea, Japan and Indonesia; in addition to essays on India, China, Turkey, Belgium, Italy, France, the United Kingdom, and more broadly, Eastern Europe. It is a refreshing and needed salve to a discussion that is often disapprovingly myopic and Eurocentric or one that merely gestures at Asia (perhaps with a nod to Turkey and India). If any critique could be levelled at the book’s clear structure and aims, it may be why the work was not also expanded to Africa as well, but constraints and other issues may have prevented such a move. Regardless, works on the secular and sacred need to become ever more globalized and far reaching to begin to do those terms justice if seeking to move through and beyond the provincial and local. Ghosh’s edited collection is important in this regard, especially as the majority of the essays are lively and lucid, with one main disappointment noted below. The work is also deeply interdisciplinary with contributors based in fields like international relations, history, political science, sociology, human geography, anthropology, Islamic studies, and women, gender, and sexuality studies. Ghosh teaches English in the University of North Bengal. Strikingly, Ghosh’s introductory essay begins with a quote from Raimundo Panikkar that sets the tone, flexibility, and balance of the work: ‘Only worship can prevent secularization from becoming inhuman, and only secularization can save worship from being meaningless’ (1). Thus, readers can anticipate a collection of essays that will seek to overcome the socalled secular/sacred divide to contend how those spheres interlap and interpenetrate while remaining distinctive at certain levels. Ghosh’s introductory essay is a stand-alone text seeking to define what he means by making sense of the secular: and in his conception the secular is deeply formed by India’s pluralist culture in which famous historical iterations of the secular were expounded by religious believers (the Buddhist Ashoka, the Muslim Akbar, and the Hindu Gandhi). The essay is replete with provocative phrases: ‘So religion has to move forward without religion’ (7) and interesting arguments revolving around a new ‘secular’ city (new because it will be rich in religious possibilities and realities). Ghosh also manages to cram in nearly every cultural studies catch-phrase or thinker coupled by clunky words (superintendency, equilateralty, traducement) that can throttle his otherwise absorbing, dialectical positions. Nevertheless, the essay rightly manages to make less sense of the secular while trying to do otherwise: and so greatly succeeds in articulating how the secular depends upon the sacred as much as the sacred depends upon the secular, especially as each comes to see the other in themselves. It goes without saying that Ghosh’s sketched ideas need a wider palette for him to try to bring them to more cohesive life. As noted above, the varied case studies are all recommended, with the exception of Shaoming Zhao’s “When Will China Become More Religious?” At first glance, the title seems both perplexing and evocative as the resurgence of religion in China has become a stated commonplace. Zhao presents a case study evaluating the attitudes of villagers in Shagou in Eastern China as they assess the practice of funeral rituals. The essay is too apologetic towards China or overly subtle in any possible critique. Comments like: ‘The villagers said that, in Shagou’s history, only the Communist Party has taken on all the villager’s affairs as its official responsibility, and whatever the party says or does, it is always to support local interests’ (159) speak for itself. Zhao also refers to cremation never 528 BOOK REVIEWS being forced on the Chinese people though claiming that attitudes changed in 1949 but ‘not necessarily a direct result of the Communist Party’s policy on funeral reforms’ (164). In addition to the writings of Harry Wu, I cannot recommend enough the recent collections of Liao Yiwu. See especially his interview with the mortician in The Corpse Walker: Real-Life Stories, China from the Bottom Up and the real reason why cremation was urged, as State-orchestrated policies led to famines with devastating effects. These omissions are grave matters (genocidal claims should never be minimized or whitewashed; thus historical context should have been added to the villagers’ remarks). Of course, examination of the secular in China is a particularly heated matter that deserves deeper and wider engagement, and this essay is one type of approach, though hopefully far from representative. Mater Dei Institute, Dublin City University Peter Admirand Beyond Church and State: Democracy, Secularism, and Conversion. By Matthew Scherer. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, $90.00. When much of one’s argument rests on a neologism or an extended metaphor—here the notion of conversion as ‘crystalline’ (32)—a lack of immediate precision in the phrase and gaps remaining after subsequent explanation threaten to shatter the viability of the entire project. Borrowing the application in part from Henri Bergson, Matthew Scherer, in his Beyond Church and State, writes: ‘A crystal produces difference (strata) within a homogenous substance (sodium chloride, or table salt, for example), within an ongoing process of (trans)formation’ (105). One can also add that crystals are (basically) all individually unique, like zebra stripes and finger prints, and so the metaphor may have limits if trying to extrapolate wider points and applications, though it might be useful in an argument advocating pluralism and multireligious belonging. While there are some interesting moments of political acumen in Beyond Church and State, it is surprising that so much time and space was devoted to proving the tenability of a seemingly uncontroversial notion and applying the (at times, forced) above metaphor. Do substantial numbers of people maintain that conversion is always a onceoff event for everyone, in all contexts? Thus, if one converts from Christianity to Judaism, is it always true that no vestiges of that original faith remain or are built upon or transformed (but still present) in one’s new faith? Moreover, in the secularizing of society, is it always a zero sum game so that the rise in one area leads to the diminishing of another? Recalling some of Charles Taylor’s argument in A Secular Age, one can concede that many theorists, particularly sociologists of religion like Steve Bruce, have painted such an extreme picture. We are also all well informed of the various ‘deaths’—and ‘rebirths’—of religion. In this regard, the notion of conversion as multilayered and multifaceted like a crystal could be useful. It points to the tenacity of earlier notions and their ongoing viability in a process that overlaps, builds upon, and transforms the other. To develop this metaphor, Scherer first turns to Augustine’s Confessions as a classic narrative of conversion but emphasizes that ‘there is no conversion experience without a conversion narrative’ (61), thus highlighting the space between experience and writing and the possibilities of refashioning and reformulating. As the Confessions ‘suggests that the new man retains the old, and that the old man is constituted in part through striving towards the new’ (68), Scherer argues that it is relevant to challenge those who advocate any abrupt separation from some supposedly unreflective and na€ıve religious past to our contemporary, secular (and so unreligious) culture (a notion he surprisingly links with Charles Taylor, 68). More surprisingly, however, the chapter only references one text of Augustine (a fitting one in the Confessions) but no reference or citation to A City of God or The Retractions, among other seminal texts. In this regard, one is struck by the limited theological analysis and references in the book, although conversion is so central in the text (168). The next major thinker Scherer examines is John Locke, turning to Locke’s Letter Concerning Toleration. Scherer aims to highlight this process of crystalline conversion through examining how Locke negotiated the overlapping boundaries of religion and the secular to show that there is no definitive separation. In this chapter Scherer also rightly adds: ‘negotiating the parameters of secularism today demands, it would seem, a renewed engagement with ethical, theological, pragmatic, and political investments placed within the concept of separation’. This may be the most important line in the entire work (especially coming from a Professor of Government and Politics) but such interdisciplinary engagement with theology and ethics needed BOOK REVIEWS to be more on display in the work. To ignore the relevant fact that John Locke was a slave holder and international slave trader when discussing Locke and ethics—see Tink Tinker’s essay on ‘Locke and Property’ in Beyond the Pale: Reading Ethics from the Margins—is the kind of omission that unfortunately undermines such good intentions. Thus, one is instead reminded that Locke as a Christian and Locke as a political theorist could each have no qualm with justifying slavery, and so while the boundary of the religions and secular may have been malleable and the process of adjudicating that boundary crystalline, the ethical was silenced and absent in both. While biography is absent in the examination of Locke, it is at the forefront of Scherer’s interesting examination of John Rawls as he weaves relevant biographical details to examine a contemporary figure, who while immersed in the secular, in some circles (apparently) inspires religious feeling of sainthood and ‘faith in Rawlsian secularism’ (134). Scherer even refers to the ‘miraculous appearance of [Rawls’] work’ (136) —another example of try- 529 ing to show the overlap and borrowings of the secular and sacred—but here again, which seem more like co-opting when little sustained analysis is made of those terms’ theological and religious foundations. Chapters on Henri Bergson and Stanley Cavell obfuscate more than illuminate and threaten the cohesion of the book on the whole. Thinkers like Jeffrey Stout, David Hollenbach, or even Gustavo Gutierrez or Irving Greenberg would have been more useful. Despite an interesting title and a worthy thesis—that ‘secularism is not a matter of separating “church & state” but rather of transforming the interrelated fields of religion and politics, and it suggests that this transformation should be understood as a process of conversion’ (219, italics in original); the end result in this work evinces the need for a deeper and more theological analysis of conversion to render Scherer’s aims more crystalline. Mater Dei Institute, Dublin City University Peter Admirand Shaping Public Theology: Selections from the Writings of Max L. Stackhouse. Edited by Scott R. Paeth, E. Harold Breitenberg Jr., and Hak Joon Lee. Pp. xxxiii, 358, Grand Rapids, Eerdmans, 2014, $40.00. This volume offers a good introduction to Stackhouse’s corpus since it includes his shorter, more succinct essays that exhibit his influence in the field of Public Theology. The work shows that Stackhouse’s career can be characterized as a comprehensive Public Theology project since he always sought to bring his Christian moral insight, informed by its faith, teaching and practice, to bear on questions of the public good in its various facets (xv-xviii). The volume contains three sections of Stackhouse’s writings, one essay evaluating his significance by the editors, and a concluding response by Stackhouse himself. The first section presents six essays that discuss the place of Public Theology in the larger Christian theological tradition. The essays cover a number of topics including a general overview of Public Theology (3-20), the life and work of Walter Rauschenbusch (21-27), the impact of Martin Luther King Jr. (28-46), the influence of Paul Tillich (47-53), Ernst Troeltsch (71-77), and Jonathan Edwards (78-81), an overview and evaluation of Alasdair MacIntyre (5470), and a critique of Stanley Hauerwas (82-92). One highlight from this section is when he relates the social gospel to contemporary issues, namely, debates over the “death of God,” “contextualist” verses “principlist” theology, and the “Christ and culture” debate (cf. 5-11). Furthermore, his discus- sion of Rauschenbusch is helpful in identifying the similarities and differences Stackhouse sees between public theology in the US and liberation theology in Latin America (cf. 25-27). The second part of the volume presents eight of Stackhouse’s essays that discuss the methodology of Public Theology. The topics addressed by Stackhouse include an introduction to Christian social ethics (93-103), the ability of Christian theology to save the arts from subjectivism (104-115), the distinction and connection between Public Theology and Christian theology as a whole (116-132), the role of deontology, teleology, and ethology in Christian ethics (133-153), the foundation of morality in universal principles but not in natural law (154-167), the necessity to “de-provincialize [the social gospel] from its Americanist roots” (168-185), the differences between Civil Religion, Political Theology and Public Theology (186-203), and finally, the what God’s Covenant with humanity means for justice in a global society (204-220). The first and last essays in this sections best illuminate Stackhouse’s thought since they summarize his two favorite themes, the primacy of social ethics for the Christian life (cf. 94-95) and the importance of a religious and ethical analysis of globalization (cf. 215-218). The third and final section of essays more fully develop the role of Public Theology by addressing particular aspects or challenges of 530 BOOK REVIEWS globalization. The seven essays examine topics such as Public Theology in a post-Communist world (221-229), the ethical foundation of a global economy (230-242), the role of Christian churches in promoting moral corporate management (243258), the challenge of theological education in a global setting (259-270), a Christian perspective on human rights (271-282), a reflection on the family and the issue of divorce (283-285), and finally, the role of Christian pastors as public theologians (286304). The work ends with the editors encouraging Stackhouse’s work as a model for future scholars interested in Public Theology (305-316) and a reflection by Stackhouse himself, in which he discusses his intellectual journey and the areas of his thought that need further development (317-320). Disciples of Stackhouse, Christians with a heart for social justice, and those concerned about the effects of globalization will surely find this volume a valuable resource. It is an effective introduction to his work and succeeds in showing the exigency of addressing the new challenges of an intercon- nected, global world. However, those from a more confessional tradition, and especially those of a Catholic background, may find certain elements of Stackhouse’s thought uncomfortable. For example, while all Christians likely consider social justice a crucial component of Christianity, many would not make it the supreme judge over speculative and religious truth, something which Stackhouse seems to imply (cf.xx-xxi). In addition, while Stackhouse rightly seeks a common ground for evaluating different religions and nobly seeks to articulate a moral foundation for a modern, pluralist society, one wonders whether he has adequately understood the thought of MacIntyre and the Catholic distinction between nature and grace. Despite this potential misunderstanding, the work is worthy of a large audience since it raises critical questions that all responsible Christians, regardless of their background, should address. Ave Maria University Luke Murray Being in the World: Dialogue and Cosmopolis. By Fred Dallmayr, Pp. xiv, 272, University Press of Kentucky, 2013, $50.00. Any work with ‘Cosmopolis’ in its title has to endeavour to be interdisciplinary; wide-ranging in themes, topics, and thinkers; global; and characterised by openness, expansiveness, and tolerance. Fortunately, such a book is in the very capable hands of Fred Dallmayr, who by turns engaging, erudite, searching, and optimistic, takes the reader across topics ranging from the link of the humanities and democracy; ethics and international politics; the Arab Spring; and the possibility of Cosmopolitan Confucianism; to the words and thoughts of thinkers like Aristotle, John Dewey, Gandhi, Hannah Arendt, Habermas, Bhikhu Parekh, Charles Taylor, Abdolkarim Soroush, and Nasr Abu Zayd. The collection of mostly previously published essays is the fruit of decades of scholarly, cross-cultural, interdisciplinary and interreligious work. It is within a word of the main title – ‘Being’ and its Heideggerian foundation with little or no critique of the ethical flaws (some might add ‘fatal’) of that philosopher – which somewhat jars. But more of that further below. Being in the World is a deeply personal, passionate book (‘written from anguish’, xii) and one can see the care and thought given in arranging, updating, and presenting the material, so that though diverse, still manages to coalesce, outlining a ‘quest for a good and just life in our contemporary world’ (xii). While eclecticism can be disparaged in some circles, it is essential for any work in ‘Search of Cosmos’, as Dallmayr subtitles one chapter. As an aside, every scholarly work, no matter its claim for objectivity and neutrality, and even if clothed in cold, direct, unadorned (perhaps mechanic) prose, is still, ultimately, eclectic (even in what is not chosen or undertaken); but works consciously so succeed all the better. In a work aiming to cultivate public ethics and civic responsibility through intercultural, interfaith, and interdisciplinary study and dialogue, one responds ‘Amen’, but needs to pause at the prominence of Heidegger in the opening chapters. Biographical contexts are essential whenever raising a person or one of his or her ethical themes of concerns as a universal foundation or building block. That Locke was invested in slavery (and so influenced his treaty on land ownership;) that Rousseau could write words of wisdom on educating children but abandon his own; that Plato could inspire many with his notion of the Good and Beautiful while advocating a type of totalitarian State none of us would want to live in; cannot be ignored or downplayed by philosophers. For every reference of Heidegger and ethics, there should be an echo and reminder of his Nazi past. A book like Hitler’s Philosophers hopefully paves the way for deeper philosophical discussions of the portraits of the thinkers presented in that work. That Dallmayr BOOK REVIEWS included little to no critique of Heidegger’s hypocrisy (or mentioning of Carl Schmitt’s Nazi links) is surprising. In short, there is something jarring about reading the merits of Gandhi and Heidegger without clear moral distinction. So, too is Dallmayr’s overly deferential view of China in a talk given at the ‘Nishan Forum on World Civilizations’ where he even remarks that China ‘has historically not been drawn to political or military imperialism’ (206), which even if technically true, must be countered with acknowledgement of its concentration camp system (the laogai); its heavy-handed tactics in Tibet; its role in the Vietnam war; and the atrocities orchestrated by Mao Tse-tung and his successors. Nevertheless, the work succeeds in spite of these faults. Highlights include Dallmayr’s fair critique of Charles Taylor’s A Secular Age (especially in his tendency to imply a ‘one-dimensional’ division (124) between immanence and transcendence and the secular and the religious, without probing further on how their interrelatedness can lead ‘to profound transformations on both (or all) sides’ (124). To sharpen these ideas, he turns to the ‘cosmotheandric conceptions’ of Raimon Panikkar (126) who spent his life showing us the links and bridges between various religious systems and the oneness and symbiosis of the cosmos. Like any good thinker, Dallmayr hones in on key quotes of the thinkers he studies, and the ones presenting 531 Panikkar are wonderfully chosen: ‘Only worship can prevent secularization from becoming inhuman, and only secularization can save worship from being meaningless’ (126) This quote, along with Panikkar’s idea of the ‘sacred quality of secularism’ (126) should be epigraphs above any studies examining the secular and the sacred. Dallmayr’s promotion of the humanities as indispensable to democracy and civic responsibility is one all-too often forgotten during times of budget crisis and cuts when subjects like music, poetry, or philosophy (and especially religious studies or theology) seem only a financial drain and of little practical value. The opposite, of course, is the case. His essay on Gandhian self-rule (swarj) is a jewel of interdisciplinary and intercultural engagement and dialogue, bringing together key concepts of Gandhi and applying them to recent political philosophy. In this regard he turns to Arendt, Taylor, and Dewey and quite rightly joins together the need to cultivate self-rule with a ‘practice of self-restraint and self-transformation capable of instilling the habit of nonviolence (amimsa) and generous openness towards others’ (161). Dallmayr’s book may have been written in anguish, but it fosters hope and inspires interconnectedness and possibility. Mater Dei Institute, Dublin City University Peter Admirand The Kingdom and the Glory: For a Theological Genealogy of Economy and Government. By Giorgio Agamben; Trans. L. Chiesa with M. Mandarini. Pp. 303, Palo Alto, Stanford University Press, 2012, $24.95. This is the translation of Agamben’ s 2007 book, Il Regno e la Gloria, continuing the genealogy of power in the West that Agamben began with Homo Sacer: Sovereign Power and Bare Life. The text is divided into eight chapters, plus an appendix. Each chapter concludes with a section marked “Threshold” that summarizes the findings, reflects upon them and prepares for the next chapter. The chapters themselves are written in numbered sections (e.g., 1.1, 1.2 and so on). Typically these sections are followed by subsections, printed in italics, which expand on a point made in the preceding numbered section or follow up on clues, and the like. The book has no index. Agamben begins with Carl Schmidt’s claim all political concepts are derived from theological ones, such that one must discover the theological predecessors to modern political concepts if they are to be correctly understood. Building of this dictum, Agamben claims that management of persons is central to modern politics, and that this is in fact derived from the early Christian interpretation of the Holy Trinity in terms of oikonomia. Agamben’s discussion ranges over the history of Trinitarian theology, the liturgy, philosophy and politics from the patristic period to the present. This profusion of texts orbits around the work of Erik Peterson and Carl Schmidt. The narrative is interesting, and makes some interesting observations, but is fundamentally unsatisfying: despite the numerous texts he cites, he leaves out a number of key texts, events and figures. I will give seven examples. First, his discussion of gloria inexplicably pays little heed to Cicero’s discussion in de Officiis; but this was one of the most widely circulated philosophical texts in the middle ages and decisively entered into Christian theology when St. Ambrose imitated it in his book of the same name. Second, major discussions of the Trinity, i.e., Augustine’s de Trinitate, the school of St. Victor, or the relevant passages of Peter Lombard’s Sentences, are unaddressed or alluded to only in passing. Third, he dodges the entire Filioque controversy, writing – in move that can only be described as 532 BOOK REVIEWS baffling – that the debate about the procession of the Holy Spirit is essential for his argument, but will not be treated in the book (p. 44). Fourth, important medieval discussions of the relationship between theology and government, e.g., John of Salisbury’s Policraticus or Marsilius of Padua’s Defensor Pacis, are not treated at all. Fifth, one finds no sustained discussion of the major continental reformers, Luther, Calvin, and Zwingli. Since the reformation provoked a radical rethinking of politics, theology and liturgy in the reformed churches and less radical, but still important revisions, in the Catholic Church, Agamben’s argument requires that it be addressed. Sixth, Agamben completely ignores the Anglican tradition although the Anglican liturgy, the Caroline divines, and the role of the sovereign in the Anglican Church are all relevant to his argument. The fifth and sixth are particular problematic since there are good reasons for supposing that the reformed and Anglican churches are more influential in modern Western politics than medieval and baroque Catholicism. Seventh and finally, Agamben shows no interest in recent historical research that is challenging early and mid-20th liturgical scholarship – witness the fate of the Anaphora of Hippolytus – choosing to rely mainly on Peterson and Schmitt’s work from the 1920’s or Kantorowicz’ 1946 work, Regina Laudes. While these were groundbreaking works, the scholarly consensus regarding the history of the liturgy has undergone important modifications in the nearly 100 years since Schmidt and Peterson’s work was published. When reading Agamben it is hard to notice these lacunae because of the vivacious prose and interesting observations found in what he does discuss – readers without some training in patristic or medieval philosophy and theology might overlook the gaps entirely. Of course, Agamben can always excuse these lacunae by arguing that he is not writing a history, but a genealogy focusing on the unthought-of ‘signature’ of events. Those willing to accept this excuse will find this book useful insofar as it expands considerably on the narrative offered in previous volumes, but those who do not accept the excuse will be unmoved and wonder about the value of that narrative. Heidegger is reported to have once joked that his Kantbuch was ‘bad Kant, but excellent Heidegger’ and the same might be said of The Kingdom and the Glory, it is bad history, but excellent Agamben. Texas Woman’s University Brian Harding Seeing the World and Knowing God: Hebrew Wisdom and Christian Doctrine in a Late-Modern Context. By Paul S. Fiddes. Pp. vii, 423, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2013, $34.85. How is wisdom to be sought in this late modern world in which we live? Would it even be something that people would want in their lives? Would it be only the religious who would seek after it? Or would it be applicable to all of humanity? Though there is much to suggest in response to such questions, and though the incompleteness of our answers might often stun us into silence, it is the explicit task of Paul Fiddes in his new book to tackle such questions. I believe, moreover, that his response, to be fair, presents us with a balanced theological viewpoint from which to incorporate the most ancient of wisdom into the contemporary world in which we live. To begin with, part one involves ‘setting the scene’ of the late modern world and introducing Fiddes’ general response to the above questions, mainly, that, indeed, a society increasingly disappointed by a ‘thinking subject’ centered understanding of the self has great need of biblical wisdom, and that we should pay attention to what it has to say to us. Fiddes presents us with the reality that the selves that we actually are are in fact ones ‘always exceeding [the] faculties’ of reason and knowledge (p. 4). He therefore calls for a ‘relational’ approach to knowledge, or what he has also termed in his work a ‘connectional’ theology. In his words, ‘The relation between self and world is at the heart of wisdom, and this makes it, I suggest, an appropriate conversation-partner with thinkers of our late-modern period’ (p. 15). His will be then a ‘practical wisdom’ that draws deeply off the Hebrew tradition of wisdom writings, and that which he brings to bear on the discussion with great erudition and relevance, pointing us toward both a relationship to ‘nature’ and the fullness of the human being which are often lacking in modern constructions of the self. With every inch of this great book, Fiddes is trying to develop a ‘wisdom theology’ for the modern age in which we live, one that emphasizes how humanity, by nature, ‘reaches out towards mystery’ (p. 25). He considers a variety of self-world relations (e.g. world-object as detached from, expressing or as threat to subject) before rehearsing a number of standard readings of the subject-object relationship via Kant, Hegel, Sartre, Lyotard and Derrida, to name only a few who participate in this BOOK REVIEWS welcomed ‘conversation of many voices’ (p. 59) that characterizes our late modern era. In short, and as it will only expand from this point on into the entire volume, wisdom, like late modern thought, is concerned with alterity, a sublime disturbance of our selves and difference—all words more than appropriate when contemplating our situatedness before that which will remain forever mysterious to us. The chapter that follows immediately takes up challenges presented in the form of the ‘death of the self’ in much of contemporary continental thought, this time including Deleuze and Lacan, though still keeping Derrida’s observations within sight. It also involves extended discussion of Levinas and Ricoeur on the book of Job and how such readings seek to dispel any ‘pretensions of the self to master or dominate the world and others’ (pp. 82-3). He lauds Ricoeur’s efforts to find dialogue between the self and the divine Other as that which moves us beyond Levinas’ deadlock between them. As he will suggest the incorporation of Ricoeur’s work involves for theological thought, ‘I aim to show that participation in the divine Other, which is inseparable from responsibility for human others, occurs when the self is mediated through the Christian symbol of the Trinity, and through the personal reality it expresses’ (p. 83). Part two attempts to describe wisdom as both ‘observation’ and as ‘participation’, though the stress is upon making the movement from the former to the latter—a suggestion which will ultimately be the subtitle of the final chapter. To underscore this, he follows Hannah Arendt in discussing the forms of alienation that modern humanity feels as it tries to ‘control and dominate the earth’ (p. 96). Wisdom literature, he feels, can alternatively demonstrate what both Arendt and Heidegger saw as the antidote to such forms of alienation, a potent mixture of ‘self-revealing’ and ‘self-concealing’, and what Fiddes considers as states of being both ‘open’ and ‘inexhaustible’ (p. 98). The overall response given by Fiddes to the situation consists then in multiple, detailed readings of specific passages from wisdom literature that illuminate an alternative option for humanity—that is, by meeting very human needs that transcend any particular context and speak directly to our late modern era. There is, in his words, a certain ‘boundlessness’ within human existence wherein the transcendence of God is entirely ‘at home’ (p. 110), one where we might likewise at times see a divine telos at work beyond our conventional ability to recognize it. To stress this point, he addresses the classic division in wisdom writings between the ‘righteous’ and the ‘wicked’, and in such a way as to illustrate a definitive telos in the world that signals beyond Arendt’s form of political action (a la Iris Murdoch’s notion of the ‘Good’), but 533 which also steers clear of simply reinvesting humanity with its own ‘domineering human subjectivity over against the world’ (p. 129). The next chapter tries to conceive of the scientific context of complexity in which we live, urging his readers to see the fundamental connection between the conclusions of wisdom literature and our elusive conditions, uncertainty, indeterminism, holistic interactions and yet the possibilities of complexity that take center stage in our world today. To make such a connection more palpable, Fiddes draws our attention to Derrida and the complexity of signs—diff erance and undecidability, to name a couple choice terms of his—as these offer us a chance to hear the deep resonance between postmodern thought, wisdom literature and even Trinitarian thought, which he begins to take up in this chapter and which will be present to each section until the end. His use of the Trinity is fitting, however, and certainly in keeping with his thesis ‘[. . .] that the most adequate, or least inadequate, symbol for God is that of personal relations’ (p. 159). The following chapter continues to pursue Derrida (and Levinas as well) in assessing the limitations and potential of sight, or seeing, here brought into alignment with both divine and human wisdom as a form of observation, as Fiddes puts it. This chapter, as with those that comprise the whole section, explores a wide range of examples all demonstrating that ‘[. . .] Yahweh’s powers of observation expose the limited vision of humanity’ (p. 183). Accordingly, he suggests that they share in the same capacity for vision, differing only (though radically) in the degree to which they are able to observe. Fiddes offers us here, as beforehand, a refashioned form of natural theology through a shared wisdom that eschews distinctions such as those between immanence and transcendence, favoring rather the ‘emanation’ of God’s spirit throughout the world. Hence, by suggesting such a connection, Fiddes is trying to demonstrate how, through the eyes of wisdom writings, ‘seeing the world is knowing God’ (p. 188), a conclusion driven home by the ample readings of ‘Lady Wisdom’ that he takes up in a number of texts. Beyond this, he also demonstrates the diversity and creativity of wisdom, which leads him to conceive that ‘[. . .] the one who observes all in the world is the same one who offers communion and everlasting friendship. This surely symbolizes a discovery made by the wise, that there is something participatory about wisdom’ (p. 203). It is also the deep font from which so much mystical theology has drawn throughout the centuries, I would add. The reader is perhaps not surprised at this point, then, when such considerations push him to go beyond 534 BOOK REVIEWS Aquinas’ rather static view of the divine and into a participatory account that draws deeply from Hebrew wisdom and Christian Trinitarian sources, which he also takes up here in more specific detail than I can here summarize. The final chapter of section two unveils in a rich tenor the human quests for both presence and place that contemporary philosophers, here represented by Heidegger, Levinas Derrida and Kristeva, challenge us to rethink anew, as they gesture toward the place of ‘no place’, or khora, that symbolizes this barren, primordial and seemingly inaccessible space. It takes Fiddes’ reading of wisdom texts such as Job and Ben Sira to bring the accessible God back into the picture and to stress his suggestive conclusion that ‘[. . .] there is no single place where wisdom is located and no path that can be followed to find it. Wisdom can only be found in exercising it’ (pp. 233-4). It is the sheer vastness of wisdom that makes it seem hidden to us—hidden, but not absent. It is, as such, a maze of complexity that we can yet access at certain points where it is open to everyone. Once again, and in a way that will actually serve to unite the various essays that make up the second half of the book, Fiddes will utilize the triune God as a model for comprehending how we can dwell within this ‘place of no place’ that is wisdom, or, in his words, ‘The least inadequate analogy for God is that of relationships, forming a space that is strictly a “no-place”’ (p. 262). Part three looks at ‘wisdom in the world’, and continues to flush out the implications for our consideration brought about through the in-depth textual analysis of wisdom literature engaged with contemporary society. Because these themes have already appeared in previous chapters, though they are here refined within the following contexts, I will be brief in summarizing their contents. The first chapter tackles ‘metaphor and mystery in the interpretation of wisdom’, converging upon Derrida and Ricoeur’s textual hermeneutics in light of the ‘unfathomable text of the world’ (p. 275), the disruption and giving of the self associated with both God (again as Trinity) and humanity itself. The second chapter explores late modern reticence to embrace the ‘whole’ in favor of partial viewpoints, which Fiddes addresses and alters by suggesting that wisdom—here in the figure of Koheleth, and juxtaposed mainly with Wolfhart Pannenberg—focuses more on the whole ‘as a sum’ of what is rather than as an exercise in totalization (and, hence, oppression). Again, the relational nature of the Trinity is invoked as that which points toward a model of accumulating what wisdom, love and relations we are able to gain, while never seeing the entirely of what actually lies before us. The third chapter on ‘the text of the world and the comprehensiveness of wisdom’ would seem to theoretically synthesize the previous two chapters, yet in the context of considering another model of comprehending the vastness and expansion of wisdom: as Torah, but also, by extension within a Christian context, as Christ. The final chapter of the third section, quite intriguingly follows Foucault’s analysis of power and the formation (and care) of the self as situated within the context of learning (or rejecting) wisdom (much as Jesus could be said to be the rejected wisdom) as a form of ‘creative activity’. A final, refreshingly speculative ‘Coda’ at the end of the volume turns to musical metaphors in an attempt to find the proper ‘attunement to wisdom’ that is needed in our age, one that searches for its embodiment in the body of God and the body of Christ. Fittingly in accord with what has come before it, this conclusion places its stress upon making the movement toward other bodies, a relational movement that seeks attunement and one that must be done in harmony with the wisdom that has come before it and shaped it. I must admit that have done almost no justice to the depth and significance of biblical scholarship that Fiddes addresses in this vast work, and I have only gestured toward the wonderful connections that he makes between contemporary society, both its faults and its hopeful possibilities, and the ancient writings of wisdom that have been passed on to us as part of a determinate religious tradition. Indeed, as I neared the end of the volume, I had the sneaking suspicion that I would be returning to the volume again and again in order to find more use for the valuable insights which his latest book presents us with. I have few doubts, moreover, that this impression will be anything less than accurate. Loyola University Chicago Colby Dickinson Nationhood, Providence, and Witness: Israel in Modern Theology and Social Theory. By Carys Moseley. Pp. xxxiii, 267, Cambridge, James Clark & Co., 2013, $21.18. Contrary to myriad theoretically sophisticated predictions from various quarters, offered under ostensibly analytical but often polemical rubrics such as ‘modernity’ and, now ‘globalization’, nations con- tinue to exist. What to make of this fact? That theology ought rigorously to take up anew this pressing and significant fact is the merit of Moseley’s welcome book. She understandably wants theologians BOOK REVIEWS to ‘take seriously the existence of nations as part of the divine plan for world history’ (ix) by arguing ‘the need for a theological theory of recognition of nations’ (196). Moseley’s plea is well and good, if one takes one’s head out of the sand and allows oneself to be open to the facts of history; but where does this leave the theologian for whom history is the theatre of God? Can there be, as R. Tudur Jones put it in ‘Christian Nationalism’, ‘[nationality] on the basis of specifically Christian presuppositions’? The problem, as Moseley rightly observes, is that ‘the topic of nationhood has proven difficult for theologians’ (xv). Clarifying and then dealing with the reasons why it has been difficult further complicates the ability of theology to take up productively nationality (as distinct from ‘nationalism’: the ideological elevation of the nation above all other attachments and attendant loyalties—a modern-day form of pagan idolatry). For the development of a theory of the theological recognition of nations, attention must be paid to the Bible, given the importance of the concepts of g^ oy (‘nation’) and ‘am (‘people’), the description of a carefully delineated, bounded territory (Numbers 34 and elsewhere), the theological (exilic?) extrapolations of those concepts and that description as the ‘chosen people/nation’ and ‘promised land’, and the allegorical (for example, Galatians 4:24-25) and metaphorical (for example, Revelations 3:12, 21:2) reinterpretations of these symbols in the New Testament and subsequent Christian exegesis and apologetic for example, Justin Martyr’s Dialogue with Trypho and Irenaeus’ Against Heresies. One may avoid the problem of nationality by implicitly agreeing with Marcion, and therefore ignore as much as possible the Hebrew Bible as the old—even primitive—Old Testament. In this case, the ‘particularism’ of the Old Testament is something of the past, at best a residue. One may keep the Hebrew Bible as the Old Testament, remaining content with replacement theology and supersessionism, thereby minimizing the problem of (biblical) nationality through the aid of that uncritical exegesis and strained apologetic which has been called into question since the Reformation. One need only recall the Lutheran accusation against Calvin for being a ‘Judaizer’, and the proper focus on the ‘plain meaning’ of words and verse. Since Moseley is no modern-day Marcionite and since she rejects replacement theology and supersessionism (202), her conclusion is that the theologian must acknowledge not only the legitimacy of Israel as a nation in both the Hebrew Bible and the New Testament but also the modern ‘nation[al] state of Israel under God, alongside other nations’ (205). Moseley does not shy away from the implications of her argument, understanding that the basis for the ‘profound resentment and demonization of the 535 [modern] state of Israel’ (68) is hostility to nationality. As she puts the matter, ‘anti-nationalism is intrinsically anti-Zionist’ (205). The Jews have had the audacity to take seriously both the liberal, democratic principle of self-determination and the biblical description of Israel’s covenant with God as eternal. Nevertheless, the problem remains: how should Christian theology view this freedom of national self-determination and God’s eternal covenant with Israel as a nation, obedient to God’s word (law)? Long-standing difficulties re-emerge - the relation between the Old and New Testaments, and various responses such as ‘two covenant theology’ or ‘subsidiarity’, that allow some opening for nationality. To tackle this problem Moseley discusses the resurgence of religion (Chapter One) and then subjects the topics of Israel and nationality in the works of Reinhold Niebuhr, John Milbank and Rowan Williams to critical examination in Chapters Two, Four and Five, interrupted by an analysis of ‘Wales as a Stateless Nation’ (Chapter 3), which includes an overview of current theories of nationality, for example, by Anthony Smith. The book concludes with the stimulating Chapter Six, ‘Israel and Jesus: Recognition, Election, and Redemption’. Despite a good discussion of Israel and nationality in Niebuhr’s work, the attention paid to the works of Niebuhr and especially Milbank and Williams is unfortunate; the profound theological problems in dealing with nationality tend to get lost in, certainly overwhelmed by, criticism after criticism, however justified, of Milbank’s and Williams’ positions. Better would it have been to isolate and then move front and center these problems, discussing the complications surrounding them for theology. For example, are nations to be understood as products of nature, or results of human activity; to reformulate the question: how is the relation between nature and history to be understood? Is this activity to be regarded as sinful, or as indicating a partnership with God in the (unfinished) creation of the world? Is the existence of nations an expression of the fallen state of brokenness and sin, or are nations a perennial way humans have organized themselves as witnesses to the freedom that God makes possible? Above all, is this freedom for Christianity, the freedom of the individual or the freedom of the individual as a member of a nation? Even if one adopts a ‘soft supersessionism’ of Pauline ‘Israel’ to image the incorporation of Gentiles into (a reinterpreted) ‘Israel’ (perhaps Romans 11) rather than an ecclesial replacement as the latter has come to be understood, it is the individual who is incorporated, in contrast to a plurality of nations, each in their own way enriching humanity, looking to Zion, as in Isaiah 2. These and the previously mentioned problems are well known; the merit of Moseley’s book is not that answers are provided, but a call has 536 BOOK REVIEWS been given for nationality to assume ‘its due regard as a topic in theology’ (232). The facts of history demand no less. It is not clear how far Christian theology can put aside supersessionism, and thereby provide a theology for the recognition of the nation of Israel and of nationality in general; in any event, to do so clearly requires a richer and more extensive formulation than appears in this book. There are suggestive hints, however, as to what direction Moseley thinks such a theology might take. She believes a re-evaluation and appreciation of ‘the historical dimensions of human life’ (55) are necessary. I gather that this is implied by her referencing ‘Niebuhr’s Hebraic turn to the Old Testament’ (50). This is an interesting characterization, but not developed. What is meant precisely by ‘Hebraic turn’ or ‘the more Hebraic strand in Christianity’ (133)? What is the theological justification for so-called ‘Christian Hebraism’, and what theologically is at stake? Here Moseley might have called attention to the recognition and incorporation of the (rabbinic) Noahide code in Hugo Grotius’ On the Laws of War and Peace and especially in John Selden’s De jure naturali et gentium juxta disciplinam Ebraeorum, as a concrete way of providing ‘real theological contours’ (95) to an understanding of nationality. A study of how these latter Christian Hebraists understood the Noahide code should find a place within Moseley’s proposal to read ‘the rise of Calvinist orthodoxy and Puritanism as part of the his- tory of the Western understanding of nations’ (xxii). If so, however, another theological problem arises, for Grotius and, in complicated and conceptually richer ways, Selden understood the Noahide laws to be natural. Here, of course, other difficulties for a theology of nationality should be critically examined: not only the legitimacy of a national—or, in England, ‘common’—law but also in what ways this law is or is not related to the ius gentium, divine law, and eternal law, as, for example, is discussed in Aquinas’ Summa. Is ‘exitus and reditus’ to be acknowledged, or, in contrast, an associational and attendant legal pluralism? Are nations and national states persona ficta, or do they have ‘corporate personality’? We must make up our minds about whether nations are natural consequences (spontaneous orders) of the limitations of human existence, or lapsarian constructs. An approximate reformulation of these alternatives would be: granted that we recognize the ideology of nationalism to be a sinful idolatry, and recognizing the distinction between nationalism and nationality, how is the latter to be understood theologically? Moseley’s provocative suggestion that we read the rise of Calvinist orthodoxy and Puritanism as part of the history of the Western understanding of nations, remains to be undertaken. If this can be persuasively accomplished, it would be an important contribution. Clemson University Steven Grosby Leon Trotsky: a Revolutionary Life. By Joshua Rubenstein. Pp. x, 225, New Haven/London, Yale University Press, 2013, £10.99. This is a sad but cautionary tale that plays out slowly over the 61 years of Trotsky’s life as a classic, patient pedagogy of how an individual who is enormously gifted but insecure in his initial family situation, reinvents himself successively in an opportunistic program of upward social mobility, finally allows himself to develop the blind spot or commit the hypocrisy of attaching himself to a system that allows for violence and persecution in its demand for a monopoly on doctrinal questions, all in the praiseworthy goal of seeking the ‘liberation of the proletariat’; eventually falls into the net he has allowed to be spread for others, loses his elevated position in the party to a more thuggish and crafty rival, loses his entire family, plus his many followers and disciples in the persecutions that follow, and finally loses his own life to assassination so that in the end it is as if he never existed. His unchecked egotism led him to a lapse that cost him and his friends everything. To win the chess game, he played a king-sacrifice. Rubenstein goes beyond Isaac Deutscher in not writing as an admirer or follower, and beyond Robert Service in not trying to damn Trotsky for his personal failings. Trotsky’s error was systematic, not personal, and wilful and deliberate rather than based on weakness. Born Lev Bronstein in 1879 to a Jewish family in the southern Ukraine, Trotsky was sent for a better education to the cosmopolitan city of Odessa where he blossomed, but also associated his personal situation with the plight of the serfs and other persecuted minorities in Russia. In an uncanny repetition of the French Revolution (which he frequently invoked), Trotsky joined the struggle to transform Russia from a feudal, agricultural, and incipiently capitalist country to a modern industrial communist state in one generation. As the French revolutionaries also justified their urgency, this had to be done violently and BOOK REVIEWS quickly, because the neighboring capitalistic countries would not tolerate this change and do everything they could to stop or reverse it. Shunning the isolated terrorist acts of ‘liberals’ who thereby hoped to propel the Tsarist regime into serious reforms, Trotsky allowed himself to be backed into the ‘unsentimental’ science of revolution of Karl Marx, as recently rebottled and updated by Lenin to show how Russia could leap over the need for a ‘bourgeois’ revolution, allowing the proletariat to advance immediately to ownership of the means of production. Trotsky laid his intellectual, oratorical, journalistic, and diplomatic gifts on the altar of the revolution and was unquestionably the propagandistic and inspirational leader that led it to its surprising success. Early on, however, he displayed an almost autistic fascination with and devotion to the ‘system’, associated with a simultaneous denial of reality. This trait appeared in small things and large. In 1917 Trotsky spent 10 weeks in New York and enjoyed socializing with the waiters in a restaurant who were mostly Russian Jewish emigres like himself; he refused, however, to tip them for their service because he was in principle 537 against tipping - and they came to avoid him as a customer. (p. 77) After the Russian civil war (in which Trotsky’s position was intuitively closer to the more humane Mensheviks who lost), when he came to address economic issues, Trotsky argued against granting labor unions any degree of autonomy, convinced that under communism workers would not need to improve their conditions or defend their rights. As Angela Balabanoff, a longtime friend, observed this transformation: he ‘was a neophyte who wanted to outdo in zeal and ardor the Bolsheviks themselves, the neophyte who wanted to be forgiven the many crimes against Bolshevism he had committed in the past – by becoming more intransigent, more revolutionary, more Bolshevik than any of them’ (p. 118). A means is to be assessed by its end, he would say, and the most important end that cannot be achieved without violence automatically justifies that means. Trotsky accepted this ambiguity in Lenin’s thinking, and thus ultimately had no defense before Stalin’s practices, against the workers or against himself. Heythrop College Patrick Madigan How China Became Capitalist. By Ronald Coase and Ning Wang. Pp. 256, Basingstoke, Palgrave Macmillan, 2012, £60.00. Ronald Coase was born in 1910. As a boy he read Marco Polo and as a student became interested in economics when he heard about the invisible hand. He made a fundamental contribution to the Nature of the Firm in an ‘undergraduate paper’ of 1937 and was a founder of the Law and Economics school. In 1991 he won the Nobel Prize. He has teamed up with Ning Wang to tell the extraordinary tale of how China became capitalist. After Mao died in 1976, and the Gang of Four were arrested, the class hatred of the decade-long Cultural Revolution was brought to a close. Order was restored, Deng Xiaoping returned to assume paramount leadership in 1978, and China opened up: welcoming capital and new technology, growing in trade, and most important of all, learning. Painfully aware of the consequences of isolation (visiting a Nissan factory Deng announced, Now I know what modernisation means) China embraced a new Long March. Lip service was paid to Mao – especially stressing the dictum of seeking truth from facts: Deng’s deft political footwork was brilliant. But he had no blueprint for economic reform – and was frank about his lack of experience. A Communique of 1978, usually associated with the birth of economic reform, made no mention of markets. In fact, Chinese bureaucrats were quite na€ıve. During a week-long intensive course given by Milton Friedman on price theory a minister asked, Who in the US is responsible for the distribution of materials? So, it was not that the reform was planned; rather that it took place on the margins in ways no one could expect. As the proverb has it, Flowers planted on purpose do not blossom; the willows no one cared for have grown into big trees offering ample shade. For example, in one of the poorest villages, Nine Dragon Hill, a ‘village of beggars,’ the experiment of private farming yielded a harvest three times that of the collectives, and the experiment was extended. Or, again: the ‘returned youth.’ Socialist China boasted that it had no unemployment - Mao had sent millions of city youths to learn from the peasants. But after his death they came back. Under pressure, selfemployment was permitted and twenty million set up their own businesses with the result that noodle sellers could earn more than nuclear scientists. The market provides. The market is necessary because we do not possess omniscience. It is not so much an efficient 538 BOOK REVIEWS allocator of resources as the channel of information. Nor was its progress automatic: an inflation rate of 8% in 1988, a student uprising in 1989, an ‘incident’ (with Deng’s approval) in Tiananmen Square leading to a fall in foreign investment all put reform in jeopardy. But Deng’s political skill in his Southern Tour, and his building up of legal institutions played its part. As one would expect from the authors, the role of institutions is not ignored. But a central theme of the book is epistemology: Discover the truth through practice, and again through practice verify and develop the truth. Start from perceptual knowledge and actively develop it into rational knowledge; then start from rational knowledge and actively guide revolutionary practice to change both the subjective and objective world. Practice, knowledge, again practice, and again knowledge. This form repeats itself in endless cycles, and with each cycle the content of practice and knowledge rises to a higher level (121). Thus Mao in 1937, who learned of the need to respect subsidiarity in the Long March and in his guerrilla warfare. He attributes the method to Marx, but the authors trace it to Confucius. Dubiously they refer to the market of ideas, illustrating the concept by the ways that local authorities (in networks ironically set up by Mao) competed for investment by trying out different plans to attract businesses, unintentionally conducting an experiment to reveal good practice. The market of ideas is urged for the sake of creativity: Chinese researchers produce plenty of Ph. D.’s but win few Nobel prizes. The problems of the market are alluded to, and in the context of social justice the authors conclude with one of Premier Wen Jiaobao’s favourite books: The Theory of Moral Sentiments, (of which there are more than a dozen Chinese editions). Unless the fruits of development are shared by all it is morally unsound. Adam Smith, in fact, actually emphasised two invisible hands, one being the market, the other being morality (185). Smith’s tone and message is compared with Confucius, Isn’t it a joy to study and regularly practice? What’s more, isn’t it a joy to receive friends from afar? At this point the authors are not simply relating China’s story, but envisioning what ours might be. This excellently written book has great merit, not least in pointing us towards a new political economy. Maryvale Institute Birmingham, UK Christopher Friel Edward Said on the Prospects of Peace in Palestine and Israel. By John Randolph LeBlanc. Pp. x, 195, Basingstoke, Palgrave MacMillan, 2013, £55.00. Literary theorist Edward Said was a central figure in the emergence of post-colonial theory, as well as an internationally renowned advocate for the human rights of Palestinians, working tirelessly to counter the popular presentation of Arab peoples in the American media. Said was more than simply an academic—he was a public intellectual whose work was debated in the mass media and whose influence went beyond the realm of literary theory. In his latest book, political scientist John Randolph LeBlanc makes a strong case for examining the political nature of Said’s work, arguing that Said’s writings suggest ‘the need for a pre-political theory. As a voice of a people dispossessed, Said’s work pushes our political thinking back beyond our present optic where politics involves controlling what one can and managing what one cannot’ (8). LeBlanc uncovers this pre-political theory in five concise chapters, the first focusing upon democratic aspirations and ambiguities in the Middle East. Of course, phrases such as ‘democratic’ and ‘liberal freedoms’ come with baggage enough, especially when promoted as universal values by the West, for ‘[t]he liberal is universal only when the moral/ political universe is narrowed to those who fit the mold’ (30). Instead, Said promotes a democratic criticism in which one constantly engages one’s preconceptions, grasping complexities and resisting ‘final solutions’ of all kinds. Such a view, applied to Palestine/Israel, to the reality that settling people somewhere depends always upon first unsettling another people, reveals the difficulty, if not the impossibility, of distinguishing ‘between settling and unsettling without recognizing that one narrative claim has been artificially and forcibly prioritized over the other’ (53). Rather than the imposition of mutually exclusive truth claims, LeBlanc’s reading of Said offers the recognition of hybridity, or the fact that places always house multiple cultures, multiple narratives: ‘human presence, place, and culture are real; the truth of antecedent justifications, claims of exclusivity, and purity are not’ (64). Building upon this theme of hybridity, and recognizing the experience of exile that underlies both Israeli and Palestinian history, Said advocates the BOOK REVIEWS embrace of exile as a cognitive stance, the ‘exile as traveler,’ always interrogating her experience, rather than the exile as potentate, who fetishizes the recovery of the homeland and the purity of group identity. Hybridity undermines the logic of separation, which produces such policies as the Israeli separation barrier being constructed around the West Bank since the start of the Second Intifada: ‘[R]ather than positing one safely beyond the reach of the other, what results is a double enclosure; first, each community is close off in the delusion or fantasy that it is, can or should be separate from the other; second, in this delusion driven by suffering, the two communities are closed off together, locked in a mortal struggle to make their part of the delusion a physical reality’ (93). Peace processes fail because the do not recognize the shared reality of the space. LeBlanc goes beyond Said’s ‘exile as traveler’ motif to adopt the image of exodus, in which an entire community lives in exile and endures a time of testing. LeBlanc’s reading of Said offers a secular, or worldly, view of human existence that prioritizes not identity, which easily fosters exclusivism, but rather ‘presence,’ or the reality of people’s lives in a particular place, both present-day and down through the past, for, ‘with presence there is memory; with memory 539 there are claims of justice and injustice; with those claims come the challenges of reconciliation and then and only then with creating and living a mature political community’ (146). What LeBlanc offers here is more than simply a reading of Edward Said’s literary corpus. Rather, he incorporates into his analysis the theoretical work of many other noteworthy scholars—such as Giorgio Agamben and Judith Butler—to complement and, sometimes, to offer a counterpoint to Said’s writings, occasionally illuminating some of his blind spots. This cross-fertilization of political and literary theory makes this LeBlanc’s own major contribution to the pursuit of peace in the Middle East, a meditation upon democracy, national identity, and ethnic conflict that calls to mind the work so many who have labored in this field. Indeed, this book should be read alongside Marc Howard Ross’s Cultural Contestations in Ethnic Conflict (2007) and Jeff Spinner-Halev’s Enduring Injustices (2012) as an exemplar of political theory that is sincerely concerned with realworld suffering and that offers a possible route away from the constraints of violence. Encyclopedia of Arkansas History & Culture Guy Lancaster The Culture of Immodesty in American Life and Politics. Edited by Michael P. Federici, Richard M. Gamble, and Mark T. Mitchell. Pp. vi, 228. Basingstoke, Palgrave MacMillan, 2013, £55.00. The idea that America constitutes an empire is not a new one, though it typically finds expression among the political Left, with a focus upon the military and economic domination of the larger part of the world. However, the contributors to The Culture of Immodesty in American Life and Politics argue that both the American Right and Left exhibit a worldview that ‘has few reservations about using power to transform society and the world,’ that ‘places faith in the ability of rulers to fashion a world much better both morally and materially than the one we were born into’ (1–2). In contrast to this worldview, the contributors to this volume hearken back to the sort of ‘modest’ republic envisioned by the founders of the United States, one that emphasizes the virtue of restraint on several levels. The book is divided into three sections: 1) America in the World, 2) Political and Economic Immodesty, and 3) Immodesty in American Culture. Noteworthy in the first section, Richard M. Gamble argues that American has bought into a messianic hoax, especially in moving ‘the conflict between good and evil from the individual human breast to a realm “out there,”’ as typified by the American ‘War on Terror,’ which conflates the sacred and the secular in a war for righteousness’s sake (24). In the second, a chapter which stands out is Brian Patrick Mitchell’s survey of the evolution of banking, with particular attention to its role in the rise of mercantilist republics more likely to wage war for economic advantage rather than dynastic or religious goals, the result of which is the emergence of a cartel of super banks more powerful than nations: ‘[T]oday, Goldman Sachs is too bit to fail, but Greece is not’ (106). A particularly enlightening piece in the third section is Darryl Hart’s analysis of the ‘immodest faith’ of modern America, which tracks specifically the influence of Reinhold Niebuhr, who, Hart insists, failed ‘to distinguish between the religious and the secular spheres,’ adopting instead ‘the idea that all of life is religious’ (206)—an idea which reduces the Church to a political entity, with a position on all issues. Not all the chapters are so insightful as these, however. Many contributors expend their precious pages in railing against ‘entitlements,’ especially 540 BOOK REVIEWS legislation expanding government-provided healthcare, equating the rise of the welfare state and federal regulations with imperial immodesty, in so far as they represent government intrusion into private life. In so doing, they fail to realize the various manifestations modesty can take. Though Scandinavian nations, for example, are well nigh socialist, the socalled ‘Law of Jante’ remains a cultural touchstone; welfare state Swedes are particularly renowned for their modesty. Too, many contributors equate secularism with immodesty, most notably Mark T. Mitchell, who writes, ‘The idea of God. . . created a horizon within which people could grasp the meaning of human existence,’ believing their actions limited by divine command (128). But is that true? One could just as easily argue that a theistic worldview might well reinforce megalomania, as people equate their personal desires with God’s, while a non-theistic outlook fosters modesty and humility by contextualizing modern life within the vastness of time and space, the evolution of the universe and of mankind. Finally, while the call for a renewal of local control will garner some support from across the political spectrum, including ecosocialists, the various authors fail to square the circle of local control and human rights; after all, ‘local control’ was, in the American South, a term regularly employed to justify Jim Crow laws and lynching. That said, what The Culture of Immodesty in American Life and Politics does well is 1) expose, from a traditionalist angle, the fundamental unity underlying America’s two (ostensibly polar opposite) political parties, and 2) offer a critique of capitalism and imperialism from the point of that body of tradition. American political and cultural life is, at present, based more upon the idea of team membership than it is truly substantive differences in policies or tastes—Democrats cheer, or at least hold their tongues, when their president pursues the same policies they cursed under his Republican predecessor. This book is not a perfect one, but it has something for people of all ideological stripes, and it constitutes a sincere and learned attempt to reinvigorate debate with a perspective beyond that of team membership, beyond the imperialistic tropes that are the common currency of the American political and economic establishment. Encyclopedia of Arkansas History & Culture Guy Lancaster The Political Economy of Environmental Justice. Edited by H. Spencer Banzhaf. Pp. xvi, 280, Stanford/London, Stanford University Press, 2012, £42.00. While it is well-known that poorer people and minorities tend to live in more polluted neighbourhoods, the reasons for these findings have hitherto received little attention in the literature on environmental justice. This book, which explores the mechanisms behind this phenomenon, seeks to fill this lacuna. Written from the perspective of economics, it is the fruit of a meeting in 2008 in Big Sky, Montana, where a number of economists concerned with environmental questions came together. Even if the book is based on findings about North American communities, much of the economic statistical analysis provides explanations that can be generalised and serve to understand the socioeconomic forces behind the link between poverty and neighbourhood pollution in other parts of the world as well. With a focus on property prices and the demographic and socio-economic effects of cleaning up environmental pollution, the first part of the book is about household behaviour and land markets. First examined is the observation that wellintended clean-up efforts might actually harm poor residents by resulting in what the authors call ‘gen- trification’—that is, rising property prices, construction and renovation, and influx of residents with a higher socio-economic status. The reasons for gentrification and for migration of poorer residents in the wake of it, needs to be understood, it is argued, in order to design environmental policies without negative effects on poorer communities. Quantitative economic analysis is used to show that while poorer residents choose to live in more polluted but low-cost areas for various reasons, they do so largely because, of necessity, they prioritise inexpensive housing. This, one may assume, might be true in many other parts of the world. In the United States, however, environmental injustice is not only associated with poverty, it is also linked to race. In chapter four the editor and his co-authors, Joshua Sidon and Randall Walsh, show that ‘that not only can richer whites outbid poorer minorities for cleaner, healthier communities, driving up the cost for accessing these communities, but these communities are even more expensive simply because they are whiter, further driving away minorities’ (p. 22). Proof that race remains a factor to reckon with in the context of American environmental justice is BOOK REVIEWS also given in the second part of the book, where Brook Depro and Christopher Timmins have an interesting chapter on empirical findings of studies in San Francisco. It is shown that blacks and Hispanics are at a disadvantage, compared with the white population when ‘trading up’ to bigger homes. Hence, they tend to move into neighbourhoods with more ozone pollution than do whites. The explanation given for this is that compared with whites, minorities face higher costs for similar sized properties. This in turn, it is shown, might be explained by discrimination or simply because minorities prioritize other public goods over low ozone levels The third part of the book is about industrial development and the behaviour of polluting firms. The question is whether polluting firms tend to locate in communities with greater concentrations of poor and minority groups and whether this is a direct result of discrimination. The overall finding is that industrial choice of site is driven more by profits than by discrimination. The most important factors are production costs such as price of land and cost and availability of labour, as well as transportation costs such as freight costs and distance to markets. At the same time it is noted that the more populated an area is, the less likely 541 is it that a polluting firm locates there. This is explained by the fact that such communities tend to be more vocal. That more vocal and politically active communities are at an environmental advantage is further borne out in the final section of the book on the behaviour of governments, both state and federal. No support is found for the hypothesis that pollution policies of governments are discriminatory and favour white middle-class communities over poor or black and Hispanic communities. But more vocal and active communities are less likely to have hazardous waste sites constructed in their vicinity. This is another finding that would probably be confirmed in many other parts of the world. It would indeed be interesting to explore whether the proffered explanations for the environmental injustices related to poverty, political activity and lobbying are applicable to other parts of the industrialized world besides the United States. In other words, this book implicitly calls for further studies of the phenomena for which is seeks explanations. Heythrop College, University of London Agneta Sutton Environmental Justice and Climate Change: Assessing Pope Benedict XVI’s Ecological Vision for the Catholic Church in the United States. Edited by Jame Schaefer and Tobias Wainwright. Pp. xxxiii, 279. Lanham, MD, Lexington Books, 2013, $100.00. The U.S. Conference of Catholic Bishops and two Catholic environmental organizations sponsored a Catholic Consultation on Environmental Justice and Climate Change in November 2012 to coincide with the semi-annual meeting of the USCCB in Baltimore. Organizers were inspired by Pope Benedict XVI’s teachings on climate change and care for the environment, as expressed in his Message on the 2010 World Day of Peace and other writings. Unfortunately, Benedict never made ecological concerns and climate justice a central focus of his pontificate, so scholars have to sift through many papal pronouncements to find environmental nuggets of wisdom. Like those official documents, most of these essays are true but uninspiring. They neither convey a sense of urgency nor provide much motivation for action. For the most part, they are as exciting as encyclopedia articles. There are exceptions. Christina Peppard’s essay, ‘Commodifying Creation?’ deftly summarizes the warning signs of impending global catastrophe and cites both John Paul II and Benedict XVI in pointing to the world’s market economy as once source of the problem. Elizabeth Groppe admits, ‘The climate crisis is one of the many indicators that our current form of human civilization is walking a path of folly’ and that Benedict XVI ‘calls us to a radical conversion’ in the way we look at nature (146). Jeremiah Vallery deplores how ‘Catholics are indifferent to the environmental crisis’ (176) and sees shortcomings in the Church’s catechetical documents as partly to blame. David Cloutier in ‘American Lifestyles and Structures of Sin’ comes closest to speaking uncomfortable truth when he denounces the suburban pursuit of luxury as a driver of overconsumption, overproduction, the depletion of resources and the degradation of the environment. Louisville, Kentucky, USA Joseph Martos 542 BOOK REVIEWS Spectre of the Stranger: Towards a Phenomenology of Hospitality. By Manu Bazzano. Pp. xii, 164. Brighton/ Portland/Toronto, Sussex Academic Press, 2012, £16.95. Manu Bazzano is a Zen Buddhist monk, a psychotherapist who lectures in philosophy and psychology, and author of Buddha is Dead: Nietzsche and the Dawn of European Zen (2006) and The Speed of Angels (2009). Spectre of the Stranger is in three parts with an introduction and an epilogue (and a model index). Each of its parts draws on a wealth of thought, both Eastern and Western, which illuminate most when unexpected associations are discovered In Part I, headed ‘A place in the sun’, Bazzano offers 40 wide-ranging notions of identity and otherness, revealing the self’s ‘fluidity’ and ‘multiplicity’ (128), 40 apparently independent sections that do, in fact, oscillate between two hypotheses, one inspired by the Zen Buddhist tradition, the other motivated by the philosophy of otherness as discussed by some prominent late twentieth-century thinkers. Perhaps interdependent would be a more apposite, if challenging, description. The first hypothesis, deconstructing the self, maintains that there is no such thing as interiority. ‘When we look closely,’ Bazzano writes, ‘we do not find a thing we can call the self . . . I simply cannot know myself as a solid and separate entity’ (5). The second hypothesis is that ‘only through hospitality [is] true identity . . . born’ (5). ‘Summoned by another, called to respond, the response creates me’ (5.) This creation of a seemingly separate entity also calls into being the recognition of the gap that separates self from other, which is ‘the call of responsibility’ (128). As such, Bazzano contends, the Christian love of one’s neighbour is challenged and wisdom is seen as the encounter with otherness. In reconstructing the self its peculiarities are recognised and there is, Bazzano argues, a desire to become intimate with it and so the approach to the inner life is a mixture of ‘curiosity and love, inquiry and compassion’ (128). In Part II Bazzano goes in search of cultural matrixes that justified hostility towards otherness, xenophobia. This part is headed ‘A human revolution’, a title used by Marx in the 1840’s when discussing a political, but also ethical and aesthetic, revolution. Here, in 18 sections, Bazzano, using insights from philosophy and psychology, posits that if individuality comes into being through openness to the other, in the wider, social sphere the citizen becomes a citizen by opening up to the non-citizen (and, by extension, the person becomes a person by opening up to the nonperson, and so on), xenophobia is transformed into xenophilia, ostracism is transformed into welcome. ‘Only thus he becomes a true citizen, for it is only a full recognition of vulnerability which defines human goodness and the meaning of justice itself’ (6). Hospitality, then, is nothing less than a revolution, a human revolution in which ‘the ethical response marries political activism and renews the tradition of anarchism, substituting the classic notion of individual emancipation of the anarchist tradition with responsibility towards otherness and revolutionary violence with a combative pacifism, civil disobedience and direct action’ (7). Inspired by H}olderlin’s ‘dwelling poetically on this Earth’, the 16 sections of Part III (which uses this phrase as its title) reassert hospitality first and foremost as the poetical action of a person who never forgets their status as a ‘passenger’ or ‘guest’ on this Earth, ‘circumventing the now predictable turn of most notions of freedom into new modes of oppression . . . by preventing us [from] taking a too literal assumption of responsibility which would become co-opted by the universal guilt of established religions’ (129). As such, an aesthetic and symbolic dimension is introduced, demonstrating how hospitality can lead to a heightened sense of well-being. Bazzano concludes ‘If we can remember our essential condition as guests on this earth we stand a chance of becoming good hosts and true citizens’ (129). Monastère de la Sainte-Presence, Brittany Luke Penkett The Tao of Liberation: Exploring the Ecology of Transformation. By Mark Hathaway and Leonardo Boff. Pp xxvi, 419. Maryknoll, NY, Orbis Books [Ecology and Justice Series], 2009, $35.00. This book is the result of a collaborative undertaking between Mark Hathaway, a Cana- dian eco-justice advocate and adult educator who is presently pursuing doctoral studies and BOOK REVIEWS Leonardo Boff, the well-known liberation theologian from Brazil, whose writings on ecology and liberation have been influential in connecting the suffering of the Earth with the suffering of the poor. Their collaboration has its origins in Hathaway’s Master’s thesis, which he wrote and shared with Boff in Toronto during 1996. The two men formed a partnership with the explicit goal of bringing together diverse perspectives emanating from their respective situations as authors committed to a cosmology of liberation. Building upon the advantage of both individuals having spent time in the other’s home region, their content-specific aspiration for this project was to represent views from both the Global South and North. The end result of this collaboration is a passionate argument about the need to orient religions, spiritualities, worldviews and modes of socio-political being in a direction that supports a praxis-driven transformation of what Hathaway and Boff understand as currently ascendant pathological practices of domination. The goal of this transformation is to support a (Thomas) Berryite dream of mutually enhancing and substantively just human-earth, human-divine and intra-human relationships. Key to this argument is a sense of deep connection linking all relationships within the universe on both of the intertwined cosmological and ecological levels. To give a sense of this multi-level connectivity, Hathaway and Boff draw on diverse imagery from cosmological reflection, green thought, religious wisdom, theology, the natural sciences, feminism and spiritual practice (amongst other areas). Their vision of the future is of one that is substantively egalitarian, sustainable, dynamic and peaceful, as ‘power-over’ and systems of domination are transformed into ‘power-with’ and systems that foster artful and creative collaboration, marked by multi-layered diversity. The discussion in this volume on how Christian theology needs to be shifted to contribute to such a transformation may be particularly noteworthy for readers of the Heythrop Journal. Perhaps what is most intriguing in that regard is Hathaway and Boff’s treatment of the Trinity, Pneumatology and Christology. Briefly, they argue that the Trinity is a prime example of an integral connection from a Christian point of view; one Hathaway and Boff consider difficult to match in other green thinking due the depths of its relational content. Here, moving beyond orthodox categories, they cite the complete unity and yet irreducible diversity and co-eternity of the Mother/Father, Son/Child and Holy Spirit. Within a similar vein, in terms of Pneumatology, Hathaway and Boff reference the 543 Pauline idea of a diversity of talents emanating from the same Spirit. They further expand upon the creative aspect of the Holy Spirit and, in that light, emphasize the indwelling of the spirit as absolute Energy across the cosmos. When focussing on the person of Christ, Hathaway and Boff note how the incarnation was dependent on the pre-existence of the universe, that it was a ‘truly cosmic event...that Jesus’ roots are found in the Milky Way, his cradle is the solar system, and his house our planet Earth‘ (p. 329). Thus, they view the Cosmic Christ as engendering a ‘panChristicism,’ joining together every human and all of creation. There are some issues with The Tao of Liberation in terms of its flow of ideas. For instance, the authors will often criticize or advocate for a specific position and then at another point in the book present another criticism or normative statement that is in tension with the first portion of analysis or statement. As an example, Hathaway and Boff write in a contrastive, analytical and normative style about the value of ecologically and social just economic system and then emphasize the importance of not thinking in dichotomies. On one occasion, they even acknowledge this tension by explicitly asking the reader to not understand such a contrast as dichotomous. Another similar feature that may be owing to the book’s initial genesis as a Master’s thesis is that illustrative examples and very specific data are often repeated in the text. Also, the same thinkers are sometimes introduced in an extended format several times. These latter tensions’ potential to be irritable is amplified by the shear length of the text. On the positive side, this length provides space for an impressive number of perspectives within the pages of The Tao of Liberation. However, it also means the relevance of these viewpoints is not always wholly evident in the concluding quarter of the book. Furthermore, negating the value of ad fontes work, on a number of occasions authors are cited with their ideas presented through secondary sources rather than with reference to their original works. Additionally, entire scientific schools of thought that do not accord with Hathaway and Boff’s favoured quantum and system theories are painted with broad and sometimes unfair brush strokes, even though acknowledgments are later given to relation-oriented pioneers in other scientific fields. Perhaps worse is that an arguably undue number of lines in text are given over to controversial theories, such as Rupert Sheldrake and his interlockers’ ideas on morphic fields. Such extended treatments, while adding relatively little to the arguments for the pressing need for and 544 BOOK REVIEWS potential of a Tao of liberation, may serve to alienate critical readers with a background in the subject matter during the first three-quarters of the book before the more original material is presented in the final chapters. Those tensions, while worth noting in the context of a review, may be of little consequence for the authors whose intent appears to have been not to write a logically consistent academic treatise. Rather, Hathaway and Boff undertook this survey of diverse perspectives to suggest that there are many paths to help reinvent the human and society in order so that they support a substantively just and ecologically sustainable future. Those looking for nourishment in that regard are sure to find fruit in reading through the pages of The Tao of Liberation. Ultimately, this potentially nourishing character is what one might legitimately expect to emerge from a collaborative work between a North American educator-activist and a Latin American liberation theologian who do not hide their commitments. In this light, the book succeeds by offering a fairly nuanced, wide-ranging and accessible discussion of theory and practice, geared toward enabling its motivated readers to reflectively ground and more fully form their own transformative ecological praxis. Saint Thomas More College, University of Saskatchewan Christopher Hrynkow Canon Law: A Comparative Study with Anglo-American Legal Theory. By John J. Coughlin. Pp. xix, 226 Oxford University Press, 2011, £47.50. Law, Person and Community: Philosophical, Theological and Comparative Perspectives on Canon Law. By John J. Coughlin. Pp. xviii, 291, Oxford University Press, 2012, £55.00. John Coughlin is a Professor of Law at NotreDame University and a Franciscan priest and these are his two recent books on comparative Catholic canon law. The first book is selfexplanatory inasmuch as it seeks to re-establish canon law as a proper system of law as this is understood in secular Anglo-American legal thought. I say re-establish because nowadays canon law is regarded as a private and trivial matter either by States or by members of the faithful, including church authorities, who should know better. That a concern for natural rights, due process, fairness, the right of defense, and other legal maxims in canon law has gone by the board in some ecclesial circles - and the conduct of the U.S. Bishops during the abuse allegations being an example which he analyses - is a retrograde development where the promotion of justice has been reduced to an antinomian idea, and law and a substantive legal spirit in the Church has been replaced or abrogated by another distortion, that of legalism. Hence the welcome arrival of these timely tomes which employ the impressive tools of history, philosophy, theology, comparative law and conceptual analysis to redress this deficiency. The author presents an overview of the formation of canon law as law and to illustrate his points he looks at three examples of recent Church life: the abuse crisis in the U.S., Church ownership of property, and the refusal of Holy Communion to U.S. Catholic public officials under the auspices of canon 915 and the uncertainty this causes because of interpretations by different bishops in the U.S. Using these examples, the author presents the way the Code has been used and abused in the Church and then how that compares with the demands of jurisprudence in secular positive law. In the first book he summarizes the thinking of important secular theorists such as Hart, Fuller, Raz, Dworkin and Habermas, amongst others, as foils to canon law theory which, he argues, both borrows from and contributes, or, at least has contributed, to secular legal thought. Chapters on specific issues such as Legislative, Executive and Judicial Power, Universal and Particular Law, International Law, the Canonization of Civil Law, and so on, are considered in the light of Dispensation, Exception and Privilege which he sees are integral features enabling canonical equity and which also fulfill the secular demand for the law to be flexible and adaptable in particular circumstances, and. most of all, to be effective. Having considered Austin’s desire for the law’s effectiveness through coercion backed by sanctions being an essential aspect of its success, and of Hart’s and Dworkin’s ripostes to this, the author argues for what he calls the personal reason or intellectus of canon law which brings together natural, theological, and historical truths. This intellectus reflects canon law’s universal and transcendent principles; expresses theological truths from revelation, and includes a historical awareness of custom and tradition. It is a critical factor, he contends, in canon law’s power to bind. The intellectus relies on an understanding of a universal human nature affected and redeemed by Christ, and is not static but dynamic in particular BOOK REVIEWS circumstances. It binds because it provides the basis for personal obedience since failure to obey can damage one’s membership in the Church and the salvation of the soul; in short, it gives insight, as Habermas points out, which the person, by free use of the intellect and will, chooses to act in accordance with canon law’s demands. Coughlin argues that canon law therefore meets the criterion for a system of law and the rule of law, at least in the terms set by Anglo-American legal theory. Canon law’s authority is not primarily derived from coercion by means of sanctions, since it contains only a few penal sanctions, but from the intention of the legislator. Since it has the backdrop of a theological understanding of sacred power, it is this which enhances the duty of obedience owed to it. However, he states that this duty goes beyond a simple command theory since canon law’s authority lies on the insight or intellectus of the believing subject to voluntarily obey its norms because it functions as a rule of law which advances personal, social and ecclesial natural and supernatural ends. As regards canon law being a substantive system of law, he examines Hart’s criterion for a developed system of law containing both primary and secondary rules, the latter concerning recognition, change and adjudication, and argues that canon law satisfies these. However, he notes that the three examples of clergy sexual abuse, the ownership of Church property and the (mis)application of canon 915 to suggest that antinomian or legalism can reduce the adherence to abide by primary rules and that the secondary rules are susceptible to these extremes of legal thought. The result is serious damage to persons, the common good and the reputation of the Church and he thinks that the intellectus of canon law, which is based on natural and supernatural truths, gives a metaphysical grounding for the rule of law. The rule of law is central to any legal system and so it is essential that the Church adhere to it. In addition, aspects of history, philosophy, theology and, I would add, legal culture, must be borne in mind when seeking to understand and interpret canon law. Coughlin argues cogently for the necessity of the rule of law being adhered to in the Church, which it was not in the three examples he considers, because of the need for a legal system to exist precisely for the good of persons, the Church, and the common good, all of which are compromised by failures in this regard. Coughlin presents his case with some force and is able to situate the case for canon law being a system of law, as compared with another legal system, well. He considers secular legal positivism and is keen to bring that to bear on canonical thinking. This theme of the importance of a 545 substantive and effective system of law is very important for the Church and society. It is clear that no legal system lives up to its expectations and that all have defects difficult to correct and he notes that secular law is often subject to political pressures. Coughlin observes that antinomianism and legalism must be balanced by the rule of law as understood in Anglo-American legal theory so that canon law does not fall into further disrepute. His second book picks up some of these themes and develops them more, particularly as regards the writings of Blessed John Paul II on the theology of the body. This anthropological focus is explored, again with great clarity, and leads to a consideration of the constituent features of personal identity such as the soul, reason, affect, conscience, free will, memory and the salus animarum. Chapters on canon law in relation to natural law, equity and its development, as well as his chapter on marriage have, as he says, been published elsewhere. Where this second tome breaks new ground is in the area of Church-State relations and in particular in the field of the U.S. First Amendment and case law on Catholic schools and the U.S. Supreme Court’s rules as regards churches with a hierarchical, as distinct from a congregationalist, structure. He considers the basis upon which both Church and State law emerge and subjects this to a critique which is profound inasmuch as it considers the issue of the authority of law to bind: an issue causing much debate in the secular legal systems not only in the U.S., but also, I would point out, of emerging supranational European law and English common law, and one where canon law has a contribution to make in terms of renewed lines of thought on the nature of law, person and community. Indeed, canon law’s incorporation of the Church’s teaching on the intrinsic dignity of the human person, human rights, the common good and the final end of the human person provide tried and tested categories of reference for legally developed nationstates and which, in the highly legally specialized and litigious country from which the author writes, may now be rediscovered as substantive jurisprudential thought. Since modern Western secular law emerged from canon law, perhaps it is time for what has been forgotten in secular legal positivism to be recalled from its Catholic legal sources, especially because of the foundation it provides via its thinking on God, divine law, natural law and subsequent positive law for basic human rights, a feature which was not lost on Martin-Luther King who appealed to St Thomas Aquinas’s account of natural law against unjust racial laws from his prison cell. Catholic thinking generally has a far more substantial, realistic and inclusive notion of law, person and community in contrast to modern 546 BOOK REVIEWS social and political thought, particularly that of Hobbes and Rawls. Coughlin concludes on this triad in canon law not being a human invention but a reflection and analogy to God and warns of the danger of re-entering a humanly pointless pagan age after centuries of Catholic humanist thinking on these matters. These two books, with their comprehensive bibliographies, are a timely and an excellent consideration on these themes and should be required reading for all jurists. Wimbledon, London James Campbell The Punisher’s Brain: The Evolution of Judge and Jury. By Morris B. Hoffman. Pp. xi, 359. Cambridge/NY, Cambridge University Press, 2014, £21.99/$30.00. Hoffman is a judge in Colorado. Despite its title, this book is not primarily a study in neuroscience, nor a contribution to evolutionary history. It is informed by deep research in both these areas, as well as by the author’s professional experience; Hoffman’s goal, however, is to offer practical suggestions to improve legal systems: he is interested in the origins of humanity insofar as this may help build a better future. He is particularly concerned with problems within the American legal system; a consideration of the origins of these problems requires reflection on English law as well; it is no surprise to find frequent references to William Blackstone. Although the problems Hoffman discusses arise within the Anglo-American tradition, the general philosophy he advances is relevant to any nation that uses some form of trial by jury. For such a system to work, laws must be such that the ordinary members of the public who make up the jury are capable of understanding them, and do not find them completely repugnant. Juries are reluctant to find criminals guilty if the punishment prescribed by law seems excessive for the crime. The good news is that it turns out that juries understand the law better than Hoffman thought they did. He had long worried that, despite being given definitions, juries were incapable of understanding the differences between acts that are purposeful, knowing, reckless and negligent. Tests showed that, contrary to his expectations, jurors do understand most of these differences (although the distinction between knowing acts and reckless acts seems hard to grasp), and they do blame purposeful actions more than knowing ones (p. 292). It is not so much a question of having clear definitions, as framing laws that are in keeping with our intuitions to begin with. This does not mean that legislation should never be framed so as to override our natural intuitions. For example, laws prohibiting juries from knowing a defendant’s prior convictions deny us the information that we instinctively seek when assessing someone’s trustworthiness, but this is no reason to alter such laws, which exist precisely to overcome our natural prejudices, ensuring that reformed criminals are not kicked back into prison by a knee-jerk reaction (p. 256). The message is not that we should always trust our feelings, which will, in any case, often be conflicting, but that since there is a price to be paid when legislation goes against our intuitions, such laws should be introduced only where necessary (p. 308). In the final chapter, Hoffman considers the four main justifications that have been proposed for punishment: retribution, deterrence, rehabilitation and incapacitation. He argues that an emphasis on rehabilitation has led to excessive prison sentences for certain crimes in the USA, leading to a problem of overcrowding in jails, while at the same time criminals have been put on probation when a short prison sentence may have been more appropriate (p. 346). Hoffman argues that our natural urge for retribution evolved as a short-cut to achieving deterrence, and that an effective legal system should build on and refine our retributive instincts (pp. 344-345). He states that trial judges like to see themselves as practical people (p. 337), and the value of this book is, above all, its contribution to practical debates about punishment. It is important not to overlook the fact, however, that, as the title implies, Hoffman’s suggestions are rigorously grounded in the scientific study of human nature. Saint Paul said that God’s law is written on the human heart, and now scientists are taking it upon themselves to decipher that writing. Hoffman shows himself to be a wise reader. Florida State University, Panama Benjamin Murphy Copyright of Heythrop Journal is the property of Wiley-Blackwell and its content may not be copied or emailed to multiple sites or posted to a listserv without the copyright holder's express written permission. However, users may print, download, or email articles for individual use.