Crawford College of Art and Design Seminar Paper 2017 Olafur Eliasson and The Sublime By Roisin Everard (R00112098) Word count: 3610 Submitted: Thursday 6th April 2017 1 Table of Contents Introduction p.3 Body of Text p.4-12 Conclusion p.13 Illustrations p.14-15 Bibliography p.16-17 2 Introduction ‘The essential claim of the sublime is that man can, in feeling and speech, transcend the human. What, if anything, lies beyond the human – Gods or the gods, the daemon or Nature – is matter for great disagreement.’1 Using the treatises of Edmund Burke and Immanuel Kant this essay will explore the origins of ‘The Sublime’, through Romantic traditions which have been reenvisaged in a contemporary art context. I will be using Olafur Eliasson’s The Mediated Motion (2001), to discuss the contemporary sublime and to highlight the shift in the preoccupations of contemporary art towards engagement with modern sciences and technologies and their complexities of scale. In order to understand this shift a focus must first be placed on the pioneering development of ‘the sublime’ during the Romantic Period. Through examination of the devices implemented by the Romantics I aim to map out Eliasson’s ability to bring the sublime moment back to the consciousness of the spectator in the gallery space, whilst concurrently referencing traditions of depicting the vastness of nature. Using the treatise of Kant to explore Eliasson’s device of slightly removing the individual from everyday nature and how it can introduce sublimity into the representation of nature and our faculty of reason. The paper will make the leap from Romantic sublime straight to the contemporary sublime in order to examine the shift in fundamental concerns in large part by technical advances. It will also bring attention to how the same devices are used by Eliasson over two hundred years later. Through this it will show how sublimity within nature remains as overwhelming and awe inspiring regardless of if it is presented in the contemporary art gallery. It will lead the reader through the installation floor by floor, each floor bringing them closer to their cleaning of understanding and reason. 1 Weiskel Thomas, The Romantic Sublime: Studies in the Structure and Psychology of Transcendence, Baltimore: John Hopkins University Press, 1976, 3 3 To understand ‘the Sublime’ we must first look at the 1757 treatise by Edmund Burke, A Philosophical Enquiry into the Origin of our Ideas of the Sublime and Beautiful, which Simon Morley among others assert was the first complete philosophical exploration separating the Beautiful and the Sublime into their own categories. Morley cites that Burke declared that ‘‘the sublime’ was ‘the strongest passion’2, and he belittled the importance of the beautiful, claiming that it was merely an instance of prettiness. The sublime experience, on the other hand, had the power to transform the self. He was interested in what happened when the individual was confronted with something overwhelming and threatening to their own existence and how this fear could be pleasurable. Making reference to the overlap between pain and pleasure in moments of terror, Burke writes that this ‘always produces delight when it does not press close.’3 Phillips described this in the introduction to Burke, he suggested, ‘This kind of ‘delight’, in a dubious distinction, is not exactly a pleasure because it ‘turns on pain’; delight is produced when ‘the idea of pain and danger’ is staged, thereby providing the sufficient distance.’4 In 1790 Immanuel Kant looked to expand on theories previously explored by Burke. Phillips affirmed that both treatises ‘share what was to become a fundamental modern preoccupation; for Burke and Kant the Sublime was a way of thinking about excess as the key to a new kind of subjectivity.’5 Although Kant shifted his focus on our consciousness and our negative experiences of limits through sublime moments. Kant writes: The feeling of the sublime is at once a feeling of displeasure, arising from the inadequacy of imagination in the aesthetic estimation of magnitude to attain to its estimation of reason, and a simultaneous awakened pleasure, arising from 2 Morley Simon, The Sublime, MIT Press, 2010, 15 Burke Edmund, A philosophical Enquiry into the Origin of our Ideas of the Sublime and Beautiful, 1757,.xxi 4 Phillips Adam, Edmund Burke: A philosophical Enquiry into the Origin of our Ideas of the Sublime and Beautiful, Oxford University Press, 1990, xxi 5 Phillips Adam, Edmund Burke: A philosophical Enquiry into the Origin of our Ideas of the Sublime and Beautiful, Oxford University Press, 1990, ix 3 4 this very judgement of the inadequacy of sense of being in accord with ideas of reason, so far as the effort to attain to these is for us a law.6 In his treatise, The Critique of Judgement (1790), Kant defines aesthetic judgements as subjective including both taste and pleasure; the beautiful and judgements of cognitive and rational; the sublime. Placing the focus point on where reason reaches its limits, as Morley affirms, ‘He thereby shifted the analysis towards the impact and consequence of the sublime was essentially about a negative experience of limits.’7 Kul-Want references this same point as he argues that ‘Kant’s theory of the sublime...:it proposes that the experience exceeds thought, and that there are no adequate concept in the subject’s understanding for synthesis with the unpresentable.’ 8 Like Burke, Kant firmly separates the Beautiful from the Sublime, although Kant’s focus is firmly placed on cognition and the recognition of limits of the mind. He states: ‘‘For the feeling of the Sublime brings with it as its characteristic feature a movement of the mind bound up with the judging of the object, while in the case of the Beautiful taste presupposes and maintains the mind in restful contemplation.’9On this point Kul-Want affirms that, ‘…. Kant suggested that the world is an indeterminate reality consisting of no more than a projection of our own thoughts and categorise.’10 The emphasis on Kant’s success in the ability to categories and analyse the unpresentable; the sublime, was key to the development to further studies of aesthetics as well as objectivity. One of the canonical applications of ‘the sublime’ in the Romantic period, Caspar David Friedrich’s Wanderer above the Sea of Fog (1818) (fig. 1), affirms Gorra, ‘seems to encapsulate the whole of European Romanticism; an image of the Kantian sublime, as if in 6 Kant Immanuel, Critique of Judgement ,1790; trans. J.J Meredith, Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press, 1973, 106 7 Morley Simon, The Sublime, MIT Press, 2010, 16 8 Kul- Want Christopher, Philosophers on Art from Kant to the Poster modernists; A Critical Readers, Columbia University Press, 2007, 4 9 Kant Immanuel, The Critique of Judgement, 1790; trans. J.J Meredith, Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press, 1973, 101-105 10 Kul-Want Christopher, Philosophers on Art from Kant to the Poster modernists; A Critical Readers, Columbia University Press, 2007, 4 5 gazing out at this white and formless haze the wanderer were peering into the murky deep of his own mind.’11 The sense of unease created by the jagged rocks and the wanderer standing on the edge of a high peak, gives the viewer the implication of a sharp, long, fatal drop. Using Rückenfigur Friedrich allows the viewer to place themselves in the position of the wanderer, allowing them to contemplate the vastness and expanse of nature and their own limitations as human. Kant referred to moment of realisation of the sublimity within nature as the moment: The mind feels itself *moved* in the representation of the Sublime in nature; whilst in the aesthetical judgments about the Beautiful it is in *restful* contemplation…. in the immensity of nature, we find our own limitation… making us recognize our own physical impotence, as beings of nature… yet it discloses to us… faculty of judging independently of, and superior to, nature… It is man who shrinks from nothing, who fears nothing, and therefore does not yield to danger, but rather goes to face it vigorously with the most complete deliberation12 The rolling fog engulfing the jagged mountainous landscape as quickly as it releases them, shows the power of nature in all its elements. The viewer is brought to a point (the end of the road) and can only watch on as they realise, as Weiskel explains: Either mind or object is suddenly in excess—and then both are, since their relation has become radically indeterminate…. the mind recovers the balance of outer and inner by constituting a fresh relation between itself and the object such that the very indeterminacy which erupted…’ in the moment of sublimity, ‘is taken as symbolising the mind’s relation to a transcendent order.13 The role of the sublime within Romanticism, ‘emerged as a response to the disillusionment with the Enlightenment values of reason and order in the aftermath of the French Revolution of 1789.’14 Weiskel stated that, ‘Locke had removed the soul from the circuit of analogical 11 Gorra Michael, The Bells in Their Silence: Travels Through Germany, Princeton University Press 2009, xxi Kant Immanuel, The Critique of Judgement, 1790; trans. J.J Meredith, Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press, 1973, 24 13 Weiskel Thomas, The Romantic Sublime: Studies in the Structure and Psychology of Transcendence, KeatsShelley Association of America Inc., 1978, 23 14 The Met Museum: Romanticism, Accessed 19/03/2017, http://www.metmuseum.org/toah/hd/roma/hd_roma.htm 12 6 relations in which it had been installed, thereby decisively displacing the locus of order.’, arguing the case of empiricism. Therefore, the natural sublime asserts Weiskel, ‘was a response to the darker implications of Locke’s psychology and what that psychology represented of changes in perception.’15 This became the key point of reference and escape for artists during the Romantic period, dealing with ideas around ‘the sublime’. Two hundred years later these same preoccupations and devices are used by Olafur Elaisson within the contemporary art gallery. ‘In the 1980’s a new wave of postmodernist sublimity swept over the art world, largely provoked by a general dissatisfaction with the potential trivialization of art in the Pop aesthetic, on one hand, and on the other, its overintellectualization in Minimal art and conceptualism.’16 The shift allowed artist to turn the focus of vastness within nature towards the vastness of technology systems while still applying the psychoanalytic theories of Burke and Kant. To expand upon experiments of the postmodernist Morley asserts contemporary artists working around notions of the sublime, ’…seek to describe what takes hold of us when reason falters and certainties begin to crumble.’17 The contemporary understanding of the sublime allowed artists to explore the earlier traditions used by the Romantics, whilst bringing modern science and technology into the conversation. On the Tate website it sites that contemporary artists ‘…have located the sublime in not only the vastness of nature as represented in modern science but also the aweinspiring complexity and scale of the capitalist-industrial system and in technology.’18 In their observation of the work of Eliasson, Uta and Burkhard declare that, ‘Olafur Eliasson’s work is focused on natural elements and the conditions under which they are experienced. 15 Weiskel Thomas, The Romantic Sublime: Studies in the Structure and Psychology of Transcendence, The John Hopkins University Press, 1976, 14 16 Morley Simon, Sublime, MIT Press, 2010, 13 17 Morley Simon, Sublime, MIT Press, 2010, 12 18 The Art of The Sublime: The contemporary Sublime, http://www.tate.org.uk/art/research-publications/thesublime/the-contemporary-sublime-r1109224, Accessed 10/03/2017. 7 Water, light, moss, ice, steam and rainbows are among the phenomena that have been central to his sculptural installations.’19 The viewer is integral in experiencing ‘the sublime’ within the work and on this point Eliasson states that, ‘Exercising the integration of the spectator, or rather, the spectating act itself, as part of the museum’s undertaking has shifted the weight from the thing experienced to the experience itself.’20 In Eliasson’s 2001 installation, The Mediated Motion viewers had to navigate the building four floors as the installation stated by Grynsztejn, ‘...used natural materials and distinctive transitions to elicit unsteady physical states...’21 Elaisson explains: The spaces are mediated with a garden-like structure, combining wood with mushrooms; a wooden parcours across a small pond filled with growing duckweed; a sloped plane of contaminated earth; and finally, a smoky room with a hanging bridge. Each floor, with the stairs between them, presented a different platform on which to move. This is mediated motion.22 The viewer enters the ground floor of the Kunsthaus Bregenz, Austria and is confronted by a row of shitake mushrooms (figure. 2) growing on logs of wood. This installation almost hinting at the beauty but also the sublimity in these asymmetrical mushrooms growing on the dead, in a sense a taster of what Eliasson is present to the spectator as they move through the building. The origin of our collective satisfaction in these objects is explained by Kant: Here it is remarkable that, although we have no interest whatever in an Object, —i.e. its existence is indifferent to us, —yet its mere size, even if it is considered as formless, may bring a satisfaction with it that is universally communicable, and that consequently involves the consciousness of a subjective purposiveness in the use of our cognitive faculty. This is not indeed a satisfaction in the Object (because it may be formless), as in the case of the Beautiful, in which the reflective Judgement finds itself purposively determined in reference to cognition in general; but [a satisfaction] in the extension of the Imagination by itself.23 19 Grosenick Uta and Riemschneider Burkhard, Art Now, Taschen, 2002, 132 Eliasson Olafur, Olafur Eliasson , Phaidon, 2002, 127 21 Grynsztejn Madeleine, Take Your Time: Olafur Eliasson, Thames and Hudson, 2007, 121 22 Eliasson Olafur, Olafur Eliasson, Phaidon, 2002, 137 23 Kant Immanuel, The Critique of Judgement, 1790; trans. J.J Meredith, Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press, 1973, 106-110 20 8 In order to ascend to the next floor of the exhibition the viewer must use the spiral wooden staircases. This gap between one floor and the next brings the focus back to the individual moving through these separate experiences. Commenting on the experience of the exhibition Eliasson states: It takes a while to walk up to the third floor; to get there you must pass through every single exhibition space in the building. Experiencing these spaces, moving through them, allows you to sense the passing of time, I believe, and allows you to sense your own presence- you’re having a bodywhen moving in and engaging with your surroundings. This sense is, eventually, what constitutes a space (and you in it)24 Arriving on the first floor the spectator is presented with a large body of still water with duckweed floating on the surface (fig.3), spanning the entire space and a wooden walkway allowing them to move through the space. The duckweed growing and changing during the course of the exhibition, again bringing the idea of time to the forefront. Mieke Bal referenced Eliasson’s use of water, he argues, ‘Rather than soliciting the experience of the sublime, then, Eliasson’s installation brings water closer to humans. There is no imminent danger, no sense of self-inflicted doom, yet the work is powerfully political.’25 The spectator must mediate this body of water in a contemporary art gallery setting, as Morley claims ‘The sublime experience is fundamentally transformative, about the relationship between disorder and order, and the disruption of the stable coordinates of time and space.’ 26 Eliasson is also playing on the ideas of Kant, the feeling of reaching one’s limitations, but by introducing technology as a means to generate the sublime experience the spectator most confront the role of technology in everyday life. As Eliasson states, ‘Technology looks at how to a large extent 24 Eliasson Olafur, Olafur Eliasson, Phaidon, 2002, 137 Bal Mieke, Take Your Time: Olafur Eliasson, San Francisco Museum of Modern Art, 2007, 155 26 Morley Simon, Sublime, MIT Press, 2010, 12 25 9 it is now the man-made world of machines that produces in us many of the kinds of emotional states once associated with nature.’27 Birnabaum references this whilst interviewing Eliasson, ‘One could say that some of your pieces initially lure the spectator into a romantic position of believing in something, or rather of being part of an overwhelming almost natural experience, only to find a few seconds later that it was part of a machine?’28 As the viewer makes their way to the next floor they are once again forced to ascend a staircase, Grynsztejn asserts that ‘…one flight was built over the existing steps and brought the spectator uncomfortably close to the ceiling.’29 The disorientated spectator is again confronted by a new object of nature, a room with a subtly inclined floor of compressed, contaminated earth. There is reference to the Romantics paintings, in particular Wanderer Above a Sea of Fog, which becomes more apparent as the viewer is moving up through the gallery space as though it was a mountain, being confront by the sublimity of nature at each point. The contaminated earth (fig. 4) creating a strong sense of unease along with the inclined floor, the viewer is now fully immersed in the experience as the room is dry, hot, and barren. By creating a floor of earth that viewers must walk across Eliasson is playing with the representation of earth, in particular contaminated earth which normally would be avoided. Brining the viewer physically and mentally close to danger leads them question their cognitive constructs, Eliasson claims, ‘In fact there is nothing ‘real’ outside us, only cultural constructs.’30 As this room contains nothing but the earth on the ground the viewer is made aware of themselves in this space and their relationship with space and time, similar to the use of Rückenfigur, although as the viewer is experiencing the installation amongst other spectators Eliasson is playing with the collective experience. This hint to the collective causes 27 Morley Simon, Sublime, MIT Press, 2010, 20 Birnbaum Daniel, Olafur Eliasson, Phaidon, 2007, 10 29 Grynsztejn Madeleine, Take Your Time: Olafur Eliasson, Thames and Hudson, 2007, 121 30 Eliasson Olafur, Sublime, MIT Press, 2010, 123 28 10 the viewer to look at themselves as an individual and brings the realisation back to the predominance of cultural constructs around nature. As Birnabaum claims, ‘His work inspires a reflective stance, reminding the viewer of his or her position as an experiencing, bodily being and of the subjective condition of all interactions with the world (and with other embodied subjects).’31 On the final floor the spectator is greeted by a room of dense fog concealing a suspension bridge spanning the length of the gallery space (fig. 5). As the viewers traverse the bridge the fog engulfs the ground, the ceiling, to the point where the spectator can but see a few feet ahead of them, placing them in the unknown. For Elaisson this is crucial at this final stage of the installation as the spectator floor by floor is confronted it by the overwhelming, culminating at the top of the building, as if at the top of the highest peak of the mountain. Elaisson states: ….it is crucial not only to acknowledge that the experience itself is part of the process, but more importantly, that experience must be presented undisguised to the spectator. Otherwise, our ability to see ourselves seeing, to evaluate and criticize ourselves and our relation to space, has failed, and thus so has the museum’s socializing potential.32 Grynsztejn asserts that, ‘The journey came to an abrupt end at the far side of the bridge, where a dead end forced the visitor to turn around and descend.’33 In this moment Eliasson is physically referencing limitations, as the end of the bridge is physically where the spectator can continue no further. The bridge is the representation of human consciousness reaching its limits. As the viewer travels back down through each floor they are filled with a sense of failure, of reaching the ceiling of reason and understanding and forced to look at their relationship to both nature and the space and time it occupies. Eliasson speaks of his 31 Birnabaum Daniel, Take Your Time: Olafur Eliasson, Hudson and Thames, 2007, 136 Eliasson Olafur, Olafur Eliasson, Phaidon, 2002, 127 33 Grynsztejn Madeleine, Take Your Time: Olafur Eliasson, Thames and Hudson, 2007, 121 32 11 experience of sublimity, ‘Looking at nature, I find nothing, only my own relationship to the spaces, or aspects of my relationship to them.’34 34 Eliasson Olafur, Olafur Eliasson, Phaidon, 2002, 127 12 Conclusion The sublime dramatized the rhythm of transcendence in its extreme and purest form, for the sublime began where the conventional systems, readings of landscapes of text, broke down, and it found in that very collapse the foundation for another order of meaning.35 Mediated Motion brought notions of the sublime, explored in the treatises of Immanuel Kant and Edmund Burke and in practice by Romantic artists into a contemporary context, through generating nature with the use of modern technology. Elaisson like Friedrich brings the viewer to the edge of the mountain (edge of reason) allowing them a moment to contemplate, as Kant argues, ‘it is in restful contemplation…in the immensity of nature, we find our own limitations…making us recognize our own physical impotence, as beings of nature.’36 Although Elaisson does this is the contemporary art gallery, which brings the focus firmly of the devices of modern technology that are at play. Like other artists of his time, such as Walter De Maria and Robert Smithson, Elaisson brings the conversation around nature’s sublimity into a contemporary context. Eliasson shifts the focus onto the technology systems and their similarities to nature, as overwhelming, uncontrollable systems with the ability to transform the self. Using Kant’s theories of sublimity as a means for the spectator to experience the feeling reaching the ceiling of their understanding and reason, Eliasson physically brings the viewer to the end of a bridge. At this point Eliasson forces the spectator to walk back through the exhibition, making them contemplate what it was that inspired feeling of both awe and failure within themselves. This allows Eliasson to bring attention back to the spectator and their consciousness as the catalyst for the sublime experience. 35 Weiskel Thomas, The Romantic Sublime: Studies in the Structure and Psychology of Transcendence, The John Hopkins University Press, 1976, 22 36 Kant Immanuel, The Critique of Judgement, 1790; trans. J.J Meredith, Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press, 1973, 101-105 13 Illustrations Figure 1 Caspar David Friedrich, Wanderer Above the Sea of Fog (1818), oil on canvas, Hamburg, Germany Taken From; www.artble.com, Accessed 04/04/2017 Figure 2 Olafur Eliasson, Mediated Motion (2001), Kunsthaus Bregenz, Austria Taken From: Taken from: www.olafurelaisson.net, Accessed 04/04/2017 Figure 3 Olafur Eliasson, Mediated Motion (2001), Kunsthaus Bregenz, Austria Taken From: Taken from: www.olafurelaisson.net, Accessed 04/04/201 14 Figure 4 Olafur Eliasson, Mediated Motion (2001), Kunsthaus Bregenz, Austria Taken from: www.olafurelaisson.net, Accessed 04/04/2017 Figure 5 Olafur Eliasson. Mediated Motion (2001) Kunsthaus Bregenz, Austria Taken from: www.olafurelaisson.net, Accessed 04/04/2017 15 Bibliography BAL, Mieke Take Your Time: Olafur Eliasson, San Francisco Museum of Modern Art,2007. BURKE, Edmund A Philosophical Enquiry into the Origin of our Ideas of the Sublime and Beautiful, 1757. BIRNBAUM, Danie Olafur Eliasson, Phaidon, 2007. ELIASSON, Olafur Olafur Eliasson, Phaidon, 2002. GORRA, Michael The Bells in Their Silence: Travels Through Germany, Princeton University Press, 2009. GROSENICK, Uta and RIEMSCHNEIDER, Burkhard GRYNSZTEJN, Madeleine KANT, Immanuel KUL- WANT, Readers, Christopher MORLEY, Simon PHILLIPS, Adam WEISKEL, Thomas BELL, Julian Art Now, Taschen, 2002. Take Your Time: Olafur Eliasson, Thames and Hudson, 2007. Critique of Judgement ,1790; trans. J.J Meredith, Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press, 1973. Philosophers on Art from Kant to the Poster modernists; A Critical Columbia University Press, 2007. The Sublime, MIT Press, 2010. Edmund Burke: A philosophical Enquiry into the Origin of our Ideas of the Sublime and Beautiful, Oxford University Press, 1990. The Romantic Sublime: Studies in the Structure and Psychology of Transcendence Baltimore: John Hopkins University Press, 1976. The Art of The Sublime: The contemporary Sublime, http://www.tate.org.uk/art/research-publications/the-sublime/the-contemporarysublime-r1109224, Accessed 10/03/2017. CALLEY GALITZ, The Met Museum: Romanticism, Accessed 19/03/2017, http://www.metmuseum.org/toah/hd/roma/hd_roma.htm. Kathryn 16 All the images in this paper have been sourced from the following web pages: Figure 1 - Caspar David Friedrich, Wanderer Above the Sea of Fog (1818), oil on canvas, 95 cm x 75 cm Kunsthalle Hamburg, Germany Taken From; www.artble.com, Accessed 04/04/2017 Figure 2-5 - Olafur Eliasson, The Mediated Motion (2001), Kunsthaus Bregenz, Austria Taken from: www.olafurelaisson.net, Accessed 04/04/2017 17