An Aristotelian Geometry of Just Distributon Gerhard Michael Ambrosi University of Trier; ambrosi@uni-trier.de October 13, 2022 Contents 1 Introduction 2 2 The text 3 3 The geometry of just distribution 5 4 Concluding remarks 9 References 10 List of Figures 1 The geometry of the just in distribution . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 6 List of Tables Abstract There is much musing in the modern literature why Euclid did not arrange differently the subject matters of the Elements. We do not question the fruitfulness of such considerations. But we argue here for taking also a phenomenological approach. The ancient treatments of reciprocity can be seen as “phenomena” of ancient geometrical and also of ethical discussion (Aristotle). Ours is an attempt to have a new look at these old phenomena. 1 1 Introduction In Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics the concept of “just distribution” seems to change its appearance from being intuitively intelligible to being not knowable. In chapter 3 of Book V (NE V,3 henceforth) one reads at 1131a25 (Bekker (1831)-line): “all agree that what is just in distributions ought to accord with a certain merit.”1 In this passage it is taken for granted that “all agree” about what is just in distribution. At this point this topic appears as being intuitively clear. Subsequently, at 1131b10f., and after some elementary exercises with ratios and proportions, Aristotle writes: Therefore, the combination of term A with C and of term B with D is what is just in the distribution; and the just here is a middle term,2 for the proportion is a middle term and the just is a proportion. Hardie (1980, p. 189) comments that this statement cannot be understood as being based on something knowable in a mathematical sense: There is no question here of arriving at a knowledge of the mean by a mathematical calculation, or quasi-mathematical quasi-calculation, which starts from a knowledge of extremes. There seems to be a strange contradiction here between Aristotle’s repeated reference to mathematical expressions on the one hand and what sensibly can be expressed with such expressions on the other hand. In the context of Hardie’s remark one is inclined to think of John Burnet’s (1900, p. v) comment that “Book V is notoriously difficult owing to the use made in it of mathematical formulas. . . which seem to give the writer almost as much trouble as they have given to his editors.” In view of these difficulties we suggest to reconsider Aristotle’s “formulas”. In this we follow a remark by Reviel Netz (1998, p. 37): “The metonym of ancient science is a diagram, a visual representation.” For moderns the corresponding metonym – the mental image – of science is “a formula, a symbolic text”.3 Aristotle’s “formulas” should then be seen in a different way than modern ones. In a scientific or otherwise systematic deductive context – philosophical considerations about ethics in the present case – Aristotle’s letter symbols are most likely to refer to a “lettered diagram” as discussed by Netz (1999) in a treatise about ancient Greek mathematical deduction. Rackham (2003 [1926], p. 270) already has two footnotes that diagrams were displayed in the discussion of proportions and of just distribution. No diagram has survived in connection with Aristotle’s text. 1 This and the next translation by Bartlett and Collins (2011, p. 95). At p.... the authors have an interesting comment concerning the term “the just”: 2 At this point Bartlett and Collins’ translation adds:“whereas the unjust is what is contrary to the proportion”. This mentioning of “unjust”, adikon, is not in Bekker (1831), only as an insert in Bywater (1890, p. 95). 3 Netz, ibid. He suggests the formula E = mc2 as “symbol of Einstein”, the modern scientist. 2 Neither Rackham nor any other well known translator and / or commentator has made the attempt to reconstruct a diagram for just distribution as a “middle term”. There is an interesting proposal by T.R. Keyser (1992) for a diagram in connection with NE V,3. But that proposal does not address the problematic passage about the proportion being “a middle term”. Thus it is still a desideratum to find an “Aristotelian” lettered diagram which deals with this problem. This desideratum will be addressed in the following. 2 The text After having stated that “all agree” about just distribution, Aristotle engages in some symbolic and argumentative exercises dealing with ratios and proportions in a just distribution. This passage addresses its readers in a remarkably elementary mathematical style. In commenting Aristotle’s treatment of just distribution, Keyt (1991) refers several times to Euclid’s Elements (Prop. V. 11, 16, 18, and the definition for similarity at VI, Def. 1.). Before and after presenting his specific proportions for a just distribution, Aristotle has some general remarks about proportions. Thomas Heath (1956, p. 131) invokes them in his influential English translation of the Elements. He observes that at 1131a31ff. Aristotle writes that “proportion is in four terms at least”. This, Heath (p. 131) points out, anticipates Euclid, V, Def. 8 (“A proportion in three terms is least.”). Aristotle explicitly addresses the seeming difference between his statement and Euclid’s definition – which is, of course, written many years later. In essence he points out that a “discrete proportion” has four letters (A:B::C:D), but a “continuous proportion” has three (A:B::B:C). Since the latter has also four terms, since one letter appears twice, the difference between the two statements is only an apparent one. Heath comments (ibid.) that Aristotle’s “distinction between discrete and continuous seems to have been Pythagorean”. It is not clear, however, what this means in terms of the history of such formulations. According to Zhmud (2012, p. 265) there is a “plausible” (his term) report by Nicomachus of Gerasa (fl. ca. 100 AD) that “the arithmetic, geometric, and harmonic proportions came down from Pythagoras to Plato and Aristotle”. Whether Pythagoras himself was the inventor of these proportions is doubtful. But scholars At 1131b15, after having made his formal point about the proportion of a just distribution, Aristotle returns to this distinction, again in a very basic way by remarking that “we cannot get a single term standing for a person and a thing”, and hence a just distribution “is not continuous”. No ethical conclusion are drawn from the latter remark. The details of a proportion for a just distribution are developed in Aristotle’s text between lines 1131b5-10:4 4 The quotes in this section follow the translation by Ross (1925) as they appear at the Bekker-lines just listed. 3 [i]As the term A, then, is to B [the persons], so will C be to D [the shares], [ii] and therefore, alternando, as A is to C , B will be to D. Therefore also [iii] the whole is in the same ratio to the whole [A+C:B+D::A:B];. . . [iv] The conjunction, then, of the term A with C and of B with D is what is just in distribution, [A+C:B+D::C:D]. . . It is maybe of some interest to check the mathematical soundness of these items and to list their relation to corresponding passages in Euclid’s Elements.5 But, as already briefly mentioned, the narrow correspondence between Aristotle’s items and the corresponding passages in the Elements should not be understood as an expression of Aristotelian prescience. It is rather an expression that these matters were known long before Aristotle and probably were transmitted either from Pythagoras (Zhmud) or from younger Pythagorean authors. Item [i]: El., V, Def. 6, “Let magnitudes having the same ratio be called proportional.” Item [ii]: El., V, Def. 12, “Alternate ratio is taking the antecedent to the antecedent and consequent to the consequent.” (ibid.) Correspondingly, there is Prop. V,16: “If four magnitudes are proportional, they will also be alternately proportional.” Items [iii] and [iv]: El., Prop. V,18, “If divided magnitudes are proportional, they will also be proportional when compounded.” In the latter context a further relevant text item may be listed [v] it is in geometrical proportion that it follows that the whole is to the whole as either part is to the corresponding part.) 1131b Perseus http://data.perseus.org/citations/urn:cts:greekLit:tlg0086. tlg010.perseus-eng1:1131b "The principle of Distributive Justice, therefore, is the conjunction of the first term [A] of a proportion with the third [C] and of the second [B] with the fourth [D]; and the just in this sense is a mean between two extremes that are disproportionate, since the proportionate is a mean, and the just is the proportionate." Hardie commenting on 1131b9-10 “The just share is a mean in the sense that it could fail to be according to the proportion, i.e. could fail to be just, either by being too large or by being too small. There is no question here of arriving at a knowledge of the mean by a mathematical calculation, or quasi-mathematical quasi-calculation, which starts from a knowledge of extremes.” It is naively formalistic, of course, when, after some general remarks about proportions and numbers, Aristotle writes (1131b4ff. B-C, p. 96) that the just “is 5 The references to the Elements follow the translations in Mueller (1981, pp. 317–370): “Appendix 4, The Contents of the Elements” 4 divided into at least four terms”, and that in just distribution “the ratio is the same, for it is divided similarly between the persons and the things involved.”6 This is then followed by several letter symbols describing proportions and their variations in ways which anticipate some items in Euclid’s Elements (Roman numbering by the present author, other inserts by the translators): “[i] Therefore, as the term A is to B [the persons], so also C is to D [the things];7 [ii] and so too alternately, as A is to C , so B is to D.8 [iii] So too, as a result, is the whole to the whole [(A+C):(B+D)::(A:B)]. . . 9 [iv] Therefore, the combination of term A with C and of term B with D is what is just in the distribution; [v] and the just here is a middle term Some commentators, e.g. Rackham (2003 [1926], 274, n. c), are convinced that this text is matched by geometrical diagrams.10 No diagrams have survived together with Aristotle’s text. Few commentators have endeavored to reconstruct the associated geometrical diagrams.11 But it seems to be clear that, in the above list, item [i] corresponds to figure 1 (a) and item [iv] corresponds to 1 (b), as will be briefly argued below. 3 The geometry of just distribution There is a frequently quoted author who traces the correspondance between Aristotle and the Elements. These proportions were used in the Pythagorean harmonics, and there are Aristotle’s presentation of a “refined” doctrine about just distribution is often treated as if it were his very own teaching. It is in this sense that, e.g., under the title of “Aristotle’s doctrine of justice” Kelsen (1957, p. 128) writes: Aristotle’s definition of distributive justice is but a mathematical formulation of the well-known principle suum cuique. . . But this tautology [is]. . . legitimizing the positive law . . . 6 This comes after Aristotle’s textbook remark at 1131a31 that “proportion is an equality of ratios, and it involves at least four terms.” Heath (1956, p. 119) observes that with this line Aristotle “appears to be quoting from the Pythagoreans”. 7 El., V, Def. 6: “Let magnitudes having the same ratio be called proportional.” (Mueller, p.331) 8 El., V, Def. 12: “Alternate ratio is taking the antecedent to the antecedent and consequent to the consequent.” (ibid.) Prop. V,16: “If four magnitudes are proportional, they will also be alternately proportional.” (Mueller, p. 333) 9 El., Prop. V,18: “If divided magnitudes are proportional, they will also be proportional when compounded.” (Mueller, p. 333) 10 In more general terms see Netz (1999, p. 15): “Aristotle used the lettered diagram in his lectures. The letters in the text would make sense if they refer to diagrams – which is asserted in a few places.” Netz (n. 12) gives as example Meteor. 363a25-6, but not the Nicomachean Ethics. 11 See, however, Keyser (1992) for a longer and interesting discussion of this issue. His figure 2 is similar to our figure 1 (a), except that he introduces “minuscule letters εζϑ for ease of reference” to auxiliary lines (p. 142). The parallel lines of his construction are analogous to the preset lines “A” and “B” and no additional letter-symbols are needed here. 5 (a) Proportion; Euclid, El., Def. V,6; Prop. V,12 (b)The just as “middle term”; cf. Euclid, El., Prop. V,18. Figure 1: The geometry of the just in distribution We propose, however, to see Aristotle’s presentation of this matter as part of a dialectical argumentation which involves the stock-taking of the “reputable beliefs” of others. In that case the following formulations express not necessarily his own conviction, but they are candidates for later puzzlement over their implications and / or about their limited validity. Strictly speaking, in order to illustrate distribution according to merit as a proportion, only figure 1 (a) is needed: the ratio of merits, represented by the parallel lines A resp. B, is equal to the ratio of just rewards which are represented by the sections C resp. D on the perpendicular line connecting the matching endpoints of the parallels so that two similar triangles are formed by a line connecting the outer endpoints of the lines marked A and B.12 Above, the second item in the quote, [ii], describes the same diagram as item [i], with specific passages in Euclid’s Elements applying to this case of “alternation”, as is indicated by a footnote attached to item [ii]. Figure 1 (b) is described by items [iii] and [iv] above. It represents a geometrical addition of lines C resp. D to lines A resp. B by forming two isosceles triangles in addition to the former ones. The figure is made symmetrical by choosing the appropriate scaling of the lines, their absolute lengths being not relevant since the discussion is only in terms of ratios. The symmetrical form of figure 1 (b) corresponds in appearance to an observation by Saito and Sidoli (2012, p. 140) in an article about “Diagrams and arguments in ancient Greek mathematics”. Under the section heading “Overspecification” the authors write (p. 140f.): One of the most pervasive features of the manuscript figures is the tendency to represent more regularity among the geometric objects than is demanded by the argument. 12 Since A:B must be equal to C:D it seems to be irritating that just before this list of ratios Aristotle writes that these two ratios are similarly divided , not using the word “equal”. This expression might be due to the geometrical solution of fig. 1 (a) producing two similar triangles, and this might explain Aristotle’s choice of words. For his definition of geometrical similarity see Posterior Analytics. 99a12-14. 6 In many manuscripts they find “symmetry in the figure where none is required by the text.” This tendency towards overspecification “is so prevalent . . . that it almost certainly reflects ancient practice.” The background of this practice is that for reasons to be discovered by specialist scholars, the ancient geometers were prepared to adjust their scaling accordingly. The lines of fig. 1 (b) are “overspecified” by having their respective units defined for a symmetrical appearance. The axis of symmetry is the line with the two segments depicting “just distribution” (ratio of C:D). Although “just distribution” gives vertical line segments which typically are not equal (typically C̸= D), the horizontal lines to its left and right are of equal length. Thus one has here not only an equality of ratios, their single elements typically being not equal to each other, but also a symmetrical horizontal equality of lines, giving a visual expression of equality and of a mean between left and right. This is what is called for by Aristotle’s text marked as item [v] above. If one goes by fig. 1 (b) one can interpret the last aspect of Aristotle’s text fairly easily: The line which gives the just distribution is the axis of symmetry with sections C:D. This line is a “middle term” in so far as it stands in the middle of the figure. But it is not the line itself which depicts the just distribution. It is rather the ratio of the two sections on this line. This ratio of just distribution can be stated verbally or by letter symbols as one has it in the surviving text of the Nicomachean Ethics. In principle, any geometrical construction could have accompanied that text as long as the issue is simply to represent that ratio – be it now our fig. 1 (a), or any one of the two figures offered by Keyser (1992). It is, however, only the present fig. 1 (b) which justifies the “bloating” of the simple proportion of just distribution by invoking – or rather: by anticipating – the Euclidean Prop. V,18 about “combining” terms of a proportion while maintaining the original, the just, ratio, namely by having the line of the just ratio as a middle term. A further aspect Without the geometry of fig. 1 (b) it is difficult to give a plausible reason why in the text on 1131b9-10 Aristotle combines “A with C” and “B with D” and then he claims that “the just here is a middle term”. This does not make any mathematical sense as far as arithmetics is concerned, as Hardie (1980, p. 189) observes in commenting this passage: There is no question here of arriving at a knowledge of the mean by a mathematical calculation, or quasi-mathematical quasi-calculation, which starts from a knowledge of extremes. What is the point of Aristotle’s characterising a just distribution by equating “the whole to the whole” to “A:B”? Commentators have great difficulties to give a plausible reason.13 It is most unlikely that Aristotle himself “wants” this formula.14 13 See, e.g., Keyt (1991, p. 241) who claims: Aristotle “wants his formula to display the yoking together (hê suzeuxis)” – but why does Aristotle want that? 14 See the antecedent footnote. 7 He rather has it in order to expose a “reputable belief”. Aristotle is well aware of the problem of commensurability of magnitudes. This appears a few lines further down in chapter NE V,5 at line 1133b19 where he stresses: “it is impossible for things that differ greatly from one another to become commensurable”. Certainly the measurement of the worth of a person differs greatly from the measurement of a piece of land.15 It is true that the just quoted line continues that “with respect to need” relative measurement sufficiently possible. This is practiced daily in market exchange, establishing, e.g., an exchange rate of “house : beds” as being “1:5” (example given by Aristotle in NE V,5 on lines ) to the problem of “homogeneity”. In the context of tracing a dialectical argument the answer is that here the As indicated by the captions, part (a) the first, only in a bloated way. It might appear as being either an unnecessary Pythagoreanism, in any case it is an anticipation of Euclid, Elements, Proposition V,12.16 The last quoted item reveals a possible purpose of “bloating” the basic result. By choosing an appropriate scale for the good which has to be passed out, the “just” point can be made to appear as the intersection of two 45-degree lines which intersect at right angles. The result has an appealingly symmetrical appearance with a middle line depicting the result of a “just” distribution. Item three of the quote can be interpreted as having been written for the purpose of giving a verbal expression for the visual appearance of fig. 1 (b). This particular shape of the figure depends on choosing the unit of accounting in a very particular way. An unfriendly characterisation of this type of measurement might call it to be “quantophrenic”. Its geometrical version is given by fig. 1 (b). One link to a Pythagorean mathematical tradition comes via Aristotle’s argumentation which involves proportions. In his text the just mentioned “accord” between merit and just distribution is determined by proportionality. This motivates Aristotle to resort to a very basic recapitulation of definitions and postulates which clearly agree with Pythagorean doctrine. Thomas Heath (p. 119), for example, notes that in the (present) chapter on distributive justice, line 1131a31, Aristotle writes that “proportion is an equality of ratios, and it involves at least four terms”. In this line “he appears to be quoting from the Pythagoreans”.17 Not only Aristotle’s formal discussion of proportionality agrees with a tradition which “came down from Pythagoras” (Zhmud). The presentation of this tradition and its ethical application by Aristotle seems to be a reception – maybe a caricature – of Pythagorean doctrine on “particular justice”. It is remarkably basic and bloated.18 15 This is the example used by Keyt, as referred to in the two preceding footnotes. p. 160: Euclid’s theorem V,12 “is quoted [sic] by Aristotle, Eth. Nic. . . . 1131b14”. Artmann (1999, p. 125) sees “Prop. V, 12 as a simple arithmetical or geometrical consequence: a : b = c : d ⇒ (a + c) : (b + d) = a : b ”. 17 Compare Zhmud (2012, p. 265). He considers it as being “plausible” that “the arithmetic, geometric, and harmonic proportions came down from Pythagoras to Plato and Aristotle”. 18 See above, n. ??: Aristotle (!) produces “pedestrian,. . . pompous common sense”. 16 Heath, 8 4 Concluding remarks When Aristotle writes that in the case of a just distribution “the proportion is a middle term”, then this should not be understood as being one of the “mathematical formulas” about which Burnet complained. It should be rather understood as referring to the middle term in a lettered diagram, the latter being a specimen of a means of deduction which is frequently used by Aristotle according to Netz. The obvious problem is that in Indeed, in recent years several authors have put enhanced emphasis on the importance of geometry in ancient scientific deduction.19 Although Netz (1999, p. 15) does not refer to the Nicomachean Ethics in this context, it is relevant here that he observes: “Aristotle used the lettered diagram in his lectures. The letters in the text would make sense if they refer to diagrams”. The issue 19 Saito and Sidoli (2012). Netz (1998, p. 37): “The metonym of ancient science is a diagram, a visual representation.” 9 References Artmann, B. (1999). Euclid: the creation of mathematics. New York, Berlin, etc.: Springer. URL: http://books.google.de/books?id=Hp2DQgAACAAJ (cit. on p. 8). Bartlett, R. C. and S. D. Collins (2011). Aristotle’s Nicomachean ethics – translated, with an interpretive essay, notes, and glossary. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press (cit. on p. 2). Bekker, I. (1831). [Aristotelis opera] Aristoteles Graece. Vol. 2. Berlin: Academia Regia Borussica and Georg Reimer. eprint: https : / / archive . org / details/aristotelisopera02arisrich (cit. on p. 2). Burnet, J. (1900). The ethics of Aristotle with an introduction and notes. Philosophy of Plato and Aristotle. London: Methuen (cit. on p. 2). Bywater, I. (1890). Aristotelis Ethica Nicomachea; recognovit brevique adnotatione critica instruxit. Oxford: Clarendon. URL: https://archive.org/ details/aristoteliseth00aris/ (cit. on p. 2). Hardie, W. F. R. (1980). Aristotle’s Ethical Theory. 2nd ed. Oxford: Clarendon (cit. on pp. 2, 7). Heath, T. L. (1956). The Thirteen Books of Euclid’s Elements – Translated from the text of Heiberg with introduction and commentary. 2nd ed. Vol. II - Books III – IX. New York: Dover Publications (cit. on pp. 3, 5). Kelsen, H. (1957). “Aristotle’s Doctrine of Justice”. In: What Is Justice: Justice, Law, and Politics in the Mirror of Science : Collected Essays of Hans Kelsen. quoted from Lawbook Exchange Ltd , September 2000, The University of California Press, pp. 110–136 (cit. on p. 5). Keyser, P. T. (1992). “A Proposed Diagram in Aristotle "EN", V3, 1131a24–b20 for Distributive Justice in Proportion”. In: Apeiron 25, pp. 135–144 (cit. on pp. 3, 5, 7). Keyt, D. (1991). “Aristotle’s Theory of Distributive Justice”. In: A Companion to Aristotle’s Politics. Ed. by D. Keyt and J. Fred D. Miller. substantially revised version of ‘”Distributive Justice in Aristotle’s Ethics and Politics, in: Topoi, 4 (1985), pp. 23-45. Oxford, UK and Cambridge, USA: Blackwell. Chap. 11, pp. 238–78 (cit. on pp. 3, 7). Mueller, I. (1981). Philosophy of Mathematics and Deductive Structure in Euclid’s Elements. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press (cit. on p. 4). Netz, R. (1998). “Greek Mathematical Diagrams: Their Use and Their Meaning”. In: For the Learning of Mathematics 18.3, pp. 33–39. URL: http://www. jstor.org/stable/40248278 (cit. on pp. 2, 9). – (1999). The Shaping of Deduction in Greek Mathematics: A Study in Cognitive History. Ideas in context, 51. Cambridge etc.: Cambridge U.P. (cit. on pp. 2, 5, 9). Rackham, H. (2003 [1926]). Aristotle XIV – The Nicomachean Ethics with an English Translation. Loeb Classical Library, L73. (This text also as a Perseus internet edition http : / / data . perseus . org / catalog / urn : cts : 10 greekLit:tlg0086.tlg010.perseus- eng1, URL visited on 10.10. 2022.) Cambridge, Mass. and London: Harvard University Press (cit. on pp. 2, 5). Ross, W. D., ed. (1925). The Works of Aristotle – translated into English. Vol. IX. Oxford: The Clarendon Press (cit. on p. 3). Saito, K. and N. Sidoli (2012). “Diagrams and arguments in ancient Greek mathematics: lessons drawn from comparisons of the manuscript diagrams with those in modern critical editions”. In: The History of Mathematical Proof In Ancient Traditions. Ed. by K. Chemla. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Chap. 2, pp. 135–162 (cit. on pp. 6, 9). Zhmud, L. J. (2012). Pythagoras and the Early Pythagoreans. Oxford: OUP. URL: http://books.google.de/books?id=of-ghBD9q1QC (cit. on pp. 3, 8). 11