Mathematical Logic A Course with Exercises Part 1: Propositional calculus, Boolean algebras, Predicate calculus Rene Cori and Daniel Lascar Equipe de Logique Mathematique Universite Paris VII Translated by Donald H. Pelletier York University, Toronto OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS Mathematical Logic A Course with Exercises This book has been printed digitally and produced in a standard specification in order to ensure its continuing availability OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS Great Clarendon Street, Oxford OX2 6DP Oxford University Press is a departinent of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University's objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide in Oxford New York Auckland Bangkok Buenos Aires Cape Town Chennai Dar es Salaan1 Delhi Hong Kong Istanbul Karachi Kolkata Kuala Ltnnpur Madrid Melboun1e Mexico City Mtunbai Nairobi Sao Paulo Shanghai Singapore Taipei Tokyo Toronto Oxford is a registered trade 1nark of Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries Published in the United States by Oxford University Press Inc., New York This English Edition © Oxford University Press 2000 Published with the help of the Ministere de la Culture First published in French as Logique mathematique © Masson, Editeur, Paris, 1993 The n1oral rights of the author have been asserted Database right Oxford University Press (1naker) Reprinted 2002 All rights reserved. No part of this publication 1nay be reproduced, stored in a retrieval systen1, or trans1nitted, in any fonn or by any 1neans, without the prior pennission in writing of Oxford University Press. or as expressly pennitted by law, or under tenns agreed with the appropriate reprographics rights organization. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the above should be sent to the Rights Depart1nent, Oxford University Press, at the address above You n1ust not circulate this book in any other binding or cover and you n1ust i1npose this sa1ne condition on any acquirer ISBN 0-19-850049-1 Foreword to the Original French edition ----·-··- ·-· Jean-Louis Krivine In France, the discipline of logic has traditionally been ignored in university-level scientific studies. This follows, undoubtedly, from the recent history of mathe­ matics in our country which was dominated, for a long while, by the Bourbaki school for whom logic was not, as we know, a strong point. Indeed, logic origi­ nates from reflecting upon mathematical activity and the common gut-reaction of the mathematician is to ask: 'What is all that good for? We are not philosophers and it is surely not by cracking our skulls over modus ponens or the excluded middle that we will resolve the great conjectures, or even the tiny ones . . . ' Not so fast! A new ingredient, of some substance, has come to settle this somewhat byzantine debate over the importance of logic: the explosion of computing into all areas of economic and scientific life, whose shock wave finally reached the mathematicians themselves. And, little by little, one fact dawns on us: the theoretical basis for this nascent science is nothing other than the subject of all this debate, mathematical logic. It is true that certain areas of logic were put to use more quickly than oth­ ers. Boolean algebra, of course, for the notions and study of circuits; recursive­ ness, which is the study of functions that are computable by machine; Herbrand's theorem, resolution and unification, which form the basis of 'logic programming' (the language PROLOG); proof theory, and the diverse incarnations of the Com­ pleteness theorem, which have proven themselves to be powerful analytical tools for mature programming languages. But, at the rate at which things are going, we can imagine that even those areas that have remained completely 'pure', such as set theory, for example, will soon see their turn arrive. As it ought to be, the interaction is not one-way, far from it; a flow of ideas and new, deep intuitions, arising from computer science, has come to animate all these sectors of logic. This discipline is now one of the liveliest there is in mathematics and it is evolving very rapidly. So there is no doubt about the utility and timeliness of a work devoted to a general introduction to logic; this book meets its destiny. Derived from lectures for the Dipl6me d'Etudes Approfondies (DEA) of Logic and the Foundations of c:omputing at the University of Paris VII, it covers a vast panorama: Boolean . Vl F O R E W O R D T O T H E O R IG I N A L F R E N C H E D I T I O N algebras, recursiveness, model theory, set theory, models of arithmetic and Godel's theorems. The concept of model is at the core of this book, and for a very good reason since it occupies a central place in logic: despite (or thanks to) its simple, and even elementary, character, it illuminates all areas, even those that seem farthest from it How, for example� can one understand a consistency proof in set theory without first mastering the concept of being a model of this theory? How can one truly grasp Godel 's theorems without having some notion of non-standard models of Peano arithmetic? The acquisition of these semantic notions is, I believe, the mark of a proper training for a logician, at whatever level. R. Cori and D. Lascar know this well and their text proceeds from beginning to end in this direction. Moreover, they have overcome the risky challenge of blending all the necessary rigour with clarity, pedagogical concern and refreshing readability. We have here at our disposal a remarkable tool for teaching mathematical logic and, in view of the growth in demand for this subject area, it should meet with a marked success. This is, naturally, everything I wish for it. Foreword to the English edition Wilfrid Hodges School ofMathematical Sciences Queen Mary and Wes{field College University of London There are two kinds of introduction to a subject. The first kind assumes that you know nothing about the subject, and it tries to show you in broad brushstrokes why the subject is worth studying and what its achievements are. The second kind of introduction takes for granted that you know what the subject is about and why you want to study it, and sets out to give you a reliable understanding of the basics. Rene Cori and Daniel Lascar have written the second sort of introduction to mathematical logic. The mark of the book is thoroughness and precision with a light touch and no pedantry. The volume in your hand, Part I, is a mathematical introduction to first-order logic. This has been the staple diet of elementary logic courses for the last fifty years, but the treatment here is deeper and more thorough than most elementary logic courses. For example the authors prove the compactness theorem in a general form that needs Zorn's Lemma. You certainly shouldn't delay reading it until you know about Zorn's Lemma - the applications here are an excellent way of learning how to use the lemma. In Part I there are not too many excitements - probably the most exciting topic in the book is the Godel theory in Chapter 6 of Part II, unless you share my enthusiasm for the model theory in Chapter 8. But there are plenty of beautiful explanations, put together with the clarity and elegance that one expects from the best French authors. For English students the book is probably best suited to Masters' or fourth-year undergraduate studies. The authors have included full solutions to the exercises; this is one of the best ways that an author can check the adequacy of the definitions and lemmas in the text, but it is also a great kindness to people who are studying on their own, as a beginning research student may be. Some thirty-five years ago I found I needed to teach myself logic, and this book would have fitted my needs exactly. Of course the subject has moved on since then, and the authors have included several things that were unknown when 1 was a student. For example their chapter on proof theory, Chapter 4 in this volume, includes a well-integrated section on the resolution calculus. They mention the connection with PROLOG; but in fact you can also use this section as an introduction to the larger topic Vlll F O R E W O R D T O THE E NGL I S H E D I T I O N of unification and pattern-matching, which has wide ramifications in computer science. One other thing you should know. This book comes from the famous Equipe de Logique Mathematique at the University of Paris, a research team that has had an enormous inft uence on the development of mathematical logic and its links with other branches of mathematics. Read it with confidence. . Preface This book is based upon several years' experience teaching logic at the UFR of Mathematics of the University of Paris 7, at the beginning graduate level as well as within the DEA of Logic and the Foundations of Computer Science. As soon as we began to prepare our first lectures, we realized that it was going to be very difficult to introduce our students to general works about logic written in (or even translated into) French. We therefore decided to take advantage of this opportunity to correct the situation. Thus the first versions of the eight chapters that you are about to read were drafted at the same time that their content was being taught. We insist on warmly thanking all the students who contributed thereby to a tangible improvement of the initial presentation. Our thanks also go to all our colleagues and logician friends, from Paris 7 and elsewhere, who brought us much appreciated help in the form of many comments and moral support of a rare quality. Nearly all of them are co-authors of this work since, to assemble the lists of exercises that accompany each chapter, we have borrowed unashamedly from the invaluable resource that comprises the hundreds and hundreds of pages of written material that were handed out to students over the course of more than twenty-five years during which the University of Paris 7, a pioneer in this matter, has organized courses in logic open to a wide public. At this point, the reader generally expects a phrase of the following type: 'they are so numerous that we are obviously unable to name them all'. It is true, there are very many to whom we extend our gratitude, but why shouldn't we attempt to name them all? Thank you therefore to Josette Adda, Marouan Ajlani, Daniel Andler, Gilles Amiot, Fred Appenzeller, Jean-Claude Archer, Jean-Pierre Azra, Jean­ Pierre Benejam, Chantal Berline, Claude-Laurent Bernard, Georges Blanc, Elisabeth Bouscaren, Albert Burroni, Jean-Pierre Calais, Zoe Chatzidakis, Peter Clote, Fran<;ois Conduche, Jean Coret, Maryvonne Daguenet, Vincent Danos, Max Dickmann, Patrick Dehornoy, Fran<;oise Delon, Florence Duchene, Jean- Louis Duret, Marie-Christine Ferbus, Jean-Yves Girard, Daniele Gondard, Catherine Gourion, SergeGrigorieff, Ursula Gropp, Philippelthier, Bernard Jaulin, Ying Jiang, Anatole Khelif, Georg Kreisel, Jean-Louis Krivine, Ramez Labib­ Sami, Daniel Lacombe, Thierry Lacoste, Richard Lassaigne, Yves Legrandgerard, Alain Louveau, Fran�ois Lucas, Kenneth MacAloon, Gilles Macario-Rat, Sophie Malecki, Jean Malifaud, Pascal Manoury, Franc;ois Metayer, Marie-Helene Mourgues, Catherine Muhlrad-Greif, Francis Oger, Michel Parigot, Donald X P R EFACE Pelletier, Marie-Jeanne Perrin, B runo Poizat, Jean Porte, Claude Pn�cetti, Christophe Raffalli, Laurent Regnier, Jean-Pierre Ressayre, Iegor Reznikoff, Philippe Royer, Paul Roziere, Gabriel Sabbagh, Claire Santoni, Marianne Simonot, Gerald Stahl, Jacques Stern, Anne Strauss, Claude Sureson, Jacques Van de Wiele, Franc;oise Ville. We wish also to pay homage to the administrative and technical work accom­ plished by Mesdames Sylviane Barrier, Gisele Goeminne, and Claude Orieux. May those whom we have forgotten forgive us. They are so numerous that we are unable to name them all. September 1993 The typographical errors in the first printing were so numerous that even Alain Kapur was unable to locate them all. May he be assured of all our encouragement for the onerous task that still awaits him. We also thank Edouard Dorard and Thierry Joly for their very careful reading. Contents ---- ------- ---- ----- Contents of Part II Notes from the translator Notes to the reader Introduction 1 Propositional calculus 1 . 1 Syntax 1 . 1 . 1 Propositional formulas 1 . 1 .2 Proofs by induction on the set of formulas 1 . 1.3 The decomposition tree of a formula 1 . 1 .4 The unique decomposition theorem 1 . 1 .5 Definitions by induction on the set of formulas 1 . 1 .6 Substitutions in a propositional formula 1 .2 Semantics 1 .2. 1 Assignments of truth values and truth tables 1 .2.2 Tautologies and logically equivalent formulas 1.2.3 Some tautologies 1 .3 Normal forms and complete sets of connectives 1.3.1 Operations o n {0 1} and formulas 1 .3.2 Normal forms 1.3.3 Complete sets of connectives 1 .4 The interpolation lemma 1.4.1 Interpolation lemma 1 .4.2 The definability theorem 1 .5 The compactness theorem 1 .5 . 1 Satisfaction o f a set o f formulas 1 .5.2 The compactness theorem for propositional calculus 1 .6 Exercises for Chapter I .. 2 Boolean algebras 2.1 Algebra and topology review 2 . 1 . 1 Algebra 2 . 1 .2 Topology 2.1.3 An application to propositiona1 calculus 2.2 Definition of Boolean algebra 2.2. 1 Properties of Boolean algebras, order relations . XIV . XVI . . xvu ] 7 8 8 11 13 15 18 19 21 21 27 31 34 34 38 40 42 42 44 45 45 48 53 63 64 64 67 71 71 72 CONTENTS Xll 2.2.2 Boolean algebras as ordered sets 2.3 2.4 2.5 2.6 2.7 3 Atoms in a Boolean algebra Homomorphisms, isomorphisms, subalgebras 2.4.1 Homomorphisms and isomorphisms 2.4.2 Boolean subalgebras Ideals and filters 2.5 . 1 Properties of ideals 2.5.2 Maximal ideals 2.5.3 Filters 2.5.4 Ultrafilters 2.5.5 Filterbases Stone's theorem 2.6.1 The Stone space of a Boolean algebra 2.6.2 Stone's theorem 2.6.3 Boolean spaces are Stone spaces Exercises for Chapter 2 Predicate calculus 3 .1 Syntax 3 .1.1 First order languages 3 .1.2 Terms of the language 3 . 1 . 3 Substitutions in terms 3 . 1 .4 Formulas of the language 3 .1.5 Free variables, bound variables, and closed formulas 3 .1.6 Substitutions in formulas 3.2 Structures 3.2.1 Models o f a language 3.2.2 Substructures and restrictions 3.2.3 Homomorphisms and isomorphisms 3.3 Satisfaction of formulas in structures 3.3.1 Interpretation in a structure of the terms 3.3.2 Satisfaction of the formulas in a structure 3.4 Universal equivalence and semantic consequence 3.5 Prenex forms and Skolem forms 3.5.1 Prenex forms 3.5.2 Skolem forms 3.6 First steps in model theory 3.6. 1 Satisfaction in a substructure 3.6.2 Elementary equivalence 3.6.3 The language associated with a structure and formulas with parameters 3.6.4 Functions and relations definable in a structure 75 79 81 81 86 88 88 91 93 94 96 97 98 102 102 106 112 113 113 115 121 122 125 127 130 131 133 135 1 37 137 140 147 157 157 160 165 1 65 170 174 176 CONTENTS 3 .7 3.8 4 Models that may not respect equality Exercises for Chapter 3 The completeness theorems 4. 1 Formal proofs (or derivations) 4. 1 . 1 Axioms and rules 4. 1 .2 Formal proofs 4. 1 .3 The finiteness theorem and the deduction theorem 4.2 Henkin models 4.2 . 1 Henkin witnesses 4.2.2 The completeness theorem 4.3 Herbrand's method 4.3. 1 Some examples 4.3.2 The avatars of a formula 4.4 Proofs using cuts 4.4. 1 The cut rule 4.4.2 Completeness of the method 4. 5 The method of resolution 4.5 . 1 Unification 4.5.2 Proofs by resolution 4.6 Exercises for Chapter 4 Xlll 179 1 82 193 1 94 1 94 1 96 200 202 203 205 209 209 212 217 217 221 224 224 230 241 Solutions to the exercises of Part I Chapter 1 Chapter 2 Chapter 3 Chapter 4 245 270 293 320 Bibliography 330 Index 332 Contents of Part II 5 6 7 Recursion theory 5 . 1 Primitive recursive functions and sets 5. 1 . 1 Some initial definitions 5 . 1 .2 Examples and closure properties 5.1 .3 Coding of sequences 5.2 Recursive functions 5 .2.1 Ackerman's functions 5 .2.2 The M-Operator and the partial recursive functions 5.3 Turing machines 5.3.1 Description o f Turing machines 5.3.2 T-computable functions 5.3.3 T-computable partial functions are recursive 5.3.4 Universal Turing machines 5.4 Recursively enumerable sets 5.4 . 1 Recursive and recursively enumerable sets 5 .4.2 The halting problem 5.4.3 The smn theorem 5.4.4 The fixed point theorems 5.5 Exercises for Chapter 5 Formalization of arithmetic , Godel 's theorems 6. 1 Peano's axioms 6. 1 . 1 The axioms 6. 1 .2 The ordering on the integers 6.2 Representable functions 6.3 Arithmetization of syntax 6.3. 1 The coding of formulas 6.3.2 The coding of proofs 6.4 Incompleteness and undecidability theorems 6.4. 1 Undecidability of arithmetic and predicate calculus 6.4.2 Godel's incompleteness theorems 6.5 Exercises for Chapter 6 Set theory 7 . 1 The theories Z and ZF 7. 1 .1 The axioms CONTENTS 7 .1.2 7.2 7.3 7.4 7.5 7.6 8 Pairs, relations and maps Ordinal numbers and integers 7.2.1 Well-ordered sets 7 .2.2 The ordinals 7 .2.3 Operations on ordinal numbers 7.2.4 The integers Inductive proofs and definitions 7.3. 1 lnduction 7 .3.2 The axiom of choice Cardinality 7.4.1 Cardinal equivalence classes 7.4.2 Operations on cardinal equivalence classes 7.4.3 The finite cardinals 7.4.4 Countable sets 7.4.5 The cardinal numbers The axiom of foundation and the reflection scheme 7 .5.1 The axiom of foundation 7 .5.2 Some relative consistency results 7 .5.3 lnaccessible cardinals 7.5.4 The reflection scheme Exercises for Chapter 7 Some model theory 8. 1 Elementary substructures and extensions 8 .1.1 Elementary substructures 8 .1.2 The Tarski-Vaught test 8.2 Construction of elementary extensions 8.2.1 Elementary maps 8.2.2 The method of diagrams 8. 3 The interpolation and definability theorems 8.4 Reduced products and ultraproducts 8.5 Preservation theorems 8.5.1 Preservation by substructures 8.5.2 Preservation by unions of chains 8.5.3 Preservation by reduced products 8.6 Aleph-zero categorical theories 8.6.1 The omitting types theorem 8.6.2 Aleph-zero categorical structures 8. 7 Exercises for Chapter 8 Solut ilons to the exercises of Part II XV Notes from the translator In everyday mathematical language, the English word 'contains' is often used indifferently, sometimes referring to membership of an element in a set, E, and sometimes to the inclusion relation between sets, c. For a reader who is even slightly familiar with the subject, this is not a serious issue since the meaning is nearly always clear from the context. But because this distinction is precisely one of the stumbling blocks encountered by beginning students of logic and set theory, I have chosen to consistently use the word 'contains' when the meaning is E and the word 'includes' when the meaning is c. It is perhaps more common in mathematical English to use the phrases 'one-to­ one' and 'onto' in place of the more formal-sounding 'injective' and 'surjective' . I have none the less retained 'injective' and 'surjective' as more i n keeping with the style of the original; even those who object must admit that 'bijective' has the advantage over 'one-to-one and onto'. Where the original refers the reader to various standard texts i n French for some basic facts of algebra or topology, I have replaced these references with suitable English-language equivalents. It is useful to distinguish between bold zero and one (0 and 1 ) and plain zero and one (0 and 1). The plain characters are part of the metalanguage and have their usual denotations as integers. The bold characters are used, by convention, to denote the truth values of two-valued logic; they are also used to denote the respective iden­ tity elements for the operations of addition and multiplication in a Boolean algebra. Ap ri l, 2000. Donald H. Pelletier Notes to the reader The book is divided into two parts. The first consists of Chapters 1 through 4; Chapters 5 through 8 comprise the second. Concepts presented in a given chapter presume knowledge from the preceding chapters (but Chapters 2 and 5 are excep­ tions to this rule). Each of the eight chapters is divided into sections, which, in turn, are composed of several subsections that are numbered in an obvious way (see the Contents). Each chapter concludes with a section devoted to exercises. The solutions to these are grouped together at the end of the corresponding volume. The solutions, especially for the first few chapters, are rather detailed. Our reader is assumed to have acquired a certain practice of mathematics and a level of knowledge corresponding, roughly, to classical mathematics as taught in high school and in the first years of university. We will refer freely to what we have called this ' common foundation' , especially in the examples and the . exercises. None the less, the course overall assumes no prior knowledge in particular. Concerning the familiar set-theoretical (meta-)language, we will use the termi­ nology and notations that are most commonly encountered: operations on sets, relations, maps, etc., as well as N, Z, Zj nZ, Q, IR for the sets we meet every day. We will use N* to denote N- {0}. If E and F are sets and i f f is a map defined on a subset of E with values in F, the domain of f is denoted by dom(j) (it is the set of elements in E for which f is defined), and its image is denoted by lm(f) (it is the set of elements y in F' for which y f (x) is true for at least one element x in E). If A is a subset of the domain of f, the restriction of f to A is the map from A into F, denoted by f ·r A , which, with each element X in A , associates f(x). The image of the map f I A is also called the direct image of A under f and is denoted by f[A]. If B is a subset of F, the inverse image of B under f, denoted by f- 1 [B], consists of those elements x in E such that f(x) E B . In fact, with any given map f from a set E into a set F, we can associate, in a canonical way, a map from p (E) (the set of subsets of E) into p (F): this is the 'direct image' map, denoted by f which, with any subset A of £, associates f[A], which we could then just as well denote by f ( A ). In the same way� with this given map f, we could associate a map from p ( F) into p (E), called the 'inverse image� map and denoted by f I which, with any subset B of F, associates f-1 [Bl, which we could then just as well denote · by ! -I ( B). (See also Exercise 19 from Chapter 2.) == - , XVlll NOTES TO T H E R E A D E R Perhaps it is also useful to present some details concerning the notion of word on an alphabet; this concept will be required at the outset. Let E be a set, finite or infinite, which we will call the alphabet. A word� w , on the alphabet E i s a finite sequence of elements of E (i.e. a map from the set {0, I, . . . , n - 1} (where n is an integer) into E); w = (ao, a 1 , . . . , an-t ), or even aoar . . . an-1 , represents the word whose domain is {0, 1, . . . , n - 1} and which associates a; with i (for 0 < i < n - 1). The integer n i s called the length of the word w and is denoted by lg( w j. The set of words on E is denoted by W(E). I f n = 0, we obtain the empty word. We will adopt the abuse of language that consists in simply writing a for the word (a) of length 1 . The set W (E) can also support a binary operation called concatenation: let WI = (ao, at, . . . , an-1 ) and w2 = (bo, bt, . . . , bm- I) be two words; we can form the new word w = (ao,ar, . .. , an-r , bo , b r, . . . , bm- I), i.e. the map w defined on {0,1, . . . , n + m - 1} as follows: w(i) = { ifO < i < n - I ; ai bi -n if n < i < n + m - 1. This word is called the concatenation of v;1 with w2 and is denoted by WI w2. This parenthesis-free notation is justified by the fact that the operation of concatenation is associative. Given two words w and WI, we say that WI is an initial segment of w if there ex­ ists a word w 2 such that w = w r w2. To put itdifferently, ifw = (ao, a 1, . . . , an-1 ) , the initial segments of w are the words of the form (ao, a 1 , . . . , ap-1 ) where p is an integer less than or equal to n . We say that w J is a final segment of w if there exists a word w2 such that w = w2 w r; so the final segments of (ao, a 1 , ... , an-I ) are the words of the form (ap , ap+l , . . . , an-J ) where p is an integer less than or equal to n . In particular, the empty word and w itself are both initial segments and final segments of w. A segment (initial or final) of w is proper if it is different from w and the empty word. When an element bof the alphabet 'appears' in a word w = aoa 1 an-l , we say that it has an occurrence in w and the various 'positions' where it appears are called the occurrences of bin w . We could, of course, be more precise and more formal: we will say that bhas an occurrence in w if b is equal to one of the a; for i between 0 and n - 1 (i.e. if bbelongs to the image of w ). An occurrence of b in w is an integer k, less than l g [w], such that b == ak . For example, the third occurrence ofbin w is the third element of the set { k : 0 < k < n - 1 and ak = b} in increasing order. This formalism will not be used explicitly in the text; the idea sketched at the beginning of this paragraph will be more than adequate for what we have to do. • • • N OTES TO T H E R E A D E R XIX The following facts are more or less obvious and will be in constant use: • • for all words WJ and w2, lg[w1w2] == lgtwd + lg[w2]; for all words w1, w2 and W3, the equality w 1 w2 = w 1 W3 implies the equality w2 = W3 (we call this left cancellation); = • for all words WJ, w2 and W3, the equality w I w2 w 1 = W3 (we call this right cancellation); • for all words WJ, w2, W3 and w4, if WIW2 = W3W4� then either WI is an initial segment of W3 or else W3 is an initial segment of WJ. Analogously, under the same assumptions, either w2 is a final segment of w4 or else w4 is a final segment of w2; • if WI is an initial segment of w2 and w2 is an initial segment of Wt, then WI = W2. W3 w2 implies the equality We will also use the fact that W(E) is countable if E is either finite or countable (this is a theorem from Chapter 7). Introduction There are many who consider that logic, as a branch of mathematics, has a some­ what special status that distinguishes it from all the others. Curiously, both its keenest adversaries and some of its most enthusiastic disciples concur with this conception which places logic near the margin of mathematics, at its border, or even outside it. For the first, logic does not belong to 'real' mathematics; the others, on the contrary, see it as the reigning discipline within mathematics, the one that transcends all the others, that supports the grand structure. To the reader who has come to meet us in this volume seeking an introduction to mathematical logic, the first advice we would give is to adopt a point of view thai is radically different from the one above. The frame of mind to be adopted should be the same as when consulting a treatise in algebra or differential calculus. It is a mathematical text that we are presenting here; in it, we will be doing mathematics. not something else. It seems to us that this is an essential precondition for a proper understanding of the concepts that will be presented. That does not mean that the question of the place of logic in mathematics i�. without interest. On the contrary, it is enthralling, but it concerns problems external to mathematics. Any mathematician can (and we will even say must) at certain times reflect on his work, transform himself into an epistemologist, a philosopher or historian of science; but the point must be clearly made that in doing this.. he temporarily ceases his mathematical activity. Besides, there is generally no ambiguity: when reading a text in analysis, what the student of mathematics expects to find there are definitions, theorems, and proofs for these theorems. If the author has thought it appropriate to add some comments of a philosophical or histori­ cal nature, the reader never has the slightest difficulty separating the concerns contained in these comments from the subject matter itself. We would like the reader to approach the course that follows in this way and to view logic as a perfectly ordinary branch of mathematics. True, it is not always easy to do this. The major objection surfaces upon realizing that it is necessary to accept simul­ taneously the following two ideas: logic is a branch of mathematics; (2) the goal of logic is to study mathematics itself. (l) 2 INTRODUCTION Faced with this apparent paradox, there are three possible attitudes. First, one may regard it as so serious that to undertake the study of logic is condemned in advance; second, one may deem that the supposed incompatibility between ( 1) and (2) simply compels the denial of ( I ), or at least its modification, which leads to the belief that one is not really doing mathematics when one studies logic; the third attitude, finally, consists in dismantling the paradox, becoming convinced that it is not one, and situating mathematical logic in its proper place, within the core of mathematics. We invite you to follow us in this third path. Those for whom even the word paradox is too weak will say: 'Wait a minute! Aren't you putting us on when you finally get around, in your Chapter 7, to provid­ ing definitions of concepts (intersection, pair, map, ordered set, . . . ) that you have been continually using in the six previous chapters? This is certainly paradoxical. You are surely leading us in a vicious circle'. Well, in fact, no. There is neither a paradox nor a vicious circle. This text is addressed to readers who have already 'done' some mathematics, who have some prior experience with it, beginning with primary school. We do not ask you to forget all that in order to rebuild everything from scratch. It is the oppo­ site that we ask of you. We wish to exploit the common background that is ours: familiarity with mathematical reasoning (induction, proof by contradiction, . . . ), with everyday mathematical objects (sets (yes, even these!), relations, functions, integers, real numbers, polynomials, continuous functions, . . . ), and with some concepts that may be less well known (ring, vector space, topological space, . . . ). That is what is done in any course in mathematics: we make use of our prior knowledge in the acquisition of new knowledge. We will proceed in exactly this way and we will learn about new objects, possibly about new techniques of proof (but caution: the mathematical reasoning that we habitually employ will never be called into question; on the contrary, this is the only kind contemplated here). If we simplify a bit, the approach of the mathematician is almost always the same whether the subject matter under study is measure theory, vector spaces, ordered sets, or any other area of so-called classical mathematics. It consists in examining structures, i.e. sets on which relations and functions have been defined, and correspondences among these structures. But, for each of these classical areas, there was a particular motivation that gave birth to it and nurtured its development. The purpose was to provide a mathematical model of some more or less 'con­ crete' situation, to respond to an expressed desire arising from the world outside mathematics, to furnish a useful mathematical tool (as a banal illustration of this, consider that vector spaces arose, originally, to represent the physical space in which we live). Logic, too, follows this same approach; its particularity is that the reality it attempts to describe is not one from outside the world of mathematics, but rather the reality that is mathematics itself. I NT R O D U C T I O N 3 This should not be awkward, provided we remain aware of precisely what is involved. No student of mathematics confuses his physical environment with an oriented three-dimensional euclidean vector space, but the knowledge of this environment assists one's intuition when it comes to proving some property of this mathematical structure. The same applies to logic: in a certain way, we are going to manufacture a copy, a prototype, we dare say a reduced model of the universe of mathematics, with which we are already relatively familiar. More precisely, we wil1 build a whole collection of models, more or less successful (not every vector space resembles our physical space). In addition to a specimen that is truly similar to the original, we will inevitably have created others (at the close of Chapter 6, we should be in position to understand why), often rather different from what we imagined at the outset. The study of this collection teaches us many lessons; notably, it permits those who undertake this study to ask themselves interesting questions about their perceptions and their intuitions of the mathematical world. Be that as it may, we must understand that it is essential not to confuse the original that inspired us with the copy or copies. 8 ut the original is indispensable for the production of the copy: our familiarity with the world of mathematics guides us in fabricating the representation of it that we will provide. But at the same time, our undertaking is a mathematical one, within this universe that we are attempting to better comprehend. So there is no vicious circle. Rather than a circle, imagine a helix (nothing vicious there!), a kind of spiral staircase: we are on the landing of the nth floor, where our mathematical universe is located; call this the 'intuitive level'. Our work takes us down a level, to the (n -l)st floor, where we find the prototype, the reduced model; we will then be at the 'formal' level and our passage from one level to the other will be called 'formalization' . What is the value of n? This makes absolute} y no diiierence; there is no first nor last level. Indeed, if our model is well constructed, if in reproducing the mathematical universe it has not omitted any detail, then it will also contain the counterpart of our very own work on formalization; this requires us to consider level n 2, and so on. At the beginning of this book, we find ourselves at the intuitive level. The souls that inhabit it will also be called intuitive objects; we will distinguish these from their formal replica by attaching the prefix 'meta' to their names (meta-integers, meta-relations, even meta-universe since the word 'universe' will be given a precise technical meaning in Chapter 7). We will go so far as to say that for any value of n , the nth level in our staircase is intuitive relative to leveJ n I and is formal relative to level n + 1. As we descend, i.e. as we progress in our formalization, we could stop for a rest at any moment, and take the opportunity to verify that the formal model, or at least what we can see of it, agrees with the intuitive original. This rest period concerns the meta-intuitive, i.e. level n + 1 . So we must face the facts: it is no more feasible to build all of mathematics ' ex nihilo' than to write an English-English dictionary that would be of use to a Martian who knows nothing of our lovely language. We are faced here with -- - 4 I N T R O D U C T IO N a question that had considerable importance in the development of logic at the beginning of the century and about which it is worth saying a few words. Set theory (it matters little which theory: ZF, Z, or some other), by giving legit­ imacy to infinite objects and by allowing these to be manipulated just like 'real' objects (the integers, for example), with the same logical rules, spawned a fair amount of resistance among certain mathematicians; all the more because the ini­ tial attempts turned out to be contradictory. The mathematical world was then split into two clans. On the one hand, there were those who could not resist the freedom that set theory provided, this 'Cantorian paradise' as Hilbert called it. On the other hand were those for whom only finite objects (the integers, or anything that could be obtained from the integers in a finite number of operations) had any meaning and who, as a consequence, denied the validity of proofs that made use of set theory. To reconcile these points of view, Hilbert had imagined the following strategy (the well-known 'Hilbert programme'): first, proofs would be regarded as finite sequences of symbols, hence, as finite objects (that is what is done in this book in Chapters 4 and 6) ; second, an algorithm would be found that would transform a proof that used set theory into a finitary proof, i.e. a proof that would be above all suspicion. If this programme could be realized, we would be able to see, for example, that set theory is consistent: for if not, set theory would permit a proof of 0 I which could then, with the help of the algorithm suggested above, be transformed into a finitary proof, which is absurd. This hope was dashed by the second incompleteness theorem of Godel: surely, any set theory worthy of this name allows the construction of the set of natural numbers and, consequently, its consistency would imply the consistency ofPeano's axioms. Godel's theorem asserts that this cannot be done in a finitary way. The conclusion is that even finitary mathematics does not provide a foundation for our mathematical edifice, as presently constructed. The process of formalization involves two essential stages. First, we fix the context (the structures) in which the objects evolve while providing a syntax to express their properties (the languages and the formulas). Here, the important concept is the notion of satisfaction which lies at the heart of the area known as semantics. It would be possible to stop at this point but we can also go further and formalize the reasoning itself; this is the second stage in the formalization. Here, we treat deductions or formal proofs as mathematical objects in their own right. We are then not far from proof theory, which is the branch of logic that specializes in these questions. This book deliberately assigns priority to the first stage. Despite this, we will not ignore the second, which is where the most famous results from mathematical logic (Godel's theorems) are situated. Chapter 4 is devoted to the positive results in this area: the equivalence between the syntactic and semantic points of view in the context that we have selected. This equivalence is called 'completeness' . There are several versions of this simply because there are many possible choices for a = INTRODUCTION 5 formal system of deduction. One of these systems is in fashion these days because of its use in computer science: this is the method of resolution. We have chosen to introduce it after first presenting the traditional completeness theorem. The negative results, the incompleteness theorems, will be treated in Chapter 6, following the study of Peano's arithmetic. This involves, as we explained above, abandoning our possible illusions. The formalization of reasoning will not occur outside the two chapters that we have just mentioned. Chapter I treats the basic operations on truth values, 'true' and 'false'. The syntax required is very simple (propositional formulas) and the semantics (well­ known truth tables) is not very complicated. We are interested in the truth value of propositions, while carefully avoiding any discussion of the nature of the properties expressed by means of these propositions. Our concern with what they express, and with the ways they do it, is the purpose of Chapter 3. We see immediately that the operators considered in the first chapter (the connectives 'and', 'or', 'implies' and so on) do not suffice to express familiar mathematical properties. We have to introduce the quantifiers and we must also provide a way of naming mathemati­ cal objects. This leads to formulas that are sequences of symbols obeying rather cornplicated rules. Following the description of a syntax that is considerably more complex than that for propositional calculus, we define the essential concept: sat­ isfaction of a formula in a structure. We will make extensive use of all this, which is called predicate calculus, in Chapters 4 and 6, to which we referred earlier, as well as in Chapters 7 and 8. You will have concluded that it is only Chapter 5 that does not require prior knowledge of predicate calculus. Indeed, it is devoted to the study of recursive functions, a notion that is absolutely fundamental for anyone with even the slightest interest in computer science. We could perfectly well begin with this chapter provided we refer to Chapter 1 for the process of inductive def­ inition, which is described there in detail and which is used as well for recursive functions. In Chapter 7 we present axiomatic set theory. It is certainly there that the sense of paradox to which we referred will be most strongly felt since we purport to construct mathematical universes as if we were defining a field or a commutative group. But, once a possible moment of doubt has passed, one will find all that a mathematician should know about the important notions of cardinals and ordinals, the axiom of choice, whose status is generally poorly understood, and, naturally, a list of the axioms of set theory. Chapter 8 canies us a bit further into an area of which we have so far only caught a glimpse: model theory. Its ambition is to give you a taste for this subject and to stiroulate your curiosity to learn more. In any case, it should lead you to suspect that mathematical logic is a rich and varied terrain, where one can create beautiful things, though this can also mean difficult things. l-Iave we forgotten Chapter 2? Not at all! It is just that it constitutes a singularity in this book. To begin with, it is the only one in which we employ notions from 6 INTRODUCTION classical mathematics that a student does not normally encounter prior to the upper­ level university curriculum (topological spaces, rings and ideals). Moreover, the reader could just as well skip it: the concepts developed there are used only in some of the exercises and in one section of the last chapter. But we have included it for at least three reasons: the first is that Boolean algebras are the "correct" algebraic structures for logic; the second is that it affords us an opportunity to display how perfectly classical mathematics, of a not entirely elementary nature, could be linked in a natural way with the study of logic; the third, finally, is that an exposure to Boolean algebras is generally absent from the mathematical literature offered to students, and is even more rarely proposed to students outside the technical schools. So you should consider Chapter 2, if you will, as a little supplement that you may consult or not, as you wish. We will probably be criticized for not being fair, either in our choice of the subjects we treat or in the relative importance we accord to each of them. The domain of logic is now so vast that it would have been absolutely impossible to introduce every one of its constituents. So we have made choices: as we have already noted, proof theory is barely scratched; lambda calculus and algorithmic complexity are absent despite the fact that they occupy an increasingly important place in research in logic (because of their applications to the theory of comput­ ing which have been decisive). The following are also absent: non-classical logics (intuitionist . . .) , second-order logic (in which quantifications range over relations on a structure as well as over its elements), or so-called 'infinitary' logics (which allow formulas of infinite length). These choices are dictated, first of all, by our desire to present a basic course. We do not believe that the apprentice logician should commence anywhere else than with a detailed study of the first-order pred­ icate calculus; this is the context that we have set for ourselves (Chapter 3 ). Starting from this, we wished to present the three areas (set theory, model theory, recursive function theory and decidability) that seetn to us to be the most important. Histor­ ically speaking, they certainly are. They also are because the 'grand' theorems of logic are all found there. Finally, it is our opinion that familiarity with these three areas is an indispensable prerequisite for anyone who is interested in any other area of mathematical logic. Having chosen this outline, we still had the freedom to modify the relative importance given to these three axes. In this matter, we cannot deny that we allowed our personal preferences to guide us; it is clear that Chapter 8 could just as well have been devoted to something other than model theory. These lines were drafted only after the book that follows was written. We think that they should be read only after it has been studied. As we have already pointed out, we can only truly speak about an activity, describe it (formalize it!), once we have acquired a certain familiarity with it. Until then. 1 Propositional calculus Propositional calculus is the study of the p1vpositional connectives; these are operators on statements or on formulas. First of all there is negation, which we denote by the symbol -, which is placed infivnt ofaformula. The other connectives are placed between two formulas: we will consider conjunction ( 'and', denoted by A), disjunction ( 'or', denoted by v ), implication (=} ), and equivalence ( {} ). Thus, for example, from two statements A and B, it is possible to form their conjunction: this is another statement that is true if and only if A is true and B is true. The.first thing we do is to construct purelyformal objects that we will call propo­ sitionalformulas, 01; more simply in this chapter, formulas. As building blocks we will use propositional variables which intuitively represent elementary proposi­ tions, and we assemble them using the connectives mentioned above. Initially, formulas appear suitably assembled sequences ofsymbols. In Section 1.1, we will present precise rules for their construction and means for recovering the method by which a givenformula was constructed, which makes it possiblefor the formula to be read. All theseformal considerations constitute what we call syntax. This formal construction is obviously not arbitrary. We will subsequently have to give meaning to theseformulas. This is the purpose of Section 1.2. lf, for each elementa1y proposition appearing in a formula F, we know whether it is true or not (we speak of the truth value of the proposition), we must be able to decide whether F itse{f is true or not. For instance, we will say that A =} B is true in three of the four possible cases: when A and B are both true, when A and B are both false, and when A is false and B is true. Notice here the d(fference from common usage: for example, in everyday language and even in mathematics texts, the phrase 'A implies B ' suggests a causal relationship which, in our context, does not exist at all. Thereby we arrive at the important notions of this chapter: the concept of tau­ tology (this is a formula that is true regardless of the truth values assigned to the propositional variables) and the notion of logical equivalence (two formulas are logically equivalent if they receive the same truth value regardless of the truth values assigned to the propositional variables). as 8 PROPOSTTIONAL CALCULUS In Section 1.3, we see that a formula is always logically equivalent to aformula that can be written in a very particularform (disjunctive or conjunctive normal form) while Section 1.4 is devoted to the interpolation theorem and the de.finability theorem whose full import will be appreciated when they are generalized to the predicate calculus (in Chapter 8). In the last section (�f this chapte1; the compact­ ness theorem is particularly important and it too will be generalized, in Chapter 3. It asserts that if it is impossible to assign truth values to p1vpositional variables in a way that makes all theformulas in some infinite set X true, then there is some finite subset of X for which it is also impossible to do this. 1.1 Syntax 1.1.1 Propositional formulas The preliminary section called �Notes to the reader' contains, among other items, some general facts about words on an alphabet. The student who is not familiar with these notions should read that section first. Let us consider a non-empty set P, finite or infinite, which we will call the set of propositional variables. The elements of P will usually be denoted by capital letters of the alphabet, possibly bearing subscripts. In addition, we allow ourselves the following five symbols: which we read respectively as: 'not', 'or', 'and', 'implies' and 'is equivalent to' and which we call symbols for propositional connectives. We assume that they are not elements of P. The symbols --. , v , 1\, =:} , <? are respectively called: the symbol for negation, the symbol for disjunction, the symbol for conjunction, the symbol for implica­ tion and the symbol for equivalence. In view of the roles that will be assigned to them (see Definition 1 .2 below), we say that the symbol is unary (or has one place) and that the other four symbols for connectives are binary (or have two places). Finally, we consider the following two symbols: � ) ( respectively called the closing parenthesis and the opening parenthesis, distinct from the symbols for the connectives and also not belonging to P. Certain finite sequences composed ofpropositional variables, symbols for propo­ sitional connectives, and parentheses will be called propositional formulas (or propositions). Propositional formulas are thus words formed with the following alphabet: A = P u { , v, A, =>, <? } u { ) , ( } . --. 9 S YNTAX From the very first sentences in this chapter, we can already sense one of the difficulties which, unless we are careful, will confront us continually during our apprenticeship with the basic notions offormal logic: certain words and certain symbols are both used in everyday mathematical language (which we will call the metalanguage) and also appear in the variousformal languages that are the principal objects of our study: for example, the word 'implies ' and the symbol ::::>, which, to say the least, arise frequently in all mathematical discourse, are used here to denote a precise mathematical object: a symbol for one of the connectives. We will attempt, insofar as is possible, to eliminate from our meta­ language any word or symbol which is used in a formal language. It would none the less be d(fficult to renounce altogether in our discourse the use of words such as 'and', 'or', 'not' or parentheses. (This very sentence illustrates thefact clearly enough.) This is why we wish to call the reader's attention to this problem right from the beginning and we invite the reader to be constantly alert to the distinction between a formal language and the metalanguage. (The same problem will arise again in Chapter 3 with the symbols for the quant{fiers.) As stated i n 'Notes to the Reader', we will identify, by convention, the elements of A with the corresponding words of length 1 in W(A). In particular, P will be considered a subset of W(A). Definition 1.2 The set F of propositional formulas constructed from P is the smallest subset of W(A) which includes P; whenever it contains the word F, it also contains the word F; whenever it contains the words F and G, it also contains the words Remark 1.1 • • ...., • ( F A G), (F v G ) , ( F => G) and (F -¢:> G). In other words, F is the smallest subset o f W(A) which includes P and which is closed under the operations: F r+ (F, G) ( F, G) r+ ( F, G) (F, G) r+ r+ r+ ...., p , (F A G), (F v G), (F ==> G), (F {:> G). Observe that there is at least one subset of W (A) which has these properties, namely W(A) itself. The set :F is the intersection of all the subsets of W(A) that have these properties. 10 P ROPOSITION A L C A LC U L U S Here are examples of formulas (A, B, and C are elements of P): ( ( (A 1\ A (A ==} (B � A)) (-.A =? A) -.(A ==} A) (-,B => -. A)) 1\ (-,B v -.C)) =} (C =} -.A)). And here are words that are not formulas: ((A 1\ A /\ B -.(A) (A => B v C) A =} B, C (A 1\ B 1\ C) VA(A v _, A) (B => C ) ) v (-.A => (B 1\ C)) 1\ (-.A v B)). Later we will agree to certain abuses in the writing of formulas: for example, A 1\ B could be accepted in some cases as an abbreviation for the formula (A 1\ B). Obviously, this changes nothing in the definition above; we are simply giving ourselves several ways of representing the same object: if A 1\ B is a permitted way to write the formula ( A 1\ B), the length of A 1\ B is none the less equal to 5. Observe in passing that the notion of the length of a formula is already defined since we have defined the length of any word on any alphabet. (See the Notes to the Reader.) It is possible to give a more explicit description of the set F: to do this, we will define, by induction, a sequence ( r )nEN of subsets of W(A). We set . 11 Fo = P and, for each n , Fn + 1 = Fn U {--. F : F E Fn} U { ( F a G) : F, G E Fn , Observe that the sequence (Fn) nEN is increasing (for n < a E { 1\, m, v, =>, � } } we have Fn c Fm). F = Un EN .rn. Proof It is clear that Un EN Fn includes P and is closed under the operations indicated above (if two words F and G belong to Fn for a certain integer then Theorem 1.3 n, -,F, (F 1\ G), (F v G), (F =* G) and (F � G) belong to Fn+ 1 · It follows that Un EN r includes the smallest set having these properties, namely, F. To obtain the reverse inclusion, we show by induction that for each integer n , we have Fn c F. This i s true by definition if n = 0, and i f we assume (this i s the . n 11 SYNTAX induction hypothesis) Fk c F, we also have Fk + 1 c of Fk+1 and the closure properties of F. F according to the definition • We thus have two equivalent definitions of the set of propositional formulas. We often speak of ' definition from above' in the first case and 'definition from below' for the one that follows from the previous theorem. At several places in this book, we will encounter this type of definition, said to be inductive or by induction (see, for example, the set of terms or the set of formulas of the predicate calculus in Chapter 3, or again the set of recursive functions in Chapter 5). In each case, we are concerned with defining the smallest subset of a fixed set E that includes a given subset and that is closed under certain operations defined on E (this is definition from above). We always have an equivalent defi­ nition from below: this consists in constructing the set that we wish to define one leve] at a time; the subset given initially is the lowest level and the elements of level n + 1 are defined to be the images under the given operations of the elements from the lower levels. The set to be defined is then the union of a sequence of subsets, indexed by the set of natural numbers. In all instances of sets defined by induction that we will meet in the future, as well as in the method of proof by induction described below, we will encounter the notion of height. Definition 1.4 The height of a formula F F E Fn. It is denoted by h[F]. For example, if A and h[ A] = 0; E F is the least integer n such that B are propositiona] variables, we have h[((A v B) 1\ (B ==> A))] = 2; h [-.-.-,-.-.Aj = 5. Note that Fn is the set of formulas o f height less than or equal t o n, and that Fn is the set of formulas of height exactly n + 1 . Fn + 1 It also follows from the definition that for all formulas F and G E F, we have: - h [-.F] < h [F] + 1 and h [ ( F a G)] < sup(h[F], h[G]) + 1, where a denotes a n arbitrary symbol for a binary connective. (In fact, we will see, after Theorem 1 .12� that we can replace these inequalities by equalities). 1.1.2 Proofs by induction on the set of formulas Suppose we wish to show that a certain property X (F) is satisfied by every formula F E F. To do this we can use an argument by induction (in the usual sense) on the height of F: so we would be led first to show that X ( F) is true for every formula F belonging to :Fo , and afterwards that if X ( F) is true for every F E Fn , then it is also true for every F E Fn+ l (and thus, for any n). This style of argument is associated with definition 'from below' of the set of formulas. 12 PROPOSITIO NAL CALCULUS I t i s more practical and more natural, however, to take the first definition as our point of departure and proceed as follows. The initial step is the same: we show that X(F) is satisfied for all formulas belonging to P (that is, to Fo); the induction step consists in proving, on the one hand, that if the formula F satisfies the property X, then so does the formula -, F, and on the other hand, that if F and G satisfy X, then so do the formulas (F 1\ G), (F v G), (F ==} G), and (F {:} G). As we see, the notion of the height of formulas does not appear explicitly in this style of argument, nor does any other natural number. Before establishing the correctness of this method of proof (which is the purpose of Lemma 1 .7) let us give an initial example of its use: Theorem 1.5 The height of a formula is always strictly less than its length. Proof In this case, the property X ( F) is: h[F] < lg[Fl. If F is a propositional variable, we have h [F] 0 and lg[F] == I ; the inequal­ ity is verified. Let us now pass to the induction step. Suppose that a formula F satisfies h[F] < lg[ F]; we then have == h [-,F] < h[F] + l < lg[F] +1 == lg[ -,p ] , which shows that X( -,F) i s true; and now suppose that F and G are formulas that satisfy h[F] < lg[F] and h [ G] < lg[ G]; then, where a is any symbol for a binary connective, we have h [ ( F a G)] < sup(h[F], h[Gl) + 1 < sup(lg [ F], lg[G]) + 1 < lg[F] + lg[G] + 3 lg[(F a G)], == which means that X(F a G) is satisfied and the proof is fi nished. • As a consequence of this property, observe that there are no formulas of length 0 (which is one of the ways to show that the empty word is not a formula!) and that the only formulas of length 1 are the propositional variables. The two lemmas that follow allow us to justify the method that we just described and used. The fi rst is a variant of it that we will then easily modify below. Consider a property Y( W ) of an arbitrary word W E W(A) (which need not necessarily be a formula). Here is a sufficient condition that every formula satisfies the property Y: Lemma 1.6 Suppose, on the one hand, that Y( W ) is truefor every word W E P, and, on the other hand, that for any words W and V, if Y( W) and Y(V) are true, then Y( _,F), Y(F A G), Y(F v G), Y(F ==} G), and Y(F ¢> G) are also true. Under these conditions, Y(F) is true for every formula F. Proof Let Z be the set of words that have property Y: z = {W E W(A) : Y(W)}. 13 SYNTAX The hypotheses o f the lemma indicate that Z includes P and that it i s closed with respect to the operations: W f-). W, (W, V) � ( W A V ) , ( W, V) � ( W v V ) , ( W, V ) � ( W =} V) and (W, V) � ( W <:> V ) . -, It follows, according to Definition 1 .2, that :F i s included in Z , which means that • every element of :F satisfies the property Y. Let us now consider the case where we have a property X (F) which is only defined for formulas and not for arbitrary words. (This is the case, for example, with the property: h[ F] < lg[F], since the notion of height is defined only for elements of :F.) Lemma 1.7 Suppose, on theonehand, that X(F) istrueforeveryformula F E P, and, on the other hand that, for all formulas F and G, if X (F) and X(G) are true) then X(-,F), X(F A G), X(F v G), X(F =} G), and X(F <:> G) are also true. Under these conditions, X(F) is true for everyformula F. Proof It suffices to consider the property Y( W ): ' W E :F and X (W) ' , which is defined for every word W operations W� -, E W(A). Since :F includes P and is closed under the W, ( W, V) ( W, V ) � f-). (W A V ) , (W, V) (W =? V ) and (W, V) � t-+ (W ( W v V), <:> V ) , we see immediately that i f the property X satisfies the stated hypotheses, then the property Y satisfies those of the preceding lemma. We conclude that Y< F) is true for every formula F and hence the same holds for X(F). • 1 . 1 .3 The decomposition tree of a formula Among the first examples of formulas that we gave earlier was the following word W: The reader, who justifiably has no intention to take us on faith, should be con­ vinced by what follows that this word is indeed a formula: By setting and WI == (C � -, A), we first observe that W can be written as ( Wo ==} Wt ) . 14 PROP O S I TIONAL C A LC U L US Then, after setting Woo = (A A (-.B =} -,A)), Wo1 = ( -,B v -,C), Wt o = C, wl l = _,A, we can write Wo = (Woo A Wo t ) and W1 = (Wto :::::::> W1 1 ) . Continuing in this way, we will be led successively to set Woo1 = (-,B � -. A) W01 1 = -.C Wo01o = -, B Wo10o = B WooiOO = B Wooo = A W01o = -, B Wno = A Woou = -,A Wot io = C Woo1 10 = A in such a way that Woo = (Wooo A Wool ) , Wot = (Woio v Wo1 1 ), W1 1 = -, W1 1o, Woot (Woo to =} Woo1 1 ), Wo1o = -, Wowo, Wou = -,Wo1 10, Wooto = -, WooiOo and Woo1 1 = ..., Woouo== This shows that the word W was obtained b y starting from propositional variables and by applying, a finite number of times, operations allowed in the defi nition of the set of formulas. It follows that W is a formula. We can represent the preceding decomposition in the form of a tree: /------------- Wo 1\ / Woo 1\ Wooo • � r- Wool ::::> � Woon Wo01oo Woono • ...., -� � ------� r --. Wcxno w Wow Wo1oo • WOI v � Won -, Wuo • Wono • • The root of the tree (the formula W) is at the top and the branches 'grow' toward the bottom. Each node of the tree is a word V (which is always a formula if the word at the root of the tree is a formula). Three cases can arise: V is a propositional 15 S YNTAX variable and, in this case, will b e an extremity o f the tree (the words corresponding to this situation are identified by a black dot in our figure above); V can be written as V' in which case there is a single branch starting from V and ending at the level immediately below at the node V ' ; or finally, V can be written as ( V ' a V") (where a is a symbol fora binary connective)andin this casethere aretwobranches starting from V and ending at the level immediately below at the two nodes V ' and V" (in this case the appropriate symbol for a binary connective has been placed in the figure between the two branches). The decomposition that we have chosen for our formula shows that it belongs to Fs. Its height is therefore less than or equal to 5. At the moment, nothing allows us to claim that its height is exactly 5. Might we not, in fact, imagine a second way of decomposing this formula which would lead to a shorter tree? All we can say (and this is thanks to Theorem 1 .3 ) is that for every formula F E F, there is at least one decomposition of the type we have just exhibited. The uniqueness will be established in the next theorem� for which we first require a few lemmas which, with the exception of Lemma 1 . 1 0 will be proved by induction on the set of formulas. ._, .. 1 . 1 4 The unique decomposition theorem .. For each word W E W(A), let us agree to denote by o[W] (respectively: c[W]) the number of opening (respectively: closing) parentheses that occur in W. Lemma 1.8 In any formula, the number of opening parentheses is equal to the number of closing parentheses. Proo1[ We argue by induction on the formula F. • • F E P, we have o[F] c[F] 0. For any formula F E F such that o[F] c[F], since o[-1F] o[F] and c[-.F] c[F], we have o[-,F] c[-,F]. For all formulas F and G belonging to F such that o[F] c[F] and o[G] c[ G], and where a is an arbitrary symbol for a binary connective, we have For any formula = = = • = = = = o[ (F a G)] = o[F] + o[G]+l Thus, o[F] = = = c[F] + c[G]+l = c[(F a G)]. c[ F] for any propositional formula F. • Lemma 1.9 For anyformula F E F and any word W E W(A), if W is an initial segment of F, then o[W] > c[W]. Proof The induction is on the formula F. If F E P, then for every initial segment W o f F we have o [W] c[W] 0, hence o[W] > c[W]. Let F be a formula such that for every initial segment W of F, w e have o[W] > c[W]. Consider an initial segment V of -.F: if V is the empty word, then • • , = = 16 P R O PO S I T I O N A L C A L C U L U S o [ V ] � c[V] == 0; if V is not the empty word, then there is an initial segment W of F such that V == W ; we have of V] == o[W] and c[ V ] == c [ W ] , and since o[W] > c[ W ] (by the induction hypothesis), we conclude that o [ V ] > c [ V ] . ...., • Let F and G b e two formulas all o f whose initial segments have at least as many opening parentheses as closing parentheses, and let a be a symbol for a binary connective. Set H == ( F a G). Let V be an initial segment of H. Four cases can anse: * either V == 0: in this case, o[V J == c [ V ] == 0; (where W i s a n initial segment o f F): * or V � ( W then o [ V ] == o[W] --r 1 and c [ V ] == c [ W ] , and since o [ W ] > c [ W ] (by the induction hypothesis), we conclude that ol V] > c [ V ] ; (where K is an initial segment of G): * o r V � (F a K then o [ V ] == o[F] + o [ K ] + I and c[V] == c [ F ] + c[K]; but o[F] � c[ F] (by Lemma 1 .8) and o [ K ] > c [ K l (by the induction hypothesis), which allows us to conclude once more that o[V] > c[V]; * or V == H: in which case o[Vl > c[V] (by Lemma 1 .8). • So we see that in all cases, o [ V ] > cL V]. For any formula F E F whose first symbol is an opening paren­ thesis and for every word W E W(A) which is a prvper initial segment of F, we have (strict inequality) o [ W] > c[W]. Lemma 1.10 Proof For once, the proof is not by induction ! Consider a formula F which can be written as F == (G a H) where G and H are arbitrary formulas and a is a symbol for a binary connective. Let W be a proper initial segment of F. There are two possible cases. • either W == (K (where K is an (arbitrary) initial segment of G); i n this case, o[W] � o[K] + I and c[WJ � c[K] , and since o[K] > e L K ] (by Lemma 1.9), we conclude that o[W] > c[W]; • (where L is an initial segment of H); o r W == (G a L in this case, o [W] == o[G]+o[L]+ 1 and c[ W ] == c[G]+c[L]; but o[G] == c[G] (by Lemma 1 .8 ) and o( L] > c[L I (by Lemma 1 .9), which leads once again to • o[W] > c[W]. For any formula F E F and for any word W E proper initial segment of F lhen W is not a formula. Proof Here too, the induction is on the formula F. Lemma 1.11 W (A), if W is a • A propositional variable does not have any proper initial segments. • If F is a formula none of whose proper initial segments is a formula, and if V is a proper initial segment of ...., F , then either V == and is not a formula (the only formulas of length I are the elements of P), or else V == W where ...., ...., 17 SYNTAX W i s a proper initial segment of F; i n this case, W i s not a formula (by the induction hypothesis) nor is V == - W. Observe that, contrary to what we might have been tempted to believe, the fact that , 'if W is not a formula, then neither is --. W' is not a trivial application of the definition of the set of formulas, but requires a proof. Here it is: if -. W is a formula, examination of its first symbol shows that it is neither a propositional variable nor a formula of the type (H a K ) ; therefore (by Theorem 1 .3) there exists at least one formula G such that -, W == --.G; if the words --. W and -,a are identical, then so also are the words W and G , which proves that W is a formula. • Let F and G be two arbitrary formulas, a a symbol fora binary connective, and V aproperinitial segmentof(F a G ) . Wehave o[V ] > c [ V ] (by Lemma 1 . 1 0). We conclude that V is not a formula (by Lemma 1 .8). Note that it was not necessary, in this part of the argument by induction, to assume that the proper initial segments of F and G are not formulas. • (Unique decomposition) For anyformula F E F, one and only one of the following three cases can arise: Case 1: F E P. Case 2: there is a unique formula G such that F -,G. Case 3: there is a unique symbol for a binary connective a and a unique pair of formulas (G, H ) E F2 such that F ( G a H). Theorem 1.12 == == Proof I t i s obvious that these three cases are mutually exclusive: we are i n case 1, in case 2, o r i n case 3 (still subject to proving uniqueness in each of these cases) according as the first symbol of F is an element of P, the symbol -., or the symbol ( (these are, by virtue of Theorem 1 .3, the only possibilities). What we know already (Theorem 1 .3) is this: either F E P, or else there is at least one formula G such that F == -.G, or else there is at least one symbol for a binary connective a and formulas G and H such that F == (G a H ) . So it only remains for us to prove the uniqueness o f the decomposition i n cases 2 and 3. This i s more or less obvious for case 2: i f F == -.G ::::: -.G', then G == G'. As for case 3, suppose that there exist formulas G , H, K , and L and symbols for binary connectives a and f3 such that F == (G a H) ::::: (K f3 L ) . We conclude that the two words G a H and K f3 L are equaL which shows that one of the two formulas G and K is an initial segment of the other. By Lemma I . I 1 , this cannot be a proper initial segment. Since the empty word is not a formula, we conclude that G == K . From this, it follows that the words a H and f3 L are equal. The symbols a and f3 are therefore identical, as well as the formulas H and L. • As the first application of the unique decomposition theorem, we have the unique­ ness of the decomposition tree of a formula, as described above. 18 PROPOSITIONAL CALCULUS We may also conclude from it (as announced at the end of Subsection 1 . 1 . 1 ) that for all formulas F and G belonging to F., we have h[-.F] == h[F] + 1 and h [(F a G)] == sup(h[F], h[G]) + 1 for any symbol for a binary connective a. For example, let u s prove the second equality (the other one i s treated i n an exactly analogous fashion): let H denote the formula (F a G ). Since this is not an element of P, there exists a (unique) integer n such that h[H] = n + 1 . This means that H E Fn+ 1 and H fj_ Fn . By the definition of :Fn+ 1 and because H begins with an opening parenthesis, we conclude that there exist two formulas Hr and H2 E :Fn and a symbol for a binary connective {3 such that H = (H1 {3 H2). The unique decomposition theorem then shows that {3 == a, H1 == F, and H2 = G. Consequently, F and G belong to :F,�. If there were some integer m < n such that F and G belonged to :Fm , the formula (F a G ) would belong to F,n+l , hence also to :Fn , which is false. It follows that at least one of the formulas F and G has height n, and so: h[(F a G)] = sup(h[F], h[Gl) + 1 . 1.1.5 Definitions by induction on the set of formulas Just as we can give proofs by induction on the set of formulas, we can provide definitions by induction of functions or of relations whose domain is the set of formulas. The principle is as follows: given an arbitrary set E, to define a mapping ¢ from :F into E, it suffices to give, first of all, the values of ¢ on P, and then to give rules which allow us, for all formulas F and G, to determine the values of ¢(-.F), ¢((F 1\ G)), ¢((F v G)), ¢((F ==> G)) and ¢( (F � G)) from the values of ¢(F) and ¢ (G). Let us be more precise: Let ¢o be a mapping from P into E, f a mapping from E into E, and g, h, i, and j four mappings from £2 into E. Then there exists a unique mapping ¢from :F into E satisfying the following conditions: Lemma 1.13 • • • the restriction of¢ to P is ¢o; for anyformula F E :F, ¢ (-.F) ==f (¢(F)); for allformulas F and G E :F, ¢((F 1\ G)) == g (¢(F) , ¢ (G)) ¢ ((F v G)) == h(¢ (F), ¢ (G )) ¢ ( ( F ==} G)) == i (¢ (F), ¢ (G)) and ¢ ( ( F {} G)) = j (¢ (F), ¢ (G)) Proof The uniqueness of ¢ is easily proved by induction on the set of formulas using the unique decomposition theorem. The existence of¢, which is intuitively clear, is proved with an elementary argument from set theory that we will not • present here. 19 SYNTAX Here i s a n initial example o f definition b y induction, for the concept o f sub­ formula of a propositional formula: Definition 1.14 With each formula F we associate a subset sf(F) of F, which is defined by induction according to F E called the set of sub-formulas of F, the following conditions: • if F E P, sf( F ) • { F} ; if F == -,G, sf( F) • = if F == (G a H) where == a E { /\ , v , sf(F) == sf( G) U { F } ; :::::} , ¢> }, sf( G) U sf(H) U { F } . [t is easy to verify that the sub-formulas o f a formula are exactly those that appear as nodes in its decomposition tree. 1.1.6 Substitutions in a propositional formula Let F be a formula in F and let A I , A 2, . . . , An be propositional variables from P that are pairwise distinct (this hypothesis is essential). We will use the notation F [ A b A2, . . . , An ] for F when we wish to emphasize that the elements of P that occur at least once in F are among A I , A2, . . . , An . For example, the formula F == (A =} (B v A) ) could be written as F [ A , B], but also as F[A , B, C, D] if it is useful to do so in a given context. If we are given a formula F [ A I , A2, . . . , A n , B1 , B2, . . . , Bml and n formu­ las G I , G2, . . . , G n , consider the word obtained by substituting the formula G 1 (respectively: G2, . . . , Gn ) for the variable A 1 , (respectively: A2, . . . , An) at each occurrence of these in F. This word will be denoted by Fc 1 jA 1 , c2 JA 2 , G11 fAn ••• • (read this as ' F sub G 1 replaces A I , G2 replaces A2, et cetera, Gn replaces A n ' ), but we will also denote it by F [G 1 , G2, . . . , Gn , B 1 , B2, . . . , B mJ despite the fact that this might cause some delicate problems. Forexample, i f F == F[A , B ] is the formula (A =} ( Bv A) ) and G is the formula (B =} A), then FcjA is the word ((B =} A) =} (B v (B :::::} A)) which we could denote by F [G, B] or equally well by F [ ( B � A), B]. If we then consider a propositional variable C (distinct from A and B ) and the formula H = C, then F H/A is the word (C =} (B v C)), which could be written, according to our conventions, as F [C, B ] . A nasty ambiguity then arises, since it is unclear how to PROPOSI TIO N A L CALCULUS 20 determine from the equalities F[A, B] == (A ==> (B v A)) and F[C, B] == (C =? (B v C )) which o f these two formulas i s the formula F . Nevertheless, the notation F[G I , G2, . . . , Gn , B, , 82, . . . , Bm ] i s extremely practical and, most of the time, perfectly clear. That is why we will permit our­ selves to use it, despite the danger we have pointed out, by limiting its use to circumstances where there can be no ambiguity. In fact we could give a definition of F c 1 jA 1 ,c2jA2, ... . G11 fA 11 by induction on the formula F (where G , � G2, . . . G n E F and A 1 , A2, . . . , An E P remain fixed): , • if F E P, then if F = Ak (I < k < n); i f F fj { A I , A2, . . . , A n } . • if F == -.G, then • if F (G a H), then == for all formulas G and H and symbol for a binary connective a . I n the examples that we provided, w e were able to observe that the word obtained after substituting formulas for propositional variables in a formula was, in every case, itself a formula. There is nothing surprising in this: Given an integer n,formulas F, G 1 . G2, . . . , Gn, and propositional variables A , , A2, . . . , An, the word Fc J fA , ,G2tA2, .. . , c11jA11 is aformula. Proof Letting G 1 , G2, . . . , G n E F and A A2, . . . ., An E P remain fixed, we Theorem 1.15 prove this by induction on the formula F. • • • 1, i f F E P, F c 1 jA 1 ,c2 jA2 , .... G11 /A11 is equal t o Gk if F = Ak (1 F if F ¢. { A 1 , A 2, . . . , An } ; in both cases this is a formula. < k < n) and to -.G, and if we suppose that GG 1 j A 1 . c2jA2 , . .. , G11 fA 11 is a formula, then FG 1 jA1 , G2jA2 .... , G11 /A11 , which is the word -, G c 1 j A 1 . c2j A2, .... G11 fA11 , is again a formula. if F == if F == (G a H) (where a is a symbol for a binary connective) and i f we suppose that the words G c 1j A 1 . c2jA 2 ..... G11f A ,1 and Hc J ! A 1 . c2jA 2, . .. , G11 fA11 are formulas, then F c 1 jA 1 .c2! A2, . . . ,Gn/A" ' which is the word ( G G t fA t ,G2/A2 ·····Gn/An a lfc t fA J . G2/A2 ..... G, jA,) , is also a formula. • 21 SEMANTICS Remark 1.16 It behooves us to insist on the fact that the formula Fc l / A 1 ,Gz/ A2, ... ,Gn ! An is the result of simultaneously substituting the formulas G 1 , G2, . . . , Gn for the variables A 1 , A2, . . . , An in the formula F. A priori we would obtain a d�fferent formula �fwe performed these substitutions one after another; moreover, the result we obtain might depend on the order in which these substitutions were performed. Let us take an example. Set We then have: whereas and We may also, in a given formula F, substitute a formula G for a sub-formula H of F. The word that results from this operation is once again a formula. Although, in practice, this type of substitution is very frequent, we will not introduce a special notation for it and will not enter into details. Let us be satisfied with an example. Suppose that F G == == ( ((A 1\ B ) => (-.B 1\ (A -¢? ( B v C)) and ==> C))) v (B -¢? (B ==> (A v C)))), (A H == ( _,B A (A ==> C)). Then, by substituting G for the sub-formula H in the formula F, we obtain the formula (((A 1\ B ) ==> (A -¢? (B v C))) v (B � (B ==> (A v C)))). 1.2 Semantics 1.2.1 Assignments of truth values and truth tables Definition 1.17 the set {0, 1}. An assignment of truth values to P is a mapping from P into Instead of 'assignment of truth values' , some speak of a 'valuation', others of an 'evaluation ' , or 'distribution of truth values'. 22 PROPOSlTlONAL CALCULUS An assignment of truth values to P is therefore an element of the set {0, 1 } P. An assignment of truth values 8 E {0� 1 } P attributes, to each propositional variable A, a value 8 ( A ) which is 0 or 1 (intuitively, false or true). Once this is done, we will see that it is then possible, in one and only one way, to extend 8 to the set of all propositional formulas while respecting the rules that agree, more or less, with our intuition as suggested by the names we have given to the various symbols for propositional connectives. Why 'more or less' ? Because, although it is doubtful that anyone would be surprised that a formula F will receive the value 1 if and only if the formula -.F receives the value 0, the decision to attribute the value 1 to the formula (F => G) when the formulas F and G each have the value 0 will perhaps give rise to more uneasiness (at least at first sight). One way to dissipate this uneasiness is to ask ourselves under what circumstances the formula ( F ==} G ) could be considered false: we would probably agree that this would only happen in the case where F were true without G being true, which leads us to attribute the value 1 to (F ::::} G ) in the other three possible cases. The difficulty no doubt arises from the fact that, in mathematical arguments, we have the impression that we practically never have to consider situations of the type 'false implies false' or 'false implies true'. But this i mpression is misleading. No one will contest, for example, that the statement 'for every natural number n , n divisible by 4 implies n is even' is true. But an inevitable consequence of this is that the following two statements are true: ' 1 divisible by 4 implies 1 is even '; '2 divisible by 4 implies 2 is even' . The situations 'false implies false' and 'false implies true' were already present in our initial statement; let us simply say that we don't really care. Another remark is called for here. If we took a poll among mathematicians asking them whether the statement 'n divisible by 3 implies n odd' is true or false, the second response would win overwhelmingly. For any mathematician would think to have read or heard the statement 'every natural number divisible by 3 is odd' and would legitimately respond: it's false. This is because standard mathematical usage considers that statements having theformof an implication are automatically accompanied by a universal quantifier that is taken for granted. There is no shortage of examples (the statement VE > 0 38 > 0 (lx ·- yl < 8 :::} f f(x ) - f(y )l < E ) is often taken as the definition of uniform continuity of a function f; in this context, the quantifiers Vx and \ly, which should be placed between '38 > 0' and the first opening parenthesis, are frequently omitted because they are considered to be understood; this could explain the difficulty that certain students have when asked to describe a function that is not uniformly continuous . . . ). As for the question in our poll, it makes no sense as we have stated it, until we know what the integer n is. 23 S EM A N T I C S And it suffices to replace n by 3, by 4 or by 5 for the statement to be true (it will be, respectively, of type 'true implies true', 'false implies false', and 'false implies true' ). There is another difficulty concerning implication, which is that mathematicians generally see in it a notion of causality, which propositional calculus absolutely does not take into account. If PI and P2 are two true statements, propositional logic imposes the value true on the statement ' PI implies P2 ' . But a mathematician will refuse, more often than not, to affirm that 'Pt implies P2 is true when the statements Pt and P2 have 'nothing to do' with one another. Is it true that Rolle's theorem implies the Pythagorean theorem? Those who do not dismiss this question as absurd will generally respond no, because to say yes suggests that they are in position to provide a proof of the Pythagorean theorem in which Rolle's theorem is actually involved. Though the conflicts between intuition or mathematical usage and the definitions that we are about to give arise especially with implication, the other connectives may also make a modest contribution to this (disjunction is often interpreted as exclusive (A or B but not both) whereas our v will not be). In propositional calculus, these kinds of questions are not to be considered. We will be content to perform very simple operations oo two objects: 0 and 1, and our only reference wilJ be to the definitions of these operations, i.e. to what we will later call the truth tables. Let it be perfectly clear that the intuition we referred to above is exclusively mathematical intuition. Our concern is not at all to invoke 'everyday' logic (the one that is known as 'common sense'). Mathematicians make no pretence of possessing a universal mode of reasoning. It is hard to resist applying mathematical reasoning to situations outside mathematics, seduced as we are by the rigour of this reasoning, when we discover it. But the result is not what we had hoped: we soon face the fact that human problems do not allow themselves to be resolved by mathematical logic. As for the supposed pedagogical virtues of giving 'real-life examples' , they are the opposite of what some may expect from them. This type of approach does not, in any determining way, make the apprenticeship of the rules of mathematical logic any easier, but it is very useful for teaching us prudence, and even humility: to learn mathematical reasoning, let us study mathematics. In fact, we can ask ourselves whether, to illustrate that a formula involving implication is equivalent to its contrapositive, it is more convincing to take the very celebrated example 'if it is raining I take my umbrella' compared to ' if I do not take my umbrella it is not raining' or the example 'if n is prime then n is odd' compared to 'if n is even then n is not prime'. Indeed� it suffices to perform the two experiments to conclude that the example of the umbrella immediately provokes, justifiably, a slew of objections. It is not uninteresting to also note that the contrapositive of 'if it is raining I take my umbrella' is most often stated in the form: 'I do not take my umbrella, therefore it is not raining' , which more closely resembles an 'argued conjunction' than an implication. The application of mathematical logic to 'everyday life' has produced • 24 PROPOSITIONAL CALCULUS a choice collection of hilarious examples that the students of Daniel Lacombe know well and which have attained a certain popularity among logicians: • A father threatens his son: 'if you are not quiet you will get a slap ! ' , and he proceeds to administer the slap even though the child had immediately become quiet; from the point of view of mathematical logic, this man is not at fault: the truth table for =} shows that, by becoming quiet, the child makes the implication true regardless of the truth value of 'you will get a slap' . . . (a good father should have said 'you will get a slap if and only if you are not quiet'). • I n view o f tautology no. 1 7 from Section 1 .2.3, what should we think about the equivalence between 'if you are hungry, there is some meat in the fridge' and its contrapositive: 'if there is no meat in the fridge, you are not hungry'? • When a contest offers as its first prize 'a new car or a cheque for $ 1 00 000', why shouldn't the winner claim both the car and the cheque, relying on the truth table for disjunction? As we see, all this no doubt has an amusing side, but it does not help us at all in resolving exercises from mathematics in general or mathematical logic in particular. We will therefore leave our umbrella in the closet and remain in the world of mathematics, where there is already enough to do. For any assignment of truth values 8 E {0, 1 } P , there exists a unique map 8 :F =} {0, 1 } which agrees with 8 on P (i.e. it extends 8) and which satisfies the following properties: Theorem 1.18 : (1) foranyformula F, - 8(- ,F) (2) 1 - ifand only if 8(F) == 0; for allformulas F and G. - 8(F 1\ G) (3) == = 1 - if and only if 8(F) == - 8 (G) == 1; == 0; for allformulas F and G , - 8 ( F v G) = - 0 (f and only if 8(F) == - 8 (G) ( 4) for allformulas F and G, - 8 (F =} G) (5) == - 0 (f and only (f 8 (F) == - 1 and 8 (G) == 0; for allformulas F and G, - 8 (F {:} G) == 1 - (fand only if8 (F) == - 8 (G). Proof To simplify the notation, let us observe right away that conditions ( I ) to (5) can be expressed using the operations of addition and multiplication on the two-element field 'll /2'1L, with which we can naturally identify the set {0, 1 } . These 25 SEMANTICS conditions then become equivalent to: for all formulas F and G: ( i ') (ii') (iii ') (iv') (v' ) - - 8(-,F) = 1 + 8 (F); 8 ((F 1\ G)) = 8 (F) 8(G); 8((F v G)) = 8 (F) + 8(G) + 8(F) 8(G) 8((F ==} G)) = 1 + 8(F) + 8 (F) 8 (G); 8 ((F <=> G)) = 1 + 8 (F) + 8(G). - - - - - - (The proof is immediate.) We see that the function 8 is defined by induction on the set of formulas, which is what guarantees its existence and uniqueness by Lemma 1 . 13; here, the functions f, g, h, i, and j are defined on 7lj27l by: for all x and y, f(x) = I + x, g(x, y) = xy, h(x, y) = x + y + xy, i (x , y) = 1 + x + xy and j (x , y) = 1 + x + y. • We should point out that identifying {0, 1 } with 7Lj27l is extremely practical and will be used in what follows. We can recapitulate conditions (i ') to ( v') above in tables which we call the truth tables for negation, for conjunction, for disjunction, for implication and for equivalence: -- F -, F -- 0 1 1 0 --- F G ( F 1\ G) F G (F v G) 0 0 1 1 0 0 1 1 0 1 0 l F G (F ==} G) 0 0 l 1 0 1 0 1 1 1 0 1 0 0 0 1 0 1 0 1 0 1 1 1 F G (F <=> G) 0 0 1 0 1 1 1 0 1 0 0 1 In practice, we will not really make the distinction between an assignment of truth values and its extension to the set of formulas. We will speak of the 'truth value of the formula F under the assignment 8' and we will eventually forget the bar over the 8 which would have indicated that we were dealing with the extension. If F is a formula and 8 is an assignment of truth values, we will say that F is satisfied by 8, or that 8 satisfies F, when 8 ( F) = 1 . 26 P R O PO S I T I O N A L C A L C U L U S Given a formula F and an assignment of truth values 8, the definition of the extension 8 clearly points to a method for calculating 8 (F): this consists in calculating the values taken by 8 on the various sub-formulas of F, beginning with the sub-formulas of height 1 (the values for those of height 0 being precisely what is given), and applying the tables above as many times as necessary. For example, if F is the formula ((A ==? B) ==? (B v (A ¢> C ) ) ) and if 8 is an assignment of truth values for which 8 (A) == 8 ( B ) = 0 and 8(C) == 1, then we have successively: 8((A ==? B) ) == 1 ; 8 ((A ¢> C ) ) == 0 � 8((B v (A ¢> C))) == 0 and 8(F) == 0. Of course, it can happen that calculating the values of 8 for all the sub-formulas of F is unnecessary: to see this, consider the formula G == (A ==? (((B 1\ - ·A) v (-,C 1\ A)) ¢> (A v (A ==? -·B ) ) ) ) and an assignment of truth values A for which A(A) == 0; we may conclude that A (G) == l without bothering with the truth value of the sub-formula ( ((B 1\ - ·A) v (-.C 1\ A)) ¢> (A v (A ==? _,B))) . In the examples that we have just examined, to calculate the truth value of a formula, we only used the values taken by the assignment of truth values under consideration on the variables that actually occur in the formula. It is clear that this is always the case. For any formula F[A 1 , A 2, . . . , An] (involving no propositional variables other than A 1 , A 2, . . . , An) and any assignments of truth values A and J.L E {0, l } P , �{A and J.L agree on { A t , A2, . . . , A}, then A( F) == JL (F). Lemma 1.19 Proof The proof involves no difficulties. It is done by induction on the formulas . • Let G[A 1 , A 2 , . . . , An] be a formula. To discover the set of truth values of G (corresponding to the set of all possible assignments), we see that it is sufficient to 'forget' momentarily the variables in P that do not occur in G , and to suppose that the set of propositional variables is just {A 1 , A2, . . . , An }- There are then only a finite number of assignments of truth values to consider: this is the number of mappings from { A t , A2, . . . , An} into {0, 1 } , namely 2n (recall that the nota­ tion G[A t , A 2, . . . , An] presumes that the variables Ai are pairwise distinct). We can identify each mapping 8 from {A 1 , A2, . . . , An} into {0, 1} with the n-tuple (8(At ), 8 (A2), . . . , 8 (An)) E {0, l} n and place the set of truth values taken by G into a tableau in which each row would correspond to one of the 2n n-tuples and would contain the corresponding truth value of G. Such a tableau, which could also contain the truth values of the sub-formulas of G, will be called the truth table of the formula G. Ultimately, this is nothing more than the table of values of a certain mapping from {0, 1 } n into {0, 1}. 27 SEMANTICS Let us return to the example given just above: G == (A =} (((B Set A -.A), == ( H v / ) , H == K A -,A) v (-,C A A ) ) <:> (B Then we have G == (A ::::::} A B c 0 0 0 0 1 1 1 1 0 0 1 1 0 0 1 1 0 1 0 1 0 1 0 1 A A), J (A v J), M I == ( -.C L == v (A (A == == =} -.B)))) . (A =} -. B ) , ( K <:> L ) . M). Here i s the truth table for G : -, A -, B -, c 1 1 1 1 0 0 0 0 1 1 0 0 1 1 0 0 1 0 1 0 1 0 1 0 H I J K L M G 0 0 1 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 0 0 1 1 1 0 1 0 1 1 1 1 1 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 1 0 1 1 1 1 1 1 0 0 1 0 1 0 We should note that, with our conventions concerning the notation we do not have uniqueness of the truth table for a formula (for example, the first four columns of the table above could be considered as the truth table of the formula -, A). There is, nonetheless, a 'minimal' table for every formula, the one which involves only those propositional variables that occur at least once in the formula. 1-Iowever, even restricting ourselves to this notion of minimal table, there can stil1 be, for the same formula, many tables which differ in the order in which the n-tuples from {0, l }n are presented. It is reasonable to choose, once and for all, a particular order (among the 2n ! that are possible) and to adopt it systematically. We have chosen the lexicographical order (the 'dictionary' order): in the table, the n-tuple (a1 , a2, . . . , an) will be placed ahead of (bt , b2, . . . , bn) if, for the fi rst subscript j E { 1 , 2, . . . , n } for which aj =P b j , we have a j < b j . ] n view of these remarks, we will allow ourselves to speak about 'the' truth table of a formula. 1.2..2 Tautologies and logically equivalent formulas Definition 1.20 • A tautology truth values. is a formula that assumes the value 1 under every assignment of 28 • • PROPOSITIONAL CALCULUS the notation for 'F is a tautology' is: I-* F ; whereas ¥* F sign�fies: ' F is not a tautology '. Given two formulas F and G, F is logically equivalent to G ifand only ({the formula (F {} G) is a tautology. The notation for ' F is logically equivalent to G ' is: F G. "-.J Remark 1.21 • The next two propertiesfollow immediatelyfrom these definitions: For all formulas F and G, we have F G 1j and only iff'or every assignment oftruth values 8 E {0, l } P , o (F) 8 (G). The binary relation is an equivalence relation on :F. "-.J = • � The equivalence class of the formula F for the relation � ci(F). is denoted by A tautology is therefore a formula whose truth table contains only ls in its last column, in other words, a formula that is �always true' . Two logically equivalent formulas are two formulas that are satisfied by exactly the same assignments of truth values, which thus have the same truth table. Any formula logically equivalent to a tautology is a tautology. Therefore the tautologies constitute one of the equiv­ alence classes for the relation denoted by 1. The formulas whose negations are tautologies (some call these antilogies, others antitautologies) constitute another equivalence class, distinct from 1. denoted by 0: these are the formulas that are 'always false', which is to say that their truth tables contain only Os in the last column. When we do semantics, we argue 'up to equivalence'. This will be justified by the study of the set of equivalence classes for the equivalence relation ""', which we will do a bit further on and will complete in Chapter 2 . Let us now examine the effect of substitutions o n the truth values o f formulas: "-.J, Given an assignment of truth values, 8, a natural number, n, formulas F, G 1 , G2, . . . , Gn, and pairwise distinct propositional variables A 1 , A2, . ., An, let A be the assignment of truth values defined by Theorem 1.22 . for all X E P, A.(X) { = 8(X) 8 (G i ) � { A 1 , A2, . if X = Ai ( l < �f X . . , An } ; i < n). We then have Proof We argue by induction on the formula • F: i f F is a n element of P , then: either F ¢:. {A I , A2, . . . , An}; in this case, Fc1 ;A1 .G2jA2 - 8 ( FG , / A t .G2f A 2····•Gil/A ,) == o( F) == o ( F) == • ••• ,G11 /Ail "A (F) == = "A ( F ) ; F and 29 SEMANTICS by definition of A. • = I f F = _,G, and i f we suppose that 8 ( G e 1 1A 1 ,e21A2, . . ., e11IA,) induction hypothesis), then - 8 ( Fe 1 I A 1 ,e21 A2, .... en1An ) = A.( G ) (the - 8 ( -, G e 1 I A 1 ,e21 A2, ... , en1An ) - 1 + 8(G e 1 IA I . e2/A2, ... ,en /An ) = 1 + A(G) = A(--,G) = A( F). • If F= ( G 1\ H ) , and if we suppose (the induction hypothesis) 8 ( G e 1 1A 1 , e21A 2, . .. ,e111 A11 ) = A(G ) and 8 ( He 1 1A 1 ,e21A2, ...,e11 IA11 ) = A(H), then 8 ( Fe 1 ; A 1 ,e2 ; A2 .. .. ,e11 jA,J = 8(( G e 1IAI ,e2IA2, ... ,e,;An 1\ He 1 IA 1 .e21 A2, ... ,en IA, ) ) = 8 (G e J !A t ,e2IA2, . . . ,en iA, ) X 8 ( He1j A 1 , e2/A2, ... , en /An ) = A(G) A(H) = A.((G 1\ • H)) = A.(F). The cases F = (G v H ) , F = ( G =} H ) , and F == (G <=? H ) are treated in a similar fashion without the slightest difficulty; indeed, we could really not bother with them at all (for this, see Remark 1 .33 later on). • The next corollary follows immediately from the theorem: For allformulas F, G 1 , Gz, . . . , G andpairwise distinctpropo­ sitional variables A 1 , A 2 , . . . , An, {f F is a tautology, then so is the formula Corollary 1.23 n Proof Given an arbitrary assignment of truth values 8, by defining the assignment A as in the previous theorem, we have since F is a tautology. • Another type of substitution also allows us to preserve logical equivalence of formulas: Consider aformula F, a sub-.formula G ofF and aformula H that is logically equivalent to G. Then theformula F', obtainedfrvm F by substituting H for the sub-formula G, is Logically equivalent to F. Theorem 1.24 30 PROPOSITIONAL CALCULUS Proof We argue by induction on the formula F. • • I f F E P, then, necessarily, = F and F ' = H. We certainly have F ' � F. F, or else G is I f F = -. Ft , then either G = F, F ' = H, and we have F ' a sub-formula of F 1 and, by the induction hypothesis, the formula F; , which results from substituting H for G in F 1 , is logically equivalent to F 1 . Then the formula F' is the formula -,F{; it is therefore logically equivalent to F since, for any assignment of truth values 8, we have � - I 8(F ) • G = - I 1 + 8 ( F1 ) = - 1 + 8 ( F1 ) = - 8 (--. FI ) = - 8(F). If F = ( Ft 1\ F2), then there are three possibilities. Either G = F, F' = H , F. O r else G i s a sub-formula of F 1 , and, b y the induction and w e have F ' hypothesis, the formula F [, which results from substituting H for G in F 1 , is logically equivalent to F 1 · Then the formula F ' is the formula (F � 1\ F2) ; it is logically equivalent to F because, for any assignment 8, we have � The argument is strictly similar in the third case, when of F2 . G is a sub-formula The cases F = (FI v F2) , F = ( FI ==} F2) , and F == (Fl {;> F2) are treated i n • an analogous fashion using relations (iii' ) to ( v ' ) from Theorem 1 . 18. In practice, to show that a formula is a tautology, or that two formulas are logically equivalent, we have several methods available. First of all, we could use truth tables, but this is no longer viable once the number of variables exceeds 3 or 4. In certain cases, we could have recourse to what might be called 'economical truth tables' : this consists in discussing the values taken by a restricted number of variables; in a way, we are treating several lines of the truth table in a single step. Let us take an example: we will show that the following formula F is a tautology: ( (A ==} ((B v -.C) 1\ _,(A ==} D))) v ((D 1\ --. £ ) v (A v C))). By setting H = K = (A ==} ((B v -.C) 1\ ...., ( A ((D 1\ --, £ ) v (A v C)), => D))) and we have F = ( H v K ) . Next, consideran assignment oftruth values 8 . I f8 (A ) = 0, then we see that 8 (H) = 1, thus also 8 (F) = l . I f 8 (A ) = 1, then 8 ( A v C) = 1 , hence 8 (K) = 1 and 8 (F) = 1 . Just a s well, we could invoke Corollary 1 .23 and Theorem 1 .24 by making use of certain 'basic' tautologies (see the list in Section 1 .2.3 ). For example, to show that the formula G = ( (....,A v B) v -,(A ==} B)) is a tautology, we first use the fact that the formulas (-,A v B) and (A ==} B) are logically equivalent, which shows - SEMANTICS 31 that G is logically equivalent to ( ( A ==} B ) v -, ( A ==} B ) ) (by Theorem 1 .24 ), then observe that this latter formula is obtained by substituting the formula (A => B) for the variable A i n the tautology ( A v-,A), and is therefore itself a tautology (by Corollary 1 .23 ). Needless to say, we will only rarely be led to present such an argument with this degree of detail. �fhere are also purely syntactical methods which can be used to prove that a formula is a tautology (see Chapter 4 ) . Finally, Exercise 1 4 shows how we can reduce all this to a simple calculation involving polynomials. 1.2.3 Some tautologies Here is a list of common tautologies (which are just so many exercises for the reader, with no solutions given! ) : (A , B and C denote propositional variables (but w e may, by Corollary 1 .23, substitute arbitrary formulas in their place); T denotes an arbitrary tautology and _L the negation of T, which is to say a formula that always takes the value 0.) (l) (2) (�) (4) (5) ( 6) (7) (8) (9) ( 1 0) (l l ) ( 1 2) ( 1 3) ( 1 4) ( 1 5) ( 1 6) ( 1 7) ((A 1\ A ) ¢> A ) ((A v A) � A) ((A 1\ B) � (B 1\ A)) ( ( A v B) � (B v A)) ((A 1\ ( B 1\ C)) � ((A 1\ B) 1\ C)) ( (A v (B v C)) � ( ( A v B) v C)) ((A 1\ (B v C)) � ((A 1\ B) v (A 1\ ((A v ( B 1\ C)) � ( (A v B) 1\ (A v ((A 1\ (A v B)) ¢> A) ((A v (A 1\ B)) ¢> A) (_,(A v B ) {} (_, A 1\ _, B)) ( _, ( A 1\ B ) � ( _,A v -, B)) ((A 1\ T) {} A ) ( (A v .L) {} A ) ( ( A A _L) {} _L) ((A v T) � T ) ((A ==} B ) {} (-rB ==} -rA)) C))) C,))) These tautologies reflect important properties. Numbers ( 1 ) and (2) express the idempotence of conjunction and disjunction, (3) and (4) their commutativity, (5) and (6) their associativity, (7) and (8) the distributivity of each over the other. But be carefu l ! All this is taking place up to logical equivalence (which is to say that these properties are really properties of operations on the set :FI � of equiv­ alence classes for the relation � on F: for more details, refer to Exercise 1 from Chapter 2). Numbers (9) and ( 1 0) are called the absorption laws. Numbers ( 1 1 ) 32 PROPOSITIONAL CALCULUS and ( 1 2) express de Morgan's laws (see Chapter 2 as well). Tautology number ( 13) (respectively, number ( 1 4)) expresses that the class of tautologies 1 (respectively, the class of antilogies 0) is the identity element for conjunction (respectively, for disjunction). Number ( 1 5) (respectively, number ( 1 6)) expresses that the class 0 (respectively, the class 1) is the zero element for conjunction (respectively, for disjunction). The formula ( _, B => _,A) is called the contrapositive of (A => B ) and tautology number ( 1 7 ) expresses that every implicative formula i s logically equivalent to its contrapositive. We will now continue our list with additional common tautologies: ( 1 8) ( 1 9) (20) (21) (22) (23) (24) (25) (26) (27) (28) (29) (30) (3 1 ) (32) (33) (34) (35) (36) (37) (A v _,A) (A => A ) (A <=> A ) ( -. -. A =? A ) (A => ( A v B)) ((A 1\ B) =? A ) (((A =} B) 1\ A) =? B ) (((A => B) 1\ -.B) => -. A ) ((-.A =? A ) =? A ) ((-.A =? A) <=> A ) (-.A => (A =? B)) (A v (A =? B)) (A => (B =? A)) (((A => B ) 1\ ( B =? C )) => ( A => C )) ( (A =? B) v (C =? A )) ( ( A =} B) v (-.A => B)) ((A =? B) v (A =? -,B ) ) ((A =? B) => ((B => C) =? (A :::::;> C))) (-,A =? ( -.. B <=> (B =? A )) ) ((A => B) => (((A => C ) => B) => B) ) Moreover, in the list below, formulas that are all on the same line are pairwise logically equivalent. (38) (39) (40) (41 ) (42) (43) ( 44) (45) (46) (47) (48) (A =? B ) , (-.A v B), (-.. B => -.A), ((A 1\ B) {:? A ) , ( (A v B) {:? B) _,(A =? B ) , (A 1\ -.B) (A # B), ((A 1\ B) v (_,A 1\ -. B ) ) , ((-.A v B) 1\ (-1B v A)) (A <=> B), ((A => B ) 1\ ( B =? A )) , (-�A <=> -.B), (B <=> A ) (A <=> B), ((A v B) =? (A 1\ B)) -.(A <=> B ) , ( A <=> -. B), (-,A # B) A , -.-.A , (A 1\ A ) , (A v A ) , (A v (A 1\ B)), (A 1\ (A v B)) A , (-.A => A ) , (A => B) => A ) , ((B => A) 1\ ( -.. B =? A )) A , (A 1\ T), (A v T), (A <=> T), (T => A ) -. A , (A =? -.A), ((A =? B) 1\ (A =? -.B)) -. A , (A =>_L), (A ¢> _L ) 33 S EM A N T I C S (49) (50) (5 1 ) (52) (53) (54) (55) (56) (57) (58) _.L, (AI\ l_ ) , (A � --·A ) T, (A v T ) , ( A ==> T ) , (J-=> A) ( A 1\ B ) , ( B 1\ A ) , (A 1\ (-.A v B ) ) , -.(A => -.B) (A v B), (B v A), (A v (-�A ;, B ) ) , (-,A => B ) , ((A => B) ==> B ) (A ==> ( B =} C)), ((A 1\ B ) :::::} C), ( B ==> (A ==> C)), ((A ==> B) ==> (A ==> C)) (A ==> (B 1\ C)), ((A => B ) 1\ ( A ==> C)) (A ==> ( B v C ) ) , ((A ==> B) v (A ==> C)) ( (A A B) => C), ((A � C) v ( B ==> C)) ((A v B) ==> C ) , ((A => C) 1\ ( B ==> C)) (A {} (B {} C ) ) , ((A {} B) {} C) . We should take notice, from lines (54) to (57), that implication does not distribute over conjunction nor over disjunction. We see however that it does distribute from the left ((54) and (55)), which is to say when 1\ and v occur to the right of =>. In the case when one or the other is located to the left of �, we have a kind of artificial distributivity, the ;, (respectively, the v) being transformed into v (respectively, into t,) after its 'distribution' ((56) and (57)). It behoves us to be vigilant in all cases when manipulating this type of formula. From now on, we will admit the following abuses of notation: • • In general, in writing a formula, we will allow ourselves to omit the outer­ most parentheses. This convention supposes that these parentheses automati­ cally reappear as soon as this formula occurs as a (strict) sub-formula of another formula: for example, we will accept the formula F = A ¢> B, and the formula F ==> -. c, but the latter will obviously be written (A {} B) => --.c and not as A. ¢> B =? _,C. For all formulas F, G , and H , the formula ( ( F 1\ G ) 1\ H ) will be written ( F 1\ G ;, H ) , the formula ( ( F v G ) v H ) will b e written ( F v G v H ) . We could also, by applying the previous convention concerning the omission of parentheses, write F 1\ G 1\ H or F v G v H. • More generally, for any non-zero natural number k, if Fr , F2 , formulas, we will let Fr 1\ F2 1\ - · - 1\ Fk represent the formula . . . , Fk are (which begins with k - 1 occurrences of the open parenthesis symbol). Of course we make the analogous convention for disjunction. • If I = {i 1 , i 2 , . . . , ik} is a non-empty finite set of indices and if F; 1 ' Fi2 , are formulas, the formula F; 1 A Fh 1\ · · · 1\ Fik will also be written: (to be read as 'the conjunction of the F j for j belonging to I ' ). • • • , Fik 34 PROPOSITIONAL CALCULUS We will notice that with this notation, there is an ambiguity relating to the order of the indices in the set I, which needs to be fixed for this manner of writing to have a meaning. But in fact� as long as we are concerned with semantics, the choice of this ordering has no importance whatever in view of the commutativity of conjunction. In the same way, the formula F; 1 v F;2 v · · · v Fik will be abbreviated: V F· j E/ .I (to be read as 'the disjunction o f the F.i for j belonging to / ' ). Naturally, we will also have variants, such as V 1 <k <n Gk or 1\FEX F (where X is a non-empty finite set of formulas), whose meaning is clear. In fact, our decision, for example, that the expression A v B v C represents the formula ((A v B) v C) is based on an arbitrary choice. We could just as well have opted for the formula (A v (B v C)) which is logically equivalent to the first one. It is the associativity of conjunction and disjunction (numbers (5) and (6) from Section 1 .2.3) that led us suppress these parentheses knowing that, whatever method is used to reintroduce them, we obtain a formula from the same equivalence class. (In Exercise 16, we will understand why it would be imprudent to allow the analogous abuses of notation in the case of {} , although this appears, according to number (58) from Section 1 .2.3, to allow it just as well as 1\ and v). 1.3 Normal forms and complete sets of connectives 1.3.1 Operations on {0, 1 } and formulas Up to and including Section 1 .3.3, we will assume that the set P of propositional variables is a finite set of n elements (n > 1 ) : P == { A 1 , A 2 , . . . , An } - This allows us to consider that every formula F E F has its variables among A t , A 2 , . . . , An and to write F == F [A 1 , A 2 , . . . , A 11 j. Notation: • n For every n-tuple (E I , £2 , . . . , En ) E {0, l } , 8€ 1 , €2 , , 811 denotes the distribution of truth values defined by 88 1 , 82 , ,€11 (A;) == £; for each i E { 1 , 2, . . . , n } . • .. ... • For each propositional variable A and for each element £ E {0, 1 } we let EA denote the formula that i s equal t o A i f £ == 1 and to _,A i f £ == 0. For each formula F, we let 6. (F) denote the set of distributions of truth values that satisfy F: t:.r.( F ) == {8 E {0, l } P : 8 ( F ) == 1}. N 0 R M A L F0RM S AN D C0M PL E TE S E TS 0F C0N N E CTIV ES 35 For each formula F, we define a mapping CfJF from {0, l } P into {0, 1 } by The mapping CfJ F is thus none other than the one defined by the truth table o f F. We will allow ourselves the slight abuse of language involved in saying that <p F is the truth table of F. Notice that two formulas F and G are logically equivalent if andonly if cp F = cpc . n What this means precisely is that the mapping F � (/J F (from F into {0, l } ({O, l } ) ) is compatible with the relation We also see that this mapping is not injective (for example, for any formula F, we have: cp-.-.F = CfJ F ), but that the mapping n that it induces, from F/ � into {0, l } ({O, l} ) (the mapping ci(F) � (/J F ) is injec­ tive (recall that ci(F) denotes the equivalence class of the formula F under the equivalence relation � ). This shows that the number of equivalence classes for the relation � on F is at most equal to the number of mappings from {0, 1 }n into {0, 1}, which is to say 22n . 2n It remains to discover if there are exactly 2 equivalence classes of formulas or if there are fewer. In other words, is the mapping F � CfJ F surjective? Or again, n can the table of an arbitrary mapping from {0, 1 } into {0, 1} be viewed as the truth table of some formula? The answer to these questions is positive, as we will see with the next theorem. The proof of the theorem will furnish us with an explicit method for finding such a formula, knowing only its truth table. �. Lemma 1.25 For any n-tuple (ct , £2, . . . , en) E {0, is satisfied by the distribution oftruth values 8 81 ,82, ... l} n , the formula ,817 and by no othe1: In our notation, this would be written: � (/\ 1 :s_k :s_n E'kAk) = {881 .82, ...• Proof For any distribution of truth values A., we have A.(/\ 1 < k < n E'k Ak) only if for every k E { 1 , 2, . . . , n} , A. (£k A k) of 881 ,82 , en , is equivalent to: = 8n }. = 1 i f and 1, which, in view of the definition .•.. in other words, to A. Lemma 1.26 = 881 ,82, .. .,8, • • Let X be a non-empty subset of {0. l } n and let F be the formula x Then the formula Fx is satisfied by those distributions of truth values 881 ,82,...,811 for which (EI , E2, , en ) E X and only by these. • . . 36 PROPOSITIONAL CALCULUS With our notations, Proof For any distribution of truth values A, we have A(Fx) = 1 if and only if there exists an n-tuple (8t , 82, . . . , 8n) E X such that A.( A1 <i <n Bi Ai) = 1, which, according to Lemma 1 .2 5, isequivalentto: thereexists ann-tuple (8I , 82, . . . , 811) E X such that A = 8£1 ,£2 , ,811 , or equivalently, to ••• • For any mapping cp from {0, l}n into {0, 1 } , there exists at least one formula F such that cpF = cp. Theorem 1.27 (In other words, every mapping from {0, 1}11 into {0, l } is a truth table). n Proof Fix a mapping <p from {0, l} into {0, l}. • I fit assumes only the value 0, then it i s a truth table, for example, of the formula F = ( A t 1\-,A I). • In the opposite case, the set is non-empty and, by virtue of Lemma 1 .26, the formula is satisfied by those distributions of truth values 861 ,62 , . . .. 611 for which cp(t:1 , 82 , . . . , t:11 ) 1 and only by these. = In other words, for any n-tuple (8 t , £2 , . . . , En ) 8c 1 ,c2, •. • ,sn E n {0, 1 } , we have (F) = 1 if and only if cp(8I , 82, . . . , 8n ) = 1. This means precisely that <p is the function <p rx , the truth table of the formula F . • 11 Thus we see that there are 22 equivalence classes of formulas on a set of n 21 propositional variables, corresponding to the 2 1 possible truth tables. Mappings from {0, 1 }17 into {0, l } are sometimes called n-place propositional connectives. We see that it is harmless to identify such an object with the class of formulas which is naturally associated to it In the cases n = I and n = 2 which we will examine in detail (and which lead respectively to 4 and to 1 6 truth tables), we will rediscover, among the common N 0 RM A L F0RM S A N D C 0M P L ETE SETS 0F C0 NNE CTI V ES 37 names for these one- or two-place connectives, names that were already used to denote symbols for propositional connectives. Thus, for example, v simultane­ ously denotes the symbol for the propositional connective and the equivalence class of the formula ( A 1 v A 2 ) as well as the corresponding mapping from {0, 1 } 2 into {0, 1 }. Tables 1 . 1 and 1 .2 present all the two-place and one-place propositional con­ nectives (cp1 to <pi6 and 1/11 to 1/14 ) . The first columns give the values of each mapping at each point of {0, 1 }2 or of {0, 1}. The column that follows gives a formula belonging to the corresponding equivalence class. Finally, the last column displays the symbol in common use, if any, that represents the connective or its usual name. Table 1.1 The two-place connectives Values of cp; E1 0 E2 0 0 1 1 0 Example of a formula whose truth table is cp; 1 Usual denotation for CfJi 1 Symbol Name 0 FALSE AND DOES NOT IMPLY ...._ - ----·- ______ CfJl ( E I , E2) CfJ2(E ! , E2) CfJ3(E l , E2) CfJ4( E J , E2) C{J)(fl , E2) CfJ6(Et , E2) CfJ7(E J , E2) cpg(E J . E2) C{J9(E i , E2) CfJ JO(EJ , E2) C{JJ ] (E J , E2) CfJ J 2 (!: J , E 2) C{J J J (E J , E2) f/)J4( E J , E 2) C{JJS(EJ , E2 ) CfJ J 6 (E J , E2) 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 1 I 1 I 1 l 1 0 0 0 0 1 1 1 1 0 0 0 0 1 1 1 I 0 0 1 I 0 0 1 1 0 0 I 1 0 0 1 1 Table 1.2 0 1 0 1 0 1 0 1 0 1 0 1 0 1 0 1 E) 0 1 1/JJ (E I ) 1/12 (E I ) 0 0 1 1 0 1 0 I 1/14(E I ) " =I? {/} v '¥ {:} => ,f\ 1 The one-place connectives Values of 1/1; 1/13 (E I ) ( A J A -. A J ) ( A 1 A A2) -.(AJ � A2) A, -.(A2 => A 1 ) A2 -.(AI ¢> A2) ( A J v A2) -.(A 1 v A2) ( A , ¢> A2) -.A 2 (A2 � A J ) -.A I ( A , � A 2) -.(A 1 A A 2 ) ( A t v -.A J ) Example of a formula whose truth table is 1/li ( A J " -.A I ) At -. A I ( A J v -.A I ) Usual designation of 1j1; 0 (FALSE) IDENTITY (NOT) 1 (TRUE) --.., NOT EQUIVALENT OR SHEFFER'S 'OR' IS EQUIVALENT TO IMPLIES SHEFFER'S 'AND' TRUE 38 PROPOSITIONAL CALCULUS 1.3.2 Normal forms There are important consequences of Theorem 1 .27. Before examining them, we need some definitions: Definition 1.28 A formula is in (DNF) and only if there exist (a) an integer m (b) integers k1, k2, . . . , k l, (c) for every i { , m}, k; propositional variables: Bit, B;2, . . . , B;k, and k; elements 8; 8;2, . . . , 8;ki in {0, 1}, such that V (8; Bil 1\ 8;2B;2 1\ 1\ 8 ik; B;ki ). A formula is in (CDNF) if and only if there exists a non-empty subset of{O, such that F == ( (\ 8;A;) V n (€1 ,€2 , ... ,€n ) E X (3) By interchanging the symbols for disjunction and conjunction in parts and we obtain respectively the definitions ofaformula being in (CNF) and a formula being in (1) F disjunctive normalform > 1, �f m > E 1 , 2, . . . 1, F (2) F == · · · 1 J <i < m canonical disjunctive normalform X l }n 1 <i < (1) (2), normal form form (CCNF). conjunctive canonical conjunctive normal These definitions call fora few remarks. First of all, we see that to be in canonical disjunctive normal form is a special case of being in disjunctive normal form (the and E case where each is equal to where for each E { 1 , 2, . . . , 8iki are pairwise == j and where the m n-tuples 1 , { 1 , 2, distinct; note, in passing, that this forces to be at most equal to 2n ). Furthermore, by examining the proof of Theorem l .27, we see that given a mapping cp from {0, l }n into 0 , 1 } distinct from the zero mapping, there exists a formula F in canonical disjunctive normal form such that ({JF == cp. (The formula Fx that we have been considering is certainly in CDNF.) As well, we conclude a kind of uniqueness for canonical disjunctive (or conjunctive) normal forms, in the sense that two canonical disjunctive (or conjunctive) normal forms which are logically equivalent can differ only in the 'order of their factors' . More precisely, if the formulas: k; . . . , m}, Bij A n, m i , . . . , n} 8; 8;2 j { ( J<i<(\n s; A;) and (171 JJ2V •.•• ,1Jn ) E Y ( (\ J <i < n r}; A;) are logically equivalent, then the subsets X and Y of {0, l }n are identical. The analogous fact is obviously true for conjunctive normal forms. N 0R MA L F0 RMS AN D C0M PL ETE SE TS 0F C 0NNE CTIV ES 39 These remarks lead us to the following normal form theorem: Every formula is logically equivalent to at least one formula in disjunctive normalform and to at least one formula in conjunctive normalform. Anyformula that does not belong to the class is logically equivalent to a unique formula in every formula that does not belong to the class is logically equivalent to a unique formula in where uniqueness is understood to be 'up to the order ofthefactors'. Tht:�orem 1.29 0 CDNF; 1 CCNF, Proof Let F be a formula. • • • A v -,A which is both a DNF is logically equivalent to A ....,A which is DNF and If F is a tautology, it is logically equivalent to 1 1, and a CNF. If ....., p is a tautology, F 1, 1 1\ CNF. In the other cases, we have just observed that F is logically equivalent to a formula in CDNF. But this is also true for ....., p , which means that there is a non-empty subset X of {0, 1 }n such that v (E t ,£2, ... ,£n) E X Therefore we have (by de Morgan's laws). This last formula, once we delete any double negations, is in CCNF. The second part ofthe theorem clearly follows from the first and from the remarks • that preceded it. We can therefore speak of CDNF' of a formula (provided it is not an antilogy) and of CCNF' of a formula (provided it is not a tautology). The normal form theorem also furnishes us with a practical method for obtaining the CDNF and the CCNF of a formula (when they exist) once we know its truth table. Thus, for example, the formula 'the 'the G = (A � ( ( (B 1\ ....,A ) v (--, C 1\ A)) ¢> (A v (A � ...., B )))), whose truth table was given in Section 1 .2. 1 , is satisfied by the distributions (0,0,0)� (0,0,1), (0,1,0), (0,1,1), (1,0,0), ( 1,0,0) and (1,1,0), while -.G is satisfied by (1,0,1) 40 PROPO S I T I O N A L CALCULUS and (1,1,1 From this we conclude that the CDNF of G is ). C) v -,C) v -.C)v -,C), (-,A 1\ B 1\ (-, A 1\ -,B 1\ (-, A 1\ -, B 1\ (-.A 1\ B 1\ C) v (A 1\ -.8 1\ -.C ) v (A 1\ B 1\ and the CDNF of _,G is (A 1\ -, B 1\ C ) v (A 1\ B 1\ C), and finally the CCNF of G is We should mention thatformulas of the type A; are sometimes called (mostly by computer scientists), thatformulas ofthe type VkEJ '1k Bk (i.e. a disjunction of literals) are often called and that conjunctive nor­ mal forms are then called We will encounter this terminology in Chapter4. Remark 1.30 Bi literals clauses clausal forms. 1 .3.3 Complete sets of connectives In a formula that is in disjunctive normal form, the only symbols for connectives that can occur are -,, A and So we may conclude from Theorem 1 .29 that every formula is equivalent to at least one formula in which these are the only connectives that may appear. This property can be restated in terms of propositional connectives, that is, in terms of operations on {0, 1}: v. For every integerm every mappingfrom { 0, 1 } m into { 0, 1} can be obtained by composition2 of the mappings -, (from {0, 1} into {0, 1 } ) together with 1\ and v (ji--om (0, } into {0, 1}) Let m be a non-zero natural number and a mapping from {0, 1 }m Lemma 1.31 > 1, , l . cp be Proof into { 0, 1}. Choose a formula F which has cp as its truth table and which is written with no symbols for connectives other than -. 1\ and v (for example, a formula in DNF). The decomposition tree of F then gives us a composition of mappings taken from among the mappings -., 1\ and v which coincides with the function cp. Without going into uselessly heavy detail, let us be satisfied with an example. The mapping cp from {0, 1} 3 into {0, 1} which assumes the value 0 for (1,0,1) and (1,1,1) and the value 1 for the six other triples in {0, 1} 3 is, as we have already shown above, the truth table of the formula , (Here we chose the CCNF, which is much shorter than the CDNF and is also written using only -,, 1\ and v). 41 N O R M A L FORMS A N D COMPLETE S ETS OF C O N N E C T I V E S The truly correct way to write this formula is (((�A v B ) v �C) 1\ ( (-,A v �B) v C)) � We conclude that for any elements x, cp (x, y, z) = y and z from . {0, 1 } , we have y A ( v ( v (�x, y) , �z), v ( v (�x, � ) , z ) ) � . (In this expression, �, 1\ and v are on this occasion denoting operations on {0, 1 } ) . We see that the operations �, 1\ and v generate all possible operations (with any • number of places) on {0, 1 } . We express the property that has just been exhibited by saying that { �, 1\, v } is a complete set of connectives. set of connectives is called if it generates, under composition, the set ofallpropositional connectives. complete set ofconnectives is called when no proper subset is a complete set of connectives. Definition 1.32 A complete A minimal The set { �, 1\, v } is not a minimal complete set. Actually, with every formula F which involves no connectives other than 1\ and v we can associate a log­ ically equivalent formula that involves only the symbols for connectives and v: it suffices to substitute, for each sub-formula of F of the form (H 1\ K), the logically equivalent formula �( �Hv � K ), repeating the operation as many times as necessary to eliminate all the /\. This shows that { v} is a complete set of connectives that is a proper subset of { --,, 1\, v } The set { v } i s a minimal complete set. To be sure, i t i s sufficient to show that {-,} and { v } are not complete sets. Formulas in which no symbol for a connective other than � occur are the formu­ las of the type � . . � A (a propositional variable preceded by a finite number, possibly zero, of occurrences of the symbol ) A formula of this type is logically equivalent either to A or to �A, and it is clear that there are formulas (for example, (A v B) ) that are not logically equivalent to any formula of this type. Thus., { } i s not complete. As for { v}, note that a formula i n which the only symbol for a connective that occurs is v will be satisfied by the distribution of truth values 81 defined by 81 (X) = 1 for every propositional variable X . This can be proved with­ out difficulty by induction (Exercise 20). From this we conclude that the formula � A 1 , which takes the value 0 for 8 1 ., cannot be logically equivalent to any formula which uses only v as a symbol for a connective. Thus { v } is not complete. ln Exercise 15, we will see that each of the connectives known as Sheffer strokes (tand �) has the property of being, by itself alone, a complete set of connectives. We will also show that, among the one- or two-place connectives. these are the only ones with this property. � , � � , . � , . � . � Suppose we wish to show, by induction, that a certain p1vperty X(F) trueforeveryformula F andsuppose that thisproperty is compatible with the relation (which is to say that anyformula that is logically equivalent to Remark 1.33 is rv E :F, 42 PROPOSITIONAL CALCULUS a formula having property X also has the property). We can then exploit thefact that { -., v} is a complete set by limiting ourselves, in the proofby induction, to the induction steps relating to ...., and to v. If we prove that X(F) is true when F is an element of and that, whenever X(F) and X(G) are true, then X(-.F) and X((F v G)) are also true, this will guarantee that the p1vperty X is true for all formulas in which no symbolsfor connectives other than -·and v occur. Now let H beanarbitraryformulafromF. Since{-., v} is complete, H is logically equivalent to at least one formula K which can be written using only these connectives. So X(K) is true, and since X is compatible with ""', X(H) is also true. Of course, this remark applies just as well to any other complete set of connectives. To give an example, note that in the proof of Theorem 1 .22 we could have legitimately dispensed with the steps relating to v, and {:? thanks to the remark P, ::::} that was just made (for { -., 1\ } is a complete set), to the compatibility of the property in question with ""' (which is obvious)� and subject to verifying that the completeness of the set { can be proved without recourse to Theorem 1 .22 (otherwise we would be running in circles!). -. , v} 1.4 The interpolation lemma 1.4.1 Interpolation lemma Let F and G be twoformulas having no propositional variable in common. Thefollowing two p1vperties are equivalent: ( The formula ( F G) is a tautology. (2) At least one of the formulas -,F or G is a tautology. It is clear first of all that the second property implies the first: for any distribution of truth values 8, we have 8 (G) 1 if G is a tautology and 8 (F) if .., F is one. In both cases, 8 (( F G)) 1 . Lemma 1.34 1) => Proof = ::::} = 0 = Now suppose that property (2) i s false. Then w e can choose a distribution of truth values A. such that A.( -.F) = 0, which is to say A.(F) = 1, and a distribution of truth values tt such that tL(G ) = 0. Now define a distribution of truth values 8 by setting, for each propositional variable X, 8 (X ) = { �-tA.((X)X ) i f X occurs at least once in F; if X does not occur in F. Since, by hypothesis, any variable that occurs in G cannot occur in F, we see that 8 coincides with A. on the set of variables of F and with 11- on the set of variables of G. We conclude (Lemma 1 . 1 9) that 8 (F) = A. (f,) = 1 and that 8(G) = t-t(G) = 0, • and, consequently, that 8 ( (f, :::::::> G)) = 0. So property ( 1 ) fails. The following result is known as the interpolation lemma: Let n be a non-ze1v intege1; A A2, . . . , An pairwise distinct propositional variables, and F and G two formulas that have (at most) the Theorem 1.35 1, THE INTERPOLATION LEMMA 43 propositional variables A 1 , A2, . . . , An in common. The following two proper­ ties are equivalent: Theformula is a tautology. There is at least one formula containing no propositional variables other than A A2, . . . , An, such that the formulas and are tautologies. (Such aformula is called an (F => G) (1) H, (2) 1, ( F => H) H (H => G) interpolant between F and G). Proof Suppose �* (F � H) and �* (H � G) and consider an arbitrary distri­ bution of truth values 8. If 8 ( H ) = 0, then 8 (F ) = 0 (because 8 ( ( F => H)) = l ) ; if 8 (H ) = l , then 8 (G) = 1 (because 8((H => G ) ) = 1). In both cases, 8 ((F=> G)) = 1, which proves property ( 1 ). To show the converse, we will assume �* (F => G) and argue by induction on the number of propositional variables which have at least one occurrence in F but have none in G . • • If this number i s zero, then b y setting H = F w e clearly obtain a formula which contains no propositional variables other than A t , A2, . . . , An and is such that 1-* (F => H) and �* (H => G ) . Suppose (the induction hypothesis) that property (2) i s true for formulas F that contain at most variables that do not occur in G and let us examine the case in which there are + 1 . Let 8 1 , B2 , . . . , Bm , Bm+I denote the variables of F that do not occur in G . According to our conventions, we thus have F = F [A 1 , A2, . . . , A n , B 1 , 82, . . . , Bm , Bm+ I l- Set m A 2, . . . , An , B I , B2, · · · , Bm A 1 ] = FA ] /Bm+ 1 F [ A I , A 2, . . . , A n , B1 , B2, . . . , Bm , A I ] = F_, A 1 / Bm+l " F1 = F [A 1 Fo = m , ' -. Notice that because Bm+I does not occur in G, the result of substituting the formula A 1 for the variable Bm+l in the formula ( F => G) is the formula ( F1 => G), and the result of substituting the formula -.A I for the variable Bm+l i n the formula ( F => G) i s the formula ( Fo => G ) . Invoking Corollary 1 .23 and our hypothesis, we conclude that ( Ft => G) and ( Fo => G) are tautologies, and hence so are the formulas ( ( Ft => G) 1\ ( Fo => G)) and ( ( FI v Fo) => G ) (see number (57) i n our list in Section 1 .2.3). The variables in the formula ( FI v Fo) are among A 1 , A2, . . . , An , Bt , B2, . . . , Bm . So we can apply our induction hypothesis and find a formula H that is an interpolant 44 PROPOSITIONAL CALCULUS between ( F1 v Fo) and G, which is to say that its variables are among A 1 , A 2 , . . . , An and it is such that f- * ( (Ft v Fo) ==> H) and f-* (H ==> G). We will now show that ( F ==> ( Ft v Fo)) is also a tautology. This will conclude the proof since we can then conclude (invoking tautology number (3 1 )) f-* ( F==>H), which will make H an interpolant between F and G. So let o be an assignment o f truth values which satisfies F. We have (by Theorem 1 .22): either o (A J ) == o(Bm+t )� and in this case o(Ft ) o(F) l, or else o(A t ) # o(Bm+l ) , and so o (Fo) o (F) 1 . I n all cases, o (( Ft v Fo)) 1 . And s o t-* ( F ==> ( Ft v Fo)). • == == == == == 1 .4.2 The definability theorem Here is a corollary of the interpolation lemma, the definability theorem: Let A , B, A be pairwise distinctpropositional vari­ be aformula (whose variables are therefore We assume that theformula 1 A 2, . . . , Ak F F[ A , A 1 , A2, . . . , Ak] A , A t , A2, . . . , Ak). Theorem 1.36 ables and among == , is a taurology. Then there exists a formula G G[A A2, . . . , Ak], whose only variables are among A A2, . . . , Ak and is such that the formula == 1, 1, is a tautology. Intuitively, the hypothesis is saying that the formula F[A , A 1 , A2, . . . , AkJ determines the value of A as a function of the values of A I , A2, . . . , Ab in the sense that distributions of truth values that satisfy F and that assign the same value to A 1 , A 2, . . . , Ak must also assign the same value to A; the conclusion is that the value thereby assigned to A is the value taken by a certain formula G [A 1 , A2, . . . , Ak ] which does not depend on A and which could be called a 'definition of A modulo F'. Exercise 1 8 suggests a proof of the theorem directly inspired by this intuition. Here, we are content to apply the preceding lemma. Proof Taking into consideration numbers (4 1 ), (53), and (54) from our list in Section 1 .2.3, the hypothesis leads successively to the following tautologies: F I B , A t , A2, . . . , Ak]) ==> (A ==> B)), (((F[A, A 1 , A2, . . . , Ak] 1\ Ff B, A 1 , A2, . . . , Ak] ) 1\ A) ==> B), ( ((F[A , A t , A2 , . . . , Ak] A A) A F[B, A 1 , A2, . . . , Akl ) � B), ((F[A, A I , A2, . . . , Ak] 1\ A) => (F[B, A I , A2, . . . , Ak] :=> B)). f-* ((F[A, A t , A2, . . . , Ak] f-* f-* f- * 1\ 45 THE COMPACTNESS THEOREM The interpolation lemma then guarantees the existence of an interpolant G [A I , A 2 , . . . , Ak] between ( F [ A , A I , A 2 , . . . , Ak] and ( F [ B , A t , A 2 , . . . , A k ] ) ==> 1\ A) B ). So, in particular, I-* ( ( F l A , A t , A2 , . . . , Ak] 1\ A) ==> G ) and hence I-* (F[A , A t , A 2 , . . . , A k ] ==? (A => G)). On the other hand, and so f-* ((G 1\ FlB, A t , A 2 , . . . , A k]) => B) I-* ((F[B, A t , A2, . . . , A k ] 1\ G ) => B), I-* (F[B, A t , A 2 , . . . , A k ] ==> (G ==> B ) ) . The result of substituting A for B in this latter formula is again a tautology (Corollary 1 .23 ): 1-* ( F [ A , A 1 , A2, . . . , A k ] => (G => A ) ) . Properties (*) and (**) together with tautologies (41 ) and (54) from Section 1 .2.3 fi nally give us • 1.5 The compactness theorem 1.5.1 Satisfaction of a set of formulas Let A and B be two sets offormulas ofthepropositional calculus on the set ofpropositional variables let be aformula and let 8 be a distribution (�f truth values on A) if and only if 8 satisfies all the formulas A is by 8 (or 8 belonging to A. A is (or or ifand only ifthere exists at least one distribution of truth values that satisfies A. A is ifand only if every finite subset of A is satisfiable. A is and only ifit is not satisfiable. Definition 1.37 P, G P. • satisfied • satisfiable • • satisfies consistent, finitely satisfiable contradictory if non-contradictory) 46 • PROPOSITIONAL CALCULUS and only every is a (which we denote by: distribution oftruth values that satisfies satisfies (The notationfor is not a consequence of is: and B are {fand only if every formula of is a consequence of B and everyformula of B is a consequence of G consequence of A A 'G • A t-* G) if G. A J.L* G). A' equivalent A if A A. For example, consider pairwise distinct propositional variables A , B , A 1 , A2, . . . , A m , . . . : the set { A , B , (_,A v B ) } is satisfiable; { A , _,B, (A ::::} B)} i s contradictory; the empty set is satisfied by any distribution of truth values what­ ever (if this were not true, we could find a distribution of truth values 8 and a formula F E 0 such that 8 ( F) == 0; but such a feat is clearly impossible . . . ). We have { A , B } I- * (A 1\ B) and { A , (A � B ) } I-* B . The sets { A , B } and { ( A 1\ B ) } are equivalent, as are the sets The following lemma lists a certain number of properties that follow from these defi.nitions. Nearly all of them are immediate consequences. It will profit the begin­ ning reader to carefully prove all of these. We will content ourselves with proving the three properties marked by two bullets ( •• ) rather than one. For all sets offormulas and B, integers m and p and formulas the following properties and are ver{fied: �f'and only is contradictory. If is satisfiable and B then B is satisfiable. If is satisfiable, then isfinitely satisfiable. is contradictory and C B, then B is contradictory. and B, then B H and only ::::} H). H ) and only and H. ifand only A is a tautology {{and only is a consequence ofthe empty set. isatautologyifandonly {f is a consequence ofany setofformulaswhateveJ: A is contradicto1y {fand only {f is contradictory and only everyformula is a consequence of is contradicto1y ifand only every antilogy is a consequence of is contradictory and only there exists at least one antilogy that is a consequence of A. Lemma 1.38 G, H, F1 , F2, . . . , Fm • A I-* G A G 1 , G2, . . . , G P ' > 1, if A U { _,G} • A if • A • {fA • If A �* G if A • A u {G} I-* if • A I-* ( G if • { FI , F2, . . . , Fm } I-* G • • • G • A • A • A • A c A, A if A 1\ c I-* G. if A I-* (G if A I-* G G A I-* ifl-* ((FI F2 1\ . . . 1\ Fm ) ::::} G). if G G A I-* (G if if -,G). if A. if A. if THE COMPACTNESS THEOREM • • • • • • • • • • • • { FJ , Fz, . . . , Fm } 47 is contradictory {{and only if(-,FJ v -, pz v . . . v _, Fm ) is a tautology. A and B are equivalent ifand only if they are satisfied by the same assignments oftruth values. When we replace eachformula in Abya Logically equivalentformula, we obtain a set that is equivalent to A. IfA is contradictory, then B is equivalent to A ifand only if B is contradictory. A is equivalent to the empty set if and only {f every formula belonging to A is a tautology. The empty set is satisfiable. The set :F of allformulas is contradictory. The sets { G } and { H } are equivalent if and only if the formulas G and H are Logically equivalent. The sets { F1 , Fz, . . . , Fm } and { G 1 , Gz, . . . , G p } are equivalent {fand only if the formula ( ( F1 1\ Fz 1\ · · · 1\ Fm) <=> ( G 1 A Gz 1\ . . . 1\ G p)) is a tautology. Everyfinite set offormulas is equivalent to a set consisting ofa singleformula. When the set P is infinite, and only in this case, there exist sets offormulas that are not equivalent to any finite set offormulas. The binary relation 'is equivalent to ' is an equivalence relation on the set of subsets of F. • • Proof •• I- * G if and only if 0 I- * G: because the empty set is satisfied by every distribution of truth values, G is a consequence of the empty set if and only if every distribution of truth values satisfies G , in other words: if and only if G is a tautology. Observe, as a result, that the notation �* G for ' G is a tautology' seems natural. •• A is equivalent to 0 if and only i f every element of A is a tautology: it is clear, first of all, that every formula belonging to 0 is a consequence of A, and this holds for any set A whatever (otherwise, there would be a formula belonging to 0 which would not be a consequence of A, and this is clearly impossible); so what we have to prove is that every formula in A is a consequence of 0 if and only if every formula in A is a tautology; but this is precisely the preceding property. •• P is infinite if and only if there exists a set of formulas that is not equivalent to any finite set: if P is fi.nite and has n elements, there are 22n classes of logically equivalent formulas; choose a representative from each class. We can then, given an arbitrary set of formulas X, replace each formula of X by the representative chosen from its equivalence class; the resulting set is equivalent to X and is finite since it can contain at most 22n elements. If P is infi.nite, consider the infinite set of formulas Y = {A 1 , A z , . . . , A m , . . . } (where the A; are pairwise distinct propositional variables); if Y were equivalent to a finite set of formulas Z, then Z 48 PROPOS[TIONAL CALCULUS would be satisfied, as is Y, by the constant distribution 81 equal to l, and we could choose at least one integer k such that the variable Ak does not occur in any of the formulas of Z (which are finite in number); so the distribution A which takes the value 1 everywhere except at Ak, where its value is 0, would still satisfy Z (Lemma 1 . 1 9) but would obviously not satisfy Y, thereby yielding a contradiction: thus we have a set Y which is not equivalent to any finite set. • 1.5.2 The compactness theorem for propositional calculus We have arrived at what is incontestably the major theorem of this chapter. We will see several applications of it in the exercises. It can be stated in several equivalent forms: The compactness theorem, version 1 : Theorem 1.39 For any set A offormulas of the propositional calculus, A is satisfiable if and only if A is finitely sati,�fiable. The compactness theorem, version 2: Theorem 1.40 For any set A offormulas of the propositional calculus, A is contradictory if and only �fat least one finite subset of A is contradictory. The compactness theorem, version 3: Theorem 1.41 For any set A offormulas (�{the propositional calculus and for any formula F, F is a consequence of A if and only if F is a consequence of at least onefinite subset �fA. ( Proof The proof that the three versions are equivalent is a simple exercise that uses the elementary properties stated in Lemma 1 .38. We also observe that the 'only if' direction of version I and the 'if' direction of versions 2 and 3 are obvious. We will now prove the 'if' direction of version l . Here is a first proof that is valid for the case in which the set of propositional variables, P , is countably infi nite: (For the case when P i s finite, the theorem is more o r less obvious (there i s only a finite number of equivalence classes of formulas), but we can always invoke the situation of the present proof by extending P to a countable set.) So consider a set A of formulas that is finitely satisfiable. We must prove the existence of a distribution of truth values that satisfies all of the formulas in A. To do this, we will define, by induction, a sequence (cn)1 1EN of elements of {0, 1 } such that the distribution o f truth values 8 o defined by: for every n satisfies A. E N, 8o(An) == en , 49 THE COMPACTNESS THEOREM To define so, we distinguish two cases: Case Oo: for every finite subset B C A, there exists at least one distribution of truth values 8 E {0, 1}P which satisfies B and is such that 8 (Ao) == 0. • In this case, we set so • == 0. Case l o : this is the contrary case: we can choose a finite subset Bo c A such that, for every distribution of truth values 8 E {0, 1 } P which satisfies Bo, we have 8 (Ao) == 1. I n this case, we set so == 1 . I n case 1 o, the following claim i s verified: For every finitesubsetB c A, there exists at least one distribution of truth values 8 E {0, 1}P which satisfies B and is such that 8 (Ao) == 1. To see this, given a finite subset B c A, note that B U Bo is a finite subset of A that is satisfiable according to the initial hypothesis. Choose a distribution of truth values 8 that satisfies it. Then 8 satisfies Bo (which is a subset of B U Bo!), and, by the choice of Bo, we have 8 (Ao) == 1 . But since 8 also satisfies B, the claim is established. Thus, from our definition of so, we may conclude the following property (Ro): (Ro) For every finite subset B c A, there exists at least one assignment of truth values 8 which satisfies B and is such that 8 (Ao) == so . E {0, 1}P Suppose (the induction hypothesis) that so, s1 , . . . , s11 (elements of {0, been defined in such a way that the following property (Rn) is satisfied: (An ) 1}) have For every finite subset B c A, there exists at least one assignment of truth values 8 E {0, 1 } P which satisfi.es B and is such that 8 (Ao) == so, 8(A l ) == St , . . . , 8 (An - J ) == Sn- l , and 8(An) == £11 • We then define sn+ l by distinguishing two cases: • Case On+ I : For every finitesubsetB c A, there existsat leastone distribution of truth values 8 E {0, 1 } P which satisfies B and is such that 8(Ao) == so, 8(A 1 ) == E l , . . . , 8 (An ) == Sn and 8 (An +l ) == 0. ][n this case we set Sn+ l • == 0. Case ln+ 1 : this is the contrary case : we can choose a finite subset Bn+ l c A such that, for every distribution of truth values 8 E {0, 1 } P which satisfies Bn +l and which is such that 8 (Ao) == so, 8 (A t ) == s 1 , . . . , 8 (An) == Sn , we have 8 (An+t) == 1 . In this case, w e set sn+l == I. Let us show that property (An+ 1 ) is then satisfied. This amounts to proving, for case 1 n+ 1 , that for every finite subset B c A, there exists at least one distribution 50 PROPOSITIONAL CALCULUS of truth values 8 E { 0, 1 } P which satisfies B and is such that 8 ( Ao) = so, 8 (A 1 ) = c ) , . . . , 8 (An) = En and 8 (An+ l ) = 1 . So consider a finite subset B c A . Then B U Bn+ l i s a finite subset o f A; and, according to property (An ) , we can choose a distribution of truth values 8 which satisfies it and is such that 8 (Ao) = so, 8 (A I ) = £ ] , . . . , 8(An) = En . So 8 satisfies Bn+ 1 and, because of the way this set was chosen, we may conclude that 8 (An+ I ) = 1. Since 8 satisfies B, our objective is achieved. The sequence (sn )n E N is thus defined; and, for every integer n, property (An) is satisfied. As anticipated, set 8o( An) = En for every n . Let F be formula belonging to A, and let k be a natural number such that all the propositional variables that occur in F are among {A 1 , A 2 , . . . , Ak } (F being a finite string of symbols, such an integer necessarily exists). Property (Rk) and the fact that { F } is a finite subset of A show that we can find a distribution of truth values 8 E {0, l } P which satisfies F and is such that 8 (Ao) = so, 8 ( A t ) = £ 1 , . . . , 8 (Ak) = Ek. We see that 8 and 8o agree on the set { A 1 , Az, . . . , A k } , which allows us to conclude (Lemma 1 . 1 9) that 8o(F) = 8 (F) = 1 . • The conclusion is that 8 o satisfies all the formulas i n A. Let us get to the proof of the theorem in the general case: we no longer make any particular assumptions about the set P . We have to invoke Zorn's lemma (see Part 2, Chapter 7). Proof Once more, we are given a finitely satisfiable set of formulas, A. Let £ denote the set of mappings whose domain is a subset of P, which take values in {0, 1 } and which, for every finite subset B c A, have an extension to the whole of P which is a distribution of truth values that satisfies B. Formally: £ = {qJ E U {0, l } x : XCP (VB E gJF(A)) (3 8 E {0, 1 } p ) (8 r x = (/) and (V F E B) (8(F) = 1))}. Note that this set is not empty, for it contains the empty mapping (those who find this object perplexing can find additional comments concerning it in Part 2, Chapter 7). To see this, note that by our hypothesis, there exists a distribution of truth values 8 on P that satisfies B. As 8 is obviously an extension of the empty mapping, the latter satisfies the condition for membership in £. It is interesting to observe that this is the only point in the proof where we use the hypothesis that A is finitely satisfiable. Define the binary relation < on £ by qJ < 1/1 if and only if ljr is an extension of qJ (in otherwords, dom(qJ) c dom(1/r) and forevery A E dom(qJ), qJ(A) It is very easy to verify that < is an order relation on £ . = '¢' (A)). THE COMPACTNESS THEOREM 51 We will prove that the ordered set ( [, < ) i s inductive, which i s to say that every subset of [ that is totally ordered by < has an upper bound in [. This is the same (see Part 2, Chapter 7) as showing that [ is non-empty and that every non-empty subset of [ that is totally ordered by < has an upper bound in £. This will permit us (by Zorn's lemma) to assert the existence of a maximal element in [ for the order <. We have already observed that [ is non-empty. Consider a non-empty subset C c: [ that is totally ordered by <. We define a mapping A as follows: • The domain of A is the union of the domains of the elements of C. • For every A E dom("A) and for every cp E C, if A E dom(cp), then 'A(A) cp(A). == This definition makes sense because, if cp and 1/1 are elements of [ such that A E dom( cp) and A E dom( 1/1 ), then we have either cp < 1/J or 1/1 < cp, and in both cases cp(A) == 1/f(A); so the value of the mapping A at the point A can be legitimately defined as the value at A taken by an arbitrary mapping that belongs to the subset C and is defined at A ; thus A is the natural common extension of all the elements of C. Let us show that A is an element of [. For this, given a finite subset B c A, we must find a distribution of truth values Jvt E {0, l} P which extends A and which satisfies B. Since B is finite, there are at most a finite number of propositional variables appearing in the formulas of B. Let A 1 , A z, . . , An be the propositional variables that occur in at least one formula from B and which belong to the domain of A, in other words, to the union of the domains of the elements of C. Then there exist in C elements f.fJ L , f.fJ2, , f.fJn: such that A 1 E dom( f.fJl ) , A2 E dom( f.fJ2 ) , , An E dom(cpn ) Because C is totally ordered by <� one of the cp; is an extension of all the others: call it f.fJO· Thus we have f.fJo E C and { A t , A2, , An } c dom(cpo). Being an element of £, f.fJo has an extension 1/Jo to P that satisfies B. Let us define the mapping Jvt from P into {0, 1} as follows: . . • • Jvt (A) 'A: == • • . • . . • {'A( A) 1/lo(A) if A E dom('A); if A ¢ dom('A). • Jvt is an extension of it agrees with A on dom('A). • Jvt satisfies B: to see this, we have on the one hand that for every variable A E dom(cpo ), Jvt(A) == 'A(A) == cpo(A) == 1/lo(A); we conclude from this that Jvt agrees with 1/Jo on { A t , A2, , A11 } ; on the other hand, if A is a variable that occurs in some formula of B without belonging to the set { A 1 , A2, . . . , An } , we have A ¢. dam(A.), so Jvt (A ) == 1/lo(A); thus . . • 52 P R O P O S I T I O N A l. C A L C U L U S we see that JL takes the same value as 1/Jo on all propositional variables that are involved in the set B; and since 1/Jo satisfies B, so does JL (Lemma 1 . I 9). So we have found a distribution of truth values that extends A and that satisfies B; thus A E £ and £ is seen to be an inductive ordered set. Zorn's lemma then allows us to choose an element y from £ that is maximal for the order <. Suppose that the domain o f y i s not the whole of P and consider a propositional variable A that does not belong to the domain of y . We will define an extension y' of y to the set dom( y) U { A } in the following way: • • y' rdom(y) == y ; y'(A) 0 if for every finite subset B of A there exists a distribution of truth values 8 on P that satisfies B, that extends y, and is such that 8(A) 0; y' (A) 1 otherwise. == == • == We then make the following claim: if y' (A) == 1 , then for every finite subset B c A, there is a distribution of truth values 8 on P that satisfies B, that extends y, and is such that 8(A) == 1. To see this, note that if y' (A) # 0, w e can find a finite subset Bo c A such that for every distribution of truth values 8 that satisfies Bo and extends y , we have 8(A) == 1. Now let B be an arbitrary finite subset of A. The set B U Bo is a finite subset of A so there is (by definition of the set £ to which y belongs) a distribution of truth values 8 that extends y and satisfies B U Bo; 8 satisfies Bo and extends y: so 8 (A) == 1 . So we have truly found an extension of y to P that satisfies B (since B c B U Bo) and takes the value 1 at the point A . S o we see that whatever the value of y' (A), there exists, for every finite subset B of A, an extension 8 of y to P that satisfies B and is such that 8(A) == y'(A). But this simply amounts to saying that 8 is in fact an extension of y'. Consequently, for every finite subset B c A, y' can be extended to a distribution of truth values that satisfies B. This means that y' belongs to £; and so y' is in £ and is strictly greater than y for the order < (dom(y) � dom(y')), which contradicts the fact that y is a maximal element of £. So the assumption we made about the domain of y was absurd. It follows that dom(y) == P. Thus we see that y is a distribution of truth values on P and that any extension of y to P is equal to y. So by definition of £, every finite subset B of A is satisfied by y. In particular, this is true for every singleton subset, which means that every formula F E A is satisfied by y. So A is satisfiable . • In Chapter 2, we will give two other proofs of this theorem. E X E R C I S ES FOR C H A PTER 53 I EXERCISES FOR CHAPTER 1 1. Given two natural numbers and n, what is the length of a formula of the propositional calculus that has n occurrences of symbols for binary connectives and m occurrences of the symbol for negation? 2. Consider formulas of the propositional calculus on a set of propositional vari­ ables P. Given a natural number n, determine the possible different lengths of a formula whose height is n . 3. The seto fpseudoformulas constructed from a set ofpropositional variables P is defined to be the smallest set of words on the alphabet P U { --,, A , v , =}, {:}, ( } that satisfies the following conditions: • • • m every element of P is a pseudoformula; if F is a pseudoformula, then so is ..., F ; i f F and G are pseudoformulas, then so are the words: (F A G, (F v G, ( F =} G, ( F {:} G. Thus the pseudoformulas are the words obtained from the usual formulas by suppressing all closing parentheses. (a) Show that there is a unique readability theorem for pseudoformulas analo­ gous to the one for the usual formulas. (b) Would the analogous result be true if we suppressed of all the opening parentheses rather than the closing parentheses? 4. Let F denote the set of all formulas constructed from a given set of propositional variables P . Let F* denote the subset ofF consisting of those formulas in which the symbois A, v, and <==} do not occur. (a) Give an inductive definition of the set F*. (b) Let Jl be a map from P into F*. Show that there exists a unique extension 11 of Jl to F* such that for all formulas F and G belonging to F* : /1( ..., p ) /i(F =} G) = = ...,fi (F), and ..., ( /i(G) =} /i(F) ) . (c) Show that for all formulas F and G belonging to :F* , if F is a sub-formula of G, then /i(F) is a sub-formula of /i(G). (d) Define Jto : P � F* as follows: for all A belonging to P, Jt o (A) = ..., A. Write down the formulas i7Q((A =} B)) and i7Q((-,A =} B)). Show that for every formula F in F*, /i6(F) is logically equivalent to F. 54 PROPOSITIONAL CALCULUS 5. (a) Show that the following two formulas are tautologies. (They use the propo­ sitional variables A t , A2, A 3 , B1 , B2 , and B3 and their written form involves some abuses of language.) F2 = (((A t =} B t ) 1\ (A2 =} B2) 1\ -,(Bt =} ((Bt =} A t ) 1\ ( B2 =} A2))); F3 = (((A 1 82) 1\ =} B t ) 1\ (A2 =} B2 ) 1\ (A3 =} 1\ -.(Bt 1\ B2 ) 1\ --.(Bt 1\ B3) 1\ ··(B2 =} ( B2 =} A 2 ) 1\ ( B 3 =} A 3))). 1\ (At v A2)) B3) 1\ B3) 1\ (At v A2 v A3)) (b) Write a tautology Fn that generalizes F2 and F3 using the 2n variables A 1 , Bt A2, B2 , . . . , An , Bn 6. E is the formula ((B 1\ C) =} (A <? (-·B v C))) in which A, B, and C are propositional variables. - (a) Find a formula that is logically equivalent to E and that is written using only the connectives => and {}. (b) Find a disjunctive normal form for E that is as reduced as possible. (c) How many terms (elementary conjunctions) are there in the canonical dis­ junctive normal form of E? (d) Show that the formulas (C =} (B =} (A {:} (B =} C)))) and (C => (B => A ) ) are logically equivalent. 7. What are the assignments of truth values on P { A J , A2, . . . , A n } that satisfy: = (a) the formula F = ( (A t =} A 2) 1\ (A 2 => A 3) (b) the formula G = (F 1\ ( A n =} A 1 )) ? (c) the formula H = A (A; =} -,A ; ) ? 1\ · · · 1\ (An - t =} l <i<n l <j<n i j.j Write down disjunctive normal forms for F, G, and H. 8. Consider the set of propositional variables P = { A 1 , A 2 , . . . , An } . (a) Show that the following formula is a tautology: ( V l <i < j <n (A ; 1\ A i)) {:} (\ l <i <n (v ) j=f=i A .i · An)) ? 55 EXERCISES FOR CHAPTER l (b) Which assignments of truth values on P make the following formula false: (c) Show that the preceding formula is logically equivalent to 9. A safe has locks and can be opened only when all n of the locks are open. Five people, a, b, c, d, and e are to receive keys to some of the locks. Each key can be duplicated any number of times. Find the smallest value of n, and a corresponding distribution of keys to the five people, so that the safe can be opened if and only if at least one of the following situations applies: • a n and b are present together; • a, • c, and d are present together; b, d, and e are present together. 10. Consider a set of 15 propositional variables: P = { Ao, A 1 , . . . , A 14}. The subscripts are viewed as elements of the additive group ('!l/ I 57l, + ) and the operations ( + and -) on the subscripts are those of this group. Find all assignments of truth values to P that satisfy the following set of formulas U {( A ; =* A _;) : 0 < i < 14} U { ((A ; A A j ) => Ai+j) 0 < i < 14, 0 < j < 14}. {Ao} : 1 1 . Consider distinct propositional variables A and B and a symbol a for a binary connective. A formula that is neither a tautology nor an antilogy will be called neutral. For each of the formulas Fa Ga = = (A a ((B a (B a A) A )), and a -.(A a B)), determine whether i t i s a tautology, a n antilogy or neutral when (a) (d) a = 1\ a = <=? (b) (e) a = v a = -1? (c) (f) a = =} a = t Of course, in cases (e) and (f), a is not a symbol for a connective, but it is used with the obvious conventions; for example, (B � A) is the formula --,(B 1\ A ) . 56 PROPOSITIONAL CALCULUS 12. (a) Show that there exists a unique 3-place connective qJ such that for all t belonging to {0, 1}, we have ({J(t, -.t, t) ({J(t, t, -.f) = ({J(t, 0, 0) = 1 and = ({J(l , 1, 1) = 0. (b) Find a disjunctive normal form for the connective defined in (a) that is as reduced as possible. (c) In each of the following cases, give an example of a formula F of the propositional calculus on { A , B , C} which, for all assignments of truth values 8 E {0, 1 } { A ,B .CJ , satisfies the condition indicated: ( 1 ) 8(F) = qJ(8( A), 8 (A ) , 8 ( A ) ) ( 2 ) 8 ( F ) = qJ(8 ( A ) , 8(B), 8(B)) (3) 8 (F ) = qJ(8 ( A ) , 8 (A ) , 8 (B)) (4) 8(F) = qJ(8 ( A ) , 8 ( B), 8(A)) ( 5 ) 8(F) == qJ(8 ( A), qJ (8(B), 8(B), 8 ( B)), 8 ( A)) (6) 8(F) = qJ(8( A ), 8 (B), 8(B)) :=} qJ (8 (A), 8(B)� 8(A)). [Notice that in (6), :=} is not a symbol for a binary connective (since this is not a formula in the formal language) but rather denotes the corresponding binary operation on {0, 1 } . An analogous remark applies to the use of ._, in the conditions imposed on qJ in part (a).] (d) Can the connective v be obtained by composition from the connective qJ? (e) Is { ({J} a complete set of connectives? 13. When we add two numbers that when written in the binary number system (numbers in base 2) use at most two digits, say ab and cd, we obtain a number withat most three digits, pqr. For example, 1 1 + 0 1 = 100. Using the standard connectives, write formulas that express p, q , and r as functions of a, b, c, and d. 14. Consider a set of propositional variables P. We identify the set {0, l} with the field ('ll/2'/L, +, x, 0, 1 } . (a) Express the usual connectives using the operations + and x. (b) Express the operations + and x using the usual connectives. (c) Show that with each propositional formula F [ A 1 , A2, . . . , An] we can as­ sociate a polynomial in n unknowns PF E 'll / 27l[X I , X 2, . . . , X11] such that for all assignments of truth values 8 E {0, 1 } P , we have - 8(F) ,...._, = � PF (8(A J ), 8 (A2) , . . . , 8 (A11)), where PF denotes the polynomial function (from {0, 1 }11 into {0, 1}) associated with the polynomial PFFor a given formula F , is the polynomial PF unique? 57 E X ER C I S E S F O R C HA PTER J (d) From the preceding, deduce a procedure for determining whether two for­ mulas are logically equivalent or whether a formula is a tautology. 15. We propose to slightly modify the notion of propositional calculus that we have defined by adding to its syntax the 'constants true and false' . We still have a set of propositional variables P, the parentheses and the five symbols for connectives, and, to complete the alphabet from which the formulas will be built, we add two new symbols T (the constant, true) and ..l (the constant, false) which we may consider, if we wish, to be symbols for 0-ary connectives. The only modification to the definition of the set of formulas is to admit two new formulas of height 0: T and 1.. From the semantical point of view, we must augment the definition of the extension 8 of an assignment of truth values 8 (which remains a map from P into {0, 1 } ) in the following way: - 8(T) - = 1 and 8(1_) = 0. All other definitions are unchanged. The formula T belongs to 1, the class of tautologies, and the formula ..l to the class of antilogies, 0. This justifies the use we made of these symbols in our earlier list of tautologies. (a) Show that, in this new context, the interpolation lemma is true, even without the hypothesis that the formulas F and G have at least one variable in common. (b) Show that any formula that is written with the unique variable A together with the symbols for connectives /\, v, T, and ..l (to the exclusion of all others) is logically equivalent to one of the three formulas T, 1., A. (c) Show that any formula that is written with the two variables A and B together with the symbols for connectives , '¢:>, T, and 1. (to the exclusion of all others) is logically equivalent to one of the eight formulas -, T, 1., A , B, -,A, -,B, (A '¢> B), _,(A '¢> B). (d) Show that the following systems o f connectives are complete: {=>, 0}; {0, '¢> , v } ; {0, '¢> , A}; { '}'}; {�}. (e) Show that the following systems of connectives are not complete: {1, :::} , /\, v } ; {0. 1 , A, v}; {0, 1 , , '¢> } . -, (f) Show that among the zero-place o r one-place o r two-place connectives, the only ones that, by themselves alone, constitute a complete set of connectives are the Sheffer strokes, t and �· 58 PROPOSITIONAL CALCULUS 16. (a) Show that the formula (A <=> ( B <=> ((A <=> B) <=> C) but not to ( (A <=> B) C)) is logically equivalent to 1\ (B <=> C)). The first of these observations might have led us to adopt a simplified way of writing the for­ mula as A <=> B <=> C as we did for conjunction and disjunction. Explain why the second of these observations motivates us to avoid doing so. (b) Consider a natural number n > 2 and a set of pairwise distinct proposi­ tional variables B = { B 1 , B2 , . . . , Bn } . Let Q (B) denote the set of formulas that can be written using one occurrence of each of the n propositional variables Bt , B2, . . . , Bn, n - I occurrences of the opening parenthesis, n - I occurrences of the closing parenthesis and n - I occurrences of the symbol <:>. Show that all the formulas in Q(B) are (pairwise) logically equivalent and are satisfied by a given assignment of truth values 8 if and only if the number of variables Bi ( I < i < n) assigned the value false by 8 . IS even. (c) For any formula G E Q(B), G denotes the formula obtained from G by ,...., replacing all occurrences of <=> with §. Show that G is logically equivalent to G if n is odd and to �G if n is even. (d) Let E be a set. For every natural number k > 2 and for all subsets X I , X 2 , . . . , X k of E, we define the symmetric difference of X I , X 2 , . . . , X k , denoted by X I tJ.. X2 tJ.. . . tJ.. Xk , by induction i n the following way: '""-' • X I !:J.. X 2l:J.. • E E : X E X I {/:? X E X 2 } ; X 1 /),. x2 = {x !:J.. X k+I = (X 1 !:J.. X 2 l:J.. . . . !:J.. X k) !:J.. Xk+l · • • Show thatforevery natural numberk > 2 and forall subsets X I , X2, . . . , Xk of E , X 1 tJ.. X 2 tJ.. tJ.. Xk is the set of elements of E that belong to an odd number of the subsets Xi. 17. Consider propositional variables A , B, A 1 , A 2 , . . . , An. . . • (a) Prove the converse of the definability theorem: for any formula F[A I , A2, . . . , An , A-1, if there exists a formula G [A I , A 2, . . . , A n ] such that the formula is a tautology (we say in this case that then the formula is also a tautology. G is a definition of A modulo F), 59 E X E R C I S E S FOR C HAPTER I (b) In each of the five following cases, with the given formula of the form F[A t , A2, . . . , An, A], associate a formula GfA t , A2, . . . , A n] that is a definition of A modulo F. 1. F = A t ¢> A ; 2. F = (At ::::} A ) 1\ (A =:::} A 2 ) 1\ (A I ¢> A 2 ); 3. F = A t A A2 A A; 4 . F = (A t =} A ) 1\ ( A v A 2 ) 1\ -,(A 1\ A 2 ) 1\ (A2 ::::} A I ); 5 . F = (A t =} A) 1\ (A2 =} A ) 1\ (A3 =} A) 1\ (_,A t ¢> (A2 ¢> _, A 3 )). 18. This exercise suggests another proof of the definability theorem. Let F[A t , A2, . . . , An, A] be a propositional formula such that the formula is a tautology. Recall that CfJF denotes the map from {0, 1}n + l into {0, 1} asso­ ciated with F (its 'truth table' ). We define a map ljr from {0, 1 }n into {0, 1} as follows: for all elements e t , £2 , . . . , en in {0, 1 } i f cpF (et , e 2, . . . , en , 0 ) = 1 otherwise. (a) Show that if CfJF(e t , e2, . . . , en, 1) = 1, then 1/l(et , e2 , . . . , en) = 1. (b) Let G = G[A t , A2, . . . , An] be a formula that has t/1 as its truth table (i.e. is such that CfJG = t/1 ). Show that G is a definition of A modulo F, i.e. that the formula is a tautology. 19. Consider a set with fi ve propositional variables, P = {A, B, C, D , E}. (a) How many formulas, up to logical equivalence, are satisfied by exactly seventeen assignments of truth values? (b) How many formulas, up to logical equivalence, are consequences of the formula (A 1\ B)? 20.. Consider a set of propositional variables P . Let 81 denote the assignment o f truth values on P defined by 8 1 (A) = 1 for every element A E P. (a) Show that for every formula F, there exists at least one formula G that does not contain the symbol -, and is such that F is logically equivalent either to G or to -,G. 60 P R O PO S I T I O N A L C A L C U L U S (b) Show that for every formula F, the following three properties are equivalent: (i) F is logically equivalent to at least one formula in which the only connectives that may appear are /\, v, and ==}. (ii) F is logically equivalent to at least one formula which does not contain the symbol --,. (iii) 8}(F) == 1. 21. Consider a finite set of propositional variables P = { A I , A 2 , . . . , A 11 } . 0 n the set o f assignments o ftruth values on P, we define a binary relation << by the condition "A << ,u if and only i f for all i E { I , 2, . . . , n }, "A(A;) < JL ( A i ) . (a) Show that << is a n order relation. Is it a total ordering? (b) A formula F is called increasing if and only if for all assignments of truth values A. and Jl to P , if A. << Jl, then 'A(F ) < M (F ) . Is the negation ofa formula that is not increasing necessarily a n increasing formula? (c) Show that for every formula F, F is increasing if and only if: (i) F is a tautology, or (ii) -,F is a tautology, or (iii) there exists a formula G that is logically equivalent to F and in which none of the three connectives , :::}, and {:} occurs. --, 22. A set A of formulas of the propositional calculus is called independent if and only if for every formula F E A, F is not a consequence of A { F } . - (a) Which of the following sets of formulas are independent? { (A ==} B), (B ==} C ) , (C ==} A ) } { (A => B ) , (B ==} C ) , (A => C ) } { (A v B ) , (A ==} C ) , ( B ==> C), (_,A ==> ( B v C)) } ; { A , B , ( A ==} C ) , (C ==} B ) } ; { (A ==} (B v C)), (C ==} __,B), (B (A ==} C), ( B ==} A ) } ; => (A v C)), ( ( B A C) { ((A ==} B ) ==} C ) , ( A ==} C ) , ( B ==} C), ( C ( ( A ==} B ) ==} ( A {:} B ) ) } . ==} {:} B), ( B ==} A ) ) , For each of them, i f i t i s not independent, find ooe (and, i f possible, several) equivalent independent subsets. (b) Is the empty set independent? Provide a necessary and sufficient condition for the independence of a set consisting of a single formula. 61 EXERCISES FOR CHAPTER I (c) Show that every finite seto fformulas has at least one independent equivalent subset. (d) Show that for a set of formulas to be independent, it is necessary and suffi­ cient that all its finite subsets be independent. (e) Does theinfinite set {A 1 , A 1 AA2, A 1 AA2AA3, . . . , A t AA2A· · · /\A n , . . . } have an equivalent independent subset? (The Ai are propositional variables.) Does there exist any independent set that is equivalent to it? (f) Show that for any countable set of formulas { F1 , F2, . . . , Fn , . . . }, there exists at least one equivalent independent set. 23. Given a set £, a graph on E is a binary relation G that is symmetric and antireflexive (which means that for every element x E £, (x, x) � G). If k i s a non-zero natural number and i f G is a graph on E, we say that G is k -colourable if and only i f there exists a map f from E into { 1 , 2, . . . , k } such that for all (x, y) E G, f(x) =!= f(y). (a) Forevery pair (x, i) E E x { 1 , 2, . . . , k } , let Ax,i be a propositional variable. Define a set A(E, G, k) of formulas of the propositional calculus on the set of variables Ax,i that is satisfiable if and only if the graph is k-colourable. (b) Show that for a graph to be k-colourable, it is necessary and sufficient that all of its finite restrictions be k-colourable. 24.. An abelian group ( G, · , 1) is called orderable if and only if there exists a total order relation < on G that is compatible with the group operation, which means that for all elements x , y, and z of G , if x < y, then x · z < y · z. An abelian group (G, · , 1) is called torsion-free if and only i f for any element n x of G different from 1 and for any non-zero natural number n, x is different k from 1. (x is defined by induction: x 1 == x and for all integers k > 1 , x k + 1 k x · x .) An abelian group (G, · , 1 ) is said to be of finite type if and only if it is generated by a finite subset of G (which means that there is a finite subs��t X c G such that the smallest subgroup of G that includes X is G itself). We will use the following theorem from algebra (for example, see Theo­ rem 5.09 in The Theory of Groups by I.D. Macdonald, Oxford University Press, == 1968) For every torsion-free abelian group offinite type (G, 1) that does not reduce to the single element 1, there is a non-zero natural number p such that (G, · , 1) is isomorphic to the group {7LP, + , 0). 2 (a) Let (G, 1) be an abelian group. Take {Ax,y : (x, y) E G } as the set of propositional variables and write down a set A( G) of formulas of proposJ.­ tional calculus that is satisfiable if and only if the group G is orderable. ·, ·, (b) Show that for an abelian group to be orderable, it is necessary and sufficient that all of its subgroups of finite type be orderable. (c) Show that for an abelian group to be orderable, it is necessary and sufficient that it be torsion-free. 62 PROPOSITlONAL CALCULUS 25. Consider two sets E and F and a binary relation R c E x F. For every element x E E, let R x denote the set of elements of related to x under R: Rx == {y E F : (x, y) E F that are R}. For every subset A c E, the following set i s called the image of A under R: We make the following two hypotheses: (I) For every subset A of E, the cardinality of RA is greater than or equal to the cardinality of A. (II) For every element x E £, the set Rx is finite. The purpose of this exercise is to prove the following property: (III) There exists an injective map f from E into F such that for every element x E £, f (x) E Rx (i.e. an injective map from E into F that is included in R). (a) Suppose that E is finite. Without using hypothesis II, prove III by induction on the cardinality of E by examining two cases: 1 . there is at least one subset A of E such that A =/= 0, A t= E, and card(A) 2. == card(RA); for every non-empty subset A � E, card(A) < card(RA ) . (b) Give an example i n which I i s true while I I and III are false. (c) By using the compactness theorem, prove III when E is infi nite. 2 Boolean algebras When we ident{fy logically equivalent formulas of the propositional calculus, we obtain a set on which, in a natural way, we can define a unary operation and two binary operations which correspond respectively to negation, to conjunction, and to disjunction. The structure obtained in this way is an example ofa Boolean algebra. Another example of a Boolean algebra is provided by the set of subsets of a given set together with the operations of complementation, intersection, and union (which, by the way, are ojien called Boolean operations). There are diverse ways of app1vaching Boolean algebras. While we will begin with two purely algebraic presentations (as rings or as ordered sets), we will discover at the end of the chapter that we can just as well adopt a topological point of view: every Boolean algebra can be ident{fied with the set ofthose subsets of some compact, zero-dimensional space that are both open and closed. The reader should not be concerned by these perhaps unfamiliar words; Section 2. _l will contain all the necessary reminders, both from algebra and topology (we nonetheless assume that the reader does know the definitions of ring, field, and topological space; if not, the reader should consult, for example, A Survey of Modern Algebra by Garrett Birkhoff and Saunders Maclane (A. K. Peters Ltd, 1997) and the text General Topology by John L Kelley (Springer-Verlag, 1 991 ) Section 2.2 contains the algebraic definitions and corresponding basic plvper­ ties. A Boolean algebra is a ring in which every element is equal to its square; but it isjust as well a distributive, complemented lattice, i.e. an ordered set in which: (i) there is a least element and a greatest element, (ii) every pair of elements has a lower bound and an upper bound, each of these operations being distributive with respect to the other, and, finally, (iii) every element has a complement. We will establish the equivalence of these two points of view and study examples. Section 2.3 is devoted to atoms: non-zero elements that are minimal with respect to the order on the Boolean algebra. This important notion arises frequently in whatfollows, especially in several exercises. In Section 2.4 we are interested in homomorphisms of Boolean algebras. As always in algebra, the kernels of these homomorphisms (which in this context are ideals) play an essential 1vle. When we consider a Boolean algebra A as a lattice, we prefer to study not the ideals but rather the filters which are canonically asso­ ciared with them (we obtain a filter by taking the complements of the elements o.f . 64 BOOLEAN ALGEBRAS an ideal). Study o.lthese ideals andfilters is the objective ofSection 2.5. Particular attention is paid to maxima/filters or ultrafilter.�·, which obviously correspond to maximal ideals, but also correspond to homomorphisms of A into the Boolean algebra {0, 1}. The set of these homomorphisms is given a topology: this is then called the Stone space ofA, a space which is studied in the sixth and last section o.l this chapte1: The compactness theorem for propositional calculus, which will prove using topology in Section 2. 1, is related in a natural way to the compactness of the Stone space of the algebra of equivalence classes of logically equivalent formulas (Exercise 13). we 2.1 Algebra and topology review 2.1.1 Algebra Consider a commutative ring with identity A = (A, +, x , 0, 1). We will always assume that i n such a ring, w e have 0 =I= 1 . A s i s customary, either of the notations a x b or ab will denote the product of two elements a and b of A. Definition 2.1 An ideal of A is a subset I of A such that • • (I, +, 0) is a subgroup of ( A , +, 0); For every element x of I andfor every element y of A, x x y E I. The set A itself obviously satisfies these conditions. An ideal of A distinct from A is called a proper ideal. An idea] I of A is a proper ideal if and only if 1 1-. I. (If I :::: A, then 1 E I ; if 1 E I, then for every element y o f A, 1 x y = y E I , hence A = /). We will only consider proper ideals here. S o for us, an ideal of A will be a subset I of A which, in addition to the two conditions above, satisfies the following property: • l (j-. 1 . To adopt this point o f view can sometimes be inconvenient: for example, given two ideals 1 and J of A, there may not be a smallest idea] containing both I and J because the sum of two ideals 1 and J , i.e. the set 1+] :::: {x E A : (3y E I)(3z E J ) (x = y + z)} which usually plays this role, may well not be a proper ideal. For instance, i n the ring of integers IE, the sum of the ideals 21E (the set of multiples of 2) and 31E is the entire ring IE. Nonetheless, these potential inconveniences are not bothersome in the current context. The reader who absolutely insists on preserving the usual definition of ideal should, in what follows, replace �ideal' by 'proper ideal' everywhere. 65 A L G E B R A A N D TOPOLOGY R E V I EW Krull's theorem can be stated this way: Theorem 2.2 Every ideal in a commutative ring with identity is included in at least one maximal ideal. (An ideal is maximal if it is not strictly included in any other ideal.) The proof uses Zorn's lemma (see Chapter 7 in Part 2). Let I be an ideal in the ring A. Let E denote the set of ideals in A that include I ; Proof E = { J E � (A ) : J i s an ideal and I c J}. The theorem will be proved i fw e can establish the existence o fat least one maximal element in the ordered set (£, C ) . For this i t suffices (Zorn's lemma) to show that this ordered set is non-empty (but this is clear since I E £) and that every non­ empty totally ordered subset of E has an upper bound in £. So let X be a subset of E that is totally ordered by the relation of inclusion (also known as a chain in ( £. C)); we assume that X is not empty. Let Io be the union of the elements of X: lo = U J E X J . A s X is not empty and as any element of X includes I_ I is included in Io, thus 0 E Io. I fx and y are elements of lo, there are two ideals J and K in X such that x E J and y E K . As X is totally ordered, we have either J c K or K c J . If we are, for example, in the first situation, then x E K and y E K . therefore x - y E K and x - y E Io. It follows that ( Io, + , 0) i s a subgroup of ( A , +, 0). As well, if x E /o and y E A , then for at least one ideal J E X, we have x E J , hence xy E J and xy E Io. Finally, we have l fj Io, for in the opposite case, 1 would belong to one of the elements of X, which is forbidden. We have thus established that Io is an ideal of A which includes I, i.e. is an element of E For each J in X, J c Io: it follows that lo is, in £, an upper bound for the chain X • I be an ideal in the ring A. We define an equivalence relation on A congruence modulo I and denoted by � Let - for all elements x and y of A, x called : =t y if and only if x - y E I. The fact that this i s a n equivalence relation i s easily proved. Let a denote the equivalence class of the element a E A. We have 0 = I. Congruence modulo I is compatible with the ring operations + and x : this means that if a , b, c, and d are elements of A , if a -� c and b =1 d, then a + b =1 c + d and a x b � c x d . This allows us to define two operations on the set A/ -� of equivalence classes, which we will continue to denote by + and x , defined by: for all elements x and J' of A , x + y = x + y and x x y = x x y. These two operations on the set AI -l give it the structure of a commutative ring with unit (the zero element is I , the unit element is 1) called the quotient ring of A by the ideal I and denoted by AI I rather than by A/ = I · All required verifications are elementary. The most well-known example of what we have just described is given by the rings 7lf n7l (where n is a natural number greater than or equal to 2). - BOOLEAN ALGEBRAS 66 Theorem 2.3 The quotient ring A/ I is afield ({and only ifthe ideal / is maximal. Proof If we suppose that I is not maximal, we can choose an ideal J of A such that I � J (strict inclusion). Let a be an element of J that does not belong to /. We have a # I , hence a is a non-zero element in the quotient ring. I f this element were invertible, there would be an element b E A such that a x h = 1 � which is to say ab =1 1, or equivalently ab l E I , so also ab - 1 E J. Because a E J and J is an ideal, ab E J. Thus the difference ab - (ab - 1) = 1 would belong to J , which is impossible. It follows that there i s at least one non-zero, noninvertible element in the ring A/ I : it is therefore not a field. Now suppose that I is maximal. Let a be an element of A such that a # 0 (equivalently, a fj. /). Our goal is to show that a is an invertible element of the quotient ring A/ I . Consider the following set: - - - K = {x E A : (3y E A)(3z E / ) (x = ay + z )}. I t is easy t o verify that ( K , +, 0) i s a subgroup o f (A, +, 0): first o f all, 0 E K since 0 = (a x 0) + 0; also, if XJ E K and x2 E K , then we can find elements YI and Y2 in A , and Z I and 22 in I , such that X i = ay1 + Z l and x2 = ay2 + 22; we conclude from this that XI - X2 = a (YI - Y2) + Z l - Z2 , that YI - Y2 E A, and that Z I - 22 E I , thus Xt - x2 E K . O n the other hand� if x E K and t E A, then x t E K : indeed, there are elements y E A and z E I such that x = ay + z, thus xt = a (ty) + tz; but ty E A and tz E /, so xt E K . This shows that the first two conditions in the definition of an ideal are satisfied by K. If the third o f these conditions were also satisfied (thus if 1 rf. K), K would be an ideal in A. But the set K strictly includes the set I : indeed, every element x of I can be written x = (a x 0) + x, and thus also belongs to K ; and the element a, which can b e written (a x 1) + 0, belongs to K but not to I. As I is a maximal ideal, K could not then be an ideal in A. We conclude from this that 1 E K . So we can then find two elements y E A and z E I such that ay + z = 1 . So w e have l - ay = z E / o r equivalently, passing t o the equivalence classes for the relation = 1 , 1 - ay = 0, which translates as a x y = l. So the element a does have an inverse in the quotient ring A// . We have thus shown that every non-zero element o f this ring i s invertible: A II • is therefore a field. .. - - Observe that the proof we have just given contains an illustration of what we said earlier concerning the sum of two ideals. Indeed, the set K which we considered is the sum of the ideal I and what is known as the principal ideal generated by a (i.e. the ideal consisting of multiples of a). We found ourselves precisely in the situation in which this sum of ideals is the entire ring. ALGEBRA AND TOPOLOGY REVIEW 67 2 . 1 ..2 Topology Let X be a topological space and Y a subset of X . We give Y a topology, called the topology induced on Y by that of X, by taking as the open sets in this topology the intersections with Y of open subsets of X . In other words, for a subset Q c Y to be open in the induced topology, it is necessary and sufficient that there exist an open set 0 in the topology on X such that Q = 0 n Y. We see immediately that the closed sets for the induced topology on Y are the intersections with Y of the closed subsets of X. When we speak of a subspace of a topological space X, we mean a subset with its induced topology. A basis for the open sets of a topological space X is a family ( 0; );E/ of open sets in the topology such that every open set is a union of open sets from this family; in other words, for every open set G, there is at least one subset J c I such that G U j E J Oj . When a basis for the open sets of a topological space has been chosen, the elements of this basis are called basic open sets. The complements in X of the basic open sets are called basic closed sets and it is clear that every closed set is an intersection of basic closed sets. For the usual topology on the set IR of real numbers, the bounded open intervals (i.e. sets of the form ] a , b[ where a E IR, b E IR. and a < b) constitute a basis for the open sets. Moreover, it is obvious that in any topological space whatever, the family of all open sets is a basis for the open sets. The following property is immediate: == Lemma 2.4 If ( 0; );EJ is a basisfor the open sets ofthe topological space X and if Y is a subset of X, then the family (0; n Y ) ; E / is a basis for the topology on Y induced by that of X. This means that the intersections with Y of the basic open subsets of X are basic open subsets of Y . Let X and Y b e two topological spaces. A map f from X into Y i s called continuous if and only if the inverse image under f of every open subset of Y is an open subset of X. In other words, f is continuous if and only if, for every open subset Q of Y, the set f- 1 [Q] = {x E X: f (x) E Q} is an open subset of X. Let (Q;)iEI be a basis for the open subsets of a topological space Y and let f be a map ftvm X into Y. For f to be continuous, it is necessary and sufficient that for every index i E /, f - 1 [Qi l be an open subset of X. Lemma 2.5 Proof This is necessary due to the definition of continuity (something that must hold for all the open subsets of Y must hold in particularfor the basic open subsets). This is sufficient since, if Q is any open subset of Y, then there is a subset J c I such that Q = Uj EJ Oj , hence f- 1 [ Q ] = Uj E J f - 1 [ 0j ] (this last fact is a wc�ll-known property of inverse images); if all of the f - 1 [ 0;] are open subsets of X'} f -1 [Q] will be a union of open subsets, and hence an open subset of X. • homeomorphism of the topological space X onto the topolog­ ical space Y is a b{iective, continuous map from X into Y whose inverse is Definition 2.6 A a BOOLEAN ALGEBRAS 68 continuous mapfrom Y into X. (We speak in this context ofa bijective bicontinu­ ous map). Definition 2.7 A topological space X is called Hausdorff (or separated) if and only (ffor every pair of distinct elements x and y of X there exist di.\joint open sets G and H such that x E G and y E H. It is immediate that every subs pace of a Hausdorffspace is Hausdorff Lemma 2.8 Let X be a topological space that is Hausdorff and let Y be a subset of X. Then the topology induced on Y by that of X makes Y a Hausdorff space. Proof If x and y are distinct points of Y, the intersections with Y of two disjoint open subsets of X that contain x and y respectively will be two disjoint open • subsets of Y that contain x and y respectively. Definition 2.9 A covering (or cover) ofa topological space X is afamily (Ei )i el of subsets of X such that X = Uie / Ef. If all of the Ei are open sets, we speak of an open covering (or open cover). A subcovering of a covering (Ei )iel is a subfamily (Ej)jeJ ( J /) which is itse?f a covering of X. We will speak of a finite covering (or subcovering) when the corresponding set of indices is finite. c Definition 2.10 A topological space is called compact if and only if 1°) it is Hausdor:ff and 2°) from every open covering of X we can extract a finite subcovering. Lemma 2.11 Let X be a Hausdorff'space. For X to be compact, it isnecessa1yand sufficient that everyfamily of closed subsets (�f X whose intersection is non-empty have a finite subfamily whose intersection is non-empty. Proof It suffices to observe that if (F; ) i El is a family of closed subsets of X and if, for each i E I, we denote the complement of Fi in X by Oi (which is an open set), then ni El Fi = 0 if and only if u i E/ oi = X. Thus, to each family of closed subsets of X whose intersection is empty, there corresponds, by complementation, an open covering of X, and vice versa. • Lemma 2.12 Let (Qi )i e l be a basis for the open sets of a Hausdorff space X. For X to be compact, it is necessary and su.fficient that from every covering of X by basic open sets we can extract a .finite subcovering. Proof The condition is obviously necessary. Assume it is satisfied and that (Gk)kEK is a covering of X by arbitrary open sets. We have X = Uk e K Gk, but since each G k is a union of basic open sets, we have a covering of X by a family of basic open sets (Qj)jEJ ( J c / ) , with each Qj included in at least one of the open sets G k· So, given our assumption, we can extract from this cover­ ing a finite subcovering and we will have, for example, X = Q j1 U Qj2 U · · · U Qj11 It is now sufficient to choose open sets G k 1 , G k2 , . . . , G kn from the family ( G k )kEK which include n.il Qj2 , , Qj11 respectively; we will then have a finite • , . . • A L G E B R A A N D TOPOLOGY R E V I EW subcovering from ( G k)k E K since X compact. == 69 G k1 U Gk2 U · · · U Gkn . This proves that X is • Naturally, the previous property can be rephrased in terms of closed sets: Let X be a Hausdorff space with a given basis for the open sets. For X to be compact, it is necessary and sufficient thatfrom everyfamily of basic closed sets whose intersection is empty, we can extract a finite subfamily whose intersection is already empty. Lemma 2.13 subset of a topological space X that is simultaneously open and closed (i.e. an open subset whose complement in X is also open) will be called Definition 2.14 A clopen. topological space which has a basis consisting ofclopen sets is called zero-dimensional. For example, in the space Q of rational numbers, the bounded open intervals whose endpoints are irrational constitute a basis ofclopen sets for the usual topology (as is easily ver(fied): thus Q is a zero-dimensional topological space. Definition 2.15 A Fora topological space to be zero-dimensional, it is necessary and su:fficient that the family of clopen subsets be a basis for the open sets. Lemma 2.16 Proof It is obvious that any family of open sets that includes a basis for the open subsets of X is itself a basis for the open subsets of X. Thus, if X is zero­ dimensional, then the family of all its clopen subsets is a basis for the open sets. The converse is immediate. • Every subspace Y of a zero- dimensional topological space X is zetV·-dimensional. Proof Let ( Oi );E I be a basis for the open subsets of X consisting of clopen sets. Lemma 2.17 The family ( 0; n Y)iE l is a basis for the open subsets of Y (Lemma 2.4) but these open sets are also closed subsets of Y since they are the intersections with Y of • closed subsets of X. Definition 2.18 A compact zero-dimensional topological space is called a Boolean space. Let (Xi )tEl be a family of topological spaces. On the product n iE/ X; of this family, we can define a topology by taking as the basic open sets all subsets oftheform n iE I 0; where, for each index i E /, 0; is an open subset of X;, but wherefor all butfinitely many indices i, we have 0; = X i . lt is easy to verify that the collection consisting of unions of sets of this type is closed under intersections and arbitrary unions. It is this collection of sets that we take as the family of open sets for the topology on ni E l X;. The topology defined in this way is called the product topology. Definition 2.19 70 BOOLEAN ALGEBRAS Tychonoff's theorem asserts that: Theorem 2.20 The product of any family of compact topological spaces is a compact topological space. The proof makes use of Zorn's lemma and can be found, for example, in the text by J.L. Kelley (General Topology, Van Nostrand, 1 955, republished by Springer-Verlag, Graduate Texts in Mathematics, 1 99 1 ) (but it has the drawback of using the notion of filter which will be studied later in this chapter). Let us now examine the special case which will interest us in this chapter (Section 2.6): the case in which each Xi in the family of spaces (Xi)iEI is the set {0, 1} with the discrete topology (the one in which all subsets are open). In this case, the product lli E/ X; is the set {0, 1 } 1 of maps from 1 into {0, 1 } . To produce a basic open set Q i n the product topology� w e must take a finite number of indices, i ] , i2, . . . ' ik in 1 and open sets 0;1 ' oi2 ' . . . ' oik from {0, l}, which, i n this case, are arbitrary subsets of {0, 1 }. We then set or alternatively It is natural to suppose that we are really interested only in those indices ij for which the corresponding open set is something other than the set {0, 1 } itself. It is also pointless to consider cases in which one of the Oi ; is the empty set, for we would then have Q = 0. There remain only two possible choices for the Oij : oij = {0} or oij = { 1 } . Thus we see that to produce a basic open set Q i n the product topology on { 0, l}, w e must take a finite number o f indices i 1 , i2, . . . , ik i n I and the same number of elements £ 1 , £ 2, . . . , Bk in {0, 1} and then set Q = {f E {0, 1 } 1 : f(i J ) = £J and f(i2) = £2 and . . . and f( ik) = Bk} . A basic open set, therefore, is the set of all maps from I into {0, 1 } which assume given values at some finite number of given points. Observe that the complement in {0, 1 }1 of the set Q that we just considered is the following set: u l <j<k {f E {0, 1 } 1 : f(ij) = l - £j }- So it is the union of k basic open sets, which is obviously an open set. We conclude that Q is a closed set. DEFINITION OF BOOLEAN ALGEBRA 71 The basic open sets i n the topology o n {0, 1 } are therefore clopen sets. Conse­ quently, we have proved: Lemma 2.21 The topological space {0, 1 } 1 is zero-dimensional. Since the discrete space {0, 1 } is clearly compact, we may conclude, using Tychonoff's theorem, that: Theorem 2.22 The space {0, 1 } 1 is a Boolean topological space. 2.1.3 An application to propositional calculus Tychonoff's theorem allows us to give a very rapid proof of the compactness theorem for propositional calculus (Theorem 1 .40). Proof Let P be a set of propositional variables and let F denote the associated set of formulas. For each F E F, let 6.(F) denote the set of assignments of truth values that satisfy it: 6. (F) == {8 E {0, l } P : 8(F) == 1}. If A t , A 2 , . . . , An are the variables that occur in the formula F, we see that the set t.�(F) is a union of sets of the form where the £; are elements of {0, 1 } . Indeed, the satisfaction of a formula F by an assignment 8 does not depend on the values that 8 assumes outside the set { A J , A 2 , . . . , An} (Lemma 1 . 19). So the set 6.(F) is a union of basic open sets in the topological space {0, 1 } P . This is a finite union: it involves at most 2n sets. So we conclude that 6.(F) is itself a clopen set. Now consider a set of formulas T c F that is not satisfiable. This means, precisely, that the intersection, nF ET bt.(F), is the empty set. Thus the family (bt.(F))FE T is, in the compact space {0, 1 } P , a family of closed sets whose inter­ section is empty. So it is possible to extract a finite subfamily whose intersection is already empty; so there is a finite subset To c T such that n F E To bt.(F) = 0. This means that there is some finite subset o f T that is not satisfiable. This proves • (version 2 of) the compactness theorem for propositional calculus. In Exercise 13, we will encounter another proof of this compactness theorem; this proof will make use of the results from Sections 2.5 and 2.6 and will avoid any appeal to Tychonoff's theorem, for which we have not given a proof. 2.2 Definition of Boolean algebra Definition 2.23 A Boolean algebra (sometimes called a Boolean ring) is a ring ( A ) +, x , 0, 1 ) in which each element is idempotent for multiplication (i.e. is equal to its square). an 72 BOOLEAN ALGEBRAS Example 2.24 The ring (IZ/2�, +, x , 0, 1 ) . Example 2.25 The ring (8;J ( £ ) , b. , n , 0, E), where E i s an arbitrary non-empty set, b. and n are the operations of symmetric difference and intersection respec­ tively on the set 8;J (E) of all subsets of E (see Exercise 2). Example 2.26 Another interesting example is furnished by propositional calculus. Consider a set of propositional variables and the corresponding set :F of formulas. As we will make precise in Exercise 1 , the set FI � of equivalence classes of logically equivalent formulas with the operations of § and 1\ has the structure of a Boolean algebra (these operations can be defined on this set because the relation � is compatible with the propositional connectives). The class 0 of antilogies and the class 1 of tautologies are, respectively, the identity elements for the operations § and /\. We will have occasion to return to this example, which is in fact our principal motivation for studying Boolean algebras. 2.2.1 Properties of Boolean algebras, order relations Lemma 2.27 • • In any Boolean algebra, every element is its own additive inverse. Every Boolean algebra is commutative. Proof Let ( A , +, x , 0, 1) be a Boolean algebra and let x and y be elements of 2 2 2 A. From the definition, we have x = x, y == y, and (x + y) = x + y, while moreover, as in any ring, we have S o w e may conclude x + y = x + xy + yx + y, or after simplification, xy + yx = 0. Letting y == 1 , we obtain in particular that x + x = 0 or x = -x, which proves the first point. For arbitrary x and y therefore, xy is the inverse of xy, but since xy + yx == 0, it is also the inverse of yx. From this we conclude that xy = yx and that the algebra is commutative. • The Boolean ring (�/2�, +, x , 0, 1 ) is the only Boolean ring that is a field, and even the only Boolean ring that is an integral domain: indeed, the relation x2 = x, which is equivalent to x (x - 1) = 0, requires, in an integral domain, that x = 0 or x = 1 . Let (A, + , x, 0 , 1 ) b e a Boolean algebra. We defi.ne a binary relation < on A as follows: for all elements x and y of A , x < y if and only if xy = x. Remark 2.28 DEFINITION OF BOOLEAN ALGEBRA 73 We will now verify that this is indeed an order relation. For all elements x , and z of A, we have y, • • • < x, since x 2 = x by definition; if x < y and y < z, then xy = x and yz = z; hence, xz = (xy)z = x (yz) = xy = x, so x < z ; if x < y and y < x, then xy = x and yx = y, hence x = y by commutativity. x So the relation < is reflexive, transitive, and antisymmetric. The following theorem lists the main properties of this order relation. Theorem 2.29 is a greatest elementfor the relation <. Indeed, for every x, 0 x 0 and 1 x x = x, hence 0 < x and x < 1 . ( 1 ) 0 is a least element and 1 Proof x :::::: • (2) Any two elements x and y of A have a greatest lower bound (i.e. a common lower bound that is greater than any other common lower bound), denoted by x ... y: specifically, their product xy. 2 2 Proof We have (xy)x = x y = xy and (xy)y = xy = xy, thus xy is a lower bound both for x and for y. Moreover, if z is a common lower bound for x and y, we have zx = z and zy = y, hence z(x y) = (zx) y :::::: zy = z, which means that • z =::: x y; thus xy is the greatest of the common lower bounds for x and y. , (3) Any two elements x andy ofA have a least upper bound (i.e. a common upper bound that is smaller than any other common upper bound), denoted by x y: specifically, the element x + y + x y. '"'"" Proof Indeed, x (x + y + xy) = x2 + xy + x2 y = x + xy + xy = x + 0 = x, and in analogous fashion, y(x + y + xy) = y. So we certainly have x < x + y + x y and y < x + y + x y. On the other hand, if z is an element of A such that x < z and y < z, which is to say xz = x and yz = y, then (x + y so x + y + x y x and y. (4) + xy)z = xz + yz + xyz :::::: x+y + xy, < z ; thus x + y + xy is the least of the common upper bounds for • The operations ,... and '-" thus defined on A are associative and commutative. Proof This is true (and very easy to prove! ) in any ordered set that satisfies • properties (2) and (3). BOOLEAN ALGEBRAS 74 is an identity elementfor the operation '--' and an absorbing elementfor the operation r,; while 1 is an identity elementfor the operation � and an absorbing element for the operation � ( 5) 0 . Proof To put this another way� for every element x of A, we have x 0 = x, x � 0 = 0 , x � 1 = x and x 1 = 1 . This i s true i n any ordered set that satisfies properties ( 1 ) (2), and (3). It is trivial to verify this. • '--' '--' , Every non-empty finite subset {XI , x2, . . . ,Xk } of A (k E N*) has a greatest lower bound equal to x 1 � x2 � · · · � Xk and a least upper bound equal to X I '--' X2 · • • Xk· Proof Except for the obvious case in which k = 1, this is a simple generalization of properties (2) and (3) which we naturally obtain by induction on k. We wish t o call your attention t o the following fact: the expression XJ � x2 � · · · Xk is not a new notation intended to denote some newly introduced object. (6) '--' '--' "--. It denotes an element of A that is legitimately defined (by induction) as soon as the operation � has been defined (it is the element that we ought to denote by an expression that contains k - 1 pairs of parentheses, which wehavesuppressed in view of associativity. Concerning the operation property (6) asserts two distinct facts: first, that the elements x 1 , x2, . . . , Xk have a greatest common lower bound; and second, that this greatest common lower bound is r-, The proof of these two facts is certainly extremely simple (indeed, we have avoided giving i t!), but the difficulty perhaps lies in determining precisely what needs to • be proved. (The same remark applies, of course, to the operation '--'). (7) Each of the operations '--' and � is distributive over the other. Proof On the one hand, x � (y "-" z) x(y + z t yz) = xy -t- xz + xyz = xy -t- xz + xy · xz = (x � y) "-" (x � z) = - - for any elements x, y, and z of A which guarantees that � distributes over '--' . On the other hand, with x, y, and z still arbitrary elements of A, (x '--' y) � (x '---' z) = (x + y -f- xy)(x + z -t- xz) 2 2 2 2 = x -t- xz � x z -t- yx -f- yz -f- yxz -t- x y + xyz -t- x yz = x + yz -t- xyz - after obvious simplifi cations. - 75 DEFINITION OF BOOLEAN ALGEBRA But x + property. yz + xyz = x '-../ (yz) = x '-../ (y r-- z), hence the other distributive • For every element x in A, there is an element x' in A called the complement of such that x x = 1, and x r-- x' = 0. (8) � '-../ Proof I f such an element x ' exists, it satisfies xx ' = 0 and x + x' + xx ' == 1 , hence also x + x' == 1 , o r again x' = 1 + x. I t i s easy to verify on the other hand that x (1 + x) = 1 and x r-- (1 + x) == 0. We have thus established not only the existence but also the uniqueness of the • complement of x: it is 1 + x. '-../ (9) The map x r-� 1 + x from A into A is a bijection that reverses the order. Proof This map is even an involution (a bijection that is its own inverse) since, for every x, 1 + ( 1 + x) = x. On the other hand, for any elements x and y, we have (1 + X) ( 1 + y) == 1 +X + y + X y. This element is equal to 1 + x if and only if y + xy = 0, or again xy in this way that 1 + x < 1 + y if and only if y < x. = y. We see • The order relation in a Boolean algebra is compatible with multi­ plication: this means that if the elements a, b, c, and d satisfy a < b and c < d, then a x c < b x d (if a b = a and c x d = c, then a x c b x d = a c). The importantfact to retain is that this order is not compatible with addition: for example, we have 0 < 1, but we do not have 0 + 1 < 1 + 1. Remark 2.30 x x x Here is a property that we will frequently use: Lemma 2.31 xy = 0. For any elements x and y of A, we have x Proof Indeed, x < 1 + y means by definition that x +· xy = x, which is certainly equivalent to xy = 0. < 1 + x (1 + y) y if and only if = x, or again • 2.2.2 Boolean algebras as ordered sets In fact, properties ( 1 ), (2), (3), (7), and (8) from Theorem 2.29 characterize Boolean algebras, as the following theorem shows; it also provides us with a second method for defining Boolean algebras. Let ( A , <) be an ordered set with the following properties: (a) there is a least element (denoted by 0) and a greatest element (denoted by 1); Theorem 2.32 76 BOOLEAN ALGEBRAS (b) any two elements x and y have a least upper bound (denoted by x '-" y) and a greatest lower bound (denoted by x y ); (c) each of the operations '-" and is distributive over the other; (d) for every element x in A, there is at least one element x' in A such that x '-" x' 1 and x x' 0. Then A can be given the structure of a Boolean algebra ( A , +, x , 0, 1 ) in such a way that the given order < on A will coincide with the order that is associated with its Boolean algebra structure (i.e. we will have x < y if and only ifxy y). r-. r-. r-. = == = The proof will be given in several stages. • Preliminary remarks: An ordered set that has properties (a) and (b) of the theorem is called a lattice. If it also has property (c), it is called a distribu­ tive lattice. If it is properties (a), (b), and (d) that are satisfied, we speak of a complemented lattice, where the complement of an element x is the unique element x' for which x '-" x' = 1 and x x' = 0. Uniqueness is easy to prove: r-. Proof Suppose that x' and x" are each complements of x and consider the element y = (x r-. x') '-" x". On one hand, y is equal to 0 x", and hence to x". On the other hand, distributivity leads us to '-" y = (x '-" x" ) r-. (x ' '-" x") = 1 r-. (x' '-" x'') = x' '-" x". So we have x" = x' '-" x", which means x' < x " . By interchanging the roles of x' and x" in this argument, we naturally obtain x" < x', and, in the end, x' = x" . • The complernent of the element x will be denoted by x c . We obviously have 1c � 0 and oc � 1. Observe that as a consequence of the uniqueness of the com­ plement, the map x � x c from A into A is a bijection that is equal to its own inverse (for every x, (xc)c = x). Note i n addition that, as we have already observed, when hypotheses (a), (b), (c), and (d) are satisfied, so too are properties (4), (5), and (6) from Theorem 2.29. • We will now establish what are generally known as de Morgan's laws: Lemma 2.33 For any elements x and y of A, (x y)c (x '-" y)c r-. = = xc xc '-" r-. yc Yc . and Proof The second law follows from the first by replacing yc and then using the properties of complementation. x with xc and y with 77 DEFINITION OF BOOLEAN ALGEBRA To prove the first law, we show that (x c '--' y c ) '--' (x ,....__ y) = 1 and that (xc y c ) ,....__ (x " y) = 0: to do this, we use the distributivity of the operations '--' and ,....__ as wel1 as their associativity and commutativity: '-/ (xc '--' yc) '--' (x ,....__ y) = (xc '--' Yc '--' x) ,....__ (x c '--' Yc '--' y) = (1 yC ) �---. ( XC 1) = 1 � 1 = 1; (xc '--' y c ) � (x ,....__ y) = (xc �"' x " y ) "" ( yc " x " y ) '--' '--' · = (0 " y) '--' (0 ,_.._ x ) = 0 '--' 0 = 0. • • De Morgan's laws generalize immediately (by induction) as follows: Lemma 2.34 • For any integer k > 1 and elements X t , x2, . . . , Xk from A, We will now define an addition + and a multiplication x on the set A : for all x and y, we set y = X y and x + y = (x " yc ) "" ( xc X X �--. J"', y) . We can obtain another expression for x + y by using the fact that '--' distributes over r'\: x -+- y = (x '--' x c ) (x '--' y) " (yc '--' x c ) " (yc '--' y ) = 1 ,....__ (x '--' y) " (xc '--' yc) 1, hence x + y = (x '--' y) ,....__ (x c '--' y c ) . /, �---. We will now prove that ( A , +, x , 0, 1 ) is a Boolean algebra. Proof 2 = x' is immediate (x �---. x = x ); • The property 'for all x , x • ( A , +, 0) is a commutative group: * commutativity follows immediately from that of �---. and * 0 is a n identity element for addition: for all x i n A , '--' . 78 BOOLEAN ALGEBRAS * every element x of A has an inverse: namely, itself: * Addition is associative: if x, (x + y) + z == ([x + y] " zc) '-J y, and z are elements of A, we have ([x + y ] c " z) (using the definition of +) == ([(x " yc) '-J (xc " y)] "' z c) ( [ x + y ] c " z) '-J (using the definition of +) == ([ (x " yc) '--' (using ( * )) == ([(x " yc) '--' (xc " Y)] "' zc) (xc ,_ y)] " zc) '--' '--' ([ (x '--' Y) " (xc ([(x '--' '-J yc) ] c " z) '--' yc) c ] " z) y)c '--' (xc (by de Morgan's laws) == ([ (x " yc) '--' (xc "' y)] " z c) � ([ (xc " yc) � (x "' y)] " z) (by de Morgan�s laws) == [ (x " yc " zc) {xc " Y " zc)] (x " y " z)] '--' '--' [ {xc " Yc " z) '--' ( "' distributes over '-._/ ). At last, using the associativity of '--', we obtain The commutativity of '--' and " implies that all permutations on x , y, and z produce this same result. In particular, (x + y) + z == ( y + z) + x, but since the addition operation is commutative, we also have (x + y) + z == x + (y + z). • • The multiplication x is associative and has 1 as a n identity element: these are obvious properties of the operation ". Multiplication distributes over addition: t o prove this, we again invoke the asso­ ciativity and commutativity of .__, and "', the distributivity of " over \..../, together with de Morgan's laws. This time we will omit the justifications of each step in the calculation; the reader will have no difficulty supplying them. 79 ATOMS I N A BOOLEAN ALGEBRA x, z A. xy + xz (x '"' y) (x '"' z) [(x y) '"' (x '"' z)c] [ (x '"' (x )] [(x (x c '"" zc)] '"" [ (xc c) '"' (x '"' z)] [ (x "xc) (x '"' y '"' zc)] '"" [ (xc '"' x '"' z) '"" (yc '"' x '"' z )] (x '"' zc) (x yc " z) x [ ( '"' zc ) ( c '"' z) ] x '"' [y + z] x(y z). (A, +, x, 0� 1) Let y, and be elements of = + = � = = = = = We have '"' y) '"' '"' y '"' = '-/ '-/ y '"' � � y '"' y)c � '"' z y '"' y + This completes the proof that is a Boolean algebra. • Let << denote the order associated with this structure. For any elements x and of x << y if and only if = or again, = but this last equality means precisely that is less than or equal to y for the order < given initially on It follows that these two orders coincide. Therefore, a Boolean algebra is, optionally, a ring in which every element is equal to its square, or an ordered set which has the structure of a complemented, distributive lattice. Without making this a strict rule, we will tend to adopt the second point of view in the rest of the course. For the case given i n Example 2.25 of the set of subsets of a given set, this point of view is more natural than the first. The order relation is the inclusion relation. The operations '-./ and '"' are, respectively, union and intersection. The complement of an element is its set-theoretic complement (see Exercise 2). In what follows, regardless of the point of view adopted, we will allow ourselves to use, simultaneously, the order relation <, multiplication and addition, and the operations '"" and '"' y A, A. x xy x, x --. y x, · 2.3 Atoms in a Boolean algebra An element A in a Boolean algebra (A, '"', 0, 1) is called an {fand only {fit is non-zero and has no non-zero strict lower bound. a a =/= 0 A, b � a, b = a o rb = 0. Definition 2.35 <, '"" , atom In other words, is an atom if and only if if then either and, for every element b in Example 2.36 In the Boolean algebra fP (E) of subsets of the set are the singletons (i.e. subsets containing a single element). E, the atoms 80 BOOLEAN ALGEBRAS Example 2.37 There are Boolean algebras without atoms: this is the situation for the Boolean algebra FI "-./ of equivalence classes of formulas of propositional calculus when the set P of propositional variables is infinite (see Example 2.26). Proof The order relation In this Boolean algebra is the following (Exercise 1): i f F and G are formulas, then ci(F) < cl( G) if and only if the formula (F ==> G) is a tautology. To prove that there are no atoms in FI we will show that every non-zero element has a strict lower bound other than 0. So consider a formula F such that cl(F) =I= 0, i.e. such that -, F is not a tautology, or equivalently that there is at least one assignment of truth values to P that satisfies F. Choose such a distribution and denote it by 8. Also choose a propositional variable X that does not occur in the formula F. This is possible because P is infinite. Let G denote the formula (F 1\ X ) . We obviously have �-* ( ( F 1\ X) ==> F), hence ci(G) < c l(F) . The assignment of truth values A defined by "-./' for all Y E P, A(Y) = { 8 (Y) if f ::/= X 1 if f = X satisfies F (since X does not occur in F) and satisfi.es X, so it satisfies G. It follows that cl( G) =I= 0. On the other hand, the assignment of truth values �vt defined by for all Y E P, J,L ( Y ) = {� (Y) if Y ::/= X if f = X satisfi.es F (for the same reason that A does) but does not satisfy G, so it does not satisfy the formula (F ==> G). So we do not have ci(F) < cl (G), which shows that cl( G) is a strict lower bound for ci(F); so it is a strict, non-zero lower • bound. Definition 2.38 A Boolean algebra is atomic ifand only {fevery non-zero element has at least one atom below it. This is the situation, for example, with the Boolean algebra of all subsets of a given set (every non-empty set contains at least one singleton). Theorem 2.39 Every finite Boolean algebra is atomic. Proof Let ( A , < , , ""', 0, 1) be a finite Boolean algebra and let x be a non-zero element of A . Denote by m (x) the set of non-zero strict lower bounds of x in A . I f m(x) i s empty, then x is a n atom. I f m (x) i s not empty, then because i t is finite, at least one of its elements is minimal in the ordering <, i.e. no element of m (x) '-" 8I H 0 M 0 M 0 R P H I S M S, I S 0 M 0 R P H I S M S, S U B A L G E B R A S is strictly below it. It i s easy to see that such a minimal element i s an atom o f A that is below x . • Let (A, +, x , 0, 1 } be a Boolean algebra (finite or not). Then for eve1y non-zero element a ofA andfor every integer k > 2, thefollowing properties are equivalent: Theorem 2.40 (I) a is an atom; (2) for every element x in A, we have a < x or a < 1 + x ; ( 3 ) for all elements X I , x2 , . . . , x k in A, �fa < X I '-" x 2 '-../ · · · o r a < x2 or . . . a < xk. '-../ Xh then a < X J Proof First observe that by virtue of Lemma 2.3 1 and the definition of the order <, (2) is equivalent to (2') for every element x in A, we have ax = a or ax = 0. Now let us prove the theorem. Let a be a non-zero element of equal to 2. • • A ( I ) :::::} (2' ): for every element x in atom, ax = a or ax = 0. and k a natural number greater than or A we have ax < a, hence, since is an :::::} (3): assume (2) and choose elements X I , x2, . . . , Xk in A such that a :< XJ '-J x2 '-" · · · '-../ Xk. If none of a < Xt , a < x2, . . . , a < Xk is true, then we conclude, from (2), that a < 1 +x t , and a < 1 +x2, and . . . and a < 1 +xk; so a wouldbe a common lower bound for 1 +x t , 1 +x2, . . . , 1 +xk, andhence would Xk ) be less than or equal to their greatest lower bound 1 + (x 1 '--' x2 · ·· (de Morgan). The element a would then be simultaneously less than or equal to both x 1 '-J x2 '-" · · · '-J Xk and its complement, which is impossible since a is non-zero. So (3) is proved. (2) '-/ • a :::::} ( 1 ) : assume (3) and let "'--' be a lower bound for a. It is obvious that a < b '-J (1 + b) = 1. By taking Xt = b and x2 = x3 = · · · = Xk = 1 + b in (3), we deduce that a < b or a < 1 + b. In the first case, we obtain b = a and in the second case, b ::::: ab ::::: 0 (Lemma 2.3 1 ). We have thereby proved that a • is an atom. (3) b 2.4 Homomorphisms, isomorphisms, subalgebras 2.4.1 Homomorphisms and isomorphisms We will generally refer to a homomorphism of rings with a unit (i.e. a map that preserves both addition and multiplication as well as the identity elements of these operations) as a homomorphism of Boolean algebras. We will give definitions, examples, counterexamples, and characterizations in terms of ordered sets. 82 B O O L E A N ALGE B R AS Let A = (A, +, x , 0, 1) and A' = (A', +, x , 0, 1) be Boolean algebras and h be a map from A into A'. We say that h is a homomorphism of Boolean algebras from A into A' if and only iffor all elements x and y in A, we have Definition 2.41 h(x + y) = h(x) + h (y); h(x x y) = h (x) x h(y); h(l) 1. = The condition h (0) = 0 is not part of the definition since it can be deduced immediately/rom the first condition (just set x = y = 0). Remark 2.42 The situation is different for the multiplicative identity element: the third relation is not a consequence of the second, as the following example shows; take A = f)J (N) and A' = f)J (Z) with their natural Boolean algebra structures and take h to be the identity map from A into A (which we can consider as a map from A into A' since A c A' ); it is very easy to verify that the first two relations above are satisfied, but the third is not since the identity element for multiplication in A is N while in A' it is Z. The reader will have observed that we committed an abuse of language by giving the same names to the operations (as well as to their identity elements) in A and A'. The notion of homomorphism defined here is nothing more than the general notion of homomorphism/or rings with unit, specialized to the case of Boolean rings. (We should note in passing that there can exist a homomorphism of rings with unit between a Boolean algebra and a ring with unit that is not a Boolean algebras.) Properties that hold for arbitrary homomorphisms of rings with unit continue to hold, obviously, for Boolean algebras: for example, the composition o.f two homomorphisms ofBoolean algebras is a homomorphism ofBoolean algebras. The same line ofthought shows that we could actually dispense with Corollary 2.49 below. Lemma 2.44 Let A = (A, <, 0, 1 ) and A' = (A ' , <, 0, 1 ) be two Boolean alge­ bras and h be a homomorphism ofBoolean algebrasfrom A into A'. Then we have (continuing with the earlier notations and with the abuse of language mentioned in Remark 2.42): For all elements x and y of A, Remark 2.43 h (x " y) = h (x) " h(y); h (x c ) = (h(x))c ; h (x y) h (x) h (y); {fx < y, then h (x) < h(y). _, = '--/ H 0 M 0 M 0 R P H I S M S, I S 0 M 0 R P H I S M S, S U B A L G E B R A S 83 Proof Because the operations x and "' are identical, the first relation is already a consequence of the definition of homomorphism. The second can be rewritten + which is an immediate consequence of as and the = = additivity of The third relation follows from the first two by de Morgan's laws. Finally, the last relation can be rewritten: if = then = and • the latter is true since = h(1) 1 h(1 -,- x) 1 h(x), h. xy y, h(x)h(y) h(x); h (xy) h (x)h(y ). Let (A, <, 1} and (A' <, 1} be two Boolean algebras and h be a mapfrom A into A'. For h to be a homomorphism ofBoolean algebras, it is necessa1y and sufficientthatfor all elements x andy in A, we have h(x "' y) h(x) "' h(y), h (xc) (h(x))c. x A. h(xy) h(x "' y) h(x) "' h(y) h(x)h(y), h(x y) h ((x " yc ) '--' (xc "' y )) h (((x "' yc )c "' (xc "' y) c) c) (h ((x "' yc)c "' (xc "' y)c))c =(h ((x "' y)c )c "' h ((xc "' y)c ))c (( h (x "' yc ))c "' (h (xc "' y))c ) c h (x "' yc) '--' h (xc "' y) (h(x) "' h{yc )) '--' (h (xc) "' h(y)) (h(x) "' (h(y))c) '-'- ((h(x))c "' h(y)) h(x) h(y). h(O) Theorem 2.45 A = 0, A' = 0, = = Proof According to the lemma, the condition is necessary. Suppose it is satisfied and let and y be elements of We then have: = = + == = = = = = = = = It follows that + = 0 (see Remark 2.42) and hence that h It is clear that in the statement ofthe preceding theorem, we could replace the operation "' by the operation '--' everywhere. An is a homomorphism of Boolean algebras that is bijective. Let (A, <, 1} and (A' <, 1} be two Boolean algebras and h be a surjective mapfrom A onto A'. For h to be an isomorphism ofBoolean algebras, it is necessa1y and sufficient that for all elements x andy of A, x < y �{and only �f h(x) < h(y). x A. x < y, h(x) < h(y). h(x) < h(y), This shows that • is a homomorphism. Remark 2.46 Definition 2.47 isomorphism of Boolean algebras Theorem 2.48 A = 0, A' = 0, (*) Proof First let us suppose that h is an isomorphism and let of If then by Lemma 2.44, If and y be elements then by 84 B OO L E A N A L G E B R A S = = ( y ). the definition of < and because h is a homomorphism, But since is injective, this requires = y, which is to say, < y . So (*) is satisfied. To prove the inverse, suppose (*) holds and that u and v are two elements of A such that (u ) = We have h(u) < and < h (u), thus, by (*), u < v, and v < u , and so u = v. Thus, h is injective. Next, let and y be arbitrary elements of A. Set = (y ) . Since is a bijection, there is a unique element z in A such that We have < and < hence, using = (*), z < and z < y, and so z < y < y, y. But since ,.,. y < and we have, always using (*), that ,.,. y) < and ,.,. y ) < which implies h h(x) h(x)h(y) h x x x x h h(v). h(v) h(v) x t h (x) ,.,. h h t h(z). h(z) h(x) h(z) h(y), x, x ,.,. x x x h(x h(x) h(x h(y), h(x) ,.,. h(y) h(z). h(x x ,.,. y x ,.,. h(x ,.,. y) h(x) ,.,. h(y). ,.,. ,.,. y ) < Using ( *) once more, we obtain which proves = < z, and putting all this together, z = y, = When we replace ,.,. by \,.J and < by > in the previous argument, we obtain h (x ..___,. y) = h (x) h (y). \,.J Let u be an arbitrary element of A' and let t be its unique preimage i n A under I n A, we have 0 < and < 1. lt follows, using (*), that, in A', < u , and u < This shows that and are, respectively, the least and greatest elements of A', or in other words, that = 1. == 0 and So for every element in A, we have h. t t h(1). h(O) x h(xc) ,.,. h(x) h(xc) h(x) h(xc ) \,.J Therefore = = h(1) h(O) h(1) h (xc ,.,. x) h(O) h (x c ---- x) h(l) h(x), is the complement o f = = 0 = = 1. h(O) and o r i n other words, h h (x h (x) ......., h (y) h The composition of two isomorphisms of Boolean algebras, as well as the inverse ofan isomorphism of Boolean algebras, are isomorphisms of Boolean algebras. We conclude, using Theorem 2.45, that algebras. is a homomorphism of Boolean Notice that the relation \,.J y) = Theorem 2.45; rather, it was useful in proving that of taking complements. Corollary 2.49 • is not required to apply commutes with the operation H 0 M 0 M 0 R P H I S M S. I S 0 M 0 R P H I S M S. S U B A L G E B R A S 85 Proof Let A = ( A , + , x , 0, 1 } , B = (B, +, x , 0, 1}, and C = (C , +, x , 0, 1 } b e Boolean algebras, let ¢ b e a n isomorphism of Boolean algebras from A onto B and 1jl an isomorphism of Boolean algebras from B onto C. The mappings ¢ - l and 1/1 o ¢ are obviously surjective. For all elements u and v of B, ¢- 1 (u) < ¢ - 1 (v) is equivalent to ¢ (¢ - 1 (u)) < ¢ (¢- 1 (v)), i.e. to u < v. On the other hand, for all elements x and y of A , we have x < y if and only if </J (x) < </J ( y ), and ¢ (x ) < ¢ (y) if and only if 1jl(¢(x)) < 'IJ(¢(y)). With the preceding theorem, we conclude that ¢ - l and 1jl o ¢ are isomorphisms of Boolean algebras, from B onto • A and from A onto C respectively. Everyfinite Boolean algebra is isomorphic to the Boolean algebra of subsets of some set. Proof Let A ( A , +, x , 0, 1 } be a finite Boolean algebra and let E be the set of its atoms. Note that E is not empty since there is at least one atom that is less than or equal to the non-zero element 1 (Theorem 2.39). We will show that A is isomorphic to the algebra of subsets of E. lo d o this, consider the map h from A into f>J (E) which, with each element x Theorem 2.50 == of A , associates the set of atoms that are below x : for each x E A , h (x) = {a E E : a < x }. h is surjective: indeed, we first o f all have h (0) = 0 (there i s n o atom below 0); as well, let X = {a1 , a2, . . . , ak } be a non-empty subset of E and set M x = a 1 '--" a2 · · · '--" ak; we claim h (Mx) = X : the inclusion X c h (Mx) follows immediately form the definition of h (every element of X is an atom which is below Mx ) ; the reverse inclusion is shown using Theorem 2.40: if a is an · · · \,.../ ak , element of h (Mx ) , i.e. an atom which is below Mx = a1 '--" a2 then we have a < a; for at least one index i (this is clear if k = 1 and this is clause (3) of the theorem if k > 2), but since a and a; are atoms, this entails a = a;, and so a E X . For all elements x and y of A , if x < y, then h (x) < h (y ) : indeed, if x < y, every atom that is below x i s an atom that i s below y. For all elements x and y of A, if h(x) c h (y), then x < y: indeed, if x is not less that or equal to y, then x (l + y) # 0 (Lemma 2.31 ). As A is finite, it is atomic (Theorem 2.39) so we can find an atom a E E such that a < x ( 1 + y ) . The atom a is thus below both x and 1 + y; i t cannot be below y as well since it is non-zero. So we have a E h(x) and a ¢: h(y), which shows that h (x) is not included in h (y). We may now conclude, thanks to Theorem 2.48, that h is an isomorphism of • Boolean algebras from A onto f>J (E). Corollary 2.51 The cardinality of any finite Boolean algebra is a power of 2. Proof If the finite set E has cardinality n, then the set of its subsets, f>J (E), has • '--" '--" • • cardinality 211 • • 86 BOOLEAN ALGEBRAS 2.4.2 Boolean subalgebras Let A == (A , +, 1) be a Boolean algebra. A subset B of A constitutes a Boolean subalgebra of A if and only if B contains the elements 0 and 1 and is closed under the operations + and (in other words, 0 E B, 1 E B, and ifx E B and y E B, then x y E B and xy E B). A Boolean subalgebra of A is thus a subring of A that contains the element 1. Definition 2.52 x, 0, x 4- This distinction is essential: i n a ring with unit, a subring can itself be a ring with unit without containing the unit element of the full ring: in this case, the role of the identity element for multiplication is played by some other element. Let us reexamine the ring (p (Z), � ' n, 0, Z): p (N) is a subset that is closed under the operations � and n and it contains 0 ; it is therefore a subring of OJ (Z). Obviously, Z ¢:. p (N). Nonetheless, N is the identity element for the ring p (N). Thus the Boolean ring p (N) is a ring with unit and is a subring of p (Z), but is not a substructure of p (Z) as a ring with unit: it is therefore not a Boolean subalgebra of p (Z). Let A == (A, + , 0, 1) be a Boolean algebra and let B be a subset of A. For B to be a Boolean subalgebra of A, it is necessary and sufficient thatthere exists a Boolean algebra A' == (A ' , +', x ' , 0' , 1') anda homomorphism of Boolean algebras, h, from A' into A such that the image of the map h is the subset B. Theorem 2.53 x, Proof • necessary: take A' == B, +' == +, x ' == x , 0 == 0, 1' == 1, and h == the identity map from B into A. It is immediate to verify that h is a homomorphism of Boolean algebras whose image is B. • sufficient: choose A' and h as indicated. We have h (0') == 0 , hence 0 E B, and h(l ' ) == 1 , so 1 E B. Moreover, if x and y are elements of B, then we can ' choose elements x' and y i n A ' such that x == h (x ' ) and y == h(y ' ). We then have x + y == h (x ' ) + h (y ') == h (x' + y' ) , hence x + y E lm(h) == B; xy == h (x ' )h(y' ) == h (x ' y' ), hence xy E lm(h) == B. and • So B is a Boolean subalgebra of A. In a Boolean algebra A == (A, +, x , 0, 1),for a subset B to be a Boolean subalgebra, it is necessary and sufficient that B contain 0 and be closed under the operations x � xc and (x, y) x y. Theorem 2.54 H ,... Proof c • necessary: since x == 1 + x and x y == x y, and since and be closed under + and x , the result is immediate. ,... B must contain 0 and 1 H 0 M 0 M 0 R P H I S M S, I S 0 M 0 R P H I S M S, S U B A L G E B R A S • 87 sufficient: for every x and y in A we have x ..._, y == (xc "' y c ) c . So the closure of B under complementation and "' guarantees its closure under ..._, . Moreover, 1 c = 0 must belong to B. Since the operations + and x can be defined exclusively in terms of "', '--', and complementation, we conclude that B is closed under + • and x and that (B, +, x , 0, 1 ) is a Boolean subalgebra of A. Example 2.55 Let E be an infinite set, let A == g;> (£), the set of all its subsets, and let B be the subset of A consisting of those subsets of E that are finite or whose complement is finite. We will show, using the previous theorem, that B is a Boolean subalgebra of the Boolean algebra of subsets of E. Proof A subset of E whose complement is finite will be called cofinite. The empty set, which is a finite subset of E, belongs to B. It is clear that B is closed under complementation: the complement (in this instance, the set-theoretic complement) of a fi nite subset of E is a cofinite subset and the complement of a cofinite set is finite. Also, B is closed under "' (in this instance, set-theoretic intersection): indeed, the intersection of a fi nite subset of E with any subset of E is a finite subset of E; as for the intersection o f two cofinite subsets o f E, this too i s a cofinite subset of E: to see this, suppose that U c E and V c E are cofinite; this means that E - U and E - V are finite and hence, so is their union ( E - U) U (£ - V) which is • simply (de Morgan) E - (U n V ) ; it follows that U n V is cofinite. Example 2.56 Here is an example that will be of use in Section 2.6. Let X be a topological space and let B(X) be the subset of g;> ( X ) consisting of subsets of X that are both open and closed in the topology on X (recall that we speak of clopen sets in this context). This set B(X) is a Boolean subalgebra of the Boolean algebra of subsets of X. Proof First of all, the empty set (0) and the whole space X (1) itself are naturally clopen sets. Next, the complement of a clopen set is clopen and the intersection of two clopen sets is clopen. So Theorem 2.54 allows us, here as well, to arrive at the expected conclusion. • lt can happen that the Boolean algebra B (X) under consideration here reduces to {0, 1 l (this is the case, for example, when X is the space IR with its usual topology: 0 and IR are the only subsets that are both open and closed); B(X) can also coincide with g;> (X) (when thetopology on X is the discrete topology (thetopology in which all subsets are open) and, obviously, only is this case). Let us now give two examples of homomorphisms of Boolean algebras. of equivalence classes of Example 2.57 Consider the Boolean algebra FI logically equivalent formulas of the propositional calculus built from a set of variables P (see Examples 2.26). Choose an assignment 8 of truth values on P and as usual let 8 denote the extension of 8 to the set F of all formulas. We can then define a map hE> from FI into {0, 1 } by setting, for every formula F, rv rv ho ( ci(F)) = 8 (F). 88 BOOLEAN ALGEBRAS This definition is legitimate since 8 (F) assumes the same value on all formulas in a given equivalence class. This map, h 0 , is a homomorphism of Boolean algebras from F ;� into {0, 1 } . By virtue o f Theorem 2.45 and the definition o f the operations for the Boolean algebra F;�, it suffices to establish that for all formulas F and G in F, we have h0 (ci(F 1\ G)) = h0 (ci(F))h0 (ci(G)) and h8 (ci(...., F )) = l - htS ( CI(F) ) . Now these relations are equivalent to - 8 (F - G) 1\ == - 8 (F) 8 (G) - 8 (-,F) = 1 and - 8 (F), which are true by definition of 8 . We will prove (Exercise 1 3) that all Boolean algebra homomorphisms from FI into {0, 1 } are obtained in this manner. "' Example 2.58 Let A ( A , +, x , 0, 1 ) be a Boolean algebra and let a be an atom in this algebra (we are assuming that one exists). Let us define a map h. from A into {0, 1 } by = h. (x ) = { 1 <x if x E A and a - 0 if x E A and a < 1 + x (these two cases are mutually exclusive since a is different from 0, and there are no other cases since a is an atom: see Theorem 2.40). We claim that h. is a homomorphism of Boolean algebras from A into {0, 1 } . Proof To prove this, let u s use Theorem 2.45: let x and y be two elements of A. We have h. (x "' y ) = 1 if and only if a < x ,.., y , but this is equivalent, by the definition of greatest lower bound, to a < x and a < y , hence to h. (x ) = 1 and h. ( y ) = 1, which is necessary and sufficient to have h. (x) "' h. ( y ) = 1. It follows that h a (X "' y ) == h a (X ) "' ha ( y ) . Also, ha (xc) = 1 if and only if a < xc, i.e. a < 1 + x, which is equivalent to h. (x) = 0. Since h. only assumes the values 0 or 1, this means that • 2.5 Ideals and filters 2.5.1 Properties of ideals As mentioned in the reminders, 'ideal' means 'proper ideal'. 89 IDEALS A N D FILTERS Let A = (A, < , 0, 1 ) be a Boolean algebra and 1 a subset of A. For I to be an ideal, it is necessary and st�:fficient that thefollowing three conditions be satisfied: Theorem 2.59 and 1 ¢ l; (ii) for all elements x and y of I, x '--' y E 1; (iii) for all x E 1 andfor all y E A, if y < x, then y E /. Proof Suppose first that I is an ideal. Then in particular, it is a subgroup of the group (A, +, 0), so 0 E 1 . If 1 were i n I, then 1 would be the entire ring and (i) 0 E l we have excluded this case; so (i) is verified. If x and y are in /, then so is their product xy and, consequently, the sum x + y + xy = x y, which proves (ii). Finally, let us verify (iii): if x E I and y E A, then xy E I and if y < x as well, then x y = y and, consequently, y E I. Conversely, suppose that (i), (ii), and (iii) are satisfied. We must show that I is y E l by (ii), but since x + y < x � y an ideal in A. If x E l and y E / , then x (this is trivial to check) and since x + y = x y (we are in a Boolean algebra), we conclude using (iii) that x y E /. Since 0 E 1 , we have all we need for ( / , +, 0) to be a subgroup of (A, +, 0). Moreover, if x E l and y E A, then since xy < x, we may conclude from (iii) that xy E / . The set I is therefore an ideal in A (1 =1= A • since 1 ¢ /). '--' '--' -- - Corollary 2.60 If I is an ideal in a Boolean algebra ( A, element x in A that can satisfy both x E I and 1 + x E I. +, x, 0, 1 ) , there is no Proof If the ideal l contains both x and 1 + x, it would also contain the element x (1 + x) = 1 (invoke property (ii) of the theorem). But this is not possible since 1 ¢ l (property (i)). • ....__, Let A = ( A , +, 0, 1 ) be a Boolean ring and let 1 be an ideal in A. For any integer k > 1 and any elements X I , x2, . . . , Xk in /, the least upper bound XI x2 · · · X k belongs to I. Corollary 2.61 '--' x, '--' '--' Proof This is a generalization of property (ii) of the theorem; its proof is imme­ diate by induction on the integer k (the case k = 1 needs no argument). • Example 2.62 ( 1 ) If E is an infinite set, the set f>Jf ( E ) of finite subsets of E is an ideal in the Boolean algebra f>J (E). It is easy to verify conditions (i), (ii), and (iii) of the theorem: 0 is a finite subset of E while E itself is not one, the union of two finite subsets of E is a finite subset of E, and any subset of a finite subset of E is a finite subset of E. (2) Let A = (A, +, x , 0, 1) b e a Boolean algebra and let a be an element of A that is not equal to 1. The set Ia = {x E A : x < a } is an ideal in A. Here too, the verification of properties (i), (ii), and (iii) is immediate: we have 0 < a 90 BOOLEAN ALGEBRAS and, since a is distinct from 1, we do not have 1 < a ; if x < a and y < a, then x '---' y < a; finally, if x < a and y < x , then y < a. Ia is called the principal ideal generated by a. This agrees with the usual definition of a principal ideal in an arbitrary commutative ring since, in a Boolean ring, the set of elements below a given element is also the set of its multiples. (3) In any Boolean algebra, {0} is obviously an ideal. For any Boolean ring A = (A, +, 0, 1) andfor any ideal I in A, the quotient ring A/ I is a Boolean ring. Proof For each element x in A , let x denote the equivalence class of x modulo I . We already know that AII is a ring with unit. S o it i s sufficient to show that every Lemma 2.63 x, element is an idempotent for multiplication. But this is an immediate consequence of the definition of multiplication in A/ I and of the fact that A is a Boolean algebra: if x E A, x 2 = x 2 = x. Recall that in an arbitrary commutative ring with unit, the ideals are precisely the kernels of homomorphisms of rings with unit defined on the ring. (See Remark 2.43.) The theorem that follows merely takes up this result for Boolean rings, with this added precision: it shows that the ideals in a Boolean ring are precisely the kernels of homomorphisms of Boolean algebras defined on the ring. • Let A = (A, +, , 0, 1 ) be a Boolean ring and let I be a subset of A. The following properties are equivalent: ( 1 ) I is an ideal in A; (2) there exists a homomorphism of Boolean algebras, h, defined on A whose kernel is I (in other words), Theorem 2.64 x I = h - 1 [{0}] = {x E A : h (x) = 0}; (3) there exists a homomorphism of commutative rings with unit defined on A whose kernel is I. Proof The equivalence of ( I ) and (3) is the result in the preceding reminder; (2) =} (3) is obvious. We will nonetheless prove (3) =} ( 1 ) and then ( 1 ) =} (2), which is, as observed above, more precise than ( 1 ) =} (3). • (3) =} ( 1): suppose there exists a homomorphism h from A into a ring with unit 1 B = (B, +, x , 0, 1) such that I = h - [{0}] = {x E A : h(x ) = 0}. Let us verify that conditions (i), (ii), and (iii) from Theorem 2.59 are satisfied. We have h(O) = 0 and h(1) = then h(x) = 0 and h(y) = 0, so h (x '---' y) = 1, hence 0 E I and 1 rJ_ I. If x E1 and y h (x + y + xy) = h (x) + h (y) + h(x)h (y) = 0 E /, 91 I D E A LS A N D FILTERS and s o x y E I . Finally, ifx E l , y E A , and y < x , then h(x) = O and xy = y, hence h(y) = h (x)h(y) = 0, i.e. y E I. Thus, I is a n ideal o f A. (Of course, it would have made no sense to use an order relation or the '-../ and .-. operations in B). '---" • ( 1 ) ===> (2): suppose that I is an ideal in A and consider the map h from A into A/ I which, with each element x, associates its equivalence class, x , modulo J (h is what is generally known as the canonical surjection of A onto A//). h is a homomorphism of Boolean algebras (the canonical homomorphism of A onto A / 1): to see this, we invoke Theorem 2.45; if x E A and y E A, then h (x y) = h (xy) = xy = :X y = h (x ) h (y) = h(x) .---. h (y) h (x c ) = h(1 + x) = 1 + x == 1 + x = 1 + h (x) = (h(x))c . x ,� Also, it is clear that I = - 0 = {x E x - A : h(x) = 0 } : I is the kernel of h. and • 2.5.2 Maximal ideals Here is a collection of ways to characterize maximal ideals in a Boolean algebra: For evety Boolean ring A = (A, +, 0, 1), for eve1y ideal I in A, andfor every integer k > 2, the following properties are equivalent: Theorem 2.65 x, ( I ) I is a maximal ideal; (2) A/ I is isomorphic the Boolean algebra {0, l}; (3) I is the kernel of a homomorphism of A into {0, 1}; (4) for every element x in A, x E I or l + x E I; (5) for all elements x and y of A, if xy E I, then x E I or y E I; (6) for all elements x r , xz, . . . , X k in A, {fxr xz · · · Xk E I, then xr or · · · or Xk E I. 10 E I or xz E I Proof • ( 1 ) ===> (2): In Section 1 , we recalled that if the ideal I is maximal, then the quotient ring A/ I is a field. But we also observed (Remark 2.28) that the only Boolean ring that is a field is {0, 1}. So the result follows using Lemma 2.63. • (2) ===> (3): It suffices to note that I i s always the kernel of the canonical homo­ morphism h from A into A/ I. If there is an isomorphism ¢ from A/ I onto {0, 1}, then I will obviously be the kernel of the homomorphism ¢ o h from A into {0, 1}. • (3) ===> (4): Consider a homomorphism h from A into { 0 , 1} whose kernel is I and let x be an arbitrary element of A . We have h (x) = 0 or h (x) = 1. In the first case, x E I ; in the second case we have 1 + h (x) = 0, so h(1 + x) == 0 and 1 + x E I. 92 • B OO L E A N A L G E B R A S (4) => (5): Let x and y be elements of A such that x ¢. I and y ¢. I. If (4) holds, then 1 + x E I and 1 + y E I, so (1 + x) (1 + y) E I (property (ii) of Theorem 2.59). But '-.../ (1 + x) '-./ (1 + y) = 1 + (x r-- y) = 1 + xy, so, by Corollary 2.60 xy • • • ¢. I, and so ( 5 ) i s proved. (5) =} ( 1): Suppose that I is not maximal. Let J be an ideal of A that strictly includes I and a be an element of J that does not belong to I. Using Coro­ llary 2.60, 1 + a ¢. J. and so 1 + a ¢. I since I c J. The ideal I contains neither a nor 1 + a, but it does obviously contain the product a(1 + a) = 0. We conclude that (5) is not satisfied. (5) ==> (6): We assume that (5) is satisfied and we argue by induction on the integer k. For k = 2, (6) coincides with (5). Assuming (6) is verified for k, we will prove that it is satisfied for k + I . Let X J , x2, . . . , x�c , Xk+l be elements of A such that X J X2 · · · XkXk+l E I. By (5) we must have either x1x2 · · · Xk E I or Xk+ 1 E I. In the first instance, by the induction hypothesis, we have x1 E I or x2 E I or . . . or Xk E I. We then conclude that we must have Xi E I for at least one index i such that I < i < k + l ; this proves (6) for k + I . (6) => (5): Let x and y be two elements of A such that xy E I . Set Xi = x and = Xk = y. So we have x 1 x2 · · Xk = xy E I. So if (6) is true, x2 = x3 = we must have Xi E I for at least one index i between I and k; so either x E I • or y E 1 and (5) is verified. . . . · In an arbitrary commutative ring, an ideal with property (5)from the preceding theorem is called a prime ideal. What we havejust p1vved is that in a Boolean ring, the prime ideals are precisely the same as the maximal ideals. But there are ringsforwhichthisfails to be true. What is always true is that an ideal is prime �{and only ifthe associated quotient ring is an integral domain (this is easy to prove); we conclude from this as well that a maximal ideal must necessarily be prime (it st�:ffices to consider the corresponding quotient ring). Thus it is the converse ofthis that canfail (for example, in the ring IR[X, Yl a,{polynomials in two variables with real coefficients: the ideal generated by the polynomial X, i.e. the set { X P : P E IR[X, Y ] } is prime but is not maximal since it is strictly included in the ideal generated by the polynomials X and Y, i.e. the set { X P+ Y Q : P E IR [X, Y], Remark 2.66 Q E IR[X, Y)}). In particula1; we should take note ofthe equivalence between prop­ erties ( 1 ) and (3). Observe that if two homomorphisms h and g from a Boolean algebra A = (A, +, 0, 1) into {0, 1 } have the same kernel, I, then they are equal: this is because for any element x in A, either x ¢. I and g (x) = h (x) = 0 or else x ¢. l and g (x) = h(x ) = 1. We may conclude from this that there is a bijection between the set of maximal ideals in a Boolean algebra and the set of homomorphisms ofBoolean algebras from this algebra into {0, 1 } . Remark 2.67 x, 93 IDEALS AND FILTERS 2.5.3 Filters We will now introduce the notion that is dual to that of an ideal on a Boolean algebra: we will define fi lters. Definition 2.68 A filter in a of A such that the set Boolean algebra A = {x E A : x8 E {A, +, x, 0, 1) is a subset F F} is an ideal in A. 0, 1 ) . Let I be the Let F be a filter in a Boolean algebra A = (A , +, ideal {x E A : x c E F } . I is realized as the inverse image of F under the oper- · ation of complementation: x x c . But, as this operation is an involution (se(� parl (9) of Theorem 2.29), I is also the direct image of F under this operation: I == {x E A : 3y(y E F and x = y8 )}. In other words, I is the set of complements of elements of F and F is the set of complements of elements of / . The ideal / i!; called the dual ideal of the filter F. It is easy to see that, given an arbitrary ideal J in A, the set G = {x E A x c E J } is a filter whose dual ideal is precisely J . x, t-----7 : To everyone's surprise, w e will call G the dual filter o f the ideal J . There is thus a bijection between the set of ideals and the set of fi.lters in a Boolean algebra. For filters, we have the dual of Theorem 2.59. Let A = ( A , < , 0, 1) be a Boolean algebra and F a subset of A . For F to b e a .filter, i tis necessary and sufficient that thefollowing three conditions be satisfied: (f) 0 ¢ F and 1 E F; (ff) for all elements x and y of I, x y E F; (ftf) for all x E F andfor all y E A, if y > x, then y E F. Proof Set I = {x E A : x c E F}. If F is a filter, then I is its dual ideal and conditions (i), (ii), and (iii) from Theorem 2.59 are satisfied. So we have 0 E I, hence oc = 1 E F, and 1 ¢ /, hence 1 c = 0 � F, which proves (f). If x E F and y E: F, then X C E / and yC E / , SO XC y C E 1 (by (ii)), and, as X C y8 (x y ) c , we conclude that x y E F and that (ff) is satisfied. Finally, if x E F, y E A, and y > x, then x c E I and yc < x c , so, (by (iii)) y8 E 1 and y E F, hence Theorem 2.69 "' ...__., "' ...__., = = "' (fff). Conversely, in a strictly analogous fashion, (i) follows from (f), (ii) from (ff) and (iii) from (fff). H Let A = ( A , < , 0, 1 ) be a Boolean algebra and F a subset of A. f'or any integer k > 1 and any elements Xt , x2, . . . , Xk in F, the greatest lower bound XI x2 · · · Xk belongs to F. Proof Analogue of Corollary 2.6 1 . H Corollary 2.70 "' "' "' BOOLEAN ALGEBRAS 94 2.5.4 Ultrafilters Definition 2.71 ln a Boolean algebra, an ultrafilter is a maximalfilter, i.e. a filter which is not strictly included in any otherfilteJ: It is clear that, in view of the duality explained above, ultrafilters correspond to maximal ideals. In other words, the dual filter of a maximal ideal is an ultrafilter and the dual ideal of an ultrafilter is a maximal ideal. There is an analogue for filters of Theorem 2.65: For every Boolean ring A = (A, +, 0, 1),for every ideal F in A, andfor every integer k > 2, the following properties are equivalent: Theorem 2.72 x, ( 1 ') F is an ultrafilter; (3') there is a homomorphism h from A into {0 , 1 } such that F = {x E A : h(x) = 1}; for every element x in A , x E F or 1 + x E F; (5') for all elements x and y of A , ifx '-" y E F, then x E F or y E F; (6') for all elements x 1 , x2, . . . , Xk in A, ifXJ x2 './ · · · -.._; Xk E F, then x1 E F or x2 E F or . . . or Xk E F. Proof Given the algebra A, the filter F and the integer k, let I denote the ideal dual to F. It is elementary to verify that properties (1 '), (3'), (4'), (5'), and (6') for the fi lter F are respectively equivalent to properties ( 1 ) , (3), ( 4) (5), and (6) of Theorem 2.65 for the ideal I (we use the correspondence between I and F, de (4') -.._; , • Morgan's laws, etc.) Remark 2.73 The property (4') above, 'or' in property (4) of Theorem 2.65, as well as the one in is in fact an 'exclusive or' (see Corolla1y 2. 60). This means that if F is an ultrafilter in a Boolean algebra (A, +, 0, 1) and (f I is the maximal ideal dual to F, then I and F constitute a partition of A. Thus each of the sets I and F is simultaneously: x, • the complement of the other (viewed as subsets of A), • the set of complements of the elements of the other (in the sense of comple­ mentation in the Boolean algebra under consideration). The second of these properties holds whenever we have an ideal and a filter that are dual to one another, but the first holds only when the ideal and filter in question are maximal. Returning to Remark 2.67, we can now add to it and insist on the factthatforaBooleanalgebra, A, there are canonical one-to-one correspondences among (i) the maximal ideals in A, (ii) the ultrafilters in A and (iii) homomorphisms of Boolean algebrasfrom A into {0, 1}. Remark 2.74 IDEALS A N D FILTERS 95 Examples: To have examples of filters, it obviously suffices to refer to the previ­ ously described examples of ideals (in Subsection 2.5 . 1 ) and to transform them by duality. The reader can, without any difficulty, provide the necessary verifications: (1) If E is an infinite set, the set ofall cofinite subsets of E (see Example 2.55) is a filter in the Boolean algebra (g;y ( E), c, 0, E ) . This filter is called the Frechet filter on E . It is not an ultrafilter since there are subsets of E which are infinite and whose complements are also infinite, so condition (4') of Theorem 2.72. is not satisfied. (2) If a is a non-zero element in a Boolean algebra (A, <, 0, 1), the set Fa = {x E A : x > a} is a filter called the principal filter generated by a. It is the duaJ filter of the ideal generated by 1 + a. (3) { 1} i s the dual filter of the ideal { 0}. Theorem 2.75 Let (A, < , 0, 1 ) be a Boolean algebra and Let a be a non-ze1v element of A. For the principal filter generated by a to be an ultrafiltel; it is necessary and sufficient that a be an atom. The set Proof By virtue of Theorem 2.40 and the definition of the filter Fa , a is an atom if and only if for every element x of A, x E Fa or 1 + x E Fa ; but for this to happen, it is necessary and sufficient that Fa be an ultrafilter ( ( 4' ) ::::} ( 1') from Theorem 2.72). • When the principal filter Fa generated by a non-zero element a of A is an ultrafilter (thus, when a is an atom), we say that this is a trivial ultrafilter. The homomorphism ha with values in {0, 1 } that is associated with it is also called a trivial homomorphism. As it is defined by : ha (x) 1 if x E Fa and ha (x) = 0 i f x rt Fa , and as this i s obviously equivalent to: ha (x) = 1 if a < x and ha (x) = 0 if a < 1 + x, we see that what is involved is precisely the homomorphism studied in Example 2.58. = Let A be a Boolean algebra and Let U be an ultrafilter on A. For U to be trivial, it is necessary and sufficient that it contain at least one atom. Lemma 2.76 Proof If U is trivial, i t is generated by an atom, a, and since a < a, a E U. Conversely, ifU contains an atom, b, i t also contains all elements greater than or equal to b (condition (fff) of Theorem 2.69). It follows that the principal filter F1; generated by b is included in U. But since b is an atom, Fb is maximal and cannot be strictly included in the filter U. Hence U = Fh and U is a trivial ultrafilter. •1 Theorem 2.77 Let E be an infinite set and let U be an ultrafilter in the Boolean algebra g;y (E). ForU to be non-trivial, it is necessary and sufficient that it includes the Frechetfilter on E. Proof The atoms of g;y (E) are the singletons (subsets consisting of a single el­ ement); so they are finite sets. If U includes the Frechet filter, every co finite sub­ set of E belongs to U, hence no finite subset of E can belong to U (U canno1 96 BOOLEAN ALGEBRAS simultaneously contain a subset of E and its complement: see Remark 2.73). In particular, no atom can belong to U. It follows, by the preceding lemma, that U is non-trivial. If U does not include the Frechet filter, we can choose a cofinite subset X of E that does not belong to U, and hence whose complement E - X does belong to U. As E is the identity element for the Boolean algebra f>J (E), E E U; hence X # E. The complement of X in E is thus a non-empty finite subset of £: for example, E - X = {at , a2, . . . , an } (n > 1 ). So we have {ai , a2 , . . . , an } E U, which is to also say: {ai } U {a2} U · · · U {an } = {ad � {a2 } � · · · � {an } E U. If n = 1 , {at } E U. If n > 2, then by property (6' ) of Theorem 2.72, we have {ad E U for at least one index i between I and n. We see that in every case, U contains a singleton, i.e. an atom. The preceding lemma then shows that U is • trivial. Remark: In Exercise 1 6, we will prove a property which includes this theorem as a special case. 2.5.5 Filterbases In a Boolean algebra (A, <, 0, 1), a basisfor a.filter (filterbase) is a subset of A that has the following ptvperty, known as the finite intersection property: every non-emptyfinite subset of B has a non-zero greatest lower bound. In other words, B c A is a filterbase if and only if: for any integer k > 1 and Xk # 0. any elements Xt , x2 , . . . , Xk of B, x1 x2 Lemma 2.79 Let (A, <, 0, 1) be a Boolean algebra and let X be a subset of A. For the existence ofa filter on A that includes X, it is necessary and sufficient that X be a filterbase. Proof If X is included in a filter F, and if x t, x2, . . . , Xk are elements of X, then their greatest lower bound X J Xk belongs to F (Corollary 2.70), and x2 as 0 � F, this greatest lower bound is non-zero; thus X is a filterbase. Now suppose that X is a filterbase. If X = 0, { 1 } is a filter on A that includes X. I f X is not empty, we set Definition 2.78 r-. r-. r-. • • • r-. r-. • • • r-. • • Fx = {x (X E A (3k > XI : r-. E X2 N*)(3x l r-. • • • r-. X)(3x2 Xk ) } . E E X) . . . (3xk E X) S o Fx consists o f greatest lower bounds of non-empty finite subsets o f X together with all elements greater than or equal to one of these greatest lower bounds. In particular, each element of X belongs to Fx, hence Fx includes X. I t is easy to prove that Fx i s a filter. We will restrict ourselves to the following 97 S T 0 N E'S T H E 0 R E M remarks: (f) 0 � Fx (otherwise the finite intersection property would not be true for X) and 1 E Fx (because X is non-empty: at least one element of X is less than or equal to 1). (f1) If x > XI "' x2 "' · · · "' Xh and y > YI "' Y2 "' X "' y > XI "' X2 "' . . . "' Xk "' YI /'"' (fff) If x > X I "' x2 "' · · · Xk and y > x, then y we have found a filter that includes X . "' · · · "' Yk, then we have Y2 "' . . . "' Yk · > X I "' x2 "' · · · "' Xk - So • In the particular case of Boolean algebras, we can state Krull's theorem (see the beginning of this chapter) in terms of filters. It is then known as the ultrafilter theorem: Theorem 2.80 In a Boolean algebra, every filter is included in at least one ultrafilter. Proof Given a filter F, the ideal dual to F is included in at least one maximal ideal; its dual filter is then an ultrafilter that includes F. Of course, for Boolean algebras, the formulation i n terms of filters and the formulation in terms of ideals are equivalent. The ultrafilter theorem allows us to give a slightly different restatement of • Lemma 2.79: Let (A, <, 0, 1 ) be a Boolean algebra and let X be a subset of A. For the existence ofan ultrafilteron A that includes X, it is necessary and sufficient that X be a filterbase. Proof The properties �there exists an ultrafi.lter on A that includes X ' and �there exists a filter on A that includes X' are equivalent: the first clearly implies the Lemma 2.81 second; the reverse implication follows from the ultrafilter theorem. The conclusion • then fallows from Lemma 2. 79. 2.(]1 Stone's theorem The first example of a Boolean algebra that comes to mind is, without a doubt, that of the algebra of subsets of a given set. !s every Boolean algebra equal to (we really mean 'isomorphic to') the Boolean algebra of subsets of some set? We already have sufficient knowledge to answer 'no' to this question: we have encountered Boolean algebras without atoms (Example 2.37) and we know that the algebra of subsets of a set always contain atoms: the singletons; and any isomorphism transforms atoms into atoms (see Exercise 3 ) ; a Boolean algebra that does not contain atoms cannot therefore be isomorphic to an algebra that does. None the less, Stone's theorem, to which this section is devoted, shows that there is always a link that connects a Boolean algebra to an algebra of subsets of a set. 98 B OO L E A N A L G E B R A S More precisely, every Boolean algebra is isomorphic to a subalgebra of a Boolean algebra of subsets of a set. 2.6.1 The Stone space of a Boolean algebra Consider a Boolean algebra A = (A, +, x, 0, 1). Definition 2.82 The set ofhomomorphisms ofa Boolean algebra A into {0, 1} is denoted by S (A) and is called the Stone space of A. We could just have well chosen the set of maximal ideals or the set of ultrafilters on A (by virtue of Remark 2.74 ). The set S(A) is a subset of {0, l } A , the set of maps from A into {0, 1}, which we have considered earlier as a topological space by taking the discrete topology on {0, 1} and giving this space the product topology (see Definition 2. 19). So we can give S(A) the topology induced by that of {0, 1} A . The open subsets of S(A) are then the intersections with S(A) of the open subsets of {0, 1 } A . Lemma 2.83 The topological space S(A) is zero-dimensional. Proof We saw (Lemma 2.2 1 ) that {0, 1 } A is zero-dimensional. So it suffices to • apply Lemma 2.17. We have exhibited, just before Lemma 2.2 1 , a basis (Q; );E/ for the space {0, 1 } A consisting of clopen sets. Each of the Q; is the set of all maps from A into {0, 1} that take specified values at a specified finite number ofpoints. I f for each i, w e set r; = Qi n S(A), as in Lemma 2.17, then the family (r; )iEI is a basis for the open sets in S(A) consisting of clopen sets. Each r; is the set of homomorphisms of Boolean algebras from A into {0, l } which assume given values at a finite number of given points. From now on, it is exclusively this basis for the open sets that we will consider for the space S(A). When we speak of a basic open set for the Stone space of A, we mean one of the clopen sets in the family (ri ) ;E J· Lemma 2.84 For a subset � of S(A) to be a basic open set, it is necessary and sufficient that there exist an element a in A such that � = {h E S(A) : h(a) = 1}. Moreove1; when this condition is realized, such an element is unique. Proof • • sufficient. Suppose that � = {h E S(A) : h (a) = 1}; � is the set of homomor­ phisms from A into {0, 1 } that assume the value 1 at the point a: so it is one of the basic open sets in S(A). necessary. Suppose � is a basic open subset of S(A). * If 6. = 0, then 6. = {h E S(A) : h(O) == 1}. 99 S T 0 N E'S T H E 0 R E M * If � =I= 0, then there is an integer n > 1 , elements a 1 , az, elements c J , £2, . . . , En in {0. 1} such that 11 == {h E S(A) : h (a t ) == c J For every k = £2 and h(a2) . . . , an and . . . and h(an) in A and == En }. E { 1 , 2, . . . , n}, set bk = For every homomorphism h 1; 1 + ak i f t:k = 0. { ak if t:k = E S(A) and for every k E { 1 , 2, . . . , n}, we have It follows that for h E S(A), h E !::1 if and only i f h (bk) { 1 , 2, . . . , n }. But this latter condition is equivalent to 1 for all k E or again, since a homomorphism is involved, to So we see that by setting a = br r-. b2 r-. • • • r-. bn , we have !::1 = {h E S(A) : h(a) = 1}. Now let us prove uniqueness: if a and b are distinct elements of A, then a+ b =1= 0; so we may consider the principal filter generated by a + b and, in view of the ultrafilter theorem, an ultrafilter that includes this filter. To such an ultrafilter, there is an associated homomorphism ¢ from A into {0, 1} that satisfies ¢ (a + b) = 1, or again, ¢ (a) + ¢ (b) == 1, which means that one and only one of the two elements ¢ («) and ¢ (b) is equal to 1. This proves that " {h E S(A) : h (a) = 1 } i= {h E S(A) : h (b) = 1} since ¢ belongs to one o f these two sets and not to the other. • 2.85 The set ofbasic closed subsets of S(A) coincides with the set of its basic open subsets. Proof Let r be a basic closed subset of S(A). Then � = S(A) - r is a basic open subset; hence (by the preceding lemma) there is an element a E A such Corollary that !::1 = {h E S(A) : h (a) = 1}. 1 00 BOOLEAN ALGEBRAS Hence, r = {h E S(A) : h(a) =1- 1 } = {h E S(A) : h(a) 0} = {h E S(A) : h(l + a) = 1 } . == S o we see, thanks again to the preceding lemma, that r i s a basic open subset. In the same way, we can show that every basic open set is a basic closed set. • Lemma 2.86 The topological space S(A) is compact. A Proof First of all, since the topology on {0, 1 } is Hausdorff, so is the topology of S(A). Next, we must show that from any family of closed subsets of S(A) whose intersection is empty, we canextracta finite subfamily whose intersection is already empty. But we have seen (Lemma 2. 1 3) that it suffices to do this for families of basic closed sets. Now, as we have just seen, the basic closed sets coincide with the basic open sets. So consider an infinite family ('L j ) J E .! of basic open subsets of S(A) such that nj E J E.i == 0. By the preceding lemma, there exists, for each j E J, a unique element xi in A such that == {h E S(A) : h (xj ) 'L i = 1}. Set X = {Xj : j E J } . To say that the intersection ofthe family ('L j ) j E J is empty is to say that there is no homomorphism of Boolean algebras from A into {0, 1 } that assumes the value 1 for all elements of X, or again, that there i s no ultrafilter on A that contains X. This means (Lemma 2.8 1 ) that X is not a filterbase. So there exists a finite subset {x ii , xh , . . . , xjk } c X whose greatest lower bound is zero. So no ultrafilter on A could simultaneously contain x.ii , xh , and . . . and x.ik . In other words, no homomorphism from A into {0. 1 } can simultaneously assume the value 1 at the points x.h , xh , and . . . and x.ik . This amounts to saying that We thus have a finite subfamily of the fam ily ('L j ) j E.! whose intersection is • empty. Remark 2.87 We can give a d�fferent proofthat S(A) is compact by invoking the fact that {0, 1 } A is itse�fcompact (Theorem 2.20). It would then suffice to show that S(A) is closed in {0, 1 } A (since every closed subset ofa compact space is compact): For a E A and b E A, set n (a, b) == { .f E { 0, 1 } A : f (ab) == f (a) f (b) and f ( 1 + a) == I + f (a)} . 101 S T 0 N E'S T H E 0 R E M From Theorem 2.45, we have S(A) b of A, we can write: Q (a, b) = {f E {0, l} A : A L J { f E {0, l } LJ {f E {0, 1} A A U {f E {0, l} : : : = naE A Q (a, b). Butfor all elements a and hE A f(a) = 0 and f (b) = 0 and f (ab) = 0 and f(1 + a) = 1} f(a) = 0 and f (b) == 1 and f (ab) = 0 and f(1 + a) = 1} f(a) = 1 and f (b) == 0 and f (ab) = 0 and f(1 + a) = 0} f(a) = 1 and f(b) = 1 and f (ab) = 1 and f(1 + a) = 0}. Allfourofthe setson the right side ofthis equality are basic open subsets of{O, 1 } A , hence are clopen. So in particulat; their union is closed. So the intersection of all sets oftheform Q (a, b) as a and b range over A is a closed subsetof{O, 1 } A . And as we have seen, this intersection is S(A). For us, this second proof suffers by depending on a theorem that we did not prove (Tychonoff's theorem, which was invoked to claim that {0, l } A is compact). The first proof that we gave depends on Krull's theorem, which we did prove in Section 2. 1 . Corollary 2.88 The Stone space of A is a Boolean topological space. Proof Indeed, the space is compact (Lemma (Lemma 2.83). Lemma 2.89 2.86) and is zero-dimensional • The set (�fclopen subsets of S(A) coincides with the set ofits basic open sets. Proof We already know that all the basic open sets are clopen (Lemma 2.83). Conversely, let 1 be an arbitrary clopen subset of S(A). As 1 is open, it is a union of basic open sets: for example, r = ui EJ r i for some subset J c I . But since r is a closed subset of the compact space S (A), it is itself compact. So from the open covering (1; ) i EJ of r, we can extract a finite subcovering, for example: 1 == 1j1 U liz U · · · U rjm · We know (Lemma 2.84) that we can find elements X J x2, . . . , Xm in A such that � for every k E { 1 , 2, . . . , m } , rik = {h E S (A) : h(xk) = 1}. Set x = X I "--' x2 "--' · · · "--' Xk and set � = { h E S(A) : h(x) = 1}; we will show that I = �- Every element of r is a homomorphism that assumes the value 1 on at least one of the points X t , x2, . . . , Xm ; so it also assumes the value 1 at x which is their least upper bound. Thus, r c 11. On the other hand, any homomorphism that is not in r, and so does not assume the value 1 at any of the points X I , x2, . . . , Xm , must assume the value 0 at each of these points, and so too at the point x which is their least upper bound; so it cannot belong to /1 . This proves that 11 c r. Finally, r = /1 , and as 11 is a basic open set (by Lemma 2.84 ) , r must be one as well. • 1 02 BOOLEAN ALGEBRAS 2.6.2 Stone's theorem Theorem 2.90 (Stone 's theorem) Every Boolean algebra is isomorphic to the Boolean algebra of clopen subsets of its Stone space. Proof The Boolean algebra of clopen subsets of S(A) is denoted by B(S(A)) (see Example 2.56). Let H denote the map from A into � (S(A)) which, with each element a in A, associates H (a) = {h E S(A) : h(a) = 1}. Let u s show that H is an isomorphism ofBoolean algebras from A onto B(S(A)). According to Lemmas 2.84 and 2.89, the map H assumes its values in B(S(A)) and its image is the whole of B(S(A)). So H is a surjection from A onto B(S(A)). By virtue o f Theorem 2.48, to show that H is an isomorphism of Boolean algebras, it suffices to guarantee that for all elements x and y in A, x < y if and only if H(x) c H(y). So let x and y be two elements of A. I f x is less than o r equal t o y , then for any homomorphism h that satisfies h(x) = 1, we must also have h(y) = 1, which means that H (x) is a subset of H (y). If x is not less than or equal to y, then x(1 , y) =I= 0 (Lemma 2.31 ). So we may consider the principal filter generated by x(1 -r- y ), an ultrafilter that includes it (by the ultrafilter theorem) and the homomorphism h E S(A) associated with this ultrafilter. Wehave h(x (1+y)) = 1, hence h(x) = 1 and h(1 + y) = 1, i.e. h(y) == 0. We conclude that h E H(x) and h ¢ H (y ), and so H (x) is not included in H (y ). • Stone's theorem allows us to give a very simple proof of Theorem 2.50. Corollary 2.91 Everyfinite Boolean algebra is isomorphic to a Boolean algebra of subsets of some set. Proof If the set A is fi nite, then the topology on {0, 1 } A is the discrete topology. So this is also the case for the topology induced on the subset S(A). All subsets of S(A) are then both open and closed. So the Boolean algebra B(S(A)) coincides • with K-J (S(A)) and A is isomorphic to � (S(A)). In the case of an arbitrary Boolean algebra, what Stone's theorem shows is that it is isomorphic to a Boolean subalgebra of the algebra of subsets of some set (Example 2.56). 2.6.3 Boolean spaces are Stone spaces With each Boolean algebra, we have associated a Boolean topological space: its Stone space S(A), and we have seen that A is isomorphic to the Boolean algebra of clopen subsets of this Boolean space. It is therefore natural to study the case in which A is given as the Boolean algebra of clopen subsets of some Boolean S T 0 N E'S T H E 0 R E M 1 03 topollogical space X. The problem that then arises is to compare the space X to this other Boolean space that is the Stone space of A, in other words, to compare X and S(B(X)). The result of this comparison will reveal that these two objects very much resemble each other. Every Boolean topological space X is homeomorphic to the Stone space S(B(X)) of the Boolean algebra ofclopen subsets of X. Proof Let X be a Boolean space. According to Lemma 20 16, we can take the Boolean algebra B(X) of clopen subsets of X as a basis for the open sets in the topology on X. For each x E X, let fx denote the map from B(X) into {0, 1 } defined by Theorem 2.92 fx ( Q) == { 1 0 Q; 1- Q . if X E if X We will show that the map f which, with each x E X, associates fx , is a homeomorphism from the topological space X onto the topological space S (B (X)) 0 • As f is, a priori, a map from X into {0, that it really assumes values in S(B(X)): 1 } B(X) , we must show, to begin with, X, fr is a homomorphism of Boolean algebras: Proof For any clopen subsets Q and b:. of X , we have fx (Q n .6.) == 1 i f and only if X E Q n b:., i.e. X E Q and X E .6., which is equivalent to fx (Q) == l and fx (l:i) == 1, and hence to fx (Q)fx (.6.) == 1. We conclude from this that For each x E • fx (Q n .6.) = fx (Q) fx ( .6. ). On the other hand, fx ( X - Q) == 1 if and only if x E X - Q, i.e. x 1- Q, or again, fx (Q) == 0. Thus, fx (X - Q) == 1 + fx (Q). We see that the conditions • from Theorem 2.45 are satisfied: fx is indeed a homomorphism. The map f is injective: • Proof Let x and y be distinct elements of X. As X is Hausdorff, we can find an open set 0 such that x E 0 and y 1- 0 (for example, we could take 0 = X - { y } ). B u t 0 is a union of basic open sets from the basis B(X); so there is some clopen set n E B(X) such that X E n and y 1- no We have fx (Q) = 1 and /y(Q) = 0, • which proves that fx is different from /y 0 The map f is surjective onto S(B(X)): • Proof Let h be a n element of S(B(X)), i.e. a homomorphism from {0 1 } . The ultrafilter on B(X) associated with h is .. u == 1 {Q E B(X) : h (Q) == 1 } == h - [{1}]0 B(X) into 1 04 BOOLEAN ALGEBRAS Since U has the finite intersection property (Lemma 2.81 ), since the elements of U are closed, and since the topological space X is compact, we may assert that the intersection of all the elements of U is non-empty. Let x be an element of this intersection. Forevery clopen set Q E B(X), we have: either Q E U, in which case fx (Q) = 1 and h (Q ) = 1, or else Q ¢ U, in which case X -� Q E U (Remark 2.73), so fx (Q) = 0 and h (Q) = 0. Thus, for every Q E B(X), fx (Q ) = h(Q). It follows • that h = fx = j (x). We may observe that the element x, which we have just shown is a preimage of h under the map J, is the unique element in the intersection of all the clopen sets belonging to U. To see this, note that any element y in this intersection would, exactly as above, satisfy h = J(y), and since f is injective, this would imply 1 x = y. This observation will allow us to describe the inverse bijection f - : it is the map from S(B(X)) into X that, to each homomorphism h of B(X) into {0, 1 } , associates the unique element i n the intersection of all the clopen sets belonging to the ultrafi Iter h - 1 [{ 1 } ] . • The map f is continuous. Proof Let G be an open set belonging to the basis of clopen subsets of S(B(X)). According to Lemma 2.84, there exists a unique element Q in B(X) such that G = {h E S(B(X)) : h (Q) = 1 } . The inverse image of G under the map f is {x E X : j� E G} = {x E X : ft (Q) = So it is an open subset of X. • 1} = {x EX:xE Q} = Q. • The inverse map f- 1 is continuous. Proof Let Q be a basic open set in the space X (i.e. an element of B(X)). Since f is a bijection, the inverse image of Q under f --l is its direct image under f . Thus i t i s the set j [Q] = {.fx : x E Q } . We have to show that this i s a n open set in the space S(B(X)). Set V = {h E S(B(X)) : h(Q) = 1 } . The set V i s open (it i s even a basic open set) i n S(B(X)) (Lemma 2.84). I f we show that j [ Q] = V , this will complete the proof. For every x E Q, we have fx (Q) = 1 by definition of .ft , so fx E V. Thus j [Q] c v . Every h E V has a preimage y E X under the bijection f, say h = /y . As h E V, we have h (Q) = f). (Q) = 1, so y E Q and /y = h E j[Q]. Hence, V is • included in j[Q]. We should remark that the proof of this last point was superfluous: there is a famous theorem of topology asserting that any continuous bUection of a compact topological space into a Hausdorff space is a homeomorphism (the continuity of the inverse bijection is guaranteed). S T 0 N E'S T H E 0 R E M 1 05 We have definitely established a one-to-one correspondence between Boolean algebras and Boolean topological spaces (up to isomorphism on one side, up to homeomorphism on the other): • every Boolean algebra is (isomorphic to) the Boolean algebra of clopen subsets of some Boolean topological space; • every Boolean topological space is (homeomorphic to) the Stone space of some Boolean algebra. In passing, let us observe that we had very good reasons for calling compact zero-dimensional spaces 'Boolean spaces'. In a natural way, w e have the following two properties (which are easily proved from all that has preceded): • for any two Boolean algebras to be isomorphic, it is necessary and sufficient that their Stone spaces be homeomorphic; • for any two Boolean topological spaces to be homeomorphic, it is necessary and sufficient that the Boolean algebras consisting of their respective clopen subsets be isomorphic. 1 06 BOOLEAN ALGEBRAS EXERCISES FOR C H A PTE R 2 1. (Refer to Example 2.26) Consider a set P of propositional variables and the associated set :F of formulas. We are going to study the quotient set :FI rv, i.e. the set of classes of logically equivalent formulas. The equivalence class of a formula F will be denoted by cl(F). (a) Show that if, for all formulas F and G of :F, we set -lci(F) = cl( _,F) cl(F) A ci(G) = ci(F A G) cl(F) v ci(G) = ci(F v G) ci(F) => ci(G) = cl(F => G) cl(F) <=} cl( G) = ci(F <=} G) ci(F) § ci(G) = cl(F § G), this defines internal operations on :Flrv (denoted, abusively, by the same symbols for the corresponding connectives). Show that :Flrv is a Boolean algebra with respect to the operations § and /\. (Reminder: (F § G) = � (F <=} G )). (b) Show that the order relation in this Boolean algebra is the following: for all formulas F and G of :F, ci(F) < ci(G) if and only if �* (F => G). (See Example 2.37). Explain how the operations of greatest lower bound, least upper bound and complementation are defined. (c) Show that if the set p is finite, then the Boolean algebra :FI rv is atomic; describe the set of atoms. 2. Let E be an arbitrary set. On f)J (E), we define a binary operation � (symmetric difference, see Exercise 16 from Chapter 1 ) as follows: for all elements X and Y of f)J (E), X �y = (X U Y) - (X n Y ) (X n (E - Y )) U ((E - = X) n Y). (The symmetric difference of the subsets X and Y is the set of elements of E that belong to one and only one of these subsets). After observing that for all subsets X and Y of E we have X � y == {x E E x E X § x E : Y}, show, using the properties o f the usual connectives, for instance 1\ and §, that the set f)J (E), with the two binary operations � and n, is a Boolean algebra. For this Boolean algebra, explain how the order relation and the operations of greatest lower bound, least upper bound and complementation are defined. EXERCISES FOR CH APTER 2 107 3. Let A = ( A , + , x , 0, 1) and B = ( B , +, x , 0, 1) be two Boolean algebras and let f be an isomorphism of Boolean algebras from A onto B. (a) Show that an element a E A is an atom of A if and only if f (a ) is an atom of B. (b) Show that A is atomless if and only if B is atomless. (c) Show that A is atomic if and only if B is atomic. (d) Show that a subset I c A is an ideal of A if and only if fl/ ] , its direct image under f, is an ideal of B. (e) Show that a subset U ultrafilter of B. 4. c A is an ultrafilter of A if and only if f [U] is an We say that a Boolean algebra ( A , + , x , 0, 1 ) is complete if and only if every non-empty subset of A has a greatest lower bound. (a) Show thatfora Boolean algebra to be complete, it is necessary and sufficient that every non-empty subset have a least upper bound. (b) Show that a Boolean algebra that is isomorphic to a complete Boolean algebra is complete. (c) Show that the Boolean algebra of subsets of a set is complete. (d) Show that if E is infinite, the Boolean algebra of subsets of E that are finite or cofinite (see Example 2.55) is not complete. (e) Is the Boolean algebra of classes of logically equivalent formulas of the propositional calculus (see Exercise 1 above) complete? (f) Show that for a Boolean algebra to be isomorphic to the Boolean algebra of subsets of some set, it is necessary and sufficient that it be atomic and complete. 5. Let A = ( A , +, x , 0, 1 ) be a Boolean algebra and let B = (B, +, x , 0, 1) be a Boolean subalgebra of A. Show that an element of B that is an atom of A must also be an atom of B but that there can be atoms of B that are not atoms of A. 6. Let A = ( A , +, a E A, the set x, 0, 1 ) be a Boolean algebra. Show that for every element B = {x E A : x > a or x < 1 + a} i s a Boolean subalgebra o f A and that i t i s a complete (see Exercise 4 above) Boolean algebra if A itself is complete. 7. Let A = ( A , +, x , 0, 1 ) be a Boolean algebra. Consider a non-empty subset Z of fYJ ( A ) whose elements are filters on A. (a) Show that the set nF EZ F, the intersection of the filters that belong to Z, is also a filter on A, but that the union U F E Z F of the elements of Z may not be a filter. 1 08 BOOLEAN ALGEBRAS (b) Suppose, in addition, that Z is totally ordered by the inclusion relation. Show that in this case, U F E Z F is a filter on A. 8. Let E be a countable subset of tJ (N) that has the finite intersection property (i.e. E is a fi.lterbase in the Boolean algebra tJ (N)). The set of filters on tJ (N) that include E is then non-empty and the intersection of the elements of this set (see Exercise 7 above) is called the filter generated by E. Show that i f the filter generated by E i s an ultrafilter, then it i s the trivial ultrafilter. 9. Consider a set P of propositional variables and its associated Boolean algebra :Ffrv (see Exercise l ). We say that a class x E :F frv is positive if there is at least one formula F in x which does not contain any occurrences of the negation symbol. (a) Show that for any class x E :Fjrv, x is positive if and only if for every formula F E x, 8 1 ( F ) == 1 (81 is the assignment of truth values that assigns the value 1 to every variable: see Exercise 20 from Chapter 1 . ) (b) Show that the set J of positive classes is an ultrafilter in the Boolean alge­ bra :Ffrv. (c) What is the homomorphism from .r/''"' into {0, 1 } associated with this ul­ trafilter? 10. Let X be a topological space. A subset Y c X is said to be dense in X if and only if every non-empty open subset of X has a point in common with Y. (Some authors say everywhere dense instead of dense.) An element x E X is called an isolated point if and only if the singleton set { x} is an open subset of X . Let A == ( A , +, x , 0, 1 ) b e a Boolean algebra. Let S denote its Stone space and let H denote the isomorphism from A onto B(S) defined in the proof of Stone's theorem (Theorem 2.90). (a) Show that for any element x E A, x is an atom of A if and only if the set H (x) is a singleton. (b) Show that A has no atoms if and only if the topological space S has no isolated points. (c) Show that A is atomic if and only if the set of isolated points of S is dense in S. 11. We say that a B oolean algebra ( A , +, x , 0, 1) is dense if and only if the order relation < on A is dense, which means that for all elements a and h of A , if a < h, then there exists at least one element c E A such that a < c < h. Naturally, it is important not to confuse the notion of dense Boolean algebra with the notion of dense subset of a topological space introduced in Exercise 10. Show that a Boolean algebra is dense if and only if it has no atoms. 12. The purpose of this exercise is to show that, up to isomorphism, there is only one countable atomless Boolean algebra. EXERCISES FOR CHAPTER 2 1 09 Consider a Boolean algebra A = ( A , +, x , 0 , 1 ) that has no atoms. Assume that the set A is countable and fi x an enumeration A = {an : n E N } . 2 (a) Given a non-zero element x i n A , a splitting of x is a pair (y, z) E A such that y i= 0, z # 0, y r-. z = 0, and y z = x. Show that (y, z) is a splitting of x if and only if 0 < y < x and z = y + x. Show that in A, every non-zero element has at least one splitting. "---' (b) Show that it is possible to define a family: of non-zero elements of A such that UVJ = 1 and, for every integer n , (uc-c;Qc;( £n- l o, u £QE( cn-1 1 ) i s a splitting of u £Q£J ... £n-l ' C' .•. . . . • and (Thus, if ao � {0, l } , then uo is an arbitrary splitting of 1 ). = ao and u 1 = 1 + ao; otherwise, ( u o, U I ) (c) Show that for every element x E A and every sequence c = (cn) neN of elements of {0, 1}, one and only one of the following two conditions is satisfied: (i) for every n E N, x r-. U £o£ 1 ...£n- I cn # 0 ; U c0c1 ... Bn-I£n # 0 . (ii) for every n E N, ( 1 + x) "' (d) Consider two integers m and n satisfying 0 < n < m and m + n + 2 ele­ ments co, c t , . . . , En , so, Sl , . . , sm in {0, l } . Show that for u80c1 . . .£n- I Bn r-. u �0� 1 {m- I {m to be non-zero, it is necessary and sufficient that co = so and c J = SI and . . . and En = Sn . (e) Let h be the map from A into � ({0, l }n ) which, with each element x E A , . . .. associates h (x) = n { / E {0, 1} : ('v'n E N)(x r-. U JO)f(l) ... f(n) ) -=/= 0)} . Show that h i s a n isomorphism of Boolean algebras from A onto the Boolean algebra 8({0, 1} N ) of clopen subsets of {0, 1} N . 110 BOOLEAN ALGEBRAS 13. See Example 2.57 for the notation used here. (a) Show that the map g from {0, 1 } P into {0� 1 }F/"' which, with each assignment of truth values 8, associates the homomorphism h0 from F;� into {0, 1 } , is a bijection from {0, 1 } P onto the Stone space S(:F j�). (b) Show, without using the compactness theorem, that for any subset T of F, T is satisfiable if and only if the set T ;� = {ci(G) : G E T} is a filterbase in the Boolean algebra :FI�. (c) Use this result to provide a new proof of the compactness theorem for propositional calculus (Theorem 1.39). 14. Let A = {A, <, 0, 1) be a Boolean algebra and let a be an element of A. Let B be the principal ideal generated by a (Example following Corollary 2.61 ) and I be the principal ideal generated by aC: B = {x E A x < a} ; I = { x E A x < ac } . : : (a) Show that the order relation < B , the restriction to B ofthe orderrelation < on A, makes B into a Boolean algebra. Compare the operations in this Boolean algebra with the corresponding operations in the Boolean algebra A. (b) Show that the Boolean algebra { B, < B ) is isomorphic to the quotient Boolean algebra A/ I. 15. Let E be a non-empty finite setandletA be the Boolean algebra of subsets of E. (a) Show that for a subset I c fiJ (E) to be an ideal of A, it is necessary and sufficient that there exists a subset X � E (strict inclusion) such that = fiJ (X). Let C = (C, <, 0, 1 ) b e a n arbitrary Boolean algebra and let h b e a homo­ morphism from A into C. Show that there exists a unique subset K C E such that for every element Y E fiJ (E), h ( Y ) = 0 if and only if Y c K . I (b) Let Z b e the complement o f K i n E . Show that the restriction of h to fiJ ( Z ) i s an isomorphism of Boolean algebras from fiJ (Z) onto the image of A under h (which is a Boolean subalgebra of C). 16. Let A = {A, <, 0, 1 ) be a Boolean algebra. (a) Show that if A is finite then every ideal of A is principal. Compare this result with that from Exercise 1 5 (a). (b) Show that if there exists an integer k > 1 and atoms a I , a2, . . . , ak of A such that a I a2 .....__, · · · "-../ ak = 1 , then A is finite. .....__, (c) Assume that the Boolean algebra A is infi nite. Show that the set G = {x E is a filterbase on A. A : 1 + x is an atom} E XERCISES FOR CHAPTER 2 111 (d) Again suppose that A is infinite. Show that for an ultrafilter U on A to be non-trivial, it is necessary and sufficient that G be included in U. Use this result to reprove Theorem 2.77. (e) Show that for the existence of a non-trivial ultrafilter on A, it is necessary and sufficient that A be an infinite Boolean algebra. 17. Let E be a set and let A = {g;; ( E ) , C) be the Boolean algebra of subsets of E. (a) Consider a family ( E t)i E I of subsets that constitutes a partition of E (which means each Et is non-empty, that U tE / E i = E, and that for i =I= j, E i =I= Ei). Show that the set is a Boolean subalgebra of A and that each of the E; is an atom i n this Boolean subalgebra. (b) Suppose that E is finite and non-empty and that C is a Boolean subalgebra of g;; (E). Show that the atoms of the Boolean algebra C constitute a family of subsets of E that partitions E . (c) Show that i f E i s a non-empty finite set, there is a bijection between the set of partitions of E and the set of Boolean subalgebras of g;; (E). 18. (a) I severy Boolean subalgebra of an atomic Boolean algebra an atomic Boolean algebra? (b) Are there Boolean algebras all of whose Boolean subalgebras are atomic? (c) Is every Boolean subalgebra of an atomless Boolean algebra an atomless Boolean algebra? (d) Are there Boolean algebras all of whose Boolean subalgebras are atomless? (e) Is every Boolean subalgebra of a complete Boolean algebra a complete Boolean algebra? (f) Are there Boolean algebras all of whose Boolean subalgebras are complete? 19. Let A and A' be two Boolean algebras and let S(A) and S(A') be their Stone spaces. (a) Show that we can establish a bijection ¢ between the set Hom(A, A') of homomorphisms of Boolean algebras from A into A' and the set C 0 (S(A'), S(A)) of continuous maps from S(A') into S(A). (b) Show that for every homomorphism cp E Hom(A, A'), cp is injective (respectively, surj ective) if and only if ¢ (cp) is surjective (respectively, i�jective). 3 Predicate calculus ---- ----- ------ ---- - - --- -- - The fundamental work of the mathematician is to examine structures, to suggest properties that might pertain to these and to ask whether these properties are sat­ isfied or not. Predicate calculus is, in some way, the first stage in theformalization ofmathematical activity. Two aspects are involved: first, we provide ourselves with formal tools that are adequate to name these objects (these will be the terms) and to express (some of) their properties (these will be theformulas); second, we study the satisfaction of these properties in the structures under consideration. As with the propositional calculus, the formulas are sequences of symbols that are taken from some alphabet and that obey precise syntactic rules. There will not be a unique alphabet but rather an appropriate alphabet, called a language, for each type ofstructure under consideration. By structure, we mean a non-empty set M, provided with thefollowing: a certain number qf"distinguished elements; for each positive integer p, a certain number of p-place relations on M (also called 'predicates', hence the expression 'predicate calculus '); andfor each positive integer p, a certain number offunctions from M P into M. Obviously, would not use the same language to speak, for example, of groups and of ordered sets. Certain symbols are common to all the languages: these are the propositional connectives and parentheses, already used in propositional calculus, but also, and this is the essential innovation, the quantifiers \:1 ( :for all') and 3 ( 'there exists ') and the variables vo, VI , . . .. The other symbols depend on the type of structure we have in mind; they will represent distinguished elements, predicates orfitnctions. For example,for groups, we need a constant symbol (to represent the identity element) and a symbol for a binary function (to represent multiplication). For ordered sets, we only need a symbol for a binary relation. The formulas that are involved here are called f ' ormulas offirst order predicate calculus'. The reason for this name is that the quantifiers will range over elements of the structure. There are numerous mathematical properties for which this re­ striction is fatal. For example, to express the fact that a set A is well ordered, we need to say: for every subset B l�l A, �l B is not empty, then B contains a least element. We note that the quant�fier :for all ' in this definition ranges over subsets we 1 13 SYNTAX of· A and not over elements of A. This is a second order quantifier. The concept of a well-ordered set is not expressible by a first orderformula. The problems of syntax, treated in Section 3. /, are substantially more compli­ cated than for the propositional calculus. First of all, because we have to define terms before we can define formulas; second, because we have to inttvduce the notions offree and bound variable: we immediately sense that the status of the variable vo is not the same in the following two formulas: vo + vo :::: vo and 'v'vo(vo -t- vo � vo) . We say that vo isfree in the .first and bound in the second. This distinction is fundamental in what follows. In Section 3.2, we temporarily abandon logic to explain what we mean by struc­ ture. In Section 3.3, we define sati.�faction of a formula in a structure (we also say that the structure is a model of the formula). The two facts mentioned above, particularly the fact that we will have to define satisfaction for formulas that contain free variables, will weigh us down considerably. But the reader must noJ be worried: despite its complication, the definition of satisfaction involves noJhing more than what the reader would probably have guessed from the beginning. In Section 3.4 we show that everyformula is equivalent to (i.e. is satisfied in the same structures as) a formula that is written in a very particularform (with all the quant{fiers at the beginning: this is called a prenexform). We will also see how to eliminate existential quantifiers by adding function symbols to the language (the Skolemform). In Section 3.5, we will present the ABCs of model theory, which is the study ofthe correspondence between a set offormulas and the class of models of this set. This will be studied in more depth in ChapterS. Finally, in Section 3.6, we will examine the behaviour of equality, which is a binary predicate not quite like the others. 3.1 Syntax 3.1.1 First order languages Definition 3.1 A .first order language (often we will simply say language) is a set L of symbols composed of two parts: the.first part, common to all languages, consists, on the one hand, ofa countably iJ�finite set, • V = { VQ , V 1 , • • • , Vn , • . . }, ofelements called symbols for variables or more simply variables, and, on the other hand, of thefollowing nine symbols: 1\, v , =::} , <¢:> * the parentheses: ), ( and the symbols for the connectives: used previously in propositional calculus, * and two new symbols: 'v', which is called the universal quantifier and is read as 'for all', and -, , 1 14 • PREDICATE CALCULUS 3, which is called the existential quantifier and is read as 'there exists at least one ' or 'for at least one ' or simply 'there exists'; (each of these quant�fiers is called the dual of the other),· the second part, which can vary f1vm one language to another, is the union of a set C and of two sequences (Fn) n E.N* and (Rn)n E.N* ofsets (pairwise disjoint and all di�jointfrom C); * * * the elements ofC are called constant symbols; for every integer n > 1, the elements of Fn are called n -place (or n-ary or ofarity n, or with n arguments)function symbols (orfunctionals) and the elements of Rn are called n-place (or n-ary or of arity n, or with n arguments) relation symbols (or predicates); (we say unary, binary and ternary respectively instead of 1-ary, 2-ary and 3-aly); we consider one particular symbol with a special status that will be explained later: the symbol �' called the equality symbol, which, when a first order Language contains it, is an element ojR2, i.e. is a binary relation symbol. Languages that contain this symbol are called languages with equality. Except in one important circumstance (see Chapter 4 ), the languages we encounter in this text will be of this type and when we say 'language' , with no modifier, we always mean a language with equality. Of course, all the symbols that we have just listed and which constitute the language are assumed to be pairwise distinct. Thus, to have a first order language, L, is to define the two sequences (Rn) nEN* and (Fn) nEN* and to consider the set: The symbols for the constants, the functions and the relations are sometimes called the non-logical symbols of the language. Some other presentations differ slightly from our own: it can happen that constant symbols are treated as 0-place function symbols or that specific 0-place relation symbols are allowed, T ('true') and _L ( ' false'). These slight variants do not modify anything that i s essential in what follows. I n most of the cases that we will examine, the languages will involve only a small number of symbols for constants, functions and relations, so that in practice, most of the sets Rn and Fn will be empty and those that are not empty will contain at most two or three symbols. Under these circumstances, rather than give a fa<itidious definition of the sequences (Rn ) nEN* and (Fn )n EN*, we will be content to provide a list of the symbols that appear in these sequences, while indicating their status (relation, function) and their arity, and to specify the elements of the set C. As it is obviously pointless to repeat, for each language, the unchanged list of symbols consisting of, for example, the variables, the connectives and quantifiers, we will commit the abuse that consists in identifying a language with the list of its 1 15 SYNTAX symbols for constants, functions and relations. Thus, when we are led to say: 'Consider the language L == { R, c, f, g} where R is a binary relation symbol, c is a constant symbol, and f and g are two unary function symbols' , this wil1 mean that we are interested in the set C == {c} and in the two sequences (Rn) nEN* and (Fn)nEN* defined by: R2 {�, R}, Rn 0 F 1 == {f, g} and Fn == == == for n 0 I- 2, for n > 2. (In the absence of any mention to the contrary, the language will be one with equality.) Starting from a first order language viewed as an alphabet, we will now construct, following the inductive method used previously for the propositional calculus, a family of words that we will call the first order formulas associated with our language. To do this will require an intermediate step in which we define, also inductively, another family of words called terms. As our ultimate purpose is to use the language to formally describe certain properties of mathematical objects (or individuals), we may intuitively consider that terms will serve as names to denote these individuals whereas the formulas will serve as statements of facts concerning them. Let us consider a first order language L. 3. 1.2 Terms of the language The symbols that serve as raw materials for the construction of terms are the variables and the function symbols. Note that the parentheses are not involved in writing terms. Definition 3.2 W(L) that: • • The set T(L) ofterms of the language L is the smallest subset of contains the variables and the constant symbols (i.e. includes the set V U C); is closed under the operation for every integer n > I and every element f E Fn. In other words, terms are words that can be obtained by applying the following rules a finite number of times: • variables and constant symbols are terms (recall that we do not distinguish between a symbol of the alphabet and the word of length I consisting of this symbol); • if n E N*, if f is an n-ary function symbol of L, and if t1 , t2, . . . , tn are terms, then the word f t1 t2 . . tn is a term. . 1 16 PREDICATE CALCULUS After this definition 'from above', let us consider the equivalent definition 'from below' : Set To(L) = V U C, and for every integer k, set 7k+ 1 ( L) = 7k ( L) U u { ft t2 . . . nE.N* 1 In : .f E F,z , t 1 E 7k ( L), t2 E 7k ( L), . . . , t E 7k (L)}. n Definition 3.3 t E 7k(L). The lwight of a term t E T(L) is the least integer k such that Observe that in a language, there are always terms of height 0: the variables; but it is altogether possible that there are no terms whose height is non-zero (this will happen when there are no function symbols at all). For terms, we can define the concept of a decomposition tree in a manner anal­ ogous to the one we used for formulas of the propositional calculus, with the difference that at each node, there can be any number of branches, this number being precisely the arity of the function symbol used at the given stage in the con­ struction of the term. There will also be a unique readability theorem (3. 7) which wi II guarantee the uniqueness of the decomposition tree. Consider, for example, the language that has one constant symbol c, one unary function symbol f and a ternary function symbol g. Consider the word W = ggffvogv2 vocfcff8fcgv2fvof}'cfcfc. Is this a term of the language? After careful inspection, or a few probings, or with a bit of luck, by setting r = gff'vo8V2vocfc, s == ffgfcgv2fvoffcfc, and t = fc, and, even better, by i nserting spaces wisely, r = g ffvo gv2voc fc, / ffvo I vo f I vo • r / 112 • • and t = fc, w / gv2voc I vo s = f f g fc gv2fvoffc fc, -� c • "" fc I c • � s / fc I c • / 'V2 • Sl I S2 I SJ I fvo I vo • t I c • -� ffc I fc I c • --� fc I c • SYNTAX 1 17 we discover that r, s and t really are terms and that the proposed word W, which is written grst (a ternary function symbol followed by three terms), is itself a term (of height 7) whose decomposition tree is not difficult to sketch (to improve its legibility we have set s3 == gv2fvoffc, s2 == gf cs3f c and s1 == fs2, so that s == fst). The theorem that follows furnishes a simple test for determining whether a word in a given language is or is not a term. It also provides, when the test is positive, a method for finding the decomposition of the term. Finally, it provides us with a simple proof of the unique readability theorem. First we give a definition: The weight of a function symbol is equal to its arity minus 1. The weight of a variable or a constant symbol is - 1 . If W is a word written with variables, constant symbols and function symbols, the weight of W, denoted by p ( W), is the sum of the weights of the symbols that occur in the word W (the weight ofthe empty word is 0). We say that a word W satisfies the rule of weights if and only �{the weight of W is - 1 and the weights of all its proper initial segments are greater than or equal to 0. Definition 3.4 For a word W, written with variables, constant symbols andfunc­ tion symbols, to be a term, it is necessary and sufficient that it satisfy the rule of weights. Theorem 3.5 Proof First we will show, by induction, that all terms satisfy the rule of weights. As far as variables and constant symbols are concerned, this is clear: their weight is equal to - 1 and they do not admit any proper initial segments. Consider an integer n > 1 , an n-ary function symbol f and n terms t1 , t2, . . . , tn which are assumed (by the induction hypothesis) to satisfy the rule of weights. Set t == f t1 t2 · · · tn. We have p (t) == p (f) + p ( t t ) + p (t2) + · · · + p (t11 ) == n - 1 + n x (- 1 ) == - 1 . Now let m be a proper initial segment of t . Then there exists an index i E { I , 2, . . . , n} and an initial segment m; of t; such that Note that if i == n, mi is necessarily a proper initial segment oft; but that if i =I= then m; might also equal t; or the empty word. We have n, p (m) == p (f) + p (tt ) + p (t2) + · · · + p (t; -I ) + p (m;) == n - l + ( i - 1) x ( - 1 ) + p (m;) (by the induction hypothesis) == n - i + p (m; ). Now, by the induction hypothesis, p(mi ) i s either - I or i s an integer greater than or equal to 0 (according as mi == t; or not). It follows that p (m) > n - i - 1 , which 1 18 PREDICATE CALCULUS IS a number greater than or equal to zero if i is strictly less than n . If i = n, then m; -=/= li (otherwise m would equal t), and so p (m) = p (m; ) > 0. We see then that, in all cases, the weight of m is greater than or equal to zero, which shows that t satisfies the rule of weights. Now we have to show the converse: that every word that satisfies the rule of weights is a term. We will prove it by induction on the length of words. The word of length 0 does not satisfy the rule of weights (its weight is 0). If a word of length l satisfies the rule of weights, then its weight is - 1 . Thus we are dealing with either a variable or a constant symbol, so it is, in all cases, a term. Consider an integer k > 1 . Suppose (this is the induction hypothesis) that any word of length strictly less than k that satisfi.es the rule of weights is a term. Consider a word W of length k which satisfies the rule of weights. For example, where the ai are variables or constant symbols or function symbols (so that p (ai) > - 1 for every i). Thus we have p( W ) = -1 and, for every i E { 1 , 2, . . , k - 1 } , . Since k > 1 , a 1 i s a strict initial segment of W; thus p( a1 ) > 0 , which shows that a 1 must be a function symbol of arity at least equal to 1 . Denote this arity by n + 1 (n = p (a t ) > 0). I fn == 0, the worda2a3 . . . ak satisfies the ruleofweights (suppressing the initial symbol of weight 0 changes neither the total weight nor the weights of any proper initial segments); since the length of this word is k - 1, the induction hypothesis applies: therefore a2a3 . . . ak is a term; and so is W since, in this case, a 1 is a unary function symbol. Now let us examine the case n > 0. Denote by ¢ the map from { I , 2, . . , k} into tZ which associates with each index, i, the value . We have ¢ ( 1 ) = n > O and ¢ (k) = - l . Since the passage from ¢(i) to ¢ (i + l ) adds an integer, p (a; + I ) , that i s greater than or equal to - 1 , we see that the map ¢, to get from its initial value n to its final value - 1 , must assume each of the intermediate values n - 1 , n 2, . . , 1 , 0, at least once (this function cannot decrease by more than 1 at each step). Denote by it (and by h . . . , in respectively) the first integer in { 1 , 2, . . . , k } for which the function ¢ takes the value n - 1 (n - 2, . , 0 respectively). Extend this by setting jo = 1 and j11+ 1 = k so that ¢ (jo) = n and ¢ (j11+ 1 ) = - 1 . - . . , . . 1 19 SYNTAX We must have io == 1< j1 < i2 < · · · < in < in+l == k. (The argument that we just gave can b e repeated to prove that the function ljJ can not pass from the value ¢ ( 1 ) = n to the value ¢ ( j2) = n - 2 without assuming at least once the value n - 1 , hence j1 < .i2, and so on.) Set We are going to show that each of these n + 1 words is a term; given that a 1 is a function symbol of arity n + I and that the word W is written a 1 tt t2 . . . tn + 1 , this will prove that W is also a term. Let h be an integer such that 1 < h < n + 1 . We have hence p (th ) == </J (jh ) - </J ( jh- I ) = n - h - (n - (h - 1 ) ) = -1. Moreover, i f th had a proper initial segment whose weight is strictly negative, this would mean that there exists an index i E {jh - 1 + I , . . . , jh - 1 } such that p (ajh-I + l . . . ai ) = ¢ (i ) - ¢ (ih - I ) = ¢ (i ) - (n - (h - 1)) < 0; or again, ¢ (i ) < n - h. But ¢ (jh- 1 ) = n - h + l . According to the argument already used twice previ­ ousJy, the value n - h would then be assumed by the function ¢ for some index between jh- l and i, i.e. strictly less than jh, and this would contradict the definition of ih · We have thereby proved that th satisfies the rule of weights and, as its length is strictly less than k , we conclude from the induction hypothesis that it is a term. • The unique readability theorem (for terms) will be proved in two stages. Lemma 3.6 For any term t E T( L), no proper initial segment oft is a term. This is an immediate consequence of the rule of weights: if t is a term and u is a proper initial segment of t, then the weight of u is positive or zero, and so u cannot be a term. • Proof 1 20 PREDICATE CALCULUS (unique readability theorem for terms) For any term t one and only one of thefollowing three cases applies: Theorem 3.7 T(L), E t is a variable of L; t is a constant symbol of L; there is a unique integerk > 1 , a unique k-aryfunction symbol f ofthe language L and a unique k - tuple (u 1 , u2, . . . , Uk) E T(L)k such that t = fu 1 u2 . . . Uk Proof Consider a term t E T(L). By the definition of T(L), we are in one of • • • the first two cases, or else in the third but without any guarantee in advance of uniqueness. It is clear, moreover, that these three cases are mutually exclusive (to see this, it suffices to examine the first symbol in the word t). So the only thing that we have to prove is the uniqueness for the third case. For this, consider two natural numbers k and h, two function symbols f and g of the language L that are k-ary and h-ary respectively and k + h terms tr , t2, . . . , tk, u 1 , u2, . . . , Uh in T(L) and suppose that: From this equality, we conclude that f and g are identical (they are the first symbols of the same word) hence their arities are equal. So we have Suppose now that there is some index i E { 1 , tt = u 1 , t2 = u2, . . . , t;- 1 = 2, . . . , k} such that Ui- 1 , and t; =/= u;. After simplifying, we obtain which proves that one of the two terms t; and u; is a proper initial segment of the other (this property was established at the beginning of the text in the section 'Notes to the Reader'). But this situation is precisely what is forbidden by the • preceding lemma. Definition 3.8 A closed term. term in which there is no occurrence of a variable is called a We immediately see that a closed term must contain at least one occurrence of a constant symbol. It follows that for a language that has no constant symbols, there are no closed terms. Notation: Given a term t E T(L) and pairwise distinct natural numbers i I , i2, . . . , in, We will USe the notation t = t [Vf 1 , V;2 , . . . , Vi, ] to indicate that the variables that have at least one occurrence in the term t are among Vi 1 , Vi2, , Vi11 • • • • 121 SYNTAX We should note that for any term t, there i s an integer m such that t = t [ VQ, V I , • • • , Vm]; (because t involves only a finite number of symbols, and hence a finite number of variables, it suffices to let m be the largest of the indices of all the variables that have at least one occurrence in t ). 3.1.3 Substitutions in terms Let k be a natural number, let w 1 , w2, . . ., Wk be pairwise distinct variables, and let t, U J , u2, . . . , Uk be terms. The word tu1 Jw1 ,u2;w2, ... ,uk /wk (read as 't sub u I replaces w I , u2 replaces w2, . . ., Uk replaces Wk ') is the result of substituting the terms u 1 , u2, . . . , ukfor the variables Wt , w2, . . . , Wk respectively for all occurrences of these variables in t and it is defined by induction (on t) as follows: Definition 3.9 • �lt is a constant symbol or a variable other than W J , w2, . . . , Wk, then • (/' t • = Wi ( I < i < k), then fti t2 . . . tn (where n is an integer greater than or equal to I, f is an n-aryfunction symbol and t1, t2, . . ., tn are terms), then if t = tu I / W I ,U2 / W2 • · · · •llk /Wk == f t1 111 I q 1 .u2I ll- 2·· · · .• uk I Wk t2U ) I Wt ,Li2I u,2 ..... UkIWk · · · · · tnU! I Wl .U2I W2··-·•LlkIU'k · . For any natural number k, any pairwise distinct variables w 1 , w2, . . . , Wk, and terms t, u J, u2, . . . , u�c, the word tu 1 fw 1 ,u2f w2, ....uk fwk is a term. Proof The proof is obvious by induction on t. • Notation: Given two natural numbers k and h, k + h variables z 1 , 22, . . , Z h, Wk, a term t[ZI , 2 2 , . . , Zh , w 1 , w2 , . . . , Wk] , and k terms u , , u2 , . . . , W t, 1v2 , Uk , the term tu 1 ;w 1 .u2;w2, ..., uk f wk will be denoted by Lemma 3.10 . . . • , . Remark 3.11 • Obviously, it is merely for convenience in writing that we have listed the vari­ ables in an order such that those involved in the substitution appear at the end of'the list. It goes without saying that given, for example, a term 122 PREDICATE CALCULUS and two arbitrary terms u and u', we understand that the expression t [W I , U 1 , W3 , U, W 5] can be used to denote the term • • The notation involving brackets presents some inconveniences analogous to those we discussed earlier concerning substitutions in formulas of the pro­ positional calculus (see Chapter 1 ). We will use it, but with the usual precautions. As with the propositional calculus, it is appropriate to recall the fact that the substitutions defined above take place simultaneously; the same substitutions, implemented one after another, yield different results, in general, which depend, among other things, on the order in which they are peiformed. 3.1.4 Formulas of the language We will now undertake the definition, by induction, of the set of formulas of the language L. Here, first of all, are the formulas 'on the ground floor' (those that will have height 0); we call these the atomic formulas. A word W E W(L) isan atomicformula {fandonly ifthere exist a natural number n E N*, an n-ary relation symbol R, and n terms I t , t2, . . . , tn ofthe language L such that Definition 3.12 In the case where L is a language with equality and in T(L), we agree to write t and u are arbitrary terms t�u for the atomic formula � tu. We will denote the set of atomic formulas of the language L by At (L). Observe that we have unique readability for atomic formulas: we can easily convince ourselves by noting that an atomic formula becomes a term i f we replace its first symbol (which is a relation symbol) by a function symbol of the same arity; it then suffices to apply the unique readability theorem for terms to obtain unique readability for atomic formulas (the convention we introduced for the equality symbol presents no difficulty i n this matter). We may now proceed with the definition of the set of formulas of L . 1 23 SYNTAX Definition 3.13 The set F(L) of(jirst order)formulas of the language L is the smallest subset ofW(L) that • • contains all the atomicformulas; whenever it contains two words V and W, it also contains the words -. W, ( V v W), ( V 1\ W), ( V =} W), (V <=> W) and, for every natural number n, the words Vvn W and 3vn W. Given twoformulas F and G in F(L), theformulas -. F, ( F 1\ G), and ( F v G), are called, respectively: the negation of the formula F, the conjunction of the formulas F and G and the disjunction of the formulas F and G. We are naturally led to compare the definition above, or at least the part of it that concerns the propositional connectives, to the definition of propositional formulas given in Chapter 1 . We note in this context that the role played there by the propositional variables is played here by the atomic formulas. The major difference arises from the fact that there, the propositional variables were primary indecomposable ingredients whereas here, the atomic formulas are already the product of a fairly complicated construction. It is essential, in any case, not to imagine any analogy between the propositional variables of Chapter 1 and what, in this chapter, have been called variables; here they are certain symbols that are constituents of terms, which in turn are ingredients in the production of atomic formulas. The other obvious fundamental difference between the two situations is the appearance of quantifiers which provide new means for constructing formulas. B y analogy with Theorem 1 .3, the following theorem, whose proof is left to the reader, provides a description 'from below' of the set of formulas. Theorem 3.14 Set Fo(L) = At(L); and, for every integer m, Fm +I (L) = Fm (L) U {-.F : U { ( F a G) : F U {Vv k F : F Fm (L)} E Fm (L), G E :Fm (L), a E {A, v , =} , ¢> } } E Fm (L), k E N} U {3vk F: F E Fm(L), k E N} . F E We then have F(L) = U Fn (L). nEN As it should be, the height of a formula F E smallest integer k such that F E Fk ( L). F(L), denoted by h[F], is the 124 PREDICATE CALCULUS For first order formulas, there is a unique readability theorem: ( Unique readability theoremforformulas) For anyformula F E F(L), one and only one ofthe following five cases applies: Theorem 3.15 • • • F is an atomic formula (and there is then only one way in which it can be tread'); there is a uniqueformula G E F(L) such that F = -,G; there is a unique pair of.formulas ( G, H) E F (L) 2 and a unique symbol for a binary connective a E {A, v , ==>, <=:> } such that F (G a H); there exists a unique integer k and a unique formula G E F (L) such that F 'Vvk G; there exists a unique integer k and a unique formula G E F(L) such that F 3vkG. = • :::: • = Proof We can easily adapt the proof given for the case of formulas of the propo­ sitional calculus: here too, it is clear that the five cases are mutually exclusive and that at least one of the cases is applicable (ignoring the feature of unique­ ness). In the last two cases, for which the propositional calculus has no analogue, uniqueness is obvious. In the fi.rst case, unique readability has already been noted (in the paragraph that follows Definition 3.1 3); in the second and third cases, the proof from Chapter 1 carries over with no problems (in particular, the relevant four • lemmas concerning parentheses and proper initial segments remain valid). Here too, we can speak of the decomposition tree of a formula: relative to the propositional calculus, the changes are, on the one hand, that the leaves are the atomic formulas and, on the other hand, that there are three kinds of unary branching instead of one: F The sub-formulas of a first order formula are those that appear at the nodes of its decomposition tree. To be precise: Definition 3.16 The set sf(F) ofsub-formulas of a formula by induction as follows: if F is atomic, • sf ( F) • = {F}; if F = -,G, sf(F) = {F} U sf( G); F E F(L) is defined SYNTAX • if F = (G a H) 1 25 where a is a symbolfor a binary connective, sf(F) = { F } U sf( G) U sf(H); sf( F) = {F} u sf( G). 3.1.5 Free variables, bound variables, and closed formulas Given a natural number k and a formula F E F(L), the occur· rences, if any, of the variable Vk in the formula F can be of two kinds: free or bound. We proceed by induction: Definition 3.17 if F is atomic, then all occurrences of Vk in F are free; ifF = -�G, thefree occurrences ofvk in F are thefree occurrences ofvk in G: ifF = (G a H ) where a isa symbolfora binaryconnective, thefree occurrences ofvk in F are thefreeoccurrences ofvk in G and thefree occurrences ofvk in H : if F = YvhG or if F = 3vh(G), ( h =I= k), thefree occurrences ofvk in F are the free occurrences of Vk in G; �f F = YvkG or �f F = 3vk(G), none of the occurrences ofvk in F isfree. The occurrences of Vk in F that are not free are called bound . Concerning thepassagefrom theformula G to theformula 'VvkG (3vkG, respec­ tively) we say that the variable Vk has been universally quantified (existentially quantified, respectively) or that the formula G has been subjected to univer·· sal quantification (existential quantification, respectively) with respect to (or over) the variable VkExample 3.18 In the language L = { R , c, f} where R is a binary relation symbol, c is a constant symbol and f is a unary function symbol, consider the formula • • • • • F= Yvo(3viYvo(Rv i vo ==> -wvo � v3) 1\ Yv2(3v2(Rv1 V2 v fvo � c) 1\ v2 � v2)). I n F, all occurrences of vo and all occurrences of v2 are bound; the first two occurrences of v 1 are bound while the third is free; finally, the unique occurrence of v3 is free. The free variables in a formula F E F(L) are those variables that have at least one free occurrence in F. A closed formula is one in which no variable is free. Thus, in the preceding example, the free variables in F are VI and V3. Conse­ quently, F is not a closed formula. Definition 3.19 We should also note that a closed formula need not contain any quantifiers: the formula Rfcc is a closed atomic formula in the language of Example 3 . 1 8. 1 26 PREDICATE CALCULUS However, in a language without constant symbols, there are no closed formulas without quantifiers. Notation: Given a formula F E F(L) and pairwise distinct natural numbers i 1 , i 2 , . . , in, we will use the notation F = F[v;1 , v;2 , • • • , v;, ] to indicate that the free variables of the formula F are among v;1 , v;2 , • . • , V;1 • 1 As is the case for terms, we should note that for every formul a F E F(L), there exists an integer m such that . F = Definition 3.20 F rvo ' v l ' . . . ' Vm ] . Given a formula F F[ v;1 , v;2 , • • • , v;, J of the language L in which each of the variables v; v;2 , • • • , v;11 has at least one free occurrence, the formula = 1, and all similarformulas obtained by permuting the order in which the variables v; v;2, • • . , v;n are quant{fied are called universal closures of the formula F. 1, Observe that the universal closures of a formula are closed formulas. Remark 3.21 We hardly ever distinguish among the universal closures ofa for­ mula F and we speak of the universal closure of F, intending in this way to denote any one of them (the choice might be dictated by the order in which the free variables ofF occur or by the order of their indices or by some other con­ sideration). This abuse of language is unimportant: we will see that the various universal closures of aformula are all equivalentfor our intended purposes, both from the semantic point of view (in the sections thatfollow) andforformal proofs (see Chapter 4). Let us return to the formula F in Example 3 . 1 8. We said that the third oc­ currence of the variable v1 , as opposed to the fi rst two, is free. This is because, as the decomposition tree of F makes clear, the quantification 3vl ' acts' on the first two occurrences but not on the third. We say that the first two occurrences of VI are within the scope of the quantifi.er 3v1 • Anticipating a precise general definition, consider the occurrence in a formula F of a quantifi.er Qv (where Q denotes V or 3 and v the variable that necessarily follows Q in F). The word Qv is necessarily followed, in the word F, by a (unique) sub-formula G of F (the word QvG being, in turn, a sub-formula of F which could be character­ ized as the sub-formula of least height that contains the occurrence of Qv under consideration). Definition 3.22 Using thepreceding notation, the occurrences ofv that are within the scope of the quantifier Q v are the free occurrences of v in G as well as the occurrence of v that immediatelyfollows the quant�fier Q. 1 27 SYNTAX For example, in the formula 3v(((v � v) v Vv-,(v � v)) � v � v), the occurrences of v that are in the scope of the first quantifier are the first three and the last two. The fourth, fifth and sixth occurrences are excluded, despite their being in the 'geographical range' of 3v, because it is reasonable to agree that each occurrence of a variable is within the scope of at most one quantifier. 3 . 1 .6 Substitutions in formulas We will now define the notion of substitution of terms for free variables in a formula. The variables in a formula necessarily occur inside terms, and since substitution of terms for variables in a term has already been defined, our new definition would be automatic if it were not for an important restriction that will apply: substitution will only take place for the free occurrences of the variables under consideration. The definition is given, as we might expect, by induction. Consider a formula F, a natural number k, pairwise distinct variables w [, w2, . . . , Wk and terms u I , u 2, . . , u k . The word Fu , fw 1 ,u2jw2, ,ukfwJ.. (read: ' F sub u I replaces w 1 , u2 replaces w2, . . ., Uk replaces w k ) is the result of substituting the terms u 1 , u 2 , . . ., Uk respectivelyfor all free occurrences oftlu� variables W I , w21 . . ., Wk in the formula F and it is defined asfollows: Definition 3.23 . •.• ' • is the atomic formula Rti t2 . . . tn (where n is an integer greater than or equal to I, R is an n-ary relation symbol and ti, t2, . . ., tn are terms), then • if F == �G, • if F = (G • if F = VvG (v ¢:. if F then a H) where a is a symbolfor a binary connective, then {wl, w2, . . . , Wk }), then Fu 1 /W J ,u2fw2,---,uk/Wk • if F = 3vG (v ¢:. if F == Vw; G VvGu 1 /WI ,u2fw2,····ukfwk ; { w t , w2, . . . , Wk}), then Fu t jw, ,u2fw2.--.,uk/wk • == (i E { 1 , 2, . . . , = k}), then 3 vG u l fwt ,u2/W2,····uk /Wk ; 128 • PREDICATE CALCULUS if F = 3wi G (i Fu l fwt .U2/W2 E { 1 , 2, . . •... ,uk fwk . == , k}), then 3w i G u 1 /Wt ,uz/Wz , ... , u;-- I /w;_, , u ; + I /wi+I , .... uk fwk • , Zh , Given two natural numbers h and k, h + k variables z 1 , 22, W J , wz, . . . , Wk, a formula F[zt , 2 2 , . . . , Zh , W f , wz , . . . , Wk], and k terms U J , uz, . . . , Uk, the formula Fu1 fw1 ,u2 fw2 , ... ,ukf wk will be denoted by Notation: . . • This notation requires certain precautions similar to those already noted con­ cerning terms. Remark 3. 1 1 concerning the distinction between simultaneous and successive substitutions and the influence of the order of substitutions is relevant here too. Example 3.24 Let us revisit the formula that we have used previously as an example: F == Vvo (3vt Vvo ( R v 1 vo ::::} �vo � v3) 1\ Vvz ( 3vz ( R v l vz v f vo Let t denote the term jj·c. Then the word FrJ v 1 � c) 1\ vz � vz)). is The result of substituting terms for the free variables in a formula is always a formula: Lemma 3.25 Consider a formula F, a natural number k, pairwise distinct vari­ ables W J , wz, . . . , Wk and terms u 1 , uz, . . . , Uk. The word Fu1 fw1 .u2fw2 ,ukfwk is •... a formula. Proof The proof i s immediate by induction on F. • Another kind of substitution, analogous to what we have already encountered with the propositional calculus, consists in replacing, in a given formula of the language, an occurrence of some sub-formula by some other formula. Without going into the details of a precise definition, we are content to point out what is essential: the result of these substitutions is always a first order formula. More important, because they are more delicate, are substitutions that we will call renaming a bound variable. This involves, specifically, the substitution into a formula of a variable (and not an arbitrary term! ) for some given variable at all the occurrences of this variable that are in the scope of some given quantifier. For example, in our formula F = Vvo(3v 1 Vvo ( R v l vo ::::} _,vo � v3) 1\ Vvz(3vz( R v 1 vz v f vo � c) 1\ vz � vz)), 1 29 SYNTAX we can rename the bound variable vz by substituting Vs for all occurrences of vz that are within the scope of the quantifier \:lvz. This leads to the formula F == 'Vvo(3vt'Vvo(Rv i vo =} -.vo � v3) 1\ \:lvs(3vz (Rv! V2 v fvo � c) 1\ vs � vs)). ln general, if, in a formula H , there is a sub-formula QvG, then changing the name of the variable v to w in the scope of the quantifier Q v consists in simply replacing the sub-formula QvG in H by the formula Q w G wfv · So we see that the result obtained is necessarily a formula. Renaming a bound variable is a p1vcedure that deserves the great­ est care. We may be tempted to believe that this is merely an anodine transforma­ tion that preserves the 'meaning ' that we will later be giving toformulas (in other words, if we may anticipate, which transforms a formula into a logically equiv­ alentformula). However, this may be false if we do not take certain precautions (we will see which ones at the appropriate time: Proposition 3.54 and Chapter 4). For example, in theformula 3w'Vv v � w, changing the name ofthe variable v t(; w leads to the formula 3w'Vw w � w which, we may suspect, will not have the same meaning the first. Remark 3.26 as We have not reserved any special notation for these name changes of bound variables. Before concluding this presentation of syntax, we will mention one more type of substitution that is of a slightly different nature from the ones we have treated so far but which is just as common. We will not dally over its definition nor on the fact, important but easy to verify, that the result of these substitutions is always 3 first order formula. This involves starting from a formula J of the propositional calculus on an ar­ bitrary set P of propositional variables and substituting for each propositiona' variable, at each of its occurrences in J, a first order formula of the language L. Here is an example involving the language L = { R , f, c} used above. Sup­ pose that A, B and C are propositional variables and consider the propositiona I formula J = J [ A , B , C] = ( (A 1\ B) => and the following three formulas of the language (-.A v L: F = \:lvo-�Rv! vo; G = (vi � c ::::} 3vz R v t .f vz); H = -.f c ::::=: c. C)) 130 PREDICATE CALCULUS Then by substituting the formulas F, G, and H respectively for the variables B, and C i n the propositional formula J , w e obtain the first order formula A, which we may choose to denote by J [ F, G, H] if this does not create an ambiguity. Every formula without quantifiers is obtained by a substitution of the typejustdescribed: it suffices to treat the set ofatomicformulas ofthe language as the propositional variables. Remark 3.27 3.2 Structures The word 'structure' is generally understood in mathematics to mean a set on which a certain number of functions and relations (or internal operations) are defined along with, upon occasion, what are habitually called 'distinguished elements' . For example, the ordered field of real numbers i s the structure (IR, <, +, X' 0, 1 ) (sometimes, it is considered superfluous to specify the two identity elements so these might be omitted); the additive group of integers is the structure (Z, +) (or (Z, +, 0)). The formulas that we have described i n the previous section serve to express properties of such structures. For this purpose, the language must be adapted to the structure under consideration. Thus, we can easily guess that to speak of the ordered field of real numbers, the language will require a binary relation symbol R (intended to represent the order <), two binary function symbols f and g (for the two operations + and x ), and, upon occasion, two constant symbols c and d (for 0 and 1 ). In this situation, we would express the fact that 1 is an identity element for multiplication by saying that the first order formula Vvo(gvod � Vo 1\ gdvo ru Vo) is satisfied in the given structure. As for the formula it is satisfied because there exists an identity element for addition. But the formula: is not satisfied because the binary relation < on IR is not symmetric. What about the formula Rcvo? We realize that the question of whether this for­ mula is satisfied or not does not make sense in the absence of any specification concerning the individual vo. However, it seems natural to say that Rcvo is sat­ isfied when the real represented by vo is n and that it is not satisfied when vo denotes - 1. STRUCTURES 131 S o w e see that the concept o f satisfaction of a formula will need to be defined carefully and that the definition must take into account, in an essential way, the presence or absence of free variables in the formula under consideration. Another observation is forced upon us by these few examples: the syntax that we have defined requires us to break some entrenched habits; if the act of representing multiplication by some symbol other than x does not bother us much, the change from the usual way of writing vo g V t to writing gvo v 1 (so-called 'prefix' or 'Polish' notation) can be more disturbing. However, this Polish notation is necessary if we wish to have a uniform syntax, applicable in all situations and, in particular, to the representation of functions whose arity is greater than 2. The other considerable advantage of Polish notation is to free us from the use of parentheses which, with the standard way of writing binary operations, we could not do without. The same remark applies, to a lesser degree, to atomic formulas: we hardly ever write < vo v 1 instead of vo < v 1 , but the prefix notation is none the less encountered occasionally. The purpose of all these remarks is to prepare the reader for a series of definitions that are marked by the constraints of syntax. Following a path that is familiar to mathematicians, once these definitions have been given, we will immediately begin committing all sorts of abuses, writing vo x v 1 and 1 < 0 instead of gvo v1 and Rd c and, more generally, taking any measures that render a formula more intelligible, at the risk of scandalizing those for whom rigour is sacrosanct. But we are not there yet! We will, in an initial phase, give a series of purely algebraic definitions and properties that relate to structures, with syntax involved only incidentally (the language will serve to make precise the type of structure under consideration while the formulas will have no role to play in this first phase). After defining structures, we will examine certain tools that allow us to compare them: sub­ structures, restrictions, homomorphisms, isomorphisms. (t is only in Section 3.3 that we will approach the purely logical aspect of things by presenting the notion of satisfaction of a formula in a structure. 3.2.1 Models of a language L that is not necessarily a language with equality. A model of the language L, or L-structure, is a structure M Consider a first order language Definition 3.28 consisting of a non-empty set M, called the domain or the base set or the underlying set of the structure M; for each constant symbol c of L, an element eM of M called the interpretation of the symbol c in the model M; for every natural number k > 1 andfor eve1y k-ary function symbol f of L, a mapping fM from M k into M (i.e. a k-ary operation on the set M) called the interpretation of the symbol f in the model M; • • • 1 32 • • PREDICATE CALCULUS for every natural number k > 1 andfor every k-ary relation symbol R of L, a subset R M of (i.e. a k-ary relation on the set called the interpretation of the symbol R in the model M. In the case where L is a language with equality, we say that the model M respects equality {f ""M , the interpretation in M of the equality symbol of L. is the equality relation on (i.e. is the set { (a, b) E : a = b}, also called the diagonal of Mk M2 ). M) M M2 As we have already mentioned, only exceptionally (see Section 3. 7) will we deal with languages without equality. Thus, in the absence of any indication to the contrary, 'language' and 'model' will always mean, respectively, 'language with equality' and �model that respects equality'. It i s important to remember that the base set of a first order structure must be non-empty. In practice, models will be described in the following way: we will denote models by calligraphic letters (usually M or N) and will usually use the corresponding Latin letter to denote the underlying set; we will then provide the interpretations of the various symbols for constants, functions and relations (preferably in the same order that was used in the presentation of the language): this may range from a simple enumeration (in circumstances where there are standard symbols or names for these interpretations) to a more laboured definition. Thus, if the language L = { R, f, c} involves a binary relation symbol R, a unary function symbol f and a constant symbol c, it will suffice to write N = (�, <, cos, n ) to define the model o f L i n which the base set i s the set of reals and in which the interpretations of the symbols R , f and c are respectively the usual order relation, the map x � cos x, and the real number n . On the other hand, we would need a bit more space to define the L-structure M= (M, RM . fM , eM ) whose underlying set is the set of natural numbers that are not divisible by in which • • • the relation RM is defined by the following: for every a and b in R M if and only if gcd(a, b) = 3; M the map J i s the one which, to each element a a + I oa ; and E 5, and M, (a, b) E M, associates the integer eM is the first prime number which, written in base 1 0. requires at least a million digits. We emphasize that in this example, the language is one with equality and that the model M respects equality since there was no mention to the contrary. 1 33 STRUCTURES It is obviously essential to make a clear distinction between a symbol of the lan­ guage and its interpretations in various models; this explains the somewhat clumsy notation sM to denote the interpretation of the symbol s in the model M. Despite this, we will omit mention of the model in contexts where there is no possible confusion. It sometimes happens that it is the symbols denoting the relations and operations of a particular structure that determine our choice of symbols of the language appropriate for that structure. Thus, for the structure N = (JR., < , cos, n ) . we might choose the language { <, cos, rr_} where < is a binary relation symbol, cos is a unary function symbol and n. is a constant symbol. We will have understood that the underlining is, in a way, the inverse of overlining (underlining represents passing from the structure to the language, while overlining (or barring) represents N passing from the language to the structure). For example, cos = cos. This kind of notation will be used i n particular for arithmetic (in Chapter 6). In contexts where additional knowledge of the interpretations of the symbols for constants, functions and relations is not necessary, we will speak of 'an L-structure M = (M, . . . ) '. 3.2.2 Substructures and restrictions How can we pass from a structure to another structure that is 'larger' ? There are two rather natural ways to imagine this passage: either we enlarge the underlying set and extend the given functions and relations in an appropriate way, keeping the language unchanged; (in this case, the result is called an extension of the original structure); or else, we keep the same underI ying set and add new relations, new functions or new constants to this set; we are consequently obliged simultaneously to enrich the language by adding a matching collection of new symbols to it. (In this case, the resulting structure is called an expansion, or enrichment, of the original structure.) It is unfortunate that the use of the two very similar words, 'extension' and 'expansion' , can be the source of some confusion; it is vital to avoid this confusion. Given two L-structures M (M, . . . ) and N (N, . . . ), M is an extension ofN and N is a substructure (or submodel) of M �fand only if the following conditions are satisfied: tv is a subset of M; for eveiJ' constant symbol c of L, Definition 3.29 = = • • • for every natural number k > I and every k-aryfunction symbol f of L, JN = f M r Nk ; 1 34 • PREDICATE CALCULUS for every natural number k > I and every k ary relation symbol R of L, - Thus, for N to be a substructure of M, the requirement is that the interpreta­ tions in N of the symbols of L be the restrictions to the subset N of their interpre­ tations in M. This has an important consequence for the constants and functions of the structure M. On the one hand, if e is a constant symbol, the element eM of M must belong to the subset N (since eN = eM ). On the other hand, if f is a k-ary function symbol of the language L, the restriction of the map J M to the N subset N k must be the map J , i.e. a map from Nk into N. We conclude from this that the subset N must be closed (or stable or invariant) under the k-ary operation -M f . In other words, given an L-structure M and a subset N c M, the existence of a n L-structure whose base set i s N and which is a substructure of M requires, first of all, that the set N is non-empty, and second, that N contains all the interpretations in M of the constant symbols of L and is closed under all the functions of the structure M . It is not difficult to verify that these conditions are also sufficient; when they are satisfied, the substructure is obviously unique. Let us examine, once again, the structure N = = (M, . . . ) (IR, < , cos, rr) that i s a model of the language L = ( R, f, e). This does not admit a substructure whose underlying set is [ - 1 , 1 ] because the interpretation of the constant symbol e is n , which does not belong to this subset of JR. Nor does it admit a substructure whose underlying set is [0, n ] since this subset ofiR is not closed under the cosine function, which is the interpretation in N of the function symbol f. There is, on the other hand, a substructure of N whose underlying set is A = [ -rr , n ]; it is the substructure A = (A , <, cos f A , n ) . This constraint relating to functions has no counterpart for relations: if L is a language with no symbols for constants nor for functions and if M = (M, . . . ) is a model for this language, then for any non-empty subset N of M, there is one (and only one) L-structure whose base set is N and which is a substructure of M: i t i s the structure i n which the interpretation o f every relation symbol i s obtained by taking the trace on N of its interpretation in M (namely, for a symbol whose arity is k, its intersection with N k ). In general, although there may not be a substructure of a given structure whose underlying set is some given subset N, there is, none the less, a substructure that is minimal, in a certain sense, whose underlying set includes the given subset N : this is called the substructure generated by N. This concept is described in detail in Exercise 3. 12. STRUCTURES 1 35 Let us now turn to expansions (or enrichments) of structures (and hence of languages). Let L and L' be two first order languages such that L c L' (we say, in this case, that L' is an expansion or enrichment of L and that L is a restriction of L'). Let M be an L-structure and M' be an L' -structure. M' is an enrichment (or expansion) of M and M is a restriction of M' {fand only if M and .M' have the same underlying set and each symbolfor a constant, a function or a relation of the language L has the same interpretation in the L-structure M as in the L'-structure M'. Very simply, this means that M' is an enrichment of M if and only if M' is obtained from the L-structure M by adding to it the interpretations of those symbols for constants, functions or relations of the language L' that were not already present in the language L. We also say that M is the reduction (or reduct) of M' to the language L . For example, where L is the language { R, f, c} and where Lo is the language { R}, the L -structure Definition 3.30 N = (�, < , cos, n ) i s an enrichment (or expansion) o f the Lo-structure (�. <) . 3.2.3 Homomorphisms and isomorphisms single language L is under consideration here. Let M = (M, . . . ) and N ( N, . . . ) be two L-structures and let ¢ be a map from M into N. A = The map ¢ is a homomorphism of L -structures from M into N ifand only ifthe following conditions are satisfied: for every constant symbol c of L, Definition 3.31 • • for evefJ' natural number n > 1, for every n-ary function symbol f of L and for all elements a 1 , az, . . . , an belonging to M, • for every natural number k > l,for every k-ary relation symbol R of L andfor all elements a 1 , az, . . . , ak belonging to M, 1 36 PREDICATE CALCULUS Thus, a homomorphism from one L-structure into another is a map from the base set of the first into the base set of the second which 'respects' all the relations, functions and constants of these structures. Definition 3.32 A monomorphism of L-structures from M morphismftvm M into N which has the following ptvperty: into N is a homo­ for every natural number k > 1 , for every k-ary relation symbol R of L ( *) andfor all elements a 1 , a2, . . . , ak belonging to M , M -N (at , a2, . . . , ak) E R �fand only (f(¢ (aJ ) , ¢ (a2) , . . . , ¢ (ak)) E R . - As our definition of monomorphism, we could just as well taken Definition 3.31 and replaced its third clause by condition (*) above. Lemma 3.33 Every monomorphism is injective. We must remember here that we are only considering languages with equality and models that respect equality. If ¢ is a monomorphism from M into N, property (*) applied to the equality symbol � shows that for all elements a and b of M, we have Proof (a, b) E -.- M if and only if (¢(a), ¢ (b)) E ;:vN , which is to say that a = b if and only if ¢ (a) = ¢ (b). • Lemma 3.34 Let N = (N, . . . ) be an L-structure and let N, be a subset of N; for the existence ofa substructure ofN whose underlying set is N1 , it is necessary and sufficient that there exists an L-structure M = (M, . . . ) and a monomorphism ¢ ftvm M into N such that the subset Nt is the image of¢. Proof First, suppose that there is a substructure N, of N whose base set is N 1 • Then Definitions 3 .29 and 3.32 clearly show that the identity map from N1 into N 1 is a monomorphism from N, into N whose image is Nt . Conversely, suppose there exists an L-structure M = (M, . . ) and a monomor­ phism ¢ from M into N whose image is NJ . Then for every constant symbol c of L, we have eN = ¢ (eM ) , hence eN E Nt ; similarly, for every k-ary function symbol f of L (k > I ) and for all elements a 1 , a2, . . . , ak belonging to N 1 , we can find elements b b2 , . . . , bk of M such that ¢ (b;) = a; for 1 < i < k, so we then have -N -M (b 1 . b2 . . . . , bn)), f (a1,a2. . . - , an) = ¢ (/ . 1, f (at,a2 . . . . , a11) belongs to N, . We may now conclude, based which proves that -N on the paragraphs that followed Definition 3.29, that there exists a substructure of • N whose base set is N1 . Definition 3.35 A n isomorphismjivm an L-structure M ontoanother L-structure N is a monomorphismftvm M into N that is surjective. SATISFACTI0N 0 F F0 RMULAS I N ST RUCTURES 1 37 An automorphism of an L-structure M is an isomorphism from M onto M. It is clear that if a bijective map ¢ : M � N is an isomorphism of the structure M onto the structure N, then the inverse map ¢-I : N � M is an isomorphism of N onto M . If there is an isomorphism between two structures, they are said to be isomorphic. Remark 3.36 Itfollows from Lemma 3.34 that any monomorphism from a struc­ ture M == (M . . . . ) into a structure N == (N, . . . ) may be considered as an isomorphism of M onto a substructure ofN. Example 3.37 • • • (in which the details are left to the reader) Where the language consists of one constant symbol c and one binary function symbol g, the structures (JR+ , 1 , x} and (IR, 0, +) are isomorphic; the map x � In x from JR+ into JR is witness to this fact. With this same language, the map n � ( - 1 )12 is a homomorphism from the structure (Z, 0, +) into the structure ({- 1 , 1 } , 1 , x ). I n the language whose only symbol i s the binary relation symbol R, the struc­ tures (JR, <) and ((0, 1 ) , <) are isomorphic thanks to the map 1 x � • - + -I arctan x 2 Jr from JR into (0, 1). However, the identity map from (0, 1 ) into JR is only a monomorphism. The reader will have noted the abuse of language that consists in using the same symbol to denote the order relation in JR and the one in (0, 1 ). With this same language, consider the structures M = ({0, I }, ==) and N = ( {0, I }, <). The identity map from {0, I } into {0, 1 } is obviously bijective and is a homomorphism from M into N, but it is not an isomorphism. This shows that we cannot replace 'monomorphism' by 'homomorphism' in Definition 3.35. 3.3 Satisfaction of formulas in structures 3.3.1 Interpretation in a structure of the terms We have already mentioned that the terms of a language will serve to denote objects. Suppose that the language involves a constant symbol c and two function symbols f and g that are unary and binary, respectively. We suspect that in a structure M == (M, c, f, g ), the term ffc will be interpreted by f(f(c)), which is an element of M, and the term gfcgcc by the element g(f(c), g(c, c)). But to interpret the term fvo, we first need to know what element is denoted by vo. Now, we will not be giving fixed interpretations in a structure for the variables (otherwise, we wouldn't have called them variables). To be more precise, the interpretation in a structure of a symbol for a variable can vary. This leads us to the fact that the 1 38 PREDICATE CALCULUS interpretation of the term fvo will depend on the interpretation given to vo. Thus for any element a of M, we will say, when the interpretation of vo is a, that the interpretation of the term fvo in M is the element .f(a) . It is obvious that, when the interpretation of V4 is a, the term f V4 will have this same interpretation. As for the term gfgv2cvi , it will be interpreted, when VI is interpreted by a and v2 by b, by the element g (f(g(b, c)), a). Let n be a natural number, let wo, W I , . . . , Wn- 1 b e n pairwise distinct variables, let t = tfwo , w 1 , . . . , Wn- 1 ] be a term of the language L, let M (M, . . . ) be an L-structure and let ao, at, . . . , an- I be n elements of M; the interpretation ofthe term t in the L-structure M when the variables wo, w 1, , Wn- 1 are interpreted respectively by the elements ao, a 1 , . . . , an- 1 is an element of M; it is denoted by Definition 3.38 = • -M t [wo � ao, w 1 � a 1 , . . . , Wn - 1 � • • an - I ] and is defined by induction on t asfollows: • ift = Wj (0 < j < n -M t • ift = � a o, w 1 � a 1 , . . . , wn - l � an- t ] = aj ; c (a constant symbol of L), -M t • [wo 1 ), [wo � ao, WI if t f t1 t2 . . . tk (where k tt, t2, . . . , tk are terms of L), = -M t [wo � ao, -M -M f fwo (lt WJ � a t , . . . , Wn - 1 E N*, � � an -I ] = -M c ; f is a k-ary function symbol of L and a 1 , . . . , Wn-1 � an - I ] ao, . . . , Wn - 1 an - d , -M t2 [wo ao, . . . , Wn- l an- I ] , . . . , -M tk [wo ao, WI a1 . . . , Wn- 1 ---+ = ---+ � � � � I n practice, we will denote the element iM r wo simply by . ---7 � an - J ) ao, . . . ' Wn- 1 I � . an- I ] more despite the fact that this notation is ambiguous: indeed, it contains no reference to a specific sequence of free variables (including those that have one or more occurrences in t ) ; there are, in fact, an infinite number of such sequences which differ from one another either by containing extra variables (that do not occur in t) or by the order in which these variables are listed. Were it not for this ambiguity, it would have been practical to define, as is sometimes done, the interpretation of t 139 S ATISFACTION OF FORMULAS IN STRUCTURES in the structure M as a map from Mn into M, i.e. the map that, to each n-tuple (ao, a I , . . . , an - I ), assigns the element -M t [wo ----+ ao, w 1 ----+ aJ, • • • , wn - 1 ----+ an - I ] . None the less, this simplified notation will prevail in most concrete situations in which the context removes all ambiguity. For example, in the language under consideration at the beginning of this subsection, if t is the term gvo fv J and M is the structure (IR, 0, cos, +), everyone will understand that for all reals a and b, tM [a , b] denotes the real a -r- cos b (however, the situation would already be less clear if the term had been gvi f v o : it would be prudent in this instance to be precise, for example, by specifying t = t [ vo , vt ] or by relying on the official notation). In the preceding definition, it is clear that the order in which the interpretations of the variables are spec(fied is immaterial: precisely, for any per­ mutation of the set (0, 1 , . . . , n - 1 }, we have Remark 3.39 a -M t [wo � ao, . . . , Wn- I � an -d = t M [Wa(O) ----+ aa (O) , . · . , Wa(n - I ) � aa(n-J ) ] . Strictly speaking, this would require a proof by induction on t , but it is obvious. The purpose of the lemma that follows is to show that the interpretation of a term in a structure does not depend on the values assigned to variables that do not occur in it. Lemma 3.40 Let m and n be two natural numbers, let wo, w I , . . . , Wn- I , z o, Z I , . . . , Zm - 1 be m + n pairwise distinct variables and let t be a term of L whose variables are among wo, W I , , Wn - I (while zo, Z 1 , , Zm- 1 do not occur in t) • • . • . . so that it makes sense to write t = t [W0, W 1 , . . . , Wn- t 1 = t [ W0 , W 1 , · · · , Wn - 1 , ZO, Z I , . · . , Zm- 1 ] ; then for any L-structure M = ( M , . . . ) and for any elements ao, a 1 , bo, b 1 , . . , bm- 1 of M, we have . . . , an- 1 , . --M t [wo ----+ ao, W I --+ a1 , . . . , Wn- 1 � an- d = -M t [wo ----+ ao, . . . , Wn- I --+ an- 1 , Z O ----+ bo , · · · , Zm-I ----+ bm_ t J . The proof is immediate by induction on t. • We will now examine the effect of a substitution in a term on its interpretation. Proof Let n be a natural number and let wo, W I , , Wn - 1 be n + 1 painvise distinct variables; consider two terms ofL, t = t [wo, w 1 , . . . , Wn- d and u = u[v, wo, w r , . . . , Wn-d and letr denote theterm u [t, wo, w 1 , . . . , W n- I ], i.e. r is the term U tfv· Proposition 3.41 v, • • • 140 P R E D I C ATE C A L C U L U S Thenfor any L-structure M = (M, . . . ) andfor any elements ao, a 1 , . . . , an- l of M, we have rM [wo -� ao, WJ -----, � aL , Wn - l ____..,... an - I j -M [WO � ao, . . . , Wn- 1 � an-- d, WO � ao, =U M [ V -� t , • • � -""- • · · · , Wn-1 -� an- l J · Note first of all that the variables that occur in r are among wo, WJ , . . . , w12 - 1 , so that the term on the left side of the equality makes sense. The equality is proved by induction on the term u: Proof • • • • i fu is a constant symbol c o f L, we have r = u = c and each side ofthe equality denotes the element eM ; if u is the variable w; (0 < i < n - 1), r = u = w; and each side of the equality denotes the element a;; if u is the variable v� we have r = t and each side of the equality denotes the element -tM [wo � ao, wt -� a 1 , · · - , Wn--l -� an- 1 ] ·, if u = fut U2 · · · u k (where k E N*, f is a k-ary function symbol of L and u l , u2, . . . , Uk are terms of L), then by setting rt = u 1 t/v , r2 = u2,1L. , . . . , rk = Ukt/v , we have the induction hypothesis is that for i E { 1 , 2, M Yi [wo -� ao, WI -� a t , . . . , Wn- l -M u; �LV -� -M t [wo -� ao, . - . , Wn- 1 --7 � . . . , k}, lln- t J = an- I ], wo --7 ao, . . . , Wn-1 -� an- 1] ·, so we see, by referring to the definition above, that -U M rtV -� -t M [wo -� ao� · . - Wn-1 -� an- d� WO -� ao� . . . � Wn- 1 -� an- 1 . ] � • 3.3.2 Satisfaction of the formulas in a structure We are given a language L, an L-structure M = (M, . . . ) , a natural number n, n pairwise distinct variables wo, w 1 , , Wn- 1 , n elements ao, a 1 , . . . , an-- 1 of M and a formula • . F = F[wo, W J , • • . . , Wn- 1 1 E F(L). 141 S ATISFACTION OF F O R M U L A S I N STRUCTURES The definition that follows, which will be given by induction on the formula F, will give meaning to the following phrase: 'the formula F is satisfied in the structureM when the variables wo, WI are interpreted respectively by the elements a o . a 1 , . . . , an -I ·' , . . . • Wn - 1 The notation for this property will be (M : wo � ao , WI � a ] ' . . . ' Wn- 1 � an- t ) I== F (the symbol I== is read 'satisfies'). In practice, as with the interpretation of terms, we will most often resort to a way of speaking and a notation that are less cumbersome, but not without ambiguity. We will write M I== F[ao, a 1 , . . . , an- d and will say M satisfies F of ao, a I , . . . , an- I ; or the n-tuple (or the sequence) (ao, a 1 , . . . , an - I ) satisfies the formula F in M ; or the formula F is satisfied in M by the n-tuple (ao, a 1 , . . . , an-I ) ; or the n-tuple (ao, a 1 , . . . , an - I ) satisfies the formula F[wo, w 1 , . . . , Wn - I l in M. The last of these formulations is intended to recall our understanding that wo, w 1 , . , Wn - 1 are to be interpreted respectively by ao, a t , . . . , a11_J ; the first three formulations ignore this. The ambiguity here is analogous to the one mentioned previously concerning terms: the choice of some fixed ordered list of variables that includes the free variables of F is left unspecified. But, just as for terms, the context will most often make things clear. For the moment, the reader is invited to interpret the notation . . M I= F[ao, a t , . . . , an- d as mere shorthand; one should not consider that F[ao, a 1 , . . . , an- I ] denotes a formula. In fact, none of what has preceded would authorize this. None the less, such a point of view will be possible a bit later; we will atthatpointhavethe means to justify it (Theorem 3.86). 142 P R E D l C AT E C A LC U L U S The negation of ' (M : wo � ao, w 1 � a 1 , . . . , Wn- 1 � an- I ) I= F' is written (M : wo � ao, WI � Q } ' • • • ' Wn - l � an-I ) � F or again, using the simplified notation M � F [ao, a t , . . . , an- d Here is the promised defi.nition. Definition 3.42 • 1. If F is the atomic formula R t1 t2 tk where k is a natural number greater than or equal to I, R is a k-ary relation symbol of L and t 1, t2, . . . , tk are terms of L (such that for each i E { 1 , 2 . . . , k}, t; == t; [ wo, W I , . . . , Wn-J D , we have(M : wo � ao, Wt � a 1 , . . . , Wn- 1 � an-I ) F= F ifand only if -M [WQ � ao, . . . , Wn-1 � an- t J , . . . , -M (t1 tk [WO � ao, . . . , Wn-1 ---* -M an- d ) E R ; (in particular, {fL is a language with equality and ifM is a model that respects equality, we have (M : wo � ao, WJ � a t , . . . , Wn-- 1 � an- t ) I= t 1 � t2 if and only if -M t2 fwo ----* ao, Wn- l � an- 1 1. lt [ WO � ao, . . . , Wn-l � an- d == --M 2. If F == -, G: (M : wo � ao, WI � at , . . . , Wn- l � an- d I= F if and only if (M : WQ � ao, W I � a J , . . . ' Wn- l � an - 1 ) � G. 3. IfF == (G A H): (M : wo � ao, WJ � a 1 , . . . , Wn- 1 � an- I ) F= F ifand only if (M : wo � ao, W I � a i , . . . , Wn- 1 � an- I ) I= G and (M : wo � ao, WJ � a t , . . . , Wn- I � an- i ) I= H. 4. If F == (G v H): (M : wo � ao, Wi � at , . . . , Wn-- l an-I ) != F ifand only if (M : wo � ao, w I � a 1 , . . . , Wn- I � an-I ) I= G or (M : WQ � ao, W I � al , . . . ' Wn- 1 � an- I ) I= H. 5. �f F == (G ==> H): (M wo ----* ao, WI ----* a1 , . . . , Wn- I ----* a - I ) I= F (f and only (f (M : U{) � ao, W I � a 1 , . . . , Wn-I ----* an- I ) � G or (M : wo � ao, w 1 � a , ' . . . ' Wn -I � an- I ) I= H. 6. /f F == (G <=> H): (M : wo � ao, WI � a t , . . . , Wil-l � an�- I ) I= F {(and only �f (M : wo � ao, W J � a1, . . . , Wn- 1 ----* an-I ) I= G and (M : WQ � ao, W J � a ) , . . . , Wn-1 � an- d I= H; or else (M : WQ � ao, W I � a i , . . . ' Wn- I ----* an- d jt: G and (M : wo ----* ao, W I � G} , . . . , Wn- 1 � Gn- I ) � H. · · · · · • • • -7 • : • n · , SATISFACTI0N 0F F0RMULAS IN STRUCTURES • If F = \fvG (where v E V - { wo, W I , . . . , Wn-1 }): (M : wo � ao, W I � G I , . . . , Wn- l � an-I ) F= F {f and only iffor every element a E M, (M v � a, wo ao, w I � a 1 , . . . , Wn- 1 � an - I ) F= G. 8. If F = 3vG (where v E V - { wo, W I , . . . , Wn- d ) : (M : wo � ao, WI � a 1 , . . . , Wn- 1 � an - I ) I= F if and only {(for at least one element a E M, wn-I � an- I ) F= G. ( M : v � a, wo � ao, w 1 � a I 9. /f F = Ywi G (where O < i < n 1 ) (M : wo � ao, W I � a I , . . . , Wn- l � an I ) F= F {f and only iffor every element a E M, (M : wo � ao, Wi-I � Gi-l , Wi � a, wi+l � Gi+I , Wn- I � an- I ) F= G. 1 0. If F = 3wi G (where 0 < i < n - 1 ), (M : wo � ao, W I � G I , . . . , Wn-1 � an- I ) F= F {f and only iffor at least one element a E M, (M : wo � ao, Wi-1 � ai- l , Wi � a, Wi+l -;... Gi+l , Wn-I an- t ) F= G. 7. � : • , • 1 43 - • • • , , - • -;... For a correct reading of this definition, it is appropriate to recall that in clauses 2, 3, 4, 5, and 6, the free variables of the formula G as well as those of H are among wo, WI , . . . , Wn-1 ; in clauses 7 and 8, the free variables of G are among v, wo, W J , . . . , Wn-1 ; and finally in clauses 9 and 1 0, the free variables of G are among wo, wi- 1 , Wi+ I , Wn- 1 (the variable wi is no longer free in F , though this in no way prevents us from considering that F = F[ wo, WI , . . . , Wn-- d ) . This definition notably applies to the case when the formula F is closed. In this context the property becomes M f= F which is read: 'M satisfies F' . When this property is satisfied, we also say that F is true in M, or also that M is a model of F. The definition ofsati�faction does not depend on the order in which the interpretations of the variables are spec{fied. This means that for any permu­ tation ofthe set {0, 1 , . . , n -- 1 }, we have Remark 3.43 . a (M : wo --7 ao, Wt � a 1 , . . . , Wn- I � Gn- I ) F= F {(and only if {M : Wa(O) � Ga(O), W a(l) ----;... Ga(l) , . . . , Wa(n-1 ) � Ga(n-1) } F F. The proof is obvious: the argument is by induction on F; the case for atomic formulas is governed by Remark 3 .39; the rest goes without saying. We have observed that the list of variables that includes the free variables of a given formula can be artificially lengthened (by adding to this list variables that have no free occurrence in the formula). It is natural to ask whether this can have 1 44 PREDICATE CALCULUS any effect on the notion of satisfaction that has just been defined. The answer, in the negative, is given by the next lemma. Let m and n be two natural numbers, let wo, W t , . . . , Wn- b zo, Z I , . . . , Zm - 1 b e m + n pairwise distinct variables and let F be a formula of L whose free variables are among wo, W I , . . . , Wn - 1 (while zo, z 1 , Zm- l have no free occurrence in F) so that it makes sense to write Lemma 3.44 • • . , F == F[wo, W t , . . . , Wn - 1 ] == F [wo, W I , . . . , Wn- I , zo, Z I , . • . , Zm- d. Thenfor any L-structure M == (M, . . . } andfor any elements ao, a1, . . . , an-I ' bo, b t , . . . , bm-1 of M, the following p1vperties are equivalent: ( 1 ) (M wo --:)> ao, W I � a t , . . . , Wn-- 1 an -d F= F (2) (M : wo�ao, . . . , Wn- t --:)o an - 1 , zo�bo, . . . , Zm- l � bm-d F= F Proof The proof is, of course, by induction on F. If F is the atomic formula Rtt t2 . . . tk where k is a natural number greater than or equal to 1, R is a k-ary relation symbol of L and t t , t2, . . . , tk are terms of L , then, by hypothesis, for each i E { I , 2 , . . . , k }, we are free to write one o r the -� : • other of t; = t; [ WO, WI , . . . , Wn - d Or li == t; [WO, W I , . . , Wn - 1 , ZQ, Z t , . · · . , Zm-d. S o w e may conclude, using Lemma 3 .40, that -M t; [wo � ao, Wt � a t , . . · , Wn- 1 � an- I ] -M [wo � ao, . . . , Wn- 1 � an- I , Z0 � bo, , Zm- l � bm- 1 ], == t; · · · which, by the definition of satisfaction (Clause I ), yields the equivalence between ( l ) and (2). • • For those stages of the induction that refer to the symbols for connectives, the proof is obvious. It is also obvious for the cases where F = {zo, z 1 , . . . , Zm- t l . where h E {0, 1 , . . . , m VvG or F = 3vG when the variable v does not belong to • If F = VZh G l } , then the free variables of G are among Zh, wo, W t , . . . , Wn- 1 · Property ( 1 ) is verified if and only if for every element b of M, (M : Zh � b, wo � ao, W t � -- a 1 , . . . , lVn - 1 � an- I ) I= G , which is equivalent, by the induction hypothesis and Remark 3.43, to: for all b E M, wo � ao, . . , Wn- 1 � an- t , zo � bo, . . . , . . . , Zh-1 � bh- l , Zh � b, Zh+l bh+I , . Zm-1 � bm- I} (M : . --7 · · , F G, 145 S AT I S F ACTION OF F O R M U L A S I N STRUCTURES but this means, by definition (Clause 9): (M : wo a o, . . . , Wn- 1 an- I , zo � bo, . . . , Zh-l � bh-1 , Zh � bh , Zh+I � bh+J , . . . , Zm - 1 � bm-d F= 'Vvh G, � � . . . ' which is precisely property (2) . • The case F = 3vh G where h E {0, 1 , . . . , m - • 1 } is treated analogously. llere is a very usefu] consequence of the definition of satisfaction; it concerns substitutions into formulas. Proposition 3.45 Suppose n and p are natural numbers, v, wo, w 1, . . . , Wn-1 , uo, u t , . . . , Up-l aren+p+1 pairwise distinct variables, t = t[wo, W J , . . . , Wn-l ] is a term of L and F = F [v , wo, W t , . , Wn-1 , uo, U J , , Up- d is a formula of L. Suppose further that in the formula F, there is nofree occurrence of v in the scope ofany quant{fication Vw; or 3w; (0 < i < n - 1). Thenfor any L-structure M = (M, . . . } andfor any elements ao, a t . . , an - J , bo h t , . . . , bp -I of M, the following two properties are equivalent: ( I ) (M : wo � ao, . . . . Wn- 1 ---+ an- I · uo � bo. . . . , Up-1 � bp t } F Ft;v; v ---+ tM [wo � ao, WI � a1 , . . . , Wn- 1 ---+ an- d, wo � ao. (2) (M WJ ---+ aJ , , Wn-1 ---+ an- l , UO ____. bQ, U J ---+ bJ , . . . , Up- 1 ---+ bp-l ) I== F. Proof Note first of all that the free variables of the formula Ft/v are among wo, w 1 , , wn - l , uo, u 1 , , up- 1 , which shows that property ( 1 ) makes sense. The proof proceeds by induction on F. If F is the atomic formula Rtt t2 . . . tk where k is a natural number greater than or equal to 1 , R is a k-ary relation symbo] of L and tt . t2, . . . , tk are terms of L, then, for each i E { 1 , 2, . . . , k } , we may write . . . • . , . , -- : • • . • . • . • . • li = t; [V , WQ, lV1 , • • . , Wn-J , UQ, U ) , • • • Up- t l , and, according to Clause 1 in the definition of satisfaction, if we set r; = t;tfv ' property ( 1 ) means Wn 1 � an- I , UO __,. bo . . · , Up-l ---+ bp - J J , . . . , rk M [wo ---+ ao, . . . , Wn- l � an-I , uo ---+ bo, . . . , Up-l ____. b p- d ) E -M R ; (rrM [WO ---+ ao , · · · , - now, by virtue of Proposition , . 3.41, if for each i E { 1 , 2, . . . , k} we set bi = ti M [v � -t M [wo ---+ ao, . . . , Wn-l ---+ an-d, wo ---+ ao, . . . . , Wn-l � an-I , UO � bo, . . . , Up-1 bp- t J] , � . . . · 1 46 PREDJCATE CALCULUS this becomes equivalent to i.e. (by Clause erty (2) : 1 of the definition) to the following assertion, which is prop­ (M : v � -M t [wo � ao, Wt � a t , . . . , Wn-1 � am- l L wo � ao, Wt � at , . . . , Wn-1 � an- 1 , uo bo, Ut � b t , . . . , Up- I � bp-1 ) -� f= F. • • The stages of the induction that concern the symbols for connectives are obvious. Suppose F is the formula 3zG ; the free variables of G are among z, v, wo, w 1 , . . . , 1Vn-1 , uo, u 1 , . . . , u p- 1 . If z is one of the 1n; , then by hypothesis v has no freeoccurrence in G, nor in F; ifz == v, v has no free occurrence in F ; in both these cases, Ft;v == F; the equivalence of ( 1 ) and (2) is then a straightforward consequence of the previous lemma. If z is different from v and from all the w; (0 < i < n - 1), then we have Ft /v == 3zG1 ;v; in the case where z differs as well from all the uj (0 < j < p - 1 ) then z is not among the variables of t so property ( 1 ) is equivalent to the existence of an element a E M such that (M : z � a, wo � ao, . . . , Wn- 1 � an- 1 , uo � bo, . . . , Up- I I= G r;v ; ---7 hp-t } by the induction hypothesis, this i s also equivalent to the existence o f an element a E M such that -M t [wo � ao, . . . , Wn-1 � an-d, z � a , wo � ao, . . . M � : ( . . . ' Wn-1 an- 1 ' uo bo, . . . ' Up- 1 bp- 1) F= G, v -� ---7 ---7 or, in other words, to the following assertion which is precisely property (2): {M : v � -M at , . . . , Wn-1 ---7 an-1 1 , wo t [wo � ao, WI . . . , Wn- 1 � an-1 , uo � bo, . . . , Up-1 � bp- t } � 3zG. ---7 ---7 ao, . . . In the case where z == u j (0 < j < p - 1 ), it suffices to repeat the five previous ' lines omitting r.u j � bj from the assignments for the variables. • The case involving universal quantifi cation is similar. • In this proposition, the hypotheses that concern the variables are rather com­ plicated. Most of the time, we will have stronger (and simpler) hypotheses at our disposition: this is the case, for example, when none of the variables wo, w1 , . . . , Wn- 1 has a bound occurrence in the formula F. Consider once again the language L == { R, f, c} used earlier as well as the L-structure N (JR, <, n, cos} . Here is an assortment of examples of a formula ;;;;;; U N I V E R S A L E Q U I V A L E N C E A N D S E M A N T I C C O N S EQ U E N C E 1 47 F[uo ] of L along with the set of reals a such that N F= F [a J (which is, we should recall� another way to write (N vo ---+ a) t== F). : Rcvo 3vi fVI � vo 3vi fvo VJ fvo � c 3vi (Rcvo 1\ fv l � vo) 3VI (RCVI 1\ fvl � Vo) 'Vv 1 Rvofvi 'Vvt Rfvofvl V v t 3 vz ( R v 1 vz 1\ f vz � vo) Vvo3vt fvi � vo 3vl 'VvzRfvz v1 � [n, +oo ) [ -1, l l JR. 0 0 [- 1 , 1 ] (-00, - 1] { (2k + 1 )n : k [- 1 , 11 E Z} 0 JR. The reader will have noticed that the last two illustrative formulas are closed. The last one is satisfied i n N while the next-to-last is not. Listing these two formulas in the category of formulas with onefreevariable may appear preposterous, especially after encountering the fastidious verifications to which we are led by the definition we have adopted. It would seem much more natural to be satisfied by associating with each formula the list ofvariablesthatactually have at least one free occurrence in it. This is, by the way, what happens spontaneously in practice: when we are interested in the sequences of elements that satisfy the formula ('VvoRvoc ==> ( -,Rv1 v2 v Rvzfv3)) in a given structure, we obviously tend to think of sequences of length 3. What justifies the more expansive definition that we have adopted in spite of this is, essentially, the fact that the subformulas of a formula do not necessarily involve all the free variables of the formula (and may even involve others which become bound in the whole formula); thus, to proceed otherwise would have led us to define the notion of satisfaction with a much more complicated induction. We realize that all these considerations are (merely) technical and that it is not necessary to pay undue attention to the purely formal subtleties that we might easily raise concerning this definition. The essential notion to retain from all the preceding is that of the satisfaction of a closed formula in a structure. 3.4 Universal equivalence and semantic consequence In this section, we will provide definitions and a basic vocabulary that are of constant use in model theory. We are given a first order language (with or without equality). Definition 3.46 • A closed formula of L is called universally valid {f and only if it is satisfied in every L-structure. Instead of 'universally validformula ' we sometimes say 'validformula '. 148 PREDICATE CALCULUS The notationfor: 'F is universally valid ' is �* • • • • • F ' while .14* F standsfor: 'F is not universally valid'. A closedformula of L is called a contradiction (or is said to be contradictory or inconsistent) if and only (lits negation is universally valid. A formula with free variables is universally valid if and only if its universal closure is universally valid (see Remark 3.47 below). Given two formulas F and G of L (whether closed or not), we say that F is universally equivalent (or logically equivalent, or simply equivalent) to G �l and only �f the formula (F {:;> G) is universally valid. The notation for 'F is universally equivalent to G ' is A set of closedformulas of L is called a theory of L. Given a theory T and an L-structure M, we say that M is a model of T (or that M satisfies T, or that T is satisfied in M) �land only {fM satisfies each formula that belongs to T. The notation for 'M is a model of T ' is M F= T, • • • while M � T stands for : 'M is not a model of T '. A theory is consistent (or non-contradictory, or satisfiable) if it has at least one model. A theory that is not consistent is called contradictory (or inconsistent). A theory isfinitely consistent (orfinitely satisfiable) if all itsfinite subsets are consistent. Given a theory T and a closedformula F of L, F is a semantic consequence of T (or simply, a consequence of T) �land only �l every L-structure that is a model ofT is also a model of F. The notation for 'F is a consequence of T · is T �* F, • • while T }L* F stands for 'F is not a consequence of T '. 1fT is a theory and F is aformula of L withfree variables, F is a consequence of T ifand only �lthe universal closure o.lF is a consequence ofT. The notation is the same as for closedformulas. Two theories Tt and T2 are equivalent if and only �levery formula in Tt is a consequence of T2 and every formula in T2 is a consequence of T1 . UNIVERSAL EQUIVALENCE A N D SEMANTIC C0NSEQUENCE 149 The definition that is given here for the universal validity ofa for­ mula withfree variables is, a priori, incorrect. It only makes sense once it has been verified that the various universal closures ofa formula are all universally equiv­ alent. This fact, which is intuitively clea1; is proved by referring to the definition of satisfaction (3.42). We will have to deal later with more or less this same issue to prvve prvperty (5) ofTheorem 3.55. Remark 3.48 We must be wary ofthe concept of universally equivalentformulas as it applies to formulas that are not closed: for two formulas to be equivalent, it is not sufficient that their universal closures be equivalent. Consider, for example, the following two formulas in the language whose only symbol is equality: Remark 3.47 Their universal closures are, respectively: The formulas Ft and G 1 are universally equivalent: indeed, they are both con­ tradictory, for {f we take an arbitrary structure M and an element a from its underlying set (necessarily non-empty), we have (M : vo a, V I a) � F and (M vo a, v2 a) � G, which shows that M satisfies neither F1 nor G 1 , and hence does satisfy ( F1 ¢> G 1 ). However, the formula (F ¢> G) is not universally valid, for its universal closure, -+ : -+ -+ -+ 'v'vo'v'v1'v'v2(_,vo � V t ¢> _,vo v2), is not satisfied in the structure whose base set is {0, 1 }; to see this, note that (M : vo -+ 0, Vt ---+ 1 , v2 ---+ 0) F= Fand(M : vo 0, Vt ---+ 1 , v2 0} JC G. I tfollows that � � � -- So the universal closure ofthis lastformula is false in the structure under consid­ eration. What is true, none the less, is that i f two fonnulas are universally equivalent, then so are their universal closures (see Exercise 6). It is time to indicate precisely which abuses of notation we will allow ourselves concerning first order formulas. In fact, we will be satisfied simply to recycle those that we have already decided to use for formulas of the propositional calculus: • suppressing the outermost pair of parentheses; • writing • (F 1\ G 1\ H) instead of ( ( F 1\ G) 1\ H); using ' large' conjunctions and disjunctions such as 1\ iEI Fi . ] 50 PREDICATE CALCULUS The justification for using these shorthand notations is essentially the same as it was for the propositional calculus. Their transfer to first order formulas is based on the following very simple and constantly used result: Let A 1 . A2, . . . , Ak be p1vpositional variables, let] [A 1 , A 2 , . . . , Ak] be a propositional formula and let Ft, F2 . . . . . Fk be first order formulas of a language L. If the formula J is a tautology, then the first order formula J L Ft , F2, . . , Fk] (the result of substituting the formulas Ft, F2, . . . , Fk for the variables A 1. A2, . . . , Ak, respectively, in theformula J) is a universally valid formula. Lemma 3.49 . Proof Suppose that the free variables of the formulas Ft , F2, . . . , Fk are among vo, v 1 , . . . , V n- 1 · Then this is also the case for the formula F = J [ Ft , F2 , . . . , Fk]. Consider a n L-structure M = (M . . . . ) and elements ao, a1 , . . . , an- I o f M . We define a n assignment o f truth values 8 o n { A 1 , A 2 , . . . , An } b y setting, for 0 < i < k: Here w e have used the simplified notation for satisfaction. The definition of satisfaction shows clearly (argue by induction on J) that the formula F is satisfied in M by the n-tuple (a o, a 1 , . . . , an-- I ) if and only if the assignment of truth values 8 assigns the value 1 to the formula J . We conclude immediately that when J is a tautology, M F= F[ao, a 1 , . . . , an - I ] , and that this holds for any n-tuple (ao, a 1 , . , an - I ), which proves that the uni­ versal closure of F is satisfied in any L-structure, i.e. that F is universally valid. • _ • The universally valid formulas that are obtained from proposi­ tional tautologies by the method we have just described are called tautologies of Definition 3.50 the predicate calculus. So we see that everything that was said in Chapter 1 concerning tautologies (associativity of conjunction and disjunction, among other facts) transfers with­ out difficulty to first order formulas; the concepts of tautology and of equivalent formulas become, respectively, those of universally valid formula and universally equivalent formulas. Note finally that we adopt no particular abbreviations involving the quantifiers. The properties asserted in the following theorem are immediate consequences of the definitions given above. U NIVERSAL EQUIVALENCE AND SEMANTIC CONSEQUENCE 151 For any theories T and S ofL, any integers m and p > 1 , and any closedformulas G, H, F1 , F2, . . . , Fm, and G 1 , G2, . . . , Gp of L, thefollowing properties are satisfied: The formula G is contradictory ifand only ((no L-structure satisfies it. The formula G is a consequence of T if and only if the theory T U { -.G} is contradictory. {fT is consistent and if S c T, then S is consistent. Jf T is consistent, then T is finite!y consistent. Jf T is contradictory and if T c S, then S is contradictory. �{ T �-* G and if T c S, then S �-* G . T U { G} 1-* H ifand only ifT � -* ( G => H). T �-* (G 1\ 11) ifand only if T 1- * G and T �-* H. { Ft , F2 , . . . , Fm } �-* G ifand only if�-* ((F1 1\ F2 1\ /\ Fm) =} G). G is universally valid (f and only if G is a consequence of the empty theory. G is universally valid ifand only if G is a consequence of eve1y theo1y ofL. T is contradicto1y ifand only ifT �-* (G 1\ -.G). T is contradictory if and only if every formula of L is a consequence ofT. T is contradictory ((and only iffor every universally validformula F, -. F is a consequence of T. T is contradictory ifand only ifthere exists at least one universaily validformula F such that -,F is a consequence of T. The theory { F1 , F2, . . . , Fm } is contradictory if and only ((theformula ( -'FI v ,F2 v v -.Fm ) is universally valid. The theories T and S are equivalent if and only {( they have the same mod­ els (in other words, for T and S to be equivalent, it is necessary and suffi­ cient that for every L-structure M, M is a model of T {(and only {(M is a model of S). Jf every formula in T is replaced by a universally equivalent formula.. the resulting theory is equivalent to T. 1( T is contradictory, then S is equivalent to T ifand only if S is contradictory. The theory T is equivalent to the empty theory if and only if. every formula belonging to T is universally valid. Every L-·structure is a model of the empty theory. The empty theory is consistent. The set of all closedformulas of L is contradictory. The theories { G } and {H } are equivalent ((and only (( the formulas G and H are logically equivalent. Theorem 3.51 • • • • • • • • • · · · • • • • • • • ... • • • • • • • • · · · 1 52 • • • • PREDICATE CALCULUS The theories { Fr , F2, . . . , Fm } and { G 1 , G2, . . . , G p } are equivalent ifand only if the formula is universally valid. Anyfinite theory is equivalent to a theoty that consists of a single formula. The binary relation 'is universally equivalent to ' is an equivalence relation on the set offormulas of L. The binary relation 'is equivalent to' is an equivalence relation on the set of theories of L, i.e. on the set of subsets of the set of closedformulas of L. Proof We invite the readertosupply proofs independently (this primarily involves arguments analogous to those used in the proof of Lemma 1.38). • The next proposition expresses the fact that the equivalence relation � for for­ mulas is compatible with the operations that enter into the construction of formulas (the use of connectives and quantifiers). For allformulas F, G, F' and G' andfor every integer k, if F and G are equivalent to F' and G' respectively, then the formulas Proposition 3.52 -,p, (F A G), (F v G), (F ::::} G), ( F {:} G), Vvk F and 3vk F are equivalent, respectively, to ( F' 1\ G ' ), ( F' v G ' ), (F' ::::} G ' ), (F' {:} G ' ) , Vvk F' and 3vk F' . -, p ' , Proof Let us treat, for example, the case of existential quantification. Suppose that the formulas F and F' are equivalent and that their free variables are among vo, VI, , Vn (n > k). We need to prove that the universal closure of the formula (3vk F <=> 3vk F') is satisfied in an arbitrary L-structure M == (M, . . . }. So let us , an of M. If we suppose that consider elements ao, a 1 , . . , ak- l , a k+ 1 , • . . . . then we can find an element a E . • M such that (M : vo --+ ao, . . . , Vk- J --+ ak- l , Vk � a, Vk + l � ak +l , . . . , Vn � an) F= F ; but, since F and F' are equivalent, we also have (M vo � ao, . . . , Vk - 1 : and hence ---+ ak- 1 , Vk � a, Vk+ 1 � ak + l , . . . , Vn - � an) t== F' , UN I V E R S A L EQ U I V A L EN C E A ND S E M A N TIC C 0N S EQ U EN C E 153 The converse is obtained in exactly the same manner. If then so we may conclude that (M : Vo ___. ao, VI � a1 , . . . , Vk- 1 � ak-l , Vk+l � ak + I , . . . , Vn � an) � (3vkF <=> 3vk F ) . ' The other cases are treated in a similar fashion. • Suppose that F is a formula, that G is a sub:formula of F and that G' is equivalent to G. Then the formula F', obtainedfrom F by substituting G ' for an arbitrary occurrence of the sub-formula G, is equivalent to F. Proof The argument is by induction on F. When F is atomic, G can only be equal to F, so F' = G' and the result is immediate. For all other stages of the Corollary 3.53 induction, it suffices to apply the preceding proposition. • We have thus justified an operation that we perform practically all the time when we manipulate first order formulas from a semantic point of view: we replace sub­ formulas by equivalent formulas. Changing the name of a bound variable, provided it is done subject to certain conditions, transforms a formula into an equivalent formula (see Remark 3.26): For any integers k and h and anyformula F, if the variable vh does not occur in F, then the formulas Proposition 3.54 are equivalent. Proof The result is trivial if h = k. So suppose h and k are distinct and that F = F[ V;1 v;2 , , v;n , Vk], where the integers i 1 , i2, . . . , in are pairwise distinct and distinct from h and k (which the hypothesis allows). Given an L-structure M = (M, . . ) and arbitrary elements a 1 . a2, . . . , an of M, what needs to be proved is that , • • • . (*) if and only if and the analogue for 3. 1 54 PREDICATE CALCULUS Property ( *) means that for any element a E M, we have but according to Lemma 3.44, this is also equivalent to We may then apply Proposition 3.45 (our hypotheses allow this), upon observing that and we obtain the following property, which is equivalent to ( * ) : which, by definition, means in other words, property ( ** ) . • Using the tautologies and the equivalent propositional formulas from Chapter 1 , we obtain, i n a natural way, countless examples of universally valid formulas and others equivalent to them. The important properties that follow will supply us with examples that have no analogue in the propositional calculus since they involve quantifiers. These properties are extremely useful. in particular, for mastering the manipulation of quantifiers in statements of everyday mathematics: among the first exercises at the end of this chapter, several are aimed at precisely this. For all integers h and k andfor allformulas F and G, we have thefollowing logical equivalences: Theorem 3.55 (1) ---.\lvk F � 3vk-,F, \lvk ( F 1\ G) � ('Vvk F 1\ 'VvkG), 3vk (F v G ) � 3vk F v 3vkG, => (2) (3 ) 3vk (F ==> G) "-J ('Vvk F 'Vvk \lvh F "-J 'Vvh 'Vvk F, (5) 3vk 3 Vh F "-J 3v�z3Vk F. (6) 3vk G), (4) Moreove1; thefollowing three formulas are universally valid: 3vk (F 1\ G) ==> 3vk F 1\ 3vkG, ('Vvk F v 'VvkG) ==> 'Vvk ( F v G), 3vk'VVh F ==> 'Vvh 3V k F. (7) (8) (9) U NI V ER S A L E QU I V A L ENCE A N D S E M A N TJ C C0N S E Q U EN CE ] 55 In addition, {fthe variable Vk is notfree in G, then: \lvkG "v 3vk G "' G, ( 10) G) (\lvk F 1\ G), 3vk ( F v G) ""' (3vk F v G), \lvk ( F v G ) ""' (\lvkF v G), 3vk ( F 1\ G) ""' (3vk F 1\ G), 3vk (G � F) � (G � 3vk F) , \lvk (G � F ) � (G � \lvk F), ( I I) 3vk ( F � G) � (\lvk F � G), ( 17) � G). ( 1 8) \lvk ( F 1\ � \lvk ( F � G) � (3vk F ( 12) ( 1 3) ( 1 4) (15) ( 1 6) Proof We obtain ( 1 ), (2), (5), (6), (7) and (9) without difficulty by referring to Definition 3.42� (3) and (8) are deduced from (2) and (7) respectively (applied to -.,F and -�G) together with ( 1 ) and familiar tautologies; (4) is an immediate consequence of (3) applied to -,F and G ; when we take the additional hypoth­ esis about Vk into account, ( 10) and ( 1 3) follow from the definition and Lemma 3.44; ( 1 1 ) and ( 15) can be deduced from ( I 0) and from (2) and (4 ); it is again thanks to ( 1 ) and to some tautologies that we obtain ( 1 2) from ( 1 1), ( 14) from ( 13), ( 1 7) from ( 1 5 ) and ( 1 8) from ( 1 6) ; ( 1 6) is obtained from ( 1 3) applied to F and _,G. • It should be understood that these brief suggestions presuppose intensive use of Proposition 3.52 and Corollary 3.53. We could say, loosely speaking, that the universal quantifier is 'distributive' over conjunction but not over disjunction, while the opposite is true for the existential quantifier. That is what is expressed by properties (2) and (3), together with the fact that the universal validity of formulas is not preserved, in general, when we replace the symbol ==} by � in (7) and (8): to see this, consider the language L that has two unary relation symbols A and B ; let F = A vo and G = B vo and take the model M whose underlying set is N and in which A and B are interpreted, respectively, by the relations 'is even' and 'is odd'; it is then clear that M satisfies the formulas 3vo F 1\ 3voG and \lvo(F v G) but does not satisfy the formula 3vo ( F 1\ G) nor the foirmula \lvoF v \lvoG. The behaviour of the quantifiers with respect to implication is more complicated; what one can keep in mind is this: if we try to 'distribute' the quantifier in a formula of the form Q vk ( F => G), where Q is \1 or 3, then, i n those circumstances where this i s possible, • if the quantifier 'enters' on the right side of the symbol ==} , then it 'enters' as is; whereas, • if the quantifier 'enters' on the left side of the symbol � ' it must be replaced by its dual Q* ( Q * = 3 if Q = \1 and Q* = V if Q = 3). 156 PREDICATE CALCULUS We can permute two consecutive universal (existential, respectively) quantifiers (properties (5) and (6)), but not a 'V with a 3: (9) is no longer universally valid if we replace � with <=> . To see this, consider once again the model M above and let F be the formula (Avo {:} Bv1); then M F= Vvo3vt F (since for any integer ao, we can find an integer a1 whose parity is different from that of ao) but M P: 3vt VvoF (for we can hardly insist that an integer have a parity that is distinct from the parity of an arbitrary integer. . . ). The formula 'Vvh 3vk F expresses the existence of a Vk for each Vh (so it may vary with Vh) whereas the Vk whose existence is expressed by the formula 3vk Vvh F must be 'the same for all Vh , which is what makes this formula 'stronger� than the preceding. There are classic illustrations of this remark in analysis involving the distinction between simple and uniform continuity and the distinction between simple and uniform convergence: we know well that the heart of the problem consists in determining whether 'the 8 (or the N) depends on x or not' . . . and, ultimately, when we express these properties formally, they differ precisely by an inversion of the order of the quantifiers. Using the results from Chapter 1 on complete sets of connectives, together with Lemma 3.49, Proposition 3.52 and Corollary 3.53, and property ( 1 ) of the preceding theorem, we immediately obtain ' Everyfirst orderformula is universally equivalent to at least one formula whose only symbolsfor connectives and quantifiers are: , v and 3. Theorem 3.56 -. In this statement, we can obviously replace -. and v by the elements of any complete set of connectives; we can also replace 3 by 'V. An analogue of Remark 1.33 applies here as well: to prove that a certain property, compatible with the relation "', is true for every first order formula, it is sufficient, in a proof by induction, to 'restrict' oneself to the stages that relate to negation, di�junction and existential quantification. Remark 3.57 We conclude this section with a result that is very easy but indispensable. It concerns comparing the satisfaction of a formula in a structure for its own language with its satisfaction in a structure for a richer language. Consider a first order language L and a language L * that is an enrichment of L. Let M = (M, . . . ) be an L-structure, let M* be an enrichment of M for the language L *, let F = F[vo, Vt , . . . , Vn - l ] be a formula of the language L and let ao, a 1 , . . , an- I be elements of M. Under these conditions, we have Lemma 3.58 . M Proof F= F[ao, a1 , . . . , an- t ] if and only if M* F F[ao, a 1 , · · · , an- l ]. The only thing that is perhaps not obvious is that these two properties make sense! We convince ourselves by noting that F is both a formula of L and a formula of L *. For the rest, a quick glance at the definition of the satisfaction of F in M* reveals that this depends only on the symbols of L and on the functions PRENEX FORMS AND S KOLEM FORMS 1 57 and relations of the structure M. So the result is automatic (the reader who wishes to be completely rigourous should give a proof by induction on F). Ill Observe, however, that this question would not have made sense if F contained symbols of L * that did not belong to L. 3.5 Prenex forms and Skolem forms What we do in this section will be amply used in the next chapter in which we will describe methods that allow us to answer questions of the form: 'is this closed formula universally valid?' or 'is it a consequence of such and such a theory?' Tht idea will be to reduce the question, at the cost of changing the language� to formulas whose syntactic construction is relatively simple: the Skolem forms. Beforehand w e will show that every formula F i s equivalent t o a formula (of the same language) structured as a sequence of quantifications followed by a quantifier-free formula (this will be called a prenex form of F). The interest and import of Theorem 3.60 about prenex forms extends beyond the context just described. It also presents "' (slight) danger, in that it leads one to believe that a formula is 'easier to understand' when it is in prenex form: in fact, one quickly realizes that the contrary is true and that, to comprehend the property expressed by a closed formula, one is well advised to 'distribute' the quantifiers to the maximum extent possible, i.e. to do the exact opposite of putting it in prenex form. 3.5.1 Prenex forms A formula F is prenex {f and only if there exist an integer k, variables W J , w2, . . . , Wk, symbolsfor quantifiers Q 1 , Q2, . . . , Qk and a formula G without quant{fiers such that Definition 3.59 The word Q l W I Q2w2 . . . Qkwk is then called the prefix ofthe prenexformula. A prenexformula is polite {fand only if its prefix contains at most one occurrence of each variable. If H is a formula, a prenexformula that is universally equivalent to H is called prenexform of H. A universalformula is a prenexformula with no existential quantifiers. An existentialformula is a prenexformula with no universal quantifiers. l\Taturally, the case k = 0 corresponds to the situation in which F = G, which is a to say that formulas without quantifiers are special cases of prenex formulas (and they are, by the way, polite, universal, and existential). We see immediately that any universal closure of a prenex formula is also a prenex formula. Caution: a formula such as 'v'vo(3v l vo � VJ =} vo � v 1 ) is not prenex! Theorem 3.60 Every first orderformula has at Least one polite prenexform 158 PREDICATE CALCULUS Proof We will prove by induction that for any formula F, we can find a polite prenex formula F' that is universally equivalent to F. Because it is clear that this property is compatible with the relation f"v we may, by Remark 3.57, restrict the number of cases to be considered. • • • If F is atomic, it suffices to take F' = F. I f F = -,G, and if G is equivalent to Q1 VI Q 2 v2 . . . Qk Vk G" , where G" i s quantifier-free and the variables w i are pairwise distinct, i t suffices to take F' = Q 1 VI Q 2 v2 . . . Qkvk-,G" where, for 1 < h < k, Qh is the dual of Qh . (G v H), if G is equivalent to G' Q I VI Q 2 v2 . . . QkvkG" and H to H' Q � z I Q �z2 . . . Q;n Z m H " (where G" and H" are quantifier-free and where, in each prefix, the variables are pairwise distinct), then after first choosing k + m pairwise distinct variables XI , x 2 , . . . , xk, YI , Y2, . . . , Ym that have no occurrence in G' or in H', it suffices to set If F = = = and to take To verify that this formula is indeed equivalent to F, we mainly apply (k + m times) Proposition 3054 and properties ( 1 2) and ( 1 3) of Theorem 3.55. It is appropriate to note that the order in which we repeatedly apply these two properties is of no importance: we might, for example, first bring all the Qj to the front, then all the Q;, or else alternate them arbitrarily; on the other hand, what cannot change (except in special cases) is the order of the Q i among them­ selves, or that of the Qj among themselves. We see, in any case, that we are far from having a unique prenex formula equivalent to F. • I f F = 3vG and if G is equivalent to Q1 w1 Q 2 w2 . . . QkwkG", where G" is quantifier-free and the variables w; are pairwise distinct, then either v rf. {W I , w2, . . . , Wk } and it suffices to take F' = 3vQI W I Q 2w2 . . . QkwkG" , or else w = wj for some index j between 1 and n: in this case, w is not free in the formula Q I WI Q 2w2 . . . Qk WkG", so we can take F' = Q 1 WI Q 2 w2 . Qk WkG" since this polite prenex formula is equivalent to F by virtue of property • ( 1 0) of Theorem 3.55. 0 0 The proofwe havejust givenfurnishes a p1vcedurefor constructing a prenexformula that is equivalent to a givenformula F (we also speak of 'putting F in prenexform'). ({ we scrupulously follow this p1vcedure, we must begin by eliminating the symbols 1\, ==> , ¢> and 'V. In truth, the only indispensable step is to eliminate ¢> . It is then possible, by judiciously changing the names of bound variables, to progressively 'bring the quantifiers to the front' by climbing the decomposition tree, using, step by step, the properties presented in Theorem 3.55 as we did above for the induction step involving disjunction. Ofcourse, depending Remark 3.61 PRENEX FORMS AND S KOLEM FORMS 1 59 on the circumstances, we can be more or less efficient in changing the names of variables: it is rarely necessary to rename all the variables that occur, as we did above. The obvious purpose of these name changes of bound variables is to obtain formula in which no variable occurs in the scope ofmore than one quantification, in order that Theorem 3.55 apply in all cases. A byproduct is a potential increase in the number of variables in use. However, if we wish to minimize the length (and height) ofthe prenexform, it can happen, on the contrary, that we are better served by substituting, for a given bound variable, a variable that already occurs in the scope of some other quantification. Let us take an example: the formula a is equivalent to the prenexformula obtained as described above, by changing the name of the bound variable v 1 (into v3) in the scope of the rightmost quantification in F; but we can find a simpler prenex form when we observe that properties (2) and (4) of Theorem 3.55 are applicable here: this leads us to substitute (in F) VI for the occurrences of v2, then vo for the last three occurrences of v 1 ; the formula obtained in this way is H == Vvo(Vvt (--.vt VJ � 3 v t vo � V t ) l\ Vvovo � vo; it is indeed equivalent to F and the properties to which we just referred ptvduce thefollowing prenexform. � whose height is 5 (that ofG is 7) and which is obviously shorter than G. Remark 3.62 The last part of the proof of the preceding theorem clearly showed that to getfrom an arbitraryformula in prenexform to an equivalentprenexformula that is polite, it suffices, for each variable, to suppress in the prefix ofF all but the rightmosT quantification involving that variable. For example, if G is a formula without quant{fiers, the formula is logically equivalent to the polite prenexformula When we apply the method described above to obtain a prenexforrn ofsome givenformula F, the result is a formula that has the samefree variable as F (this is immediately verified). In particular, applying the method to a closed formula produces a prenexformula that is closed. Let F be a first order formula, let G be a prenex form of F, and let H be the subformula of G obtained by suppressing the prefix. As H is quantifier-free, it is Remark 3.63 ,· .. 160 PREDICATE CALCULUS obtained from some propositional formula J by a substitution of the kind described in Remark 3.27. As for any propositional formula, 1 has a conjunctive normal form J1 and a disjunctive normal form J2. The substitution that transforms J into H will transform It and J2, respectively, into first order formulas HI and H2 which are clearly universally equivalent to H. The prenex formulas G I and G2 obtained by placing the prefix of G at the front of HI and flz , respectively, are equivalent to F . We say that G I ( G2, respectively) is a conjunctive (disjunctive, respectively) prenex form of F. 3.5.2 Skolem forms Consider a polite prenex formula of a language L. Thus there exist pairwise distinct variables w J , w2, . . . , Wn , quantifiers Q 1 , Q2, . . . , Q11 and a quantifier-free formula G of L such that F = Q I WI Q2w2 · · · Q n wnG. Denote by jI , }2 , . . , jP the indices of those Q that correspond to an existential quantification: that is, . { j 1 .i2 , , . . . , jp } = {j E { 1 , 2, . . . , n } : Qj = 3} (we assume l < }1 < }2 < · · · < }p < n). With F, we will associate a language Lsk (F) that will be an enrichment of the language L obtained by adding p new symbols /1 . {2, . . . , /p for constants or functions (these are called the symbols for the Skolem functions associated with F and they correspond to the p occurrences of the symbol 3 in the prefix of F). For 1 < h < p, the arity of the symbol fh must equal . ih h, i.e. the number of times the quantifier V occurs to the left of Qj11 in the prefix of F (we adopt the convention of treating constant symbols as function symbols of arity 0; for fh to be a constant symbol, it is necessary and sufficient that jh = h, i.e. that the first h quantifications in the prefix of F be existential; naturally, in such a situation, /1 , .f2 , . . . , /h - I will also be constant symbols; moreover, the arity of fh increases with h). For example, if the prefix of F is . . - five new function symbols !1 , .f2, j3, 14 and fs whose respective arities are 2, 3, 5 , 5, and 7 will be added to the language L. Now that w e have defined our new language, w e will use it to define a formula Fsk , which will be a polite universal formula of the language L sk ( F ) and which we will call the Skolem form of F First of all, for 1 < h < p we let uh denote the term of Lsk (L) that consists of the symbol /h followed by the }h h universally quantified variables that occur to the left of the variable wjh in the prefix of F. In other words, .. -· 161 PRENEX FORMS AND SKOLEM FORMS Then, for each index h between 1 and n , we replace each occurrence o f the variable wjh in G by the term U h . Finally, in front of the formula thus formed, we place the prefix of G from which all existential quantifications have first been deleted. We arrive in this way at the Skolem form of F, which is, therefore, f'Sk = 'v'W 1 . . 'v'Wj1 - 1 'v'Wj1 + 1 . . . 'v' Wjh • - G ui fw.i1 ,uz/wh .... ,u /w; p p - 1 'v'Wjh + 1 . · . 'v'W jp I 'v'WjP + 1 - · .· 'v'Wn · Example 3.64 Suppose the language L consists of a unary function symbol f and a binary relation symbol R . Consider the following formula F of L: The language Lsk (L) then contains, in addition to the symbols R and f, four new symbols: two constant symbols !1 and !2, a unary function symbol /3 and a ternary function symbol /4. The Skolem form of F is the formula Given an arbitrary formula F in a language L, we have seen how to fi nd a polite prenex formula F' that is equivalent to F. The Skolem form of F' will also be called a Skolem form of F (so we do not have uniqueness of the Skolem form of an arbitrary formula). lt is very important not to lose sight of the fact that a Skolem form of a formula F of a language L is not (in general) a formula of L, but of a richer language. This will allow us to avoid a rather common error which consists in thinking that a formula is equivalent to its Skolem form. Such a statement makes sense only i f we view F as a formula of the enriched language Lsk (F), which is, of course, possible but we realize right away that in order to support this, we would be led to examine arbitrary Lsk ( F)-structures and that the proposed equivalence would be rather pointless. An example would really be more convincing that an overly lengthy dissertation: the Skolem form of the formula F 'v'vo3v1 Rvovt is the formula 'v'vo Rvogvo (we have added the symbol for the unary Skolem function g to the initial language L consisting of the binary relation symbol R); the structure whose base set is Z, in which R is interpreted by the usual order relation and g by the map n �-----+ n 1 , obviously satisfies the first formula but not the second. What is true, none the less, is that every formula F, considered as a formula of the language Lsk ( F) , is a semantic consequence of its Skolem form. As well, provided we allow the Axiom of Choice (see Chapter 7 in Volume 2), any L-structure that satisfies a (closed) formula F can be enriched to an Lsk(F)-structure that satisfi.es the Skolem form of F. A notable consequence of this is that for a closed formula to be satisfiable, it is necessary and sufficient that its Skolem form be satisfiable (we sometimes say that F and FSk are equisatisfiable, in the absence of their being equivalent). It is this last property that will be mainly used in the next chapter. = - 1 62 PREDICATE CALCULUS Before proving everything that we have just claimed, let us verify it on a very simple example in which the essential ideas are clearly apparent. Let us reconsider the formula F = V'vo3VI R vo v i that we just used as an example. So we have L = { R } , Lsk (F) = { R, g} and Fsk = 'VvoRvogvo. Let M = (M, R , g} be an Lsk( F)-structure that satisfies Fsk · This means that for every element a E M, we have (a, g (a)) E R . Obviously then, for every element a E M, we can find an element b E M (namely, g (a)) such that (a, b) E R, which means that M satisfies the formula F. Thus, FSk ==} F is a universally valid formula of Lsk (F). Now consider an L-structure N = (N, p } that is a model of the formula F. This means that for every element a E N, the set of those elements b E N such that (a, b) E p is non-empty. It is here that the Axiom of Choice intervenes: it guarantees the existence of a map ¢ from the set of non-empty subsets of N into N (called a choice function on N) such that for every non-empty subset X c N, the value of ¢ at X is an element of X (¢(X) E X). With the help of such a choice function ¢, we will enrich N into an Lsk(F)-structure that will satisfy Fsk · The problem is to provide an interpretation for the extra symbol g. For this, we will take the map y defined on N in the following way: for all a E N, y(a) = ¢ ( {b E N : (a, b) E p }). I t is then clear that the Lsk (F)-structure (N, p , y) i s a model o f Fsk · Let us now approach these properties in the general case. Let y 1 , Y2 , . . . , Yn be pairwise distinct variables and let F F[Yl , Y2 , . . . , Yn] be a polite prenexformula of a language L. Then the formula Fsk =} F of the language Lsk ( F) is universally valid. Lemma 3.65 Proof By induction on the number of occurrences of the existential quantifier in the prefix of F, we will prove, for every Lsk (F)-structure M = (M, . . . } and for all elements h i , b2, . . . , bn of M, that if the formula Fsk is satisfied in M by the sequence (hi , b2, . . . , bn), then the formula F is also satisfied in M by the same sequence (recall that the formulas FSk and F have the same free variables). The result is evident when the formula F has no existential quantifiers at all, for then FSk = F. Suppose (this is the induction hypothesis) that the result is true for all polite prenex formulas that have at most k existential quantifications and suppose that F has k + 1 of them. Thus where G itself is a polite prenex formula with at most k existential quantifications. There is then an m-ary function symbol fi in the language Lsk(F) such that the Skolem form of F is the formula obtained from the Skolem form of the formula by substituting the term fi X lX2 . . . x m for the variable x. 1 63 PRENEX FORMS AND SKOLEM FORMS So we have Fsk = F�k/1 1 X2···xm /x x · (We should note that Lsk ( F') = Lsk ( F) - {fJ } . So we may consider F' as a formula of Lsk ( F), whose satisfaction in an Lsk-structure is equivalent to its satisfaction in the reduced language Lsk ( F) (see Lemma 3.58)). But we see immediately, by referring to the definition of the Skolem form, that starting from the formula F', the result of first taking its Skolem form and then substituting into it !IXIX2 . . . Xm for x is exactly the same as the result of perform­ ing these two operations in the opposite order, i.e. of first doing the substitution in F' and then taking the Skolem form of the formula thereby obtained; this depends, essentially, on the fact that the variables involved in the substitution are not exis­ tentially quantified in F'. So we also have The formula F1'l x I x2 · · ·Xm /x is a polite prenex formula with at most k existential quantifiers, so we may apply the induction hypothesis to it: i f (M : YI � ht � Y2 � b2, . . . , Yn � bn ) � Fsk, then we also have (M Yl : � b1 , Y2 � b2, · · · ' Yn � bn) F FJ1 x 1 x2 • • • xm /X ' which means that for all elements a 1 , a2, . . . , am of M, (M : Y t � bt , . . . ' Yn � bn , Xl � a t , . . . , Xm � am} t== G !J X]X2 ...Xm/X · Again, this is equivalent (Proposition 3.45) to (M : YI � bt , . . . , y n � bn, XI � a 1 , . . . , Xm � am , x � -M !1 (a1 , a2, . . . , am) ) F= G. Thus, for all a 1 , a2, . . . , am , there exists an element b E M, namely -M !1 (a 1 , a2, . . . , am ) , such that which proves that and, finally, (M : YI � b t , Y2 � b2, . . . , Yn � bn ) F Vxt'VX2 . . . Vxm3xG, which is the long awaited property. • 1 64 P R ED I C ATE C A L C U L U S (using the axiom of choice) Assume that L is any language, that YI . Y2, . . . , Yn are pairwise distinct variables, that F F [YJ , Y2, . . . , Yn] is in polite prenex form, that N (N, . . . ) is an L-structure. and that the n-tuple (bt , b2, . . . , bn) ofelements of N satisfies theformula F in N; then it is possible to enrich the structure N to an Lsk (F)-structure in which then-tuple (bt , b2, . . . , bn) satisfies theformula Fsh the Skolemform of F. Lemma 3.66 = = Once again, the proof is by induction on the number of existential quan­ tifications in the formula F and, as before, we note that the case i n which this number is 0 is trivial (Lsk( F) = L, Fsk = F and N is sufficiently rich as is). So we assume that the result is true for all polite prenex formulas (in all languages) that have at most k existential quantifications and that F has k + 1 of these. Under the same conditions as in the proof of the previous lemma, we may set Proof F F' = = Vxt Vx2 . . . Vxm 3xG[YI , Y2, . . . , Yn, X) , X2, . . . ' Xm , x] ; Vx1 Vx2 . . . Vxm G [YI , Y2, . . . , Yn , XI , x2, . . . , Xm , x]; and, for the same reasons, we have Since our hypothesis is (N : y 1 --* b 1 , Y2 --* b2, . . . , Yn that for all elements a1 , a2, . . . , am of N, the set --* bn) F= F, it follows is non-empty. So, using a choice function ¢ on N, we may define a map N m into N by setting y from for all a L , a2, . . . , am in N. We may immediately assert that (*) : (N : Y1 t= � b 1 , . . . , Yn � bn , XJ --* a 1 , . . . , Xm --+ am , X � y (a 1 , a2, . . . , am ) ) G. Let L 1 denote the language obtained by adding to L the m-ary function symbol lt of the language Lsk (F) (the one corresponding to the firstoccurrence of3 in F). We can enrich N to an L � -structure N1 if we interpret the symbol f1 by the map y . FIRST STEPS IN MODEL THEORY 1 65 The previously displayed assertion (*) then becomes (by applying Lemma 3.58): This is also equivalent (by Proposition 3 .45) to Consequently, (NI : Yl � b 1 , · · · , Yn � bn} I= 'lx1 \lx2 · · · 'lxm [G fiXJX2···xmfx ] . Since x is distinct from the x; , this last formula is none other than which is a polite prenex formula F1 of the language L 1 with at most k existential quantifications. By the induction hypothesis, we can enrich the structure N1 to an L 1 Sk ( Ft )-structure N* such that {N* : YI -4 h t , Y2 � h2 , ·· · ' Yn � bn} F FfJXJX2···xm/Xsk · We recognize this to be the formula F (in passing, we will have observed that the • language L 15k (F1 ) is exactly the language L sk (F). For a closedformula to have a model, it is necessary and sufficient that any one of its Skolemforms have a model. Corollary 3.67 Proof This is an immediate consequence of the two preceding lemmas and the theorem about prenex forms (Theorem 3.60). • The exercises in Chapter 4 will provide other occasions to practise the art of putting a formula in prenex from or in Skolem form. 3.6 First steps in model theory 3 ..6.. 1 Satisfaction in a substructure We will begin to take interest in what happens to the satisfaction of formulas when we pass from one structure to another. Though we should not expect to have much information when the two structures are completely arbitrary, we do have a few elementary results at our disposal in particular cases. In fact, we have already encountered one: the case where we compare the satisfaction of a formula in a structure with its satisfaction in an enrichment of the structure to a more extensive language (Lemma 3.58). We will now examine, successively, what can be said when we study the satisfaction of a formula in two structures, first, where one is an extension of the other, and second, where the two structures are isomorphic. 1 66 PREDICATE CALCULUS Knowing that a formula is satisfied in a certain structure, can we conclude (when this is meaningful) that it is satisfied in a substructure or in an extension? In general, the answer is no, but we do have, none the less, some useful information if the formula under consideration is sufficiently simple (see the next two theorems below). We need a lemma to begin with: (M, . . ) is an L-structure, Assume that L is a language, M N (N, . . ) is an extension of M, t t[vo, VJ , , Vm- t l is a term of L, and ao, a I, . . . , am - I are elements of M. Then -M am-t J . t [ao ' a 1 ' ' am - I] -N t [a o, a 1 ' Lemma 3.68 == == . == . • • . == • • • . • • ' Proof This is proved by induction on t : • if t is the variable Vj (0 < J m - 1), then -tM [ao, a 1 , . . . , am- I ] < -N t [ ao, a 1 , . . . , am -- I ] aj ; eM eN if t is a constant symbol c, then tM [ao, a 1 , , am-d tN [ao, a t , . . . , am- d (since N is an extension of M); if t ft 1 t2 . . . tp, where f is a p-ary function symbol and tt , t2, . . . , tp are terms . that sattsfy ti [ ao, a 1 , . . . , am- I ] for 1 < l. < p (th"IS li M [ ao, a 1 , . . . , a m-1 ] -N == • • • • • == == is the induction hypothesis), then -M t [ao, a 1 , • • • , am- 1 ] == fM (tt-M [ao , a i , . . . , am-Il, . . . , tpM [ao, a t , - - - , am - d) -,..N -M == J (t 1 [ao, a1 , . tp M [ao, at , . . . , am-1 ]) . . , am-IL . . . , == fN (-N t1 [ ao, a 1 , . . . , am- I ] , . . . , -N tp [ ao, a 1 , . . . , am- L ] ) == -M t (*) (**) [ ao, a 1 , . . . , am - I ], N where (*) i s justified by the fact that fM i s the restriction of f ( ** ) is a consequence of the induction hypothesis. to Mk and • Assume that L is a language, M = ( M, . . . ) is an L-structure, N (N, . ) is an extension of M, F F[vo, V I , . . . , Vm-I l is a quantifier-free formula of L, and ao, a 1 , . . ., am-I are elements of M. Then F is satisfied in M by the sequence (ao, a1 , . . . , am - I ) if and only if F is satisfied in N by this same sequence. Proof The proof is by induction on F. I f F is atomic, there is a k-ary ( k > 1 ) relation symbol R and terms t1 , t2, . . . , tk , Vm-l such that F Rtt t2 tk. So whose variables are among vo, VJ, Theorem 3.69 = . . = • • • == • (M : vo ---+ a o, V] ---+ a ] , . . - ' Vm-1 ---+ am- d F F · · · 167 FIRST STEPS IN MODEL THEORY if and only if -M [ao, a I , . . . , am I ] , . . . , lk M [ao, a I , . . . , am-I J ) E -M R . - ( lt - (t) Now, according to the lemma, we have -M t i [ao, a t , . . . , am- d ti [ao, a 1 , . . . , am- r ] ::::::: -N N M for 1 < i < k and, since R ::::::: R n M k , (t) is equivalent to (iJ N R , [ao, a} , . . . , am-d, . . , -N tk [ao, a t , . . . , am-I ]) E -� . which means precisely that (N : vo ---+ ao, VI ---+ a t , . . . , Vm- l ----+ am-d • F= F. The induction steps that concern the connectives -., 1\, v, =}, and {:} are obvious. • There are no other cases to consider since F has no quantifiers. Assume that L is a language, M = (M, . . . ) is an L-structure, N == (N, . . . ) is an extension of M, F = F[vo, V I , Vm- I ] is a universal formula of L, G = G [vo, V I , . . . , Vm- t l is an existentialformula of L, and ao, a I, . . . , am-I are elements of M. Under these conditions: if F is satisfied in N by the sequence (ao, at , . . . , am- I ) then F is satisfied in M by this same sequence; (f G is satisfied in M by the sequence (ao, a 1 , , am- l ) then G is satisfied in N by this same sequence. Theorem 3. 70 • • • • • , . Proof The second assertion follows immediately from the first: if G is existential, -,G is equivalent to a universal formula F' (property ( 1 ) ofTheorem 3.55). I f G is satisfied in M by (ao, a I , . . . , am-I ), then F' is not, hence (by the contrapositive of the first assertion) F' is not satisfied in N by (ao, a 1 , . . . , a m-I ), which proves that G is. We prove the first assertion by induction on the number of universal quantifiers in the prefix of F. If this number is 0, the result follows from Theorem 3.69. Otherwise, F = Vvk H (where H is universal and has one fewer universal quan­ tifier than F, so, by the induction hypothesis, it satisfies the assertion). Subject to replacing k by h == sup(k, m) and H by Hvhfvk (which produces a formula that is equivalent to F), we may assume k > m (and even, if we wish, k ::::::: m). We then have H = H [vo, V I , . . . , Vm-I , Vk ] and the fact that (N : vo ---+ ao, vI means that for every element a E a1 , ---+ • • • , Vm- I ----+ am - 1 ) F= F N, (N : vo ---+ ao, VI - ---+ a 1 , • • • , Vm-1 - ---+ am-1 , Vk ----+ a) F= H ; 1 68 PREDICATE CALCULUS in particular, this must be true for every element a E M. Thanks to the induction hypothesis, we may now conclude • The content of Theorem 3.70 can be summarized by saying that universal formulas are preserved by substructures while existential formulas are preserved by extensions. Some more refined preservation properties will be presented in Chapter 8 (we will also have a converse to Theorem 3.70: every formula that is preserved by substructures (extensions, respectively) is equivalent to a universal (existential, respectively) formula.) There is one preservation property that we have every reason to expect should apply to arbitrary formulas: preservation by isomorphisms. This will be guaranteed by the next theorem. Assume that L is a language, M == (M, . . . ) and N == (N, . . . ) are two L-structures, and that h : M N is a homomorphism from M into N. Then for every term t == t [ vo, v 1 , Vm t 1 andfor all elements ao, a 1, , am- I of the set M, we have Lemma 3.71 t- • h (-t M [ao, a 1 , . . . , am-I l) == • � • _ • • • • -N t [h (ao), h (a t ) , . . . , h(am - 1 ) ] . · Proof The proof i s by induction o n t: • • • i f t i s the variable vj ( 0 < j < m - 1 ), then each side of the proposed equality is equal to h(aj ) ; if t i s the constant symbol c, then the left side i s h (eM ) and the right side i s eN and these are equal since h is a homomorphism� if t == ft 1 t2 . . . t P' where f is a p-ary function symbol and t t , t2, . . . , tp are . y h (t-M terms that satlsf t i [h (ao ) , h (a I ) , , h (am- 1 ) ] , am- t J) == -N i [ ao, a 1 , for 1 < i < p (this is the induction hypothesis), then • • • • • • h (IM [ao, a I , . . . , am- d) h (-M f (-M t i [ao, a1, . . . , am - IL . . . , tp M [ao, a 1 , . . . , am - d) ) M [ao, a 1 , . . . , am-d) , . . . , h (tp M [ao, a1 , . . . , am - d)) ( * ) == JN ( h (t) == == -.f N (--N t 1 [h (ao), h (a 1 ) , . . . , h (am - I ) ] , . . . , tpN [h(ao), h(al ), . . . , h (am- 1 )]) -N [h(ao), h (a 1 ) , . . . , h (am - I ) ] , == t ( ** ) where ( * ) holds because h is a homomorphism and ( ** ) follows from the • induction hypothesis. Assume that L is a language, that M == (M, . . . ) and N == (N, . . . ) are two L-structures, that h M N is an isomorphism from M Theorem 3.72 : .-� 1 69 FIRST STEPS IN MODEL T HEORY onto N, that F = F[vo, v 1 , . . . , Vm- 1 ] is an arbitrary formula of L and that ao, a 1 , . . . , am- I are elements of the set M. Then F is satisfied in M by the sequence (ao, a 1 , . . . , am- I ) if and only if F is satisfied in N by the sequence (h (ao) , h (a 1 ) , . . . , h (am - 1 ) ). Proof The proof is by induction on F. If F is atomic, there is a k-ary (k > 1 ) relation symbol R and terms tt , t2, . . . , tk whose variables are among vo, V t , . . . , Vm- 1 such that F Rt1t2 . . . tk . So (M : vo � ao, V I � a t , . . . , Vm - 1 � am- I ) F= F if and only if (t1 M [ao, a 1 , . . . , am- t ], . . . , tk M [ao, a 1 , . . . , am - t l ) E RM . ( *) • = - - - Because h is an isomorphism, (*) is equivalent to -M [ao, a 1 , . . . , am- d), . . . , h(tk -M [ao, a t , . . . , am- d) ) E -N (h(tt R , or again, according to the lemma, to -N [h(ao), . (tt h (a 1 ), . . . , h (am-1)], . . . , -N tp [h(ao), h (at ), . . . , h (am - d D -N E R , which means precisely that (N : vo � h(ao), • VI � h(a t ), . . . , Vm- 1 ---+ h (am - 1 ) ) F= F. The subsequent induction steps present no problems (in view of Remark 3.57, we may restrict our attention tot he cases involving --,, v and 3). For example, let us treat the case of existential quantification: so we suppose that F = 3vkG and, as in the proof of Theorem 3.70, that k > m and G = G[vo, Vt , . . . , Vm- 1 , Vk]; then ( M : vo � a o, v 1 ----?- a1 , . • • , vm- 1 � am - 1 ) F= F means that we can find an element a E M such that (M : vo --+ ao, VI --+ a t , . . . , Vm-1 ----+ am-1 , Vk � a) F= G; by the induction hypothesis, this is equivalent to (N : vo -)· h (ao), V t ---+ h(a1), . . . , Vm- 1 -4 h (am - 1 ) , Vk ---4- h (a)) F= G, which proves that (N : vo � h(ao), VI ----+ h (a t ) , . . . , Vm- 1 ---+ h (am-1 ) ) F= F. Conversely, if this condition is satisfied, we can find an element b E N such that (N : vo -� h(ao), Vt � h (a i ) , . . . , Vm- l � h(am-1), Vk � b) F= G, 170 PREDICATE CALCULUS and, since h is a bijection, an element a E M such that b = h(a); the conclusion • now follows, as before, from the induction hypothesis. 3.6.2 Elementary equivalence An immediate consequence of the previous theorem is that two isomorphic L­ structures satisfy exactly the same closed formulas of the language L. This leads us to a notion that is absolutely fundamental in model theory, that of elementary equivalence. Definition 3.73 An L-structure M is elementarily equivalent to another L­ structure N (we will denote this by M = N) if and only if every closedformula of L that is satisfied in M is also satisfied in N. We immediately conclude that M = N if and only if M andN satisfy the same closed formulas of L : indeed, if a closed formula F is not satisfied in M, then M F= -sF, so N F= -,p and F is not satisfied in N. Thus we see that = is an equivalence relation on the class of £-structures. So we will indifferently say 'M is elementarily equivalent to N' or �M and N are elementarily equivalent' . The notation M =I= N means that M and N are not elementarily equivalent. Therefore, the following is a consequence of Theorem 3.72: Proposition 3.74 equivalent. If two L-structures are isomorphic, then they are elementarily We will have countless opportunities to observe that the converse of this is far from being true. The existence of elementarily equivalent models that are not isomorphic is clear evidence for the fact that the expressive power of first order languages is limited: in the usual practice of mathematics, when two structures are not isomorphic, we can generally discern some property that is satisfied by one and not by the other; but if the structures are elementarily equivalent, then such a distinguishing property will not be expressible as a fi rst order formula of the language, nor even by a set of such formulas. If we permit ourselves to anticipate, we can discuss an example: it will turn out that the structures (�, <) and (Q, <) are elementarily equivalent (naturally, the language consists of a single binary relation symbol); they cannot possibly be isomorphic since the second is countable while the first is not; consequently, none of the properties that distinguish them can be expressible by a theory of the language. In particular, this is the case for the famous least upper bound property (every non-empty subset that has an upper bounded has a least upper bound) which is true in ll� but not in Q. The remarks we have just made lead us to the foJlowing definition: 3.75 Let L be afirstorder language and let X(M) be a property that an L-structure M may or may not satisfy. The property X(M) is axiotrUltizable (respectively, finitely axiomatizable) if there exists a theory T of L (respectively, a closed formula F of L ) such that for every L-structure M, X(M) is ver{fied if and only �f M is a model of T Definition FIRST STEPS IN MODEL THEORY 171 (respectively, of F). When this happens, we say that the theo1y T (respectively, the closedformula F) axiomatizes the property X(M). We say that X(M) is pseudo-axiomatizahle if there exists a language L * that extends L and a theory T of L * such that for every L-structure M, the property X(M) is satisfiedifandonly ifM is the reduct to the language L ofan L *-structure that is a model ofT. Obviously, every axiomatizable property is pseudo-axiomatizable. Instead of 'axiomatizable property', we often say 'first order property' . What we noted above can then be paraphrased as follows: the property (for a set and a binary relation on it) of 'being a totally ordered set in which every non-empty subset that has an upper bound has a least upper bound' is not axiomatizable (it is not even pseudo-axiomatizable). Lemma 3.76 {fa property is finitely axiomatizable, then so is its negation. Proof This is immediate from the definition: if a property is axiomatized by the closed formula F, its negation is axiomatized by the formula -.F. Lemma 3.77 axiomatizable. • �fa property is not axiomatizable, then its negation is not finitely Proof This follows from the contrapositive of the previous lemma. • To show that a property is axiomatizable, it obviously suffices to find a set of closed formulas whose models are precisely the structures that have the property in question. One suspects that it is a more delicate matter to show that a property is not axiomatizable. The fact that you have not found a theory that works clearly does not imply that such does not exist. The example of lR and Q suggests a possible route: find two elementarily equivalent structures, one of which satisfies the property while the other does not. Many of the exercises will focus on this type of question. We will treat some simple examples a bit further on. Beforehand, let us develop a very efficient tool for resolving not only these problems of non-axiomatizability but also numerous other problems of model theory. This is the compactness theorem for predicate calculus, which we should consider as one of the 'grand' theorems of mathematical logic. Only in Chapter 4 will we see the proof, but it would be unfortunate not to allow ourselves the possibility of using it right away (which will be done in many of the exercises), especially since its statement is very simple, all the more for those who have previously studied the analogous theorem for propositional calculus. Theorem 3.78 (with the axiom ofchoice) For a theory in afirst order language to be consistent, it is necessary and sufficient that it be finitely consistent. As for the propositional calculus, this compactness theorem has several equiva­ lent versions: l-or a first order theory to be contradictory, it is necessary and SU;{ficient that some finite subset be contradicto1y. 172 PREDlCATE CALCULUS Or again: For a closedformula F ofa.first order language L to be a semantic consequence ofa theory T of L, it is necessary and sufficient that there exists a .finite subset To ofT such that F is a semantic consequence of To. The equivalence of these three versions follows directly from Theorem 3.5 1 . Also, the 'necessary' part of the first version and the 'sufficient' part of the other two are evident. We will now examine the question of the axiomatizability of some standard properties, relative to structures for the simplest possible language: the language whose only symbol is the equality symbol. Clearly, these structures are none other than the non-empty sets. For every integer n > 2, the property 4is a set with at least n elements' is finitely axiomatizable thanks to the formula: 1\ ......, vl· ,.....__ vJ· . - l <i<j< n The property 'is a set with at most n elements' is axiomatizable by the formula -., Fn + l · The property 'is an infinite set' is axiomatizable by the following theory: { Fn :n EN and n > 2 } . Two natural questions now arise. I s the property 'is a n infinite sef finitely ax­ iomatizable? Is the property 'is a finite set' axiomatizable? The answer in both cases is 'no' . Theorem 3.79 The property 'is a finite set' is not pseudo-axiomatizable. Proof The proof is by contradiction. Suppose T is a theory in a language L that conforms with the properties required by Definition 3.75. Then T U { Fn : n E N and n > 2 } is a set of closed formulas of L that is contradictory (for to satisfy it, a set would have to be both finite and infinite!). By the compactness theorem, we can find a finite subset T' c T U { f�1 : n E N and n > 2} that is contradictory. There certainly exists an integer p such that T' c Tp = T U { Fn : 2 .� n < p}. S o the theory Tp itself i s contradictory. But we can see right away that this i s false: for the finite set {2, 3, . . . , p} is, according to our hypothesis, the underlying set of at least one L-structure M that is a model of T, and M obviously satisfies F2, • F3, . . . , Fp, so is a model of Tp. From Lemma 3 .77, we also immediately obtain: Theorem 3.80 The ptvperty 'is an infinite set ' is notfinitely axiomatizable. FIRST STEPS IN MODEL THEORY 1 73 However, the infinite sets are precisely those that can support a dense total order­ ing. So we might say that 'being an infinite set' is a 'pseudo-finitely-axiomatizable' property. Here is another absolutely fundamental notion: Definition 3.81 A theory ( 1 ) T is consistent; and T in a language L is complete �fand only if (2) all the models of T are elementarily equivalent. Lemma 3.82 For a theory T in a language L to be complete, it is necessary and SU;fjicient that ( I ) T is consistent; and (2)for every closedformula F of L, we have that either T r-* F or T r-* -,F. Proof If the second condition is not satisfied, we can find a closed formula F of L such that T ¥* F and T ¥* -,F, which means that there are two models M and N of T such that M Jt= F and N Jt= F, or in other words, M � F and N t= F. So we see that M :/=. N, which contradicts condition (2) of the definition and so T is not complete. Conversely, if T is not complete but is consistent, we can find two models A and B of T such that A ¢= B, which proves that there is some closed formula F that is satisfied in A but not in B; so neither T r-* F nor T r-* -,p can -, • hold. Example 3.83 In the language whose only symbol is equality, the theory con­ sisting of the single formula 'v'vo'v'v1 vo � VI is complete. Indeed, the models of this theory are the sets with only one element; these are all isomorphic, hence elementarily equivalent. In this same language, the empty theory is not complete: indeed, every L-structure is a model of this theory and it is not difficult to find two L-structures that are not elementarily equivalent; thus a set with only one element satisfies the formula 'v'vo'v' v1 vo :::: VI but a set with at least two elements does not satisfy it. The fact that a theory is complete or not depends in an essential way on the chosen language: if we consider the formula 'v'vo 'v'v1 vo � VJ as a formula of a language that has, in addition to the symbol ::::, a unary relation symbol P, we see immediately that it is no longer a complete theory, for some of its models will satisfy 3vo P vo and others will not. Remark 3.84 Having some more interesting examples in mind, let us consider another defini­ tion: Given an L-structure M, the set ofclosedformulas of L that are satisfied in M is called the theory of M and is denoted by Th(M): Definition 3.85 T h(M) = {F Theorem 3.86 E F(L) : F is closed and M t= F}. For any L-structure M , Th(M) is a complete theory of L. 174 PREDICATE CALCULUS Proof On the one hand, Th(M) is consistent since M is, evidently, a model. On the other hand, for any closed formula F of L, we have • • either M F F , in which case F E Th(M), so 1n(M) t-* F; orelse M � F, in which case M F -.F, so -,F E Th(M) and Th(M) t- * -.F. • Invoking Lemma 3.82 now completes the proof. We will find many examples of complete and incomplete theories in the exercises. 3.6.3 The language associated with a structure and formulas with parameters Consider a language L and an L-structure M == (M, . . . ) . We will enrich the language L to a language, denoted by LM and called the language associated with the L-structure M, in the following way: with each element a E M, we associate a new constant symbol denoted by a_; we assume that these new symbols are really new (i.e. are distinct from all the symbols of L) and that they are pairwise distinct (if a =/= b, then a =/= b). We then set LM == L U {a. : a E M } . It i s then not very difficult to enrich M into a n L M -structure. We must decide on an interpretation for each of the new symbols. No one will be surprised when we decide to interpret the symbol a by the element a. If we denote the enriched structure by M*, we then have for every a E M: a M* - a - - ' and we assign to the symbols of L the same interpretations in M* that they had in M. With every formula F == F[vo. VI , Vm- d of L and with every nt-tuple (ao, a 1 , , am - 1 ) of elements of M, we can, in a natural way, associate a closed formula of the language LM: specifically, the formula Faofvo.a 1 jv1 , ,am--I_/vm - l which, according to our conventions, could also be written . • • • . , • ••• F[ao, a r , . . . , am-dWe then obtain the following result: The following properties are equivalent: ( 1 ) (M : vo � ao, v 1 � a 1 , , Vm - I � am - 1 ) F F (2) M* F F[ao, a r, . . . , am - d· Proof Recall that F[ao, a1, . . . , am- I ] is the following formula of L M : Theorem 3.87 • . . 175 FIRST STEPS IN MODEL THEORY Before giving the proof, we should note that it will provide the justification that we promised in Section 3 .3.2 for the notation: (*) that we have already suggested as a possible abbreviation for property ( 1 ) above (and of which we have already made use). Indeed, we get from property (2) to (*) by forgetting to place the asterisk on M and to underline the a; . The abuses that consist in identifying, on the one hand, the elements of a model with the constant symbols that represent them in the enriched language, and, on the other hand, identifying the model with its natural enrichment to this language, present no real da111ger and we will often adopt them. Once the theorem is proved� an assertion such as (*) can have two distinct meanings but the theorem tells us precisely that these meanings may legitimately be treated as one. • In fact� this theorem is a special case of the following more general result: For any integers p and q, anypairwise distinct variables xo, x 1 , . . . , Xp-- 1 , yo, YJ, . . . , Yq- 1 , any L-formula G = G [xo, X J , . . . , X p-I , yo, YI , . . . , Yq-d and any ( p + q)-tuple (ao,a J , . . . , ap- 1 , bo, b 1 , . . . , bq-l) of elements of M, the following two properties are equivalent: ( 1 ) (M : xo � ao, XI ---+ a 1 , . . . , x p- l ---+ a p-I , Yo ---+ bo, Y 1 ---+ b 1 , . . . , Yq- t � bq - l ) I= G; Lemma 3.88 (2) (M* : YO - � bo, YI � bt, . . . , Yq- 1 ---+ hq-1 ) I= Gao/xo,l�j_/XJ. ... ,ap-t /Xp- 1 " Proof The proof is by induction on G. If G is the atomic formula Rtt t2 . . . lk (where !t , t2, . . . , lk are terms of the language whose variables are among xo, X I , . . . , Xp- 1 , yo, Y I , . . . , Yq- I), then property ( 1 ) is equivalent to tk [ao, . . . , a p- I , bo, . . . , bq- d) E -M R , (t1-� [ao , . . . , ap- t , bo, . . . , bq- I L . . . , -M and property (2) is equivalent to t 1 * [ao M* , . . . , a p -1 M* , bo , . . . , bq- t J , . , (-M -M* tk [ao M* , . . . , a p-I M* , bo, . . . , bq -I ] ) E -M* R . • -M* -M . Now, R t_; = -M t.i for I < j < k since these are symbols for a = R and -M* relation and for terms of L. The desired equivalence is now a consequence of the definition of the a_; M* . The other steps in the induction are easy. Let us examine existential quantifica­ tion: if G = 3zH[xo, X I , . . . , Xp- l , yo, YI , . . . , Yq-- 1 , zJ (for reasons mentioned in Theorem 3.70 and in Theorem 3 .72, we may suppose that z is distinct from the 1 76 PREDICATE CALCULUS x; and the yj ), then property ( 1 ) means that there exists an element a E M such that (M : xo � ao, . . . , Xp- 1 -� ap- 1 , yo � bo, . . . , Yq - 1 -) bq- 1 , z -� a) F= H, which is equivalent, by the induction hypothesis, to the existence of an element a E M such that (M* : YO -� bo, Yl � h 1 , . . . , Yq-1 ---'> bq- 1 , Z � a) F Haofxo,l_!J../X I , ... ,ap-1 /Xp- 1 ; but, by the definition of satisfaction, this is equivalent in turn to and this last formula is none other than equivalence of properties ( l ) and (2). Gaofxo.'!.J.fx 1 , . . . ,a" _ 1 fx p - t · This proves the • To obtain the theorem, it obviously suffices to take q = 0 in the lemma. Observe that there was no way to bypass the generalization that this lemma provides: indeed, in the induction proof, it is not possible to only consider closed formulas of the language LM. The formulas of the language L M are often called formulas with parameters in M, the parameters being precisely the elements of M which have 'become' constant symbols. We will use this concept extensively in Chapter 8. At that time, we will have a need for the following two definitions that relate to a model M and a language L : The set ofclosed quant{fier-freeformulas of L M that are satisfied in M* is called the simple diagram of M and is denoted by 6. (M). Definition 3.90 The set of closedformulas of the language L M that are sati.�fied in M* (i.e. the set Th(M*)) is called the complete diagram of M and is denoted by D (M). Definition 3.89 Some authors use the phrase elementary diagram instead ofcomplete diagram. They have an excellent reason for doing this that will appear in Chapter 8. As it is not necessarily simple to make the distinction between simple and elementary, we prefer to insist on our terminology (an elementary precaution . . . ) . We will state right away a result whose proof will be given in Chapter 8. It allows us to characterize, up to isomorphism, the extensions of a structure. 3.91 Given an L-structure M, for an LM-structure N to be a model of the simple diagram of M, it is necessary and st�;fficient that M be isomorphic to a sub-structure of the reduct ofN to the language L. Theorem 3.6.4 Functions and relations definable in a structure Consider a first order language L and an £-structure M = (M, . . . ) . FIRST STEPS IN MODEL THEORY ) 77 Definition 3.92 • • • For any integer k > 1 and any subset A of Mk , A is definable in M by a formula of L ifand only ifthere existsaformula F = F[w 1 , w2, . . . , Wk ] of L with at most k free variables such thatfor all elements a 1 , a2, . . . , ak of M, When this happens, we say that such a formula F is a definition of A in M. An element a E M is said to be definable in M by a formula of L ifthe subset {a} is. Any de_finition of {a} is then called a definition of the element a. For any integer k > I and any map ¢from Mk into M, ¢ is definable in M by formula of L (f and only if there exists a formula F = F [w 1 , w2, . . . , Wk , z] of L with at most k + 1 free variables such thatfor all elements b, a1, a2, . . . , ak of M, a Such a fonnula is then called a definition of¢ in M. When we consider the graph of a map ¢ from Mk into M to be the set { (a 1 , a2, . . . , ak, b) E Mk+ I : b = ¢(a1, a2, . . . , ak)}, we immediately see that such a map i s definable in M by a formula o f L if and only if its graph is also, and that the formulas that define the map are the same ones as those that define its graph. It is important to note that the definability of a subset of Mk or of map from Mk into M depends in an essential way on the language under consideration and on the structure that accompanies the set M. For example, it may happen that a subset that is not definable in M by a formula of L becomes definable in an enrichment of ivt thanks to a formula of the extended language. However, when there can be no reason to fear confusion over the subjects of language or structure, we will be content to speak of a definable subset (or relation) or function, without further precision. Example 3.93 • • The set Mk and the empty set are always definable subsets of Mk : the first, thanks to the formula Wt � w, and the second, thanks to its negation. The set of even integers is definable in the structure (Z, +) by a formula of the language {g} (g is a binary function symbol): it suffices to consider the formula 3 wogwowo = w 1 . For any integer k > I the set ofsubsets of Mk that are definable in Nl by a formula of L is a sub-algebra of the Boolean algebra of all subsets ofMk . Theorem 3.94 , 178 PREDICATE CALCULUS Proof We have just seen that 0 and Mk are definable. Now, if A and B are defin­ k able subsets of M and if F = F[w 1 , w2, . . . , Wk] and G = G[wi , w2 , . . . , Wk] are, respectively, definitions o f A and B, i t is clear that -,p, (F A G) and ( F v G) are, respectively, definitions for the complement of A in Mk , the intersection of A • and B and the union of A and B. Theorem 3.95 If k is an integer greater than or equal to I and A is a subset of Mk that is definable in M by a formula of L and if h is an automorphism of the structure M, then the set A is invariant under h (this means that for all elements a t, a2 , . . . , ak ofM, if(ar , a2, . . . , ak) E A, then (h(ar), h(a2), . . . , h (ak)) E A). Proof Suppose that F = F [w 1 , w2, . . . , Wk] is a formula of L that defines A C Mk and that a 1 , a2, . . . , ak are elements of M. If (at , a2 , . . . , ak) E A, then M F F[ar , a2, . . . , ak ]; i n this case, then for any automorphism h o f the structure M, we also have M F F[h(a t ) , h (a2), . . . , h(ak)] (by Theorem 3.72), which proves that (h(at ) , h(a2), . . . , h (ak ) ) E A (because F is a definition of A) . • This theorem is useful when we want to show that a set is not definable: to do this, it suffices to find an automorphism of the structure under consideration that does not leave the set in question invariant. To illustrate this, let us prove that no subsets offfi( other than JR( and 0 are definable in the structure (JR, <) by a formula of the language { R } (R is a binary relation symbol). We will argue by contradiction; suppose that there is a subset A c JR( , distinct from {Fg and 0, that is definable by a formula F == F[ w] of this language. Then choose an element a E A (A is not empty) and an element b E 1R - A (JR - A is not empty). Observe that the map h from JR( into JR( which, with every real x, associates the real x + b - a , i s an automorphism o f ( JR, < ) which does not leave A invariant (since h(a) = b), which contradicts the previous theorem. Next, we will introduce the notion of definability with parameters, which generalizes the notion we just studied. We still consider a first order language L and an L-structure M = (M, . . . ). For any integer k greater than or equal to I and any subset A of Mk, A is definable with parameters from M if and only if there exist an integer m > I, aformula F = F[w 1 , w2, . . . , Wk, Z l , 22, . . . , zm] ofL with at most k + m free variables, and m elements b 1 , b2, . . . , bm of M such thatfor all elements a 1 , a2, . . . , ak of M, Definition 3.96 When this happens, the formula F[ w 1 , w2, . . . , Wk, b 1 , b2 , . . . , bm] is called a definition of A in M with parameters b 1 , b2, . . . , bm . The notion of a map from Mk into M that i s definable with parameters from M has an analogous definition. MODELS THAT MAY NOT RESPECT EQUALITY 1 79 For example, every finite subset { 0:'1, a2 , . . . , ap } of M is definable in M with the parameters a 1 , 0:'2, . . . , aP thanks to the formula w � O:'i . v l i p << We immediately see that to be definable with parameters from M is equivalent to being definable (in the sense of Defi.nition 3.92) by a formula of the language l�M in the structure M*, the natural enrichment of M to LM (see Theorem 3 .87). 3.7 Models that may not respect equality Our excursion into this topic will be as brief as possible. We consider a language that includes the symbol for equality, �. Let E denote the theory of L that consists of the following closed formulas (called the axioms of E�quality) : • • • • the formula: Vvovo vo; the formula: VvoVv1 (vo � VJ ==? v1 � vo); the formula: VvoVv1 Vv2((vo � v1 /\ v1 v2) ==? vo i".J v2); and every k-ary function symbol f of L, the formula: � for every integer k > I Vv1 . . . VvkVVk+l . . . Vv2k • 1\ v; ( l<i< k � Vk+i i".J ) fvl . . . Vk � fvk+l . . . V2k ; => for every integer k > I and every k-ary relation symbol R of L, the formula: Vv1 . . . VvkVvk+ 1 . . . Vv2k (( Rv1 . . . Vk 1\ 1\ I <i<k v; � Vk+i ) => ) RVk + J . . . v2k . It is quite clear that all of these formulas are satisfied in any L-structure that respects equality. Consider an arbitrary L-structure M = ( M, . . . ) in which the symbol for equal­ ity, :::::, is interpreted by some binary relation on M that we will denote by e . We are going to show that if M is a model of the theory E, then we can define from M, in a natural way, another model that does respect equality and possesses some interesting properties. So suppose that M F= E. Then, according to the fi rst three formulas of E, the relation () is an equivalence relation on M that is, according to the remaining formulas of E, compatible with the functions and relations of the structure. Let A denote the quotient Mje (the set of equivalence classes relative to e). The equivalence class of the element a E M will be denoted by cl(a). We can make A into an L-structure A by defining the interpretations of the symbols of L in the following way: • for each constant symbol c of L, cA = cl(cM ); 1 80 • • PREDICATE CALCULUS for every integer k > I and every k-ary function symbol f of L, .FA is the map from A k into A which, to each k-tuple (cl(a t ) , cl(a2), . . . , cl(ak)) E A k , assigns M the element cl(f (at , a2, . . . , ak)); this makes sense because e is compatible -M with f ; for every integer k > 1 and every k-ary relation symbol R of L, R A is the A k-ary relation on A defined by: (cl(a i ), cl(a2), . . . , cl(ak )) E R if and only M if (a I , a2, . . . , ak) E R (again, this makes sense because e is compatible -M with R ) . We see immediately that the £-structure A defined i n this way respects equality: indeed, the interpretation in A of the symbol � is the set of pairs (cl(a), cl(b)) E A 2 such that (a, b) E ""'M , i.e. such that (a, b) E e , or equivalently, such that cl(a) = cl(b ) ; this is precisely the diagonal of A 2 • For every formula F = F [ vo, v 1 , , Vn- 1 ] of L and for all ele­ ments ao, a 1 , , an-- I , bo, bt , . . . , bn - I of M, we have: ( 1 *) if (a; , b;) E e for O < i < n - 1 , then M F F[ao, a t , . . . , an- I ] if and only il M F= F[bo, b t , . . . , bn - d: (2*) M F= F[ao, a t , . . . , an-- I l ifandonly ifA t= F[cl(ao), cl(a 1 ) , . . . , cl(an - 1 )]. Lemma 3.97 . . • . • . Proof We prove these two properties by induction on F. The case for atomic formulas is settled by the very definition of A. Next, Remark 3.57 allows us to limit our attention to the induction steps that relate to , 1\ and 3. It is only this last one that deserves any effort: so suppose, then, that -. F = 3vm G[ vo, V I , . . . , Vn- 1 , Vm ] . We may suppose that m > n - 1 i n view of a remark that we have made o n many earlier occasions. Under these conditions, for M to satisfy Ff ao, a 1 , . , a11 _ 1 ] , it is necessary and sufficient that there exist an element b E M such that M F= G [ao, a 1 , . . . , an - 1 , b]. Given that G satisfies the lemma (by the induction hypoth­ esis) and that for every b E M, (b, b) E e (the first formula of E), if (a; , b;) E e for all i, then we may conclude that M t= F[ao, a 1 , . . . , an- t ] if and only if there exists an element b E M such that M t= G[bo, bt , . . . , bn-1 , b J. In other words, M F= F[ao, a 1 , . . . , an- d if and only if M t= F[bo, b1 , . . . , bn-d, which proves (I *). In the same way, we see b y the induction hypothesis that M F= F[ao, a 1 , . . . , an- I ] if and only if there exists an element b E M such that . . A t= G [(CI(ao), cl(ai), . . . , cl(an _ ! ), cl(b)], which is equivalent to {A : vo -� cl(ao), V) ---4 cl(at), . . . , Vn- 1 � cl(an- I ) } F= 3vm G, M O D E L S T H A T M A Y N O T R E S P E C T EQ U A L I T Y 181 or again, to A f= Ffcl(ao), cl(a 1 ), . . . , cl(an-1 )] ; this proves property (2*) for F . • For a theory T of a language L containing � to have a model that respects equality, it is necessary and sufficient that the theory T U E have an (arbitrary) model. Proof lf T has a model that respects equality, then E is satisfied in such a model, as we have already noted just after the definition of E; hence, T U E has a model. If T U E has a model M = (M, . . . ) , then since M is a model of E, we can, as above, construct the model A on the quotient of M by the interpretation in M of Theorem 3.98 the symbol � - It is a consequence of the preceding lemma that every formula of T (recall that these are closed formulas) that is satisfied in M will also be satisfied • in A. So the structure A is a model of T that respects equality. The reader who is interested can show that the second and third formulas in the list of axioms of equality (the ones that express the symmetry and transitivity of equality) could have been omitted for they are derivable from the ones that express compatibility with the relations of the structure (among which can be found, naturally, the interpretation of � ) . 1 82 PREDICATE CALCULUS E X ERCISES FOR C HAPTER 3 1. The language L consists of a unary function symbol symbol g. Consider the foilowing closed formulas: Ft : F2 : F3 : F4 : Fs : F6 : f and a binary function 3x3yfgxy � fx Vx\:lyfgxy � fx 3y\:lxfgxy ;--v fx \:lx3yfgxy ;--v fx 3x\:lyfgxy � fx \:ly3xfgxy � fx. Consider the four structures whose underlying set is N*, where g is interpreted by the map (m, n) � m + n, and where f is interpreted respectively by (a) the constant map equal to 103; (b) the map which, with each integer n, associates the remainder after division by 4; (c) the map n � inf(n 2 + 2, 19); - ·., (d) the map which, with each integer n, associates 1 if n = 1 and the smallest prime divisor of n if n > 1 . For each of the six formulas� determine whether it is satisfied or not in each of the four structures. 2. The Language consists of a unary predicate symbol P and a binary predicate symbol R. Consider the following six formulas: 3x'Vy3z((Px ==> Rxy) 1\ Py 1\ --.Ryz) G2 : 3x3z((Rzx ==} Rxz) ==} \:lyRxy) G3 : \:ly(3z\:lt Rtz 1\ \:lx(Rxy ==> --.Rxy)) G4 : 3x\:ly((Py ==> Ryx) 1\ (\:lu(Pu ==} Ruy) ==> Rxy)) Gs : \:lx\:ly((Px 1\ Rxy) ==} ((Py 1\ --.Ryx) ==> 3z(--.Rzx 1\ --.Ryz))) G 6 : \:lz\:lu3x\:ly((Rxy 1\ Pu) ==} (Py ==} Rzx)). G1 : For each of these formulas, determine whether or not it is satisfied i n each of the three L-structures defined below: (a) The base set is N, the interpretation of R is the usual order relation < , the interpretation of P is the set of even integers. E X E R C I S ES FOR C HA PTER 3 1 83 (b) The base set is 6J (N) (the set of subsets of N), the interpretation of R is the inclusion relation c, the interpretation of P is the collection of finite subsets of N. (c) The base set is �, the interpretation of R is the set of pairs (a , b) E �2 such that b a 2 , the interpretation of P is the subset of rational numbers. 3. The language L has two unary function symbols f and g. (a) Find three closed formulas F, G, and H o f L such that for every L-structure M :::: {M, f, g }, we have :::: M I= F if and only if f :::: g and f is a constant map; M I== G if and only if lm(f) c lm(g); M I== H if and only if lm(/) n lm(g) contains a single element. (b) Consider the following five closed formulas of L : F1 : F2 : F3 : F4 : Fs : 'Vxfx � gx 'Vx'Vyfx � gy 'Vx3yfx � gy 3x'Vyfx � gy 3x3yfx � gy Find a model for each of the following six formulas: 4. Let L be a first order language. For every formula F[vo, v1 , . . . , Vk ] of L, the expression 3 ! vo F denotes the following formula: 3!voF is read: 'there exists one and only one vo such that F' . Note that i n any L-structure M :::: (M, . . . ) , 3!vo F i s satisfied by a k-tuple (a t , a2, . . . , ak) if and only if there exists a unique object a E M such that the (k + 1 )-tuple (a , a1 , a2, . . . , ak) satisfies F. Let F[vo, v t ] be a formula of L. Find a closed formula G of L which is satisfied in an L-structure M = (M, . . . ) if and only if there exists a unique pair (a, b) E M2 such that (M vo � a, Vt � b) F= F. Are the formulas : equivalent? 5. Let L be a first order language and let A [ x, y] be an arbitrary formula of L with two free variables. 1 84 PREDICATE CALCULUS (a) rs the formula 'v'x3y A [x, y] ==> 3y'v'xA[x, y] satisfied in any L-structure? (b) Repeat question (a) for the formula 3yVxA [x, y] ==> 'v'x3yA[x, yj. (c) Show that for arbitrary formulas with two free variables A [x, y l and B [x, y ], the following formula is universally valid: ('v'x'v'y A[x , y] ==> 3x3y B [x, y]) (d) Let F be the formula <=? 3x3y(A[x , y] ==> B [x, y ]). 'v'x'v'y(A[x, y] ==> A [y, x]) ==> (('v'u'v'v(A[u, v] ==> B[u, v]) ==> 3x3y(A[x , yJ ==> C[x, y J))) where A , B and C are arbitrary formulas with two free variables. Show that there exists a quantifier-free formula G = Gfx, y] with two free variables such that F is universally equivalent to 3x3yG. 6. Show that i f two formulas are universally equivalent, then so are their universal closures. 7. In all of the languages considered in this exercise, R is a binary relation symbol, * and EB are binary function symbols, c and d are constant symbols. We will write x EB y and x * y respectively, rather than EBxy and *XY (with a reminder that this necessitates the use of parentheses when writing terms). x2 will be an abbreviation for x * x . (a) I n each o f the following six cases ( 1 < i < 6), a language Li and two Li-structures Ai and Bi are given and you are asked to find a closed formula of Li that is true in Ai and false in Bi . At = (N, <) ( 1 ) L I = {R} BI = (/Z, <) (2) L 2 { R } A2 = (Q, <) B2 = (/Z, < ) (3) L 3 = { * } A3 = (N, x) B3 == (8'J (N), n) (4) L4 = {c, *} A4 = (N, 1, x ) B4 = (Z, 1, X ) (5) Ls = {c, d, EB, * } As = (JR, 0, 1, +, x } Bs = ( Q, O, 1, +, x } A6 = (Z, -2) (6) L6 = { R } B6 = (Z, =3) ( x and + are the usual operations of multiplication and addition, n is the operation of intersection, =P is the relation of congruence modulo p.) (b) For each of the following closed formulas of the language {c, EB, *, R}, find a model of the formula as well as a model of its negation. :::= Ft : 'v'u'v'v3x( -.v � c ==> u EB (v * x) � c) F2 : VuVvVw3x (-.w � c ==> u EB (v * x) EB (w * x2 ) � c) 1 85 EXERCISES FOR CHAPTER 3 F3 : VxVyVz (Rxx /\ ( ( Rxy /\ Ryz) : VxVyVz (Rxx => R x * z y * z) F4 => Rxz) /\ (Rxy => Ryx)) VxVy(Rxy => -,Ryx ) . Fs : 8. The language L consists o f a single binary predicate symbol, R . Consider the L-structure M whose base set is M = {n E N : n > 2 } and in which R is interpreted by the relation 'divides', i.e. R is defined for all integers m and n > 2 by the condition: (m, n ) E R if and only if m divides n. (a) For each ofthe following formulas o f L (with one free variable x ) , describe the set of elements of M that satisfy it. Ft : F2 : F3 F4 : : Vy(Ryx => x :::: y) VyVz ((Ryx A Rzx) => (Ryz v Rzy)) Vy\lz (Ryx => (Rzy � Rxz)) Vt3y3z(Rtx => (Ryt /\ Rzy /\ _,Rtz)). (b) Write a formula G[x, y, z , t ] of L such that for all a , b, c and d of M , the structure M satisfies G [a, b, c, d] if and only if d is the greatest common divisor of a, b and c. (c) Let H be the following closed formula of L: VxVyVz((3t (Rtx/\Rty) A3t (Rty/\Rtz)) ::::} 3tVu (Rut => (Rux/\Ruz))). ( I ) Find a prenex form of H. (2) Is the formula H satisfied in M? (3) Give an example of a structure M' = (M', R) such that when M is replaced by M' in the previous question, the answer is different. 9. Let L be the first order language which has one unary relation symbol Q and two binary relation symbols I and R . Consider the following formulas o f L: : 'tfx-,Rxx F2 : Vx(Qx => -,Rxx) Ft F3 : F4 : Fs : F6 : F1 : Fs : Fy : FLO : VxVy\lz ((Qx A Qy /\ I xz /\ I zy) => Qz) VxVyVz((Qx /\ Qy /\ Qz /\ Rxy /\ Ryz) => Rxz) Vx't/y((Qx /\ Qy) => ( -,Rxy v -, Ryx)) VxVy((Qx /\ Rxy) => Qy) Vx\ly(Qx /\ Ryx) => Qy) Vx3y3z (Ryx /\ Rxz) Vx3y3z (Qx => ( Ryx /\ Rxz /\ Qy /\ Qz)) VxVy3z((Qx /\ Qy /\ Rxy) => ( Rx z /\ Rzy /\ Qz) ) . (a) Consider the L-structure M whose base set is &J (N), i n which the inter­ pretation of Q is the unary relation '. . . is infinite and its complement is infinite', the interpretation of I is is the inclusion relation, and the pairs 1 86 PREDICATE CALCULUS that satisfy the the interpretation of the binary relation R are those for which A c B and card(A) = card(B - A) (the notation card(X) denotes the cardinality of a set X; see Chapter 7). For each of the formulas above, determine whether it is satisfied or not in the structure M. (b) We add a new unary predicate symbol D to the language. ls i t possible to enrich the structure M with an interpretation of D such that the following four formulas are satisfied? (A, B) G1 : G2 : G3 : G4 : VxVy((Dx /\ Dy) => (Ixy v Iyx)) VxVy3z((Dx /\ Dy /\ I xy A -.x � y) => (Dz /\ Ixz /\ Izy /\ -,x � z /\ -.y � z)) Vx3y3z(Dx => (Dy /\ Dz /\ Ixy /\ I zx /\ -.x 3xDx � y 1\ -.x � z)) 10. Let L be a language and let F be a formula of L . The spectrum of F i s the set o f cardinalities o f finite models o f F; i.e. it is the set of natural numbers n such that F has a model whose base set has exactly n elements; it is denoted by Sp( F). (a) For each of the following subsets of N, exhibit, when this is possible, an example of a language L and a closed non-contradictory formula F of L whose spectrum is the subset in question. ( 1 ) 0 ; (2) N; (3) N*; (4) {n E N* : (3p E N') (n = 2p)}; (5) {n E N* : (3p E N) (n = p2 ) } ; (6) { 3 } ; (7) { 1 , 2, 3, 4}; (8) N - {O, I , . . . , k}; (9) the set of non-zero composite natural numbers; ( 1 0) the set of prime numbers. (b) Show that any formula whose spectrum is infinite has at least one infinite model. 1 1 . Show that if all the models of a non-contradictory theory are isomorphic, then the theory is complete. 12. Let L be a first order language, let M be an L-structure and let A be a subset of the base set of M . (a) Show that if A i s not empty, there exists a unique sub-structure A of M such that: ( 1 ) the base set of A includes A ; (2) every sub-structure o f M whose base set includes A i s an extension of A. A is called the substructure of M generated by A . (b) Show that, when A = 0, there may not be a substructure generated by A . Give an example, however, i n which one does exist. 1 87 EXERCISES FOR CHAPTER 3 (c) Suppose that L contains no function symbols of arity > 1 . What is the substructure generated by a subset A in this case? (d) A sub-structure N of M is said to be of finite type if and only if N is generated by a non-empty finite subset of M . Let F be a closed universal formula of L. Show that F is satisfi.ed in M if and only if F is satisfi.ed in every sub-structure of M of finite type. (e) Give a counterexample to (d) for a formula that is not universal. 13. The language L consists of one constant symbol c and two unary function symbols f and g. The theory T consists of the following formulas: Ht : H2 : H3 : H4 : Hs : Vvoffvo � fvo Vvoggvo � gvo Vvo(fgvo � c 1\ gfvo ::::: c) VvoVvt ((f vo � fvt 1\ g vo ::::: gvt ) ==> vo ::::: V I ) Vv1Vv2 ((fv 1 ::::: V I 1\ gv2 �2) => 3vo(fvo � VI 1\ gvo � v2)). (a) Show that for any term t of L, at least one of the following cases applies: T !-* t � c; o there exists a variable x such that T 1- * t � x ; o there exists a variable x such that T 1- * t � fx ; o there exists a variable x such that T 1- * t � gx . (b) Let A and B be two non-empty sets with ao E A and bo E B . We denote by M (A , B, ao, bo) the L-structure whose underlying set is A x B , and in which c is interpreted by (ao, bo), f by the map (a, b) r------7 (a, bo) and g by the map (a, b) � (ao, b). Show that M(A, B, ao, bo) is a model of T. (c) Show that the following formulas are consequences o f T : o H6 : H1 : Hs : Hg : Hio : H1 1 : H12 : H13 : fc � c gc � c Vvo(fvo � vo <=> gvo � c) Vvo(gvo � vo <=> fvo � c) Vvo(f vo � vo {:} 3vt jv1 � vo) Vvo(gvo ::::: vo <=> 3vtgVI � vo) Vvo((fvo � vo 1\ gvo � vo) <=> vo � c) VvoVvt (f vo � gvi => fvo � c). (d) Given four non-empty sets A, B, C and D and four elements ao E A, bo E B, co E C, and do E D, show that i f A and C are equipotent and if B and D are equipotent (two sets are called equipotent if there exists a bijection between them), then the structures M(A, B, ao, bo) and M (C, D , co, do) are isomorphic. 1 88 PREDICATE CALCULUS (e) Let M = ( M, a, A = {X E M : cp , l/1 ) be a model of T. Set cp (x) = X}, B == {X E M : lj! (X) = X } , ao = ho = a. Show that M is isomorphic to the structure M ( A , B, ao, bo) . For every integer n > I , write a closed formula Fn (respectively Gn ) of L that is true in M if and only if the set A (respectively, B) contains at least n elements. Show, for all integers n and p > 1.. that the theory is complete. (f) Let F be a closed formula of L that is satisfied in every infinite model of T. Show that there exists at least one integer n such that T U { Fn v Gn } 1-* F. Is the theory T U { Fk v G : k E N* } complete? k The last two questions make use of concepts that will be introduced only in Chapters 7 and 8. (g) Describe all the countable models of T. (h) Is the theory T'' = T U { Fk : k E N*} U { Gk : k E N* } complete? (To answer this question, we will need Vaught's theorem (see Volume 2).) 14. The language L consists of one unary function symbol f . We let A denote the following formula: Vx (fffx � x 1\ -.fx � x) . (a) Show that the following formula i s a consequence of A: Vx3y'Vz(-,ffx � x 1\ -,ffx � f x 1\ fy � x 1\ (.fz � x =? z � y)). For every integer n E N*, we let Fn denote the following formula; 3xr 3x2 . . . 3xnvx (( 1\ 1 <i < j <n -·x; � Xj) !\ ( V 1 <i <n x � x; )) . (b) Show that, for every integer n E N*, the fonnula A 1\ Fn has a model if and only if n is a multiple of 3. (c) Show that, for every p E N*, the theory { A , F3P } is complete. (d) Exhibit a countable model of the formula A (i.e. a model of A whose base set is in bijection with the set of natural numbers). (e) Show that all the countable models of A are isomorphic. 15. The language L consists of two unary function symbols r and I. For every term t of L, set r0t = t0t = t and, for every integer k, r k+l t = rr kt and zk+ l t = Itk t . 1 89 E X E R C I S E S FOR C H A PT E R 3 Let F be the formula Yx'v'y3u3v(((rx (x ry v lx � ly) ::::} x � y) 1\ � ru 1\ x � lv) 1\ (--.rx � lx 1\ rlx � lr x)), � and for every pair (m, n) of natural numbers, let Fmn be the formula Let T be the theory consisting of F together with the set of all the Fmn such that (m, n) =f. (0, 0). (a) Show that for every term t of L, there exists a variable x and integers m and n such that T 1--* Vx (t � rm ln x). (b) Show that the structure Mo whose underlying set i s Z and l are interpreted respectively by the maps Sr : Si : x Z and where r (i, j) r--+ (i, j + 1 ) (right successor) (i, j) �� (i + 1 , j) (left successor) is a model of T; it will be called the standard model of T. (c) Show that for any two integers A and B, the map hab from Z x Z into Z x Z defined by hab {i, j) = (i + a, j + b) is an automorphism of Mo. (d) Which subsets of Z x Z are definable in the structure Mo by a formula of L? 16. We wil1 allow the following abuse of notation: for every integer n > 1 , we will let 0, 1 , . . . , n - 1 denote the elements of Z/ n Z (i.e. the respective equivalence classes modulo n of 0, 1 , . . . , n - 1 ) and will let + denote addition in this set. (a) The language L has a single unary function symbol f. Consider the following L-structures: M1 = M2 = (ZjnZ, x x + 1) ; (ZjnZ, x r--+ x + 2) . � For each structure, determine which subsets of the underlying set are definable. (b) The language L' has a single binary function symbol g . Consider the following L'-structures: N1 N1 Nt = (Z/37l, (x, y) �� x + y) ; (Z/6Z, (x, y) �� x + y) ; = (�, (x, y) �� xy) . = For each structure, determine which subsets of the underlying set are definable. 1 90 P R E D I C A TE C A L C U L U S (c) The language L" has a single binary relation symbol R. Consider the L"-structure (IR, <}. ( 1) Which subsets of 1R are definable i n this structure? (2) Which subsets of JR2 are definable in this structure? 17. Given an integer n > 2 and a binary relation S on a set E, a cycle of order n (or n-cycle) for S is an n-tuple (at , a 2 , . . . , a11 ) of elements of E satisfying: (at , a2) E S, (a2, a3) E S, . . . , (a11 - t , an ) E S and (an , at ) E S. For example, the usual strict ordering on 1R has no n-cycles, whereas the binary relation on the set { 1 , 2, 3 } whose graph is { ( 1 , 2 ), (2, 3 ), (3, I ) } has 3-cycles but no 2-cycles. In the first order language L that has a single binary relation symbol R, consider, for every n > 2, the following formula Fn : Set T = { Fn : n E N, n > 2 } . We say that a n L-structure ( M , R } i s cycle-free i f for every n > 2 , R has no n-cycles; in the opposite case, we say that the structure has cycles. It is clear that the models of T are the cycle-free L-structures. (a) For every n > 2, exhibit a model of of the formula (b) Show that if G is a closed formula of L that is a consequence of T , there exists at least one integer p > 2 such that G is satisfied in every L-structure in which the interpretation of R has no cycles of order less than or equal to p. (c) Show that every closed formula that is a consequence of T has at least one model that has cycles. (d) Show that T is not equivalent to any finite theory. (Hence the concept of a cycle-free binary relation, which T axiomatizes, is not finitely axiomatiz­ able). 18. Recall that an order relation on a set E is a well-ordering if and only if every non-empty subset of E has a smallest element with respect to this order. This exercise shows that this concept is not pseudo-axiomatizable. Let Lo be the language whose only symbol is a binary relation symbol R and let L be a language that enriches Lo. Show that there does not exist a theory T of L with the following property: for every L0-structure M = (M, p} , p is a well-ordering of M if and only if M can be enriched to an L-structure that is a model of T. To do this, use the language L' obtained from L by adding a countably infinite set of new constant symbols, co, c1, . . . , en, . . . (pairwise distinct) and, for every integer n, consider the following closed formula F11 of L': 1 91 E X E R C I S E S F O R C H A PT E R 3 19. Let L be a first order language and let L' be the language obtained from L by adding new constant symbols CI, c2, . . . , Ck · Consider a theory T and a formula F[X t , X2, . . . , Xk ] of L. Show that if the closed formula F [c1 , c2, . . . , Ck] of L' i s a consequence of T (considered as a theory of L'), then T f-* Vx1 Vx2 . . . Vxk F[x1 , x2, . . . , Xk I (this conclusion concerns only the language L ). 20. We are given a fi rst order language L, an L-structure M = (M, . . ) and a theory T of L. Recall that � (M) denotes the simple diagram of M (Definition 3.89). (a) Assume that no extension of M is a model of T. Show that there exists a quantifier-free formula G [x1 , x2, . . . , Xn] of L such that . T f-* Vx1 Vx2 . . . Vxn G [XI , X2, . . . , Xn] and M Jr Vx 1 Vx2 . . . VxnG [XI , X2 , . . . , Xn]. (Consider the theory T U � (M); use Theorem 3. 91 and Exercise 1 9). (b) Let U (T) denote the set of closed universal formulas of L that are conse ­ quences of T. Show that for the existence of an extension of M that i s a model o f T , i t i s necessary and sufficient that M be a model o f U(T). (This result is a special case of what is called the extension theorem). (c) A sub-structure of M that is generated by a non-empty finite subset of !VI is called a sub-structure of finite type. (The sub-structure of M generated by a non-empty subset A c M is the smallest sub-structure of M whose base set includes A: see Exercise 1 2.) Show that for the existence of an extension of M that is a model of T, it is necessary and sufficient that every sub-structure of M of finite type have this same property. 21. Let L be a first order language and let F1 denote the set of formulas of L that have at most one free variable. Given an L-structure M = (M, . . . ) and an element a E M, the set () (a) of formulas in F1 that are satisfied in M by a is called the type of a in M (or simply, the type of a if there is no ambiguity; this vocabulary will be taken up again in Chapter 8). In other words: () (a ) = { F[v] E F1 : v is a variable and M f= F[a]}. (a) Show that i f all the elements o f a subset A c M have the same type in an L-structure M = (M, . . . ), then every subset of M that is definable in M by a formula of L must either include A or be disjoint from A (see Definition 3.92). (b) Let h be an automorphism of an L-structure M = (M, . . . ), and let a be an element of M. Show that a and h (a ) have the same type. 192 PREDICATE CALCULUS (c) R, f, g and c are, respectively, a binary relation symbol, a unary function symbol, a binary function symbol and a constant symbol. In each of the foilowing examples, find two elements a and b of the proposed model whose types are distinct, or show that this is not possible. L1 = L2 = L3 = L4 = Ls = {R} { f} { f} {g, c} {g} M1 = (JR, < ) ; M2 = (N, n n + 1 ) ; M3 = (Z, n � n + 1 ) ; M4 = (Z, + , 0) ; Ms = (Z, ·+) . � . (d) Let T be a theory of L and let F1 , F2 , . . , Fn be n formulas of Ft (n > 1 ). Suppose that the formula G = VvoVvt ( 1\ l < i <n ( F; [ vo] <o> F; [v t l ) =? vo :::::: Vi) is a consequence of T. Show that every model of T has at most 2 n elements. (e) Let S be a theory of L that has at least one infinite model. Show that there exists a model M = (M, . . . ) of S such that M contains at least two elements that have the same type. (Hint for an argument by contradiction: enrich the language with two new distinct constant symbols and apply the compactness theorem to an appropriate theory in the enriched language, then make use of Exercise 1 9 and the preceding question.) (f) Give an example of a language L and a theory T such that: • there exists at least one model of T of cardinality > 2; • there is no model o f T that contains two distinct elements of the same type. (g) Give an example of an infinite model of a finite language L that contains no distinct elements of the same type. 4 The completeness theorems The formalization that we have implemented thusfar allows us to represent math­ ematical statements, or at least some ofthem, in the form ofsequences ofsymbols. We will now pur suefurther in this direction andformalize proofs. There are many ways of doing this and, let us admit it from the start, the one we have chosen comes with a certain number of inconveniences; in particula1; it does not properly reflect the manner in which proofs are conceived in the minds of mathematicians. Moreover, it does not lend itselfwell to the analysis ofproofs, a topic that is known as proo.ftheory and that we will discuss only briefly in this text. In its favour, our method is a bit closer to the way in which proof� are actually written and, primar­ ily, it requires the introduction offew prerequisites. That is why it appeared to us that this approach is the easiest to understand upon first exposure. A formal proof (or derivation) is a sequence of formulas in which each is just{fied either because it is an axiom or because it can be deduced from for­ mulas that precede it in the sequence. It is quite clear that, provided we do things correctly, a formal p1vo.f can lead only toformulas that are universally valid. The converse of this assertion, namely that eve1y universally validformula has a for­ mal p1vof, is what we will call a completeness theorem; indeed, such a result will show that the axioms and rules that we have allowed ourselves are sufficiently strong, 01� in other words, that they are complete. In Section 4.2 we will present a proof of this that uses a method due to Henkin, and from this we will extract an important, purely semantic consequence, the compactness theorem. The purpose o.{Section 4.3 is to describe Herbrand's method which reduces the satisfiability of aformula ofpredicate calculus to the satisfiability ofan infinite set ofpropositional formulas. An essential aspect ofthese notions is their effective character. For example, here is a natural question: can we find an algorithm that produces proof� of theorems ? We will see late1; in Part 2, Chapter 6, how to think about this question in general terms. In Section 4.4, our interest turns to a restricted class of universal formulas (the universal clauses) and we will introduce a new type ofproof; this is the method o.f resolution. This method is better suited to implementation on computers (it is the basis for the language PROLOG). We will be content to sketch the required algorithms without giving the details of a potential realization. 194 THE COMPLETENESS THEOREMS In this chapter, we will not speak of equality; thus, we will not assume that the equality symbol is part of our language and, when it is, we will not assume that the models we construct necessarily re.\JJect equality. However, thanks to Theorem 3.97, we can reduce to a model that does respect equality. To avoid misunderstandings, the word 'derivation ' will be reserved, throughout this chapte1; to meanformal proof The word 'p1vof' by itselfwill be used to denote what is necessary to prove the stated theorems; so we could, to conform with what was said in the introduction, call these 'meta-derivations '. 4.1 Formal proofs (or derivations) 4.1.1 Axioms and rules In mathematics, to prove a theorem is to derive it from propositions given in ad­ vance, called axioms, according to exactly specified rules. It is this notion of proof that we will formalize in this section. What the axioms are and what the rules are must, therefore, be made absolutely precise. Let us begin with the rules. These are rules that allow us to deduce a formula from one or more other formulas. For the notion of derivation that will be presented here, there are two deduction rules: Definition 4.1 • • THE DEDUCTION RULES Modus ponens: from the two formulas F and F =} G, modus ponens allows us to derive G. The rule of generalization: if F is a formula and v is a variable, the rule of generalization allows us to derive VvF f1vm F. Despite its Latin name, with which you may not be familiar, the idea behind modus ponens is totally banal. The rule of generalization is a bit more troubling but its justification is simple: if we know, without any particular assumptions about v, how to derive F ( v ) , then we know that V v F ( v ) is also true. It is used all the time in mathematics. Imagine, for example, that you wish to prove that every positive integer is the sum of four perfect squares. You would say: let n be a positive integer, and you would develop an argument that concluded with: hence, there exist a, b, c, and d such that n = a 2 + b2 + c2 + d2 , and you would, justifiably, consider the proof to be finished. This is nothing but an application of the rule of generalization in which n plays the role of the free variable. Exercise 5 will help us to appreciate the usefulness of this rule. Definition 4.2 • THE LOGICAL AXIOMS. These are the followingformulas: The tautologies. Recall that the tautologies o.fpredicate calculus are obtained in the following way: we start with a tautology F of the propositional calculus whoseptvpositional variables are, say, A t , A2, . . . , An; we also have nformulas G t , Gz, . . . , Gn of tire language under consideration. Theformula H obtained F 0 R M A L P R 0 0 F S (0 R D E R I V A T I 0 N S) 1 95 by replacing in F all occurrences of A 1 by G 1, all occurrences of A2 by G2, and so on, is, by definition, a tautology of the predicate calculus (see De.finition 3.49). • The quantification axioms. These are grouped into three infinite sets (these infinite sets are usually called axiom schemes): * formulas of theform: (a) where F is an arbitrary formula and v is an arbitrary variable; * formulas of the form: 'Vv ( F � G) � ( F => 'VvG) (b) where F and G are arbitrary formulas and v is a variable that has no free occurrence in F; * formulas of the form: 'V v F => Ft;v (c) where F is a formula, t is a term and there is no free occurrence of v in F that lies in the scope ofa quantification that binds a variable oft. For each of these three axiom schemes, we will show that we are dealing only with universally valid formulas and we will also justify the restrictions that we have placed on the variables. (a) These axioms present no difficulty. Their purpose is to give a syntactical definition of the existential quantifier in terms of the universal quantifier (see part ( 1 ) of Theorem 3.55. (b) This one is not very difficult either (see part ( 1 6) of Theorem 3.55). Clearly� the restriction on the variable v is necessary: for example, consider a language that has only one unary predicate symbol P and set F == G == Pv. Then 'Vv(Pv =} P v ) is always true, while this is not the case for P v =} 'V v P v which means that i f something satisfies P then everything satisfies P. (c) This scheme is the hardest one to understand because the condition that is attached to it is not simple and also, perhaps, because a superficial analysis might lead one to believe that \:fvF =} Ftfv is always satisfied without the need for any restrictions. Let us show that this is an illusion. In the language consisting of the single binary relation symbol R, consider the formula F = 3vt �Rvvl and the term t == v l · So that Ftfv = 3 v t � R v 1 VI and this formula is false, for example, in a structure whose base set contains more than one element and in which R is interpreted by equality. THE COMPLETENESS THEOREMS 196 We can see what is happening: contrary to what we may have naively expected, the formula F1fv does not, in any way, say that the object represented by t possesses the property expressed by the formula F; the reason is that the term t, which, here, is a variable, finds itself quantified in F1fv· Now we will show that all the formulas from scheme (c) are universally valid. Let u 1 , u 2 , . . . , Un be the variables in t and let W J , w2, . . . , Wp be the free variables of Vv F other than u 1 , u 2 , . . . , U n . We insist: the variables Wi are distinct from the u j , but the u j may well occur, either free or bound, in Vv F, and it is possible that the variable v is among the U j . This hypothesis places us precisely in a situation where Proposition 3.45 is applicable. Let M be a structure for the language of F; we will show that the formula VvF ::::} Ftfv is true in M. Consider elements a 1 a2, . . . . an , b t , b2, . . . , bp of the underlying set M of M such that � This means, by definition, that for every element a E M , we have When a is taken to be the element -t M [a1 , a2 , . . . , an ] , we may conclude, thanks to Proposition 3 .45, that which finishes the proof. In fact, schema (c) will be used most frequently in situations where no variable of t is bound in F (which is obviously a stronger condition than the one imposed by schema (c)), and, in particular, when t is a closed term. We will also use it in the fourth example of the next section; that example will itself be used several times during the proof of the completeness theorem. 4.1.2 Formal proofs We can now give the definition of a derivation (or formal proof). Recall that the formulas that constitute a theory are all closed formulas. Definition 4.3 Let T be a theory and F be a formula of L; an L-derivation of F in T is a .finite sequence offormulas V ( Fo, F1 , . . . , Fn ) of L that ends with == F and is such that each F; (jor 0 < i < n) satisfies at least one of the following conditions: • • • Fi E T; Fi is a logical axiom; Fi is derivablefrom one or two of the formulas that precede it in the sequence V by one of the two deduction rules. 197 F 0 R M A L P R 0 0 F S (0 R D E R I V A T I 0 N S) If there exists a L-derivation of F in T, we say that F is L-derivable in T or that F is an L-syntactic consequence of T or that F is an L-theorem of T and we write T �L F. In the case where T is empty, we say that F is L-derivable and we write �L F. For aformula F and a theoty T in a language L, it could happen, at least a priori, that F is notderivablefrom T in L but that it is derivablefrom T {{we allow a richer language. The completeness theorem will show, howeve1� that this is not the case. Once this theorem is proved, we will simply say 'derivable ' rather than ' L-derivable ' and 'syntactic consequence ' instead of 'L-syntactic consequence '. In the meantime, if we do not spec�fically mention the language L, you should consider that the language is fixed and is sufficiently rich that it contains all the formulas and theories determined by the context. Remark 4.4 F and G are two closed formulas and set T { F, G}; we are going to prove that T � F 1\ G. Here i s a sequence of formulas that Example 4.5 Suppose that = constitutes a derivation of F 1\ G in T : (1) (2) (3) (4 ) (5) F G F =} (G =} (F 1\ G)) G =} (F 1\ G ) F 1\ G ( Fisin T ) inT ) (a tautology) (by modus ponens from ( 1 ) and (3)) (by modus ponens from (2) and (4)). ( G is 4.6 Let F be a formula and t be a term and suppose that no free occurrence of v in F is within the scope of a quantification that binds a variable of t. We will show (Table 4. 1 ) that 1- Frtv =} 3vF. Example Table 4.1 (1) Vv-.F => -. Ft;v ( 2) (Vv-. F => -.Ft;v) quantifier axiom of type (c) => ( Ft;v => -.\fv-. F ) Ft;v => -.\fv -.F (4 ) 3v F ¢> -.\fv-.F (5) ( Ft;v => -.\fv-.F ) => ((3v F <=? -.\fv-. F ) => ( F1;v => 3v F )) (6) (3v F <=? -.\fv-. F ) => ( F1;v => 3v F ) (7) Ft;v => 3v F (3) Example 4.7 If tautology obtained from (A => -. B) => (B => -.A) by modus ponens from (1) and ( 2) quantifier axiom of type (a) tautology obtained from (A => B) -=> ((C <=> B) => (A => C)) by modus ponens from (3) and (5) by modus ponens from (4) and (6) w is a variable that has no occurrence in bound), then l- Vw Fw;v :::} Vv F: F (neither free nor THE COM PLETENESS THEOREMS 1 98 The justification for step ( 1 ) in the derivation that follows involves a somewhat acrobatic use of schema (c): in the formula F ; v , the only free occurrences of w are those that replaced the free occurrences of v in F and, quite obviously, these do not lie within the scope of a quantifier that binds v (otherwise, they would not be free !). So formula ( 1 ) in Table 4.2 does belong to axiom schema (c). w Table 4.2 (I) VwFwjv => ( Fw;v ) vjw quantifier axiom of type (c) ( I ') VwFwft• => F since w does not occur in F F so ( I ') is a rewriting of ( I ) (F w/t•) vfw (2) Vv(VwFw;v ==> F) from ( ') by generalization (3) Vv(VwFwjv => F) quantifier axiom of type (b) (4) VwFw;v => VvF = => (VwFwfv => VvF) J since v is not free in VwFw;v by modus ponens from (2) and (3) Example 4.8 Let us prove that 1- VvF :=> F. r�;v , and it is certain Again, this is a use of axiom schema (c). Indeed, F that the free occurrences of v in F do not lie in the scope of a quantification that binds v. Example 4.9 Finally, let us prove (Table 4.3) 1- Vvo'VVI F :=> 'Vv1 VvoF. Table 4.3 (1) Vv0Vv1 F => Vv1 F Example 4.8 Vv1 F => F Example (3 ) (VvoVv1 F => Vv, F) => ((Vv1 F => F) => (VvoVv1 F => F)) a tautology (4) VvoVv1 F => F from ( 1 ) , (2) and (3) by modus ponens. twice (5 ) Vvo(VvoVVI F => F) from (4) by generalization (6) Vvo(VvoVv1 F => F) => (VvoVv, F => Vvo F) axiom schema (b) (7) VvoVv1 F from (5) and (6) by modus ponens (8) Vv1(VvoVv,F (9) (Vv1 (VvoVv 1 F ==> VvoF)) => (VvoVv1F => Vv , VvoF) axiom schema (b) VvoVv, F => Vv1VvoF from (2 ) ( I 0) => VvoF ==> VvoF) 4.8 from (7) by generalization (8) and (9) by modus ponens F 0 R M A L P R 0 0 F S (0 R D E R I V A T I 0 N S) 199 Remark 4.10 Suppose that F =} G is a tautology. Then Vv F =} VvG is a theorem. Example 4.8 a tautology, by hypothesis F =} G (Vv F => F) => ((F => G) => (Vv F => G ) ) a tautology by modus ponens, twice VvF => G by generalization Vv(VvF =} G) axiom schema (b) Vv(Vv F =} G) => (VvF => VvG) by modus ponens VvF =} VvG VvF =} F Remark 4.1 1 Suppose that F is a closedformula, that T � F and that T U { F } I­ G,4 then T 1- G. see this, note that if ( Fo , F1 , . . . , Fn ) is a derivation of F in T (so Fn = F) and (Go, G t , . . . , Gm ) is a derivation of G in T U { F } (so Gm = G), then ( Fo, F1 , . . . , Fn , Go, G l , . . . , G m ) is a derivation of G in T . To Definition 4.12 A theory T is callednon-contradictory in L ifthere is noformula F such that we have both T � L F and T � L --,F simultaneously. If this does happen, T is called contradictory in L. Remark 4.13 If T is contradictory, then every formula is derivable in T. Indeed, suppose that both T � F and T � ., F and let G be an arbitrary formula. Begin a sequence by placing the derivations of F and ···1F end-to-end. To produce a derivation of G from this, it suffices to add to the sequence the following formulas from Table 4.4. ... Table 4.4 F -> ( -.F => G) a tautology -. F => G by modus ponens, since F occurs earlier in the sequence G again by modus ponens, since -.F occurs earlier in the sequence. The converse ('if every formula is derivable in T , then T is contradictory' ) is obvious from the definition. Moreover, we may immediately verify that: Remark 4.14 • • �fT is contradicto1y, thenfor every formula F, T r- F 1\ -, F; for T to be contradictory. it is necessary and sufficient that there exist one formula F such that T � F 1\ -,F. 200 THE COMPLETENESS THEOREMS 4.1.3 The finiteness theorem and the deduction theorem The next simple but extremely important theorem is known as the finiteness theorem. Theorem 4.15 For any theory T and any formula F, finite subset To of T such that To � F. if T � F, then there is a Proof Let V be a derivation of F in T ; it is a finite sequence of formulas. Only a finite number of formulas of T can appear in it. If To is the finite subset of T • consisting of these formulas, then V is also a derivation of F in To. Corollary 4.16 Jf T is a theory all of whose .finite subsets are non-contradictory, then T is non-contradictory. Proof If not, then from T we can derive F 1\ -�F (here, F is an arbitrary formula) and we conclude from the finiteness theorem that F 1\ __,F is derivable from some finite subset To of T; so To is contradictory (by Remark 4.13) and this violates our • hypothesis. Let us be more precise: Proposition 4.17 Let I be an ordered set andfor every i E /, let T; be a theory in a language L; which is not contradictory in L;. Suppose that if i is less than j, then L; C Lj and 1j C 1). Set T = Ui E I T; and L = Ui E / L;. Then the theory T is not contradictory in L. Proof The proof is almost the same as the proofof Corollary 4. 1 6: an L-derivation D of a formula F in T is in fact an L; -derivation in T; for some i E I provided that L; and 1j contains all the formula in D. Such an index i exists. thanks to our • hypothesis. It is more or less obvious that if the formula F =? G is derivable in T, then the formula G is derivable in T U {F} (by modus ponens). The converse of this is a very useful tool and is known as the deduction theorem. Theorem 4.18 Assume that F is a closedformula and that T U { F } � G. Then T t- F =} G. (Go, G 1 , . . . , Gn ) be a derivation of G in T U { F } . We will construct a derivation V' of F =} G in T by inserting various formulas into the sequence (F =} Go, F =} G 1 , . . . , F =} G n ) . Proof Let V • • • = I f G; i s a tautology, there i s n o problem since F ::::} G; i s then also a tautology. If G; is a quantification axiom or is an clement of T, we need to insert the two formulas G; and G; =} (F =} G ; ) (which is a tautology) between F ==> G; - I and F =} G; (or, more simply, in front of F =} G; in case i = 0); F =} G; is then derivable from these two preceding formulas by modus ponens. J f G; = F, there is no problem since F =? F is a tautology. F 0 R M A L P R 0 0 F S (0 R D E R I V A T I 0 N S) • 201 Now suppose that G i is obtained by modus ponens, which is to say that there exist integers j and k, strictly less than i , such that G k is the formula Gj => G i . We then insert the following formulas between F => G i - t and F => Gi: (F => G j ) => ( ( F => ( G j => G; ) ) => ( F => G i)) (this i s a tautology) (this is derived by modus ponens (F => (G j => Gi)) => (F => G i ) from the previous formula together with F => Gj which appears earlier in the sequence) F => (this follows by modus ponens from the previous formula together with F => ( G .i => G i ) which is equal to F => Gk and has therefore also appeared earlier). • Gi Suppose G; is derived by generalization from G.i with j < i (thus, G; is VvG.; ) . Then the following formulas should be inserted between F => G i - 1 and F => G ; : (obtained by generalization from F ::::::> G j ) Vv(F => G i ) (this is quantification axiom because, Vv ( F => Gj) => ( F => VvG j ) since F is closed, v is certainly not free in F) F => G; (this follows by modus ponens from the two preceding formulas). • The next corollary justifies the general use of proofs by contradiction. Corollary 4.19 T � F if and only if T U { ...., F } is contradictory. Proof It is clear that if T � F, then T U { ...., F } is contradictory. Conversely, if T U { -, F} is contradictory, any formula is derivable from it, and, in particular, F ; by applying the deduction theorem� we then see that T r- -,F => F. Now, • ( F => F) => F is a tautology, so we may conclude that T I- F . -. The least of the demands that we might make on derivations is that they should lead to formulas that are true (more precisely, a derivation from a theory should lead to formulas that are semantic consequences of the theory). That is what we will now prove. Theorem 4.20 Let T be a theoty, F a formula and F' a universal closure of F. Then ( ] ) If T and � F, then every model of T is a model of F' (in other words, T r-* F). (2) If'. F, then F' is universally valid. (Recall that the universal closures of a formula are obtained by universally quan­ tifying all the free variables i n the formula; it may have several universal closures because there is a choice in the order of the quantifications: see Definition 3 .20). 202 THE COMPLETENESS THEOREMS Proof Since (2) is a special case of ( 1 ) (take T 0), it suffices to prove ( 1 ). We have already observed that all the axioms are universally valid; their universal closures are therefore true in every model of T. We will now prove the following property by induction on n : = I Let ( Fa , F1 , . . . , Fn ) be a derivation of F� in T and let Fn be a universal closure of Fn ; then T f--* F�. • • Case n = 0: then the formula Fo is either an axiom or else is an element of T . I n both instances, F� i s true i n every model of T . For the passage from n to n + 1 , we distinguish several subcases: * if Fn+ 1 is an axiom or an element of T, then, as in the previous case, every model of T IS a model of Fn+ 1 . * if Fn+ 1 is obtained by modus ponens, there exist integers i and j less than or equal to n such that F; is Fj � Fn+ 1 · Suppose that the free variables of Fi are vo, v 1 , . . . , v (and so the free variables of Fj and of Fn+ 1 are among P these); Fj and Fj => f�+ 1 have derivations whose length is at most n. So by the induction hypothesis, if M is a model of T, then • I and hence, I Because the formulas 'v'vo'lv1 . . . 'v'vp Fn+ l and F11 + 1 are universally equivalent, we may now conclude that M F= Fn + 1 . * if Fn+ 1 is obtained by generalization, there exists an integer i < n and a variable v such that Fn+ 1 = 'v' v F; . Fn + 1 is then a universal closure of F; and • the conclusion now follows from the induction hypothesis. 1 I Corollary 4.21 If T has a model, then T is non-contradictory. Proof If T were contradictory, then formula has no model. F 1\ -,p would be derivable from it, yet this • 4.2 Henkin models We will now prove the converse of the corollary that concluded the previous section: if T is non-contradictory, then T has a model. The proof must necessarily proceed by constructing a model and, for this reason, is certainly much more difficult. We will need a certain number of preliminary definitions and )em mas. 203 HENKIN MODELS 4.2.1 Henkin witnesses Definition 4.22 Let T be a theory in a language L. We say that T is syntactically complete (in L ) if it is not contradicrory in L and if, for every closed formula F of L , we have T �L F or T �L _, F. It is worth noting that the syntactical completeness of T depends on the language in which it is viewed; in principle, if we do not specify the language, it will be because the context already makes it clear. It will follow from the completeness theorem (4.29) and from Theorem 4.20 that a theory is syntactically complete if and only it is complete (see Definition 3.80). There will be no need, from that point on, to distinguish between these two notions. The next item is the one that will allow us to construct models: Definition 4.23 Let T be a theory in a language L. We say that T possesses Henkin witnesses iffor everyformula F [ v] wirh a single free variable v, there is a constant symbol c in L such that the formula 3vF[v] =} F [c] belongs to T. The proof of the completeness theorem splits into two parts: first we show that a syntactically complete theory which possesses Henkin witnesses has a model; then we show that any non-contradictory theory can be enriched to a syntactically complete theory that possesses Henkin witnesses. Proposition 4.24. (A) ff T is a syntactically complete theory in a language L that possesses Henkin witnesses, then T has a model. Proof Starting from a theory T that satisfies the hypotheses of the theorem, we will construct a model of T from virtually nothing. Let T be the set of closed terms of L. Since the theory has Henkin witnesses, the language contains constant symbols and the set T is non-empty. Here is the L-structure M that will turn out to be a model of T : • • • The underlying set of M i s the set T. If c i s a constant symbol, its interpretation in M is c. If R is an n-ary relation symbol, the interpretation R all lt , t2, . . . , tn in T, (lt , 12, . . , In ) . • ER M if and only if T M 1- of R is defined by: for Rtt t2 . . . ln. If f is an n-ary function symbol, the interpretation fM of f in M has to be a map from yn into T: for l t , t2, . . . , ln in T, let fM (t t t2, . . . , tn ) be the term , f ft t2 · · · ln. With this definition, we see that for any closed atomic formula F, we have T � F if and only if M I== F. We will now prove that this equivalence continues to hold 204 THE COMPLETEN E S S THEOREMS for all closed formulas of L . The proof is by induction on F. Since the case for atomic formulas has been treated, we may assume that the formula F has one of the following forms: (1) (2) (3) F (4) F == G =} H ; (5) F == G (6) F == VvG; (7) F == -.G; F == G 1\ H; F == == G v H; <=> H; 3vG. We will only treat cases ( 1 ), (3), (6), and (7), leaving the others to the reader. ( 1 ) By the induction hypothesis, we know that T 1- G if and only if M F= G . Now M t= F i f and only i f i t i s false that M F= G . Because T i s a syntactically complete theory, T � F if and only if it is false that T 1- G ; hence the result. (3) Suppose first that M t= F; then M F= G or M F= H; if, for example, M � G, then, by the induction hypothesis, T 1- G ; but the formula G =} G v H is a tautology, and so T 1- F. In the other direction, suppose T 1- G v H. lf T 1- G, then, by the induction hypothesis, M F= G, so M f= F. If not, then, again because T is syntac­ tically complete, T 1- -.G; and since G v H =} (-,G =} H) is a tautol­ ogy, it follows that T H. So by the induction hypothesis, M F= H , and so 1- M f= F. (6) If T 1- VvG and if t E T , then because the formula VvG ::::} Grfv is an axiom (t is a closed term), we see that T 1- G1 /v and, by the induction hypothesis, M f= G 1 f v . Now, since every element of M is the interpretation of a closed term, it follows that J\11 F= VvG . Now suppose that V v G is not derivable i n T. Invoking Remark 4. 1 0 (noting that -.-.G � G is a tautology), we see that the formula Vv-.-.G is not derivable in T either, and since T is syntactically complete, T 1-- -.vv-,-.G. But the formula 3v-.G ¢} -.vv-, -.G is an instance of axiom scheme (a); this allows us to conclude T 1- 3v-,G thanks to modus ponens and some tautologies. Because T has Henkin witnesses, there is a constant symbol c such that T f- -.G cfv (v is the only free variable of G since F is closed). As T is non-contradictory, G cf v is not derivable in T; by the induction hypothesis, M F= Gcf v so VvG is false in M. (7) I f M F= 3vG, this must b e because there is an element o f t E T such that M F= G 11v so, by the induction hypothesis, T 1- G 1 f v · It is easy to find a derivation of 3vG from G1 fv (see Example 4.6) and hence T 1- 3vG. Conversely, suppose that T 1 - 3vG thanks to the flenkin witnesses, i t follows that there exists a constant symbol c of T such that T 1-- G cfv so by the induction hypothesis, M F= Gcfv; hence M F= 3vG. This completes the proof of Proposition A. • -, 205 HENKIN MODELS 4.2.2 The completeness theorem We will now see how to obtain, from a non-contradictory theory. a theory that satisfies the conditions of Proposition A. Proposition 4.25. (B) Let T be a non-contradictory theory i n a language L ; then there exists a language L' that includes L and a theory T' that includes T, that is syntactically complete and possesses Henkin witnesses in L'. Here, since we are working with several languages, we have to be careful. We will need the following two lemmas. Lemma 4.26 Let S be a theory in a language L and let F be a formula in L with at most onefree variable v and let c be a constant symbol that does belongs to L ; if S �-LU{c} Fcj v, then S 1 - L VvF. Proof Let ( Ht , H2 , . . . , Hn) be an (L U {c})-derivation of Fcfv in S (thus H11 = Fcf v ) . Choose a variable w that does not occur in any of the formulas Hi ( 1 < i < n) and let K; denote the formula obtained from H; by substituting w for c. A straightforward examination of the rules and axioms shows that: • • • if H; is a logical axiom, then so is Ki ; if Hi is derived either by generalization or by modus ponens from one or two preceding formulas, then K; is derived in exactly the same way from the corresponding formulas; furthermore, if Hi belongs to S9 then Ki = Hi so K; belongs to S. It follows from all this that (K 1 , K2 , . . . , Kn) is an L-derivation in S of Fwfv · By generalization, we now obtain S 1-L VwFwfv and, thanks to the quantification axioms, S 1-L VvF (see Example 4.7). • Lemma 4.27 Let T be a theory in some language L, and assume that T is not L -contradictory. Let L' be the language obtained/rom L by adding a .finite set C of constant symbols. Then T is not L' -contradictory. If C contains just one new constant� then it is an immediate corollary of the preceding lemma (with F a closed formula of L). In the general case, we just have to apply this several times. • Following the same pattern as for the compactness theorem of propositional calculus (Theorem 1 .39) we are going to give two proofs (in fact, two versions of the same proof) of Proposition B. In the second, we will appeal to the axiom of choice; in the first, which is easier to understand, we will add as a supplementary hypothesis that the set of symbols of L is finite or countable. We will see later (in Chapter 7 of Part 2) that under these conditions, we can find an enumeration ( Fa. Ft , . . . , Fn , . . . ) of all the formulas of L . First proof We add to L a countably infinite set C = {co, c t . . . , Cn , . . . } o f new constant symbols (this means that none of the c; already belong to L ). Denote the . 206 THE COMPLETENESS THEOREMS resulting language by L'. The language L' is also countable and we can find an enumeration ( Fo, Ft , . . . , Fn , . . . ) of all the closed formulas of L. By induction on n, we will define a language L n and a theory Tn , starting with Lo = L and To = T, in such a way that the following conditions are satisfied: • • • • • Tn is not L n contradictory; Ln C Ln+I and Tn C Tn+ I ; Ln - L is finite; Fn E 7�+1 or -,Fn E Tn+ l ; if Fn is of the form 3 v H and belongs to 1;'l+ 1 , then there exists a constant symbol c such that Hcj v E Tn+ 1 · Here is the procedure for constructing Ln+I and Tn+l from Ln and Tn : it operates on Fn which is the (n + l )st formula in the enumeration that we fixed at the beginning of the proof. Let L� be the language obtained from Ln by adding the constants of C that occur in Fn · We see from Lemma 4.27 and by the induction hypothesis that Tn is not contradictory in L� . If Tn U { Fn } is not contradictory in L� , then set G n = Fn ; if it is contradictory in L�, the reason is because Tn f- L� -,Fn, and we then set Gn = -,Fn · In both cases, the theory T U {Gn } is not contradictory in L � . If Gn is not of the form 3vH, we stop here and set Ln+I = L� and Tn+ l = Tn U {Gn } · If G n i s of the form 3 v H , we choose a symbol c E C which i s not in L�; this is possible because L� - L is finite. We then set Ln+ l = L � U {c} and The last four conditions required of Tn+ 1 are clearly satisfied. It remains to prove that the theory 7;1+ 1 is not contradictory in L n+ 1 ; we show that the opposite cannot hold: suppose that 7�+1 is contradictory in Ln+ I · From Corollary 4. 1 9, we see that From Lemma 4.26 and by our choice of the constant c, we deduce that which is not possible since Tn U ( G n } is not contradictory in L11 • We have thus completed the construction of the theories Tn ; now set L' = U Ln n EN HENKIN MODELS and T' == 207 UN Tn . nE The fact that T' is not contradictory in L' follows from Corollary 4. 1 7 . To show that T' is syntactically complete, suppose that F is a closed formula of L'; then there exists an integer n such that F == Fn and, by construction, F E Tn+ 1 or -,J'i E Tn + l · Also, T' has Henkin witnesses: let H be a formula of L' with one free variable v ; again, there exists an integer n such that Fn == 3vH and, either -,£n E Tn+l or there exists a symbol c such that Hcj v E Tn+l · In both cases� Tn -t- 1 �L' 3 v H ::::} Hcj v, which proves that 3vH ::::} Hcj v E T' (otherwise T' • would contain -,(3vH ::::} Hcj v) and would be contradictory). Second proof This time we will use Zorn's lemma. We begin by adding Henkin constants to the language. According to Lemma 4.26, if a theory T in a language L is not L-contradictory, if F is a formula of L whose only free variable is v and if c is a constant symbol that does not belong to L then the theory T U { 3 v F [ v] ::::} F [ cJ } is not contradictory in (L U {c} ). Let us introduce a new constant symbol cp for each formula F of L that has one free variable and let L I be the language thus obtained. Let n be an integer and for every integer p between 1 and n, let Fp be a formula with one free variable w p; then by applying Lemma 4.26 n times, we conclude that the theory T U {3wpFp [Wp] ::::} Fp[cpP ] : 1 < p < n } i s not contradictory in (L U {cpP : I < p < n } ) . It then follows from Propo­ sition 4. 1 7 that the theory T1 == T U {3vF[v] ::::} F [c F] : F is a formula of L with one free variable v } i s not contradictory i n L I · One must not jump to the conclusion that Tt has Henkin witnesses: i t has them, but only for formulas of L, and this is insufficient since the language L I is richer. But it will pay us to be stubborn and to repeat the process: let us, for each new formula F of L 1 with one free variable, add a new constant symbol cF ; let L2 be the resulting language and set T2 = r, u { 3 v F[ v] ::::} F[c F] : F is a formula of L 1 (not of L) with one free variable v } . T2 is non-contradictory i n L 2 and w e define, using the same pattern, L 3 and T3 , and so on. All the theories Tn obtained this way are non-contradictory and, since they extend one another, we see, using Proposition 4. 1 7, that T' == Un EN Tn is not contradictory in L', where L' == U n EN Ln and, this time, has Henkin wit­ nesses: for if F is a formula of L' with only one free variable v, then there is an integer n such that F is in Ln. Consequently, 3 v F[v] ::::} F[cp] belongs to Tn +l and hence to T' . 208 THE COMPLETENESS THEOREMS It remains to find, while remaining in L', a theory T" that includes T', that is non-contradictory and that is syntactically complete in L'. It is clear that T" will still have Henkin witnesses since we are no longer changing the language. The lemma that follows provides the required conclusion. Lemma 4.28 Let T' be a non-contradictory theory in a language L'. Then there exists a theory T" in L' which is non-contradictory, syntactically complete, and includes T'. Proof It is here that we will invoke Zorn's lemma. Consider the set r = {S : S is a non-contradictory theory in L' that includes T' } . r i s not empty since it contains T Moreover, let I. S = { S; : i E / } be a subset of r that is totally ordered by inclusion, meaning that if i and j are elements of I , then either S; c Sj or s1 c S; . Then the theory is still non-contradictory (Proposition 4.17) so is an upper bound for S in r. Thus Zorn's lemma (see Part 2, Chapter 7) applies and we can find an element T" in r that is maximal for inclusion. We will now show that T" is syntactically complete. Let F be a closed formula of L' and suppose that F ¢:. T". This implies that T U { F} strictly includes T", so by the maximality of T , it is contradictory. Using • Corollary 4. 1 9, we conclude that T" �-- -,p. This concludes the second proof of proposition B . • We will finish this section with the completeness theorem. " Theorem 4.29 ( Godel, 1 930) Evety non-contradictory theory has a model. Proof Using Proposition B, we produce a language L' extending L and a theory T' in L' that includes T, that is non-contradictory, syntactically complete and possesses Henkin witnesses; using Proposition A, we find a model M' of T' . The • reduct of M' to L is then a model of T . The following is an alternate way of stating the completeness theorem: Proposition 4.30 If T is a theory and F is a closedformula that is true in every model of T, then T l- F. Proof If F is not derivable in T, then T U { _,p} is non-contradictory (Corollary 4. 1 9) so it has a model. In particular, we see that the universally valid formulas are precisely those that • are derivable from the empty theory. We are finally convinced, thanks to the completeness theorem, that the twtions ofsemantic consequence and syntactic consequence coincide. Sofrom Remark 4.31 209 H E R B R A N D' S M E T H 0 D now on, it is no longer indispensable to distinguish them. In particulat; beyond this chapter, we will ident�fy the two symbols 1-* and 1- that were reserved until now for these two notions, respectively, and will only use the second. Let us conclude with a harmonious marriage, that of the finiteness theorem (Theorem 4. 1 5) and the completeness theorem (Theorem 4.29); the offspring has been expected since Chapter 3 ; it is the compactness theorem for predicate calculus: Theorem 4.32 If every finite subset of a theory T has a model, then T itse?fhas a model. Proof Every finite subset of T is non-contradictory, and hence (by the finiteness theorem) T is non-contradictory. The completeness theorem then tells us that T • has a model. 4.3 Herbrand's method 4.3.1 Some examples In this section we will give another proof of the completeness theorem, essentially for the opportunity it offers us of explaining Herbrand's method. So forget that we have already proved the completeness theorem. Despite the fact that Herbrand's method applies to all formulas, we will be content here to restrict our attention to prenex formulas. The reader who is upset by this restriction can reduce the general case to this one by proving that every formula F is syntactically equivalent to a formula in prenex form (caution: this is not the same as Theorem 3 .60; here, this means that there exists a formal proof of F <::> G, where G is a prenex form of F). We will develop an argument that is similar in style to those familiar to high school students; it begins with: 'suppose the problem has been solved' . We are trying to determine whether a formula F has a model. So we suppose that we indeed have a model at our disposal and we observe that in it, there have to be some elements that satisfy certain quantifier-free formulas. We gather, in this way, a certain amount of information and after a while, we notice either that all this information is contradictory or else that we actually have enough to construct a model. Before presenting the general case, here are two examples. Example 4.33 The language consists of a single ternary predicate, P . We seek to determine whether the following formula F, Vvo3vt 3V2 ( (-, P vo v t v2 !\ has a model. ( -, <=> P vo v2 v 1 ) !\ (..., P vo v t v2 p Vo V I V2 ¢> p V I Vo V2) ) , ¢} P v2v1 vo) 210 THE COMPLETENESS THEOREMS Any eventual model cannot be empty, so assume a is one of its elements. The formula tells us that there must exist two points, call them ao and a 1 , such that (-.Paaoa l ¢> Paa1 ao) A (-, Paao al <=> Pa1aoa) A (-.Paaoal ¢> Paoaa1 ) i s true i n the model. Next in turn, for ao, we require the existence of two other points; obviously, it may happen that one of these points is equal to a or to ao or to a1 ; but in the absence of any other information, we will give these points new names (in any case, nothing prevents us from giving several names to the same point). So there are two points aoo and ao 1 such that (-,Paoaooaoi A ( -.Paoaooaol A (--, P aoaooao1 <=> <=> <=> Paoao1aoo) Pao1aooao) Paooaoao 1 ) is true in the model. Repeating this for a 1 , we find two points a 10 and a 1 1 such that (-.Pa1a 1 oa 1 1 ¢> Pa1 a 1 1 a 1o) A (-.Pal a1oa1 1 ¢> Pa1 1a 1 oa i ) A ( P a 1 a 1 oa 1 1 ¢> P a 1 oa 1 a 1 1 ) _, is also true in the model. Then we have to start all over for the points aoo, ao1 , a1o, and a1 1 and after that, repeat the process for the eight new points, etc. Let S denote the set of finite sequences of Os and 1 s. Continuing in this way then, we define, for each s E S, a point as in such a way that for every s E S, ( -, P as asoas 1 ¢> Pas as 1 aso) A (-.Pasasoa.d ¢> Pasi asoas) A (..., P as asoas l ¢> Pasoas a...,- 1 ) is true. This information now guides us toward the actual construction of a model of F: for every s E S, we choose a point c.� in such a way that if s =f. t, then Cs # c1 (we could, quite simply, take Cs = s ) The underlying set of our model M will be M = { cs : s is a finite sequence of Os and 1 s}. . It remains to define the interpretation of P and i t suffices to do this in such a way that for every s E S, (..., P csCsoCsl ¢> PcsCsi Cso) A (..., P CsCsoCsJ ¢> Pcsl CsOCs ) A (..., P csCsOCs l ¢> PcsoCsCs l ) 211 H E R B R A N D' S M E T H 0 D is true. At this point, we are reduced to a problem of the propositional calculus: indeed, let us introduce, for each triple (s, t, u) of elements of S, a propositional variable As , t . u . We seek an assignment of truth values 8 that makes all of the following formulas true: --.A s,sO, s l ¢> As, s l ,sO --. A s,sO,sl ¢> As l ,sO,s --.A s,sO,s 1 ¢> Aso,s,s 1 for S for s for s S E S E S. E If we find one, it will suffice to define the interpretation P for all s , t, u in S, (cs, cr , Cu) E M of P by P M if and only if 8(As.t , u ) = 1. If, on the contrary, there is no such assignment, we will then know that F does not have a model. For the case at hand, such an assignment s is very easy to find: for example, we may take 8(As, t., u) = 1 for all triplets of the form (s, sO, s 1 ) and 8 (As,t,u) = 0 for all the others. We have thus found a model of F. Example 4.34 The language contains one ternary predicate symbol P and one constant symbol c. Consider the following four formulas: F1 : VvoVv t Vv2Vv3Vv4Vvs ((Pvov1v3 1\ P v 1 v2v4 1\ Pv3V2 Vs) =? P vov4vs) F2 : VvoVv1Vv2Vv3Vv4Vvs ((Pvov1v3 1\ Pv1 v2v4 1\ Pvov4vs) =? Pv3V2 vs) f3 VvoPvocvo £4 : Vvo3vl Pvov1c. : We wish to prove that these four formulas imply VvoPcvovo. So we add the negation of this formula (or rather a formula that is equivalent to this negation), Fs : 3vo--.Pcvovo, and we attempt to construct a model of the formulas F1 , , F5 by the same method as in the previous example. The failure of this attempt will give us a proof of the fact that the set { F, , . . . , Fs} is contradictory and hence that VvoPcvovo follows from F1, . . . , F4. So suppose that M is a model of F1 , . . . , Fs. The satisfaction of the formula Fs requires the existence of a point d in M such that . • • ( 1 ) M F= -·Pcdd; then F4 commits us to the existence, for i E N, of points c; and d; in M starting with co = c and do = d, such that (2) M t= Pc;Ci+ l c for all i E N; (3) M F= Pd;d; + I C for all i E N. Set A = {c ; : i E N} U {d; : i E N). The interpretation of P in M must satisfy conditions ( 1 ), (2), and (3) as well as the following conditions (4), (5), and (6) 212 THE COMPLETENESS THEOREMS imposed by formulas F, , F2, and F3: (4) M F= ( Pxyu 1\ Pyzv 1\ Puzw) ==} Pxvw for all elements x, y, z, u, v, w of A ; (5 ) M F= ( Pxyu 1\ Pyzv 1\ Pxvw) ==;> Puzw for all elements x, y, z, u, v, w of A; (6) M F= Pxcx for all x E A . S o we are once again reduced t o the question o f the satisfiability o f a set of propositional formulas (whose propositional variables are the Pxyz for x, y, z in A). We will show that it is not satisfiable. To see this, observe that when we take (4) with x == c and v == w = d, we obtain implications whose conclusion is Pcdd, which is false according to ( 1 ). Hence, we must have (7) -.(Pcyu and so, by taking u 1\ Pyzd 1\ P uzd) for all elements y , z , u of A; y = = c, (8) -. ( Pccc 1\ Pczd 1\ Pczd) for all z in A . We know from (6) that Pccc must be true, and so, taking z = d2 , (9) -.Pcd2d. Condition (5) with w ( 1 0) == x == d, y = d1 , z ( Pdd, c 1\ Pd1 d2c 1\ Pdcd) = ==} d2 and u = v == c yields Pcd2d. Now Pddrc and Pd1 d2c are true according to (3) and Pdcd is true according to (6) but Pcd2d is false according to (9): so our set is contradictory. Thus 'VvoPcvovo does follow from F1 , . . . , F4. Remark 4.35 We will better understand this proof �f we think of P as the graph (�f a bina1y operation. Then F1 and f2 express the fact that this operation is associative, F3 that it has a right identity, and F4 that eve1y element has a right inverse. The conclusion asserts that the right identity is also a left identity. This is a fact that can be proved rather easily; we are slightly surprised here to learn that we can do without the hypothesis that P is the graph of a binary operation. 4.3.2 The avatars of a formula . We will now approach things in full generality. We will also do things better since, in situations where the attempt to construct a model of F fails, what we will obtain is a derivation of -, F. First of all, here are a few definitions. Definition 4.36 ( 1 °) A formula F is said to be propositionally satisfiable (f -�F is not a tautology. (2°) A finite set E offormulas is said to be propositionally satisfiable if the conjunction of the formulas in E is propositionally satisfiable. H E R B R A N D' S M E T H 0 D (3°) A set of formulas is subsets are. propositionally satisfiable if all 213 of its finite Let L be a language and let F be a fixed closed prenex formula of L. We may assume that L is countable since it suffices to retain only the symbols that actually occur in F. We are going to take as a hypothesis that in the sequence of quantifiers appearing at the beginning of F, the universal quantifiers and existential quantifiers alternate, that the first one is universal and the last one is existential. In other words, we suppose F has the form where B is a quantifier-free formula. Without this hypothesis, the proof would be exactly the same, except that it would require considerably more complicated notation. Besides, we can always artificially reduce the situation for an arbitrary formula to this case by adding quantifications over variables that have no free occurrence in the formula (and proving that the resulting formula is syntactically equivalent to the initial one, which is not too difficult to do). Let T be the set of terms of L and, for i E N, let 8; be the set of sequences of length i of elements of T. For each i between 1 and k, fix, once and for all, an injective map a; from 8; into N so that the following conditions are satisfied: (i) if Vn occurs in one of the terms t t , t2, . . . , t; , then a; (ti , t2, . . . , t;) > n ; (ii) if j < i and (tt , t2, . . . , t; ) i s a sequence that extends (ti , t2, . . . , t_; ) , then aj (tt , t2, . . . , tj) < a; (tt , t2, . . . , ti ) ; (iii) if r and a are two distinct sequences, whose respective lengths are i and j then a; ( r ) =I= aj (a). It is very easy to construct such maps: for example, using the codings that will be implemented in Chapter 6, we can set, for i between l and k , a; (t ! , t 2, . . . ' t; ) = 2m 3 r (tds r(t2) . · n (i )r(t ;) ' . where m is the largest index of any variable that occurs in one of the tj ( I < j < i ), where r is the map denoted by # in Chapter 6, and where n is the function that, with each integer n , associates the (n + l )st prime number. Definition 4.37 An avatar of F = is a formula oftheform Yv1 3v2Vv3 . . . 'v'v2k - t 3V2kB[Vt, v2, . . . , V2k] where t 1 , t2, . . . , tk are arbitrary terms of L. Each avatar A of F is a formula without quantifi.ers, so is a boolean combination of atomic formulas. Let At denote the set of atomic formulas of L . If we view the elements of At as propositional variables, then the avatars behave as propositional 214 THE COMPLETENESS THEOREMS formulas. To say that a finite set E of avatars is propositionally satisfiable (see Definition 4.36) is to say that there is an assignment of truth values, 0 or 1, to each atomic formula whose extension to boolean combinations makes each of the propositional formulas corresponding to the elements of E true. Thanks to the compactness theorem for propositional calculus (Theorem 1 .39), this remains true for any set of avatars. We are now in position to state the first important result of this section: Theorem 4.38 Ifthe set of avatars of F is propositionally satisfiable, then F has a model. Proof Let 8 be a map from At into {0, 1} such that 8 (A ) = 1 for all avatars A of F, where, as usual, 8 is the canonical extension of 8 to the set of quantifier-free formulas of L . We have to construct a model M of F. The simplest idea would be to take T itself as the underlying set of M and to use 8 to define the interpretations of the various symbols of the language in such a way that all the avatars of F are true in M ; this is hardly desirable, however, for symbols such as vo would then at the same time denote both a variable and an element of the model; and, as a consequence of our abuses of language, there would be an ambiguity when we encountered them in a formula. We are therefore going to make a copy of T by adding new constant symbols Ci , for i E N, to the language L whose purpose is to take the place of the variables v; ; let L* denote the language obtained in this way. For each term t of L, let t* denote the closed term of L * obtained by replacing, for every integer n , the occurrences of V11 i n t by Cn . (In other words: if the only variables of t are vo, v 1 , . . . , Vn .) We will do the same thing with the formulas: if G is a formula of L, G* is the closed formula of L * obtained by replacing, for every integer n, the free occurrences of Vn in G by en . Let T* denote the set of closed terms of L * (this is also the set {t * : t E T}). Also, At* will be the set of closed atomic formulas of L * (this too is the set { G* : G E A t } ). It is clear that the set {A* : A is an avatar of F} is also propositionally satisfiable; let us define an assignment of truth values c on At* in the following way: for all G E At, c(G*) = 8 (G ) ; then, for any quantifier-free formula H of L, we will have c (H*) = 8 (H), and consequently, for any avatar A of F, 8(A *) = 1. We are finally ready to define M . Its underlying set is T* . lf c is a constant symbol of L, then eM = c; if f is a function symbol of L, of arity n, say, and 215 H E R B R A N D' S M E T H 0 D u 1 , u2, . . . , Un E T*, then -M f (U I , U2 , . . · , Un ) = fu t U 2 · · · Un . If R is a relation symbol of L, again of arity n, say, and u 1 , u2, . . . , Un E T*, then (u t,U2, . . . , u n ) E RM if and only if s(Rut u2 . . . u n ) = 1, which can also be written M F= Ru 1 u2 . . Un if and only if s(Ru1u2 . . . U n ) . = 1. This equivalence extends to all quantifier-free formulas (the proof i s by induction on the height of the formula): if H [v t , v2 , . . . , vn] is a quantifier-free formula and u 1 , u2, . . . , Un E T*, then M F H [u 1 u 2 . . . un] if and only if &(H[u 1 u 2 . . . un]) = 1. In this way, we are assured that if A i s a n avatar o f F , then M F= A * . It remains to verify that we do have a model of F. This is where the functions a; reveal their true nature: they are Skolem functions in disguise. For each i between I and k, let us define the map fi from (T*i into T* by Then for every sequence (ti , t2, . . . , lk ) of elements of M, we have because B lt t , ft (tt ) , t2, f2 Ct1 , t2) , . . . , tk , fk ( tt , t2, . . . , tk )] = B [tt , Va1 (tl ) ' t2, Va2(t1 ,t2) , • • · , tk , Vak(CJ ,C2, ... , tk ) ]* . If we consider the functions f; as Skolem functions, we see that M satisfies a • Skolem form of F, and hence M satisfies F (Lemma 3.65). The previous theorem shows that if F does not have a model (which is the case, in particular, if ....,p is derivable), then there is a conjunction of avatars of F whose negation is a tautology. We now wish to prove the converse of this. Theorem 4.39 If the set of avatars of a formula F is not propositionally satisfi­ able, then -,p is derivable. Proof We know that there are a finite number of avatars of F, say Ap for p between 1 and n, such that the formula V 1 <p <n -, A p is a tautology. Let A denote the set of formulas of the following form: VW2i+! 3W2i+2 . . . VW2k - t 3W2k B [t 1 , VaJ (ll ) ' l2, Va2(c1 ,c2) , • • · , t; , Vai (lt ,f2 , · .. , ci ) ' W2i+I , W2i+2, . . . , W2k ] 216 T H E COMPLETENES S THEOREMS where i is an integer between 0 and k, t 1 , t2, . . . , t; E T, and where the wj are variables that do not occur in any of the terms t1 , , t; and are different from • Var ( tl ) ' Va2 (t1 ,t2 ) ' · • · ' Vai (lJ ,f2, ... • • • ti) · The avatars o f F clearly belong to A (take i = k). S o we know there i s a finite subset I of A such that � V .t EI -,f. The idea is to gradually quantify all of the free variables in this formula. Once this is done, we will have a formula equivalent to ._,F. So suppose that I is a finite subset of A such that � V .t E I _,f. We will find another finite subset, J, of A such that � V1 El _,f and such that the number of free VariableS in � v /EJ -,f iS at leaSt One fewer than in f- vfE/ -.j. Let f = Yw2i + I 3W2i+2 . . . Yw2k-t 3W2k B[ti ' Val(tJ ) , t2, Va2 (tJ ,l2 ) ' · · · , t; , Vai(t1 .t2, ... ,ti ) , W2i+ l , W2i+2, . . . , W2k] be a formula of A. We associate the integer n(f) = a; (ti , t2, . . . , t; ) with f. This is the largest index of a variable that has a free occurrence in f; in other words, if p > n(f), then Vp does not occur free in f. This follows from the properties we imposed on the functions a;. Suppose, as welt that for some other formula f' E A, we have n(f) = n(f' ) ; set f' = YZ2J+ t 3Z2)+2 . . . YZ2k-1 3Z2k B [u 1 , Va1 (u 1 ) , U2, Va2(u 1,u2 ) , • • • , U .l , Vaj(u 1 ,u2 •••• , u 1 ) � Z2 j+ l , Z2)+ 2, . . . , Z2k]. By construction, the images o f the different functions a; are disjoint; it follows from this that i = j and, since the a; are injective, that t1 = u 1 , , t; = u;. In other words, f and f' differ only in the names of their bound variables and hence, � f <=> f' (see the Examples in the subsection on formal proofs). We can begin by eliminating the repeats in I; the remarks that we have just made allow us to suppose that if f and f' are in /, then n(f) # n(f ' ) . Now choose the formula g E I for which the integer n (g) is maximum. Then the variable Vn (g) is not free in any other formula f of I. Set • g = Yw2i + t 3W2i+2 . . . Yw2k-t 3W2k B[t1 , Va1 (11 ) , t2, Va2(tr ,t2 ) , · · , l;, Vctc(t1,t2 · • • • • , ci ) , and H = l - {g}. By generalization, we obtain 1- Vvn(g) ( V �J) /El • W2i+ l , W2i+2, • • . . , W2k] 217 PROOFS U S I N G CUTS and, since it is only in g that Vn (g ) has free occurrences (see Exercise 4), 1- ( V -.j) V V V n ( g) -.g . jEH Let w2i- l be a variable that has no free occurrence in g and take w2; = g' =VW2i-1 3W2i · · . 3w2k B [tt , Va q (tt ) , t2, Va2(tt ,l2 ) ' · · · , t; - 1 ' Va; - x (ti ,l2, .... li - 1 ) ' W2i -! , W2; , So 1- g ' => · Vn(g) · · · ' Let W2k]. 3 vn ( ) g ( 'take' W2i - I = t; ) and hence g 1- VVn (g ) -, g => -,g' and it remains only to set J = H u {g'} to have 1- v.fE J -.f. Once all of the free variables have been eliminated and after suppressing the duplicates, we obtain and this last formula differs from -.F only in the names of their bound • variables. Let us recapitulate: Theorem 4.40 The following three conditions are equivalent: (i) F does not have a model; (ii) there exist avatarsA 1 , A2, . . . AnofF such that V I <p<n -.A p is a tautology; (iii) 1- -1 F. � Proof The implication (i) => (ii) is Theorem 4.3 8; the implication (ii) Theorem 4.39; and the implication (iii) => (i) is Theorem 4.20. => (iii) is • Remark 4.41 The proof ofthe completeness theorem that we have just presented applies only to a singleformula, whereas Henkin 's methodp1vves itfor an arbitrary theory. We will see, in Exercise 8, how to use Herbrand's method to prove the completeness theorem for a countable theory. Remark 4.42 From the preceding proof, can perfectly well extract an algo­ rithm that allows us to construct a derivation of -,p starting from a tautology of theform V ! <p<n _, Ap . we 4.4 Proofs using cuts 4.4.1 The cut rule In these last two sections, we are going to present a new kind of derivation. In it, the deduction rules, rather than the axioms, will play a privileged role. But these 218 T H E C OM PL E T E N E S S T H E O R E M S proofs only apply to a very restricted class of formulas, the universal clauses. Why should we prove the completeness theorem once again, especially in a much less general context? Because these are the kinds of derivations that we can most easily ask acomputerto do. They form the basis of the language PROLOG. Hidden within nearly every result in this section, there is an algorithm; we will be content, however, to to give the idea behind the method, without really concerning ourselves with the algorithms. In the first sections of this chapter, we did not bother with formal proofs in propositional calculus, quite simply because we chose to brutally include all the tautologies as axioms. That is not what we will do here because we wish to provide a method that is much faster than using truth tables for determining whether a proposition is a tautology or not. So this section relates only to propositional calculus. First, a reminder concerning a definition that appeared in Chapter 1 (see Remark 1 .30). Definition 4.43 A clause is a proposition of the form where the A; and Bj are p1vpositional variables. The clause is logically equivalent. when n and m are strictly positive, to the formula and this is the way we will usually write it. The premiss of this clause is the conjunction while its conclusion is the disjunction It can happen that either n or m is zero; in this situation, the clause will be written => ( B1 v 82 v · ·· v Bm) and the clause will be written (A I 1\ A 2 1\ · · · 1\ A n ) => . 219 PROOFS USING CUTS (We could extend the conventions adopted in Chapter 1 and define the conjunction of an empty set of formulas to be the proposition that is always true and the disjunction of an empty set of formulas to be the proposition that is always false). If n and m are both zero, we obtain an empty disjunction which, by conven­ tion, denotes the false proposition; we will call this the empty clause and denote it by D. It has already been shown that every proposition is equivalent to a finite set of clauses (Theorem 1 .2 9 ). Proofs by cut proceed exclusively with the use of the deduction rules. The first is the rule of simplification: if a propositional variable A appears several times in the premiss of a clause A, then the clause A' obtained from A by deleting all but one of the occurrences of A in the premiss of A is a formula that is logically equivalent to A. Obviously, the same property holds for the conclusion of A. I n these circumstances, we say that A has been simplified and that A' is derived from A by simplification. For example, can be simplified to which, in tum, can be simplified to Definition 4.44 ( The cut rule) Let an� V = ( C 1 1\ C2 1\ · · · 1\ Cp) ==> ( D 1 V D2 V · · · V Dq ) be two clauses. If there exist integers i (1 < i < m ) and j ( 1 < j < p) such that Cj and if£ is the clause Bi =: (A I A A 2 A · · · 1\ An � (Bt V B2 V · · · 1\ v C1 1\ C2 1\ · · · 1\ Cj - 1 1\ Cj + 1 B;_ J v B;+ I v · · · v Bm v 1\ · · · 1\ C p) D 1 v D2 v · · · v Dq ) , w e say that £ is derivedfrom C and V (or from V and C) by cut. In other words, if there is a propositional variable that occurs in both the con­ clusion of C and the premiss of V, then we can derive from these two clauses a third clause whose premiss and conclusion are, respectively, the conjunction of the premisses and the disjunction of the conclusions of C and V from which the common variable has been deleted. 220 THE COMPLETENESS THEOREMS Example 4.45 Consider the two clauses: C == V= (A A B A C) =} (D v E v F) (D A A A G) ==? (E v H). We can apply the cut rule so that the variable D disappears from both the conclusion of C and the premiss of V. We obtain the clause (A A B A C A A A G) :=} (E v F v E v H) which, after simplification, yields the clause (A A B 1\ C A G) =? (E v F v H). The cut rule is justified semantically by the following proposition. Proposition 4.46 Suppose that [ is derived by the cut rule f1vm C and V. Then every assignment of truth values that makes both C and V true will also make [ true. Proof Take C and V as in Definition 4.44, with Bi [ = = C.i , and ( A t A A2 A · · · A An A C t A C2 A · · · A C.i -1 A Cj--rl A · · · 1\ Cp) =} (Bt v 82 v · · · v Bi- t v Bi + l v · · · v Bm v Dt v D2 v · · · v Dq ). Let £ be an assignment of truth values for which s(£) we must then have either s (C ) = 0 or s(V) = 0. We must have = = 0. We will show that I < k < n; (2) s (Ck) = 1 for all k such that 1 < k < p and k =1- j ; (3) s ( Bk ) = 0 for ali k such that l < k < m and k =I i ; (4) s (Dk) = 0 for all k such that I < k < q. (1) s(Ak) And since Bi * * = 1 for all k such that Cj , we have either s(Cj ) = 1, so s(V) = 0 (because of (2) and (4)), or s (Bi ) = 0, so s (C) = 0 (because of ( I ) and (3)). • Remark 4.47 • • It is obvious that if a given variable occurs simultaneously in both the premiss and the conclusion of a clause, then this clause is a tautology. The converse is also true: ifa clause is a tautology, then its premiss and iis conclusion have at least one variable in common. It is useful to note that the empty clause cannot be derivedf1vm another clause by simpl{fication. 221 PROOFS USING CUTS • Moreover, {f D is derivedftvm clauses C and V by cut, then there must be a propositional variable A such that C is A =} and V is =} A, or vice versa. In practice, proofs by cut are usually implemented as refutations: we show that a set of clauses is not satisfiable. DeUnition 4.48 Let C be a clause and let r be a set of clauses. A derivation by cut of C from r is a sequence of clauses (Vt , V2, . . . , Vn ) that ends with the clause C (i.e. Vn = C) and is such thatfor all i between 1 and n, either V; belongs to r, or V; is derived by simpl{ficationfrom a clause Vj where j is strictly less than i, or V; is derived by cut from two clauses Vj and Vk where j and k are strictly less than i. We say that C is derivable by cut from r if there is a derivation by cut of C from r. A refutation of r is a derivation by cut of the empty clause D from r. {{there exists a refutation of r, we say that r is refutable. This method of proof is adequate, which means that the only things we can refute are those that are never true. Proposition 4.49 /fr is refutable, then r is not satisfiable. Proof Let (Vt , V2, . . . , Vn) be a refutation of r and suppose, to arrive at a contradiction, the & is an assignment of truth values that makes all of the clauses in r true. We will argue by induction on i , for i between 1 and n, that &(Vi) = 1 . This is clear i f V; E r . I f Vi i s derived by simplification from V j (j < i), then &(Vj ) = 1 (by the induction hypothesis) so &(V; ) = 1 because V; and Vj are logically equivalent. Finally, if V; is obtained by cut, we invoke Proposition 4.46. If D belongs to r then� according to our conventions, r is not satisfiable (we may observe, by the way, that this case i s of no real interest: the method that we are describing is intended to be applied to sets of 'real' propositional formulas). If not., then as we have seen, Vn = D is derivable by cut from two clauses A ==> ( = V; ) and => A (= Vj) where j and i are less than n (see the last item in Remark 4.4 7). But this is not possible for we would have to have &(V;) 1, which implies • &(A) = 0 and &(Vj) = 1 , which implies &(A) = 1 . 4..4..2 Completeness of the method We will now show that this method is complete. Theorem 4.50 Any set of clauses that is not satisfiable is refutable. Proof Let r be a set of clauses that is not satisfiable. Thanks to the compactness theorem for propositional calculus (Theorem 1 .39), we may assume that r is finite. Our argument is by induction on the number of propositional variables that appear in r . 222 THE COMPLETENESS THEOREMS For a clause C, let us denote its premiss and conclusion by c- and c+ respectively. We will first show that the general situation is reducible to the case where r satisfies the following hypotheses: ( 1°) (2°) (3°) (4°) r does not contain any tautologies; r does not contain the empty clause; all clauses in r are are simplified; for any propositional variable A that occurs in a clause of r, there exist two distinct clauses C and V in r such that A occurs in the premiss ofC and in the conclusion of V. To obtain the first three conditions, there is hardly any problem: if we delete the tautologies and replace each clause of r by a simplified clause, we still have a set that is not satisfiable; and if r contains the empty clause, then we know it is not satisfiable. To obtain condition (4 °), it suffices to apply the next lemma: If A is a propositional variable that does not occur in the premiss ofany clause of r (or not in the conclusion ofany clause of!), then: Lemma 4.51 r' = {C : c E r and A does not occur in C} is not satisfiable. Proof Suppose fi.rst that A does not occur in the premiss of any clause in r and, in view of arriving at a contradiction, suppose that r' is satisfiable. Let 8 be an assignment of truth values such that 8(C) = 1 for any clause C of r'. Let 8' be the assignment of truth values that agrees with 8 everywhere except perhaps at A, and such that 8'(A) = 1 . I f C E r', then 8 1(C) = 8(C) = 1 (because A does not occur in C), and ifC E r - 1'.. then 81(C) = l (because A appears in the conclusion of C). The argument is analogous when A does not appear in the conclusion of any clause of r; in this case, we set 8' (A) = 0. • The proof of the theorem continues by induction on the number n of propositional variables involved in r. We note that n is not zero since r ¥= 0 (the empty set is satisfiable! ) and o rt: r . Suppose n = 1 . Having eliminated tautologies and the empty clause, the only simplified clauses that involve only the variable A 1 are : A 1 ==} and ==} A 1 · Since 1 is not satisfiable, r = { A 1 ==}, ==} A 1 }, so r is refutable. Next, let ustreatthe passage from n to n + 1 . Supposethereare n + 1 propositional variables appearing in r and let A be one of them. Set: 1o = r- = 1+ = {C E 1 : A does not occur in C}; {C E r : A occurs in C - } = {Ct , C2, . . . , Cm } ; { C E 1 : A occurs i n c + } = { V 1 , V2 , . . . , Vp} . PROOFS USING CUTS 223 From our hypotheses, we see that r is the disjoint union of fo, r- and r+ and that neither r-- nor r + is empty. If i is between 1 and m and j is between 1 and p, we may apply the cut rule to C; and Vj to eliminate the variable A; let £;.j bt� the clause obtained in this way. If one of the clauses E;,j is the empty clause, then we have found a refutation of r. If not, set r' = ro U {E;,j : 1 < i < m and I < j < p}. We will show that r' is not satisfiable. As there are only n variables appearing in r ' (they are all those of r with A omitted), the induction hypothesis will tell us that r' is refutable; in view of the way the £;,j were defined, this refutation of r' will be immediately extendible to a refutation of r . The argument i s by contradiction. Suppose that 8 is a n assignment of truth values that satisfies r'. Since A does not occur in r', we may assume that 8 (A) = 0; it is clear that r' is also satisfied by the assignment A which agrees everywhere with 8 except that A (A ) = 1. We see that 8 satisfies fo (since fo is included in f') and r - (since 8 (A) = 0) but not r (which is not satisfiable). So there must exist at least one integer i between l and p such that 8 (V;) = 0, which implies that 8 (Vj ) = 1 and 8 (Vf) = 0. Fix an integer j between I and m . We know that 8 satisfies Ei,j· Hence one or the following two holds: • • Vj- A C', where C' is the formula obtained from C)­ by suppressing the variable A ; in this case, 8 (C') = 0 (because 8 (Vj) == 1 ) and, since 8 and A agree o n all the variables except A , A(C') = 0 , which implies 8 (Ei,j ) A(C�) J 8 (E;+ ) j = = = 0; now £,"0 = 0. 1 ; this time, Ei+ . suppressing the variable A{ V', where V' is obtained from vt by as 8 (Vi) = 0, we must have 8 (Cj) ::::: A(Cj) = 1 . = Cj v I n both cases, A(Cj) = 1 . Since this argument i s valid for all j between 1 and m , i t follows that A satisfies r-. But A also satisfies r o (since i t satisfies f') and r-t (since A(A) = 1). Hence A satisfies r, which is impossible. II To determine whether a fi.nite set r of clauses is satisfiable, it suffices to apply the following algorithm: first, simplify all the clauses in r and then eliminate all clauses that have a variable that is common to both its premiss and its conclusion� then apply the cut rule systematically to all pairs of formulas in r in all possible ways; having done this, repeat the process. After a while, we will not obtain any new clauses (because the number of propositional variables is finite, so is the set of simplified clauses and this cannot grow forever); if we obtain D by this process, r is not satisfiable; otherwise it is. Obviously, if we wish to undertake this work ourselves, or even ask a computer to do it, we will have to employ a slightly more subtle strategy than the one we just described. But that is another story. Example 4.52 We use the cut rule to derive the clause B :::} from the clauses ( A 1\ B) � C, � A and C � (in other words, derive -.B from (A 1\ B) � C, A 224 THE COMPLETENESS THEOREMS and -,C). From (A 1\ B) ==> C and C ==;. we derive (A 1\ B) ==> From (A 1\ B) ==> and => A, we derive B ==> . , • Example 4.53 We show that the following set of clauses is not satisfiable: C I is (A 1\ B) ==> (C v D) C2 is ( C 1\ E 1\ F) => C3 is (A 1\ D) => C4 is =} (B v C) Cs is => (A v C) C6 is C ==> E C1 is C => F. Here is a refutation of { CI , . . . , C1 } : (1) (2) (3 ) (4) (5) (6) (7) ( C 1\ C 1\ F ) ==> from C2 and C6 from ( 1 ) by simplification (C 1\ F) ==> from (2) and C7 ( C 1\ C) ==> from (3) by simplification C ==> from (4) and Cs =} A from (4) and C4 ==> B from (5) and C3 D ==> B ==> (C v D) from (5) and Ct from (8) and (6) ==> (C v D) (8) (9) ( 1 0) ==> D ( 1 1) D from (9) and (4) from ( 1 0) and (7). 4.5 The method of resolution 4.5.1 Unification In this section, we will introduce the technique of unification which will be needed to extend the method of proofs by cut to the predicate calculus. Here is the problem: in a given language containing function symbols, we have two terms t1 [ VJ , v2, . . . , Vn] and t2[w 1 , w2, . . . , Wm ] in which the Vi and the wj are variables; the problem is to decide whether there exist terms a I , a2, . . . , an and b 1 , b2, . . . , bm such that the terms t1 [a1 , a2, . . . , an] and t2[b1 , b2, . . . , bm] are identical, and if so, to find all possible solutions. This is what is called unifying the terms t1 and t2. We will proceed in a rather formal way. Let L be a language with no predicate symbols and let V be a fixed subset of the set of variables. Let T( V ) denote the set of terms of L whose variables all belong to V . Most of the time, V will either be determined by the context or else will be THE METHOD OF RESOLUTION 225 of no particular importance, in which case we will not even mention it and simply write T in place of T (V). We can, in a natural way, define an L-structure whose underlying set is T ( V ) ; we will denote it by 'I ( V) (or 'I): if c is a constant symbol, the interpretation of c in 'I is c itself; if f is a function symbol of arity n, then the interpretation frr of f in 'I is the function from yn into T defined by f rr (tr , t2, . . . , tn ) = ft r t2 . . . tn . For example, if L has only a single unary function symbol (and no constant sym­ bols), and if V = { v; : i E N}, then T = {f11v; : n E N, i E N}, where it is understood that fn is an abbreviation for the sequence consisting of n occurrences of the symbol f (it is the empty sequence if n = 0). Let us recall Definition 3 . 3 1 which, in our present situation where there are no predicate symbols in L, becomes Let M = (M, . . . ) and N = (N, . . . ) be two L-structures and let be a map from M into N. The rnap a is a homomorphism (fand only if the following conditions are satisfied: Definition 4.54 u • for every constant symbol c of L, a(cM ) = eN; • for every natural number n > 1, for every n-ary function symbol f of L and for all elements a 1 , a2, . . . , an belonging to M, 17 a \J M (a 1, a2, . . . , an ) ) = fN (a (a i ) , a (a2 ) , . . . , a (an ) ) . The structure 'I ( V ) is freely generated by the set V , which, to be precise, means the following: Let M = {M, . . . ) be an L-structure and let a be an arbitrary map from V into M. Then there is a unique homomorphism /rom ':r( V) into M which extends a. Proof We are going to define a map f3 from T(V) into M by induction on terms· ( i) if t = c is a constant symbol, the set f3 (t) = eM ; (ii) if t = v; is a variable, then f3(t) = a (v; ) ; (iii) i f t = ft r t2 . . . tn , where f i s a n n-ary function symbol and the t;, for i between 1 and n , are terms for which f3 (t;) has already been defined, then Proposition 4.55 f3(t) = f M (f3(tr), f3 (t2), . . . , f3(tn)). The map f3 defined i n this way clearly extends a (because o f (ii)) and i s a homomorphism because of conditions (i) and (iii). Moreover, if {J' is another 226 THE COMPLETE N E S S THEOREMS homomorphism that extends a , then for every term t, f3(t) = f3'(t): this is easily • proved by induction on t. Definition 4.56 Homomorphismsfrom 'I into itse�fare called substitutions. This name is entirely justified: for if a is a map from V into T(V), with a ( Vn ) = u n, and f3 is the unique homomorphism of 'I into itself that extends a, then f3 is none other than the map which sends a term t [ v 1 , v2 , . . . , Vn J into lu1 ;v1 .u2jv2 , , un fv11 • A substitution is therefore entirely determined by the values it assumes on the set V of variables. Obviously, we will not bother to use two distinct notations to denote a map from V into T and the unique substitution that extends it. •• • Let S = { (!I , u t ), (t2, u2), . . . , (tn, un)} be a finite set of pairs of terms. A unifier of S is a substitution a such that, for every i between 1 and n, a (t;) = a (u; ). To un{fy S is to find all the un{fiers of S. A finite set of pairs of terms will also be called a system. Remark 4.58 Ifa is a unifier of S and if r is arbitrary substitution, then r o a is also a un{fier of S: it is clear that if a (t;) = a (u; ), then r o a (t;) = r o a (u; ) . Example 4.59 Suppose that V = { v i , v2, v3 , v4}, that c and d are constant sym­ bols, that h is a unary function symbol and that f and g are binary function Definition 4.57 an symbols. • S = {(.f v i hV2 , g v2gv1 v3) } . For any substitution a, the term begins with the symbol f whereas the term • • begins with g : so there is no unifier. S = { (VI , g vI v2) }. Here again, there is no unifier: indeed, for any substitution a , a (gvi v2) = g a ( V I )a ( v2) i s a term that i s strictly longer than a (vi ). S = { (.f V t 8 V2 V3 , f hv3v4 ) } . Let a be a substitution and suppose., for v; E V , that a (vi ) = U i . For a to be a unifier, i t is necessary and sufficient that the terms fu1 gu2u3 and fhu3u4 be identical, hence (Theorem 3.7) that So we see that the values of u2 and u3 can be arbitrary, but once these are fixed, these equations determine the values for u 1 and u4. So here is a unifier, n , that is the simplest one that comes to mind: T H E M ET H O D O F R E S O L U T I O N 227 We have already seen that any substitution of the form r o n is also a unifier. In fact, this gives us all the unifiers (we say, in this situation, that n is a principal unifier; the next definition will treat this in detail): for suppose that a is an arbitrary unifier of S and that r is a substitution such that r ( v2) = a ( v2) and r (v3) = a (v3) . We will show that a = r o n . Indeed, if i is equal to 2 or to 3 , then a ( v; ) = r (v; ) = r o n(v; ). Also, a(vt ) = ha (v3) (because a is a unifier) and ha (v3) = hr (v3) = r (h v3 ) (because r is a substitution) and we know that h v3 = n (v J ) . So the conclusion is that a (v i ) = r o n ( v i ) . The proof that a (v4 ) = r o n(v4) is similar. We say that n is a principal unifier ofa system S if it is a unifier of S and {ffor every unifier a of S, there is a substitution r such that a = r o n. Definition 4.60 The existence of a principal unifier is not a special case. Every system that has a unifier has a principal unifier. Let S = { (ti , u 1 ) , (t2, u2), . . . , (tn , u n ) } be a non-empty system. Proposition 4.61 Proof Let V (S) denote the (finite) set of variables that occur at least once in some term that appears in S and let Uni(S) denote the set of unifiers of S. Two systems will be called equivalent if they have the same set of unifi.ers. We will say that a term t appears efficiently in S if S contains a pair of the form (t, u) or (u, t) with t =} u . The height of a system is the smallest of the heights of the terms that appear eiliciently in S. We are going to describe an algorithm that will permit us to • • either prove that S does not have a unifier; or else find a system, S 1 , and a substitution r such that V (S 1 ) has strictly fewer elements than V (S) and U ni(S)={ a o r : a E U ni(S 1 ) } . This algorithm involves three stages: clean-up, simplification, and reduction. (A) Clean-up (or garbage collection). In this stage, we first eliminate from S alii pairs of the form (t, t ) ; next, if a pair occurs more than once, we only keep a single occurrence; finally, if both pairs (t, u) and (u, t) belong to the system under consideration, we keep only one of them. We then have a new system S1 that i� equivalent to S and has the same height. (B) Simplification. This stage will allow us either to find an equivalent system whose height is 1 or to conclude that unification is impossible. Let h be the height of St and assume it is greater than or equal to 2 (otherwise there is nothing to prove). Choose a pair (t, u) in St such that the height of t, say, is equal to h. We know that the height of u is greater than or equal to h and that, hence, the first symbol of both t and u is a function symbol. We then perform the first compatibility test: if t and u begin with different function symbols, there is no point in continuing since neither St nor S has a unifier. Otherwise, we may write t = f r1 r2 . . . rk and u = fSt s2 . . . Sk, where k is the arity of f. The system S2 obtained from St by replacing the single pair ( t, u) by the 228 THE COMPLETENESS THEOREMS k pairs (ri , SI), (r2 , s2), . . . , (rkSk) is equivalent to St. Also note that the height of each r; is strictly less than h . As we have assumed t f. u , there exists an i between 1 and k such that r; =I= s; . So by performing another clean-up, we obtain a system S2, equivalent to S, whose height is strictly less than h and which, moreover, satisfies V (S2) c V (S) since we have not introduced any new variables. By iterating this process, we will, unless we are led sooner to conclude that S has no unifier, arrive at a system S3, equivalent to S, whose height is I and is such that V ( S3) c V ( S). So let (XI , YI ) E S3, Xt # YI , with the height of XI equal to 1 . (C) Reduction. We will now concentrate on the unification of (xi , YI). We begin with a few tests in order to eliminate certain cases: • • the second compatibility test: if XI is a constant symbol and YI is not a symbol for a variable, there is no unifier. the occurrence test: if x 1 is a variable, say v; , and if v; occurs in YI (but is not equal to YI since XI # YI ), then for any substitution a , o· (VI ) is a proper sub-term of a (YI )1 so a (xi ) = a (YI ) is impossible and there is no unifier. Except for these cases, and by interchanging XI and YI if necessary, we obtain a pair (v; ,YI ) such that the variable v; does not occur in YI · The unification of XI and Yt is then possible: let r1 be the substitution defined by • e Tt (V; ) = YI if j ;f; i , rt (Vj ) = Vj . Since !I leaves all the variables that occur in YI fixed , rt (YI ) = y l · It follows that !I (v; ) = rt (YI ) , so r1 is a unifier of (v; ,YI ). Better yet, i t i s a principal unifier: for suppose a is a unifier of (v; ,Yl ) . We will show that a = a o r1 . Indeed1 on the one hand, if j # i , !I ( v.i ) = v,; and o· o !I ( v.i) = a (v.i ) ; on the other hand, a (v;) = o· (y i ) (because a is a unifier of (v; ,YI )) and r t (V; ) = YI and hence ' o- o rt (V; ) == a (YI ) = a (vi ). So we have in fact found a substitution o- , namely o-, such that o· = a' o r 1 . Let us return now to the system S3. All the unifiers of S3 are, in particular, unifiers of (x i , Y I ) so must be of the form a o rt , where r 1 is the substitution defined above. Let us list S3: For a o rt to be a unifier of S3, it is necessary and sufficient that for all i between 1 and m, a (rt (x; ) ) = a (rt (Y; )). We already know, from our choice of r1 , that a ( r1 (xt )) = a ( rt (YI) ). So it is necessary and sufficient that a be a unifier of S 1 = { (!I (x2 ) , r 1 (Y2) ) , ( r1 (X3 ) , r 1 (Y3)) , . . . , r 1 (xm ) , r1 (ym ) } . Now exactly which variables can occur in r t (xk) or in r1 (Yk) for 2 < k < m? Only those variables that occur in a term rt ( v .i) such that v.i itself occurs in one of the terms xk or Yk for k between 2 and m; i.e. such that Vj belongs to V(S3). 229 THE METHOD OF RESOLUTION Referring back to the definition of r1 , we see that V (S 1 ) does not contain v; and is included in V ( S3). We have thereby kept our promises. It then suffices to repeat these three operations A, B, and C, to eliminate all the free variables: either we come upon an impossibility or we find systems s 1 ' S2 ' . . . ' sk ' where V ( Sk ) is empty, and substitutions TI ' T2, . . . ' Tk such that for all i between 1 and k - 1 , U ni (S ; ) = { a o r;+I i I : a E Uni ( S + ) } . A t this point, the terms appearing i n sk are all closed terms (since V (Sk ) i s empty); hence, they are left fixed by any substitution. So, if there exists a pair (t, u) E sk such that t # u, then neither sk , nor S, consequently, has a unifier. If no such pair exists, then all substitutions are unifiers of sk and the unifiers of S are then exactly those substitutions of the form a o Tk o · · · o r2 o r1 where a is any substitution; • Tk o · · · o r2 o r1 is then a principal unifier of S. This proof furnishes us with an algorithm that can be used to decide whether a system has unifiers and, if it does, to find a principal unifier. We have to alternate two sub-algorithms: on the one hand, the operations of clean-up and simplification produce an equivalent system that contains no pairs of the form (t, t) and which involves at least one term of height 1 ; on the other hand� the reduction operation decreases the number of variables. Example 4.62 In this example, c is a constant symbol, f and g are binary func­ tion symbols and k is a ternary function symbol. We will proceed to unify the system S: S = {(kjcgV4V3 jcgV3V4kV3V4V2 , kV2V2VI)}. l B : Simplification. The system S i s equivalent to {(j'cg V4 V3, V2), (jcg V3 V4, V2 ) , (k V3 V4 V2, V I ) } . l C: Reduction. Set system S1 = r1 (v2) = jcgv4v3 and r1 (v;) = v; for i # 2. We obtain the { (jcgV3V4, jcgV4V3), (kV3V4jcgV4V3 , Vt)}. 2 A and 2B: There i s nothing to do: the system i s simplified. 2C: Reduction. Set r2(v1) = kv3v4jcgv4v3 and r2(v;) = v; for i # obtain the system S2 = {(jcgV3V4, jcgV4V3) } . 3 B : Simplification. We obtain, i n succession, systems equivalent to then {(c, c), (v3, v4), (v4, v3)}; and after a clean-up, we see that S 2 is equivalent to { (v3,v4) }. S2 : L We 230 THE COMPLETENESS THEOREMS 3C: Reduction. We now set r3(v4) = V3 and r3(v;) = v; for i # 4. The system 3 S is empty. The substitution r = T3 o r2 o rt is a principal unifier of S We may calculate We could have calculated this differently (for example, by reducing the pair (kv3v4v2, V I ) at stage 1B or by setting T3(v3) = V4 at stage 3B); we would have found a d{ferent f principal unifier: Exercise 15 explains how to find all principal unifiers of a system once one is known. Remark 4.64 For some systems, there may arise the possibility of performing several reductions at one time. For example, suppose S contains the pairs (Vt, t1 ) and (v2, t2). If these pairs satisfy the occurrence and the compatibility tests and if, moreover, v2 does not occur in t1 nor v1 in t2, then we may reduce using the substitution r defined by r (vi ) = t1, r (v2) = t2, and r (v;) = v; for i different from 1 and2. Remark 4.63 4.5.2 Proofs by resolution We are going to adapt the method of proof by cuts to the predicate calculus. As with the propositional calculus, we deal in practice with refutations rather than derivations and the method will only apply to a restricted class of formulas, the class of universal clauses. We fix a language L (which may contain relation symbols) and denote the set of terms of L by T. Let us agree that when we speak of substitutions in what follows, we mean substitutions in the sense of Definition 4.56 relative to the language L without its relation symbols. Definition 4.65 A universal clause is a closedformula of thefollowing type: where the A; and Bj are atomic formulas. We will often be content to write 'clause' rather than 'universal clause'. We will also adopt several conventions which simplify the writing of clauses: ( 1 °) We will not write the quantifiers: this is justifi.ed by the fact that all the quantifiers are universal and all the variables are quantifi.ed. The only ambiguity is then in the order in which the variables are quantified and this, in fact, has no importance. (2°) Along with our convention to omit writing the universal quantifiers and just as for the propositional calculus, we will use the notation: to denote the universal clause: THE METHOD OF RESOLUTION 231 As before, (A 1 1\ A2 1\ · · · 1\ An) will be called the premiss and ( B 1 v B2 v . . . v Bm ) the conclusion of the clause. (3°) It is possible that the integers n or m or both are zero. We adopt the same notations as in the previous subsection: (At 1\ A2 1\ . . . 1\ An ) =} is the clause: and ==> (Bt v B2 v . . . v Bm) is the clause: If n and m are both zero, we have, by convention, the empty clause which will again be denoted by o . Let a be a substitution ofT (the set of terms o f L ) . Then a also acts on formulas: if F is a formula whose free variables are V I , v2, . . . , vk, then by definition� a (F) is the formula where, for i between 1 and k, x; it has the form = a (v; ) . For example, if A is an atomic formula, where R is a predicate symbol of arity j and where t t , t2, . . . , tj are terms; in this case, If C is a universal clause, say C = (A 1 then, by definition, 1\ A2 1\ · - · 1\ A n ) =} (BI v B2 v · · · v Bm), From the definition of satisfaction of a formula in a structure (Definition 3.42), we immediately deduce the following very important property: if F is a universal clause and if M is a model of F, then for every substitution a, M is also a model ofa ( F ). Remark 4.66 Unification, in turn, applies to formulas. Suppose A I , A2, . . . , An are atomic formulas. We wish to determine all substitutions a such that a (A t ) = a (A2) = · · · = a (An); these will be called unifiers of (A I , A2, . . . , An). Since the A; are atomic formulas, they can be written 232 THE COMPLETENESS THEOREMS where the R; are predicate symbols of arity m; and the t.It. are terms. We have seen that if a is a substitution, then a (A ; ) = R; a (tf) a (t�) . . . a (t�; ). Thus if, for distinct integers i and j between 1 and n, R; is different from R i , then there are no unifiers. In the opposite case, all the m; must equal a common value, which we will call m, and the unifiers of (A 1 , A2, . . . , An) are precisely the unifiers of the set { (ti , t£) : 1 <k < m. l < i < n}, so we may apply the results of the previous subsection: either there is no unifier or else there is a principal unifier. Two clauses are said to be variable in common. Definition 4.67 eparated (f they s do not have any If C and D are two clauses and the set V of variables is infinite, then we can find a permutation a of V (i.e. a bijection of V onto itself) such that C and a (V) are separated. It suffices to define a so that for every variable v; that occurs in D, a (vi) is a variable that does not occur in C. We are now in position to describe the rule of resolution. Given two clauses C and V, we will explain what we mean by 'a clause £ is derived from C and D by resolution '. The situation is analogous to the one for propositional calculus where we explained the cut rule. The role played there by the propositional variables is played here by the atomic formulas. The essential difference in the method is that in the present context, we will not require that some specific atomic formula appear both in the premiss of one and in the conclusion of the other; we will only require that we can reduce the situation to this case by means of a unification. Starting with C and D (it is quite possible that C = D), we begin by separating them, i.e. we replace D by a clause D' = 1: (D), where 1: is a permutation of variables such that C and V' are separated, as we explained above. Suppose that C and D' are written: C = (A 1 D' = ( C 1 1\ A2 1\ 1\ C2 1\ · · · · · · 1\ 1\ An ) =} ( B 1 Cp) =} B2 v ( D 1 V D2 V v · · · · · · Bm) and V Dq ) . v Suppose that certain formulas i n the conclusion o f C can be unified with certain formulas in the premiss of D'; more precise!y, suppose there exist a non-empty subset X of { 1 , 2, . . . , m } and a non-empty subset Y of { 1 , 2, . . . , p} such that the set { B; : i E X } U { C.i : j E Y } has a unifier. Suppose then that a is a principal unifier of { B; : i E X} U {Cj : j E Y}. THE METHOD OF RESOLUTION 233 The rule of resolution permits, in this circumstance, the derivation of the universal clause £ from the clauses C and V, where: • the premiss of £ is the conjunction of a(A I ) 1\ a (A2) 1\ · · · 1\ a (An) and the formulas a ( Ch ) for h E { I , 2, . . , m } X ; the conclusion of£ i s the disjunction of a ( D t ) v a (D2) v · · · v a ( Dq ) and the formulas a ( Bk) for k E { 1 , 2, . . , p } Y . . • . - - We could also say that £ i s obtained from C and V' by simplification and cut (in the sense of the previous section). In the rule ofresolution, we insist that the un{fication is performed with a principal un{fier. The reason for this lies in computer science: it is much easier to write an algorithm that searchesfor a principal un{fier than to write one that searchesfor all un{fiers. Example 4.69 The language consists of one unary function symbol h, a binary function symbol f, a binary predicate symbol R and a ternary predicate symbol P. Remark 4.68 Consider the following clauses: C is PVt V2V3 V is Rv1hvt � � (Rfvi V2V3 V Rfvl V2hfv1 V2) Pv1 V J V J . We begin by separating the clauses: so we replace V by V': It is easy to unify P v 1 v2 v3 in the premiss of C with P V4 v4 v4 in the conclusion of V': a principal unifier of {( VI , v4),( v2, v4),( V3 ,v4)} is a : Then and From the rule of resolution, we now derive the clause It is also possible to unify Rfvl v2v3, Rfv t v2hfv1 v2, and Rv4hv4. For this, we must find a principal unifier of 234 THE COMPLETENESS THEOREMS The reader should verify that the substitution T that follows is a principal unifier: We then have and The rule of resolution then allows us to derive The next proposition expresses the fact that the rule of resolution is semantically justified. Suppose that the universal clause £ is derivable from clauses C and V by an application of the rule of resolution. If M is a model ofC and V, then M is also a model of£. Proof Clearly, we may assume that C and V are separated. So there is a substitu­ tion a such that £ is obtained from a (C) and a (V) by a cut, possibly after a simpli­ fication. Let M = (M, . . . ) be a model of C and V. We have seen (Remark 4.66) that M is also a model of a (C) and a (V). Let us be explicit: suppose Proposition 4.70 a (C) = (AI 1\ A2 1\ · · · 1\ An ) => (B1 v B2 v · · · v Bm) and a (V) = (C1 1\ C2 1\ · · · 1\ Cp) => (DI v D2 v · · · v Dq), and suppose that the cut i s performed on the formulas Bt for i E X where X c { 1 , 2, . . . , m} and Cj for j E Y where Y c { 1 , 2, . . . , p}. Thus £ is equivalent to the formula £' = A 1 ( =* 1\ ( 6 )) v Dq v ( � Bk )) A2 1\ · · · 1\ An (D1 v D2 v · · · 1\ Ch where I = { 1 ,2, . . ., m} - X and J = { 1 ,2, . . . , p } - Y. Suppose that the variables appearing i n these clauses are v 1 , v2, . . . , Vk and that a 1 , a2, . . . , ak are elements of M. Set (Note that we are passing to the language L M.) THE METHOD OF RESOLUTION 235 We then have M F= M F A�) => (B� v B� v · · · v B�) and (C� A C� A · · · A C� ) ::::} (D� v D� v · · · v D� ). (A� 1\ A; 1\ • · · 1\ B y using simplification and the cut rule i n the context o f propositional calculus (Definition 4.44) , we obtain M t= (A; =? 1\ A� 1\ · · · 1\ A� 1\ (D� v D� v ·· · ( [J C� )) v D� v ( :L Bk )) and hence, • Definition 4. 71 Let r be a set of clauses. A refutation of r is a sequence of clauses S = {Vt,V2, . . . ,Vn } that ends with D and is such thatfor every i between 1 and n, either V; belongs to r, or V; is derivable from two clauses that pre­ cede it in S by the rule of resolution. We say that r is refutable if there exists a refutation of r. It follows from what we said, as in Proposition 4.49, that if r is refutable, then r does not have a model. It is the converse that we are concerned with here. So if r is not refutable, we need to construct a model of r. We will reduce this to the case for propositional calculus by using a simplification of Herbrand's method. Recall that V = { Vk : k E N} is the set of variables and T is the set of terms of L_ Since there are no quantifiers that require manipulation, we need not be as scrupulous as we were in Section 4.3 and we will construct a model whose underlying set is precisely T. The interpretation of the function symbols is defined as in the proof of Theorem 4.38: if f is a function symbol of arity n, then, naturally enough, the interpretation of f is the function from yn into T that sends (t t . t2, . . . , tn ) to f t 1 t2 . . . tn. Let P be the set of atomic formulas. To completely define our L-structure, it remains to decide, for every integer n, for every n-ary predicate symbol R and for every sequence (t t ,t2, . . . , ln), whether Rt1t2 . . . tn is true or not. All these decisions are independent from one another and may be taken arbitrarily. In other words, for every function 8 from P into { 0,1}, we construct an L-structure Mo in the following way: if R is an n-ary predicate symbol and if t 1 ,, t2, . . . , tn E T, then (tt , t2, . . . , tn) belongs to the interpretation of R in Mo (i.e. M0 F= Rt1t2 . . . tn ) i f and only i f 8 ( R t1 t2 . . . t n ) = l. We will consider the elements ofP as propositional variables and 8 as a n assign­ ment oftruth values. We extend 8 in a canonical way to a map 8 which assigns truth 236 THE COMPLETENESS THEOREMS values to the quantifier-free formulas of L and so, if F is one of these formulas without quantifiers, Mo F= F if and only if 8 (F) = 1. Now let G = Vvt Vv2 . . . Vvn F[vt , v2, . . . ,Vn ] be a universal formula. Under what conditions is Mo a model of G? The response is simple: it is necessary and sufficient that for all sequences (lt , t2, . . , tn) of elements of T, we have . Mo 1=: F [ t t , t2, . . . , tn L which amounts to saying that for any substitution a, M o F= a (F), or, alternatively, 8 (a (F)) = 1 . I t remains to prove: Theorem 4.72 Let r = {C; 1 < i < n } be a set of universal clauses that has no model; then r is refutable. Proof The set X = {a (C; ) 1 : < i < n and a is a substitution} is not propositionally satisfiable: if 8 were a distribution of truth values satisfying X, then the structure M0 constructed above would be a model of r . By the com­ pactness theorem for propositional calculus, we conclude that there is a finite subset Xo of X which is not propositionally satisfiable, and, by Theorem 4.50, that there is a refutation of Xo using simplification and the cut rule. We are going to see how to transform this refutation into a refutation of f" (in the sense of Defi nition 4.7 1). First, we must introduce some more precise concepts. • • • [f � is a set of universal clauses and V is a universal clause, we will say that V is derivable from � by cut if there exists a sequence (Vt ,V2, . . . , Vn ) such that V = Vn and, for all i between 1 and n, either V; E �' or there exists j < i such that V; is derived from Vj by simplification, or there exist j and k less than i such that V; is derived from Vj and Vk by the cut rule. If t::,. is a set of universal clauses and V is a universal clause, we will say that V is derivable from � by resolution if there exists a sequence (Vt ,V2 , . . . , V11 ) such that V = Vn and, for all i between 1 and n, either Vi E !::,. or there exist j and k less than i such that V; is derived from Vj and Vk by resolution. If C is a clause, c+ will denote the set of atomic formulas appearing in its conclusion, and c- the set of those appearing in its premiss. If C and V are two clauses, we will write c c v if c- c v- and c + c v+ . We already know that the empty clause D is derivable by cut from Xo. We will prove: Lemma 4.73 Let V be a clause that is derivable by cutfrom X. Then there exists a clause £ that is derivable by resolution from r and a substitution r such that r (£) c V. 237 THE METHOD OF RESOLUTION First of all, it is clear that the theorem follows from the lemma: by applying it to the empty clause, we see that there exists a clause £ that is derivable from r by resolution and a substitution r such that r (£) c 0. Necessarily, r (£) = 0 and £ = D . Proof (of the Lemma) Let (Vt , V2, . . . , Vn ) be a derivation from X ofV by cut (so V = Vn ). We will argue by induction on the integer n. There are several cases to consider. (a) Vn E X; this means that there is a substitution a and a clause Ci E r such that v = a (Ci ) . It then suffices to take £ = ci and T = a . (b) There exists an i < n such that Vn i s obtained by simplification from Vi . This implies that Vi c Vn since Vj = V,-; and Vj = V;t . By the induction hypothesis, there exists a clause £ that is derivable by resolution from r and a substitution r such that r (£) c Vi . The conclusion follows. (c) Vn is obtained by cut from two clauses Vi and Vj where i and j are integers less than n . By the induction hypothesis, there exist clauses £1 and £2 derivable by resolution from r and substitutions r1 and r2 such that r1 C£1 ) c Vi and r2 (£2) c Vj . Let us separate £1 and £2: let a be a permutation of the set of variables such that, by setting £3 = a (£2), £1 and £3 are separated. There is then a substitution 1-L such that: if Vi is a variable that occurs in £1 , then tt( v; ) = TJ (Vi ) 1 and i f Vi i s a variable that occurs i n £3, then J.i-(v;) r2 o a - (vi ) . Under these conditions, = /l (£t ) Jvt(£3) = T J (£1 ) c Di ; = r2 o 1 a - (£3) = r2(£2) C Vj . Let us write £1 and £3 explicitly: £1 = ( A I 1\ A2 1\ · · · 1\ Ar) => ( B t v B2 v · · · v Bs) £3 = ( C 1 1\ C2 1\ · · • 1\ Ct ) => and ( D 1 v D2 v · · · v Du ) . We know that the cut rule applies to the pair (V; ,Vj ). This means that there is an atomic formula E that appears in the conclusion of V; and in the premiss of Vj (or vice versa); we may assume, without loss of generality, that E E Vi and E E Vj . Because Vn is obtained by cut from V; and Vj and since 11 (£1 ) c V; and t-t (£3) c Vj , we see that {tL(A ; ) : I < i < r} U ({tL( Ci ) : I < i < t } - { £ } ) c V,-; , and { J-l ( Dt ) : I < i < u } U ( { /l ( Bi ) : I < i < s} - { E}) c V� . (*) The formula E may not appear in tt(Et) + nor in tL(£3 ) - ; this forces us to distinguish several cases: ( J ) for all k between 1 and s , E =I= �-t ( Bk ) ; in this case, tL(£1 ) c Vn and we have the desired conclusion; (2) for all k between 1 and t, E =I= JL( Ck ) ; in this case, tl.-(&3 ) = r2 C£2) c Vn and again we have what we seek; 238 THE COMPLETENESS THEOREMS (3) The sets I = {i : 1 < i < s and tL(B; ) = £ } and J = {j 1 < j < t and J1- (Cj ) = E } : are non-empty. Then we can unify { B; : i E /} U { C.i : j E J } and apply the rule of resolution to £1 and £2. Here, more precisely, is how this can be done. We have already separated £1 and £2 to obtain £1 and £3. Let a be a principal unifier of { B; : i E / } U { Cj : j E J } . Since JJ. unifies these formulas, there is a substitution r such that J-L = r o a . By resolution, we obtain a clause £4 with all the desired properties: • It is derivable by resolution from r (since £1 and £2 are). £;t = {a (B;) : 1 < i < s and i fj / } U {a(D; ) : 1 < i < u } ; this shows that • Invoking (*), we conclude that r (£;t) A similar argument shows that r (£4-) • c c vt. V,-; . • Example 4.74 The language contains one constant symbol c , two unary predicate symbols S and Q, a binary predicate symbol R and a unary function symbol f. We will derive the empty clause from the following six clauses: Qfvo ==> Svo (3) P vo ==> Qvo (5) ==> Pc (1) (2) ==> (Svo v Rfvovo) (4) ( P VI A R VQ V 1 ) ==} P VQ (6) Sc ==> First, we apply the rule of resolution to ( 1 ) and (6) by unifying Svo and Sc using the principal unifi.er a (vo) = c (by convention, if we are not explicit about a (v; ) , i t i s understood that a (v; ) = v; ) . We obtain (7) Qfc =*· Then, from (3) and (7), by unifying Qfc and Qvo (the principal unifier is a' (vo) = fc). we obtain (8) Pfc ==> ; and together with (4), by unifying Pf c and P vo using a', we obtain (9) ( Pvt A Rf cv1 ) =} . We may now unify Rfcv1 from (9) and Rfvovo from (2). The principal unifier is a'' ( vo) = a" ( v 1 ) = c and the rule of resolution yields ( 1 0) Pc ==> Sc. With (5), we obtain ==? Sc and with (6) we obtain the empty clause. 239 THE METHOD OF RESOLUTION Example 4. 75 We will reconsider Example 4.34. Formulas F4 and Fs are not clauses. To reduce the situation to this case, we introduce Skolem functions, specifi­ caHy, a constant symbol d and a unary function symbol f. We must then derive the empty clause from the fallowing clauses: ( PVoVIV3 A P V I V2V4 A PV3 V2 V5) � PVoV4V5 (PvoVI V3 A Pv1 V2V4 A PVOV4V5) � P V3 V2V5 � Pvocvo => Pvofvoc Pcdd :::::} From ( 1 ) and (5), by unifying Pvov4V5 and Pcdd (the unifier is obvious), we (1) (2) (3) (4) (5) obtain (6) (Pcv1 v3 1\ Pv1 v2d A Pv3v2d) :::::} . Clauses (6) and (3) are separated and we can unify Pvocvo and Pcv1 v3 using the principal unifier a (vo) = a (vi) = a (v3) = c; we obtain (7) ( Pcv2d A P cv2d) :::::} . We now apply the rule of resolution t o (7) and (2): they must first be separated, so we replace (7) by (Pcv6d A Pcv6d) :::::}. We then unify Pcv6d and Pv3 v2vs (using a (v3) = c, a (vs) = d, a (v6) = v2) and we obtain (8) (PVOVtC A PVt V2V4 A Pvov4d) :::::} . To separate (3) and (8), we replace ( 3 ) by PV6CV6 and by unifying this formula with Pvov4d (using a (vo) = a (v6) = d, a (v4) = c), we obtain (9) (Pdvrc A Pv1 V2c) :::::} . We then apply the rule ofresolution to (4) and (9)by unifying Pvofvoc and Pdv1c (using a (vo) = d, a (Vt ) = fd ); from this, we derive ( 1 0) Pfdv2c :::::} and a final application of the rule of resolution to (4) and ( 1 0) (using a (vo) fd, a(v2) ffd) yields the empty clause. Proposition 4.70 and Theorem 4.72 furnish a theoretical basis for the method of resolution. Imagine that we wish to derive a formula F from the formulas G 1 , G2, . . . , Gn . We would instead try to show that the set = = does not have a model. We begin by replacing these formulas by a set of clauses. To accomplish this, we first add Skolem functions and in this way we obtain universal formulas. We then replace the quantifier-free part of each of these formulas by their conjunctive normal forms (see Defi.nition 1 .28). Finally we distribute the universal quantifiers over the conjunctions (see Theorem 3.55) to produce a set of clauses. It is then from this set that we try to derive the empty clause using the rule of resolution. Obviously, in practice, we cannot merely apply the rule of resolution 240 THE COMPLETENESS THEOREMS systematically in all possible ways. It is necessary to adopt a strategy; a great number of these strategies, which we will not treat here, have been elaborated. Note that there is an essential theoretical difference between the propositional calculus and the predicate calculus when it comes to applying the method: we have already mentioned that in the former case, the search is bounded. By this, we mean that after a certain number of applications of the cut rule, a number which can be bounded in advance (at most 3n if there are n propositional variables: see Exercise 1 0), if we have not obtained the empty clause, then we will never obtain it and the original set of clauses is satisfiable. This is no longer true for the predicate calculus (except for some particularly impoverished languages). I n the general case, we cannot be certain that the search is complete until the empty clause is obtained. It is only if we never obtain the empty clause and if the search is conducted in a systematic fashion that we may conclude for certain that the initial set of clauses is satisfiable (Theorem 4.72). We will express this difference in a more striking way in Chapter 6: the propositional calculus is decidable while, in general, the predicate calculus is not. EXERCISES FOR CHAPTER 4 241 E X E R C £ S E S F O R C H A PT E R 4 - ----- ------ 1. Is the formula F ==> Vv F universally valid for any formula F? 2. (This exercise is motivated by Example 4.7.) (a) Give an example which illustrates why the restriction 'w is not free in F' must accompany the assertion that V v F => Fw/v is universally valid. (b) Give an example which illustrates why the restriction 'w is not bound in F' must accompany the assertion that VvF => VwFw/v is universally valid. 3. In a language L, we are given a theory that T and two formulas F and G. Assume T I- 3vo F and T I- Vvo(F => G). Without appealing to the completeness theorem, show that T I- 3voG. 4. Let F and G be two formulas and suppose that the variable v i s not free i n F. Give a derivation of F v VvG starting from Vv( F v G). 5. Let L be a language and F be the set of formulas of L . (a) Show that there exists at least one map ¢ from the set F into {0,1} that satisfies the following conditions: ( I ) If F E F and F begins with a universal quantifier, then ¢ (F) = 0; F and F begins with an existential quantifier, then ¢ (F) = 1; (2) If F E (3) I f F is of the form ·�·,G, then ¢ (F) = 1 - ¢ (G); (4) I f F is of the form (G a H ), where a is a binary connective, then ¢ (F) = a(¢ (G), ¢ (H)), where a is the map from {0, 1 }2 into {0, 1} corresponding to the connective a. (b) Show that if F is an axiom, then ¢ ( F) = 1. (c) Show that if ¢ ( F => G) = 1 and ¢ (F) = 1, then ¢ (G) = 1; (d) Show that if there exists a derivation of F that makes no appeal to the rule of generalization, then ¢ ( F) = 1. Conclude from this that we cannot do with­ out the rule of generalization, i.e. that there exist formulas that are derivable but which are not derivable without using the rule of generalization. 6. Using a method analogous to the one just used in Exercise 5, we can show that the quantification axiom schema (c) is indispensable. (a) Define a map ¢ from F into {0, 1} which satisfies conditions (3) and (4) from Exercise 5 as well as: 242 THE COMPLETENESS THEOREMS F and F begins with a universal quantifier, then ¢ (F) = 1; (2) I f F E F and F begins with a n existential quantifier� then ¢( F ) = 0. ( 1 ) If F E (b) Show that i f F has a derivation in which axiom schema (c) is never used, then t; ( F ) = 1. (c) Find a formula that is derivable but whose derivations all use schema (c). 7. For any formula F, let F* denote the formula obtained by replacing all occur­ rences of the existential quantifier by the universal quantifier. Show that if F has a derivation that makes no appeal to axiom schema (a)� then � F* . Find a formula that is derivable but whose derivations all use schema (a). 8. Use Herbrand ' s method to prove the following completeness theorem. Let T = { Fn : n E N} be a set of closed formulas in prenex form. Show that if T is non-contradictory, then T has a model. 9. Using a derivation with cuts, exhibit a refutation of each of the following four sets of clauses: (a) (b) (c) (d) 1\ B) :::::} C, :::::} A , C =} , :::::} B } ; { (A 1\ B) =} C, A =} B, =} A , C =} } ; {(A 1\ B) =}, C =} A , =} C , D =} B, =} (D v B ) } ; {(A 1\ B ) =} (C v D), ( C 1\ E 1\ F) :::::} , (A 1\ D) :::::} , :::::} ( B v C), :::::} (A v C), C :::::} E, C :::::} F}. { (A 10. Suppose the set of propositional variables has cardinality n and i s equal to { A J , A2, . . . , An}. We wish to count the number of clauses, but subject to two conditions: first, we count only those in which no propositional variable occurs more than once (if a propositional variable occurs more than once in the premiss or more than once in the conclusion, the clause can be simplified; if a propositional variable occurs in both the premiss and the conclusion of a clause, then this clause is a tautology); second, clauses which differ only in the order of the variables that occur in either the premiss or the conclusion should be counted only once. We will say that a clause is reduced if it is of the form where (i 1 , i2, . , in) and (j1 }2, . . jm ) are strictly increasing sequences. The number we seek is the number of reduced clauses. What is it? 11. Let S be a set of7 clauses such that at least three distinct propositional variables occur in each of them. Show that S is satisfiable. . . � . � EXERCISES FOR CHAPTER 243 4 12. Let r consist of the following four clauses: Ct is (A A B) ==> C C3 is A ==> B C2 is ( B A C) ==> C4 is ==> A . (a) Exhibit a refutation of r using a proof with cuts. (b) Show that the clause V A ==> C is derivable from clauses C 1 and C3 using the cut rule and simplification but that the set {C2, C4 , V} is not refutable. == 13. The language L has two constant symbols a and b, two unary function symbols h and k, and two binary function symbols f and g. Unify each of the following five pairs of formulas: (a) (gvoghbgv2v3, gggvs v 1 h v4ghbvo); (b) (gv3ggv2agvo v 1 , gggvov2gvo v 1 ggv2av3); (c) (gv4ggjgv1 V6fV5 VI2gfV1QG V2 f V? V8 , gjjv3 v9! v u v 1 1 ggv2gf v1 oaf v6vov4); (d) (f v2fffgv4v1 fv3vsfgV?bvogv6V8, fggv9V3gV9 V10ff vofgv?b/ V l l V 1 2 v2 ) ; (e) (gvogggk vsgV I I v7ggv1ghV2kvsv6hV9, ghgvt o v3ggv6ggkkv4gh v2 v 1 g v 12 vg vo). 14. Let V be the set of variables and T the set of terms. Let a be a permutation of V (i.e. a bijection of V onto itself). Show that the unique substitution, a, that extends a is bijective. Conversely, assuming that the substitution a is a bijection from T into T, show that the restriction of a to V is a permutation of V. 15. I n this exercise, we assume that the set V of variables is finite and is equal to {VI , v2, . . . , Vn } . Let T be the set of terms. (a) Suppose that t is a term, a is a substitution, and that a (t) = t. Show that if v occurs in t, then a (v) = v. (b) Let a and rr be two substitutions and let v be a variable. Assume that rr = a o rr. Show that at least one of the following two assertions must be true: (i) a (v) = v; (ii) for any term t, v does not occur in rr (t ) . (c) Suppose now that rr . n 1 = a1 o rr . Set A B = = {v JT 1, a. a1 are substitutions. that rr = a o rr 1 and that V : there exists a term t such that v occurs in rr ( t)}, and {at(v) : v E A } . E 244 THE COMPLETENESS THEOREMS Show that B c V, that a1 is a bijection from A onto B, that a is a bijection from B onto A, and that a o a1 is the identity on A . Construct bijections a ' and a; from V into V such that (i) for every v E A , a1 (v) = a � (v); (ii) for every v E B, a (v) = a ' (v); (iii) a' o a [ and a ; o a' are equal to the identity on V; (iv) rr = a ' o 1 q ; (v) n t = a ; o n . (d) Suppose that n i s a principal unifier of a system S . Show that the set of principal unifiers of S is equal to {a o n : a is a substitution and a bijection from T onto T}. 16. The language consists of three unary relation symbols P, R and S , one binary relation symbol Q , and one unary function symbol f. Apply the rule of resolu­ tion in two different ways to the following two universal clauses: Svo ==> (Pvo v R vo), 17. The language i s the same a s in Exercise 1 6. Add Skolem functions to the language to rewrite the following formulas as clauses and use the method of resolution to show that the set they form is contradictory: 3voV'vi (Pvo 1\ (Rv1 ==> Q vov 1 ) ) ; YvoV'v1 (...., P vo v -,Sv1 v -, Q vovi); 3 v i ( R v i 1\ Svt ) . 18. The language consists of one binary relation symbol R and one unary function symbol f. Consider the following formulas: Ft F2 F3 G Yvo(3vi Rvovl ==> Rvofvo); Yvo3vi Rvo v 1 ; 3voRffvo vo ; 3vo3vi 3V2 (Rvov1 1\ Rv 1 v2 1\ R v2 vo). Using the method ofresolution, show that G i s a consequence o f { FI , F2 , F3} . Solutions Solutions to the exercises for Chapter 1 1. For an arbitrary formula F, we let b [ F] and n [F] denote the number of occurrences of symbols for binary connectives and for negation, respectively. We will prove by induction that the length of F is lg[F] • • • If F E P, then b[F] = 4b[F] + n [F] + 1 . (*) 0 and lg[F] == 1 ; so (*) is verified. If F = -.G, then b l F] = b[G], n [F ] = n [G] + I , and lg[F] = lg[G] + l . By the induction hypothesis, lg[G] = 4b[G] + n [G] + I . It follows that (*) is again satisfied. If F = (G a H) (where a is a binary connective), then b[F] = b[G] + b [ H] + I , n [F] = n[G] + n [ H ] , and lg[F] = lg[G] + lg[H] + 3. By the induction hypothesis, lg[G] = 4b[G] + n [G ] + 1 and lg[H] = 4b[ H ] + n [H] + 1 . Here too, (*) is satisfied. == n[F] == 2. (a) Let Xn denote the set of lengths of formulas of height n. Since the formulas of height 0 are the elements of P, we have Xo = { 1 } . We have proved (Theorem 1 .5) that the height of a formula i s always strictly less than its length. We may conclude from this that every element of Xn is greater than or equal to n + 1 . Now the formula . . . -.A (with n occurrences of the symbol -.) is of length n + I and of height n. This proves that n + 1 is an element of X n and that it is the smallest element. To convince ourselves that Xn is finite, we note that if all the formulas of height n 1 have a length that is at most some integer x, then all the formulas of height n will have a length that is at most 2x + 3 : to see this, observe that if F is a formula of maximum length among the formulas of height n 1 , then the length of any formula of height n will be less than or equal to the length of the formula (F a F), where a is a symbol for a binary connective. Since Xo = { 1 }, we have thereby proved by induction that for every integer n, the set Xn is bounded and hence finite (since it is a set of natural numbers). Let Ln denote the greatest element of Xn. The argument above establishes the following recurrence relation: -,-t - - Ln = 2Ln- J + 3 . 246 SOLUTIONS A classic computation then shows that Ln = zn+2 - 3. The length of any formula of height n is thus between n + 1 and zn +2 - 3, where the minimum corresponds to formulas that use n occurrences of the negation symbol and no occurrences of symbols for binary connectives while the maximum corresponds to formulas in which the negation symbol does not occur. The reader may find it amusing to show that all values between these two extreme values are possible, except for n + 2, n + 3, 2n +2 - 8 , 2n + 3. (a) For any word W on the alphabet P U {-., 2 - 5 and 211+2 - 4. /\, v, :::} , {:;> , ( } , let b[W] denote the number of occurrences in W of symbols for binary connectives and recall that o[W] is the number of opening parentheses in W. In a way that is more or less analogous to the one used for formulas. we prove the fallowing four facts by induction: ( 1 ) Every pseudoformula ends with a propositional variable. (2) If F is a pseudoformula, then o[F] = b[F]. (3) If W is a proper initial segment of a pseudoformula F, then o[W] > b[W]. (4) If W is a proper initial segment ofa pseudoformula and ifthe last symbol of W is a propositional variable, then o[W] > b[W]. From this, it is not difficult to show that ( 5) A proper initial segment of a pseudoformula cannot be a pseudoformula. We may then continue, as in the case for formulas, and arrive at the unique readability theorem for pseudoformulas: For any pseudoformula F, one and only one of the following three situ­ ations is applicable: • F is a propositional variable; • there is a unique pseudoformula G such that F = -.G; • there exists a unique symbol a for a binary connective and a unique pair of pseudoformulas H and K such that F = (H a K ) . (b) So we have proved that, for writing formulas, w e can very well d o without closing parentheses. We must avoid jumping to the conclusion that we could just as well eliminate opening rather than closing parentheses: the culprit here is the presence of the symbol for the unary connective, negation, which destroys all symmetry. As an illustration, consider the formula -.(A ==> B) which, i n the context above, becomes the pseudoformula -, (A =} B; if opening parentheses are suppressed, this becomes -.A =} B), but this is exactly the same word that would result if the formula -,(A ==> B) were to receive the same treatment. So this procedure is doomed to fail. SOLUTIONS FOR C HAPTER I 247 4. (a) T* is the smallest set of words on the alphabet P U {...., , ::::} , ) , ( } that includes P and is closed under the operations X � ....,X and (X, Y) � (X ::::} Y ) . To have a n equivalent definition from below, we would set To* = P and for every integer n E N, �*+ 1 = �* U { ...., F : F E '4z* } U { ( F ::::} G) : F E �* , G E �* } . We would then have T* = UneN�* . (b) The given conditions allow us to define a unique map /1 from T* into T* by induction: /1 is already defined (equal to JL) on To* = P, and, if we assume it is defined on �* , the given conditions determine its values on �*+ 1 • (c) We argue by induction on G. I f G E P, then the only sub-formula of G is F = G and, in this case, /i(F) = /i(G) is a sub-formula of /i(G). If G = ...., H and i f F is a sub-formula of G, then either F = G and /l(F) = /l(G) is a sub-formula of /l(G), or else F is a sub-formula of H and, by the induction hypothesis, /i(F) is a sub-formula of /i(H), hence also of -,/i (H ) = /i( -,H) = /i(G). If G = ( H => K) and if F is a sub­ formula of G, then either F = G and /i(F) = /i(G) is a sub-formula of /i(G), or else F is a sub-formula of H or a sub-formula of K and, by the induction hypothesis, /l(F) is a sub-formula of /l(H) or a sub-formula of /i(K), hence also of the formula -.,(jl(K) =} /l(H)) = /l((H =} K)) = /l(G). (d) jlQ ((A ::::} B)) = _, ( ...., B ::::} _,A) and jlQ((...., A ::::} B)) = ...., (...., B It would obviously be an error to write, for example: => ...., ....,A ). jlQ((A => B)) = -.(A ::::} B), despite the fact that these formulas turn out to be logically equivalent. With each formula ofT*, the map jlO associates a uniquely determined formula. The last property is proved by induction on F. If F E P, ilQ(F) = -.F, thus jlQ(F) ...., F. If F = ...., G and if (induction hypothesis) jlQ(G) -,G, then ilQ(F) = --,jlQ(G) is logically equivalent to --,-,G = -..,F. If F = (G ::::} H) and if (induction hypothesis) jlQ(G) -.G and ilQ (H ) -.., H , then ilQ(F) = -.(jlO(H) ::::} fiQ(G)) i s logically equivalent to -,(...., H => -,G), hence also to -.(G =? G) = -.F. 5 . We will treat question (b) directly since (a) merely presents two special cases. A.. s Fn (n E N, n > 2) we take the following formula: r-v r-v r-v r-v SOLUTIONS 248 If we set Gn = 1\ l < i <n (A; :::} B; ) , Hn = 1\ l -<i < i <n -, (B; V 1 <i <n A ; , and Ln = /\� <i <n (B; => A;), then we ca� write 1\ Bj ) , Kn Let 8 be an assignment o f truth values and suppose that 8(Ln) = 0. This means that we can fi nd an index j between 1 and n such that 8(Bj ) = 1 and 8(Aj ) = 0. If we suppose as well that 8 (Hn ) = 1, then we must conclude that for all indices i between 1 and n and distinct from j, we have 8 ( B;) = 0. Now let us add the hypothesis that 8(Gn ) = 1. Then for all i different from j, we must have 8(A;) == 0. But since 8 (A j ) is also zero, the conclusion is that 8 does not satisfy the formula Kn. In this way, we see that it is not possible for 8 to assign the value 0 to Ln while simultaneously assigning the value 1 to Gn , to Hn and to Kn. This amounts to saying that 8 cannot assign the value 0 to Fn . So this formula is a tautology. 6. (a) With the help of items 38 and 53 from the list in Section 1 .2.3, we see that E is logically equivalent to (B => (C :::} (A {:} (B :::} C)))), which is a formula that satisfies the required conditions. (b) Any assignment of truth values that gives the value 0 to B or to C will satisfy the formula - E. If 8 is as assignment of truth values such that - 8 (B) = 8(C) = 1, then 8((..., B v C)) = 1, from which we deduce that 8(£) = 1 if and only if 8 (A) = 1. Thus� there is a unique assignment of truth values to the set { A , B, C } that makes the formula E false: namely, it assigns 1 to B and to C and 0 to A. This observation provides us with the CCNF of the formula £: (A v _,B v -,C). which is, at the same time, in reduced disjunctive normal form. (c) It follows from what has just been said that there are seven assignments of truth values to {A, B , C} that satisfy E. So there are seven elementary conjunctions in the CDNF of E. (d) I n question (a) we noted that the formula E is logically equivalent to (B :::} (C :::} (A {:} (B => C)))), but this formula is also logically equivalent to (C :::} (B � (A {:} (B ==> C)))) (again, refer to item 53 of Section 1 .2.3). Also, the disjunctive normal form of E that we found in (b) is clearly logically equivalent to (C ==> (B :::} A)); this proves the desired result. 249 S O L U T I O N S FOR C H A PTER l 7. P i (a) Letinteger8 bebetanwassieengnment of trut h val u es t o that sati s fi e s F and l e t be an and We see immediately that 8 ( A n) iif8(A;) f 8(A;) 0, then ... 8(A; + t) (A; + 2) then 8(A;- I) <S(A;-2) ... 8(AI) 0. It folassilogwsnments that the8 assignments of t r ut h val u es to t h at sat i s fy F are t h e p n) t h at gi v e t h e val u e t o t h e l a st vari a bl e s in and the value 0 to the first p variables; specifically: n p; {0 i f i 8 (A· ) - f n -p. From this, we may obtain the CDNF ofF: (-,A I -,A2 -,An) (_,A,An) -,An-I An) (_,At · · -,An-2 An-I (-,AI A2 An) (AI A2 An-I An ). of t r ut h val u es t o that sati s fi e s Obvi o usl y , 8 (b) Letmust8 satbeisanfyassiF, gsonment 8 must be one of the assi g nments 8p above. But 8 must alandso 8sat(Aisfy (An0; thisAexclsoudesit isthenotpossi possibbillietythatthatwe8 have bot h 8(An) coul d equal 8 when We easi l y veri f y that the assi g nments of trut h val u es 8o and p 8njust(isai.e. dththate twthese o constant assi g nments) sat i s fy f o l o ws from what was are t h e onl y ones. We conclude from this that the CDNF of is (-,At -,A2 · -,An) (At A2 · An-1 An). t o -,(A formul a -,A is l o gi c al l y equi v al e nt A ) Con­ (A; (c) The ; sequentl y , a necessary and suffi c i e nt condi t i o n for an assi g nment of t r ut h valsuchuesthatto 8sat(A;)isfy 8 i(As that thereSonottheexiassistganments pair ofofdistrtiutnhctvalindiuescestoi andthat satiare stfyhen+are assithosegnments that givAepthe valupe to atdefmost one vari a bl e i n these ined by A (A · ) -- {0 i·ff i ::f. p.p (Thus is t h e constant assi g nment equal to 0). We concl u de from t h i s that the canonical disjunctive normal form of is (-,A 1 -,A2 -,An) -,A2 -,An) (-,AI tA2 -,A3-, - · -,An) -,An) (-,At -,An-I An). An 2 An-1 (-,A n. I • = • = 1, <5 = = n+ I P (0 P � 1\ • · l· > 1 I 1\ · · · 1\ V • • p < 1\ 1\ 1\ = - - ' 1\ · · · 1\ ···V = 1\ 1\ V... V 1\ • • · 1\ < G. 1) => 1 1\ 1\ P 1) <n 1; P 1 n 1\ · 1\ v = < P 1\ = = = 1 P 1. G. It G 1\ 1\ · · 1\ = H 1\ · · 1\ 1\ j) => H V .i) 1\ 1\ j . j = P P: 1. 1 < n) (0 < 1 P l t I · l = A.0 H 1\ 1\ V ··· 1\ · · · 1\ v 1\ 1\ · · · 1\ V 1\ · · 1\ 1\ (A I 1\ · · · 1\ 1\ v . . . 1\ v 1\ · · · 1\ 1\ 250 SOLUTIONS 8. (a) Set F == V t < i < j <n ( A i A Aj) and G = l\ 1 <i <n < V j#i A j). Let 8 be an assignment of truth values on P. For 8 to satisfy F, i t is necessary and sufficient that 8 assume the value l for at least two of the variables A t , A2, . . . , An. In order that 8 not satisfy G , i t i s necessary and sufficient that there exist an index i such that 8 (A j ) = 0 for every index j different from i . In other words, 8 (G) = 0 if and only if 8 assigns the value 1 to at most one of the variables A t , A2, . . . , An. We may conclude that 8 satisfies G if and only if 8 assigns the value 1 to at most one of the variables A t , A 2, . . . , An. So we see that 8 satisfies G if and only if 8 satisfies F. The formula (F {:} G) is thus a tautology. (b) Set H = V 1 < i <n A; and consider an assignment of truth values 8 on P. For 8 to satisfy H, it i s necessary and sufficient that 8 assign the value 1 to at least one of the variables A t , A2 , . . . , An . Now we have just seen that 8 satisfies G if and only if 8 assigns the value 1 to at least two of the variables A 1 , A2, . . . , An · It follows immediately that • if 8 assigns the value 0 to all the variables in P, then 8( G) = 8 (H) = 0; • if 8 assigns the value 1 to one and only one of the variables in P, then -o (G) == 0 and -o(H) = 1 ; • i f 8 assigns the value 1 to at least two o f the variables i n P then 8 (G) = o (H) = 1 . Thus the assignments of truth values that make the formula ( H ¢? G ) false are precisely the n assignments 8 1 , 82, . . . , 8 n defi.ned by � 8·l (A j· ) - { l if i == j 0 if i # j (for 1 � i < n and 1 < j < n). (c) Once we know the assignments of truth values that make the formula ( H {:} G) false, we immediately obtain its CCNF: (..., A t v A2 v · · · v A n ) A ( A 1 v _,A2 v A3 v · · · v An ) A ( A t v · · · v An-I v ..., A n ) . A . . . For I < i < n, the ith of these n clauses is logically equivalent to this provides us with the desired result. 9. Consider a set of five propositional variables: P == { A , B, C, D, £ } . Intuitively, the variable A (respectively, B, C, D, E) will have the value 'true' if and only if person a (respectively, h� c, d, e) is present. The safe can be opened 25 1 SOLUTIONS FOR CHAPTER I if and only if the following propositional formula is satisfied: F == (A A B) v (A 1\ C 1\ D) v (B 1\ D A £). Let S1 , S2 , . . . , Sn denote the keys to the safe. To be able to open the safe, it is necessary and sufficient that for every integer i between I and n, at least one person possessing the key S; be present. If, for example, the holders of the key S; are persons c and e, the ability to unlock S; is equivalent to the satisfaction of the formula (C v £). The ability to open the safe is thus equivalent to the satisfaction of the conjunction of formulas of this type (in which i assumes the values l , 2, . . . , n), i.e. to a formula in conjunctive normal form. Now, as we saw above, the ability to open the safe is equivalent to the satisfaction of the formula F which is in disjunctive normal form. So it will suffice to fi nd a conjunctive normal form for F that is as reduced as possible; the number of disjuncts (clauses) in this CNF will correspond to the minimum number of keys required and each clause will provide a list of those persons who should receive a key to the corresponding lock. By distributing the con junctions over the disjunctions in F (which leads to a CNF that has eighteen clauses, each having three variables) and then simplifying (using the properties of idempotence and absorption as in items (2) and ( I 0) from the list of tautologies: for example, (B v C v B) becomes (B v C) which then allows us to eliminate (B v C v D) and (B v C v £)), we arrive at the following CNF for F : (A v B) 1\ (A v D) 1\ (A v £) 1\ (B v C) 1\ (B v D). Some fastidious verifications would convince us that we cannot further reduce the number of clauses. We will not attempt to treat this issue. The CNF that we have obtained tells us that the number of locks required is five and that one possible distribution of keys consists in giving: • • • • • to a, the keys for St , S2, and S3 ; to b, the keys for St , S4, and Ss; to c, the key for S4; to d, the keys for S2 and Ss ; to e, the key for S3. 10. Let 8 be an assignment of truth values to P that satisfies A. Let H8 denote the set of elements i of IZ/ 1 5/Z such that 8 (A i ) = 1. We see that 0 E H8 and that lf8 is closed under the operations i � -i and (i, j) � i + j . This means that H8 is necessarily a subgroup of the group (IZ/ 1 5/Z, +). Conversely, if H is a subgroup of (IZ/ 1 5/Z, +), then the assignment of truth values 8 defined by 8 (A ; ) = {� if i E H if i � H 252 SOLUTIONS clearly satisfies the set A. Now (Z/ 15Z, +) has precisely the following four subgroups: Z/ 15Z, {0}, {0, 5, 1 0}, and (0, 3, 6, 9, 1 2} . There are thus four assignments of truth values that satisfy A: the one that is constant and equal to 1, the one whose value is 1 on Ao and 0 elsewhere, the one whose value is 1 on Ao, As, and A 1 0 and 0 elsewhere and, finally, the one whose value is 1 on Ao, A3, A6, Ag , and A 1 2 and 0 elsewhere. 11. The formulas F.=::;> and Gv are tautologies. The formulas G 1\ , G <=? ' G ::t? , and Gt are antilogies. The six other formulas are neutral. We list them here and place, below each of them, a simpler formula that is logically equivalent. The proofs present no difficulties. Fv AvB F::tr> A F<=? B 12. (a) The given conditions entirely determine <p: the first tells us that <p must assume the value 1 at the points (0, 0, 0), (0, 1 , 0), ( I , 0, 0), and ( I , 0, I ) ; the second tells u s that cp must assume the value 0 at the points (0, 0, 1 ) , (0, 1 , I , ) , ( 1 , 1 , 0 ), and ( 1 , 1 . 1 ) . (b) A DNF for <p i s given by the following formula: (c) lt suffices to take a formula that is logically equivalent to G [ A , A , A] in case I , to G [ A , B , B] in case 2, to G [ A , A , B] in case 3, to G [A , B, A] in case 4, to G [ A , G [ B , B , B] , A] in case 5, and to (G[ A , B, B] � G [A , B , A]) in case 6. Here are some possible answers: ( 1 ) _,A (4) (--rA v _,B) (2) -·.,B (5) (A � B) (3) (--,A 1\ (6) (--·,A v _, B ) A). (d) A s the formula ( A v B) i s logically equivalent t o (-,--·,A v B ) we will refer to case 4 of the preceding question; it is then not difficult to verify that the connective 1/f defined by -, -, , for all x and y belonging to {0, 1 } , 1/f (x, y) = <p(<p(x , x , x) , <p(y , y, y ) , <p(x , x, x)) i s precisely disjunction. (e) Using composition, the connectives disjunction (question (d)) and negation (case 1 of question (c)) can be expressed in terms of the sole connective <p. As every connective can be expressed in terms of negation and disjunction, it follows that every connective can be expressed in terms of the connective <p. Thus, { <p} is a complete system of connectives. S O L U T I O N S F O R C H A PT E R 253 I 13. The solution is p == (a A b A d) V (b A C A d) V q = (b A d) <=> (a A -.b A c) V (a A C A -.d); (a <=> c) r = -,(b {} d). It is not difficult to verify this. Here, of course, -, A, v, and <=> denote operations on {0, 1 } . 14. (a) Our concern is to express the connectives a s operations in 7lj27l. For all elements x and y of this set, we have , X A y = xy -,X = 1 + X x ==> y = 1 + x + xy X V y = X + y + xy x {} y = 1 + x + y. The verifications are elementary. As usual, we permit ourselves to write xy in place of x x y. (b) For all elements x and y of 'llj 2Z, we have xy = X A y ; X + y = -,(X {} y ) = X {I} y = ( x A -. y ) V (-.x A y ) . (c) Obviously inspired by question (a), we define PF by induction. • If F is the propositional variable A; (1 < i < n), set PF X; . • If F = G set PF = 1 + Pc . • If F = (G 1\ H), set PF = Pc x PH . • If F = (G v H ) , set PF = Pc + PH + Pc PH. • If F = (G ==> H ) , set PF = 1 + Pc + PcPH. • I f F = (G {} H), set PF = 1 + Pc + PH . We then prove by induction that for every assignment of truth values 8 E {0, 1 } P , we have == -, , 8 ( F) ,...,_, == PF (8(A J ), 8 (A2), . . . , 8 (An)). (*) If F is the propositional variable A i , we have P F = X;, and the associated polynomial function PF is the ith projection, i.e. the map from {0, 1 } P into {0, 1 } whose value on any n-tuple (ct , £2, . . . , en ) is £i · This shows that the relation (*) is satisfied. If F (G 1\ H) and if (induction hypothesis) for all assignments of truth values 8, we have ::::: 8(G) = Pc (8(A I ) , 8 (A2), . . . , 8 ( A n )) and - I"J 8 ( H ) = PH (8( A J ) , 8 (A2) , . . . , 8 (An)), - � 254 SOLUTIONS � � � then, given that Pp = Pc PH, we would have PF = Pc PH; thus, for any assignment 8 , - - - Pp (8(A t ) , 8 (A2), . . . , 8 (An)) = 8(G )8(H) = 8 ((G 1\ H)) (by definition of 8 ) ; this proves ( * ) . The other steps in the induction are treated in an analogous manner. The definition that we have adopted defines, for every formula F, a unique polynomial Pp ; but we could have chosen others while still preserv­ ing property ( *) : for example, the polynomial associated with the formula (A t ¢> A2) is, according to our definition, 1 + X t + X2, but it is clear that the polynomial 1 + Xf + Xi would work just as well. What is unique, for a given formula F� is the associated polynomial function (it is the truth table of F). (d ) From what we have just seen, we conclude that for a formula to be a tauto­ logy, it is necessary and sufficient that the associated polynomial (or rather, the polynomial function) assume the constant value 1. For two formulas to be logically equivalent, it is necessary and sufficient that their associ­ ated polynomial functions coincide. To illustrate this, let us verify that the formulas G = (A =? (B =? C)) and H = ((A 1\ B) =? C) are logically equivalent (to simplify, w e have used A , B , and C instead of A 1 , A2, and A3 and X, Y, and Z instead of X 1 , X2, and X3). We have Pc = 1 + X + X ( l + Y + YZ) = I + X Y + X Y Z (since X -r- Y i s the null polynomial), and PH = I + ((XY) + (X Y) Z ) = 1 + X Y + X Y Z = Pc . 15. (a) We have seen (Lemma I .34) that if the formulas F and G have no propo­ sitional variable in common, and if the formula (F =} G) is a tautology, then either the formula G is a tautology or the formula F is an antilogy. It is obvious that in the fi rst case, the formula T is an interpolant between F and G while in the second case, the formula l.. is an interpolant between F and G. (b) The proof is by induction on F. If the height o f F is 0, this is obvious. We then simply need to verify that, given two formulas G and H , if both of them are logically equivalent to one of the three formulas T, l..� and A, then the same is true for (G 1\ H) and (G v H); this presents no difficulty. (c) The argument is analogous. This time, we show that if each of the formulas G and H is logically equivalent to one of the eight formulas T, l.., A, B, -,A, --,B, (A ¢> B),-,(A <::> B), then this is also the case for the formulas S O L UTIONS F O R C H A P T ER 1 25:5 (G 1\ H) and (G v H ). There are 64 cases to examine but some elementary arguments allow us to reduce this number considerably. (d) Since we already know that the systems { v } and {···,, /\} are complete, to show that a given system of connectives is complete, it suffices to prove that the connectives ....., and /\, or else the connectives ....., and /\, can be obtained by composition from the system of connectives under consideration. We will apply this remark to the systems that have been proposed. For all elements x and y belonging to {0, 1 } , we have • -,x = x � 0 and x v y = (x � 0) � y; hence {�, 0} is complete. • -,x = x ¢> 0 and v E {0, ¢>, v } ; hence {0, ¢> , v} is complete. • -,x = x ¢> 0 and 1\ E {0, ¢> , 1\ } ; hence {0, ¢> , /\} is complete. • -,x = x'{tx and x 1\ y = (x'{ty )'{t(x'{ty ) ; hence {�t} is complete. • -,x = x t} x and x v y = (xt}y) t}(xt}y); hence {,�} is complete. (Here, the symbols .....,, /\, v, ::::}, ¢>, t, and !}denote operations on {0, 1 } . ) (e) Let 8 1 denote the assignment of truth values to P that i s constant and equal to 1 and let 1t denote the set of formulas that can be written using the symbols for connectives T, =?, 1\, and v , to the exclusion of all others. 1-{ is defined inductively as the smallest set of formulas that includes P U { T } and that i s closed under the operations �..,, (M, N) t--7 (M � N ), ( M , N) � ( M 1\ N) and (M, N) � (M v N). (We may compare this with Exercise 20). By induction, we show that the assignment of truth values 81 satisfies all the formulas that belong to 11. For the propositional variables, this is true by definition of 81 ; it is also true for the formula T, hence for all formulas in 1t of height 0. Assuming that f' and G are two formulas of 'H such that 8 1 (F) = 81 (G) = 1, then we have 8 1 ((F => G)) = 8 1 ((F 1\ G)) = 8 1 ((F v G)) = l . It follows from this that the formula ...., A is not equivalent to any formula of 1t since 8 1 (-,A ) = 0. The conclusion is that {1, ::::} 1\, v} is not a complete system. It is easy to find a formula, -.A for example, that is not logically equivalent to any of the three formulas T, ..L, and A. We conclude from this, by virtue of question (b), that -.A is not logically equivalent to any formula that can be written using the variable A and only the connectives T, _L, /\, and v ; this shows that the system {/\, v, 0, 1 } is not complete. One may object that we have not considered the possibility that _,A could be logically equivalent to a formula that involves only the connectives T, _L, /\, and v but that might involve variables other than A: if G were such a formula, the formula G' obtained from A by replacing all occurrences of variables other than A by T would still be equivalent to -. A (Lemma J . 1 9) and this would contradict what we proved earlier. , 256 SOLUTIONS A similar argument, using question (c), will show that the system { 0, 1 , -., {} } is not complete. Consider, for example, the formula (A v B) which is not logically equivalent to any of the eight formulas in the set E of question (c). From this, we conclude that it is not logically equivalent to any formula that can be written using only the connectives T, 1_, , and {} . (If such a formula existed, we could find one that is logically equivalent, that is written with the same connectives and with the propositional variables A and B alone.) (f) Refer to the tables of one-place and two-place connectives given in Section 1 .3. No system of one-place connectives is complete: for example, the formula ( A t v A2) is not logically equivalent to any formula written with only the connectives T, 1_ , and -.,. Let us now prove that, with the exception of cpg and cprs, no two-place connective constitutes, by itself, a complete system. As far as cp2, cp4, cp6, cps, cpro, cp 1 2 , cp14, and cp 1 6 are concerned, notice that each of these connec­ tives assumes the value 1 at the point (1, 1), which proves that the con­ nective cps, for example, which assumes the value 0 at the point (1, 1), cannot be obtained by composition from one of these (nor from several of these, for that matter). This argument was already used in another form, in question (e) to show that the system {1, ==> , 1\, v } (which is none other than {CfJ2 , cpg, cp14, cpr6}) is not complete. A kind of dual argument applies for connectives that assume the value 0 at (0, 0) : the case of cp1 , cp3 , cps, and cp7 are thereby settled. As for cp] 1 and cp 1 3 , they really depend on only one of their arguments; so i f either of these constituted a complete system by itself, the same would be true for the corresponding one-place connective and we have seen that this is not true. Since we said in question (d) that each of the connectives <pfJ and cp IS constitutes a complete system, we have arrived at the desired conclusion. 16. (a) We have already indicated, several times, the logical equivalence between (A {} (B {} C)) and ((A {} B) {} C) (item 58 in Section 1 .2.3 ); we could check this with the help of the corresponding polynomials in Z/2Z[X, Y, Z ] (Exercise 14) or, as well, by verifying that these two formulas are sat­ isfied by precisely the same assignments of truth values to { A , B, C } , namely (0, 0 , 1 ) , (0, 1 , 0), ( 1 , 0 , 0), and (1, 1 , 1 ) . A s for the formula ((A {} B) 1\ (B {} C)), it is satisfied by the two assignments of truth values (0, 0, 0) and (1, 1, 1) and only these; it is therefore not logically equivalent to (A {} (B {} C)). Now it is a nearly universal practice, in contemporary mathematics, to write equivalences in a 'chain ' ; for example, when we say of three properties I, II, and III that they are equivalent, which we would write I{} II{} III, what we mean is that either all three of them are true or else that all three of them are false; and we, in effect, interpret the written expression I{}II{}Ill as (1{}11) 1\ (II{}III) and certainly not as (I{}(II{:}III)) which, -. S O L U T I O N S FOR C H A PTER I 257 as we have seen, has a different meaning. Naturally, this goes against the usual conventions relating to associativity which, were they applied in this case, would lead to interpreting I {:} I I{:} III indifferently, as an abbreviation for either (I�(II�III)) or ((I<:>II)�III). That is the reason why, in this particular case, it is important not to use any abbreviations: neither the one suggested by associativity, for the formula (A � (B � C)), nor the one dictated by mathematical practice, for the formula ((A � B) 1\ (B <=> C)). (b) The argument i s by induction on the cardinality, n , of the set B. For n = 2�. it is obvious. Suppose that the property is true for all sets of cardinality less than n and let us prove it if the cardinality of B is equal to n. Let F E Q(B). It is appropriate to distinguish three cases: • The formula F has the form (H � B ) , where B is a propositional variable belonging to B and H E Q(B - { B} ) . For an assignment of truth values 8 to satisfy F, it is necessary and sufficient that one of the following two situations holds: (i) 8 satisfies H and B (ii) 8 does not satisfy H nor B . I n case (i), there are an even number of elements o f B - { B } that are not satisfied by 8 and exactly the same number in B. In case (ii), there are an odd number of elements of B - { B } that are not satisfied by 8 and, as 8 (B ) == 0, there are an even number in B. The formula F has the form ( B � H), where B is a propositional variable in B and H E Q(B - { B } ). The same analysis applies. • There exists a partition of B into two sets B1 and fn, each having at least two elements, and formulas H1 and H2 belonging respectively to Q(BI ) and Q(B2) such that F = (Ht � H2). For 8 to satisfy F, it is necessary and sufficient that 8 satisfy both H 1 and H2 or else that 8 satisfy neither H 1 nor H2 . In the first case, the number of propositional variables in B 1 that are not satisfied by 8 i s even (by the induction hypothesis) and so is the number of propositional variables in B2 that are not satisfied by 8 which, i n all, make an even number. In the second case, the number or propositional variables in Bt that are not satisfied by 8 is odd and so i s the number of propositional variables in B2 that are not satisfied by 8, which) once again, make an even number in all. (c) We prove by induction on the cardinality of the set B that, for every formula G E Q(B), the formula G is satisfied by an assignment of truth values 8 if and only if 8 satisfies an odd number of propositional variables in B. The proof is analogous to the one for (b). The required equivalence follows immediately. • "' 258 SOLUTIONS (d) Let x E E . For each integer i between 1 and k, we introduce a propositional variable A; and define the assignment of truth values 8 by 8 (A i ) = ] if and only if x E Xi . We easily see, by induction on the integer k, that x if and only if 8 satisfies the following formula F: E X 1 t:J,. X2 l::J,. . . . t:J,.X k the result now follows from question (c). (Also see Exercise 2 from Chapter 2.) 17. (a) We argue by contradiction. If the formula i s not a tautology, there exists a n assignment o f truth values 8 that satisfies the formulas F[A 1 , A2, . . . , An, A] and F[A 1 , A2, . . . , A n , B] and does not satisfy the formula (A <:> B ). But, by hypothesis, 8 must satisfy the formula since this is a tautology, as well as the formula obtained by substituting B for A in the preceding, namely, ( F [ A t , A 2 , . . . , A n , B] ::::} (G[A 1 , A2 , . . . , An] ¢;> B ) ) . Since 8 ( F [A 1 , A2 , . . . , A n , A J ) = 8 ( F [A I , A2, . . . , A n , B]) = 1, we must have 8 (G [A 1 . A2 , . . . , A 11 ] ) = 8 (A ) = 8 (B ) , which i s incompatible with the fact that 8 does not satisfy ( A � B ) . (b) For each of the cases under consideration, we present formulas G [A 1 , A2, . . . , An] that are possible definitions of A modulo F (these need not be unique). The verifications are immediate and are left to the reader. (1) G (2) G (3) G (4) G (5) G = A1 = A 1 or G = A2 = At or G = A2 or G = ( A I v ..., A I ) = (A J v _,A J ) or G = _,A2 = (A I v _,A I ) or G = ( A t ¢> (A2 ¢> A3)). 18. (a) It suffices to prove that if cp F( cJ , £2, . . . , En , 1 ) = 1, then we do not have cp F (E l , £2, . . . , En , 0) = 1 . We argue by contradiction. If these two equal­ ities were verified, this would mean that the assignments of truth val­ ues 'A and Ji.· on {A t , A 2 , . . . , A n , A } defined by 'A(A J ) = Jl. ( A I ) = £ I , 'A(A2) = tL (A2) = c2, . . . , 'A(A n) = tL ( An) = en , 'A (A) = 1 and p,(A) = 0 SOLUTIONS FOR CHAPTER I 259 both satisfy the formula F[A 1 , A 2 , . . . , A n , A ] . This amounts to saying that the assignment of truth values 8 on { A t , A2, . . . , A n , A , B } defined by simultaneously satisfies the formulas As we have assumed that <=> is a tautology, 8 must also satisfy (A of 8. B ) ; but this contradicts the definition (b) Having chosen G as indicated, let us consider a distribution of truth values 8 on {A 1 , A 2 , . . . , An, A } that satisfies the formula F[A 1 , A2, . . . , An, A] and set • • If 8 (A ) = 0, then cpF(8 I , 82 , . . . , 8n , 0) = 1, hence cpc (8 I , 82, . . . , 8n) = 1/1 (8 1 , 82, . . . , 8n ) = 0, which means that 8 (G) = 0. If 8 (A ) = 1, then cpF(8 I , 82, 8n , 1) = l , hence according to the first question, cpc (81 , 82 , . . . , 8n ) = 1/1 (81 , 82, . . . , 8n ) = 1, which means that 8 (G ) = 1 . . • . , So i n every case, 8 (A ) = 8 (G), which shows that 8 satisfies the formula (G[A 1 , A 2 , . . . , An] <=> A ) . Thus we have proved that the formula is a tautology, since every assignment that satisfies the left side of this implication also satisfies the right side. 19. (a) A formula is determined, up to logical equivalence, by its truth table or, which amounts to the same thing, by the set of assignments of truth values that satisfy it. The set ofassignments oftruth values on P = { A , B , C, D , £ ] has 25 = 32 elements. There are therefore 1 7 C32 subsets that have seven­ teen elements. If one prefers, there are 1 7 C32 ways to place seventeen 1 s and fifteen Os in the last column of a truth table that has 32 lines. Consequently, there are, up to logical equivalence, 1 7C32 = 32! 17! 15! = 565 722 720 formulas that are satisfied by seventeen assignments oftruth values (whereas 32 there are 2 = 4 294 967 296 equivalence classes for the equivalence relation on formulas that is logical equivalence). SOLUTIONS 260 (b) Let A denote the set of assignments of truth values 8 on { A , B C, D, E } that satisfy 8 (A ) = 8 (B ) = 1. For a formula to be a consequence of (A 1\ B ) , it is necessary and sufficient that it receive the value 1 for all the assignments that belong to A . There are eight such assignments (we extend each of the eight assignments from { C, D, E} into {0, 1} by setting their values on A and B equal to l). A formula that is a consequence of (A 1\ B) is therefore determined, up to logical equivalence, by the set of assignments of truth values, other than the eight required, that satisfy it. So there are as many such formulas as there are subsets of the set {0, l } P A , which is to say, , - 224 = 1 6 777 2 1 6. If one prefers, in the last column of the truth table of a formula that is a consequence of (A 1\ B ) , the value 1 must appear in the eight lines corre­ sponding to the assignments of truth tables in A ; in the other 24 lines, we 2 may arbitrarily place the values 0 or 1 ; this leads to exactly 2 4 possible truth tables. 20. (a) We argue by induction on F. If F is a propositional variable, we may obviously take the formula G to be F itself. Next, let H and K be two formulas with which we have associated (induction hypothesis) negation­ free formulas H' and K' such that H is logically equivalent to H' or to -,H' and K is logically equivalent to K' or to -,K'. We will distinguish four possibilities: 1 I. 1 0. OL 00. H H H H "' "' "' ""' H' and K "' K'; H' and K "' -.K'; -.H' and K ""' K'; - ,H' and K -.K'. ""' We will prove that in each of the following five cases: I. F 11. F III. F IV. F V. F = = = = = -.H ( H 1\ K) (H v K) (H ::::} K ) (H <=> K ) w e can fi nd a formula G that does not involve negation and i s such that F is logically equivalent either to G or to -.G. I. If H is logically equivalent to H', F is logically equivalent to -.H' ; i f H is logically equivalent t o -.H', F is logically equivalent t o -·-.H', hence to H'; we may therefore take G = H'. G. In case II. In case 1 1 , we take G = (H' 1\ K') and we have F -.G. In case 0 1 , we take 1 0, we take G = (H' ::::} K') and we have F G = (K' ::::} H') and we have F "' -.G. Finally, in case 00, we take G = ( H' v K') and we have F "' -.G. � "' 26 1 SOLUTIONS FOR CHAPTER I III. In case 1 1 , we take G = ( H ' v K') and we have F G . In case G. In case 01. we take 1 0, we take G = ( K' =} H') and we have F G = (H' => K') and we have F G. Finally, in case 00, we take r-v r-v r-v G = (H' 1\ K') and we have F r-v -,G. IV. In case 1 1, we take G = (H' =} K') and we have F G. In case 1 0, we take G = (H' 1\ K') and we have F -,G. In case 0 1 , we take G = (H' v K') and we have F r-v G . Finally. in case 00. we take G = (K' � H ' ) and we have F G. V . I n cases 1 1 and 00, we take G = ( H ' <¢:> K') and we have F G . In cases 1 0 and 00, take G = (H' ¢> K' ) and we have F "' -,G. r-v r-v r-v r-v (b) It is obvious that ( i ) implies (ii). To see that (ii) implies ( i ) is not difficult: as the formula (G <¢:> H) is logically equivalent, for all formulas G and H, to ((G =} H) 1\ (H =} G)), any formula written using the four connectives 1\, v, =}, and ¢} is logically equivalent to a formula that can be written using only the first three of these symbols. (Perfectionists would prove this by induction on F.) Let us now prove the equivalence of (ii) and (iii). (ii) implies (iii). We can see this by induction on the height of formulas F written without negation: if it is a variable, 8 1 (F) = 1 by definition of 8 1 , if it is (G 1\ H), (G v H ) , (G =} H), or (G ¢} H ) , where 8 1 (G) = 1 and 8 1 ( H ) = 1, then we obviously have 8 1 (F) = 1 also. Conversely, let F be a formula such that 8 1 ( F ) = 1. According to (a), we can find a negation-free formula G such that F is logically equivalent either to G or to -lG. As-G is negation-free, we may conclude, knowing that (ii) implies (iii), that 8 1 (G) = 1 = 8 1 ( F ). It is therefore not possible for F to be logically equivalent to -,G; F is consequently logically equivalent to G . We have thus shown that (iii) implies (ii). 21. (a) The reflexivity, transitivity, and anti symmetry of the relation << are proved without difficulty. This is certainly an order relation, but this is not a tota] ordering: if n > 2, the assignments of truth values A and 11- defined by A ( A I ) = 0, M (A t ) = 1, A ( A i ) = 1, and M ( A ; ) = 0 for 2 < i < n do not satisfy A. << 11- nor 11- << A. (b) The formula ( A 1 =} A2) is an example of a formula that is not increasing and whose negation is not increasing: to see this, it is sufficient to consider the assignments of truth values A, /J-, and v defined by A ( A i ) = 0 for all i E { 1 , 2, . . . , n } ; E { 1 . 2 . . . . , n }. M ( A l ) = 1 and M ( A i ) = 0 for all i v ( A i ) = 1 for all i E {2, 3 , . . . , n } ; So we have A << /J-, A. (F) = 1, and M (F) = 0 ; hence F i s not increasing. On the other hand, 11- << v, p., ( _, F ) = 1, and v (-., F) = 0; hence -, p is not . . tncreastng. 262 SOLUTIONS (c) First we prove 'if' . It is clear that if F is a tautology, or if -.F is a tautology (i.e. F is an antilogy), then F is increasing. Let C denote the set of formulas in which the symbols ....., , =}, and {} do not occur. Because it is evident that any formula logically equivalent to an increasing formula is itself increasing, it suffices to prove that i f F belongs to C, then F is increasing. We prove this by induction on the height of the formula F : it needs to be proved that propositional formulas are increasing (this is obvious) and that if G and H are increasing, then so are (G 1\ H) and (G v H ) ; this is not very difficult. Next we prove 'only if'. Let F be an increasing formula that is neither a tautology nor an antilogy. We must prove that there exists a formula G belonging to C, defined above, that is logically equivalent to F. Let !:l. (F) denote the set of assignments of truth values that satisfy F: !:l. (F) = {8 {0, 1 } P : 8 (F) = 1 }. E For an arbitrary assignment of truth values 8, set V+ (8) = {A E P : 8 (A ) = 1}. Note that the sets defined this way are finite and that !:l. (F) is not empty (otherwise -.F would be a tautology). We also see that for every 8 belonging to !:l. F), V+ ( 8) is not empty: for there is only one assignment of truth values 0, namely the assignment 8o defined by 8o(A) 0 8 for which V+ (8) for all propositional variables A. And if 8o belonged to !:l. ( F), we would have 8o(F) = 1; but as F is increasing and since every assignment of truth values 8 satisfies 8o << 8, we would also have 8 (F) = 1 for all 8 E {0, 1 } P ; but this i s impossible since F i s not a tautology. We may thus define the formula = = G= V oE6.(F) ( f\ A ) AEV+ (o) which is clearly an element of the set C. Now let us show that F and G are logically equivalent. Let /... be an assignment of truth values on P that satisfies F; it follows that /... E !:l. ( F), hence the formula /\ A EV+(A)A isone ofthe terms in the disjunction that is the formula G. Since we have, by definition, that /... (A) = 1 for all A E V+ (/... ) , we conclude that /... (1\ A E V+ (o)A) = 1 and hence that /... ( G) = 1 . Conversely, if J.l is an element of {0, l } P that satisfies G, there exists an assignment of truth values 8 E !}.(F) such that f.l(/\ A E V+(o) A) = 1; this means that for all A belonging to V+ (8), J.l(A) = t which in turn means that for every propositional variable A, if 8 (A) 1, then J.l (A) = 1 ; in other words, for every propositional variable A, 8 (A ) < J.l(A); this says that 8 << J.l. Since 8 E !:l. (F) (so 8 (F) = 1 ) and F is an increasing formula, it follows that 1. We have established that F and G are satisfied by exactly the �(F) - - = = S O L U T I O N S F O R C H A PT E R 263 l same assignments of truth values to P ; so the two formulas are logically equivalent. 22. Given a finite set of formulas { Ft . F2 , . . . . Fk L to show that it is independent� it suffices to find, for each index i , an assignment of truth values that satisfies all the Fj (j =/: i) and that does not satisfy Fi ; on the contrary, to prove that it is not independent, we show that one of the Fi is a consequence of the others. In the situation where the set of formulas under consideration is not indepen­ dent, we invoke the following observation when we wish to find an equivalent independent subset: if A is a set of formulas and if the formula F is a conse­ quence of A - { F } , then the sets A and A - { F } are equivalent. (a) We will only treat sets ( 1 ), (2), and (6). None of the other sets is independent. ( 1 ) The set { ( A =} B), (B => C), (C =} A ) } is independent. Note that the assignment of truth values 8 defined by 8 (A) = 1, 8 ( B ) = 0., and 8 (C) = 1 does not satisfy the first formulas but does satisfy the other two; similarly, we note that any assignment of truth values that makes one of these formulas false will necessarily satisfy the other two. (2) The set { ( A =} B), (B =} C ) , (A => C) } is not independent since {(A => B ) , (B => C)} 1-* (A =:::} C ) . The subset { ( A => B ) , ( B =} C ) } i s independent and i s equivalent to the given set. It is easy to see that this is the only subset with this property. (6) The set { ( (A =} B ) =} C), (A =:::} C), ( B => C), (C =} (B => A)), ((A => B ) => (A <=> B ) ) } is not independent; observe that the last formula is equivalent to (B =} A) and so the next to last formula is a consequence of it. There are two independent equivalent subsets: { ((A =} B) =} C), (A =} C), (C =} (B =} A ) ) } and { ((A =} B) =} C), ( A => C), ( (A => B) => (A <=> B)) } . (b) The empty set is independent: if i t were not, i t would contain a formula { F } �* F ; this is obviously impossible. If A = { G } , F such that 0 { G } J=* G i s equivalent to 0 �* G (which means that G i s then A a tautology). Consequently, a necessary and sufficient condition for a set containing a single formula to be independent is that this formula is not a tautology. - - (c) We establish this property by induction on the number of formulas in the set. [t is true when this number is 0 because 0 is an independent subset that is equivalent to 0. Suppose that every set containing n formulas has at least one equivalent independent subset and consider a set A of n + 1 formulas. If A is independent, it is itself an independent subset equivalent to A. If not, then we can find in A a formula F that is a consequence of B = A { F } . B, which contains n formulas, has� by the induction hypothesis� an independent - 264 SOLUTIONS subset C that is equivalent to B. But B is equivalent to A according to the remark at the beginning of this solution. As a result, C is a subset of A that is independent and equivalent to A. Remark: Concerning this proof, there are two errors to be avoided (which, by the way, are related). The first consists in believing that if A is an independent set of formulas and if F is a formula that is not a consequence of A, then A U { F} is independent. The second consists in thinking that a maximal independent subset of a set of formulas is necessarily equivalent to this set. The example that follows shows that these two ideas are incorrect. Let A = { A } , F = (A 1\ B) and B = A U { F } . We see immediately that A is independent, that F is not a consequence of A, that A U { F } is not independent and that A is a maximal independent subset of B but is not equivalent to B. (d) If A is an independent set of formulas and if B is a subset of A (finite or not), then B is independent. Now suppose that A is a set of formulas that is not independent. So there is at least one formula G in A such that A - { G } 1-* G. According to the compactness theorem, there is some finite subset B of A - { G } such that B 1--¥ G. Set C = B U { G } ; we then have C - { G } r-* G, which proves that C is a finite subset of A that is not independent. Thus, for a set of formulas to be independent, it is necessary and sufficient that all its finite subsets are independent. (e) For each integer n > I , set Fn = A 1 1\ A2 1\ · · · 1\ An and let A denote the set { Fn : n E N* } . For n < p, Fn is a consequence of Fp ; thus the only subsets of A that are independent consist of a single element. It is also clear that for every n, f� + 1 is not a consequence of Fn Gust take the assignment of truth values that satisfies A 1 , A2, . . . , A11 and not An+ d; it follows that no independent subset of A can be equivalent to A. None the less, there exist independent sets that are equivalent to A, for example, { A t . A2, . . . • A,p . . . } . (f) We seek a set of formulas equivalent to :F = { Fo. Ft , . . . , Fn } . First, we obtain a set that is equivalent to :F by removing those formulas Fn that are a consequence of { Fo, Ft , . . . , F� - d . In other words, we may assume thatforevery n, the formula Fn is not a consequence of { Fo , F1 , . . . , Fn - I } and, in particular, that Fo is not a tautology. We then consider the following set Q : • Q = . . . { Fo, Fo =} Ft . ( Fo 1\ Ft ) :::} F2, . . . , (Fo 1\ F1 1\ · · · I\ Fn ) :::} Fn+J , . . . } . It i s clear that i f an assignment of truth values satisfies all the formulas Fn , then it satisfies Q; conversely, if it satisfies all the formulas in Q, then we see, by induction on n, that it satisfies all the formulas Fn . The sets F and Q are thus equivalent. We will show that Q is independent by exhibiting, for S O L U T I O N S F O R C H A PT E R I 265 every formula G in Q, an assignment of truth values that does not satisfy G but that satisfies all the other formulas of Q. If G == Fo, we take an assignment that makes Fo false (one exists since Fo is not a tautology). The other formulas of Q are then all satisfied. • If G = ( Fo 1\ F1 1\ · · · 1\ Fn ) ==> Fn+ I , we choose an assignment of truth values 8 that satisfies Fo, Fr , . . . , Fn and that makes Fn+ 1 false (one exists since Fn+l is not a consequence of { Fo, F1 , . . . . Fn- 1 }); it is easy to verify that 8 has the required properties. 23. (a) For each a E E , consider the formula Fa : • Fa = (V ) ( 1 <i <k Aa ,i 1\ (\ -, (A a i 1\ A a , j ) , ) , l <i <} <k and for every pair (a , b) E £ 2 , the formula: Ha, b = (\ I <i<k -� (Aa . i 1\ Ab,i ) . We will show that G is k-colourable if and only if the set A(E, G ) = { Fa : u E E } U { Ha,b : (a, b) E G } i s satisfiable. If f i s a function from E into { 1 , 2 , . . . , k } that satisfies the conditions that are required for G to be k-colourable, we define the assign­ ment of truth values 8 by 8 (Aa,i ) == 1 i f and only if f (a ) == i, and we easily see that 8 satisfies all the formulas in A(E. G). Conversely, suppose that we have a n assignment of truth values 8 that satisfies all the formulas in A(E, G). Let a E E. The fact that Fn is satisfied by 8 means that there is one and only one integer i between 1 and k such that 8 ( Aa,i ) = 1 ; denote this integer by f(a). The fact that 8 satisfies the formulas Ha, b for (a , b) E G shows that if (a , b) E G, then f(a) i= f (b). G is therefore k-colourable. (b) It is clear that if a graph is k-colourable, then all its subgraphs and, in particular, all its finite subgraphs are k-colourable. Conversely, suppose that all the finite subgraphs of G are k-colourable. We will establish that G is k-colourable by showing that A (E, G) is satisfiable and, to do this, we will invokethecompactnesstheorem. So let A be a finite subset of A ( E , G). Let E ' denote the subset of points a in E such that for some integer i , the variable Aa,i occurs in some formula of A and let G' denote the restriction of G to E'. G' is a finite subgraph of G and A c A(E', G'). Since G' is k-colourable, A(E', G') is satisfiable (question (a)) and so too is A. Hence, by the compactness theorem, A(E, G) is satisfiable and G is k-colourable (question (a)). SOLUTIONS 266 The following illustration explains the terminology used in this exercise. For E, take a set of countries and for G the relation 'have a common bor­ der that does not reduce to a single point'; in this context, k-colourability corresponds to the possibility of attributing a colour to each country (in view of producing a geographical map), the diverse colours available being E 1 , £2, . . . , Ek . The obvious constraint is that bordering countries must always receive distinct colours. Cartographers rarely have to deal with an infinite set of countries, so this exercise is of no great use to them. It is rather the problem of finding the smallest possible value for k that con­ cerned specialists in graph theory for a long time. The conjecture was that this smallest value is 4 (for a certain class of graphs that are not too com­ plicated): this was the famous four-colour problem that remained unsolved until 1 986, when two American mathematicians together with a number of powerful computers produced a 'proof' of this conjecture. The quotes are justified here by the fact that, even if the number of pages of this book were increased beyond anything the reader might imagine, and if we had the nec­ essary competence, we would still be hard pressed to provide it here . . . . This is the first example of its kind for a theorem of mathematics. The only thing that logic has taught us is that the four-colour problem is no easier for finite sets than it is for infinite sets. 24. (a) Intuitively, the propositional variable Ax,y has the value 1 if and only if x is less than or equal to y. We set: { Ax ,x : X E G } ; C(G) == { (Ax,y 1\ Ay.z) =? Ax,z : X E G , y E G, Z E G } ; V(G) = { (Ax .y <#? Ay,x) : X E G , y E G , X # y}; E(G) = {Ax.y =} Ax·z,y·z : X E G , y E G, Z E G}; B(G) == and A(G) == B(G) u C ( G ) u V(G) U E(G). Suppose that the group G is orderable. Let < be a total ordering on G that is compatible with the group operation. Define an assignment of truth values 8 on P by setting: for all elements x and y of G , 8 ((x , y)) == 1 i f and only i f x < y. This assignment satisfies all the formulas in A( G): those in B(G) because the relation < is reflexive, those in C (G) because it is transitive, those in V(G) because it is antisymmetric and total, and finally, those in E (G) because it is compatible with the group operation. We have thus shown that the set A( G) is satisfiable when the group G is orderable. Conversely, suppose that A( G) is satisfiable. Let A. be an 267 SOLUTIONS FOR CHAPTER 1 assignment of truth values that satisfies it and define a binary relation R on G as follows: for all elements x and y of G, (x, y) E R if and only if A.(Ax , y) = 1 . The fact that the sets B ( G ) , C ( G ) , and E (G) are satisfied shows that R is reflexive, transitive, and compatible with the group operation. Also, R is antisymmetric and total because A. satisfies the formulas in V( G). This rela­ tion is therefore a total ordering that is compatible with the group operation, i.e. G is orderable. (b) If a group is orderable, it is clear that all its subgroups (in particular, the subgroups of finite type) are orderable (by the restriction to the subgroup of the order on G). It is the converse of this property that is not obvious. Suppose that (G, · , 1) is a group all of whose subgroups of finite type are orderable. According to (a), to prove that G is orderable, it suffices to show that the set of formulas A( G) is satisfiable. By the compactness theorem, it is then sufficient to show that every finite subset of A( G) is satisfiable. Let U be a finite subset of A( G). Let M denote the set of elements of G that appear in at least one formula of U; this is, of course, a finite subset of G, so the subgroup, H, that it generates is of finite type. According to our hypothesis, H is orderable, hence (question (a)) the set of formulas A( H ) i s satisfiable. Because U i s included in A ( H ) , U i s therefore satisfiable. (c) First we will show the easy part of the equivalence: if an abelian group is orderable, then it is torsion-free. Let (G, · , 1) be an abelian group that is ordered by < . Suppose that G is a torsion group, i.e. that there is an element n x in G, distinct from 1, and a non-zero natural number n such that x = 1 . (Such a n element x is called a torsion element). Because the ordering < is total, we have either 1 < x or x < 1 . I f we suppose that 1 < x , then using the compatibility of < with the group operation · , we obtain successively It follows that x < 1 by transitivity and hence, by antisymmetry, x = 1 , which i s not possible. I n a similar way, we arrive at a contradiction from the assumption that x < 1 . Thus the group is torsion-free. Let us now tackle the other implication. Suppose that ( G, 1) is a torsion­ free abelian group and consider a subgroup, H, of G of finite type. Then H is also a torsion-free abelian group (for a torsion element in H would obviously be a torsion element i n G also). If H is the trivial subgroup { 1 } , i t i s obviously orderable. If H i s non-trivial, then b y the theorem stated as part of the exercise, there is a non-zero natural number p such that (H, · , 1 ) is isomorphic to the group (ZP, + , 0). Now the group (G, · , 1 ) is orderable: it suffices to consider the lexicographical ordering on ZP , specifically, i f the elements (at , a2, . . . a p ) and (hi , b2, . . . , b p) of ZP are distinct and if k · , , 268 SOLUTIONS is the smallest of the indices i between 1 and p such that ai # bi , then This is clearly a total ordering and it is compatible with the group operation (which, in this case, is coordinate-wise addition): more precisely, if then for any element (c1 , c2 , . . . , cp) of 7l P , we also have which is to say, (Q I + C I , a2 + C2, . . . , a p + Cp) < (b I + C J , b2 + C2, • . • , b p + Cp). I f cp is an isomorphism of the group (G, · , 1) onto the group (�P, then the binary relation -< defined on H by +, 0), for all elements x and y of H, x --< y if and only if cp (x ) < cp(y) is a total ordering on H that is compatible with the group operation (what we are saying here is that any group that is isomorphic to an orderable group is orderable ). We have just proved that every subgroup of (G, · , 1) of finite type is orderable. According to question (b), this proves that G itself is orderable. 25. Where precision matters, we will denote properties I, II, and III by I £ .F. R , IlE,F.R, and IIIE. F. R respectively. (a) If E is the empty set� III is trivially verified (the empty map is injective). This is also the case when E consists of a single element, a: for then, I means that Ra is non-empty, so by choosing an element b in Ra and setting f (a) = b, we define a map f that satisfies the requirements. Let k be a natural number greater than or equal to 2. We suppose (induction hypothesis) that for all sets X and Y and relations S £ X x Y, if card( X) < k and if lx . r.s is satisfied. then so is Illx, Y. S · Now suppose that E is a set with k elements. First, we examine case 1 : there exists at least one non-empty subset A of E, distinct from E, such that card(A) = card(RA). By the induction hypothesis, we can find an injective map !1 from A into RA such that for every element a in A , f1 (a) E Ra . Set B = E - A , C = F - RA , and S = R n (B x C). We will show that 1 8 ' c ' s is true. To see this, consider an arbitrary subset M of B and set N = A U M . It is not difficult to verify that SOLUTIONS FOR CHAPTER 269 I This implies (because RA and SM are disjoint) that card(RN) == card (RA ) + card(SM) and, according to IE,F. R , card (RN) > card(A) + card(SM) (since A and M are disjoint). It follows that card( A ) -r card(SM) > card(A) + card( M). Since card( A) is finite, we may conclude that card(SM) > card (M), which shows that IB,c.s is satisfied. So the induction hypothesis is applicable; this yields an injective map /2 from B into C such that, for all b in B, f2(b) belongs to Sb, which means that (b, 12 (b)) E R. The desired map f is the map that is equal to /1 on A and to !2 on B. Next, consider case 2: for every non-empty subset A of E , distinct from E , the cardinality o f A i s strictly greater than that of R A . Choose a n element u in E (which is not empty) and an element v in Ru (which is also not empty by virtue of IE,F.R and which even has, in the present case, at least two elements). By the induction hypothesis, there is an injective map from E { u } into Ru { v}. It suffices to extend this map to the whole of E by setting f (u ) == v. - - (b) If E == F == N and if R = { (0 , n ) : n E N} U { (n + I , n) : n E N}, we can check that property I is satisfied while II and III are not. (c) Let X and Y be two sets and let S c X x Y be a binary relation such that properties I x .r,s and Ilx.r. s hold. Take P == X x Y as the set of propositional variables and consider the foilowing sets of formulas: Bx , Y. S = { yVE Sx (x, y) : x E X Cx, Y S == { --. ((x , y) A (x, z)) , Vx, Y, S == } x E X, y E Y, Y and y -# z } { --. ( (x, y ) A (t, y ) ) : x E X , t E X , y E Y and x =1= t } . : z E Then set: Ax , r. s == B x Y, S . U Cx,Y.S U Vx,Y,S· Observe that for each element x of X, v yESx (x , y) is a formula because the set Sx is fi nite (property II) and non-empty (property I: card(Sx) > card( {x}) ). If 8 is an assignment of truth values that satisfies Ax, r.s, then we can define a map f from X into Y that satisfies the conditions in III in the 270 SOLUTIONS following way: for all x E X , f (x ) is the unique element of Y for which 8 (Ax,y) = 1 . Conversely, i f we have a map f that satisfies the conditions i n III, then we can obtain an assignment of truth values 8 that satisfies Ax,Y,S by setting: for all (x , y) E X x Y, 8 (Ax,y) = 1 if and only if (x) = y . So w e see that the set of formulas Ax,Y,S is satisfiable i f and only if property Ill x,Y. S is verified. Now consider the sets E and F and the relation R that we have been studying. Since they satisfy properties I and It to show that they also sat­ isfy III, it suffices to prove that the associated set of formulas AE, F, R is satisfiable. By the compactness theorem, this amounts to proving that every finite subset of this set is satisfiable. Let Q be such a finite subset. We easily see that there exists a finite subset X of E such that, if we set Y = Rx and s = R n (X X Y), then Q is included in Ax, Y, S · Now properties Ix , Y, S and Ilx , Y, S are obviously verified; hence, from (a), IIIx, Y, S i s also verified and, from the preceding argument, Ax, Y, s is satisfiable as well as Q. The property proved in this exercise is known as the marriage theorem. We can illustrate it this way: E represents a set of men, F a set of women, (x , y) E R means that '"x knows y' and y = f (x ) means 'x marries y ' . What w e have proved i s that i f a n arbitrary number of men chosen from E collectively know at least the same number of women, then it is possible to marry each man in E to a woman in F that he knows, with no polygamy occurring. (Let us add that if we wish to consider the improbable case in which these sets are infinite, we would have to add the hypothesis that each man knows only a finite number of women . . . ). Such an illustration could naturally be criticized, specifically for the asymmetric roles played by E and F, or else for its conformity with the imposed rules: monogamy and marriage between people who know each other. Solutions to the exercises for Chapter 2 1. (a) It is the fact that the relation of logical equivalence, �, is compatible with the propositional connectives that allows us to define internal operations on FI � by the relations given in the statement of the exercise (these relations are independent ofthe choice ofrepresentativesfrom the equivalence classes of formulas). More precisely, and in conformity with Theorem 1 .24, for all formulas F, G, F', and G', if ci(F) = ci(F') and ci(G) = ci(G'), then cl( -, p) = cl( -,p'), ci(F A G) = ci(F' A G'), ci(F v G) = ci(F' v G'), ci(F ==} G) = ci(F' ==} G') and ci(F <¢:> G) = ci(F' <¢:> G'). (Also see our comments in Section 1 .2). S O L U T I O N S F O R C H A PT E R 27 1 2 We have the following logical equivalences (T is a tautology, ..l an anti­ logy, the numbers in brackets refer to the list established in Section 1 .2): • • • • • • • • • (A § B ) � ( B § A ) ; [no. 4 1 ] (A � ( B § C) ) ; [the first of these formulas is ((A {I} B ) {I} C ) ...., ( ...., ( A <=> B) <=> C) which is logically equivalent to ((A {:?- B ) <::> C) [no. 43], to (A <=> (B <=> C)) [no. 58 ], and hence to the second formula.] (A § .l) A [no. 48 and no. 4 1 ] (A § A ) '"'"'J_ [no. 49 and no. 43] (A 1\ B) "'"' (B 1\ A) [no. 3] ((A "\ B ) 1\ C) (A 1\ (B 1\ C)) [no. 5] ((A 1\ B ) � (A 1\ C)) [we j ustify this using the (A 1\ (B § C)) method of Exercise 14 from Chapter 1 : the polynomial associated with the first formula is x ( 1 + 1 + y + z); the one associated with the second is 1 + 1 -r-- xy -r xz, which is the same.] (A 1\ T) A ; [no. 46] (A ;, A) A ; [no. 1 ] . � r-v ,..._. ,..._. � ,..._. These equivalences prove that the operation § on FI is commutative and associative, that it admits the class 0 of antilogies as an identity ele­ ment, and that every element has an inverse element (itself) relative to this identity element. The structure (FI ""', §} is thus a commutative group. Moreover, the operation 1\ is commutative, associative, distributive over {!}, is idempotent and has an identity element: the class 1 of tautologies. Consequently, the structure (FI {!} , /\ ) is a commutative ring with unit that is a Boolean ring. ,..._. r-v, (b) It is true by definition that for all formulas F and G, cl( F ) < ci(G) if and only if cl(F) 1\ cl( G) = ci(F), which is equivalent to ci(F 1\ G) = ci(F), which is to say ( F 1\ G) F, or also to !-- * ( ( F 1\ G) <=> F). Now the formula ( ( F 1\ G) <=> F) is logically equivalent to ( F => G) (see [no. 38]). It follows that ,..._. cl( F ) < ci(G) if and only if !--* ( F => G). (Let us observe i n passing that the property ' ( F => G ) i s a tautology' defines a binary relation on F that is compatible with the relation of logical equivalence, ""', and that the relation induced by it on the quotient set F I ""' is the order relation of the Boolean algebra.) Let us also observe that this is in no case a total ordering: if A is a propositional variable, we have neithercl(A) < ci(...., A ) norci(...., A ) < ci(A) since neither of the two formulas ( A ::=:> -,A) nor (...., A => A) is a tautology (they are equivalent, respectively, to -,A and to A). For the ordering <, the smallest element is the class 0 of antilogies and the greatest element is the class 1 of tautologies. 272 SOLUTIONS Let x == ci(F) and y == cl( G) be two elements of :FI ""'. We have (Theorem 1 . 18) x "' y == xy == x and XC == 1 +X l == A y == ci(F {I} X = A G) CI(-,F). It follows, using de Morgan's laws, that x 'J c ( ) c c y = x "' y == ci(�(�F A -.G)) == ci(F v G ) == x v y . Hence, the operations o f least upper bound, greatest lower bound, and complementation are, respectively, disjunction, conjunction, and negation. (c) Suppose that P is the finite set {A 1 , A2, . . . , An } (n E N*). Then the quotient set :F1 ""' is also finite and has 22" elements (see Section 1 .3). This shows that the Boolean algebra (:FI § A O 1) is atomic (Theorem 2.39) andalso that the number ofits atoms is 2n (Theorem 2.50 and Corollary 2.5 1 ) We will show that these atoms are the the equivalence classes of the formulas ""' , (\ I <k sn , , , ek Ak , n obtained as the n-tuple ( et , £2, . . . , Bn ) varies over {0, 1 } . Let us observe from the outset that there are 2n such classes, which amounts to saying that these formulas under consideration are pairwise logically inequivalent (which is guaranteed by Lemma 1 .25). Thus, if we succeed in showing that these classes are atoms, we will be assured that we have thereby found all the atoms of this Boolean algebra. Consider an n-tuple ( c-1 , £2, , en ) E {0, 1 }11 and let H denote the asso­ ciated formula: H == ck Ak. • • • (\ l sk <n We will reuse the notation from Section 1 .3. We have � ( H ) == {c5 c 1c2 cn } (Lemma 1 .25); hence, c i(H) =I= 0. It also follows from this that for any formula F such that ci(F) < ci(H) (which means that �* ( F ==> H) and is obviously equivalent to � (F) c 8 ( H ) ), • either D.(F) == {c5s1 82 c, } == � ( H ) , and so ci(F) == ci(H); • or D. ( F ) == 0, and in this case, ci(F) == 0. We have thus proved that ci(H) is a non-zero element of the Boolean algebra :FI ""' below which the only elements are itself and 0; this means that it is an atom. •.• .. • 2. We will make use of the results from Exercise 1 . Let X and Y be two subsets of E . For every element x E X , we have x E X D. Y if and only if one and only one of the statements x E X and x E Y is true; this . 273 SOLUTIONS FOR CHAPTER 2 means precisely that x E X � y if and only if the statement x E X <#? x E Y is true. The commutativity of �!!,. follows from that of <#?; for all subsets X and Y of E , X I!!,. Y = {x E E : x E X = {X E E : X E <#? y {I} x E Y} X E X} = y I!!,. X . The associativity of �!!,. is obtained from that o f § i n an analogous fashion_ Moreover, X 1!!,.0 = {X E E : X E X {/? X E 0 } = {X E E : X E X} = X (here, we have used the fact that x E 0 is false and that false is an identity element for § ). Also, X /). X = {X E E : X E X {I} X E X} = 0. Thus, for the operation �!!,. , 0 is an identity element and every element of t;.J (E) is its own inverse. These remarks show that (t;J (£), �!!,.) is a commutative group. The intersection operation on t;J ( E ) is commutative, associative and has E as an identity element. These facts follow from the corresponding properties of the propositional connective 1\. Moreover, X n ( Y I!!,. Z) = {x E E : X E X 1\ (x E y {/} X E Z ) } ; ( X n f ) �!!,. (X n Z ) = {x E E : (x E X 1\ X E Y ) {/} (x E X 1\ X E Z ) } � these two sets coincide i n view o f the distributivity of 1\ over §. Thus, inter­ section distributes over symmetric difference. We have thereby shown that the structure (t;J (£), �!!,. , n) is a commutative ring with unit. It is also a Boolean algebra since for every X E fiJ (E), we have X n X = X . [t i s immediate to verify that the order relation i n this Boolean algebra is inclusion, that union and intersection correspond to the operations '-J and "', and that the complement of an element is its usual complement in the set-theoretic sense. 3. The fact that properties of the kind considered in this exercise are preserved under isomorphism is banal and it is never a problem to verify this. As an example, we will treat question (a), leaving the others to the reader. (a) Let a E A be an atom of A and let y E B be less than or equal to f (a) in B. As f is an isomorphism, there is a unique element x E A such that y = f (x) and this element, x, is such that 0 < x < a since 0 < f(x) < f(a) (Theorem 2.48). But a i s an atom; hence either x = 0 (and so y = f(x) = 0) or else x = a (and so y = f (x ) = f (a )}. It follows that the only elements less than or equal to f(a) are 0 and f(a). Given that a is non-zero, that 274 SOLUTIONS /(0) == 0 and that f is injective, we can only conclude that f(a) is non-zero and hence that it is an atom of B. Conversely, if we suppose that it is f (a) that is an atom of B, it suffices to apply what we have just done to the isomorphism f - 1 from B into A to 1 convince ourselves that a == f - (f(a ) ) is an atom of A. 4. (a) Let ( A , <, 0, l) be a Boolean algebra. Suppose that it is complete and consider a non-empty subset X of A. Set Y == {x E A : x c E X} and let b denote the greatest lower bound of Y ( Y is obviously a non-empty subset of A). It is very easy to prove that a == be is the least upper bound of X: on the one hand, for every x E X, we have b < x c , hence x < be == a and a is an upper bound for X; on the other hand, if m is an upper bound of X, then me is a lower bound of Y (trivial to verify), hence me < b and a == be < m, which shows that a is the least of the upper bounds of X. When we interchange the words 'upper' and 'lower' and reverse the inequalities in the preceding, we prove that if every non-empty subset of A has a greatest upper bound, then the Boolean algebra is complete. (b) Let A == ( A , < , 0, l) and B == ( B , < , 0, 1 ) be two Boolean algebras and let f be an isomorphism of Boolean algebras from A onto B. We assume that A is complete and will show that the same is true of B. Let B be a non-empty subset of Y and let X denote its preimage under f; X is a non-empty subset of A since f is a bijection. It is very easy to verify that if a is the greatest lower bound of X (which exists, by hypothesis), then f (a) is the greatest lower bound of Y . (c) Let E be a set and let X b e a non-empty subset of fiJ ( E ) . I t is clear that the set G = nzEX Z, the intersection of the elements of X, is the greatest lower bound of X. (d) Let E b e a n infinite set and let H be a n infinite subset of E whose com­ plement in E is infinite. (Concerning the existence of such a set, refer to Chapter 7.) Consider the following subset X of � (E): X == { {x } : x E H } . I f the Boolean algebra of finite o r cofinite subsets of E were complete, X would have a greatest upper bound, M. Then M would have to be a finite or cofinite subset of E that is greater than or equal to (i.e. includes) all the elements of X : so we would have H c M ; this prevents M from being finite so forces it to be cofinite. Since H, by hypothesis, is not cofinite, the preceding inclusion would be strict so we could find an element a E E such that a E M and a fj. H. The set N == M {a} would then be, as is M, a cofi.nite subset of E that would still be an upper bound for X . But in this case, M would not be the least upper bound of X, which is a contradiction. The Boolean algebra under consideration is therefore not complete. - 275 SOLUTIONS FOR C HAPTER 2 (e) To begin with, let us recall that every finite Boolean algebra is complete (property 6 of Theorem 2.29). It fallows that when the set P of propositional variables is finite, then the Boolean algebra :FI � of equivalence classes of logically equivalent formulas (which is then itself fi.nite) is complete. Now suppose that the set P is infinite. Consider two sequences (Pn) n EN and (qn )nEN of pairwise distinct elements of P. We construct two sequences of formulas , ( Fn)nE N and (Gn )nEN� in the following way: Fo = po V qo; F1 = p J V qo V q 1 ; . . . � Fk = pk v qo v q 1 v · G o = qo ; G 1 = · · v qk ; . . . qo v (q 1 /\ Po) ; . . . . . . , G k = qo V (q J /\ Po) V · · · V (qk /\ Po /\ P 1 /\ · · · /\ Pk - ! ) ; For every integer n, we have Gn+l = G n v (qn+l /\ PO /\ P I 1\ · · · /\ Pn ) , hence r-* G n ==> G n+ 1 ; in other words, ci(Gn) < ci(Gn + I ) , relative to the order relation in the Boolean algebra FI '"'"'· This inequality is strict, for we can find an assignment of truth values Dn that satisfies G n + 1 but that does not satisfy Gn ; it suffices to set Dn (qo) = Dn (qi ) = · · · = Dn(qn) = 0 and Dn (Po) = Dn (p t ) = · · · = Dn (Pn) = Dn (qn+I ) = 1 ; the values of Dn on the other propositional variables may be chosen arbitrarily. Let n be an integer and consider an assignment of truth values A such that A ( Fn ) = 0. We then have and, for every integer k > 1, A(qk /\ po /\ P J 1\ · · · /\ Pk- 1 ) = 0. Indeed, if k < n, 'A(qk) = 0; and if k > n, then Pn occurs in the conjunction Po /\ P I /\ · · · /\ Pk 1 which is therefore not satisfied by A. So we see that for every m, 'A(Gm) = 0. We have thus shown, for all integers m and n , that Gm => Fn is a tautology, or, as well, that ci(Gm) < ci(F11) . The inequality is strict since, with what we have just proved, we have ci(Gm ) < ci (G m+ I ) < ci( Fn ) . Suppose that the set {ci(Fn ) : n E N} has a greatest lower bound, c i(F). According to the preceding, we would then have for all integers m and n , ci(Gm) which is to say 1- * Gm => < ci(F) < ci( Fn ) , F and 1-* F => Fn . (t) 276 SOLUTIONS Choose an integer r such that for every integer k > r, neither Pk nor qk occurs in the formula F (this is possible since a formula can involve only finitely many propositional variables). We will now define two assignments of truth values a and f:J that are obtained, respectively, by modifying the value assumed by the assignment or , defined above, at the points Pr and qr : a(pr ) = 0 and a (x ) = or(x) for all variables x other than Pr ; f:J (qr ) = 1 and f:J (x ) = or (x) for all variables x other than qr . Since Pr and qr do not occur in F, we obviously have a (F) = f:J (F ) = or ( F ) . (tt ) On the other hand, it is easy to verify that a ( Fr ) = 0 and f:J (G r) = 1 , which, according to ( t ), requires a ( F) = 0 and {3 (F) = 1 ; but this mani­ festly contradicts (t t). It was therefore absurd to assume the existence of a greatest lower bound for the set {ci (Fn ) : n E N}. So the Boolean algebra under consideration is not complete. (f) We have seen that the B oolean algebra of subsets of a set is atomic and, in question (c) above, that it is complete. We are guaranteed by question (c) of Exercise 3 and by question (b) above that every Boolean algebra that is isomorphic to a Boolean algebra of subsets of some set is necessarily atomic and complete. Now let us consider the converse. We will be motivated by the proof of Theorem 2.50, which can be viewed as a special case of the result to be proved here. Let A = ( A , <, 0, 1 ) be a Boolean algebra that i s atomic and complete. Denote the set of its atoms by E and let cp denote the map from A into tp (E) which, with each element x in A , associates the set of atoms that are less than or equal to it: cp(x) == {a E E : a < x}. Let us show that cp is surjective. Let X be a subset of E. If X is empty, then X = cp (0) (there is no atom below 0). If X is not empty, it has a least upper bound that we will denote by M. Every element of X is an atom that is below M , thus X c cp(M). If b is an atom that does not belong to X, then for every element x in X, we have x < h e (this follows from Theorem 2.40: x is an atom and we do not have x < h since b is also an atom and x < b would mean that either x = h or x E X and b ¢ X). We conclude from this that M < h e and, consequently, that b is not below M (for, since b is non-zero, we cannot have b < h e ). It follows that every atom that is below M is an element of X, i.e. cp(M) c X. To conclude, X == cp(M) and cp is surjective. S O L U T I O N S FOR C H A PT E R 277 2 For all elements x and y of A, i f x < y, then cp(x ) c cp(y) since any atom that is below x is an atom that is below y. For all elements x and y of A, if cp (x) c cp ( y ) , then x < y: indeed, if x is not below y, then x yc # 0 (Lemma 2.3 1 ; since A is atomic, we can then find an atom a E E such that a < xyc , which is to say a < x and a < yc ; but the atom a cannot simultaneously lie below y and y c ; this shows that a E cp(x ) and a tj cp (y), hence cp (x ) � cp(y). Theorem 2.48 permits us to conclude that cp is an isomorphism of Boolean algebras from A onto t;J ( E ) . Thus, every Boolean algebra that is atomic and complete is isomorphic to the Boolean algebra of subsets of some set. Since every finite Boolean algebra is atomic and complete, Theorem 2.50 is a corollary of what we have just proved. 5. Let b be an element of B that is not an atom of the Boolean algebra B. Then either b = 0 and so b is not an atom of A or else we can find an element c E B that is non-zero, distinct from b, and that satisfies c < b; but, since c E A, we have found a non-zero element of A that is strictly below b, which shows that b is not an atom of A. 6. We apply Theorem 2.54. We have 0 E B since 0 < 1 + a ; if x E B , we have either x > a and so x c < l + a, or else x < 1 + a and so x c > a ; so in all cases, x c E B ; finally, if x and y are elements of B and if at least one of these is below 1 + a, then so is their greatest lower bound x ;--.. y; and if this is not the case, then we have x > a and y > a, hence x "' y > a; so in all cases, X "' y E B . Suppose that A is complete and consider a non-empty subset X of B. I n A , X has a greatest lower bound, m. Let us show that m E B ; this will prove that the Boolean sub-algebra that is B is complete. To do this, observe that if at least one of the elements of X is below 1 + a , we have m < 1 + a ; and otherwise, for every element x E X, x > a and so a is below X, hence below m; in all cases, m E B . 7. (a) Set G == nFEZ F. We will verify that G satisfies the three conditions of Theorem 2.68. Let Fo be a filter in the (non-empty) set Z. We have 0 � Fo hence 0 E G. As well, we have 1 E F for every F E Z, hence 1 E G. This verifi.es condition (f). Let x and y be two elements of G ; for every F E Z, we have x E F and y E F, hence x "' y E F; it follows that x "' y E G and that condition (ff) is satisfied. Finally, if x E G, y E A , and x < y, then for every .f E Z, we have x E F, hence y E F ; this shows that y E G and that condition (fff) is satisfied. So the set G is a filter on A. Let a be an element of A that is distinct from 0 and 1 (we assume such an element exists). Consider the principal filters Fa and Ft+a generated by a and 1 -r a , respectively and let Z == { Fa , Ft +a }. The set K == U FEZ F = Fa U Ft +a is certainly not a filter since a E K , 1 + a E K and a (1 + a ) = 0 tj K. "' 278 SOLUTIONS (b) We set H == U FEZ F and once again apply Theorem 2.69. As before, choose a specific filter Fo E Z. We have 1 E Fo hence 1 E H. For every F E Z, we have 0 � F, hence 0 � H . So H satisfies condition (f). Let x and y be elements of A such that x E H and y > x ; there exists a filter F E Z such that x E F, and so y E F; hence y E H. This verifies condition (fff) for H . As we see, the additional hypothesis on Z is not involved in the proofs of these two conditions. We will use it to verify condition (ff): given two elements x and y of H , we have to show that x y E H. There are filters Ft and F2 in the set Z such that x E Ft and y E F2; as Z is totally ordered by inclusion, we have either Ft c F2 or F2 c F1 ; F == F1 U F2 is therefore a filter in Z that contains both x and y; so it contains their greatest lower bound x y. We thus have x y E F and F E Z, from which it follows that x y E U F E z F == H. "' "' "' "" 8. Let E* denote the set of intersections of finitely many elements of E. We can construct E* in the following way: set Eo == E and for every n E N, En+l == {Z E &J (N ) : (3X E E ) (3 Y E En) ( Z == X n Y)}; w e then have E* == u En . n EN Since the set E is countable, we easily show, by induction, that each of the sets En is countable; so their union E* is also countable (a countable union of countable sets). We may refer to Chapter 7 in Volume 2 for details concerning these questions of cardinality. We can therefore produce an enumeration of E * : E* == {Xn : n E N } . Let us now show that the filter generated by E is the set F == {X E <9 (N) : (3n E N)(X :J Xn ) } . We can convince ourselves that F is a filter that includes E by examining the proof of Lemma 2.79 (note that the elements of E * are all non-empty). To continue, suppose that G is a filter that Includes E ; G must contain any element that is a lower bound (i.e. intersection) of finitely many elements of E , as well as any element that is above such an element. The first condition is equivalent to G J E and the second, to G :J F. We have proved that F is a filter that includes E and that it is itself included in any filter that includes E ; accordingly, F is the intersection of all filters that include E or, equivalently, the filter generated by E . Suppose that F is a n ultrafilter. We will distinguish two cases. I n the first, we will show that F is trivial and in the second, we will arrive at a contradiction. S O L U T I O N S FOR C H A PTER 2 279 We will thereby have established the desired property. • If there exists an integer n such that the set Xn is finite, then since X n E F , N - Xn � F, which shows that F does not extend the filter of cofinite subsets of N (the Frechet filter); so F is a trivial ultrafilter (Theorem 2.77). ·• In the case where Xn is infinite for every n E N, we will construct a subset A c N such that neither A nor N - A belongs to F, which shows that F is not an ultrafilter, contrary to our hypothesis. Let us define two sequences (an )nEN and (bn )nEN of natural numbers by induction as follows: ao is the least element of Xo and bo is the least element of Xo -- {ao}; and for every n E N, an+ I is the least element of Xn+ 1 - {ao, a 1 , • • • , an , bo, b 1 , . . . , hn } and bn + l is the least element of Xn+ l - {ao, a 1 , . . . , an , an+ l , bo, h1 , . . . , bn } . The fact that all of the sets Xn are infinite guarantees that this is a valid definition. Set A = {an : n E N} and B = N - A . It i s clear that the set {bn : n E N } i s included in B and that the sets A and B are both infinite. For every integer n, we have which shows that the set Xn is not included in A nor in B . It follows that neither of the sets A nor B = N - A belongs to the filter F. So it is not an ultrafilter. 9. ( a) This property was established in Exercise 20 from Chapter 1 . (b) and (c) Consider the map cp : :FI cp { ( x) = "'----+ { 0. 1 } defined for all x E :FI "' by 1 if 81 ( F ) = 1 for all formulas F E x 0 if 8 1 ( F ) = 0 for all formulas F E x (there are obviously no other cases). We see that cp is nothing more than the assignment of truth values 8 1 'modulo' the relation of logical equivalence "'; it is the map that would be denoted by h01 using the notation from Example 2.57 and it is a homomor­ phism of Boolean algebras from :FI "' into {0, l } . We obviously have J = {x E :FI "' : cp (x ) = 1 } , which proves that J i s an ultrafilter and that cp i s its associated homomor­ phism (Theorem 2.72, ( 1 ') ¢> (3')). 10. (a) Let x be an element of A . To say that H (x) is a singleton is to say that there is a unique homomorphism of Boolean algebras from A into {0, 1 } that assumes the value 1 at x . 280 SOLUTIONS • • Suppose that x is an atom: so we have x # 0 and H (x) is then non­ empty. But if h is an element of H (x ), then for all y E A, we have either that xy == y, which requires h (y) == 1 , or else xy == 0 which requires h (y) == 0 (since h (xy) == h (x)h (y) == h (y )). The value of h (y) is thus determined for any element y E A . There is therefore a unique element in H (x ) : it is a singleton. Now suppose that H (x) is a singleton: it is then necessarily an atom in the Boolean algebra B(S) (since it is an atom in g;y (S) (Exercise 5)). As H is an isomorphism of Boolean algebras, x is an atom of A (Exercise 3a ). Remark: In the first part of the proof, we could have, in similar fashion, observed that H (x) is an atom in B(S); but this would have in no way implied that H (x ) is a singleton, for an atom in B(S) is not necessarily an atom in g;y (S) (Exercise 5). (b) If A contains an atom a, H (a ) is an open (and closed) subset of S that re­ duces to a single point: consequently, S contains at most one isolated point. Conversely, if h is an isolated point in S, then {h} is an open subset of S. As the topology of S is Hausdorff, every singleton is closed. It follows that {h} is clopen, i.e. an element of B(S). As a consequence, there is a (unique) element a E A whose image under the isomorphism H is {h } . According to question (a), a is necessarily an atom. (c) As the clopen sets constitute a basis of open sets for the topological space S, and as every non-empty open set must include at least one open set from a given basis, we see that for a set X c S to meet every non-empty open set (i.e. for it to be dense in S), it is necessary and sufficient that it meet every non-empty clopen set. Let I denote the set of isolated points of S. Suppose that A is atomic. Let Q be a non-empty clopen subset of S. There then exists one and only one element x in A such that H (x) == Q. As Q is not empty, x is not zero; so we can choose an atom a E A that is below x. Then H (a) is included in H (x) since H is order-preserving. But according to (a), H (a) is a singleton and its unique element is an isolated point of S; so Q contains a point from I. This proves that I is dense in S. Conversely, suppose that I is dense in S. For every non-zero element x E A, H (x) is a non-empty clopen subset of S and, in view of this, it contains at least one isolated point, h. But then { h} is the image under H of one (and only one) atom a in A (see the proof of (b)). We have h (a) == {h } c H (x), hence a < x (Theorem 2.48). We have found an atom that is below x , i.e. A is atomic. 11. Suppose first that the Boolean algebra A == ( A , <, 0, 1) is dense. If b is a non­ zero element in A , then, by definition, there is at least one element c E A such that 0 < c < b, which shows that b is not an atom. Conversely, suppose there S O L U T I O N S FOR C H A P TER 28 1 2 are no atoms in A and consider two elements a and b of A such that a < b; then a + b is not zero and is not an atom. So there is an element d E A such that 0 < d < a + b. Set c == a ...__, d. It is immediate to verify that we then have a < c < b; so A is dense. 12. (a) Suppose that (y, z) is a bipartition of x. We then have x=y ...__, z == y + z + yz = y + z + (y r-.. z) :::: y + z . It follows immediately that x + y = z. We have y # x since z # 0 , and y < x since x = y '-' z. As y # 0, we conclude that 0 < y < x. Conversely, if 0 < y < x and z == x + y, then we have y # 0, z # 0 (since y # x ), y '-' Z = y + Z + yz == Y+X+y 1 2 yx + y = X + y + XY = X '-' y = X and finally, y r-.. z = y(x + y) == yx + y2 = y + y = 0. Let a be a non-zero eJement of A . Since a is not an atom, there is an element b E A such that 0 < h < a. From all that has preceded, (b, a + b) is a bipartition of a . (b) We proceed by induction. The choice o f uo and u 1 is explicitly given in the statement of the exercise. Suppose that the element u£0£1 £n - l has been defined in conformity with the imposed conditions (by convention, for the case n = 0, u£0£ 1 . . .£11_ 1 = u0 = 1). Then this element is non-zero and, according to (a), has at least one bipartition. If the condition u £0£ 1 . 1 r-.. an =/= 0 and u£0£1 .. .c:n - 1 r-.. (1 +a) =/= 0 is not satisfied, we choose an arbitrary bipartition of uc:0£1 . . .c:n- l as the pair (u£0c:1 £n_ 1 o , u£0c:1 . . .£n_ 1 I ). I f the condition i s satisfied, then i t is easy to verify that the pair (u£o£ J ...£n - l ''""" an, u£0£ 1 . . . £n- l r-.. (1 + an)) is a bipartition of u c:0£ 1 ... En 1 (c) Let x and £ be as indicated. First, observe that for all natural numbers m and n , if n < m, then u£08 1 ...£m < uc:0£1 . . .£n . It follows that for every integer • . . .. 8"_ •• • • k E N, ( 1 ) if x u£0£1 . . .£" = 0, then for every integer p > k, x uc:0£ 1 ... £p = 0; (2) if x Uc:o£ 1 £" =/= 0� then for every integer q < k, x r-.. u£0£1 £q =/= 0. Let us next prove that at least one of the conditions (i) or (ii) is satisfied: if (i) is not satisfied, we can find an integer k such that x u£0c:1 ... £" == 0; according to ( 1 ), we then have that for every integer p > k , Uc:o£ 1 ... == 0; but U c:0c: 1 . .£p =/= 0, and "' " "' ••• ••• ' '""" c:P . u £Q £ ) . . .£ p = (x it follows that (1 + x) satisfied. r-.. u £Q£ ] . . . £p r-.. u£0£ 1 . • •Ep ) ......__, ((1 + x) ) r-.. u £Q £ f . . . £p ·' # 0, which means that condition (ii) is 282 SOLUTIONS Now let us show that (i) and (ii) cannot be satisfied simultaneously (it is here that thatthecountability of A intervenes). Sincex is one ofthe elements of A , there is an integer k such that x = ak. Three cases are then possible: • ak "" u808 1 ... sk -l = 0; this contradicts condition (i); • (1 + ak) "" u s0s1 sk - t = 0; this contradicts condition (ii); • ak "" Us0s1 . . . sk - l # 0 and (1 + ak ) "" U8081 ... sk -t # 0; in this case, ••• - ak "" u o£Q£ I Bk -l , Us0s1 sk - t 0 "" (1 + ak ) = 0: u£Q£ t ... Bk-1 •.. W · h'ICh 1mp I'IeS ••• and Us0s1 . .. sn_1 I = Us 0s1 £k -l 1 . • • (1 + ak ) "" Usos l ...£k - I , which implies "" ak = 0. Thus, if ek = 0, then u80s1 ... sk0 "" (1 + ak ) = 0 and condition (i) fails. or if ek = 1, then u808 1 8k "" ak = 0 and it is condition (ii) that fails . ••• (d) The condition is sufficient: indeed, we have already noted that if n < m, Us0s1 £m < u8081 £n · It follows that ••• . .• To show that it is necessary, suppose there exists an integer k such that 0 < k < n , e o = �o, . . . , Ek-I = �k - 1 and ek # �k· We then have u 80s1 sk "" u �o�t ---�k = 0, because (u80q . . . sm ' u �0 �1 �k ) is a bipartition of u�0�1 l;k - t . On the other hand, Us0s1 s, < u808 1 sk and u �0�1 . ..�m < u �0�1 �k ; hence U808 1 sn "" u�0�1 --- �m = 0. (e) Let x be an element of A . Question (c) shows that for any sequence f E {0, l}N, we have f E h(x ) or f E h ( 1 + x ) , but never both simultaneously. In other words, h (1 + x) is the complement of h(x) in {0, l}N. For every integer n E N , set . ••. . • .•. •.. •.. . .• .•. {0 , l } N (x "" U f(O) f( l )... f(n) # 0}, and n Vn = { (e o, e l , . . . , en ) E {0, 1 } + l : x "" Us0s1 ... s11 # rn (X) = {.f E : 0} . We then have u {.f E {0, l}N : .f (O) = eo and f ( I ) = E 1 and . . . and f (n) = en } and h(x) = nn EN rn (X ) . So for every n, rn (x) is a finite union of clopen sets from the basis of open sets for the topology on {0, l }N . So it is itself clopen. S O L U T I O N S F O R C H A PT E R 283 2 The set h (x ), an intersection of closed sets, is then closed. But we have seen that the complement of h (x) in {0, l } N is h (l + x ) ; so it too is a closed set. We conclude from this that h (x) is clopen, i.e. is an element of the Boolean algebra B({O, l }N ). Let us prove that h preserves the order and least upper bounds: if x and y are elements of A such that x < y, then for every sequence f E h (x) and for every integer n E N, we have Y "' U f(O)f(I ) .. . f(n ) > X � U /(0)/( l )...f(n) > 0, which shows that f E h (y)� hence h (x) c h (y). It follows that for all elements z and t of A, we have h (z) c h(z '--' t) and h (t) c h (z t), hence '--' h (z ) u h ( t ) c h (z '--' t ) . Conversely, suppose that f i s an element o f h (z '--' t) and that f tj h (z): this means that there exists an integer k such that z r-. u f(O) f( I ).. . f(k) = 0. According to remark ( I ) from (c)� we also have that for every integer p > k� z r-. u f(O)f( I ) ... f( p ) = 0. Now, for every integer n, we have (z r-. u f(O)f( I ) .. . f(n) ) '--' (t "' u f(O)f(l ) ...f(n) ) = (z '--' t) r-. u f(O)f(I ) ... f(n) =I= 0. It follows that tc r-. u f(O)f(I ) . . . f(p ) =I= 0 for all p > k; but remark (2) from (c) shows that this must also be true for the integers p < k. Finally, for every integer n, we have t r-. u f(O)f( l ) ... f(n) =I= 0, i.e. f E h (t ) Thus h (z '--' t) c h (z) U h (t ) which completes the proof that h preserves greatest upper bounds. Fromthe definition ofh , it is immediate thath (O) = 0 and h (l) = {0, l } N . Theorem 2.45 and Remark 2.46 allow us to conclude from the preceding that h is a homomorphism of Boolean algebras from A into B( {0, l }N ). This homomorphism is injective: to see this, it suffices to verify that for every non-zero element a E A , h (a ) is not empty. To accomplish this, we will define by induction a sequence f E {0, l }N as follows: . , / (0) = {� if a "' uo =I= 0 . if a r-. uo = 0 ' and for every n, f(n + 1 ) = {� if a r-. u f(O)f(l )... f(n)O "# 0 if a � u f(O)f(I )...f(n)O = 0 . As a is non-zero, we cannot have a r-. uo = 0 and a r-. u 1 = 0 simulta­ neously (since u 1 == 1 + uo ) ; hence a r-. u f(O) i= 0. 284 SOLUTIONS Suppose (induction hypothesis) that a r--the pair u f(O)f( l ) . .. f(n) =I= 0. Since (UJ(O)J(I) .. . f(n)Q , U f(O)J(l). . .f (n) l ) is a bipartition of u f(O)f( 1 ) f(n) , we can not have a r--- u J(O)f(l). .. f(n)O == 0 and a r--- u f(O)f(l) .. .f (n) 1 == 0. We conclude from this that a r--- a r--- u f(O)f( l) . . . f(n)f(n+ l ) =I= 0. We have thereby proved that f E h (a ) ; hence h (a ) =I= 0. • .. It remains to prove that h is surjective. For every integer n and every (n + I )-tuple (ao, a 1 , . . . , an ) E {0, l} n +I, set r2a0a1 • • . a11 == { .f E {0, l} N : / (0) == ao , f(a) == a 1 , . . . , f (n) == an } , and let us show that h ( ua0a 1 we have Uaoa J ...an r--- a11 ) •.• == �2a0a1 . . _a11 • If f E r2a0a1 UJ(O)f(l) ...f(k) { u aoaJ ...an == U j(O)J(I) ... J(k) .• _a11 and k E N, if k < n . if k > n ' so in both cases, we have a non-zero element of A� which proves that .f belongs to h (u a0a 1 an ) . Conversely, if f E h (ua0a 1 _ _ _a11 ) , we have, in particular, that • • • Uaoa r ...an ----. U j(O)f(l ) . .. f(n) =/= 0; hence, according to question (d), j (O) == ao, .f(a) == a 1 , . . . , and f (n) == an, which shows that f E r2a0a1 ...a11 • It is easy to be convinced that the family constitutes a basis of open sets for the topology of {0, 1 }N. Indeed, in Section 2 . 1 .2, we considered basic open sets of the following form: the set of maps from N into {0, 1 } that assume given values at a given finite num­ ber of points; now such a set is manifestly a (finite) union of sets from the family 0. So let us consider an arbitrary clopen set V E 8({0, t }N). V is a union of sets from the family 0 but, since we are in a compact space, there is a finite number of sets from the family 0 whose union is V. Suppose, for example, that V == G 1 U G2 U · · · U G P where each G; is a set of the form Qa0a1 a11 • Now each set r2a0a 1 a11 is the image under h of the ele­ ment Ua0a1 an . Hence there exist elements h1 , b2 , . . . , hp in A such that and Gp == h (bp ). Since h preserves greatest G 1 == h (h i ) , G2 == h (b2 ) , upper bounds, we may conclude that ••• •.• ••• . V == . q h (b I '-J b2 '-J • • • '-J b p) . It follows that the image of the map h is the whole of 8({0, l}N) . S O L U T I O N S F O R C H A PT E R 285 2 We have thus proved that every countable atomless Boolean algebra is isomorphic to the Boolean algebra of clopen subsets of the space {0, 1 } N (with the discrete topology on {0, l } and the product topology on the space). We may also conclude from this that any Boolean topological space with a countable basis of clopen sets is homeomorphic to the space { 0, 1 }N . This space is often called the Cantor space. It is in fact homeomorphic to the Cantor ternary set (the set of real numbers in the interval [0, 1 ] that are of the form where, for every n , Xn is equal either to 0 or to 2), where this set has the topology induced as a subset of JR. Details concerning this can be found in the text of Kelly which we cited earlier in connection with Tychonoff's theorem. 13. (a) The map G is injective: indeed, if 8 and 'A are two distinct elements of {0, 1 } P , then for at least one propositional variable A, we will have 8 (A) i= 'A (A), hence h8(ci(A)) # hJ.(ci(A)), which implies that h8 =/:. hJ., i.e. g (8) i= g ('A). The map G is surjective onto S(:FI roy): indeed, let h be a homomorphism from :F1 into {0, 1 } ; define 8 : P -7 {0, 1 } by 8 (A ) == h (ci(A)) for any propositional variable A . We will prove that hs == h , in other words, that for every formula F E F, roy 8(F) == h (cl(F)). It suffices, in fact, to prove this for formulas that can be written exclusively with the symbols for connectives --, and 1\ (and the propositional variables !) since we know that every equivalence class contains such a formula. We argue by induction on the height of formulas: • for propositional variables, this is the definition; c • if 8(F) == h (ci(F)), then 8(-,F) == 1 + h (cl(F)) == h ((ci(F)) ) since h is a homomorphism; but -(ci(F))c == ci(--,F), hence 8 ( F) == h (ci(--.F)}; • if 8 ( F ) == h (ci(F)) and 8(G) == h (ci(G)), then -, 8(F A G) == 8(F) == h (ci ( F ) x 8(G) x == h (ci(F)) ci(G)) == x h (ci(G)) h (ci(F A G)). (b) Let T be a subset of F. • Suppose that TI is a filterbase. Then (Lemma 2.8 1 ) there is an ultra­ filter U on :FI � that includes T I �. Let h denote the homomorphism of Boolean algebras from :FI into {0, l } that is associated with this ultrafil­ ter. We then have that h (x) == 1 for every x E T I �. According to (a), we can fi nd a (unique) assignment of truth values 8 on P such thath0 == h. For roy roy 286 SOLUTIONS • every formula F E T, we will have ci(F) E Tl "-', hence h8 (ci(F)) = 1, or in other words, 8(F) = 1. We conclude that T is satisfiable. Conversely, suppose that T is satisfiable and that 8 is an assignment that satisfies it. Then for every formula F E T, we have h8(ci(F)) = 1 , which can also be expressed as: for every element x in TI h8 (x) = 1. It follows that T1 "-' i s included in the set ,..._, , u= {y E F I "-': h 8 ( y) = l}' which is none other than the ultrafilter o n FI "-' associated with the ho­ momorphism h8. So there does exist an ultrafilter that includes T 1 "-', which amounts to saying (Lemma 2.8 1 ) that TI � is a filterbase for the Boolean algebra :FI "-'. (c) We will prove the non-trivial implication in the second version of the com­ pactness theorem. So suppose that T is a contradictory set of formulas from :F. According to (b), T I "-' is not a filterbase, i.e. TI "-' does not have the finite intersection property or, equivalently, there exist (a finite number of) formulas F1 , F2 , . . . , Fk such that the greatest lower bound in TI � of ci(F, ) , ci(F2), . . . , ci(Fk) is 0. Now this greatest lower bound is the equivalence class of the formula It follows that this formula is not satisfied by any assignment of truth values, or again that the set ( Fr , F2 , . . . Fk } is a finite subset of T that is contradictory. 14. (a) Let us verify that the order relation < 8 satisfies the properties listed in Theorem 2.32. • • E B and is obviously the least element; a is the greatest element; if x and y are elements of B , then x < a and y < a, hence x y < a and x y < a, which shows that any two elements of B have a greatest lower bound (a least upper bound, respectively) which is their greatest lower bound (least upper bound� respectively) in .A; since the operations "' and '-./ are the same as in A, they are obviously distributive with respect to one another; for any element x in B , we have a "' xc E B (since a "' xc < a); more­ over, it is immediate that (a "' x c ) '-./ x = a and that (a '"' x c ) '"' x = 0. 0 "' '-./ • • Thus B, with the order relation <, is a Boolean algebra which has the same least element and the same operations "' and '-.-/ as the Boolean algebra .A, but whose greatest element and whose complementation operation are different: the greatest element is a and the complement of an element x E B is a "' xc (where xc is its complement in A). SOLUTIONS FOR CHAPTER 287 2 (b) Consider the map cp from A into B which, with each element x, associates x � a. For all elements x and y in A, we have cp (x � y) = (x � y) � a = (x � a) � (y � a) = cp (x) � cp (y), and cp (xc) = xc � a = (xc � a) '--' (ac '"" a) = (xc '"' ac) "' a = (x � a)c "' a = (qJ(x))c � a. Since (cp(x))c � a is the complement o f cp(x) i n the Boolean algebra (B, <) considered in the previous question, Theorem 2.45 allows us to con-­ clude that cp is a homomorphism of B oolean algebras from A into (B , <). This homomorphism i s surjective since for all y E B, y = cp(y). The kernel of cp i s {x E A : x � a = 0} = { x E A : x < ac}, which i s precisely the ideal / . The Boolean algebra (B , < ) , which is the image of the homomorphism cp, is thus isomorphic to the quotient Boolean algebra A/ I (the isomorphism being the map from B into A/ I that, with each element x in B, associates the set : {y E A : y � a = x} ). 15. (a) Let X be a subset of E distinct from E. We have t;J (X ) = { Y E t;J (E) : Y c X } . Here, we recognize the principal ideal o f A generated by the element X (Example 2.62). Conversely, let I be a subset of t;J (E) that is an ideal of A. Let X denote the union of all the subsets of E that belong to I (I is non-empty since 0 E /): X = U Y. YE l I t i s obvious that I i s included i n t;J ( X ). Since E i s finite, so i s I and hence X is the union, i.e. the least upper bound, of a non-zero finite number of elements of the ideal /, which proves (Corollary 2 .6 1 ) that X belongs to / . As a consequence, every subset of X , i.e. everything below X , also belongs to I (part (iii) of Theorem 2.59). Thus SJ (X) is included in /. As we also have the reverse inclusion, we conclude that I = SJ (X). Note that X can not possibly equal E, for this would mean that l = SJ (E) and I would no longer be an ideal. (b) The kernel I of the homomorphism h is an ideal in the Boolean alge... bra A (Theorem 2.64). According to question (a), there must then ex-­ ist a subset K c E such that I = SJ ( K ). Uniqueness is automatic: i:f I = SJ (K) = SJ (L), then K c L and L c K , so K = L. It is the case that for every element Y in SJ (£), h ( Y ) = 0 if and only if Y c K . 288 SOLUTJONS Given that h is a homomorphism of Boolean algebras, that h ( K ) == 0 and that Z == E - K is the complement of K in the Boolean algebra fYJ (E), we necessarily have h (Z) == 1 . For all subsets V and W of Z, we have h ( V n W ) == h(v) r h ( W ) (this is true for arbitrary subsets of A ) and, on the other hand, h(Z - V) == h ( Z n (E - V)) == 1 � (h (V))c == == h(Z) --. h(E - V ) (h(V))c. Sow e may assert (Theorem 2.46) that the restriction o f h t o f[.J ( Z) is a ho­ momorphism of Boolean algebras from fYJ (Z) into C. The image h (f>J (Z)) of this homomorphism is a Boolean sub-algebra of C (Theorem 2.53) and we obviously have h (f)J (Z)) c h (f)J (E)). Let us now prove the reverse inclusion: for every element y E C, if y E h (f>J (E)), there exists a subset V c E such that y == h ( V ); but V == ( V n K) U ( V n Z), hence y == 16. h ( V n K ) '--' h ( V n Z) == 0 "' h ( V n Z) == h ( V n Z) (since V n K C K); it follows that y E h (f)J (Z)). Moreover, the kernel of h is I == fYJ (K) and, since fYJ (K) n fYJ (Z) == {0}, we see that the homomor­ phism restricted to fYJ (Z) is injective. Finally, the restriction of h to fYJ (Z) is an isomorphism from fYJ (Z) onto h (f)J (E)). (a) Let A == (A, <, 0, 1 } be a finite Boolean algebra and let I be an ideal of A. As 1 is finite and non-empty (0 E I), we can consider the least upper bound a of all the elements of /. By virtue of Corollary 2.6 1 , a belongs to I . Every element of I is obviously below a and every element of A that is below a belongs to I (part (iii) of Theorem 2.59). Thus we have I == {x E A : x < a}, which means that 1 i s the principal ideal generated by a. In 1 5(a) we showed that in the Boolean algebra of subsets o f a finite set, every ideal is principal. But we also know that every finite Boolean algebra is isomorphic to the algebra of subsets of some set (Theorem 2.50) and, as it is easy to verify that the property of being a principal ideal is preserved by isomorphism, we realize that in fact, nothing new has been proved here that is not already included in 15(a). (b) Naturally, we assume that the atoms a; are pairwise distinct. Let qJ denote the map from A into fYJ ({ 1 , 2, . . . , k}) which, with each element x E A, associates the set (/) (X) For every x E == {i E { 1 , 2, . . . , k} : X A we have � a; = ai } . 289 SOLUTIONS FOR CHAPTER 2 But since the a; are atoms, each of the elements x ai is either equal to ai or equal to 0. It follows that x is the least upper bound of the atoms a; for which i E cp(x). This proves that the map cp is a bijection: for every subset J c { 1 , 2, . . . , k }, there exists a unique element x E A (the least upper bound of the atoms aJ such that j E J) that satisfies cp (x) = J. We may then conclude that the Boolean algebra is finite: we can even show with ease that cp is an isomorphism of Boolean algebras from A onto g;; ({ 1 , 2, . . . , k} ). (c) If G were not a filterbase, there would exist a finite number of atoms a 1 , a2, . . . , ak in A such that " which translates as: a 1 ...__, a2 ...__, · · · ...__, ak = 1 (de Morgan). According to question (b), A would then be fi nite, which is contrary to our hypothesis. (d) If U is trivial, then it contains at least one atom a E A (Lemma 2.76); we then have 1 + a E G and 1 + a ¢ U, hence G is not included in U. lf U i5. non-trivial, then it does not contain any atom (Lemma 2.76); in this case, for every x E G, 1 ,- x is an atom; hence 1 + x ¢. U, so x E U (Theorem 2. 72) which shows that G is included in U. In the particular case where A is the Boolean algebra of subsets of ar.. infinite set £, G is the collection of cofinite subsets of E , i.e. the Frechet filter on E. So the result that we have just proved is precisely Theorem 2.77. (e) It follows immediately from question (a) that if A is finite, every filter on A is principal (dual of a principal ideal); in particular, every ultrafilter on A is principal, i.e. is trivial. Now suppose that A is infinite. According to question (c) and the ultrafilter theorem (Theorem 2.80), we can find an ultrafilter that includes G . According to (d), such an ultrafilter must be non-trivial. 17. (a) If we take 1 = 0, then U j E J Ej = 0, hence 0 E B. If X E B and Y E B ! there exist subsets J and K of I such that X = u jE J Ej and y = uk E K Ek . Given that the Ei form a partition of E , then by setting L = J n K , we have X n Y = Ui EL E ; (indeed, E j n Ek = 0 if j '# k and E j n Ek = E,; = Ek if j = k). We conclude from this that X n Y E B . On the other hand, it is clear that the complement of X in E is the set E - X = Uj EI-J E .i, which shows that E - X E B. We may thus conclude, using Theorem 2.54, that B is a Boolean sub-algebra of A . Fix an index i E I and consider an element X in B such that X c E; . We have X = Uj E J Ej for a certain subset J of I . Thus, for every j E J , we have Ej c E; , which requires (since we are in the presence of a partition) that Ej = Ei or Ej = 0. We conclude that X = E; or X = 0, which proves that Ei is an atom of B. .. 290 SOLUTIONS (b) Let U and V be two distinct atoms of C. We have U n V E C and U n V c U , hence either U n V = 0 o r U n V = U . The second possibility i s excluded since, U and V being atoms, we can only have U c V if U = V. It follows that distinct atoms of C are disjoint subsets of E. On the other hand, the least upper bound of the atoms of C (i.e. their union) is the set E. Indeed, in a finite Boolean algebra, every non-zero element is the least upper bound of the set of atoms below it (this follows from the proof of Theorem 2.50 and, in the notation used there, we have that x = Mh(x ) for every non-zero element x of A). We have thereby established that the atoms of C constitute a partition of the set E. (c) To each Boolean sub-algebra of g;y (E), there corresponds the partition of E, studied i n part (b), formed by the atoms o f this sub-algebra. This correspon­ dence is injective: indeed, as we have just recalled, every non-zero element in a finite Boolean algebra is the least upper bound of the atoms below it; thus, if the same set of atoms is associated with two Boolean sub-algebras, these sub-algebras must coincided. This correspondence is also surjective: given a partition of E, we may, as in (a), associate with it a Boolean sub-algebra B of A and we have seen that the elements of the given partition are the atoms of B. These are, by the way, all the atoms of B for if there were others, the atoms of B would no longer constitute a partition of E and (b) would be violated. 18. We have seen (Exercises 3 and 4) that the properties 'is atomic' and 'is com­ plete', as well as their negations, are preserved by isomorphisms of Boolean algebras. As well, we know that every Boolean algebra is isomorphic to a sub­ algebra of a Boolean algebra of subsets of some set (Stone's theorem) and that the Boolean algebra of subsets of a set is atomic and complete (Exercise 4). Finally, we know that there exist Boolean algebras that are not complete and others that are not atomic. These remarks permit us to answer questions (a) and (e): consider a Boolean algebra that is non-atomic (respectively, not com­ plete); it is isomorphic to a Boolean sub-algebra of some Boolean algebra A of subsets of a set; A is a Boolean algebra that is atomic and complete and has at least one sub-algebra, B, that is not atomic (respectively, not complete). The answers to questions (b) and (f) are affirmative: it suffices to consider a finite Boolean algebra. For (b), there are also examples that are infinite (Example 2.55); but for (f). it can be shown that the finite Boolean algebras are the only ones. The answers to questions (c) and (d) are negative: every Boolean algebra has at least one sub-algebra that contains atoms: the sub-algebra consisting of 0 and 1, in which 1 is obvious!y an atom. 19. Preliminary remarks: Given a map .f from a set E into a set F, let us agree to write J- 1 to denote the 'inverse image map' from g;y (F) into g;y (E) (which, with each subset Y of F, associates the set {x E E : .f (x) E Y } ; we reserve the 291 S O L U T I O N S FOR C H A PTER 2 notation .r- 1 to denote the inverse (from F into E) of the map f in the case where f is a bijection). Let us recall some well-known properties of the inverse image map. As opposed to the 'direct image' map, the inverse image map preserves all the Boolean operations on g;; (F) and p (E), which means that for all subsets X and Y of F, we have or in other words, J - 1 is a homomorphism of Boolean algebras from t;.J (F ) into p (E). Moreover, we have the following two equivalences: J- 1 is injective if and only if f is surjective; J- 1 is surjective if and only if f is injective. Proof: If f is surjective and if Y and Z are subsets of F such that f- 1 ( Y ) J 1 (Z), we see easily that Y n lm(j) = Z n lm(j), i.e. Y Z, hence �--1 is injective; if f is not sutjective, and if y E F lm(j), then we have J - l ( { y}) = j- 1 (0), hence J- 1 is not injective; i f f is injective and i f X is a subset of E, then we have X = J - 1 (f(X)) (we have abused notation and written f(X) for the direct image of X under f), hence J- 1 is surjective; fi­ nally, if f is not injective and if x and y are distinct elements of E such that j(x) = f (y), then it is clear that {x } � lm(f- 1 ) and y fJ lm(j - 1 ), hence f - 1 is not surjective). Suppose now that A = (A, +, x , 0, 1) and A' = (A', +, x , 0, 1 ) . As well, let us write HA (respectively, HA' ) to denote the isomorphism of Boolean algebras from A onto B(S(A)) (respectively, from A' onto B(S(A' ))) constructed using Stone's theorem. (a) For every homomorphism cp E H o m (A, A'), let us define <l> (cp) to be the map from S (A') into S(A) which, with each homomorphism h from A' into {0, 1 } , associates the homomorphism h o cp from A into {0, 1 } obtained by composition. Let us prove that <I> ( cp) is a continuous map: We will tnvoke Lemma 2.5, naturally taking the clopen subsets of S(A' ) and S(A) as bases for the open subsets. Let Q be a basic open subset of S (A). There then exists an element a E A such that Q = H A (a) = {h E S(A) : h (a ) = 1}. Thus we have =· -- := - - ' ' ' <l> (cp)- 1 (Q) = {h E S(A ) : ((<l> (cp)) (h )) (a) = 1 } = {h ' E S(A' ) : (h ' o cp)(a ) = 1 } = { h ' E S(A') : h ' (cp(a)) = 1 } = HA' ( cp(a}). So this i s a basic open subset of S(A') . Hence Q (cp) E C0 (S(A' ), S(A)). 292 SOLUTIONS We are now going to define a map \lJ from C0(S(A') , S(A)) into Hom(A, A') and we will then show that it is the inverse of the map ¢. For every map a E C0(S(A')� S(A)), set Observe that because a is continuous, the inverse image of any clopen subset of S(A) is a clopen subset of S (A'); in other words, the restriction of the map a-1 to B(S(A)) assumes its values in B(S( A')); this validates our definition of \IJ (a). Moreover, as we recalled earlier, a - 1 is a homo­ morphism. Consequently, the map \ll (a), which is the composition of three homomorphisms of Boolean algebras (see the diagram below) is indeed an element of Hom(A, A'). A HA I I I I ! - - B(S(A)) - - w(a) - -- -1 0 -----+ ---+ A' i I I I I H-t A' B(S(A')) Let us show that \II o <I> is the identity on Hom(A, A') . For every cp E Hom(A, A'), ('-11 o <I>) (cp) is the map from A into A' which, with each element a E A, associates ((tll o <l>) (cp))(a) = = = = S(A) : h(a) == 1})) H�/ ({g E S(A') : ((¢(cp)) (g))(a) == 1 } ) HA/ ({g E S(A') : (g o cp)(a) == l }) HA/ ( HA' (cp (a))) == cp(a). HA' 1 ( <l> (cp)- 1 ({h E Hence, (\lJ 0 <l>) (cp) = cp. Next, we show that <I> o \II is the identity on C0(S(A'), S(A)). For every continuous map a from S(A') into S(A), (¢ o W)(a) is the map from S(A') into S(A) which, with each element g E S(A'), associates ((¢ o \IJ ) (a))(g) = (<t>(HA,1 o a - 1 o HA )) (g) = g o HA} o a·- I o HA . 293 S O L UT I O N S FOR C H A PTER 3 Now, by definition of HA 'J , we have (for example, see the proof of Theorem 2.92) that for all a E A , g( HA} (a- 1 (H A (a)))) = 1 if and only if g E a - 1 (HA (a)) , which is equivalent in turn to and to (a(g))(a) Consequently, for every a = 1. A, E (let u s not forget that the only possible values are 0 and 1). We conclude that 1 a o HA g o HA' o � = a (g ) , which shows that (<}) o \lJ )(a) = a. We have thus established that ¢ and \IJ are two bijections that are inverses of one another. (b) It amounts to the same thing to prove that for every map a E C0(S(A'), S(A)), is injective (respectively, surjective) i f and only if \lJ (a) is surjective (respectively, injective). Now this is a nearly immediate consequence of the definition of \IJ and the properties of the inverse image map that were discussed in the preliminary remarks. Indeed, we have a \(! (a) = HA' 1 o a -1 o HA . Since HA 'l and HA are both bijections, we also have a-1 = HA o 'lJ (a) o HA,1 • We conclude that \ll (a) is injective (respectively, surjective) if and only if a - 1 is; but we have seen that this happens if and only if a is surjective (respectively, injective). Solutions to the exercises for Chapter 3 1. First we observe that Ft is a consequence of each of the F; , that each of the F; is a consequence of F2, that F4 is a consequence of F3 and that F6 is a consequence of Fs (see Exercise 5(b)). 294 SOLUTIONS Moreover, it is easy to verify that in every structure whose base set is N*, in which the symbol g is interpreted by the 'addition' map, and the symbol f by a sequence u = (un ) nEN* (a map from N* into N*), the following properties will hold: • Ft is satisfied if and only if u is a sequence that assumes some value at least twice (i.e. it is not injective); • F2 is satisfied if and only if u is a constant sequence; • F3 is satisfied if and only if the sequence u is periodic; • F4 is satisfied if and only if each value assumed by the sequence u is assumed infinitely many times; • Fs is satisfied if and only if the sequence u is stationary (i.e. is constant from some point on); • F6 is satisfied if and only if u is a sequence such that for every integer p E N*, there exists an index n E N* for which un == Un+ p· These remarks allow us immediately to answer the questions asked: (a) The six formulas are satisfied since F2 is. (b) Are satisfied: F1 , F3 (the period is 4) and F4; are not satisfied: F2 , Fs, and F6 (there is no integer n for which Un Un+ l ) . (c) Are satisfied: Ft, Fs, and F6; are not satisfied: F2, F3, and F4 (the values 3, 6, 1 1 , and 1 8 are assumed only once; these are, respectively, u 1 , u2, u3, and u4). (d) FJ is satisfied (we have u2 == u4 == 2); the other five formulas are not satisfied: the sequence is neither constant nor periodic nor stationary and it assumes the value 1 only once; finally, if n > I , n , and n + 1 can not have the same smallest prime divisor ( 1 is not a prime number!). 2 . Using the distributive rules for quantifiers (Theorem 3.55) as well as some common tautologies, in particular, == (A => (B ==> C)) <=> ((A 1\ B) => C), we obtain the following formulas H; that are equivalent to the corresponding G; : HI : 3x'v'y (Px ==> Rxy) 1\ 'v'yPy 1\ 'v'y3z-.Ryz; H2 : 'v'x'v'z(Rzx ==> Rxz) ==> 3x'v'yRyz; H3 : 3z'v't Rtz 1\ 'v'y'v'x (Rxy ==> -.Rxy); H4 : 3x('v'y(Py =? Ryx) 1\ 'v'y('v'u(Pu =? Ruy) ==> Rxy)) ; H5 : 'v'x'v'y( ( Px 1\ Py 1\ Rxy 1\ -·Ryx) ==> 3z(-•Rzx A -.Ryz)); H6 : 3u'v'x3y(Rxy A Pu A Py) ==> Vz3x Rzx. We then see that HI is false in any structure in which Vy Py is false, which is obviously the case for the three structures under consideration. We also see S O L U T I O N S F O R C H A PT E R 3 295 that H3, which is equivalent to 3zYt Rtz A Yy\lx--, Rxy, is contradictory. Finally, we observe that H6, which is further equivalent to (3uPu A Yx3y(Rxy 1\ Py)) ::::} Yz3x Rzx , is clearly a universally valid formula. It follows from these remarks that in the three structures under consideration, G 1 and G3 are false and G6 is satisfied. As for G2, G 4, and G s , we must examine each structure separately. (a) The formula 3xYy Rxy is satisfied (0 is the least element for <), hence H2 is satisfied. If H4 were satisfied, then the formula 3xYy(P y =} Ryx) would also be satisfied and there would exist an integer that is an upper bound for all the even integers, which is absurd; thus H4 is false. As for Hs , it is satisfied: if m and n are even integers such that m < n, then we can find an integer p (for example, one half the sum of m and n ) such that m < p and p < n. Conclusion: G2, Gs, and G6 are satisfied while G 1 , G3, and G 4 are not. (b) The formula H2 is satisfied for reasons that are analogous to those for case (a): the empty set is the least element for the relation c. The formula H4 is satisfied: it suffices to take x to be the set N; indeed, N contains all its finite subsets and any subset of N that contains all the finite subsets of N is the whole of N. The formula Hs is also satisfied: if X and Y are finite subsets of N such that X � Y (strict inclusion), then by choosing an integer n that is not in Y (which is always possible), the subset {n} of N is not included in X and does not include Y (note that Y can not be empty). Conclusion: G2, G4, Gs, and G 6 are satisfied while G 1 and G3 are not. (c) The formula H2 is satisfied: indeed, the interpretation of the symbol R is not symmetric, so the formula YxYz(Rzx ::::} Rxz) is false. If H4 were satisfied, then the formula 3xYy(Py ::::} Ryx) would also be satisfied, so there would exist a real number that would equal the square of al1 rational numbers, which is absurd; so H4 is false. The formula Hs is satisfied: if 2 2 x and y are two rational numbers such that y = x and x =!= y , then it suffices to take z = x and we will have x =!= z2 and z =!= x2 . Conclusion: G2, Gs, and G6 are satisfied while G 1 , G3, and G4 are not. 3. (a) We may take � F = Yxfx gx G = Yx(3y x H = 3x3y(fx A Yx'Vyfx � fy; � fy ==} 3z x � gz); � gy A YzYt (fz � gt ::::} fz � fx)). 296 SOLUTIONS We could just as well have taken the formulas F2 and F3 from (b) in place of F and G respectively. (b) For every £-structure M = (M, f, g ) , we have: o M I= Ft if and only if f = g ; o M I= F2 if and only if f = g and f is a constant map; o M I= F3 if and only if lm (f) c lm(g ); o M I= F4 i f and only i f lm(g) c lm(f) and g is constant; o M I= Fs if and only if lm(f) n lm(g) is a non-empty set. Based on these remarks, it is easy to produce the desired models. In each case, the underJying set is N and we will simply give the interpretations f and g of f and g : for a model o f F t 1\ -. F2 : for a model of F2 : for a model of --. FI 1\ F3 : for a model of F1 1\ F4 : for a model of --. F3 1\ -.F4 1\ F5 for a model of --. Fs : f =g = n � n + 1; f = g = n �--;- 0; f = n t---7 1 and g = n --. : 4. For G, we may take the formula •� n + 1; f = n � n + 1 and g = n � 1 ; f == n t---7 2n and g = n � n 2 ; f = n t---7 2n and g = n � 2n + 1 . Set H = 3 !vo3 ! v 1 F and K = 3 ! v l 3 ! vo F. If the language L has a single binary relation symbol R and if F is the formula Rvov t , then the L-structure {N, < ) is a model of K but it is not a model of H nor of G. Indeed, the following properties hold: {a E N : { N : vo � a) I= 3! v 1 R vo vI } = C1 (no integer has a unique upper bound); {b E N : {N : VI ----+ b) F= 3!voRvovd = {0}; is the only natural number that has a unique lower bound (which is, of course, 0)). So it is true that there is a unique natural number that has a unique lower bound, but it is false that there exists a unique natural number that has a unique upper bound. Since it is obviously false that there exists a unique pair (a, b) E N2 such that a < b, we have here a mode) of K, of _, H and of _, G. We obtain a model of H and --.K by considering the structure {N, > ) . This shows that the formulas G , H, and K are pairwise inequivalent. (0 297 S O L U T I O N S F O R C H A PT E R 3 5. (a) The answer is negative: in the language whose only symbol is the one for equality, consider the formula A [x , y] = ....,x � y � it is clear that in any structure that has at least two elements, the formula V'x3yA[x, y] is satisfied but the formula 3yVx A [x , y] is not. (b) This time the answer is positive: let M = (M, . . . ) be an L-structure that satisfies the formula 3yVx A [x, y] and consider an element a belonging to M such that (M : y � a ) F= VxA [x , y]; then for every b in M, we have (M : y � a, x � b) F= A [x , y], hence (M : x � b ) F= :3y A [x , y ] , which shows that M F= Vx3yA[x , y]. This result is already included, by the way, in part (9) of Theorem 3.55. (c) 1 t suffices to apply part ( 4) of Theorem 3.55 twice. (d) Subject to a change of bound variables, question (c) shows that the formula VuVv(A[u, v] ::::} B[u, v]) ::::> 3x3y(A[x , y] ::::} C[x, y]) is equivalent to 3x3y((A[x , y] ::::} B [x , y]) ==} ( A [x , y] ::::} C [x , y])). Applying (c) a second time, we see that if we set G = ( A [X ' y] ::::} A [y' X]) ::::} ( (A [x , y] 6. => B [x , y]) ::::} ( A [x , y] ::::} C[x, y])), then F is equivalent to 3x3yG. , Xm , Z 1 , Z 2, . . . , z p] be , Xm , y 1 , Y2, , yn ] and G [x 1 , X2 , Let F [x 1 , X2 , two formulas in a language L that are universally equivalent. This means that for every L-structure M = (M, . . . ) and for all elements a 1 , a2, . . . , am , bt , b2 , . . . , bn , C J , c2, . . . , Cp belonging to M, we have . if and only if • . . . • . . • (* ) 298 S OL U 1 I O N S We need to prove that the formulas Fo == 'Vx 1 'Vxz . . . 'Vxm 'VYI 'VYz . . . 'Vyn F and Go == 'Vx 1 'Vx2 . . . 'Vxm'VZJ 'Vz2 . . . 'VzpG are universally equivalent. To do this, consider a model M == (M, . . . ) of Fo and arbitrary elements a 1 , a2, . . . , am , C J , c2, . . . , cp of M. By choosing arbitrary elements b 1 , b2, . . . , bn in M , we have M F F [a J , a2, . . . , am , b1 , b2 , . . . , bn ] since M is a model of Fo ; thus, by (*), M F= G[a i , a2, . . . , am , CJ , c2, . . . , cp], which shows that M is a model of Go. In the same way, we show that any model of Go is a model of Fo, which proves the desired result. 7. (a) For every i between 1 and 6, we provide a formula Gi that answers the question; we leave the verifications to the reader. G1 == 3x'VyRxy; G2 == 'Vx'Vy((Rxy 1\ ..,x � y) G3 == 3x ··x * x � x; =} 3z(Rxz 1\ Rzy 1\ -,z � x 1\ ..., � y)); G 4 == 'Vx (x * x � c =} x � c); * x � d tB d; Gs == 3x x G6 == 'Vx'Vy'Vz(Rxy v Ryz v Rxz). (b) The formula F1 (where the language is { c , ffi, *}) is satisfied in the structure (�, 0, +, x ) (in IR, every polynomial of degree 1 has a root); ··FI is satisfied in the structure (Z, 0, +, x) (the polynomial 2X + 1 , for example, does not have a root in Z). The formula F2 (in the same language) is satisfied in the structure (<C, 0, +, x ) (in <C, every polynomial of degree 2 has a root); -.F2 is satis­ fied in (IR, 0, +, x ) (the polynomial X 2 + I , for example, does not have a root in IR). The formula F3, which expresses (in the language { R }) that the interpre­ tation of R is an equivalence relation, is satisfied in the structure (Z, =2) while ..., p3 is satisfied i n the structure (Z, < ) (the relation < on Z is not symmetric). The formula F4 (in the language { * ' R}) is satisfied in the structure (N, x , < ) , while -, p4 is satisfied in (Z, x , <) (the usual order relation is compatible with multiplication in N but not in Z). The formula Fs, which is equivalent to 'Vx\Jy-,(Rxy A Ryx ) , is satisfied in the structure (Z, <) (strict order) while its negation is satisfied in the structure ( Z, < ) . 8 . (a) F1 i s satisfied by an integer n E M i f and only i f n has n o other divisor than itself, i.e. if and only if n is prime. F2 is satisfied by an integer n if and only if any two divisors of n are comparable for the relation 'divides ' . Now any number that is a power of S O L U T I O N S FOR C H A P TE R 3 299 a prime has this property: indeed, if n = pk , and if r and s divide n, then there are integers i and j less than or equal to k such that r = p i and s = pl and it is clear that either r divides s or s divides r . On the other hand, an element of M that is not a power of a prime has at least two distinct prime divisors (note that I is not in M), neither of which divides the other. So such an element does not satisfy F2. Thus, the integers in M that satisfy F2 are precisely the powers of primes. If an integer n E M satisfies F3 ., it also satisfies the following consequence of F3 (obtained by letting y equal z in F3 and invoking a well-known tautology): 'Vy ((Ryx 1\ Ryy) � Rxy). So every divisor of n must equal a multiple ofn, which amounts to saying that every divisor of n must equal n, as for Fr . It follows that a number that is not prime does not satisfy F3. On the other hand, if n is a prime number, if r divides n and if s divides r and if n, r, and s are in M, then r == s == n, hence n divides s ; so we see that n satisfies F3 . Thus, the elements of M that satisfy F3 are precisely the prime numbers. By 'distributing' the quantifiers according to the usual rules, we easily see that f4 is universally equivalent to the following formula: 'Vt (Rtx � 3y3z(Ryt 1\ Rzy 1\ -, Rtz)). But it is easy to verify that the formula 3y3z ( Ryt 1\ Rzy 1\ -, Rtz) is also equivalent to -,"f/y'Vz(Ryt � ( Rzy � Rtz)). Now this last formula is none other than equivalent to _, F3rtx . So the formula f4 is In this way, we see that for an element n E M to satisfy F4, it is necessary and sufficient that no divisor of n satisfy F3, which amounts to saying that the elements of M that satisfy F4 are those that have no prime divisors. But in M, every integer has at least one prime divisor. Hence the set in question is the empty set. (b) For G, we may take the following formula: Rtx 1\ Rty 1\ Rtz 1\ ( (Rux 1\ Ruy 1\ Ruz) � Rut), which is satisfied by a quadruple (a, b, c, d) from M i f and only if d is a common divisor of a , b, and c and every common divisor of a , b, and c is a divisor of d. 300 SOLUTIONS (c) ( 1 ) We change the names of the bound variables in H and then 'bring them to the front' by applying the usual rules. In this way, we obtain, in succession, the following formulas that are equivalent to H, with the last formula in prenex form: VxVyVz( (3 v(Rvx 1\ Rvy) 1\ 3w(Rwy 1\ Rwz)) =} 3tVu (Rut =} (Rux VxVyVz(3v3w((Rvx A A Ruz)) ) ; R vy) A (Rwy 1\ Rwz)) =} 3tVu (Rut =} (Rux 1\ Ruz))); VxVyVzVvVw3tVu ( ((Rvx 1\ Rvy) 1\ (Rwy 1\ Rwz)) =} (Rut =} ( Rux A Ruz))) . (2) Consider the following sub-formula of H : 3tVu (Rut =} (Rux A Ruz)). It is satisfied in M when the variables x and z are interpreted respectively by a and c if and only if there exists an integer d E M all of whose divisors (in M) divide a and c ; this amounts to saying that a and c have at least one common divisor in M, or again that a and c are not relatively prime. The interpretation of H in M is then clear: H is satisfied in M if and only if for all integers a, b, and c greater than or equal to 2, if a and b are not relatively prime and if b and c are not relatively prime, then a and c are not relatively prime. Now this is manifestly false: (a , b, c) == (2, 6, 3) is a counterexample. (3) We obtain a model of H by taking N as the underlying set and interpreting R by the equality relation in N; it is immediate to verify this. 9. (a) Let Q I , /1 , and R1 denote the respective interpretations of Q, /, and R in the structure M. First, observe that the infinite subsets of N all have the same cardinality (they are all in one-to-one correspondence with N). The formula F1 is not satisfied in M since we have 0 c 0 and card(0) == card(0 - 0); so M � 3x Rxx. Note that for every non-empty subset X of N, we have (X, X) tt. R1 since card( X) > 0 while card(X - X) == 0. As the elements of n1 are infinite, hence non-empty, we see that M F= F2. Suppose that X and Y are two elements of n 1 and that Z is a subset of N such that X c Z c Y ; then Z is infinite (since it includes the infinite set X ) and N - Z is infinite (since it includes the infinite set N - Y); hence Z E Q 1 , which proves that M F= F3 . Let X, Y , and Z be three elements of n 1 such that (X, Y) E R t and ( Y, Z) E R t ; then we have X c Y c Z and the sets Y - X and Z - Y are infinite; thus Z - X is infinite since Z - X == (Z - Y) U (Y - X); it follows that (X� Z) E Rt and that M F F4. For all subsets X and Y of N, we can not have both (X, Y ) E R 1 and ( Y, X) E R 1 unless X == Y == 0; as 0 tt n 1 , we conclude that M I= Fs. Let 2N denote the set of even natural numbers; we have 2N E n 1 and (2N, N) E R1 but N tt n 1 , hence M � F6. For all subsets X and Y of N such that X E n , and ( Y, X) E Rt , Y is a subset of X that must be SOLUTIONS FOR CHAPTER 3 301 infinite (otherwise X - Y would be finite and (X - Y) U Y = X would be as well); moreover, N - Y , which includes N - X , must also be infinite; hence Y E Q 1 and M I= F1 . If X is a finite subset of N whose cardinality is odd, then there is no partition of X into two sets whose cardinalities are equal; then no subset Y of N can satisfy ( Y, X) E R 1 ; so M � Fg. In contrast, if X is an element of Q l , then we can fi nd, on the one hand, a partition of X into two infinite sets Y and Y' and, on the other hand, a partition of N - X into two infinite subsets Z 1 and Z2 ; by setting Z = X U Z 1 , we see that Y and Z belong to Q 1 and that ( Y, X) E R1 and that (X, Z) E R 1 ; it follows that M t= Fg . Let X and Y be two elements of QI such that (X, Y) E R1 ; then the set Y - X is infinite (for it is equipotent to X); so we can then partition it into two infinite subsets X 1 and X2 ; set Z = X U X 1 ; we then have X c Z c Y and the sets X, Z - X = X 1 , Y - Z = X2 , and N - Z are all infinite, which proves that (X, Z) � R 1 , (Z, Y ) E R 1 , and Z E Q I ; it follows that M t= FI O· (b) Let D 1 be a subset of 8J (N) and let M' be the enrichment of the structure M obtained by interpreting the symbol D by the set D I · For the four formulas under consideration to be satisfied in M ' , it is necessary and sufficient that D1 be non-empty (formula G4) and that the inclusion relation restricted to D1 be a total ordering (formula G 1 ) that is dense (i.e. for all subsets X and Y in D 1 , if X � Y, then there exists a subset Z E D1 such that X � Z � Y) (formula G 2 ) and that has no least or greatest element (formula G3). We will now construct a subset D 1 of tp ( N ) that has these properties. First, we define a subset E 1 of g;y (Q) that has these same properties: this is not difficult; it suffices, for example, to set Jr = r -r, r] n Q for each rational r > 0 and to then set £1 = { lr : r E Q� }; we have £1 =I= 0 and the inclusion relation on E 1 is a dense total ordering (if 0 < r < s, and if r t = !s , then Jr � lt � ls) with no least nor greatest element. We then convert from g;; (Q) to g;; (N): choose a bijection cp from Q onto N (one does exist; see Chapter 7); cp induces a bijection ¢ from g;J (Q) onto g;y (N) (for every X E g;y (Q), ¢(X) = {qJ(x) : x E X } ) that is an isomorphism between the ordered structures (g;y (Q), C) and (g;y (N), C ) (the verification i s immediate). I t follows that the subset D 1 = ¢ (E t ) o f N answers the question. 10. (a) In the examples that we are about to give, 0 and 1 are constant symbols, f is a unary function symbol, g , +, and � are binary function symbols, U and V are unary relation symbols, and R is a binary relation symbol. To show that the set X c N is the spectrum of a formula F, we must show, on the one hand, that the cardinality of every fi nite model of F is an element of X and, on the other hand, that for every element n in X, there exists a model of F whose cardinality is n. There is a tendency to omit this second condition, which is, however, indispensable. ( 1 ) L = { f } ; F = VxVy(fx ::::: fy =} x � y) 1\ 3xVy-.x ::::: fy. 302 SOLUTIONS (The existence of an injective map from the base set into itself that is not surjective is possible only if this set if infinite; so F does not have any finite models). (2) Impossible. The base set of any structure is non-empty, hence 0 can not belong to the spectrum of any first order formula. (3) L reduces to the equality symbol; F = Yx x � x. (4) L = {f}; F = Yx(ffx � x 1\ -,jx � x). (Let (M, cp) be a finite model o f F. Then cp i s an involution (i.e. cp o cp is the identity map) from M onto M that has no fixed points. The binary relation � defined on M by a � b if and only if cp(a) = b or cp(b) = a is an equivalence relation whose equivalence classes each contain ex­ actly two elements. As the classes constitute a partition of M, we see that the cardinality of M is an even number. Conversely, for a non-zero even number n = 2 p, we obtain a model of F of cardinality n by taking { 1 , 2, . . , n } as the base set and by taking the interpretation of f to be the map k � k + p if I < k < p ; k � k - p if p + I < k < n . . ( 5) L = { U, G } ; F is the conjunction of the formulas G = Yx3y3z(Uy 1\ Uz l\ X � gyz) and H = Yx\:ly\:lz\:lt ((Ux Uy 1\ Uz 1\ Ut 1\ gxy � gzt) =} (X � Z I\ y � t)). /\ (Let (M, Uo, go) be a finite model of F. Then the restriction of go to Uo x Uo is a bijection from Uo x Uq onto M; thus the cardinality of M is that of Uo x Uo, which is a perfect square. Conversely, for every integer n > I , if n is a perfect square, for example n = p2 , it is easy to verify that the formula F is satisfied in the L-structure (M, Uo, go), where M = {0, 1 , 2., . . , n - 1 } , Uo = {0, 1 , 2, . . . , p - 1 } and go is the map from M x M into M which, with each pair (a, b), associates ap + b if a and b both belong to Uo and 0 otherwise.) (6) L = {�}; F is the formula . 3x3y3z(-,x (7) L (8) L = = � y 1\ -,Y � z 1\ _,x � z 1\ Yt(t � x v t "' t v t � z)). {�}; F = 3x3y3z3t\:lu(u x v u � y v u z v u {�}; F = 3vo3vi . . . 3vk 1\o < i<j <k _,v; � Vj · � � '"'v t). SOLUTIONS FOR CHAPTER 3 (9) L = 303 { U, V, g } ; we set A = VxVy x � y; B = Vx3y3z(Uy 1\ Vz 1\ x � gyz); C = VxVy'VzVt ( (Ux 1\ Vy 1\ Uz 1\ Vt 1\ gxy � gzt) ::::} (x � z 1\ y � t ) ) ; D = 3x3y(Ux 1\ U y 1\ -.x � y) 1\ 3z3t (Vz 1\ Vt 1\ -·z � t ) ; and we take F == (A v ( B 1\ C 1\ D)). (The inspiration comes from (5)). Given a finite model (M, Uo , Vo , go) of F, either M is a singleton or else Uo and Vo each have at least two elements and the restriction of go to Uo x Vo is a bijection from Uo x Vo onto M. Thus the cardinality of M is either equal to 1 or else is the product of two integers that are both greater than or equal to 2, i.e. it is, in all cases, not a prime number. Conversely, for every non-zero integer n that is not prime, it is easy to construct a model of F that has n elements). (10) L = {0,1,+,�, R } (the language of fields, together with a binary rela­ tion symbol). Let I denote the conjunction of the axioms for a commu­ tative field together with formulas expressing that the interpretation of R is a total order relation; let J be the following formula: 'VxROx 1\ 'Vx (3y(Rxy 1\ -.x � y) ::::} Rx+ l t ))). ===> (Rxx+l 1\ 'Vt ( (Rxt 1\ --,x � t ) We then set F = I 1\ J. (Let (K, 0, 1, +, x , <} be a finite model of F; K is then a finite field with an order relation < for which 0 is the least element and in which every element a that has a strict upper bound has a least strict upper bound (a successor), namely a + 1. Let us agree to denote the strict order associated with < by < . Recall that the characteristic of K is the least integer m > 0 such that m 1 = 0 (m1 denotes the element 1 + 1 + · · · + 1, with m occurrences of 1) and it is easy to show that this characteristic is always a prime number, which we will here denote by p. The satisfaction of the formula J shows that we have (if, for every integer j , we denote the element j 1 by j) 0 < 1 < 2 < · · · < p- l , (so the cardinality of K is at least equal to p ) and that for every integer k with 0 < k < p 2, there is no element of K that is strictly between - 304 SOLUTIONS K and k + 1. Since the order is total and since 0 is the least element, any element of K other than 0, 1, . . . , p - 1 must be strictly greater than p - 1 . I t follows that if the cardinality of K i s strictly greater than p, we can find an element b in K for which p - 1 < b; p - 1 then has a strict upper bound hence, according to formula J, it is strictly less than p - 1 + 1 == p == 0 since p is the characteristic of K . We would then have 0 < p - 1 and p - 1 < 0, and hence 0 < 0 by transitivity, which is absurd. So the cardinality of K is equal to p (and K is isomorphic to the field 7l/ p?l). Thus the cardinality of any finite model of F is a prime number. Conversely, for every prime number p, if we let < denote the total ordering on 7lf p?l defi ned by: 0 < 1 < · · · < p - 1 (here, k is the equivalence class of k modulo p ), then the structure (7l/p?l, 0, 1 , +, x , <) is a model o f F of cardinality p. The verification i s immediate.) (b) Let G be a closed formula, in an arbitrary language, whose spectrum is infinite. For every integer k > 1 , let Fk denote the formula 3vo 3v 1 • • • 3vk (\ O<i < j<k ....., Vi � v.i that was previously used in part (8) of (a). Let T be the theory { G} U { Fk : k E N* } . Given a n arbitrary integer n , G has at least one model whose cardinality is greater than or equal to n + 1 since the spectrum of G is infinite. Such a model is also a model of { G } U { F1 , F2 , . . . , Fn } . This shows that every finite subset of T has a model. By the compactness theorem, T also has a model. But a model of T is nothing other than an infinite model of G . 1 1 . Let T be a non-contradictory theory i n a language L such that all its mod­ els are isomorphic. All the models of T are then elementarily equivalent (Proposition 3 .74); this means that T is complete (Definition 3.8 1 ). 12. (a) Let M denote the base set of M. RecaJl the three conditions that are nec­ essary and sufficient for a subset C to be the base set of a sub-structure of M : ( 1 ) C is non-empty; (2) C contains the interpretations in M of the constant symbols of L; ( 3) C i s closed under the functions that are the interpretations in M o f the function symbols of L. It is clear that the intersection of all the subsets o f M that satisfy these conditions and that include A will be a set that again includes A (so is non-empty since we assumed that A is non-empty) and satisfies conditions SOLUTIONS FOR CHAPTER 3 305 (2) and (3) above. It is therefore the base set of some sub-structure of M that includes A . It is the base set of the desired structure A. The uniqueness of A is clear: if a sub-structure B has the indicated prop­ erties, then each of the structures A and B is a sub-structure of the other, hence A = B. (h) If the language consists of the single binary relation symbol R, there is no sub-structure generated by 0 in the structure (IR, < ) : indeed, the two substructures ( {0}, <) and ( { 1 } , <) can not have a common sub-structure, so property (2) must fail. In fact, whenever the language does not contain any symbols for functions or for constants, then there can not be a sub­ structure generated by the empty set in any structure whose underlying set contains at least two distinct elements. However, in ( {0}, <) for exam­ ple, there is a sub-structure generated by the empty set: it is the structure itself! If the language has at least one constant symbol, then in any structure, the empty set generates the same sub-structure as that generated by the set of interpretations of the constant symbols (which in this case is non­ empty). For example, if the language is {c, f} (one constant symbol and one unary function symbol), then in the structure (N, 0, n � n -r- 1 ) , 0 generates the entire structure whereas in the structure (N, 0, n � n ) , 0 generates the sub-structure ({0}, 0 , n � n + 1 ) . Let us give another ex­ ample, without constant symbols, but with a unary function symbol f . Consider a structure M in which f i s interpreted by the constant function equal to a . In M, there is a sub-structure generated by the empty set: it is ( { a } , identity). (c) Let C be the set of interpretations in M o f the constant symbols o f the language. If A U C is not empty, the substructure A generated by A has A U C as its base set; the interpretations of the constant symbols are the same as in M and the interpretation in A of each relation symbol is the restriction to A U C. In the case where A = C = 0, the examples given in (b) show that nothing can be said in general. (d) If F is satisfied in M, then F is satisfied in every sub-structure of M (Theorem 3.70), in particular, in every sub-structure of finite type. Conversely, suppose that F is not satisfied in M . • • If F has no quantifiers, then F is not satisfied in any sub-structure of M (Theorem 3.69; note that F is closed). Let a be an arbitrary element of M. The sub-structure of M generated by {a } is then a sub-structure of M of finite type in which F is not satisfied. If F =: 'Vx t 'Vxz . . . 'Vxn G [xi , Xz , . . . , xn ] (where G has no quantifiers and n > I ), then we can find elements a 1 , az , . . . , an in M such that M � G [a 1 , az, . . . , an ]. Let A denote the sub-structure (of finite type) of M generated by {a1 , a2 , . . . , an } . We have A � G [a1 , a2, . . . , an ] 306 S OLUTIONS (Theorem 3.69). It follows that so we have a sub-structure of M of finite type in which F is not satisfied. (e) Let L be the language consisting of the equality symbol and let F be the formula 3x3y --,x � y ; F is satisfied in the structure (N) but is not satisfi.ed in the sub-structure ( { 0}) generated by { 0}. 13. (a) We argue b y induction o n t. • • I f t i s of height 0, it i s either a constant symbol c or a variable x. So one of the the formulas t � c or t � x is universally valid and, a fortiori, a consequence of T. I f t = f u , the induction hypothesis presents us with four possibilities concerning the term u : * * * * • T F=* u � c; then T F= * t � fc; or T I=* fc � Jjgc(H3), T F=* ffgc � fgc (formula Ht ) and T I=* fgc � c; it follows that T I=* t � c; there exists a variable x such that T F'* u � x; then T I=* t � fx; there is a variable x such that T I=* u � fx; then T I=* t � fix; we may then conclude (formula HI ) that: T I=* t � fx; there is a variable x such that T �* u � gx; then T �* t � fgx; it then follows (formula H3 ) that: T F=* t � c. For the case where t = g u, the argument is analogous. (b) Let f and g denote, respectively, the maps (a, b) r-+ (a, bo) and (a, b) (ao, b) from A x B into A x B . For all pairs (a, b) E A x B , we have r-+ f(f(a , b)) = f(a, bo) = (a , bo) = f(a, b); g (g (a , b)) = g (ao , b) = (ao, b) = g (a, b); f (g(a , b)) = f (ao , b) = (ao , bo) = g (a , b o) = g ( f (a , b)) ; this shows thatthe formulas Ht, l/2 , and H3 aresatisfied in M ( A , B , ao, bo). Let (a, b) and (a', b') b e two elements of A x B. If f(a, b ) = f (a', b'), then a = a'; and if g(a, b) = g (a', b'), then b = b', which proves the satisfaction of H4. Moreover, if f(a, b) = (a, b) and if g (a', b') = (ab'), then b = bo and a' = ao; in these circumstances, we have f (a , b') = (a , b) and g(a, b') = (a', b') ; we have thus found an element whose image under f is (a, b) and whose image under g is (a', b') ; thus Hs is satisfied in M (A , B , ao, bo). (c) Let M = ( M, a, cp, 1/1) be an arbitrary model ofT . In the fi.rst case under (a), we have already seen that M t= H6 and we prove in an analogous fashion that M F= H1. For every element x E M, if cp (x) = x , then l/f (x) = 1/J (cp(x)) = a (according to H3); conversely, if 1/f (x) = a, then 1/J (cp (x)) = a (according SOLUTIONS FOR CHAPTER 3 307 to H3); since we also have q? (q?(x ) ) = q? (x) (according to Ht), the elements q? (x) and x have the same image under q? and the same image under 1/J; it follows (according to H4) that q? (x) = x. So we see that M �= Hs. The proof that M I= Hg is analogous. Let us show that M I= H 10 · The implication from left to right is evident (take v 1 equal to vo). Let x be any element of M. If there exists an element y in M such that x = q?(y)� then q? (x ) = q?(q?(y)) = q?(y) (according to Ht ), so q? (x ) = x. The proof for H1 1 is analogous. To show that M I= H 1 2 , we first note that the implication from right to left follows immediately from H6 and H1 . In the other direction, let x be an element of M such that q? (x ) = x and 1/r (x) = x; we then have 1/r (x) = a and cp (x) = a according to H8 and Hg; hence x = a . It is immediate to verify that H13 is satisfied i n M : i fx and y are elements of M such that q? (x) = 1/J (y), then q? (q?(x)) = q? ( 1j; (y)), hence (according to H1 and H3) q? (x) = a. (d) Let f and g b e the respective interpretations of f and g i n M ( A , B , ao, bo) and let Jand g be their interpretations in M ( C, D, co, do). We may choose a bijection A (respectively, J.L) from A onto C (respectively, from B onto D) such that "A (ao) = co (respectively, tt (bo) = do). The map y from A x B into C x D which, with each pair (x , y ), associates the pair ( "A (x ), J.L(Y)) is an iso­ morphism between the structures M ( A , B, ao, bo) and M ( C, D, co, do) : indeed, y i s first of all a bijection from A x B onto C x D ; also, w e have y (ao, bo) = (co, do) and'! for an pairs (a . b) E A X B . y (f(a, b )) = y (a, bo) = ("A (ao), do) = f ("A(a), tt (b)) = f ( y (a , b)), and, analogously, y (g(a , b)) = g( y (a, b) ) . (e) We begin by observing that a E A and a E B ( H6 and H7 ) ; so the structure M ( A , B , ao, bo) is well defined (we will continue to denote the interpretations of f and g in this structure by f and g). Let h denote the map from M into M x M which, with each element x in M, associates the pair ( cp(x ) , 1/J (x)). The satisfaction in M ofthe formulas H 10 and H II shows that A = l m (q?) and B = l m ( 1/J ); so the values assumed by h are in A x B . The satisfaction of H4 shows that h is injective (if (q?(x), ljl (x)) = (q?(y), 1/J (y)), then x = y ), and the satisfaction of Hs shows that h is surjective onto A x B (if x = q?(x) and y = 1/1 (y ), then we can find an element z E M such that (x � y) = (q?(z)� 1/J (z)) = h (z)). So the map h is a bijection from M onto A x B . We will now show that it is a monomorphism from M into M (A , B, ao, bo) . This is a consequence of the following properties: 0 0 h (a) = (q?(a), 1/J (a)) = (a, a) = (ao, bo); for every x E M, h (cp(x)) = f (h(x)) ; 308 SOLUTIONS stnce . h (cp(x ) ) == (cp(cp (x ) ), t/J (cp(x)) ) == (cp(x ) , a ) (HJ and H3) == ( cp (X), ho) == f ( cp (X) , l/J (X)) = j ( h (X)). o for every x E M , h ( 1jl (x )) = g (h (x )) (using a similar argument). The formulas Fn = 3vo3VJ . . . 3 Vn - L ( Gn = 3vo3vJ . . . 3vn-l ( 1\ O�i <j< n - vi :::::: vj 1\ · 1\ f Vi :::::: Vi ) 1\ gv; :::::: Vi ) O�i < n and 1\ O�t <J < n -·vi :::::: Vi 1\ O�i < n (for n > l) then clearly answer the question. Fix two strictly positive integers n and p. Let Tnp denote the models of T in which the interpretations off and g have n and p elements, respectively. Consider twomodelsM = (M, a, cp, 1/J ) andM ' == ( M ', a', cp', 1/J') ofTnp · Let A == lm(cp), B = lm(1jl), A' == lm (cp'), and B' = lm(1jl'); A and A' are equipotent (they both haven elements) and so are B and B ' (which each have p elements). According to question (d), the structures M (A , B , a, a) and M (A ' , B ' , a'a') are isomorphic. Now we have seen that M is isomorphic to the first of these and M' to the second. It follows that any two models of the theory Tnp are isomorphic, which proves (Exercise I I ) that this theory is complete (it is non-contradictory by question (b)). (f) The infinite models of T are those models M == (M, a, cp . 1jl) of T for which at least one of the sets lm(cp) or lm(v; ) is infinite. It follows that these are exactly the models of the theory T ' == T U { Fk v Gk : k E N* } . The closed formulas that are satisfied in every infinite model of T are thus the closed formulas that are consequences of T ' . If F is such a formula, there exists, by the compactness theorem, a finite subset X of T ' such that X !-* F. There then exists an integer n > I such that X c Tn == T U { Fk v Gk : 1 < k < n } and we have, naturally, Tn 1-* F. But it is obvious that for every integer k such that I < k < n, Fk is a consequence of Fn and Gk is a consequence of Gn; so Fk v Gk is a consequence of Fn v Gn . As a result, the theories Tn and T U { F11 V Gn } are equivalent and we have T U { Fn v Gn } 1-* F. The theory T ' is not complete: as we have seen, its models are the in­ finite models of T ; now in such models, one of the sets I m (cp ) or I m ( 1/J ) 309 SOLUTIONS FOR CHAPTER 3 can have an arbitrary finite number of elements; for example, the struc­ tures M (N, N, 0, 0) and M (N, { 0 } , 0, 0) are models of T' (they satisfy the formulas Fk for all k > 1 ) but the first satisfies the formula G2 while the second does not satisfy this formula; so these structures are not elementarily equivalent. (g) Questions (d) and (e) show that the models of T are determined up to isomorphism by the cardinalities of the sets that are the interpretations of f and g . Precisely, given a countably infinite model M of T, there exist two non-empty sets A and B , each of cardinality less than or equal to �o, at least one of which is infinite, and two elements ao E A and bo E B such that M is isomorphic to the structure M ( A , B , ao, bo) . For each integer n E N*, set M oc n = = Mn oo = M oo oo = M (N , {0, 1 , . . . , n - 1 } , 0, 0); M ({O, 1 , . . . , n - 1 } , N, 0, 0); M (N, N, 0, 0). We see that every countably infinite model of T is isomorphic either to M 00 oc or to one of the M 00 n or to one of the M noo. Naturally, these models are pairwise non-isomorphic. There are therefore, up to isomorphism, �o countably infinite models of T. (h) The models of T " are the models of T in which the sets of fixed points of the interpretations of f and g are both infinite. The structure Moo 00 is clearly one such model. According to (g), it is immediate that every count­ ably infinite model of T " is isomorphic to M 00 00 • The theory T" is thus �a-categorical (Chapter 8); moreover, it is consistent and only has infinite models; it is therefore complete (Vaught's theorem, Part 2, Chapter 8). - - - 14. (a) Let M = (M, f) be a model of A . Ifan element a E M satisfies f(f(a ) ) = - - since a, then by applying f again� we obtain f (f(f(a))) == f(a); but - A is satisfied in M, we have f (f(f(a))) = a and hence a = f (a), which is excluded (also by A). In a n analogous manner, if we suppose - - - - /(f(a)) = f(a), we obtain /(/(f(a))) = f(f(a)), i.e. a = f(f(a)) which, as we have just seen, is i mpossible. So the structure M satisfies the following formula G : \:1X (--"�ffX � X 1\ -, ffX � fx) · Furthermore, i f w e let b denote f(f(a)), w e have f (b) =a and every element c E M that satisfies f (c) = a will also satisfy /(/(f(c))) = - f(f(a)), so c = b. In other words, every element of M has a unique preimage under f (which is therefore bijective) and M satisfies the formula H : Vx3yVz(fy � x 1\ ( f z � x ==> z � y)). 310 SOLUTIONS The rules concerning 'distribution' of quantifiers show that the formula (G 1\ H) is equivalent to the formula proposed in the statement of the exer­ cise. So this formula is satisfied in every model of A, i.e. it is a consequence of A . (b) Let n b e an element o f N * and let N = a binary relation p on N as follows: (N, J) be a model o f A 1\ Fn· Define for all a and b in N, (a, b) E p if and only if a = b or a = f(b) or a ,...,_ f(f(b)). ,...,_ = ,...,_ It is not difficult to verify that this is an equivalence relation. The equivalence class of the element a is its orbit under the function f: it contains ,......, the three elements a , j(a), and f(f(a ) ) (which are pairwise distinct) and only these. So every equivalence class contains three elements. Since these constitute a partition of N which has n elements, we conclude that n is a multiple of 3 . Conversely, for every integer p > 0, w e may construct a model Mp of A 1\ F3p that has 3p elements in the following way: For the underlying set, we take MP = {0, 1 , 2} x {0, 1 , 2, . . . , p - 1 } and as the interpretation of f we take the function /p defined as follows: ,..._, ""'-' "' for every pair (i, j) E MP ' /p (i, j) = (i + l [mod 3], j). (c) I t is sufficient (Exercise 1 1 ) to prove that for every p E N* , the models of A 1\ F3p are all isomorphic. So consider an integer p > 0 and a model M = (M, g) of A 1\ F3p · There are p classes for the equivalence relation p defined as in part (b). Denote them by Bo, B 1 , . . . , B p-t and choose an arbitrary element b; in each B; . Now, define a map (J? : M t--+ {0, l , 2} x {0, 1 , . . . , p - 1 } by (J? (b;) = (/> (g (b; ) ) = (/> (g (g (b;)) ) = (0, i ) ; ( 1, i) for all i E { 0 , 1 , . . . , p - 1 } ( 2 i). ' (J? is an isomorphism from M onto the model M p defined in (b) because the classes are in correspondence with one another and for every a E M , we have (J? (g (a )) = fp ((J? (a )). (d) I t suffices to generalize the construction of the models Mp from ques­ tion (b). This time, we take {0, l , 2} x N as the underlying set. The interpretation of F is the unique function defined on this set that simultaneously extends 311 SOLUTIONS FOR CHAPTER 3 all the /p (where the definition of /p is the same except that the index j can assume any integer value). (e) We generalize (c). Consider a countably infinite model of A. This time there is a countably infinite number of equivalence classes for p; denote them by { Bn : n E N } . Again, select a sequence {bn : n E N} such that bn E Bn for all n . We define the isomorphism from this model onto the one defined in part (d) exactly as cp is defined in (c), the only difference being that n ranges over N. The verification is simple. All the countably infinite models of A are isomorphic (since they are all isomorphic to the model that we have constructed). 15. PRELIMINARIES: First, observe that F is equivalent to the conjunction of the following formulas: 'Vx'Vy(dx 'v'x3v x � dy =} x � y) 'Vx'Vy(gx � gy =} x � y) � gv 'Vx3u x � du 'v'xdgx � gdx . It follows that for F to be satisfied in a structure M = (M, d, g), it is necessary and sufficient that d and g be bijections that commute and that, at any given point, never assume the same value. As well, i f M I= F, then for every natural number m, we have for every element a E M , dm (g(a)) This is obvious i f m dk +l (g(a)) == 0; suppose i t i s true for m == dk (d(g (a))) == g(dk(d(a))) = g(dk+ I (a) ) . = dk (g(d(a))) == g(dm (a) ) . == k; then [since g and d commutel [by the induction hypothesis] (a) We argue by induction on the height o fthe term t . Since there are n o symbols for constants in L, a termt of height 0 is a variable, y for example, and since y can also be written d0 g0 y (this is the same term), the formula 'Vy t � d0 g 0 y is universally valid; in particular, it is a consequence of T . I f t == d u and i f T �-* Vx u � dm gn x , then T r* 'Vx t � dm + l gn x . I f t == g u and i f T �-* 'Vx u � dm g n x, then in every model M (M, d, g) of T, we have that for all a E M, g(dm (gn (a)) ) == dm(gn+l (a)) (preliminaries), which shows that T r-* Vx t � dm g n + I x. 312 SOLUTIONS (We will have observed, although this was not explicitly used in the proof, that every term of L can be written in the form where x is a variable and where the m; and n; are natural numbers that are all non-zero, except possibly m 1 and nk ). (b) Mo is a model of F since the maps sd and sg are bijections that commute [sd(sg (i, j)) == sg (sd (i, j)) == (i + 1 , j + l) ] and do not assume the same value at any point [(i, j + 1 ) # (i + 1 , j ) ] Also, for all i and j in ll and for all natural numbers m and n, we have . Sdm (Sgl1 (i, j)) == (i + n , j + m). It follows that for (m. n ) # (0, 0), we have Sdm (sgn (i , j)) # (i , j ) and Sdm (i , j) == (i, j + m ) # (i + n , j) = s8n (i, j). Thus, M o is a model of each of the formulas Fmn ((m, n) # (0, 0)) and, consequently, is a model of T. (c) The map hah i s a bijection whose inverse bijection i s h-a-h· Moreover, for all pairs (i, j ) E ll x ll, we have ha b (sd (i , j) ) = (i + a, j + I + h) == Sd (habU , j ) ) ; and hab (sg (i, j) ) == (i + 1 + a , j + h) == Sg(h a b ( i , j )) . So hah is an automorphism of Mo. I n fact, i t can be shown that there are no automorphisms of Mo other than the ones in the family of hah· (Hint: given an automorphism h of M o , let h 1 and hz denote the maps from ll x ll into ll obtained by com­ posing h with the two projections [which means that for i and j in Z, h (i, j) == (h 1 (i, j ) , hz (i, j))] ; then show that h 1 does not depend on the second coordinate, that hz does not depend on the first coordinate, and that the functions of one variable that are naturally associated with h 1 and hz are bijections on ll that commute with the successor function.) (d) We already know that ll x ll and 0 are definable. Let A be a subset of ll x ll that is distinct from ll x ll and 0. Let i , j, k, andl be elements ofZ such that (i, j) E A and (k, l) fj A. Seta == k == i and h = l - j . We have hab Ci, j) == (k, l), which shows that A is not invariant under the automorphism hab and hence (Theorem 3.95) is not definable. So Z x Z and 0 are the only subsets of Z x Z that are definable in Mo. 16. PRELIMINARIES: We describe a method that we will then use several times for determining all the definable subsets of the base set (or of some cartesian power of this set) in a model M == (M, . . . } of a language L. SOLUTIONS FOR CHAPTER 3 313 Suppose that we have determined a finite number o f subsets A 1 , A z , . . . , An of Mk that are all definable in M and that constitute a partition of the set Mk . Suppose as well that for every index i between I and n and for all elements a = (a t , az, . . . , ak) and {3 = (h i , bz, . . . , bk) belonging to A ; , there exists an automorphism of the structure M that sends a to {3, i.e. that sends a 1 to b t 1 az to bz, . . . , ak to bk (this property is automatically satisfied for those A; that contain only a single element; the automorphism in question reduces to the identity). Under these circumstances, according to Theorem 3.95, for every subset X of M k that is definable in M, each of the A; is either included in X or else is disjoint from X. It is then easy to conclude that every subset of Mk that is definable in M must be a union of sets chosen from among A 1 , A z , . . . , A n . In other words, the Boolean algebra of subsets of Mk that are definable in M is the sub-algebra of tJ ( Mk ) generated by A 1 , A 2, . . . , A n . This sub-algebra has n 2 elements (refer to Exercise I 7 and to Corollary 2.5 I ) . (a) Let A be a non-empty subset o f Z/nZ that is definable i n M 1 and let k be an element of A. For every element h E 7ljn7l, the map ifJ : x r-7 x + h - k is a bijection of 'll/ n'll onto itself that commutes with the map x � x + I (which means that for all x E 7ljn7l, ({J (x + 1 ) = ifJ (x ) + 1 ); so ifJ is an automorphism of the structure M 1 • Since A is definable, it follows that h , which i s equal to ({J (k), belongs to A (Theorem 3.95). Hence A = 7lfn7l since the only definable subsets of 'll/ n'll that are definable in M 1 are 0 and 7ljn7l. In exactly the same way, (by replacing M 1 by Mz and x I-> x + 1 by x � x + 2) we prove that the only subsets of 'll/ n'll that are definable in Mz are 0 and 'll/ n'll . (b) In the structure N1 , the set {0} is defined by the formula gvovo � vo, and the set { I , 2} by the negation of this formula. Also, the map x 1-� x + x is clearly an automorphism of the structure that interchanges the elements 1 and 2. We conclude, from the preliminaries, that there are four subsets of 7lf37l definable in N1 : 0� 7lf37l, {0}, and { 1 , 2 } . In the structure Nz, the sets { 0}, { 3}, { 2 , 4}, and { 1 , 5} are defined respec­ tively by Ho : gvovo � vo; H3 : ggvovogvovo � gvovo 1\ -.Ho; H24 : :3vt gvt vt � vo 1\ -.Ho ; H1s : ·-,Ho 1\ -.H3 1\ -.H24 · Moreover, the map x r-7 x is an automorphism of Nz that interchanges 2 and 4, on the one hand, and I and 5 on the other hand. So the circumstances described in the preliminaries are fulfi.lled and we may conclude that the subsets of 7lj67l that are definable in Nz are the 1 6 elements of the algebra - 314 SOLUTIONS generated by {0} , {3}, {2, 4}, and { 1 , 5}, namely: {0}, {3}, {2, 4}, { 1 , 5 } , {0, 3 } , {0, 2, 4}, {0 , 1 , 5 } , {2, 3, 4}, { I , 3, 5}, { 1 , 2, 4 , 5 } , {0, 2, 3, 4}, {0, 1 , 3, 5}, {0, 1 , 2, 4, 5 } , { 1 , 2 , 3, 4, 5}, 'lll6'1l. 0, Finally, we consider the structure N3 . The sets {0}, { 1 }, { - 1 } , and IR+ are defined, respectively, by the formulas: Fo : F1 : V' v 1 g v 1 vo � v o; V'v 1 g v 1 vo � v 1 ; F- 1 : V' v 1 g v I g vo vo � VI FJR+ : 3vl gv 1 v 1 � vo. 1\ --., FI ; All Boolean combinations of these four sets are also definable (Theorem 3.94), in particular, IR� - { I } and IR� { - 1 }. If a is a non-zero real number, the map 1/r[a] from JR. into IR which, with each real x� associates - 0 xa - (-X )a if X = 0; if x > 0; if X < 0; is a bijection which commutes with the map (x, y) � x y (for all reals x and y, ljr [a](x, y) = ljr[a](x) ljr [a](y)); so this is an automorphism of the structure N3. Let a and b be two elements of IR� { 1 } ; In bI In a is then a non-zero real number and the automorphism 1/r [In bI In a l sends a to b. We obtain the same conclusion when we replace IR� - {1 } by IR� - { - 1 }, assume that a and b belong to IR� { - 1 }, and consider the automorphism 1/r fln(-b)/ ln(-a)]. In this way, we see that the five sets {0}, { 1 }, { - 1 } , �� - { 1 }, and IR� - { - 1 } , which are definable in N3 and which constitute a partition of IR, satisfy the conditions described in the preliminaries. It follows that the Boolean algebra of subsets of IR that are definable in N3 is the subal­ gebra of !9 (IR) generated by {0}, { 1 }, { - 1 } , IR� - { I }, and �� - { - 1 }. It contains 32 elements. (c) Question ( 1 ) was answered just after Theorem 3. 95 where we saw that the only subsets of IR definable in (JR, <} are 0 and JR. We will again invoke the preliminaries to answer question (2). Consider the following three subsets of IR2 : - - A1 = { (x , y) E IR2 : x = y } , which is defined by the formula S O L U T I O N S F O R C H A PT E R 3 A2 == { (x, y) R vov1 A3 == 1\ E --,vo 315 IR2 : x < y } , which is defined by the formula � v1; { (x , y) E IR2 : x > y } , which is defined by the formula R v 1 vo 1\ -,vo � v 1 . Let a == (a, b ) and f3 == (c, d) b e two elements of iR2 . I f they both belong to A 1 , then a == b and c == d and the map x � x -rc-a is an automorphism of the structure (IR, <) that sends a to f3. If a and f3 belong to A 2 (respectively, to A3), then a < b and c < d (respectively, a > b and c > d); the real : � is strictly positive and the map x� d-c b-a x+ be - ad b-a --- is an automorphism of (IR, <) that sends a to f3. So the conditions described in the preliminaries are satisfied and we see that there are eight subsets of IR2 that are definable: 0, IR2 , A 1 , A 2 , A3 and the following three sets: A 2 U A3 == { (x, y) E IR2 : x # y } ; A 1 U A3 == { (x, y) E IR2 : x > y } ; A t U A2 == { (x, y) E JR2 : x < y } . 17. (a) We take Z/(n + 1)Z == {0, 1 , . . . , n } a s thebaseset and for the interpretation of R , we take the binary relation R defined by for all elements a and b in Z/(n + 1 )Z, (a, b) E R if and only if b == a + 1 ; in other words, R is addition in 'll / (n + 1 )Z. The (n + 1 )-tuple (0, 1 , . . . , n) is an (n + I )-cycle for R hence the structure we have just defined does not satisfy �z+ 1 · Moreover, it is easy to verify that if 2 < k < n, then there are no k-cycles in this structure; this shows that it satisfies the formulas F2 , F3 , . . . , Fn . (b) If T I-* G, then, by the compactness theorem, there is a finite subset T' of T such that T ' 1-* G. We can find an integer p > 2 such that T' c { F2 , F3 , . . . , Fp } ; naturally, this implies that { F2 , F3 , . . . , Fp } 1-* G, which means precisely that G is satisfied in any L-structure that does not have any cycles of length less than or equal to p . (c) Let G be a closed formula that i s a consequence o f T and let p bean integer greater than or equal to 2 such that G is satisfied in any L-structure that does not have any cycles of length less than or equal to p (see question (b)). Consider a model of the formula 316 SOLUTIONS (part (a) guarantees that such a model exists); G is satisfied in this model which contains at least one cycle of length p + 1 . (d) We argue by contradiction. Let To be a finite theory that is equivalent to T and let H be the conjunction of the formulas of To. The theory T is then equivalent to { H } . In particular, the formula H is a consequence of T ; hence (question (c)), i t has at least one model that contains a cycle; but such a model is not a model of T (whose models must not contain any cycles). This contradicts the equivalence of T and { H } . 18. We will suppose the existence of a theory T o f L that has the indicated property and arrive at a contradiction. Consider the theory (in the language L') T' == T U {Fn : n E N}. So a model of T' must be an L'-structure i n which the interpretation of R is a well-ordering and in which the set of interpretations of the en constitutes an 'infinite descending chain', i.e. a non-empty subset of the base set that does not have a least element modulo R. This situation is obviously contradictory and we conclude that T' is contradictory. From the compactness theorem for predicate calculus, we can find a finite subset T" of T' that is contradictory. So there is a natural number N such that T" c T U { Fn : n < N } . The theory T U { �1 : n < N } is then itself contradictory. However, consider the Lo­ structure Mo == (N, <) (in which R is interpreted by the usual order relation on N). According to our hypothesis, Mo can be enlarged to an L-structure M that is a model of T. M can be further enlarged to an L' -structure M' by interpreting each symbol en by the integer N + I n if n < N + I and by 0 if n > N + I . It is clear that M' is a model of the formulas Fo, Ft , . . . , FN and also a model of T. Thus we have a model of the theory TN , which is absurd. So the property 'is a well-ordering' is not finitely axiomatizable. 19. Suppose that F[c t , c2, . , ck] is a consequence of T. Let M == ( M , . . ) be an L-structure that is a model of T. For all elements a 1 , a2, . . . , ak of M, we can enrich M to an L'-structure M' by interpreting each of the constant symbols c; (for 1 < i < k) by the element a; ; M' is also a model of T (Lemma 3.58) and hence, by our hypothesis, a model of F[ct , c2 , . . . , ck]. It follows (by applying Proposition 3.45 k times) that - . . . but this is clearly equivalent to which allows us to conclude that the formula YxtVx2 . . . Vxk F[xt , x2, . . . , Xk] i s satisfied i n M. This formula, which i s true i n every L-structure that i s a model of T, is therefore a consequence of the theory T. S O L UTIONS FOR CH APTER 3 317 20. (a) According t o Theorem 3.9 1 , the stated hypothesis means that the theory T U � (M) (in the language L M ) does not have a model. By the compactness theorem, we conclude that some finite subset E of this theory does not have a model. Let K denote the conjunction of the formulas from � (M) that belong to E (there are only finitely many). The theory T U { K } is then contradictory. Note that any conjunction of formulas from � (M) is again a closed, quantifier-free formula of LM that is satisfi ed in M* (the natural extension of M to the language L M ). Thus K E � (M). So there exists a quantifier-free formula H = H [x 1 , x2, . . . , Xn] of the language L and parameters a1 , a2, . . . , an in M such that K = H[at , a2, . . . , an] (we have omitted the underlining and avoided the distinction between the parameters and the corresponding constant symbols of the language L M ) . To say that T U { K } is a contradictory theory in the language L M is equivalent to saying that the formula -,K is a consequence of the theory T : Using the result from Exercise 1 9 , w e conclude that the formula is a consequence of the theory T. Since we also have that (because K E � (M) ), the formula is not satisfied in M . So the formula G = -,H answers the question. (b) Suppose there exists an extension N of M that is a model of T. Then N also satisfies all the closed formulas that are consequences of T, in particular, those that are universal; so N is a model of U (T). But any universal closed formula that is satisfied in N must also be satisfied in the substructure M of N (Theorem 3.70); it follows that M is a model of U (T). Conversely, suppose that M is a model of U (T). Then there cannot exist a quantifier-free formula G [x 1 , x2, . . . , Xn] of L such that \lx1 \lx2 . Vxn G [x l , x2, . . . , Xn] and M � Vx 1 \lx2 . . . V'xn G fxl , X2, . . . , Xn]. T I-* _ . So we cannot b e i n the situation described i n the previous question. The conclusion is that there exists at least one extension of M that is a model of T. (c) If M has an extension that is a model of T, then every substructure o f M has this same property since an extension of M is also an extension of any 318 21. (a) (b) (c) (d) SOLUTIONS substructure of M. In particular, every substructure of M of finite type has an extension that is a model of T. To prove the converse, we will use the equivalence established in (b): it suffices to prove that M is a model of U (T), knowing that all its substructures of finite type are. But this result follows immediately from part (d) of Exercise 12: every formula of U (T) is universal; if it is true in every sub­ structure of M of finite type, then it is true in M ; hence M is a model of U (T). We argue by contradiction. Suppose that all the elements o f A have the same type; suppose also that B is a subset of M that is definable in M by a formula F [v] of L and is such that B n A =f. 0 and A cJ. B. If we choose elements a and b in A such that a E B and b ¢ B , then we have that M � F[a ] and M Jr F[b]; It follows that F E e (a) and F ¢ e (b), hence e(a) =f. () (b); this contradicts that fact that a and b have the same type. Again, we argue by contradiction. If e (a) =f. e (h (a)), then there exists a formula f[vd E Ft such that M F= F[a] and M ;t F[h(a)]; but this situation contradicts Theorem 3.72. In M 1, all elements have the same type: if a and b are elements of Z, the map x � x + b - a is an automorphism of M 1 that sends a to b; so a and b have the same type according to the preceding question (we find ourselves in the situation that was already studied in Section 3.6. 1 and again in part (c) of Exercise 16). In M2, 0, and l do not have the same type: indeed, the formula 3w fw � w is satisfied by I but not by 0. In M3, all elements have the same type: if a and b are elements of Z, the map x r--? x + b - a is an automorphism of M3 that sends a to b; so a and b have the same type according to question (b). In M4, 0, and 1 do not have the same type: indeed, the formula gvv � v is satisfied by 0 but not by 1 . Let M = (M, . . . ) be a model of T . We define a map cp from M into {0, l}n in the following way: for every element a E M and for al1 i between 1 and n , we set 8i {1 = if Fi E () (a); 0 if Fi ¢ 8 (a); and define cp (a) = (c 1 , c2 , . . . , cn ) . Let a and b be two elements of M such that cp(a) = cp(b); this means that for all i between 1 and n , F; E () (a ) if and only if Fi E ()(b), or equivalently that the formula 1\ t <k<n ( Fi [vo] {} Fi[vd) is satisfied in M by the pair (a, b). 319 SOLUTIONS FOR CHAPTER 3 Given that M i s a model of T and that w e have assumed that the formula G is a consequence of T, it follows that we must have a == b, which proves that the map q; is injective. So the cardinality of M is at most that of {0, l }n which is 2n . (e) As indicated, let us add two new constant symbols c and d to the langu­ age L and let us consider the following theory S1 of the enriched language L t : SI == S U { F fc] ¢> F [d] : F E Ft ( L ) } U {-,c � d}. I t i s clear that i n every model o f S I , the interpretations of c and d are two distinct elements that have the same type in the reduct of this model to the language L . So to answer the proposed question, it suffices to show that S 1 is a consistent theory in L 1 · Suppose it is not. Then by the compactness theorem, there would be a finite subset of S 1 that is contradictory; so there would exist a finite number of formulas F1 , F2, . . . , Fn of L with one free variable such that the theory is contradictory. It amounts to the same thing to say that the formula f\ I <i <n ( Fi [c] ¢> Fi [d]) A c � d is a consequence of S. We may then apply the result from Exercise 1 9 and, relative only to the language L, conclude that S f--* VvoVv1 ( 6 (F; [vo] {} F; [vJ]) n =? vo � VJ . ) According to question (d), this requires that any model of S can have at most 2n elements. But we assumed that S had at least one infinite model; so we have arrived at a contradiction. We could give a shorter proof of the property that we just obtained by invoking a theorem that will be proved in Chapter 8 of Part 2, the ascend­ ing Lowenheim-Skolem theorem, which asserts that when a theory has a countably infinite model, then it has models of every infinite cardinality. So let M = (M, . . . ) be a model of S and suppose that there is no pair of elements of M that have the same type; this means that the map a r-+ e (a) from M into the set of subsets o f F1 is injective (indeed, i f i t were not. we could find two distinct elements a and b in M for which fJ (a) = () (b), i.e. distinct elements having the same type). As a consequence, the cardinality of the model M is bounded by the cardinality of the set fiJ (FI ). So it would suffice to take a model of S of cardinality strictly greater than that of fiJ (Ft ) (such a model would exist by the Lowenheim-Skolem theorem cited above, 320 SOLUTIONS since we have assumed that S has at least one infinite model) to guarantee the existence of at least one pair of distinct elements having the same type. (f) According to what we have just proved, a theory T can satisfy the required conditions only if it does not have any infinite model. We could consider, for example, in the language L that has only two distinct constant symbols c and d, the theory T consisting of the single formula V'vo(vo � c v vo � d) 1\ -.c ""' d. I t is obvious that every model o f T has exactly two elements, c and d, and that these two elements do not have the same type since the formula vo � c belongs to e (c) but does not belong to e (d). (g) The language L consists of a constant symbol c and a unary function symbol f. Consider the L-structure N whose base set is N, in which c is interpreted by 0 and f by the successor function. This structure is infinite and contains no pair of distinct elements having the same type: indeed, if n and p are integers such that 0 < n < p ' the formula vo � f p c belongs to e (p) but does not belong to e (n) ; so n and p do not have the same type. Solutions to the exercises for Chapter 4 1. There are cases in which F => V' v F is not universally valid. For example, in a language that contains a unary predicate symbol P , take F = P v. The universal closure of Pv ::::} V'v P v is equal to V'v(Pv ::::} V'vPv) which is itself equivalent to 3 v P v =} V'vPv. This last formula is false in a structure in which the interpretation of P is neither the empty set nor the entire underlying set. 2. (a) In a language that contains a unary predicate symbol P, take the formula F = Pw. Then V'vF =} V'w Fwfv is equal to V'v Pw =} V'wPw which is logically equivalent to Pw ::::} V'w Pw. We saw in Exercise 1 that this formula is not universally valid. (b) This time, the language has a binary predicate symbol R and F = 3w Rvw. Then V'vF =} V'wFw/v is equal to V'v3wRvw =} V'w3wRww, which is logically equivalent to V'v3wRvw => 3wRww. This formula is false, for example, i n the structure whose base set is N and i n which R is interpreted by the strict order relation. 3. We begin by writing a derivation of 3vo F in T, followed by a derivation of of V'vo ( F ::::} G), always in T (these two proofs exist by hypothesis). We complete this with the sequence of formulas in Table S4. 1 , which constitute a derivation of 3voG from 3vo F and V'vo( F =} G). S O L UTIONS FOR C H A P T E R 4 321 Table S4.1 (I) Vvo ( F => G) => (F => G) Example 4.8 (2) (F => G) by modus ponens, since Vvo(F => G) appears earlier (3) Vv0-.G => -.G Example 4.8 (4) (F => G) => ((Vvo-.G => -.G) => (Vvo-.G => -.F)) tautology (5) (Vvo-.G (6) Vvo-.G => -. F (7) Vvo(Vvo-.G (8) Vvo(Vvo-.G (9) Vvo-.G => Vvo-.F => ¢? -.G) => => => (Vvo-.G => from (2) and (4) by modus ponens -.F) from (3) and (5) by modus ponens -.F) from (6) by generalization �F) => (Vvo�G => Vvo-.F) axiom schema (b) from (7) and (8) by modus ponens ( 1 0) 3voF -.Vvo-.F (1 1) (3voF ( 1 2) 3voF => -.Vvo�F from ( 10) and ( I I ) by modus ponens ( 1 3) -.Vvo-.F from ( 1 2) by modus ponens, since 3voF appears earlier ( 1 4) (Vvo�G => Vvo�F) => (-.Vvo-.F (15) �Vvo�F ( 1 6) -.Vvo-.G ( 1 7) 3voG ( 1 8) (3voG ( 1 9) -.Vvo-.G => 3voG from ( 17) and ( 1 8) by modus ponens (20) 3voG from ( 16) and ( 1 9) by modus ponens ¢? ¢? axiom schema (a) tautology -.Vvo-.F) => (3voF => -.Vvo-.F) => => -.Vvo-.G) tautology from ( 1 4) and (9) by modus ponens �Vvo�G from ( 1 5 ) and ( 1 3) by modus ponens -.Vvo�G ¢? -.Vvo-.G) axiom schema (a) => 4. Here is a proof of F v (-.Vvo-.G => tautology 3voG) VvG from Vv(F v G): (1) Vv(F v G ) :::} ( F v G ) (2) Vv(F v G ) (3) ( F v G ) (4) ( F v G) :::} (--.F :::} G ) ( 5 ) -,p :::} G (6) Vv(--.F :::} G) (7) Vv( --.F :=:} G) ==} ( ..., p ==> VvG) (8) ( ..., p :::} VvG) (9) (-.F :::} VvG) :::} ( F v VvG) ( 1 0) ( F v VvG) axiom schema (c) formula of the theory from ( 1 ) and (2) by modus ponens tautology from (3) and (4) by modus ponens by generalization axiom schema (b) (v is not free i n F) from (6) and (7) by modus ponens tautology from (8) and (9) by modus ponens 5. (a) We define cp(F) by induction on F: if F is an atomic formula, then cp(F) = 1 (in fact, here, we could just as well have chosen cp(F) = 0) o if not, we use conditions ( 1 ), (2), (3), and (4) as the definition, after noting that they are compatible with one another. (b) The verification is immediate: if F is a tautology, then cp(F) = 1 thanks to conditions (3) and (4); if F is ofthe form 3vG � -.vv-.G, then cp (3vG) = 1 o 322 SOLUTIONS by condition (2), cp( -.vv--,G) = l by condition ( 1 ) and hence cp( 3 vG {:} __,yv--,G) = 1 by condition (4). For the formulas of schema (b) or (c), the same type of argument applies. (c) According to condition (4) when the connective a is ==> , if cp( F ==> G) = l and cp(F) = 1, we must have cp(G) = 1 . (d) Let (F1 , F2 , . . . , Fn ) b e a derivation o f F(F = Fn ) that does not invoke the rule of generalization. This means that for all i between 1 and n, one of the following two situations must hold: • F; is an axiom, • F; follows by modus ponens from two formulas that precede it, i.e. there exist j and k less than i such that Fj = Fk ==> F; . We can show immediately by induction on the integer i , using the results from parts (b) and (c), that cp(F; ) = 1. Hence cp (F) = 1. Now consider the formula F = Vv( G � G) where G is an arbitrary formula. This formula is clearly provable (it is obtained by generalization from the tautology G ==> G). However, cp(F) = 0 and hence it cannot be derived without the rule of generalization. 6. (a) We adapt the definition from the previous exercise in an obvious way. (b) One must first verify that cp assumes the value 1 for the tautologies and for the formulas of axiom schemas (a) and (b); this follows from the conditions imposed on cp. Finally, if F is obtained by generalization, then F begins with a universal quantifier so cp(F) = l . This allows us to show, as before, that if F has a proof that does not make use of axiom schema (c), then cp( F) = 1 . (c) Let F b e a formula of axiom schema (c) such that cp( F) = 0, for example, F = Vvo3vt G ==> 3v 1 G, where G is an arbitrary formula. This formula is provable but, since cp (F) is not equal to 1, it cannot be proved without appealing to schema (c). 7. Let (F1 , F2 , . . . , Fn) be a derivation of F (F = Fn) that does not appeal to axiom schema (a). We will show that (Ft , F{ , . . . , F; ) is a derivation of F*. • If F; is a tautology, then so is F;*. To see this, note that there exists a proposi­ tional tautology P [A 1 , A 2 , . . . , Ak] depending on the propositional variables A 1 , A2, . . . , Ak and formulas G 1 , G2 , . . . , Gk such that • So F;* = P [GT, G2, . . . , G/:] which shows that F;* is a tautology. If F; belongs to axiom schema (b), say F; = Vv(H => G) ==> (H ==> VvG) where v is a variable that has no free occurrence in H , then F;* = Vv(H* ==> G*) :=> (H* ==> VvG*) so F;* is also an axiom. 323 SOLUTIONS FOR CHAPTER 4 • • The argument is similar if F; belongs to axiom schema (c). If F; is obtained by modus ponens from Fj and Fk with j and k less than i, then Fj = Fk � F; hence Fj F! ==> Ft i s obtained by modus ponens from Fj and Fk* . If F; is obtained by generalization from Fj U < i ), then Fz* i s obtained by generalization from Fj . � ta = This shows that ifF can be proved without an appeal to axiom schema (a), then 1- F*. For example, if P is a unary predicate symbol, F = 3v P v {:? -,Vv-.Pv is certainly provable (it i s a n axiom) but it is not provable without schema (a): otherwise, F* = VvPv � -,\lv-, P v would also be provable, which is not the case since F* is not universally valid (it is universally equivalent to Vv P v <::> 3 v P v). 8. We are asked to prove, using Herbrand's method, that i f T does not have a model, then T is not consistent. As in the section on Herbrand's method, we assume that each formula Fn can be written in the form where k is an integer and Bn is a formula without quantifiers. Let T denote the set of terms of the language and 8; denote the set of sequences of length i of elements of T. We then introduce, for all n and i , a map a;,n from 8 i into N i n such a way that the following properties are satisfied: ( I ) if Vm occurs in one of the terms l t , 12 , . . . , 1; , then a;,n (1I , 12, . . . , 1; ) > m ; (2) i f j < i and (11 , 12, . . . , 1; ) i s a sequence that extends (1t , 12 , . . , 1j ), then . a; , n (11 , 12 , . . . , 1j ) < a;,n (1I , 12 , . . . , 1; ) ; (3) if r and o· are two distinct sequences whose respective lengths are i and j and if n and m are arbitrary integers, then a;,n(r) =I= aj.m (a). The codings from Chapter 6 show how such functions can be constructed without difficulty. By definition, an avatar of Fn will be a formula of the form Denote the set of all avatars of Fn by An . To prove the two lemmas that follow, it more or less suffices to recopy the proofs of Theorems 4.38 and 4.39. Lemma I : I f U n EN An is propositionally satisfiable, then { Fn : n E N} has a model. Lemma 2: If I is a finite subset of N and if U nE/ An is not propositionally satisfiable, then 1\n EI Fn is provable. These two lemmas permit us to prove the desired theorem. -, 324 SOLUTIONS 9. Here are some possible refutations. (a) (A 1\ B) =} B =} D (b) (A 1\ B ) � (A 1\ A) =} A =? 0 (c) (B 1\ C) =} B� =} (B v B ) =} B D from (A 1\ B) :=} C and C => by cut on C from (A 1\ B) =} and =} A by cut on A from B =} and B =} by cut on B from (A 1\ from (A 1\ from (A 1\ from A =} B) => C and C � by cut on C B) =:::;> and A =} B by cut on B A) by simplification and ::::} A by cut on A from (A 1\ B) =} and C =} A by cut on A from (B 1\ C) =} and � C by cut on C from D � B and � ( D v B) by cut on D from =} (B v B) by simplification from B ::::} and =} B by cut on B (d) (A 1\ A 1\ B ) =:::;> C from (A 1\ B) =:::;> (C v D) and (A 1\ D) =? by cut on D (A 1\ B) =} C from (A 1\ A 1\ B ) � C by simplification B � (C v C) from (A 1\ B) � C and =} (A v C) by cut on A B =} C from B ::::} (C v C) by simplification from B =} C and =} (B v C) by cut on B =} (C v C) from (C v C) by simplifi.cation =} C from =? C and C � E by cut on C from =? C and C =} F by cut on C � F from =} C and (C 1\ E 1\ F) � by cut on C (E v F) � F ==} from =} E and (E 1\ F) =} by cut on E D from F ::::} and =} F by cut on F A denote the set of propositional variables. We define a map from the set of reduced clauses into the set of maps from A into {0, 1 , 2 }: to each clause C corresponds the map ac from A into {0, I , 2 } defined by 10. Let ac (A) ac (A) ac (A) 0 if and only if A appears in the premiss of C � = 1 if and only i f A appears in the conclusion of C; = 2 if and only if A does not appear in C. = This map has an inverse: i t is the map which, with a given map a from A into {0, 1 , 2 } , associates the clause whose premiss is the conjunction of the propositional variables A for which a(A) = 0, taken in the order of increasing index, and whose conclusion is the disjunction of the propositional variables A 325 SOLUTIONS FOR C HAPTER 4 for which a(A) = 1, also taken in the order ofincreasing index. Therefore, there are as many reduced clauses as there are maps from A into {0, 1 , 2 } namely 3n . � 11. Suppose that there are, in all, n propositional variables appearing in S. Let P be a clause in S. We may begin by supposing that any given propositional variable occurs at most once in P : for if some variable occurs in both the premiss and the conclusion of P, then P is a tautology and we can ignore it; if not, we can reduce to this case by simplification. Let M be the number of variables appearing in P; m i s greater than or equal to 3 by hypothesis. For P to be false, all the variables in its premiss must be true and all the variables in its conclusion must be false. Among the 2n assignments of truth values to P, there are at most 2n -m (i.e. at most one-eighth of them, since 2n -m < 2n !) that could make P false. If we perform this calculation for each of the seven clauses in S, we see that there are at most seven-eighths of the assignments of truth values that could make one of the clauses in S false. So there are some left over that must satisfy all the clauses in S. · 12. (a) Here is the desired refutation: Cs = => B c6 = c ==> C7 = (A !\ B) => Cs = A => D from C3 and C4 by cut on A from Cz and Cs by cut on B from c. and c6 by cut on c from Cs and C7 by cut on B from C4 and Cs by cut on A (b) From C1 and C3, we derive (A !\ A) => C by cut on B , then A � C = I> by simplification. The set {Cz , C4, V} is satisfied by the assignment of truth values 8 defined by 8 (A ) = 8 (C) = 1 and 8(B) = 0; therefore it is not refutable. Our conclusion is that in a derivation of the empty clause from a finite set of clauses r, it is not legitimate to replace two arbitrarily chosen clauses by a clause that can be obtained from them by cut. What is possible (and which is what we did to prove Theorem 4.50), is to perform this operation systematically for all pairs of clauses that permit the elimination of some given variable (and only these pairs). 13. We will be content to provide the details for (a), (c), and (d) and to simply state the answer for the others. (a) l .B. Simplification. The system (a) is equivalent to (vo, g gvsVJ hv4), (g hb g vzv3 g hb vo). I . C. Reduction. First set r1 (vo) = g g vs VJ hv4 then unify: (g hb gvz v3 , g hb ggvsv1 hv4). 2. A and B. Simplification and clean-up; we obtain in succession (hb, hb), (gvzv3, g g vsVJ hv4); (vz, gvsvt ) , (v3, hv4). 326 SOLUTIONS 2.C. Reduction. We can perform two reductions simultaneously by setting r2 (v2) = g vs v 1 and r2(v3) = hv4. We then obtain the empty system. The substitution r = r2 o ri is a principal unifier. We may calculate r (vo ) = g gvsv1 hv4, r (v2) = gvsvi , r (v3) = hv4. (b) There is no unifier. (c) LB. Simplification. We obtain: ( V4 , f j V3 V9 j V 1 1 VI I ) , ( g gjgV J V6 j V5 V I28fVIOQV2 j V7Vg , g gV2gf V J oafV6VO V4). l .C. Reduction. Set r1 (v4) = f jv3v9 f V I I V I I and the reduced system is (g gjg V I V6 f VsV128fVIOQ V2 j V?V8 , g gv2gfVJOllfV6VO jj V3V9 j V 1 1 VI I ). 2.B. Simplification. (g jg v 1 V6fV5 V I28f VIOQV2 , g V2 gfvt oafV6VO), ( .f V7V8, j j V3V9 j v 1 1 V u ) . Then (f gVI V6 j V5 Vl2, V2), (g j VIOQ V2 , g fVlOQ j V6VO ) , (V7 , jV 3V9) , ( Vg, f VI I Vl l ) · 2.C. Reduction. Set r2(v2) = f g v i V6 fvs VJ2 , r2 (v7) f v i l V I I · We then obtain (g j V(OQ jg V I V6fV5Vl2 , g j V] OQ j V6Vo). == jv31J9 , r2(vg ) = 3 . A and B. Simplification and clean-up. We obtain i n succession (jv10a, fvJoa), (f gv1 V6 jvs v 1 2 , fv6vo ) ; (gVI V6 , V6) , (j V5 V l 2 , VO) . It i s impossible to unify (gv1 V6, V6 ) so system (c) does not have a unifier. (d) 1 . B. Simplification. (v2, g gv9 v3 g v9vw), (f jjgv4V 1 j v3vs jgv7 b vo g v6 V8 , f fvofgv?bfv i i v1 2 V2). 1 . C . Reduction. We set TI (v2) g gv9v3 gv9v1o and we obtain (f ffg v4V J .f v3vs jgv7 b vo gv6V8, f fvofgv?bfv u V I 2 ggvgv3gvgv1o). = 2. B . Simplification. (f jgV4 V 1 f V3 V5 jgv7 b VO, j VO jgV?bfV l l V I 2 ) , (gV6V8, g gv9V3 8V9 V IO) ; (.f g v4V] j V3V5 , VO), (f g V? b VO, j gv7b j V J I V J 2 ) , ( V6 , gV9V3 ) , ( vg, gv9 V J o ) . 2. C. Reduction. We set r2 (vo) = f gv4v1 jv3v5 , r2 (v6 ) == gv9 V3 , r2 (vg ) == g V9 V I O and we obtain ( j gv7b jgv4 V I fV3V5, f g v7 b f V I I VJ2). 3. A and B . Simplification. We obtain i n succession (gv7 b, gV? b), (. f gv4V1 jv3V5, f V I I VI2); (gV4 V I . V l l ) , (.f V3V5 , V I2). 3. C. Reduction. We set T3(V I I ) gv4v1 and r3 (v12) = j v3 v5 . The system we then obtain is empty and r == r3 o !'2 o r1 is a principal unifier of = 327 SOLUTIONS FOR C HAPTER 4 system (d). We may calculate r (vo) = f g v4 v 1 jv3v5, r (v2) = g gv9 v3 gv 9 v1o, r (v6) r ( vs ) = gv9V!O , r (v 1 1 ) = g v4 v 1 and r (v12) = jv3v5. = gv9 v3, (e) There is no unifier (we notice this from the occurrence test after having completely decomposed the terms). 14. Consider the inverse a-1 of a (it is a permutation of V ) and let o-' denote the substitution that extends it. It is immediate to verify that o· o a ' and a ' o a are substitutions that equal the identity on V , and hence are equal to the identity : therefore a has an inverse so it bijective. For the converse, we begin by observing that if a is a substitution and t is a term, then the length of t, lg[t], is less than or equal to that of a (t) (easily proved by induction on t ). Suppose that r and r' are two substitutions such that both r o r' and r' o r are equa] to the identity. Then. for every variable v. lg[r (v)] < lg[r ' (r(v))] = 1; since r'(r(v)) = v , r (v) cannot be a constant symbol, so it must be a variable. So the restriction of r to V is a map from V into V and w e see, without difficulty� that the restriction of r' to V is the inverse map. 15. (a) By induction on t. If t is a variable or a constant symbol, there is nothing to prove. If t is of the form ft1 t2 . . . tn where n is an integer and f is an n-ary function symbol, then the equality t == a (t) = fa (tr )a (t2) . . . a Ctn) implies tr = a (t1 ), t2 = a (t2), . . . , ln = a (tn) by the unique readability theorem. We then invoke the induction hypothesis. (b) This follows immediately from (a). .. (c) Let v E A; then v has an occurrence in a term of the form rr (t). But rr == a o ar o rr and so, according to (b), a o ar ( v) = v. This shows thac a1 ( v) cannot be a constant symbol nor a term whose length is greater than 1 (see Exercise 14 ) . Hence it is a variable and the restriction of a1 to A. is a surjective map from A onto B. But since for every variable v E A a o a 1 (v) == v, this map is also injective. Let A' denote the complement of A in V and B' the complement of B in V . Then A' and B' have the same number of elements and we can find a bijection r from B' onto A'. Let r1 denote the inverse bijection. We define the substitutions a' and a { by l a'(v) a ' (v) a { (v) a { (v) a (v) = r (v) == a r (v) == = rr (v) if v if v if v ifv E E E E B; B'; A; A'. Then properties (i), (ii), and (iii) in the statement of the exercise are evident. Let us consider (iv): for example, we need to show that for every 328 SOLUTIONS variable v, we have a ' o Jrt (v) = a o n 1 (v); but this is clear since all the variables that occur in rr 1 ( v) (which is equal to o·1 o n ( v)) are in B and a and a ' agree on B. (d) First of all, it is clear that i f a is a bijective substitution from T into T, then a o r is also a principal unifier. Conversely, suppose that rr ' is another ' principal unifier of S. Then there are substitutions a and a such that n = a o n1 and n 1 = a1 o n . But, according to (c) there also exists a bijective substitution a { such that n 1 = a { o n . 16. To apply the rule o f resolution, we must. begin by separating the two clauses. We obtain Before applying the cut rule, we can unify P v2 and P vo or else Pv2 and P/V ] . In the first case, the principal unifier i s r (vo) = v2 and r (v; ) = v; for i =!= 2. The result is (Sv2 1\ P! v i ) :::} (Rv2 v Qvo v i ) - In the second case, the principal unifier i s r (v2) = fv1 and r(v;) = v; for i =f=. 2. The result is 17. To obtain the Skolem forms of these formulas, we must add two constant sym­ bols, say a and b, to the language. We obtain the following formulas: Vv1 ( P a 1\ (Rvt :::} Qav t ) ; Vvo'Vv t (-. Pvo v -.sv1 v-.Qvo v i ) ; R b i\ Sb. When we rewrite these in the form of clauses, we obtain the set: => Pa (2) Rv1 => Qav1 ( 3) ( p VQ 1\ S VI 1\ Q VQ V I ) ::::::} (4) ==? Rb (5) => Sb. Using the principal unifier r (vo) = a and r (vi ) = v; for i =!= Pa in ( 1 ) with P vo in (3) and obtain, by the cut rule: (6) (Sv1 1\ Qav1 ) =} . (1) 0, we can unify We can then apply the cut rule to (2) and (6) (to be strictly rigorous, we would first have to separate these two formulas, for example, replacing (2) by Rv2 =} Qav2 , and then return to the two original formulas with the help of a unifier!): (7) (Rv1 1\ Sv1 ) =}. S O L U T I O N S F O R C H A PT E R 329 4 Now we can unify Rb and Rv1 (the principal unifier is the cut rule to (4) and (7): the result is r(vt ) = b ) and apply (8) Sb =:> which, together with (5), yields the empty clause. 18. We must refute the set { F1 , F2, F3, -.G } . So we begin by putting F1 and -,G in prenex form; this produces, respectively: VvoVvt (Rvov1 ::::} Rvofvo) and VvoVvt Vv2(-.Rvov1 v ...., R v1 v2 v ...., R v2vo). Then, w e must add Skolem functions to the language i n order to rewrite these formulas as clauses; we need a unary function symbol g and a constant symbol a. We obtain ( 1 ) Rvovi =? Rvofvo (2) ==> Rvogvo (3) ::::} Rffaa (4) ( R vo vI 1\ R v 1 V2 1\ R V2 vo) =} . We may apply the rule of resolution to ( 1 ) and (2 ). To separate these clauses, we replace (2) by ==} Rv3gv3 then we unify Rv3gv3 with Rvovt (the unifier is r (vo) = v3, r (v i ) = gv3) and we obtain (5) ::::} Rv3jv3. We can then unify R v3 f v3 with R vo v 1 which occurs in the premiss of (4) (the unifier is r (vo) = V3, r (vt ) = jv3) and, after resolution, we have (Rjv3 v2 1\ Rv2 v3) =} . Replace (5) by ::::} Rvofvo to separate it from (6), then unify Rvofvo with Rv2v3 (the unifier is r (v2) vo and r (v3) = fvo). The result is (7) Rff vovo ::::} and after unifying with (3) (r (vo) = a), we obtain the empty clause. (6) == B ibliography ·---- --- ------ ------ First, we will suggest a list (no doubt very incomplete) of works concerning mathe­ matical logic. These are either general treatises on logic or more specialized books related to various topics that we have presented. There is one exception: the book edited by J. Barwise, whose ambition was to produce, at the time it was published, a survey of the state of the art. Some of these titles are now out of print but we have included them none the less because they should be available in many university libraries. J.P. Azra and B. Jaulin, Recursivite, Gauthiers-Villars, 1 973. j . Barwise (editor), Handbook of mathematical logic, North-Holland, 1 977. J.L. Bell and A.B. Machover, A course in mathematical logic, North-Holland, 1 977. J.L. Bell and A.B. Slomson, Models and ultraproducts, North-Holland, 1 97 1 . E. W. Beth, Formal methods, D. Reidel, 1 962. C.C. ChangandJ.H. Keisler, Model theory, North-Holland, 1 973. A. Church, Introduction to mathematical logic, Princeton University Press, I 996. P. Cohen, Set theoty and the continuum hypothesis, W.A. Benjamin, I 966. H. Curry, Foundation of mathematical logic, McGraw-Hill, 1 963. D. van Dalen, Logic and structures, Springer-Verlag, 1 983. M. Davis, Computability and unsolvability, McGraw-Hill, 1 958. F. Drake, Set theory, North-Holland, 1 979. H.D. Ebbinghaus, j. Flum and W. Thomas, Mathematical logic, Springer-Verlag, 1 984. R. Fralsse, Cours de logique mathematique, Gauthier-Villars, 1 972. J.Y. Girard� Proojtheo1y, Bibliopolis� 1 987. P. Halmos, Lectures on Boolean algebras, D. Van Nostrand, 1 963. P. Halmos, Naive set theory, Springer-Verlag, 1 987. D. Hilbert and W. Ackermann, Mathematical logic, Chelsea, 1 950. K. Hrbacek and T. Jech, Introduction to set theory, Marcel Dekker, 1 984. T. Jech, Set theoty, Academic Press, 1 978. S. Kleene, Introduction t o metamathematics, Elsevier Science, 1 97 1 . G. Kreisel and J.L. Krivine, Elements de logique mathematique, Dunod, 1 966. J.L. Krivine, Theorie des ensembles, Cassini, I 998. K. Kunen, Set theory, North-Holland, 1 985. R. Lalement, Logique, reduction, resolution, Masson, 1 990. R.C. Lyndon, Notes on logic, D. Van Nostrand, 1966. A.I. Mal'cev, The metamathematics o.falgebraic systems, North-Holland, 1 97 1 J. Malitz, An introduction to mathematical logic, Springer-Verlag, 1 979. Y. Manin,A course in mathematical logic (translated from Russian), Springer-Verlag, 1977. M. Margenstern, Langage Pascal et logique du premier ordre, Masson. 1 989 and 1 990. E. Mendelson, Introduction to mathematical logic, D. Van Nostrand, I 964. 331 BIBLIOGRAPHY P.S. Novikov, Introduction a La logique mathematique (translated from Russian), Dunod, 1 964. North-Holland, 1 989. J.F: Pabion, Logique mathematique, Hermann, 1976. R. Peter, Recursive functions, Academic Press, 1 967. B. Poizat, Coursde theorie des modeles, Nural-Mantiq wa1-Ma'rifah (distributed by Offilib, Paris), 1 985. P. Odifreddi, Classical recursion theory, D. Ponasse, Logique mathematique, OCDL, 1 967. W. Quine, Mathematical logic, Harvard University Press, 1 98 1 . W. Quine, Methods of logic, Harvard University Press, 1 989. H... Rasiowa and R. Sikorsh:i, The mathematicsofmetamathematics, PWN-Polish Scientific Publishers, 1 963. A. Robinson, Complete theories, North-Holland, 1 956. A. Robinson, Introduction t o model theory and to the metamathematics of algebra. North-Holland, 1 974. H.. Rogers, Theory of recursive functions and effective computability, McGraw-Hill, 1 967. J.lB. Rosser, Logicfor mathematicians, McGraw-Hill, 1 953. J.lR. Shoenfield, Mathematical logic, Addison-Wesley, 1 967. K .. Shiitte, Ptvof theory, Springer-Verlag, 1 977. W. Sierpinski, Cardinal and ordinal numbers, PWN-Polish Scientific Publishers, 1 965. Springer-Verlag, R. Smullyan, First order logic, Springer-Verlag, R. Sikorski, Boolean algebras, 1 960. 1968. Springer-Verlag, J. Stern, Fondements mathematiques de l 'informatique, McGraw-Hill, P. Suppes, Axiomatic set theory, D. Van Nostrand, 1 960. P. Suppes, Introduction to logic, D. Van Nostrand, 1 957. R.I. Soare, Recursively enumerable sets and degrees, 1 987. 1 990. A. Tarski, Introduction to logic and to the methodology of deductive sciences, University Press, Oxford 1 965. and R. Robinson, R.L. Vaught, Set theory, Birkhaiiser, 1 985. A. Tarski, A . Mostowski Undecidable theories, North-Holland, 1 953. Below, for the benefit of the eclectic reader whose curiosity may have been piqued, we supplement this bibliography with references to books which, while related to our subject overall, are of historical or recreational interest. L. Carroll, The game of logic, Macmillan, 1 887. M. Gardner, Paradoxes to puzzle and delight, W .H. K. . Godel, Collected works University Press, Freeman, 1 982. (published under the supervision of S. Feferman), Oxford 1 986. J. van Heijenoort, From Frege to Godel, a source book in mathematical logic ( 1879-1931), Harvard University Press, 1 967. Simon & Schuster, 1 983. R. Smullyan, What i s the name of this book?, Prentice Hall, 1 978. J. Venn, Symbolic logic, Chelsea, 1 97 1 (first edition: 18 8 1 ). A. Hodges, A lan Turing: the enigma, Index Absorption laws, 3 1 Alphabet, xviii And, 8 Antilogy. 28 Antireflexive, 61 Antitautology, 28 Appears efficiently, 227 Assignment of truth values, 2 1 Associativity, 31 Atom in a Boolean algebra. 80 Atomic Boolean algebra, 80 formula, 122 Automorphism of structures, 13 7 Avatar, 214 Axiom of Choice. 1 62. 165, 1 72 axiom schemes, 1 95 Axiom(s) logical, J 94 of equality, 1 79 of predicate calculus, 1 95 of quantification, 195 tautologies, 1 94 Axiomatizable, 1 70 Base (set), 1 3 1 Basis for a filter, 97 for a topology, 67 B icontinuous, 68 Boolean algebra, 7 1 ring, 7 1 space, 69 subalgebra, 87 Boolean algebra atomic, 80 complete, 107 dense. 1 08 Bound variable, 1 25 Canonical homomorphism, 9 1 Cantor set, 285 Cantor space, 285 CCNF, 38 CDNF, 38 Chain. 65 Characteristic of a field, 303 Choice function, 162 Clausal forms, 40 Clause, 40, 2 1 8 uni versaI, 230 Clean-up, 227 Clopen (set), 69 Closed formula, 1 25 term, 1 20 Closure of a formula, 1 26 CNF, 38 Cofinite, 87 Con1mutativity, 31 Compact (space), 68 Compactness theorem for predicate calculus, 1 7 1 , 209 for propositional calculus, 48 Compatability test first, 227 second, 228 333 INDEX Complement in a Boolean algebra, 75 Complemented lattice, 76 Complete Boolean algebra, 1 07 diagram, 1 76 set of connectives, 4 1 theory, 173 Completeness syntactical, 203 Completeness theorem for predicate calculus, 209 Concatenation, xviii Conclusion of a clause, 218, 230 Congruence modulo an ideal, 65 Conjunction, 8, 1 23 Conjunctive normal form, 38 prenex form, 1 60 Connective 0-ary, 57 complete set of, 41 minimal set of, 4 1 n-place, 36 Sheffer' s, 37 Consequence, 46 of a theory, 1 48 syntactic, 1 97 Consistent set of formulas, 45 theory, 148 Constant, 1 1 4 Continuity uniform, 22 Continuous map, 68 Contradiction, 1 48 Contradictory set of formulas, 45 theory, l99 contradictory in L, 1 99 Contrapositive, 32 Covering of a topological space, 68 cut rule, 2 1 9 Cycle, I90 Cycle-free, 1 90 de Morgan's laws, 32 in a Boolean algebra, 76 Decomposition tree of a formula of predicate calculus, 1 24 of propositional calculus, 1 3, 124 Deduction ru]es, 1 94 Deduction theorem, 200 Defi nability theorem, 44 Definable set, 177 with parameters, 1 78 Definition by induction, 1 1 by induction on formulas, 1 8 from above, 1 1 from below, 1 I inductive, I 1 modulo A formula, 44 of a set in a structure, 1 77 with parameters, 1 78 Dense Boolean algebra, I 08 subset of a topological space, 1 08 Derivable by cut, 236 by resolution, 236 formula, I 97 Derivation, 1 96 by cut 220 Derived by cut, 2 1 9 by resolution, 232 by simplification, 2 1 9 Diagonal, I 32 Diagram of a model, I 76 Discrete (topology), 70 Disjunction, 8, 1 23 Disjunctive normal form, 3 8 prenex form, 160 Distribution of truth values, 2 1 334 Distributive lattice, 76 Distributivity, 3 1 DNF, 38 Domain, xvii, 1 3 1 Dual filter, 93 ideal, 93 Elementary diagram, 17 6 equivalence, 170 Enrichment of a model or a structure, 1 35 Equality, 1 I 4 axioms of, 179 Equisatisfiable, I 6 1 Equivalence, 8 elementary, 1 70 of formulas, 148 of theories, 1 48 Equivalent sets of formulas, 46 Evaluation, 2 1 Existential formula, 157 quantifier, 1 14 Expansion of a model or a structure, 1 35 Extension, I 33 Extension theorem, 1 9 1 Filter dual, 93 Frechet, 95 generated by a set, 1 08 in a Boolean algebra, 93 maximal, 94 principal, 95 Filterbase, 97 Finite intersection property, 96 Finite type, 6 1 , 1 87 Finitely axiomatizable property, 1 70 Finitely consistent theory, 1 48 Finitely satisfiable, 45 Finiteness theorem, 200 INDEX First order formula, I 23 language, I I 3 First-order property, 1 7 I For all , 1 1 3 Formal proof, 1 96 Formula antilogy, 28 antitautology, 28 atomic, 1 22 avatar of, 2 I 3 canonical conjunctive normal form, 38 canonical disjunctive normal form, 38 clausal form, 40 clause, 40 closed, 1 25 conjunctive normal form, 38 conjunctive prenex form, 1 60 contradictory, 148 contrapositive of� 32 derivable, 1 97 disjunctive normal form, 38 disjunctive prenex form, 1 60 equisatisf1able, 1 6 1 existential, 1 57 in prenex form, 157 in Skolem form� 1 60 inconsistent, I 48 increasing, 60 literal, 40 logically equivalent, 28 model of, 1 43 neutral) 55 polite, I 57 prefix of, I 57 propositional, 9 pseudoformula, 53 satisfiable, 45 spectrum of, 1 86 sub-formula, 1 9 tautology, 2 7 universal, 1 57 valid, 147 with parameters, 176 Frechet (filter), 95 Free variable, I 25 . . . 335 INDEX Freely generated, 225 Functional, 1 14 Garbage collection, 227 Generalization Jrule of, 1 94 Graph, 6 1 k-colourable, 6 1 Greatest lower bound, 7 3 Group of finite type, 6 1 orderable, 6 1 torsion-free, 61 Hausdorff (space), 68 Height, I I of a formula, 1 24 of a term, 1 1 6 Henkin witness, 203 Hilbert's programme, 4 Homeomorphism, 68 Homomorphism canonical, 9 1 of Boolean algebras, 8 1 of structures, 135, 225 Ideal, 64 dual, 93 in a Boolean algebra, 90 maximal, 65 prime, 92 principal, 90 proper, 64 sum of ideals, 64 Idempotence, 3 1 Idempotent, 7 1 Identity element, 3 2 Image of a subset under a relation, 62 Implication, 8 Implies, 8 Inconsistent theory, 148 Increasing (formula), 60 Independent set of formulas, 60 Induction definition by, 1 1 Inductive, 5 1 Interpolant, 43 Interpolation lemma, 42 Interpretation, 1 3 1 o f a symbol, 1 3 1 o f a term i n a structure. 1 37 Involution, 7 5 Isolated point of a topological space, 1 08 Isomorphic structures, 1 3 7 Isomorphism of Boolean algebras, 83 of structures, 1 36 Kelley, J. L., 70 Krull's theorem, 65 L-derivation, 1 96 L-syntactic consequence, 197 Language, I 1 3 associated with a structure, 1 74 model of, 1 3 1 with equality, 1 14 Lattice, 76 complemented, 76 distributive, 76 Least upper bound, 73 Lemma interpolation, 42 Zorn's, 50 Length of a word, xviii Literal, 40 Logical axioms, 1 94 Logical equivalence, 28 Lowenheim-Skolem theorem, 3 1 9 Macdonald, I . D. , 6 1 Map bicontinuous, 68 continuous, 67 homeomorphism, 6 7 Marriage theorem, 2 70 Maximal filter, 94 ideal, 65 Metalanguage, 9 Minimal set of connectives, 41 336 Model diagram of, 1 76 of a formula, 143 of a language, 1 3 1 standard, 1 89 that respects equality, 1 32 Modus ponens, 1 94 Monomorphism of structures, 1 36 Morgan, see de Morgan's laws Negation, 8, I 23 non-contradictory in L, 1 99 Non-contradictory set of formulas, 45 theory, 1 99 Normal form canonical conjunctive, 38 canonical disjunctive, 38 conjunctive, 38 disjunctive, 38 Normal form theorem, 3 9 Not, 8 Occurrence of a letter in a word, xviii Occurrence test, 228 Or, 8 Orbit, 3 1 0 Order of a cycle, 1 90 Orderable, 6 1 Parameter(s), 1 76 definable with, I 7 8 Polish notation, 1 3 1 Polite (formula), I 57 Polynomial function, 254 Positive class of formulas, 1 08 Predicate, I 1 4 Prefix of a formula, 1 57 Premiss of a clause, 2 1 8, 230 Prime ideal, 92 Principal filter, 95 INDEX ideal, 90 unifier, 227 Product topology, 70 Proof by induction on the set of formulas, I I formal, 1 96 Proper final segment, xviii ideal, 64 initial segment, xviii Property axiomatizable, 1 70 finitely axiomatizable, I 70 first-order, 1 7 1 pseudo-axiomatizable, 1 7 1 Proposition, 8 Propositionally satisfiable, 2 1 2 Pseudo-axiomatizable, 1 7 1 Pseudoformuia, 53 Quantification axioms, I 95 Quantified existentially, 1 25 universally, 1 25 Quantifier existential, I 1 3 scope of, I 26 universal, 1 1 3 Quotient ring, 66 Reduction of a model or a structure, 1 35 Refutable, 22 1 set of clauses, 235 Refutation, 221 , 235 Restriction of a model or a structure, 1 35 Rule cut, 2 I 9 deduction, I 94 of generalization, I 94 of simplification, 2 1 9 o f weights, I 1 7 o f resolution, 232 Satisfaction of a formula by an assignment, 25 of a formula in a structure, 141 of a formula in a substructure, I 66 337 INDEX of a set of formulas, 45 of a theory in a structure, 148 Satisfiable propositionally, 2 1 3 set o f formulas, 45 Scope, 1 26 Semantic consequence, 148 Semantics, 21 Separated clauses, 232 space, 68 Se[ base, 1 3 1 basic closed, 67 basic open, 67 clopen, 69 closed, 67 cofinite, 87 definable, 177 dense, 1 08 of first order formulas, 1 23 open, 67 underlying, 1 3 1 Sheffer strokes, 57 Sheffer's connectives, 37 Simple diagram of a model, 176 Sitnplification, 227 rule of, 2 1 9 Singleton, 7 9 Skolem normal form, 1 60 Space Boolean, 69 Cantor, 285 compact, 68 Hausdorff, 68 separated. 68 Stone, 98 zero-dimensional, 69 Spectrum of a formula, I 86 Splitting, 1 09 Standard model, 189 Stone space. 98 Stone's theorem, 97, I 02 Structure, 1 3 1 isomorphic, 1 36 language associated with, 1 74 of finite type, 1 87 theory of, 1 73 Sub-formula, 19, 124 Subcovering of a topological space, 68 Submodel, 1 33 Substitution in a propositional formula, 1 9 in terms, 1 2 1 o f terms, 1 27 order of, 2 1 Substitution(s), 225 Substructure, 1 3 3 generated by, 1 34 generated by a subset, 186 Symbol binary, 8 constant, I 14 equality, 1 1 4 for propositional connective, 8 for Skolem functions, 1 60 function, 1 14 non-logical, 1 14 one-place, 8 predicate, 1 14 relation, 1 1 4 two-place, 8 unary, 8 Symmetric difference, 58 Syntactic consequence, 1 97 Syntactically complete, 203 Syntax, 8 System, 226 Tautology of the predicate calculus, 1 50 of the propositional calculus, 27 Term, l 1 5 closed, 120 Theorem, 1 97 compactness for predicate calculus, 1 7 1 , 209 for propositional calculus, 48 completeness for predicate calculus, 208 Deduction, 201 Definability, 44 existence of prenex form, 157 338 INDEX finiteness, 200 Krull's, 66 Lowenheim-Skolem, 3 1 9 marriage, 270 normal form, 39 Stone's, I 02 Tychonoff's, 70 to prove the compactness theorem, 71 Ultrafilter, 97 Unique decomposition for propositional calculus, 1 5 Unique readability for formulas, 1 24 for pseudoformulas. 53. 246 for terms, 1 20 Theory, 148 complete, 1 73 consistent, 148 contradictory, 1 48, 1 99 finitely satisfiable, 148 inconsistent, 148 non-contradictory, I 99 of a structure, 1 7 3 There exists , I I 4 Topology basic closed sets, 67 basic open sets, 67 basis for, 67 discrete, 70 Hausdorff, 68 induced, 67 product, 69 separated, 68 Torsion element, 267 Torsion-free, 6 1 Tree decomposition tree of a formula of predicate calculus, 1 24 of propositional calculus, 14 root of, 1 4 Trivial homomorphism, 95 ultrafilter, 95 True in a model, 1 43 Truth table(s), 25 ... Truth value(s), 2 1 assignment of, 22 Tychonoff, 70 Type of an element i n a structure, 1 9 1 Ultrafilter, 94 Ultrafilter theorem, 97 Underlying (set), 1 3 1 Unifier, 226 principal. 227 Uniform continuity, 22 Unify, 226 Unique readability theorem for formulas, 1 24 for pseudoformulas, 246 for terms, 1 20 Universal clause, 230 closure, 1 26 formula, 1 57 Valid (formula), 1 47 Valuation, 2 1 Variable bound, 1 25 changing the name of, 1 28 free. 1 25 propositional, 8 Weight of a constant symbol, 1 1 7 of a function symbol, 1 1 7 of a variable, 1 17 of a word, 1 1 7 rule of, 1 1 7 Well-ordering, 1 90 Word final segment of, xviii initial segment of, xviii left simplification of, xix on an alphabet, xviii right simplification of, xix Zero element. 32 Zero-dimensional (space), 69 Zorn's lemma, 50, 65, 70, 208, 209