Uploaded by jicksjoy99

AHistoryofRealAnalysis

advertisement
See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.net/publication/355444457
A History of Real Analysis
Preprint · October 2021
DOI: 10.13140/RG.2.2.15699.09764
CITATIONS
READS
0
3,451
1 author:
Harris R. Dela Cruz
Bulacan State University
4 PUBLICATIONS 0 CITATIONS
SEE PROFILE
All content following this page was uploaded by Harris R. Dela Cruz on 21 October 2021.
The user has requested enhancement of the downloaded file.
A History of Real Analysis
Harris R. Dela Cruz
College of Science, Bulacan State University
Abstract
Real analysis is a branch of mathematical analysis dealing with the real
numbers, sequence and series of real numbers, and real-valued functions of a
real variable. In particular, it deals with theories on limits, convergence, continuity,
differentiation, and integration. Although real analysis is distinguished from
complex analysis which deals with theories concerning the properties of complex
numbers and functions of complex variables, the two were not totally separated
and were developed almost simultaneously especially toward the recent century.
We present here a short history of real analysis.
Analysis in the Ancient Times
The history of analysis is intertwined with the quest of early mathematicians to
understand real numbers. In Greek mathematics, it was believed initially that all things
[with non-zero magnitude] can be measured using the natural numbers 1, 2, 3, and so
on, and their ratios, the rational numbers. This was first challenged by the discovery of
irrational numbers about 500 BCE when the Pythagorean Hippasus of Metapontum
pointed out to Pythagoras that the square root of 2 (the length of the diagonal of a
square with sides of length 1 unit) cannot be represented as a rational number (Tesleff,
2020). They have shown that the set of rational numbers is not sufficient in representing
measurements of even simple geometric objects.
While 2 challenged the concept of measurement, Zeno’s paradox of the
dichotomy challenged the concept of motion. According to Zeno, as recounted by
Aristotle (Physics, VI:9, 239b11),
“That which is in locomotion must arrive at the half-way stage before it
arrives at the goal.”
Suppose one wants to walk to the end of a path. Before the end is reached, one must
get halfway there. Before one can get halfway there, one must get a quarter of the way
there. Before traveling a quarter, one must travel one-eight, before that a one-sixteenth,
and so on. The total distance one needs to traverse is therefore
1=
1
2
+
1
4
+
1
8
+
1
16
···.
This would mean that one is required to perform [and finish] unlimited tasks in a limited
amount of time, which to Zeno at the time, was impossible. (Huggett, 2018)
Due to Zeno’s paradoxes, Greek mathematicians started to realize that the
concept of infinity was indispensable in the mathematics of continuous magnitude (one
which admits of being cut into an indefinite number of parts). In 350 BCE, the theory of
proportions was created by Eudoxus of Cnidus (as claimed in Euclid’s Element). He
developed the method of exhaustion to compute [and proved the formula] for the area of
a circle, and the volume of a sphere, a pyramid, and a cone (O'Connor & Robertson,
1999). He found the area of a circle by inscribing inside it a sequence of regular
polygons with increasing number of sides, As the number of sides becomes arbitrarily
large, the difference between the area of the polygon and that of the square becomes
arbitrarily small, and the possible values for the area of the circle are systematically
exhausted by the inscribed polygon. This was the first explicit, but informal, use of the
concept of limit and convergence.
Using the same method, in 225 BCE, Archimedes gave the first known example
of an infinite series with a finite sum. He showed that the area of a segment of a
parabola is 4/3 the area of a triangle with the same base and vertex by constructing an
infinite sequence of triangles between the existing ones and the parabola. He used this
same method of exhaustion to find an approximation of the area of a circle and an
ellipse, as well as the volume and the surface area of a sphere, a cone, and any
segment of a paraboloid and of a hyperboloid of revolution. (O'Connors & Robertson,
1996)
After Archimedes, the attention of Greek mathematics was shifted either to
number theory, mechanics, or astronomy, mainly inspired by Euclid. However, the
emergence of analysis during these times is not limited to Ancient Greece only.
According to Basant & Panda (2013), Acarya Bhadrabahu gives the sum of a geometric
series around 433-355 BCE in his Kalpasutra, but Singh (1936) suggested that the Jian
literature may contain accounts of Hindus having possession of the formula for the sum
of arithmetic and geometric series as early as 4th century BCE or even earlier.
Analysis during the Medieval Period
At the turn of the millennia, the method of exhaustion used by Eudoxus and
Archimedes continued to play a big role in furthering analysis as a different approach to
solving geometry problems. In 263 AD, the Chinese mathematician Liu Hui edited and
published the book Jiuzhang suanshu (Nine Chapters on the Mathematical Art) which
contains his use of the method of exhaustion in finding the area of a circle (Straffin, Jr.,
1998). The 5th-century mathematician Zu Chonzhi, together with his son Zu Genzhi,
wrote Zhui Shu (Methods for Interpolation), a mathematical text which is said to contain
formulas for the volume of a sphere, cubic equations, and an approximation of the value
of π (Ho, 1985). The method was later became known as Cavalieri’s principle, a modern
implementation of the method of indivisibles.
Meanwhile, during the 12th century, Indian mathematician Bhaskara II gave
some examples of derivatives using what is now known as Rolle’s Theorem. Although
most of differential and integral calculus was credited to Newton and Leibniz,
Goonatilaka (1998) believed that it was Bhaskara who first conceived the differential
coefficient and differential calculus, predating the two by over half a millennium. On the
other hand, according to Rajagopal & Rangachari (1978), Madhava of Sangamagrama
during the 14th century was the first to use infinite series approximation and developed
infinite series expansion, now called Taylor series. Although, most of the mathematical
works in India during the medieval period were lost,
Modern Real Analysis
The modern foundations of mathematical analysis were established in the 17th
century. Bonaventura Cavalieri was led to his method of indivisibles by Kepler's
attempts at integration. It appears that Cavalieri thought of an area as being made up of
components which were lines and then summed his infinite number of indivisibles.
Roberval considered problems of the same type but was much more rigorous than
Cavalieri. Gilles Roberval looked at the area between a curve and a line as being made
up of an infinite number of infinitely narrow rectangular strips. On the other hand, Pierre
de Fermat generalized the parabola and the hyperbola. He also investigated maxima
and minima by considering when the tangent to the curve was parallel to the 𝑥-axis.
(O'Connors & Robertson, 1996)
It was in 1637 that mathematical analysis was established when Rene Descartes
introduced the Cartesian coordinate system and proposed to unify algebra and
geometry into one subject, now known as analytic geometry (Descartes, 2006). A few
decades later, Isaac Newton and Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz independently developed
infinitesimal calculus. During this period, calculus techniques were applied to
approximate discrete problems by continuous ones. It was during these times that
differential and integral calculus flourished.
Afterward, the development of calculus was continued by Jacob Bernoulli and
Johann Bernoulli. However when Berkeley published his Analyst in 1734 attacking the
lack of rigor in the calculus and disputing the logic on which it was based much effort
was made to tighten the reasoning. Maclaurin attempted to put the calculus on a
rigorous geometrical basis but the really satisfactory basis for the calculus had to wait
for the work of Cauchy in the 19th Century. (O'Connors & Robertson, 1996)
Real analysis began to develop as an independent subject when Bernard
Bolzano introduced in 1816 the modern definition of continuity, which was not known
until the 1870s. By that time, Cauchy’s work had already put calculus on a firm logical
foundation in terms of geometric ideas and infinitesimals. His definition of continuity
required an infinitesimal change in 𝑥 to correspond to an infinitesimal change in 𝑦.
By the mid-19th century, Bernhard Reimann created what was now known as the
Riemann Integral. It was the first rigorous definition of the integral of a function on an
interval. For many functions and practical applications, the Riemann integral can be
evaluated by the fundamental theorem of calculus or approximated by numerical
integration.
In 1854, Karl Theodore William Weierstrass submitted his paper on Abelian
functions to the famous Crelle Mathematical Journal. Although most of his work was not
published because of his insistence of rigor in all of his proof, Karl Weierstrass is known
as the father of modern analysis. He formalized the definition of continuity of a function,
proved the intermediate value theorem, the first person to create a continuous function
that is nowhere differentiable, developed theory on Abelian functions, devised tests for
convergence of series, proved the sequential compactness theorem, now more
popularly known as the Bolzano-Weierstrass theorem, and contributed a great deal in
the theory of periodic functions, functions of a real variable, elliptic functions, infinite
products, and the calculus of variation. (O’Connor & Robertson, 1998)
Most of Weierstrass’ work was delivered through his lectures, and which he
continued to give until 1890, covering the theory of analytic functions, elliptic functions,
Abelian functions, and calculus of variation. Through the years, the courses developed
and a number of versions taken from the notes made by students who attended his
lectures have been published. Weierstrass' approach and style still dominate how
analysis is taught today.
References
Aristotle. (2000). Physics (R. P. Hardie & R. K. Gaye, Trans.). The Internet Classics
Archive. http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/physics.html
View publication stats
Basant, K. B., & Panda, S. (2013). Summation of Convergent Geometric Series and the
Concept of Approachable Sunya. Indian Journal of History of Science,
48.2(2013), 291-313.
Descartes, R. (2006). A Discourse on the Method (I. Maclean, Trans.). Oxford University
Press. (Original work published 1637)
Goonatilaka, S. (1998). Toward a Global Science: Mining Civilizational Knowledge.
Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Ho, P. Y. (1985). Li, Qi and Shu: An Introduction to Science and Civilization in China.
Hong Kong University Press.
Huggett, N. (2018). Zeno’s Paradoxes. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved
September 21, 2021, from https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/paradox-zeno/#Dic
O;Connor, J. J., & Robertson, E. F. (1998). Karl Theodor Wilhelm Weierstrass.
MacTutor. Retrieved September 21, 2021, from
https://mathshistory.st-andrews.ac.uk/Biographies/Weierstrass/
O.Connor, J. J., & Robertson, E. F. (1999). Eudoxus of Cnidus. MacTutor. Retrieved
September 21, 2021, from
https://mathshistory.st-andrews.ac.uk/Biographies/Eudoxus/
O'Connors, J. J., & Robertson, E. F. (1996). A History of the Calculus. MacTutor.
Retrieved September 21, 2021, from
https://mathshistory.st-andrews.ac.uk/HistTopics/The_rise_of_calculus/
Rajagopal, C. T., & Rangachari, M. S. (1978). On an untapped source of medieval
Keralese mathematics. Archive for History of Exact Sciences, 18, 89-102.
https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00348142
Singh, A. N. (1936). On the Use of Series in Hindi Mathematics. Osiris, 1, 606-628.
https://doi.org/10.1086/368443
Straffin, Jr., P. D. (1998). Liu Hui and the First Golden Age of Chinese Mathematics.
Mathematics Magazine, 71(3), 163-181. https://doi.org/10.2307/2691200
Thesleff, H. (2020). Pythagoreanism. Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 09 21, 2021,
from https://www.britannica.com/science/Pythagoreanism
Zill, D. G., Wright, S., & Wright, W. S. (2009). Calculus: Early Transcendentals (3rd ed.).
Jones & Bartlett Learning.
Download