568342 research-article2015 CDPXXX10.1177/0963721414568342Monroe, AndersonDepression: The Shroud of Heterogeneity Depression: The Shroud of Heterogeneity Scott M. Monroe and Samantha F. Anderson Current Directions in Psychological Science 2015, Vol. 24(3) 227­–231 © The Author(s) 2015 Reprints and permissions: sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.nav DOI: 10.1177/0963721414568342 cdps.sagepub.com University of Notre Dame Abstract Over the past several decades, depression has emerged as a major public health problem. Yet depression has not always represented such a prominent psychiatric condition, and the term depression has harbored different meanings over time. One widely agreed upon way of explaining such variation in what depression implies has been to describe depression as being heterogeneous. In the present article, depression is examined in relation to different types of heterogeneity, particularly with regard to the concept of a syndrome. The consequences of various meanings of heterogeneity for understanding the nature of depression are then explored. Finally, we speculate on the implications for the future of depression research and practice. Keywords depression, classification, diagnosis, heterogeneity, psychological disorders Over the past few decades, depression has emerged as one of the most prominent mental disorders and pressing public health problems. It is currently the leading cause of disease-related disability worldwide (World Health Organization, 2012). Long known as one of the most significant contributors to suicide, depression now is recognized to be associated with life-threatening diseases (e.g., coronary heart disease and diabetes). Without question, a strong consensus exists about the importance of this highly prevalent and destructive condition (Monroe & Harkness, 2011). However, depression has not always been viewed as such a serious problem. Some contend that only 50 years ago depression was a relatively rare and obscure psychiatric condition, confined largely to the severely afflicted in the back wards of psychiatric hospitals (Healy, 1997). And although descriptions approximating what we currently label depression can be traced far back into history, what “depression” signifies has also varied considerably over time and place (Berrios, 1988; Jackson, 1986). This semantic elasticity is detectable in contemporary incarnations of the term: “Depression” carries with it many connotations, which in turn contribute to ongoing confusion about its nature and classification (Cole, McGuffin, & Farmer, 2008; Parker, 2014). This problem of multiple meanings is evident in even the most basic of tasks: defining clinical depression. According to current practices, two people can be diagnosed with an episode of major depression without sharing a single symptom. Although patients may have symptoms in common, there are sundry alternative and unique constellations of signs and symptoms that can qualify for a formal diagnosis of major depression (American Psychiatric Association, 2013). With some lifetime estimates for the prevalence of major depression exceeding 40% (Moffitt et al., 2010), unprecedented numbers of individuals are becoming depressed, and doing so in potentially many different ways. Statistics such as these must give pause to many. The skeptic might wonder how two people could suffer from the same underlying disorder but not share any of its core defining attributes. The cynic might dismiss the situation as a social construction of contemporary culture. And the historian might wonder how things could have changed so dramatically over such a brief period of time—or even if the construct of depression is becoming so general and diffuse that it no longer serves a useful purpose and will return to its putative obscurity of the early 1960s. Our goal in the present article is to consider how depression has come to be what it appears to be today, and to suggest how such an analysis can inform expectations for the future. While inconsistencies and controversies abound, the field approaches unanimity on one Corresponding Author: Scott M. Monroe, Department of Psychology, 118 Haggar Hall, University of Notre Dame, Notre Dame, IN 46556 E-mail: smonroe1@nd.edu Monroe, Anderson 228 Table 1. DSM-5 Criteria A Symptoms for Major Depressive Disorder Five (or more) of the following symptoms have been present during the same 2-week period and represent a change from previous functioning; at least one of the symptoms is either (1) depressed mood or (2) loss of interest or pleasure. Note: Do not include symptoms that are clearly attributable to another medical condition. 1. Depressed mood most of the day, nearly every day, as indicated by either subjective report (e.g., feels sad, empty, hopeless) or observation made by others (e.g., appears tearful). 2. Markedly diminished interest or pleasure in all, or almost all, activities most of the day, nearly every day (as indicated either by subjective account or observation). 3. Significant weight loss when not dieting or weight gain (e.g., a change of more than 5% of body weight in a month), or decrease or increase in appetite nearly every day. 4. Insomnia or hypersomnia nearly every day. 5. Psychomotor agitation or retardation nearly every day (observable by others, not merely subjective feelings of restlessness or being slowed down). 6. Fatigue or loss of energy nearly every day. 7. Feelings of worthlessness or excessive or inappropriate guilt (which may be delusional) nearly every day (not merely selfreproach or guilt about being sick). 8. Diminished ability to think or concentrate, or indecisiveness, nearly every day (either by subjective account or as observed by others). 9. Recurrent thoughts of death (not just fear of dying), recurrent suicidal ideation without a specific plan, or a suicide attempt or specific plan for committing suicide. Note: Adapted and reprinted from the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (5th ed.; pp. 160–161), by the American Psychiatric Association, 2013, Arlington, VA: American Psychiatric Publishing. Copyright 2013 by the American Psychiatric Association. Reprinted with permission. point: Depression, as currently conceived, encompasses a broad range of mental and physical states. Depression is heterogeneous. Consequently, we focus on this theme of heterogeneity and its implications for depression. Heterogeneity in Depression Most simply, heterogeneity refers to variation in signs (observable manifestations), symptoms (subjective reports), and syndromes (combinations of signs and symptoms associated with depression). The phenotypic expression of depression (i.e., presenting signs and symptoms) can vary substantially from one depressed person to another. This may be in terms of both the severity of specific indicators and the range of symptoms. Heterogeneity in this sense can be expanded, also, to address variation in clinical course over time. Overall, this phenotypic or horizontal heterogeneity is confined to the observable or reportable features of depression. Heterogeneity also refers to variation in the theoretical causes, or etiology, of depression. On the one hand, this can be straightforward: Different causes lead to the shared phenotype of depression. For example, one person may become depressed in response to life stress, whereas another may become depressed as a result of a genetic predisposition. This vertical heterogeneity implies that there are distinctive subtypes of depression with their own particular causes. However, etiologic heterogeneity can be more difficult to pin down. The causes of depression often are referred to as “multifactorial.” This position compounds the heterogeneity problem. First, it means that many factors contribute to depression. These individual factors, though, vary in their effects across persons, such that heterogeneous causal arrangements can bring about depression. Second, it suggests that there is a “final common pathway” through which these alternative causal complexes converge, initiate, and ultimately orchestrate the features of depression (Akiskal & McKinney, 1975). Thus, although different vulnerabilities might bring about depression, they eventually do so via common mechanisms and processes. The critic might begin to wonder why people with so many phenotypic and etiologic differences are believed to suffer from the same disorder. To understand this, we next take a more basic look at the defining features of major depression. Heterogeneity and the Defining Features of Depression What are the criteria for defining clinical depression, and how are they brought together to diagnose an episode? Can an analysis at this level shed further light upon the heterogeneity problem? Table 1 lists the symptoms of major depression as specified in the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders, fifth edition (DSM-5; American Psychiatric Association, 2013). Most of the individual symptoms of depression are readily recognizable as extensions of common human feeling states. These include emotional and physical responses to everyday life, as well as to the less frequent Depression: The Shroud of Heterogeneity major challenges of human existence. It is the unusual person in the population who does not evidence any of these symptoms to some degree. To some extent, depression is a part of everyday life. Depression and its features, then, can be both a part of normal functioning and a severe psychological disorder. The criteria listed in Table 1 are imperfect indicators of the clinical meaning of depression. This is yet another form of heterogeneity, a dimensional one, wherein the continuum of depression’s symptoms blends normal, understandable, everyday negative emotions with more psychopathological states. Although the diagnosis of depression also requires a number of other criteria be met (American Psychiatric Association, 2013), there is no attention to the patterning of the indicators for a primary diagnosis. All combinations are presumed to be of equal information value. Given the symptoms of depression, part of the heterogeneity of depression can be easily explained. This is because there could be serial dependencies between some of the symptoms. For example, someone with “troubles sleeping” will also likely experience “fatigue or loss of energy” and “diminished ability to think or concentrate.” Some researchers even contend that depression can be explained at this phenotypic or symptom level, without recourse to assumptions about underlying mechanisms or disorders (Borsboom & Cramer, 2013). More generally, many people can be diagnosed with depression yet exhibit symptoms that vary widely and whose origins can be traced to very different underpinnings. One might ask, again, why it is assumed that depressed persons whose symptoms sometimes appear similar, sometimes rather different—and sometimes entirely different—suffer from one common disorder. We suggest that this passive acceptance of heterogeneity stems from confusion about what a syndrome represents in science and medicine. The Premise and the Promise of a Syndrome Technically, as defined by the Oxford English Dictionary, a syndrome is “a concurrence of several symptoms in a disease” (“Syndrome,” n.d.). The syndrome concept helps to explain similarities—not perfect likenesses—in the concurrences and course of symptoms. Not all persons suffering from the same condition will display the exact same constellation of signs and symptoms or an identical clinical course. The general similarities, however, can be sufficient to suggest a distinctive syndrome, which in turn can be an indicator of a distinctive disorder. Distinguishing a specific syndrome has many advantages. It supplies a working definition for a condition of, 229 as yet, unknown origins. Importantly, it also implies a common underlying pathophysiology (e.g., shared mechanisms and processes), which likely results from the same etiology. Most importantly, these hypothetical shared mechanisms provide the meaning and coherence associated with the particular arrangement of signs, symptoms, and courses: They cohere because of the orchestrating influences of these underlying mechanisms. More generally, a syndrome recognizes yet unites “noisy” variation in the manifestations of a disorder. This helps to mitigate the larger heterogeneity problem and to carve out a more homogenous entity; it also enhances the likelihood of finding a common underlying pathophysiology and possible cause. With a deeper understanding of these matters, treatment and prevention can be more effectively developed based upon recognized causes and mechanisms. But can there be a potential problem with such reasoning? By permitting some degree of heterogeneity in symptoms, a syndrome helps to identify potentially similar conditions that have variability in their phenotypic expression. But at what point might heterogeneity become an unproductive way to think about the matter, a conceptual carte blanche? The allure of a distinctive syndrome may blind investigators to the illusions that it can foster. The Dark Side of the Syndrome Concept The syndrome concept is an integral tool in science and medicine. But the slippery part of classification and diagnosis is the process of “recognizing things to be alike when they are not identical,” as well as to be different when they appear similar (Bronowski, 1978, p. 21). It is in this vague and imprecise realm that problems can arise and vague insights based on imperfect similarities and differences eventually may prove to be clear oversights. Specifically, when are similarities and differences sufficient to demarcate a distinctive syndrome? With regard to depression, how can phenotypes that share few, or no, overlapping features reflect the same syndrome and, in effect, a common underlying disorder? In essence, what are the boundaries of the syndrome concept? Little attention has been paid to this question. In part, this is because the idea of a syndrome has become such an entrenched and overpowering premise. In theory, a syndrome not only carves out a specific condition, it also presupposes a concrete pathophysiology and cause, simplified down to presumed basic biological mechanisms and processes. If a syndrome can be distinguished—or declared, it creates an aura—or an illusion—that the problem is well on its way to being resolved. Monroe, Anderson 230 It is this aura surrounding the syndrome premise that is important to consider. A syndrome confers an air of certainty—scientific, medical, and cultural legitimacy. It serves as a reassuring placeholder for the eventual and inexorable discovery of the true disorder and its biological causes. With these extra-theoretical functions, a syndrome begins to reify all conditions that fall under its patronage. Thus sanctioned, heterogeneity becomes malleable and may potentially be appropriated for misleading professional, social, economic, and scientific agendas. No longer are symptoms arranged in some consequential way to signify underlying mechanisms and possible etiology. Rather, they have become a constellation of symptoms—many rather common over the course of life—and, as such, perhaps no more intrinsically meaningful than the constellations of stars in the heavens above (Mirowksy & Ross, 1989). Depression at a Crossroads? About 100 years ago, Americans were afflicted with a mental disorder of epidemic proportions (Schuster, 2011). Called neurasthenia, and often referred to as the “American disease,” it began its medical odyssey as a disabling condition, with sundry signs and symptoms, often overlapping with what today we would call depression, anxiety, fatigue, and general malaise. It was an attractive alternative to the more stigmatizing diagnoses of the day (thought to be degenerative and highly heritable). Presumed to be firmly anchored in biological origins, initially considered to afflict only society’s elite, and believed to be treatable, neurasthenia in time caught the attention of legions. It helped to encapsulate, explain, embody, and legitimate a multitude of ailments and miseries. All but unknown in America today, neurasthenia provides a fascinating reference point for thinking about current-day problems and misconceptions about depression. For some 30 years, neurasthenia was the de facto explanation for an expanding array of uncomfortable and overwhelming physical and mental states. But the more heterogeneous the conditions that neurasthenia came to subsume and to legitimize, the less useful it became. Neurasthenia largely faded from medical nomenclature in America after about 1910. Could such a fate await depression? “Major depression” officially entered the psychiatric nomenclature in 1980 (American Psychiatric Association, 1980; Hirshbein, 2007). Through good intentions over the intervening 30-plus years, depression has become increasingly widely recognized through public awareness campaigns, the media, and education programs for general practitioners. Further, because Americans live in one of the very few countries in the world allowing direct-to-consumer pharmaceutical advertising, the American population has become unusually well versed via television commercials in the warning signs of, and availability of pharmaceutical treatments for, depression. Arguably, perhaps no other society has ever been so attuned to, or concerned about, its emotional wellbeing. All of these factors likely have catapulted depression into the psychiatric and social limelight and expanded its “detection” and diagnosis over time. We speculate that depression, as we currently know it, will not be sustained much longer. The point has been reached where respected spokespersons on the topic are in stark disagreement. Some lament the “loss of sadness,” contending that understandable unhappiness has become overly medicalized as major depression (Horwitz & Wakefield, 2007). In contrast, others contend that depression has been overly romanticized and, even in its mildest forms, eventually will be eradicated from society (Kramer, 2005). Should these diametrically opposing viewpoints be politely shrugged off as additional reflections of “heterogeneity”? There are good reasons to be optimistic about progress that can come from insights into the heterogeneity problems in depression. These may be partially resolved through distinguishing clinically meaningful subtypes, which in turn could guide investigators toward discovering more substantive syndromes. For instance, recent research suggests that major depression can be a destructive and highly recurrent disorder or a more benign and time-limited condition (e.g., Wakefield & Schmitz, 2014). As yet, little is known about what distinguishes the firstonset cases of depression who will never suffer a recurrence from those who will do so repeatedly—why or how someone who becomes clinically depressed for the first time does or does not suffer subsequent recurrences (Monroe & Harkness, 2011). The recent National Institutes of Mental Health Research Domain Criteria (RDoC) initiative, too, holds promise for tightening our understanding of depression and its boundaries (Cuthbert & Kozak, 2013). The RDoC project promotes the identification of syndromes based upon pathophysiology, with a primary focus on neural circuitry and its relationships with behavior. Such an approach could realign the syndrome concept as originally intended, reflecting specific underlying mechanisms—not presupposing them. By removing the shroud of heterogeneity, advances along lines such as these may be made to help so many people suffering from such mysterious and multifarious conditions. Recommended Reading Borsboom, D., & Cramer, A. O. J. (2013). (See References). An interesting article that introduces an alternative way to conceptualize the interrelations of signs, symptoms, and syndromes. Depression: The Shroud of Heterogeneity Horwitz, A. V., & Wakefield, J. C. (2007). (See References). A book whose authors provide an in-depth and careful analysis of the challenges involved in distinguishing responses to adversity and understandable unhappiness from the disorder of major depression. Kramer, P. D. (2005). (See References). An insightful and very readable account of the destructive biological aspects of depression. Monroe, S. M., & Harkness, K. L. (2011). (See References). A review article that makes the case that the likelihood of recurrence of major depression has been overestimated and that the emphasis on the recurrent forms of depression has overshadowed the substantial number of people who have only one episode over the life course. Wakefield, J. C., & Schmitz, M. F. (2014). (See References). A recent empirical study that demonstrates the potential for distinguishing subtypes of depression that have very different clinical implications over the life course. Acknowledgments S. M. Monroe gratefully acknowledges support from the John Simon Guggenheim Memorial Foundation. Declaration of Conflicting Interests The authors declared that they had no conflicts of interest with respect to their authorship or the publication of this article. References Akiskal, H. S., & McKinney, W. T., Jr. (1975). Overview of recent research in depression: Integration of ten conceptual models into a comprehensive clinical frame. Archives of General Psychiatry, 32, 285–305. American Psychiatric Association. (1980). Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders (3rd ed.). Washington, DC: Author. American Psychiatric Association. (2013). Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders (5th ed.). Arlington, VA: American Psychiatric Publishing. Berrios, G. E. (1988). Melancholia and depression during the 19th century: A conceptual history. British Journal of Psychiatry, 153, 298–304. Borsboom, D., & Cramer, A. O. J. (2013). Network analysis: An integrative approach to the structure of psychopathology. Annual Review of Clinical Psychology, 9, 91–121. doi:10.1146/annurev-clinpsy-050212-185608 231 Bronowski, J. (1978). The common sense of science. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Cole, J., McGuffin, P., & Farmer, A. E. (2008). The classification of depression: Are we still confused? The British Journal of Psychiatry, 192, 83–85. Cuthbert, B. N., & Kozak, M. J. (2013). Constructing constructs for psychopathology: The NIMH research domain criteria. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 122, 928–937. Healy, D. (1997). The antidepressant era. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Hirshbein, L. D. (2009). American melancholy: Constructions of depression in the twentieth century. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press. Horwitz, A. V., & Wakefield, J. C. (2007). The loss of sadness: How psychiatry transformed normal sorrow into depressive disorder. New York, NY: Oxford University Press. Jackson, S. W. (1986). Melancholia and depression. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press Kramer, P. D. (2005). Against depression. New York, NY: Viking. Mirowsky, J., & Ross, C. E. (1989). Psychiatric diagnosis as reified measurement. Journal of Health and Social Behavior, 30, 11–25. Moffitt, T. E., Caspi, A., Taylor, A., Kokaua, J., Milne, B. J., Polanczyk, G., & Poulton, R. (2010). How common are common mental disorders? Evidence that lifetime prevalence rates are doubled by prospective versus retrospective ascertainment. Psychological Medicine, 40, 899–909. doi:10.1017/S0033291709991036 Monroe, S. M., & Harkness, K. L. (2011). Recurrence in major depression: A conceptual analysis. Psychological Review, 118, 655–674. doi:10.1037/a002519 Parker, G. (2014). Is major depression that major? Acta Psychiatrica Scandinavica, 129, 458–459. Schuster, D. G. (2011). Neurasthenic nation: America’s search for health, happiness, and comfort, 1869-1920. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press. Syndrome. (n.d.). In The Oxford English dictionary (2nd ed.). Retrieved from http://eresources.library.nd.edu/databases/oed Wakefield, J. C., & Schmitz, M. F. (2014). Predictive validation of single-episode uncomplicated depression as a benign subtype of unipolar major depression. Acta Psychiatrica Scandinavica, 129, 445–457. doi:10.1111/acps.12184 World Health Organization. (2012, October). Depression fact sheet. Retrieved from http:// http://www.who.int/mediacentre/factsheets/fs369/en/