See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.net/publication/326400648 GALILEO'S MANUSCRIPT 72 : GENESIS OF THE NEW SCIENCE OF MOTION (Padua, ca. 1600 -1609) Preprint · August 1996 CITATIONS READS 0 769 1 author: Mohammed Abattouy Mohammed V University of Rabat 47 PUBLICATIONS 66 CITATIONS SEE PROFILE Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects: History of mechanics, in the context of the long term and broad history of physics View project Galileo Research View project All content following this page was uploaded by Mohammed Abattouy on 14 July 2018. The user has requested enhancement of the downloaded file. GALILEO'S MANUSCRIPT 72 : GENESIS OF THE NEW SCIENCE OF MOTION (Padua, ca. 1600 -1609) With a General Presentation of the Manuscript Mohamed ABATTOUY * University of Fez, Morocco Max Planck Institute for the History of Science, Berlin * Address of the author: - Max Planck Instiute for History of Science, Wilhelmstrasse, 44. D-10117 Berlin. E-mail: abattouy@mpiwg-berlin.mpg.de. - Department of Philosophy, Faculty of Letters and Human Sciences, Dhar el-Mehraz - Fez University. P. O. Box 50. 30001. Fez, Morocco. Acknowledgment Originally, this text has been presented in a lecture given at the Max Planck Institut für Wissenschaftsgeschichte in Berlin in March 27, 1996. I expanded and revised it during a stay of research of four months (July through October 1996) in the MPIWG . I thank Professor Dr. Jürgen RENN, Director of the Institute, who invited me for this stay of research in the MPIWG in Berlin during which, among other things, I revised this text and participated to the rich work of research which is being done in the Institute. This stay was the beginning of a collaboration that lasted for eight years (1996-2003) and which was very fruitful on the scientific level. I also want to thank all the staff of the Institute for the help they afforded to me, and specially Jochen SCHNEIDER, the Research Coordinator, and Urs Schoepflin, the head Librarian and their collaborator. Should this work be the expression of my gratitude to all of you. Finally, I would like to thank my colleagues and friends Sadik RADDAD (University of Fez) and Paul WEINIG (Max Planck Institute for History of Science, Berlin) who revised my English. Of course, I am responsible of all the remaining errors M. A. _____________________________________________ Abbreviations * degV (A) = degree of velocity in A. * m (AB, AC) = mean proportional between AB and AC. * mom grav (CE) = momentum gravitatis along CE. * mom vel (A) or mom vel (AB) = momentum velocitatis in A or along AB. * mom (C) = momentum or momento at C. * t (AB) = time of motion along AB from rest. * t (BC, A) = time of motion on BC, after a previous descent from A. * tard (FB) = tarditas or tardity on FB. * tot mom = totale momentum or momento totale. * v (C) = instantaneous velocity in C. * V(AB) = velocity on AB or speed acquired in descent from A to B. TABLE OF CONTENTS Acknowledgment ....................................................................................................... 2 Abbreviations .............................................................................. ............................... 2 Introduction .............................................................................................................. 4 I. Prolegomena ......................................................................................................... 7 1. Description of the Manuscript ........................................................................... 7 2. On the problem of datation ................................................................................ 11 3. Preliminary work in natural philosophy and mechanics .................................. 13 3. 1. De motu antiquiora.............................................................................................. 13 3. 2. Le Mecaniche......................................................................................................... 17 II. First Discoveries, First Demonstrations ………........................................ 21 1. Isochronism and paths of least-time .......................................................... 22 1. 2. Attempts to demonstrate the law of chords .............................................. 25 1. 3. Preliminary demonstrations of Theorem XXII ......................................... 28 2. Comparison of motions on different slopes ....................................................... 29 2. 1. Folio 173r : geometrical exercises ...................................................................... 30 2. 2. Folios 177 r-v and 180r : the Right-Angle Theorem 30 III. INVESTIGATIONS ABOUT VELOCITY AND FREE FALL 35 1. Speculations and paradoxes about velocity and acceleration 35 1.1.Dynamical approach to the problem of velocity 35 1.2.Emergence of the Rule of Double Distance 37 1.3. A paradox on velocity 40 2. Derivation of the Law of fall: The crisis of 1604 41 2.1. Official Announcement of the Times-squared theorem 42 2.2. Kinematical demonstration of the Mean Proportional 43 2.3. Physical proof and indications on the resolution of the crisis 45 2.4. Formal deduction of the Times-squared theorem 46 IV. AFTER 1604: NEW RESEARCHES ON FREE FALL AND FURTHER RESULTS 1. Demonstration of the Length-Time Theorem 53 2. Return to a dynamical foundation 58 3. Deduction of the proportionality Time-Velocity 60 4. Final stage 70 BIBLIOGRAPHY 75 INTRODUCTION In this text, I will expose a general view of Galileo's work on motion in Padua between ca. 1600 and 1609. During this period, the pisan scientist developed a new theory of motion without equivalent in the past of the scientific thought. Before he was distracted by the news of the telescope and before he began his astronomical observations and the subsequent Copernican campaign he conducted after his move to Florence in 1610, Galileo –as a "professor of mathematics" in Padua university and as a private researcher in physics and natural philosophy– carried on/executed an intense program of work in which he studied different physical questions, centered essentially on the problems of motion. In this laborious research, he discovered many of the theorems and propositions that constituted the nucleon of his last great publication, the Discorsi e dimostrazioni matematiche (1638) where he delivered to the scientific community the foundations of two new sciences, the theoretical mechanics (or "scientia de motu locali") and the resistance of materials. In the following reconstruction of Galileo's scientific work on motion in the decisive period of the first decade of the XVIIth century, I will have recourse systematically to some manuscript documents preserved in the Manoscritti Galileiani in Florence –especially to a group of notes preserved in the famous Volume 72. In order to fill the gaps left by these manuscripts, I will also use the data furnished by a group of letters written or received by Galileo between 1602 and 1610 which provide valuable information on the evolution of his physical thought. After an introduction, the first section will describe the Manuscript Volume which contains the notes on motion, with the presentation of some historiographical elements related to the study of these documents. This section will also present the conceptual background in which the first discoveries accomplished by Galileo in the field of motion were deeply rooted, that is the framework constituted by the pisan De motu and the paduan Mecaniche. Section II deals with the early scientific discoveries realized by Galileo and with his attempts in order to found them on mathematical proofs. Section III is devoted to the presentation of the work on free fall in the period gravitating about the last quarter of 1604, as it is extant in some documents associated with the letter to Sarpi. Finally, Section IV is imparted to the investigations that can be dated approximately in the limits of the period after 1604, until the beginning of the astronomical program in late 1609. After Galileo left Padua in 1610, he was occupied almost continually by other things than his work on motion, to which he returned only occasionally. This situation didn't find an end before his engagement in the redaction of the Dialogo and in the preparation of a systematic treatise on motion about 1630, which was published in its final version in the Discorsi e dimostrazioni matematiche (1638). I don't pretend to provide an extensive study of the subject-matter. In reality, a complete reconstruction of Galileo's work in the first quarter century of his scientific career can hardly be said to be in the scope of a unique scholar. In the actual state of the Galilean studies, a thorough analysis of the notes on motion bounded in Vol. 72 requires a collective undertaking and a close collaboration between researchers of various competences (historical, mathematical, philological, paleographical...) In the following brief and limited panorama, I propose to analyze some selected documents with the aim of drawing a general picture describing the evolution of Galileo's theory of motion. I think that we don't actually need to produce supplementary scenarii for partial orderings of the manuscript material in Vol. 72 and to describe the possible ways along which Galileo's thought may have evolved. There are enough of these partial reconstructions. What can give a new departure to the Galilean studies is the concentration of the endeavours of specialists in the elaboration of a global and well documented interpretation of all the material which can inform us on the genesis of the Galilean science of motion. Evidently, it is an immense task and a fascinating one. Such an endeavour is undoubdetdly an international undertaking and requires an intense collaboration on various levels. After the large debate raised by the studies on Galileo's notes on motion in the last three decades, the future of the Galilean studies depends probably on the realisation of such a mission. I. PROLEGOMENA 1. Description of the Manuscript The Vol. 72 or Codex A of the Manoscritti Galileiani (Divisione 2a-Parte 5a, Tomo 2) in the Biblioteca Nazionale di Firenze (BNF) is a volume of Galileo's original papers that comprises specifically all the manuscript material of his work on motion and some other sheets concerned with other topics. It is composed of 241 miscellaneous folios of 345-235 mm in size. The numbering of the sheets begins from 1 to 196. Actually, folio 1 bears the title of the volume: Opere / di / Galileo Galilei / Parte 5 / Tomo 2 / Meccanica1, while folio 2 contains the table of contents of the volume. The first 32 folios are devoted to diverse topics. Folios 9-26 are an incomplete copy of Le Mecaniche, a Galilean treatise on simple machines, while another complete copy of the same treatise is inserted between folios 27bis and 28 1 According to the classification made by V. Antinori in the 19th century, Vol. 72 was classified as Tomo II of the Parte V (that comprises the ten volumes of the Galilean Collection in the BNF devoted to the writings on "Meccanica" (science of motion and related topics) of the Divisione II. The attribution of numbers to the successive volumes of the Manoscritti Galileiani evokes a chronological ordering. For example, we note the strict succession between Vol. 71 (Div. 2a - Parte 5a, t. 1) and Vol. 72 (Div. 2a - Parte 5a, t. 2). The former contains the pisan De motu antiquiora, while the latter gathers together Le Mecaniche and the notes on motion. –in the form of a treatise of 40 folios that bears independent numbering from 1 to 402. The other components of these preliminary sheets are: a copy of an early work on centers of gravity (ff. 3-6), a copy of the treatment of the properties of the lever (f. 27r-v) (Opere, VIII, pp. 366.1-367.14)3, two drafts of the original dedication of the Discorsi by Galileo to the "Conte de Noailles" (f. 28r-v), and the preface to the same Discorsi (ff. 31-32) 4. The notes on motion begin properly from f. 33r to f. 194r. The great part of these notes are autograph drafts in the original hand of Galileo, but almost 30 sheets exist which are copies written by two of his disciples, Mario Guiducci and Nicolò Arrighetti, perhaps under the direction of the Master in Florence betwenn 1616 and 16185. These copies were made from Galilean original material and many of these copies also contain corrections and additions in the hand of Galileo. All the notes of Vol. 72 –whether original material or later copies– have a direct relation to propositions, theorems, scholia, lemma and problems presented and discussed in the Discorsi, and especially to those of the De motu locali, the mathematical treatise of the third and fourth days of this book 6. In general, they are more or less complete versions of the published propositions. The importance of this manuscript material for the study and the reconstruction of the development of Galileo's science of motion has been recognized since the work of Caverni (1891-1900). In the eighth volume of the Edizione Nazionale of the Opere di Galileo Galilei, Favaro edited the great part of these documents as footnotes to the corresponding propositions of DML or as an Appendix to the Discorsi (Galilei, 1898). It was not however until the last quarter of this century that they became the centre of Galilean studies and focalised upon them the attention of historians concerned with the question of the genesis of the new science of motion in the XVIIth century7. Effectively, these private notes were Procissi (1959, p. 152) remarks in the two cases: "Copia corrispondente a quanto è stato pubblicato in Gal., Ediz. Naz., II, 155-181 lin. 19" and "copia del tempo. Pubbl. in Gal., Ediz. Naz., II, 155-190". 3 All the references to the writings of Galileo will be to the Edizione Nazionale (Galileo, 18901909) in the following manner: Opere, n° of volume in Roman figures, n° of page in Arab figures and n° of lines (if necessary). For all the bibliographical references, see the Bibliography following this text. 4 For a complete description of the material in Vol. 72, cf. Procissi (1959, pp. 151-154), the critical apparatus added by Drake to his edition of Galileo's Notes on Motion (Galilei, 1979, pp. XLIII-LII) and Camerota ,1995. 5 On the question of the copying of some paduan notes in Florence, cf. Favaro's Avvertimento to Galilei, 1898, p. 34; Drake, 1978, p. 77 and Drake's "Introduction" to Galilei, 1979, p. XIII. 6 The De Motu Locali being composed of three books: "On Uniform Motion", "On Accelerated Motion" and "On the Motion of Projectiles", each one of these books will be refered to by DML 1, 2 or 3. 7 A great number of the notes of Vol. 72 were translated in Italian and published by Carugo and Geymonat in their edition of the Discorsi (Galilei, 1958). This "edition" of the fragments, 2 composed at various dates and reflect with a high degree of fidelity the changes and the transformations of Galileo's physical thought in the large amount of time that separated the old pisan dynamics of De motu antiquiora (Opere, I, pp. 251-419) and the paduan analysis of the machines in Le Mecaniche (ibid, II, pp. 155-190) from the mathematical physics expounded in the Discorsi. From this point of view the papers of Vol. 72 provide important tools for the reconstrucion of the intellectual itinerary of their author. "These manifestations of Galileo's thinking, which accompanied the ongoing work on motion leading from De motu to the Discorsi and thus document the transition, offer an invaluable opportunity to study the cognitive background of the origins of classical mechanics" (J. Renn, 1992, p.132). On the other hand, the analysis of these papers constitutes an excellent example of the substitution of a study of the context of discovery to the traditional examination of the context of proof. In fact, this recent tendency within Galilean studies displays a fundamental methodological presupposition implemented by recent history of science: that science is not only what is published by the scientists and presented to pairs in a highly structured form; it is also, and perhaps principally, what scientists write and think when they conduce their research, what they record when they perform experiments and make observations, when they mark notes and ideas... This method happened to be very fecond. It helped displace the interest of historians of science from the published and, consequently, public scientific production, towards the private papers. These incomplete and obscure records of calculations, theoretical meditations and experiments, although they are later abandoned, became a privileged instrument for any attempt to reconstruct a theoretical structure. The recent studies on Galileo’s notes on motion were inaugurated by the pioneer work of W. Wisan (1972, 1974), who carefully examined the great part of the folios, with the explicit objective of elucidating the gaps and the blanks in the evolution of the Galilean theory of motion. Although her work has been challenged by other historians (Drake, Naylor), her main results are still an excellent piece of analysis of the Vol. 72. The work of S. Drake shed new light on several papers of the manuscript, especially those which had been left unpublished until he had the privilege of being the first scholar to submit them to an interpretative investigation. The conclusions of Drake had been systematically criticized by R. Naylor and the debate between the two historians has greatly enriched the recent Galilean studies. P. Souffrin, for his part, explored a group of fragments concerned principally with the relation velocitas–momentum and reinterpreted them in a new way. In the same very recent period, J. Renn performed original work with the scope of a general reconstruction of the Galilean theory of motion, and within this framework paid special attention to the analysis which constitutes an important stage in the story of the papers bounded in Vol. 72, is rarely mentioned by the historians. of Vol. 72 papers devoted to projectile motion (Renn, 1990, 1992). These last two contributions initiated interesting ideas on the theoretical foundation and evolution of Galilean theoretical mechanics, and led to a new asses-sment of its status within the general framework of classical mechanics8. In order to show the exceptional interest of the manuscript material in Vol. 72, an important element in this context is worthy of mention. It is related to the new elements of information this material may provide on Galileo's experimental activity, a topic largely controversed in the history of science. In 1961, T. Settle repeated successfully the famous experiment of the motions on the inclined plane described in the Discorsi (Opere, VIII, pp. 212-213). Subsequently, S. Drake –within his systematic campaign of study of Galileo's notes on motion– identified some of the fragments in Vol. 72 as records of experiments performed by the pisan scientist. He reproduced many of these experiments (Drake, 1975c; Drake & MacLachlan, 1975). These two historiographical performances made an end to a long debate on whether Galileo was a real experimentalist or not, and what were the results he drew from his experimental activity. Since then, besides the general recognition of the effectiveness of the experimental dimension of Galileo’s work, another debate has been opened concerning the interpretation of the documents bearing records of this empirical investigation. In this context, some of the fragments which were discarded (partially or totally) from the Edizione Nazionale (as the folios 114r, 116v, 117r, 180r ...), became the subject of intense studies and their interpretation passionately controversed. This debate led to a new understanding of the whole Galilean scientific enterprise, and above all of the the interaction between theoretical and experimental investigations. But, as J. Renn pointed out (Renn 1990, p. 78; 1991, p. 110), there is another group of manuscripts contained in Vol. 72 that, to some extent still remain to be rediscovered. Those are the sheets that neither include a coherent piece of text nor any numbers or sketches related to experiments. In effect, besides the vast majority of Galileo's notes on motion which are direct evidence on the intensive and long struggle of our scientist with theoretical problems of mechanics, this last category of documents may lead to the rediscovery of "Galileo's theoretical laboratory", since they are concerned essentially with theoretical problems, as some conceptual and mathematical questions of the work of Galileo on the motion of projectiles and its relations to the free fall on the vertical or on inclined planes9. These indications are not intended to describe exhaustively the rich and live and still ongoing debate on the Vol. 72. To be exhaustive, it must include mention of the original writings published during the last quarter of century by P. Galluzzi (1979), E. Giusti (1981), D. Hill (1986, 1988, 1994), K. Takahashi (1993) ... 9 In his analysis of some of these sheets (ff. 83v, 86v, 90ar ...), J. Renn reconstructed comprehensively Galileo's original work on projectile motion and its relationship to the problems of free fall. For more information, see Renn (1984), (1988), (1990), (1992, pp. 213225). 8 As metioned above, almost all Galileo's notes on motion were edited in the eighth volume of the Opere, but this publication was more a transcription of the documents than a real edition, since two major questions were left unanswered: the chronology in which they were composed and their interpretation on the basis of a careful analysis of their mathematical, conceptual and experimental contents. The research conducted by the scholars in the two last decades tended to resolve a great deal of these unfinished missions. S. Drake realized a facsimile edition (Galilei 1979) of the notes relatively well supplied by critical tools, but the value of this work was diminished by some errors and inaccuracies in the references system (especially the refrences to the sources and to the list of watermarks) and by the criticable procedures which oriented all the editorial enterprise. Indeed, the main feature of this edition was that it reproduced the documents in their probable order of composition. In this perspective, the photographs of the original papers were cut in many pieces, assumed to be non contemporaneous. In most cases this procedure was not justified by any legitimate argument, save the ones issued principally from Drake’s own studies, who neglected to take into account almost systematically the available suggestions of other researchers. Until now, a real edition of the Vol. 72 is still lacking. In this context, the project announced by J. Renn in 1988 and which is actually in course of execution will provide the Galilean scholars with a magnificent tool of work and will surely initiate a new departure in the studies on the genesis of Galileo’s mechanics. This project consists of the production of an electronic edition of Vol. 72 material. Conducted by scholars at the Max Planck Institut für Wissenschaftsgeschichte in Berlin, in collaboration with the Istituto e Museo di Storia della Scienza and the Biblioteca Nazionale at Florence, the first part of this ambitious project has by now been completed in Berlin at the Max Planck Institute. Using electronic tools developed by the editors, a carefully-controlled transcription of the texts related to motion (folios 33-194), encompassing a markup of the text indicating emendations, deletions, marginal notes, and insertions has been prepared. The relation of the transcription to digital images of the manuscript pages has been documented by means of frames and hypertext links, the diagrams of the manuscript redrawn, and a preliminary transcription of the calculations prepared. The result of this work will be made accessible on different computer platforms, by means of specific programs developed for this aim, in order to convert data in the standardized format of the HTML of the World Wide Web. In the next future, this electronic edition of Mss. 72 will be put on the Web for free access and could be viewed via Internet. Further work is being executed now in the second stage of the project. This part will be devoted to the English translation of the documents, the analysis of their deductive structure and the accomplishment of the critical apparatus for texts and calculations, besides completing the physical description of the manuscript 10. 2. On the problem of datation No page of the Vol. 72 is explicitly dated. Now the study of the documents contained in it requires that they should be put in a logical order corresponding as much as possible to the order of their composition. For this purpose, different methods and criteria have been proposed. Ca-verni (1891-1900, IV, p. 341) founded his examination of the notes in question on a double criterion of datation: their conceptual content and "material indications" –in particular the calligraphical variations of writing of the different fragments. Without recognizing it explicitly, Favaro was greatly influenced by the work of Caverni, as it is now clearly stated by the historians, and this influence was evident in the relative chronology in which he edited the documents of Vol. 7211. As far as the question of the criteria of datation is concerned, recent scholars are divided in two groups: these who prefer theoretical clues, as W. L. Wisan and R. H. Naylor, and the others who adher to material clues, especially S. Drake and W. Hooper. In her pioneering work, Wisan declared her preference for theoretical methods for the establishment of a relative chronology of Galileo's notes : "neither handwriting nor watermarks suffice to determine the order of undated fragments within a given period. To reconstruct the relative chronology of Galileo's drafts within the different periods, other evidence is needed. For my own study the main evidence used is taken from variations in terminology and mathematical techniques" (Wisan, 1974, p. 127). For Drake, on the contrary, material tools provide the best way for the ordering of the fragments: The informations on this electronic edition are extracted from the Annual Report for the year 1995 of the Max Planck Institute for History of Science in Berlin. I thank Jürgen Renn and Peter Damerow, MPIWG reponsibles for the project for the Vol. 72project, for providing to me this information and allowing me to publish it. 11 Drake remarked (in his "Introduction" to Galilei, 1979, p. VIII) that the arrangement of Galileo's notes of motion in the eighth volume of the Opere "was based partly on the order of appearance of topics in Galileo's last book, and partly on conjectures published in 1895 by Raffaelo Caverni, who had selected a few documents to support his theory of Galileo's sources". More recently, Camerota (1995, p. 9) asserts that "Favaro seguì in modo piuttosto stretto le indicazioni caverniane, mutuandone in più punti le opzioni nella pubblicazione di importanti sequenze di stralci del Ms. 72". 10 "To make sure that any ordering is free of serious implausibilities requires attention to handwriting, vocabulary, watermarks in paper, color and condition of ink, and in addition to the implications in that ordering of what was known to Galileo at every stage, and what remained to be discovered" (Drake, 1978, p. 77). In reality, it seems that the most efficacious method has to make use of a synthesis of these two choices and try to combine theoretical and material indications. Since the aim behind any ordering is logically not the establishing of an absolute chronology, but only a relative one, the combination of such two methods would be very valuable. The question of the criteria of datation is a fundamental one. Without the realization of significant porgress in this field, the study of Galileo’s notes on motion will always suffer of incompleteness. Actually, the currently executed electronical edition of Vol. 72 will undoubtedly shed a new light on the ordering and datation of these documents. The examination of the physical properties of the Manuscript is, indeed, an important part of this unprecedented project. For this investigation, scholars of the collaborative institutions make use of new and sophisticated technology in the analysis of the ink and paper, in the identification and classification of watermarks, in the photographying of the original documents... Undoubtedly, this work will bring to light much hidden information that remained unsuspected by previous research. 3. Preliminary work in natural philosophy and mechanics Before we start the analysis of some Vol. 72 documents, let us begin with a rapid presentation of the texts elaborated by Galileo during the XVIth century part of his scientific life and where is manifest his familiarity with the traditional problems of the medieval natural philosophy and the classical theory of machines. The texts to which I refer are precisely the De motu antiquiora and Le Mecaniche. In these two sets of writings, our hero obtained some assumptions and positive results of which he will make use in his later research. Among these results : the De motu theorem as a general proposition demonstrated twice in the context of the inclined-plane analysis; the idea of conservation of motion on the horizontal plane, the conception of acceleration as an accidental feature of the descents of bodies. 3. 1. De motu antiquiora De motu antiquiora is the generic title of six latin documents written by Galileo in Pisa ca. 1590 on the problems of natural philosophy12. In these texts, we can distinguish a main version composed of 23 chapters which is the most developed quantitatively. It contains a section on the movement on inclined planes where Galileo, after a laborious mathematical demonstration, obtained a proposition on descents. Following Wisan (1974, p. 152), this proposition is known as "De motu theorem". The analysis of the inclined plane in De motu is founded on an explicit principle: a heavy body is moved downward with as much force as it is necessary to draw it up, or, it is moved downward with the same force with which it resists being raised (Opere, I, p. 297.4-6). In this perspective, the problem of the inclined plane takes the form of a search for the force with which a body descends a given plane; this force will be the same as that required to hold the body at rest on the plane. Making use of this assumption and applying the principle of the lever to the case of the bent lever, Galileo assumes that the motion of a body at any point around the lower quadrant of a circle may be identified with the motion along an inclined plane tangent to that point. E C A Z P S B T G D Q [Fig. 1] N De motu antiquiora {1} R H F In the demonstration, he tried to find out the ratio of the effective weight of the body on the respective planes. For this purpose, he elaborated the famous demonstration with the bent lever applied to a vertical circle. After the preliminary steps, a general proportionality is deduced in terms of the diagram [fig. 1]: celeritas on EF is to the celeritas on GH as QS to SP. In other terms, the descents on a vertical and on an oblique path are as the length of oblique descent to the vertical height of that length. This is the first version of De motu theorem, enunciated in terms of inverse proportionality of celeritates to the oblique and vertical fall of the same height. Then the theorem is enunciated generally : The texts De motu were edited by Favaro in Opere, I, pp. 251-419. An important historiographical problem related to these writings is the conceptual and chronological order of their composition. For a synthesis on this topic, see Abattouy & Mazet (1996, forthcoming). 12 "And it is clear that the same weight can be drawn up an inclined plane with less force than vertically, in proportion as the vertical ascent is smaller than the oblique. Consequently, the same heavy body will descend vertically with greater force than on an inclined plane in proportion as the length of the descent on the incline is grea-ter than the vertical fall" (ibid, I, p. 298.26-30; Galilei, 1960, p. 65)13 . Continuing his argument, Galileo deduced the theorem in a more general form: ratios of celeritates along planes of any inclination, but with the same vertical height, are inversely proportional as the lengths of the planes. As in diagram 2, celeritas on CA / celeritas on AD = AD / AC. Since DA / AB = tarditas on AD / tarditas on AB, and since tard (AB) / tard (AC) = AB / AC, it follows, ex aequali, that DA / AC = tard (AD) / tard (AC). A [Fig. 2] De motu antiquiora{2} B C D "And therefore line DA will be to line AC also as the celeritas on AC is to celeritas on AD. It is clear, then, that the celeritas of the same body moving on different inclinations are to each other inversely as the lengths of the oblique paths, if these entail equal vertical descents" (Opere, I, p. 301.24-26; Galilei, 1960, p. 68). The De motu theorem constitutes the first proposition of Galileo's work on motion. It left indelibile and evident traces in the subsequent Galilean investigations. Precisely, the law of chords (which will be discussed below) is nothing else than one of its geometrical consequen-ces. Recently, the understanding of this theorem has been renewed by P. Souffrin who rejected the prevailing view about its falsity. He affirms (1991, pp. 93-96; 1993, p. 122 sq.) that the central proposition elaborated by Galileo in chapter 1414 is deprived of any amibiguity concerning the signification of celeritas; for this reason, the theorem is correct and the classical mechanics gives the same result. In this section of De motu, nothing is said nor explicitly assumed concerning a law of descent on a given inclined plane; the problem posed is typically standard in pre-classical treatment of The excerpts of Galileo's writings reproduced in the present text are in most cases adaptations of the available English translations of his works (by Wisan, Drabkin, Drake, Renn...) In some cases, I have revised the translations of some passages 14 That is the celeritas of the same movable on planes of different inclinations are between them as the inverse of the inclined descents corresponding to the same vertical height. 13 motion. In fact, the problem consists of comparing the spaces traversed "in the same time or in equal times" by two movables15. In another part of the treatise De motu, Galileo elaborated a rule of motion intented to take into account the material in which the movable is made and the media in which it descends. According to such a rule, the velocity of motion of falling bodies is quantitatively characterized as a ratio between the specific gravity of the body and that of the medium, but the acceleration is not mentioned. On the contrary, it is considered as an accident, the manifestation of an external quality which impels the agreement between the observed motions of the bodies and the theoretical predictions. In general, the motion of fall is considered as accelerated, but it is explained by the difference between the falling body's weight and a gradually decreasing impressed force. In this perspective, the phenomenon of acceleration is said to intervene only towards the end of motion, when the body moves swiftly, after it has regained more weight. This change of speed is accounted for by the action of an external force that is impressed on the falling body and which has nothing to do with any influence on the part of the medium (Opere, I, pp. 315-318). The impressed force remains in the body when it begins to fall naturally, but its progressive disappearence explains why the movable is accelerated in a later stage of its fall. With the same reasoning is also explained how acceleration is stopped when the impressed force is so weakened that the inherent weight of the body recovers a great amount of its vigor (ibid, pp. 319-323). In a subsequent chapter, Galileo adds supplementary elements to explain why bodies that are less heavy move more swiftly in the beginning of their motion than heavier ones (ibid, pp. 333-337). According to this pisan theory of acceleration, heavy bodies must destroy more of the impressed force than must lighter bodies, and this is the cause of their slowness; but since the contrary quality is weakened by itself, the heavy bodies get rid of it more rapidly than lighter ones (thanks to the great opposition manifested by their matter) and regain their inherent great weight. An important aspect of the interpretation elaborated by P. Souffrin is that he doesn't agree with the consideration of De motu theorem as applying only to uniform motions. "Les lectures critiques modernes ont ceci en commun qu'elles entendent celeritas dans l'un des sens que nous donnons actuellement à "vitesse" en cinématique : soit "vitesse moyenne", soit "vitesse instantanée". Or ...il s'agit là d'acceptions spécifiques de la tradition classique, et de ce fait les interprétations se trouvent marquées par un anachronisme fondamental relatif au concept central de la discussion". In order to justity this point of view, P. Souffrin restated the theorem in the preclassical conceptual terms by the attribution of the standard preclassical signification to celeritas and enunciated the theorem as follows : "Il est donc clair que le rapport des espaces parcourus dans un même temps par un même mobile sur des plans d'inclinaisons différentes est égal à l'inverse du rapport des descentes obliques sur ces mêmes plans correspondant à une même descente verticale... ce qui est évidemment... théoriquement parfaitement exact" (Souffrin, 1991, pp. 95-96). For more details, see Souffrin (1992a), (1993). 15 In this later stage, they increase the speed of their motion and catch up the lighter bo-dies, with which they reach the ground at the same time, at least for short distances of fall16. The treatment of projectile motion in chapter 17 shares the general lines of the above reasoning. The motion of projection is considered as a violent motion and it is explained by the same accidental quality used to account for the temporary acceleration, that is an impressed force. In this context, the trajectory of oblique projection is composed of two parts: a straight one followed by a curved part, generated when the projectile begins to descend downward [fig. 3]17. B C D [Fig. 3] E De motu antiquiora{3} A In the conception of acceleration as in the analysis of the motion of projectiles, the theoretical structure of De motu proves to be tightly linked with the medieval tradition of natural philosophy. The treatise of mechanics composed at Padua many years later, although manife-sted some conceptual progress, reveals the continuation of a strict adhesion to the same fundamental theses stated in De motu. 3. 2. Le Mecaniche Galileo’s texts on mechanics of simple machines provide important and useful elements of information for the reconstruction of his thought in the period preceding the researches recor-ded in Vol. 72. Indeed, his paduan production in In Chap. 14, just after the general enunciation of the De motu theorem, Galileo warns that the theoretical ratios stated in this proposition are not observed because of the imperfections of matter and of the "accident" of acceleration (a lighter body descends more quickly than a heavier one at the beginning of its motion). Because of the difficulty of these two elements, and because their interferences intervene in so many ways, "rules cannot be given for these accidental factors since they can occur in countless ways" (ibid, p. 302.12-13). 17 The last section of De motu (chap. 23) devoted to the exploration of a specific question: "Why objects projected by the same force move farther on a straight line the less acute are the angles they make with the plane of the horizon" (Opere, I, pp. 337-340). As is it remarked by J. Renn (1992, p. 144) , the way the question is posed presupposes that an obliquely projected body follows a straight line before it statrts to turn downward, as it is illustrated by the diagram drawn by Galileo in his text. For an analysis of Galileo's theory of projectile motion in De motu, see J. Renn, 1992, pp. 144-147. 16 the theory of machine is extant in three texts of which many copies were preserved up till now. But none of these copies is an autograph of Galileo. The three texts may be classified in fact into two main categories: two of them are abridged memoranda which served eventually as booknotes for Galileo's private and public lessons on mechanics, while the third is a developed and more extended revision of the same material contained of the early concise outlines, with the addition of some new sections. This revision was executed very probably around 160018. The definition of the term momento in Le Mecaniche constituted an important conceptual achievement by Galileo. In Section II of the treatise, this term is defined as: "the tendency to move downward caused not so much by the heaviness [gravità] of the movable body as by the arrangement which different heavy bodies have among themselves... Momento is that impeto to go downward composed of heaviness, position, and of anything else by which this tendency may be caused" (Opere, II, p. 159.17-28; Galilei, 1960, p. 151). Two aspects of momento emerge from this definition. First the signification of static moment, meaning the product or combination of weight and distance on a balance. The second aspect is represented by the dynamical implication of the concept, which assimilate it to the product of weight and velocity. In fact, it is possible that Galileo considered the velocity as a component of the second aspect This last text alone has been edited in the Opere (vol. II, pp. 155-190) under the title Le Mecaniche, while one of the two early versions has been published elsewhere by Favaro (cf. Favaro, 1899). The third version was discovered and published by S. Drake in the middle of this century (cf. Drake, 1958). The datation of the three versions of the Mechanics is a topic of debate between historians, but the standard opinion holds that the two first versions were written at Padua about 1593-1594, while the revision was accomplished ca. 1600 (Drake (1958); (1978, p. 55)). I am preparing a French annotated edition of Le Mecaniche that I began in September 1995 at the Observatoire de la Côte d'Azur (Nice) where I was appointed as a "chercheur associé du CNRS" for three months (sept.-nov. 1995). This edition will be published in Paris, at Les Belles Lettres. In this work, I pay a careful attention to the structure of the texts Delle Meccaniche. I have already localised new elements for the datation and the organisation of the different sections of the main text and its relations with the earlier versions. In the same context, I will try to elucidate the "mystery" of the presence of the two copies of Le Mecaniche in Vol. 72 among the notes on motion : what significance can we give to this presence? Who insert them there and when? This problem is similar to the one raised by Fredette (1969, pp. 85-111) about the presence of the draft De motu accelerato in Vol. 71 among the various documents of De motu antiquiora. On the basis of various elements, it is very probable that no one else than Galileo himself who proceeds to the organisation of the contents of Vol. 72 as it is now extant. So we can suppose logically that it was Galileo too who inserted the copies of his work on simple machines in the file of his notes and fragments on motion. I think that the signification of this act is of chrnonological nature, as an indication of a sequential ordering. It can mean, in effect, that all the work on motion now extant in Vol. 72 was brought into play after the revision of Le Mecaniche. 18 of momento. But this dynamic meaning of the concept is not sufficiently valorised in Le Mecaniche. It was made a fundamental element of Galileo’s theory of motion only in subsequent work19. That the definition of momento in Le Mecaniche may be seen as having a dynamical implication is strongly suggested by the analysis of the inclined plane in Section 7 "Della vite" of the treatise. The analysis of the motion on inclined planes in Le Mecaniche begins with the enunciation of a much more developed version of the proto-inertial idea if compared with the one edicted in De motu. Effectively, it is observed here that a body would move downward on a surface only slightly tilted; on the contrary, if posed on a horizontal plane, it would be indifferent to motion or to rest, but it would have resistance toward the ascentional motion upward (Opere, II, pp. 179.9180.6). Then two weights of equal momenti are considered which are balanced at A and C; the arm of the bent lever BC is supposed to be rotated to the position indicated by the line BF, with the weight at F [fig. 4]. The momento of the weight in this new position is as if it were suspended from K, and its ratio to the weight at A is as KB to BA. If the arm BC continues to rotate until it coincides with BL, the momento of the weight will go on diminishing proportionally. Until this point, the demonstration has been conducted along the same lines of the precedent one elaborated in De motu. But at this point a new approach is inaugurated in the proof developed in Le Mecaniche. D [Fig. 4] B A M K CH Le Mecaniche {1} O F I N L G E Many passages of Le Mecaniche testify that Galileo made a sort of parallel between the static and the dynamic meanings of momento. But it was only in the Discorso on floating bodies (1612) that the dynamic aspect of the concept was made fully explicit as follows: "Moment among mechanicians signifies that force, that power, that efficacy, with which the mover moves and the moved body resists, which force depends not only upon simple heaviness, but upon the speed of motion and upon the varying inclinations of the space over which the motion is made, as a descending body has more impeto in a very steep descent that in one less steep" (Opere, IV, p. 68). 19 "You see, then, how the weight placed at the end of line BC, inclining downward along the circumference CFLJ, comes gradually to diminish its momento and its impeto to go downward, being sustained more and more by the lines BF and BL. But to consider this heavy body as descending and sustained now less and now more by the radii BF and BL, and as constrained to travel along the circumference CFL, is not different from imagining the same circumference CFLJ to be a surface of the same curvature placed under the same movable body, so that this body, being supported upon it, would be constrained to descend along it. For in either case the movable body traces out the same path, and it does not matter whether it is suspended from the center B and sustained by the radius of the circle, or whether this support is removed and it is supported by and travels upon the circumference CFLJ... if the movable body is located at the point F, then its heaviness is partly sustained by the circular path placed under it, and... at the first point of its motion it is as if it were on an inclined plane according to the tangent line GFH, since the tilt of the circumference at the point F does not differ from the tilt of the tangent FG, apart from the insensible angle of contact" (Opere, II, pp. 181-183; Galilei, 1960, pp. 173-174). Then, similarly, the mom (L) / mom (C) = BM / BC; and mom (HG) / total impeto on DCE = KB / BC = KB / BF. From the similarities of the triangles KBF and KFH, it is concluded that "the whole and absolute moment" acquired by the movable body in the perpendicular is in the same proportion to that which it has on the inclined plane HF as the length of the inclined plane HF is to the vertical line FK(ibid, 183.5-9). In other terms, mom (FH) / tot mom (FK) = KF / FH [fig. 5] F [Fig. 5] Le Mecaniche {2} K H Namely, "upon the inclined plane the force has the same proportion to the weight as the perpendicular dropped to the horizontal from the end of the plane has to the length of the plane" (ibid, p. 183.22-24). The specific aspects of the demonstration of De motu theorem in Le Mecaniche can be summarized as follows. An important point of this geometrical deduction is indeed the diminution of the momento as the body descends on the internal face of the circumference. In the second part of the proof, Galileo indicates clearly that he considers the motion of the body continuously about the lower quadrant of a circle. He assumes also that at each point of its trajectory, the motion of the body is the same as if it were on an inclined plane tangent to that point20. Nevertheless, the main aspect of the above deduction is the fact that the momento of the movable is diminished as the body descends down and approaches the horizontal. The diminution of the moment downward of the body operates in two ways: if the body is sustained by the arm of the bent lever along the lines BF and BL (in this case the momento is measured on the projected points M and K) or if it travels freely along the circumference CFL. Besides, the momento being total and integral on the perpendicular, on a horizontal plane the body has no tendency to move and "would remain indifferent and questioning between motion and rest" (Opere, II, p. 180.3; Galilei, 1960, p. 171) and would be made in motion "da qualunque minima forza" (ibid, p. 180.9-10). Several notes recorded on the papers bounded in of Vol. 72 make use of the diminution of momento during the descent in the lower quadrant of a vertical circle. Similarly, some typical expressions –like totale momento– or the geometrical technique of representation by the bent lever representing the rotating arm of a balance are manifest evidences of the influence of the theory of machines on the early Galilean researches on motion in the period following the revision of Le Mecaniche. II. FIRST DISCOVERIES, FIRST DEMONSTRATIONS In the second half of 1602, Galileo obtained his first three mathematical propositions while he was investigating the properties of isochronism. Just after this important achievement, he attempted laboriously to build mathematical demonstrations of these theorems. He tried geometrical and experimental procedures, working under the direct and tenacious influence of the concepts, methods and terminology of the theory of machines. 1. Isochronism and paths of least-time According to an hypothesis formulated by S. Drake (Galileo, 1960, p. 174n.; Drake, 1978, p. 61), a possible consequence of this demonstration may have been the establishment in the mind of Galileo of points of similarity between the motion of a body on the internal face of the circumference while it is sustained by the arm of the balance and the oscillation of a pendeulum 20 On 29 November 1602 Galileo sent to Guidobaldo dal Monte a letter (Opere, X, pp. 97-100) which constitutes a document of great importance. It is precisely dated and affords, consequently, an excellent means for the datation of other documents associated with it of which the date of composition is not precisely known. This letter contains the mention of the first three results discovered by the Pisan scientist in his new process of research on motion: the isochronism of the pendulum, the law of chords (or Theorem VI, DML2) and a proposition on the descents in the least time along the chords of a quadrant (Theorem XXII, DML2). In terms of the diagrams in fig. 6-7, as they are drawn in the letter, the three propositions can be expressed as follows: Pendulum isochronism: t(FIG) = t(BCD) [fig. 6]; law of chords21: t(FA) = t(EA)... = t(BA) = t(IA) [fig. 7]; Theorem XXII t(SIA) < t(SA) [fig. 7] 22. C A E D S B E F D C G I Letter to Guidobaldo {1} [Fig. 6] I F A Letter to Guidobaldo {2} [Fig. 7] Galileo didn't communicate to Guidobaldo the proofs of the three propositions he said he had discovered, but he specified that he demonstrated them "without transgressing the bounds of mechanics". His demonstrations are extant in some sheets preserved in Vol. 72. These autograph documents reveal, in effect, that his attempts to demonstrate the pendulum isochronism were essentially The law of chords or Theorem VI-DML2 (Opere, VIII, pp. 221 sq.) is known as "Galileo's Theorem": the time of descent along any chord of a vertical circle to its lowest point remains the same, regardless of the length and slope of the plane; in other words, descents along arcs of the lower quadrant should be completed in the same time. This is true of chords (paths of pendulum oscillations) as of arcs (isochronism of the chords). On the work of Galileo on isochronism , cf. Abattouy , 1996c (forthcoming) 22 Theorem XXII (ibid, p. 262 sq.) states that a descent along conjugate chords in the lower quadrant of a vertical circle to the lowest point takes less time than along the single chord connecting their endpoints. On Galileo's work on Theorem XXII, see below, Section II. 2. 2. 21 calculatory and experimental (ff. 115v, 154r, 166r, 183r, 189v...)23 On the contrary, the main feature of his work on Theorems VI and XXII took the form of an extensive theoretical study, in which the empirical and numerical approach were not missing (ff. 121v, 131r, f. 150v, 151r, 160r, 163r, 186v, 189r). 1. 2. Attempts to demonstrate the law of chords The recto of f. 154 contains traces of Galileo's research on the isochronism, superficially analysed by means of analytical tools made up in the preceding investigations on the theory of machines. Beside some scattered calculations disseminated on the page, the principal diagram [fig. 8] shows a suspended body, supported from the center and from a point located in the arm of a balance, touching the circumference at a point where a line is tangent to the circle. Folio 121v [Fig. 9] Folio 154r [Fig. 8] Folio 121v (Galilei, 1979, p. 13) bears probably the traces of geometric exercises on the law of equality of times for descents along chords of a vertical circle [fig. 10]. This diagram is similar to another diagram drawn in W. Gilbert's De Magnete and may then be dated after 1600 (Drake, 1978, p. 67). Another fragment on the recto of the folio (Galilei, 1979, p. 20) shows vestiges of investigations on pendulum oscillations. The diagram drawn on the verso of f. 150 24 [fig. 10] reveals the same concerns: the determination of the geometrical means for the demonstration of the law of isochronism. But the essential part of the work conducted by Analysing folios 166r, 183r and 189v, Hill (1994) affirmed that these papers are records of careful and impressive experiments in which Galileo determines empirically the times of descent for arcs and chords (pendulums and planes), and thus develops a method for determining time of descent for any height, given the quarter period of any pendulum. In this analysis, he found that Galileo was well aware of the non-isochronism of the pendulum, despite his published claims of the opposite. For a different assessment of Galileo's manuscript material related to pendulum (ff. 151v, 154r, 198v), see S. Drake, 1990, pp. 12-31 24 Galilei, 1979, p. 12. Folio 150v is dated 1603 by Drake. 23 Galileo on the law of chords in this early period is reflected in folios 151r and 160r. These documents contain two demonstrations of Galileo's theorem which will be reproduced almost verbatim in the Discorsi. G Folio 150v [Fig.10] D E B A C Here is the translation of the fragment written on f. 151r: "Let GD be erected [perpendicular] to the horizon, but DF inclined [to it]: I say that motion takes place from G to D in the same time as from F to D. Thus the moment along FD is the same as that along the tangent in E, which is parallel to that same FD; therefore, the moment along FD is to the total moment as CA to AB, that is, to AE; but as CA to AE so is ID to DA and also the double [of ID] FD to the double [of DA] DG; therefore the moment along FD is to the total moment, namely, along GD, as FD to GD; therefore, the motion along FD and GD takes place in the same time" (Opere, VIII, p. 378.1-11; Galilei, 1979, p. 25). The relation to be deduced is t (GD) = t (FD). Constructing the line tangent to the circle in E, mom (FD) = momento on the tangent, while the totale momentum is the same on all GD, so mom (FD) / mom (GD) = CA / AB. The momento on FD being equal to that on the tangent, it is measured on the balance AB as if it were suspended from C , so mom (FD) / mom (GD) = CA / AE . But CA / AE = ID / DA = FD/ DG. Therefore mom (FD) / mom (GD) = FD / GD. Finally, t (FD) = t (GD). The deduction is left unfinished, but it can be completed by the same elements used in the demonstration of the inclined plane in Le Mecaniche. As noted by Wisan (1974, p. 164), the conclusion follows from the assumption that in equal time intervals, speeds are proportional to distances traversed. Speed is not distinguished from momentum and in the last step of the proof, it is not distinguished from distance either. The other part of the early work of Galileo on the law of chords is documented on folio 160r, where is elaborated a complete proof of the theorem. This time, Galileo intended to prove the proposition mechanically. The use of expressions like "constat ex elementis mecanicis", "momentum ponderis" and "momentum suum totale" denotes of the early date of the document, and they are in the same time evident reminiscences of the conceptual framework of the theory of machines25. 1. BA being equal to DA, construct BE and DF perpendicularly to the horizontal; "from the elements of mechanics", momento on ABC / momentum totale on the vertical = BE/BA (De motu theorem enunciated in terms of moments). 2. Since mom(DA)/mom(DF) = DF/DA or DF/BA, 3. therefore ("constat ex elementis mechanicis") that momentum ponderis (DA)/mom(CA) = DF/BE. 4. Now, CA/DA = BE/DF. 5. Therefore, t(CA) = t(DA). In the second part of the demonstration, the core of the proof is concentrated in the relation AC/AD = BE/DF, which is proved by geometrical tools introducing geometry of angles and triangles, as in the proof on f. 151r26. 1. 3. Preliminary demonstrations of Theorem XXII Many papers of Vol. 72 document the long search of Galileo in order to provide a rigorous proof for the other theorem discovered in 1602 and numbered later Theorem XXII in DML2. This theorem affirms that less time is required in The text on f. 160r has not been published by Favaro among the Frammenti attinenti ai Discorsi, but in the footnotes to Theorem VI in DML2: Opere, VI, pp. 221-222n. Later, it was reconstructed by W. Wisan (1974, p. 164) and reproduced by Drake (in Galilei, 1979, p. 5). The date of composition of the note recorded on this folio is evidently an early date. This conclusion is supported by many elements, material and theoretical, as the mathematical technique, the handwriting with which the fragment is written and by terminological data. For example, it contains one of the rare occurences of the expression "momentum ponderis", to which Galileo substituted later the concept of "momentum gravitatis". 26 The material on f. 160r is published in the DML2 as the second demonstration of Theorem VI (the famous "mechanical proof"). In DML, the result -at step 4- is said to follow from Theorem II of uniform motion (DML1). This reference had been considered by the commentators as a false assumption, since it relies on an illegitimate use of a proposition valid exclusively for uniform motions (cf. M. Clavelin in Galilée, 1970, n. 90 to p. 155). But a recent study did prove that there is no problem in the use of Theorem II of De motu æequabili in this demonstration of the law of chords (Souffrin & Gauthero, 1992). 25 the descent along conjugate chords to the lowest point than along the single chord connecting their endpoints. In some early entries recorded on folios 131r and 189r, we find Galileo’s first attempts to demonstrate the theorem by geometrical means, arithmetical calculations and probably experimental measurements also. A B C D [Fig. 13] Folio 189v E F On the verso of folio 189 (Galilei, 1979, p. 28), there is a diagramn containing traces of preliminary work on the problems of isochronism with relation to Theorem XXII [fig. 13]. The diagram is similar to the one used for the final and successful demonstration of this proposition recorded on the folios 186v and 163r. Folio 131r is an early draft composed of four fragments, the first of which is deleted by cross lines [fig. 14]27. That these fragments may be attenpts to prove Theorem XXII is testified by the diagram, almost identical to the one on f. 189v. Here is a paraphrase of the four fragments: T R D F O V M B S A Folio 131r [Fig. 14] L G 1. Suppose DO C= m (RC, BT); CO will be = m (CD, DF) which is the same DO; 2. As in Le Mechanice, Sect. 7, the momentum diminishes as the body moves downward along the quadrant, as if it is weighed in a balance suspended from DR; and the weight of the body diminishes as T (the fulcrum of the balance) approaches to the center R. 3. BC / CD = CD ... Folio 131r (Opere, VIII, p. 417.8-17; Galilei, 1979, pp. 7, 9, 50) was cut by S. Drake in four non contemporaneous fragments. It is evident that this document is of early composition, as it is attested by the incompleteness of the argument, the terminology (totale momentum) and the similarities existing between its graphical representation and the analysis of the inclined plane in Le Mecaniche. Besides, as in folio 154r, the line of momenti is a dotted one. It is possible that the first fragment was added later while the third was probably abandoned for the fourth. For an analysis of this document, cf. Wisan, 1974, pp. 176-177. 27 4. Momentum (DC) / total moment = TR / RD, with LB parallel to CD. The third fragment can be completed in this way: BC / CD = CD/CA, and it becomes an expression of De motu Theorem. It is possible that this proportionality was abandoned for the last and fourth fragment, which is aonther version of the reasoning outlined on f. 160r, where the law of chords was demonstrated by the use of the tangent to the circle and the balance. What Galileo sought to prove was precisely a relation of the type : t (DBC) < t (DC). As it can be reconstructed from the diagram and from the fragments disseminated on the folio, the mathematical argument is identical to the one used for the final proof of the theorem on f. 163r (the letters O and V, the relation of the first fragment : m (RC, BT) = DO = m (CD, DF). To prove the theorem, it was sufficient to introduce the mean proportional in order to show that if VA = m (AC, BA), then the relation between CO and CV is the solution of the problem. The work on Theorem XXII required the mobilisation of Galileo's efforts for many years as it is revealed by several padouan documents. In this laborious endeavour, worth of independent and minutious study, he obtained and demonstrated three other propositions concerned with descents accomplished in least time: theorems XIX, XX, XXI of DML 2. The final conclusion of this family of propositions was reached in the scholium of the brachistochrone28. In the folios 140r, 127v, 168r, where we find the demonstrations of these theorems, the proofs have the form of geometrical exercises on the paths of the quickest descents. Developing mathematical consequences of the law of chords, they deal with an identical problem: the determination of the trajectory where is realized the swiftest descents between two points, between a line and a point and between a point and a line. The method employed is based on elementary geometrical procedures, issued principally from the geometry of the circle. Reference is made to abstract mathematical relations of times that are not represented on the diagrams. Finally, in the three cases, the result is deduced by simple application of the law of chords. On the other hand, the work on Theorem XXII was accomplished in two other directions: geometrical exercises and experimental investigations. Indeed, on folios 166r, 183r, 184r, 189r and 192r abundant numerical calculations founded on empirical measures related to this proposition are preserved, while the geometrical The proposition of the brachistochrone is enunciated in the DML2 as a scholium to Theorem XXII : Opere, VIII, pp. 263-264. It asserts that the path of quickest descent in the lower quadrant of a vertical circle is the arc and not along the chord subtending the arc. There is no manuscript version of this proposition in Vol. 72, which may mean that this proposition is a late discovery made up by Galileo when he prepared the Discorsi for publication. W. Wisan has made of the scholium of the brachistochrone a fundamental piece of her interpretation of the development of Galileo's work on motion and related it even to his cosmological concerns : see Wisan, 1974, pp. 184-187, 1977, p. 155sq., 1983, 1984, pp. 270-271 and the critics of Drake (1978, pp. 503-504n. 19) and Naylor (1976, pp. 95- 96) . 28 research was recorded on the folios 129r, 140r, 149v, 150r-v , 157v, 185v and 188. Finally, on the folios 163r, 172r and 186v complete mathematical demonstrations were constructed. The proof composed on the recto of f. 163, where Galileo succeeded in the deduction of this difficult theorem, is specifically elaborated along an euclidean model and on the basis of physical principles. Later, he reproduced it in full in the third book of De motu locali29. 2. Comparison of motions on different slopes In this sub-section our attention will be focused on a group of documents (folios 173r, 180r, 177r, 172v, 163v...) in which the work of Galileo on a specific problem is reflected: the ratio existing between motions of bodies moving under natural acceleration along different planes from the same point. An aspect of this question is the relation of the accelerated and the uniform motions. These investigations led Galileo to the discovery of many important results: the RightAngle Theorem, the Length-Time proportionality and the Rule of Double Distance. In the same context, emerged in the mind of our scientist some speculations and paradoxes on the concept of velocity and on the way of finding a rational foundation for the velocity in accelerated and uniform motions. Although they are presented in a sequential succession, the order in which these papers will be discussed doesn’t pretend to be a chronological one. The succession they evoke is rather of conceptual nature. Effectively, it is possible that Galileo's treatment of the ratios of velocity, time and distance in the different cases of motion has followed an itinerary similar to the one described here. In this perspective, it doesn't matter so much if these papers were written in this order or not. 2. 1. Folio 173r : geometrical exercises Discarded from the publication amongst the Frammenti in the Edizione Nazionale of Galileo's works, folio 173r remained unpublished until the recent period. It reflects the survival of the mechanical conceptual framework. An important feature of the material recorded in this document is represented by some cogitations on motions along the vertical and the incline in the case of two bodies beginning their descents from the same point along different slopes30. For more information on the papers documenting the work on least-time theorems, see Wisan (1974, pp. 177-187); (1983); Drake (1974b); (1987), (1989, chap. 1); and Abattouy (1989, pp. 345-349, 470-489). 30 This document has not been edited by Favaro; it was the merit of S. Drake to signal it to the attention of historians (Drake, 1978, p. 66; Galileo, 1979, pp. XIV-XV, 4). I reproduce the main parts of the folio below in fig. 14. For more convenience, I added numbers desides the 29 The first diagram [fig. 14] represents two balls of the same volume descending along two different slopes; below, a note is concerned by the ratio of momenti, in the vein of the basic relation of De motu theorem. At the right side, a diagram shows a vertical height which is to the inclined path in the ratio of 1 to 2. If two balls were moving from rest in the same instant on the incline and on the vertical, in the same time in which the first will attain the extremity of the plane, the second will traverse all the length of the perpendicular. The extreme point attained on the inclined plane will be the beginning of a perpendicular to the vertical path which represents geometrically the ratio existing between the two paths of descent. The diagrams marked 3 and 6 in my reproduction of f. 173 [fig. 14] are concerned respectively with planes of various inclinations related to vertical and horizontal lines, and with an inclined plane tangent to a vertical circle. The examination of the contents of the folio reveals the multiform presence of relations describing the behaviour of motions on different slopes. The inverse proportionality relation emerges sometimes and the De motu theorem is applied to momenta : totale momentum on BC/ momentum on BD = BD/ BC [3]. Similarly, the presence of the inclined plane tangent to a vertical circle is an evident reminiscence of the analysis of the inclined plane in De motu and Le Mecaniche, but this time the bent lever seems to be replaced by a body oscillating about the lower part of the dotted line circle [6]. 2. 2. Folios 177 r-v and 180r : the Right-Angle Theorem Folio 180r begins with the enunciation of the theorem, followed by a relatively detailed demonstration. Such a careful enunciation and demonstration is not usual in the early documents of Vol. 72. Here Galileo stated and demonstrated a proposition called by the historians "the Right-Angle theorem" and which is similar to the sequence of theorem IX31. "If a vertical and an inclined plane are drawn from the same point on the horizontal, and on the inclined plane is taken any point from which a line perpendicular to it is extended toward the vertical, [then] the motions [both] along the part of the vertical intercepted between the horizontal and the [point of] intersection with the perpendicular and along the part of the inclined plane intercepted between the same perpendicular and the horizontal are completed in the same time" (Opere, VIII, p. 385.21-26). After that the proposition was enunciated in terms of the diagram, the demonstration was laid down as follows: different fragment parts. The diagram corresponding to number 6-fig. 14 was reproduced by Drake (in Galilei, 1979, p. 9) in a false way. The circle is not on the inclined plane but under it. 31 The sequence of theorem IX is composed of theorems such as Propositions IX-XVI (DML 2). "From the ... point F draw FH perpendicular to the horizontal, which is be parallel to the vertical CD. Then angle HFC will be equal to the alternate angle FCG, and right angle CHF to right angle CFG. Therefore triangles CHF and CFG will be equiangular, so that as HF is to FC, so is FC to CG. But just as HF is to FC, so the moment of heaviness [momentum gravitatis] of a movable on plane CE to its total moment [totale suum momentum] on the vertical CD. Therefore distance CF has to distance CG the same ratio that the moment of heaviness on the plane CE has to the total moment along the vertical CG. Wherefore the motions along CF and CG will be accomplished in the same time" (Opere, VIII, pp. 385.21-386.11)32. What was to be proved is that t(CG) = t(CF). This was demonstrated by geometrical means and by the use of the moment of heaviness. The main steps of the deduction can be summarized as follows: 1. ° HFC = ° FCG and ° CHF = ° CFG = Right angle. 2. 3. Consequence: HF / FC = FC / CG. 4. But HF / FC = mom grav (CE) / tot mom (CD). 5. Therefore from 3 and 4, FC/CG= mom grav (CE) / mom grav (CG). 6. Wherefore t (CF) = t (CG). The result may have been demonstrated by the application of the law of chords, after the drawing of a circle around the diameter CG. But Galileo discarded this solution and preferred to deduce his result as a relation of velocities where he invested De motu theorem. From the proportionality between momenta gravitatis and velocities, assumed elsewhere (as in f. 172v), the equation [5] may be transcribed as FC / CG = V (CF) / V (CG), assuming that the moment of heaviness is constant along all the parts of the inclined plane and along all the parts of the vertical [mom grav (CE) = mom grav (CF) and mom grav (CD) = mom grav (CG)]. On the basis of these implicit assumptions, Galileo didn't pose the question if the moments of heaviness make the instantaneous velocities or the total velocity increase. This question threatened to ruin all his reasoning, but for him it wasn't worthy of attention; he contented himself with establishing a proportionality between the momenta gravitatis and the velocity, wether instantaneous or total. Cut by S. Drake in two pieces (Galilei, 1979, pp. 4, 8), the text of folio 180r was neatly and elegantly copied by Arrighetti on the verso of f. 177 (Galilei, 1979, p. 148). 32 Later, in Florence around 1618, according to the available results of the recent critical li-terature, Nicolò Arrighetti made a copy of the contents of folio 180r on the verso of f. 177v. On the recto of this last document, he copied another Galilean fragment, composed of two parts. The first one was crossed out by cross lines and interrupted in the middle of a word. Its transcription in the Ediz. Naz. didn't reproduce the letter "b" present on the diagram in the manuscript; although this letter plays an important role in recent interpretations of this document, it has been neglected by previous studies. "The velocities of moving bodies which begin motion with such unequal moment[s] that, for example,the body begins its motion along AC with a moment [momentum] which is to the moment along AD as AD is to AC, are always to one another in the same ratio as if they were to move with uniform motion [ac si aequabili motu progrederetur]. If it were to move with uniform motion [si aequabili motu progrederetur], the time along AC would be to the time along AD as AC is to AD, which I doubt in the case of accelerated [motion]; and therefore demontrate [quod in accelerato dubito quidem, et ideo demonstra...]" Thus, otherwise [Aliter sic]33: "From the preceding [proposition], the time along AC is to the time along AB as line AC to line AB. But it has the same ratio also with respect to the time along AD, since AB is the mean proportional between AC and AD. Therefore, the times along AD and along AB will be equal" (Opere, VIII, pp. 386.12-24, Galilei, (1979), pp. 10, 26).34 In this translation of "aliter sic" I follow the "ainsi autrement" proposed by P. Souffrin (1991, p. 101). 34 Folio 177r is a copy in the hand of Arrighetti. The first paragraph is canceled by cross lines, probably by Galileo, whom the traces of the revisions and corrections on the copies made by his disciples are visible in many documents of Vol. 72. Favaro estimated that Arrighetti did add at the beginning of the fragment : "addere hanc propositionem ad praecendetem existimo", then he cancelated the first word "addere" to which he substituted "necessariam" (Opere, VIII, p. 386, n.2). Drake (1978, p. 81, n.16), considering that f. 177r shares with f. 180r the same theoretical concern, considered that this phrase is a part of the original galilean note copied by Arrighetti. So, in his translation of the fragment, it begins with : "I deem this proposition necessary to the preceding". If we pay attention to the substitution of "addere" to "necessarium", the sentence should be: "I consider [or I deem] that I should add this proposition to the preceding". Logically and very probably, the "preceding" to which the fragment refer is nothing else than the fragment of f. 180r copied by Arrighetti on the verso of f. 177. As it is remarked by P. Souffrin (1991, p. 101), the two fragments are considered in the historiographical literature as independent and without relation with each other. In this perspective, the "aliter sic" is seen to have no precise signification. But the results of the recent investigations show that such an attitude doesn't help to understand this document. 33 A D A B C D [Fig. 16] C B [Fig. 17] Folio 177r Stated in the first fragment is a relation of momenti: Mom (AC) / Mom (AD) = DA / AC. Then, and under the explicit condition of the uniformity of motion, the Theorem III is said to follow: t (AD) / t (AC) = AD / AC. The apparent evokation of uniform motion does not mean that Galileo considered that the theorem holds only in this type of motion. Indeed, according to a point of view widely accepted, this first part of f. 177r reveals the doubts Galileo raised concerning the validity of Theorem III in the case of accelerated motion. According to this view, it was for this reason that he returned to its demonstration in the second fragment. But the results of contemporary research show that no question was raised in the mind of Galileo on the applicability of the theorem in accelerated motion. From the time in which he revised Le Mecaniche and discovered the three propositions communicated to Guidobaldo dal Monte, he couldn't ignore the acceleration any more. Therefore, the sort of motion he was occupied with after 1602 –as in f. 177r– must be nothing else than the accelerated motion. In this document, he stated, in a standard medieval way of speaking, that the Theorem III holds in the case of uniform motion (of which it is a sort of definition) and proposed to demonstrate it also in the case of accelerated motion. The disappointment he manifested is relevant to his incredulity of the fact that the theorem holds in the case of the two kinds of motions. In order to find his way out of the puzzle, he paraphrased the theorem in terms of momenti (Mom (AC) / Mom (AD) = DA / AC). Assuming that the momenti generate equal velocities, this relation may be expressed in terms of velocity: V(AC) / V (AD) = AD / AC. But his supposition is founded on the assumption of the double equality AD = AC and V (AD) = V (AC). Seeking to demonstrate the Length-Time proportionality in the second fragment, Galileo began by stating the theorem: 1. By the preceding, it is assumed that t (AC) / t (AB) = AC / AB. 2. But t (AC) / t (AD) = AC / AB, AB being m (AC, AD). 3. Therefore, t (AD) = t (AB). Referring to the diagram of the second fragment [fig. 17], the last equality is attesting the Right-Angle theorem demonstrated in f. 180r and copied on the verso of f. 177. If this interpretation is exact, the two fragments cited above are attempts to resolve puzzles and doubts gene-rated by the Right-Angle theorem and the Length-Time proportionality. In these puzzles lays the question of the status of velocity in the relations of times and distances35. The investigations conducted by Galileo on the problem of the Right-Angle Theorem led him to the discovery of the Rule of Double Distance and the Postulate36. Several theorems of DML2 (numbered later as theorems IV-V, VIIXI) emerged within these investigations. It is seen in the passages concerned with the question of velocity in the First Day of the Dialogo (Opere, VII, pp. 47-50) the expression of Galileo's remembering of his ancient speculations on the RightAngle Theorem and the question of the motion of two bodies from rest on two different slopes. III. INVESTIGATIONS ABOUT VELOCITY AND FREE FALL In this section a decisive period of the Galilean investigations on motion will be approached, when Galileo began to deal directly with the problems of the law of fall. The heart of this work is evidently constituted by the two folios 128 and 85v, which are the documents associated with the letter to Sarpi of October 1604. But other contemporaneous papers of Vol. 72 are also concerned. For example, folio 147 documents the effort of Galileo to prove the law of fall according to a geometrical pattern more in conformity with the Euclidean canons. For a more detailed analysis of this first fragment, see Souffrin (1991, pp. 100-103) and Takahashi (1993, pp. 12-14). It is remarkable that the independent researchs of P. Souffrin and K. Takahashi led them to almost identical interpretations of f. 177r. The main feature of Souffrin's interpretation is the strict relationship he established between the two fragments of the document, in order to clear out the physical situation. In this perspective, the proposition demonstrated in the second fragment is considered to be strictly linked with the statement proposed in the beginning of the first fragment, i. e. the distances traversed in equal times are in a constant ratio, while the conclusion of the second fragment is precisely a geometrical construction of such a ratio. He concluded, finally, that the result established by Galileo was the Right-angle theorem: in the motion on the vertical and on an inclined plane from rest, distances that are as the spaces (which are as the moments) are traversed in equal times or, in other words, the velocities are between them in a constant ratio, which is the ratio of the moments. 36 The Postulate is the second principle on which was grounded the theory of accelerated motion in DML, the first being the definition of naturally accelerated motion. According to this principle, "the degrees of speed acquired by the same moveable over different inclinations of planes are equal whenever the heights of those planes are equal" (Opere, VIII, p. 205; Galilei, 1974, p. 162). The Rule of Double Distance as well as the Postulate pose the problem of the ratios of velocities or of the times along different paths of motions. On the emergence of the Rule of Double Distance see in the next section the discussion of a fragment recorded on f. 163v; for the postulate, see below section IV. 1. 35 But before we discuss this episode of the genesis of the Galilean thought, let us begin with the analysis of some notes that inform us on the paradoxes and the confusions faced by Galileo in his meditations on velocity and acceleration. 1. Speculations and paradoxes about velocity and acceleration The folios 172v, 163v and 164v document the early efforts of Galileo to precise his ideas on the problem of velocity in motion. The general background of his analysis is still marked by the De motu theorem and by the mechanical conceptual system. In folio 172v the problem of velocity is posed in relation to the law of chords and in this document we may see the emergence of a dynamic principle according to which the velocities are generated by momenta gra-vitatis. On the other hand, folio 163v reveals the discovery of a positive result that will be useful in later research: the Double Distance Rule. If this folio has been composed after the docu-ments associated with the letter to Sarpi, it may mean that Galileo sought for a while to construct a theory of motion on the basis of the proportionality velocity-space. Finally, a fragment entered on the verso of folio 164 accounts for a paradox on velocity. 1.1. Dynamic approach to the problem of velocity Folio 172v reflects Galileo's concerns with the concept of velocity. Here is the text of this important document: "Let there be a horizontal plane along line ABC and two planes inclined to it along lines DB and DA; I say that the same movable will move more slowly along DA than along DB in the ratio of length DA to length DB. Indeed, erect BE from B vertical to the horizontal, and from D draw DE perpendicular to BD, meeting BE at E. Around triangle BDE describe a circle tangent to AC at point B; from this, draw BF parallel to AD, and connect FD. It is clear that the slowness [tarditatem] along FB will be similar to the slowness along DA. But since the movable moves in the same time along DB and FB, clearly the velocities [velocitates] along DB to the velocities along FB are as DB to FB, so that two moveables coming from points D and F by lines DB and FB always travel along proportional parts of the entire lines BD and FB in the same times [from rest]. But since angle BFD in the segment is equal to angle DBA with the tangent, while angle DBF is alternate to BDA, triangles BFD and ABD are similar, and as BD is to BF, so AD is to BD. Therefore as AD is to BD, so the speed along DB is to the speed along DA, and conversely, the tardity along DA is [in the same ratio] to the tardity along DB. E Folio 172v [Fig. 18] D F A B C If this is assumed, the rest can be demonstrated. Therefore it is to be postulated that velocity of motion is increased or diminished according to the ratio in which moments of heaviness [gravitatis momenta] are incresaed or diminished; and since it is clear that the moments of heaviness of the same moveable on the plane DB are to the moments [of heaviness] on plane DA as length DA is to length DB, for that reason the velocity along DB is to the velocity along DA as DA is to DB" (Opere, VIII, pp. 378.12-379.6; Galilei, 1979, p. 11) 37. The proposition is first ennunciated generally in terms of the diagram: the ratio of slowness on two inclined planes is proportional to the lengths of these planes. The final conclusion affirms instead a relation of velocities. The demonstration proceeds as follows: 1. Tard (DA) / tard (DB) = DA / DB, the tardity being assumed inversely proportional to velocity. 2. After the construction of the diagram, tard (FB) = tard (DA), the two planes having the same slope. 3. t (DB) = t (FB), by the law of chords. This demonstration has been copied by Guiducci on f. 34r (Galilei, 1979, p. 127). Folio 172v is a document very controversed in recent galilean studies. W. Wisan (1974, p. 222) linked it to the letters exchanged by Galileo and Luca Valerio in 1609, but in a subsequent work (Wisan, 1984, pp. 272-273) she considered it implicitly as belonging to the period before the letter to Sarpi of 1604. For S. Drake (1978, p. 80) f. 172v is an early document composed around 1603 in which Galileo sought to express the conclusion of the law of chords in terms of constant but differing speed along each slope. P. Souffrin (1991, pp. 96-100), on his part, interpreted it as a document that seeks to prove a proposition which is theoretically exact and constitutes the De motu theorem: "the spaces traversed in equal times on inclined planes of the same height are to each other inversely proportional as the lengths of the planes". For a detailed analysis of f. 172v, see the critical literature refered to in this note and galluzzi (1979, pp. 288-291); Giust (1981, p. 12) and takahashi (1993, pp. 4-6). 37 4. So it is evident that the velocities along DB / velocities along FB = DB / FB, that is V (DB) / V (FB) = DB / FB. 5. Since the ratio of the velocities on two planes of diverse inclinations is constant in the course of motion, then that parts of DB and FB which are between them as DB / FB are always traversed in the same times. 6. From elementary geometry, it is infered that BD / BF = AD / DB 7. Therefore, AD / DB = V (DB) / V (DA) and conversely AD / DB = tard (DA) / tard (DB). 8. In the lat paragraph a postulate is assumed: the increase or decrease of velocity depends on the increase or decrease of moments of heaviness. 9. Since mom grav (DB) / mom grav (DA) = DA / DB, 10. So V (DB) / V (DA) = DA / DB. What was to be shown is that the velocities on CA and on DB are in the ratio of DB to DA. In other terms, that the spaces traversed in equal times on two inclined planes of the same height are between them inversely as the lengths of these planes. This is, of course, the De motu theorem. The same result is infered in the last part of the document, but this time it is expressed in the form of a general dynamical principle, as a relation of moments of heaviness generating constant velocities, applied here to free fall. The analysis is founded on the law of chords and on the assumption that on two inclined planes, the spaces corresponding to the same time of motion from rest are in a constant ratio. This last assumption was assumed by Galileo at least from Le Mecaniche period. 1. 2. Emergence of the Rule of Double Distance During his Paduan researches on motion, Galileo recorded many entries on folio 163. Among the numerous notes marked on this document we find the complete derivation of Theo-rem XXII on the recto. The verso was devoted to a couple of fragments, written probably at different dates. The first of these is a sort of derivation of the Rule of Double Distance by means of comparison between velocities in accelerated and uniform motion. In the second note was attempted a demonstration of the Length-Time Proportionality, considered as a consequence of the law of fall and of the theorem of chords38. The text of the first note is short and illustrated by a double diagram: "Let there be naturally accelerated [naturaliter acceleratus] motion from A to B: I say that if velocity [velocitas] at all points AB were the same as that found at point B, the space AB would be 38 See below for an analysis of this note, Sect. IV. 1. traversed twice as quickly, because all the velocities [velocitates omnes] in the single points of line AB have the same ratio to all the velocities each of which is equal to the velocity BC, as the triangle ABC has to the rectangle ABCD. From this, it follows that if there were a plane BA inclined to the horizontal line CD, and BC being double BA, then the moving body would come from A to B and successively from B to C in equal times. For after it was in B, it will be moved along the remaining BC with the same uniform velocity that it had at terminus B after fall AB. It is further clear that the whole time through ABE is three-halves [sesquialterum] that through AB" (Opere, VIII, pp. 383.24-384.13; Galilei, 1979, p. 19)39. A D A B [Fig. 19] C C Fo lio 163v {1} E B D [ Fig. 20 ] In De motu, Galileo has affirmed a notion of the possibility of continuation of motion on the horizontal plane; in Le Mecaniche, this idea was well developed: on such a plane, a frictionless body should be indifferent and questioning between rest and motion (Opere, II, p. 180.1-5). On the verso of f. 163, a similar idea of conservation is formulated in the shape of a mathematical relationship, the Rule of Double Distance, This rule will be so useful in the subsequent work performed by our scientist later on projectile motion40. Another assumption guided the reasoning on f. 163v. Since velocity at any point on AB is to the final velocity on BC as triangle ABC to rectangle ABCD (that is in the ratio 1 to 2) [fig.19], the space AB would be traversed "twice as fast" in that uniform motion whose velocity is equal to the final velocity acquired at point B [fig. 2O]. This result may be called the double velocity rule. It is obvious that Galileo is assuming here the relation v d. In a subsequent note on the same f. 163v, the Double Distance Rule is set forth, on the basis of the result stated in the first note: This note had been copied by Arrighetti (f. 181r, Galilei, 1979, p. 150). In the bottom of f. 181r, the Galilean note is followed by the following remark: "Huic demonstrationi necessarium mihi videtur ostendisse antea, motum orizontalem uniformiter progredi in infinitum". 40 DDR affirms that if a body is moved from rest on an inclined plane and then its motion continued on an horizontal plane with a uniform motion equal to the maximum velocity acquired in the accelerated descent, it would complete the space AB "twice as quickly" as in the first accelerated motion. This rule has been helpful in the process of derivation of the fundamental relation v t . On this point, see below the analysis of f. 91v, Sect. IV. 3. 39 if BC= 2AB, then t (AB) = t (BC, A) [fig. 21]. "If a motion is continued through the horizontal plane after a fall through a certain inclined plane, the time of fall through the inclined plane will be to the time of fall through any horizontal line as double the length of the inclined plane is to the taken horizontal line. Let a horizontal line be CB, and an inclined plane be AB. And after the fall through AB let a motion be continued through the horizontal, in which let any line, BD, taken. I say that the time of fall through AB is to the time of fall through BD as double AB is to BD. For, BC be taken double AB, it is clear from what were demonstrated that the time of fall through AB is equal to the time of motion through BC. But the time of motion through BC is to the time of motion through BD as line CB is to line BD. Therefore the time of motion through AB is to the time of motion through BD as double line AB is to line BD" (Opere, VIII, p. 384. 14-24). A Folio 163v {2} [ Fig. 21 ] C D B In the inference of DDR, Galileo sought to find BC such that t(BC, A) = t(AB). On the basis of the idea of preservation of motion and the result of the first step, he derived DDR: if BC = 2AB and t (AB) = t (BC, A) = T. Then, two corollaries are derived on the lower part of the page. The first one stated that if BE = 1/2 BC, then t (BE, A) = 1/2 t (AB) = 1/2 T; and t(AB) + t (BE, A) = T + 1/2 T = 3/2 T; while we learn from the second that if D is a point between B and C, then t (AB) / t (BD) = 2 AB / BD. This corollary will be later formalized as Theorem XVI of DML2. The Double Distance Rule provided an important element on the the relationship between accelerated and uniform motions. In the Discorsi, this relationship will be expressed formally as the Theorem I which opens the Liber II of DML41. In f. 163v, this rule was founded on the assumption that in free fall the velocity is directly proportional to distance of fall. In effect, altough the Double Distance Rule is a correct statement about the motion of fall from the point of Theorem I de motu naturaliter accelerato enunciated that a body traversing the same distance under acceleration from rest has half as much velocity as if it moved uniformly over the whole distance at the maximum speed acquired under acceleration (Opere, VIII, p. 208). 41 view of classical mechanics, Galileo's derivation of it depends on the principle mentioned in the letter to Sarpi (the proportionality between velocities and distances in accelerated motion), which is a false principle from the point of view of classical mechanics42. If the first fragment of f. 163v was composed after the letter to Sarpi, it may mean that Galileo considered the possibility of founding a theory of motion on the basis of the proportio-nality v s. If this hypothesis is correct, a document of the same period, the folio 172r (Opere, VIII, pp. 392.16-393.17; Galilei, 1979, p. 45), shows that he also attempted to derive Theorem III directly from the relation v s so that he could demonstrate the law of chords on the basis of the law of fall and of Theorem III. 1. 3. A paradox on velocity Folio 164v reveals a paradox related to the status of the concept of velocity in accelerated motion. Comparing two accelerated motions, one along the vertical and the other along an inclined plane, Galileo posed the question about the velocity in the two cases. "It has to be seen [Mirandum] wether the motion along the perpendicular AD is not perhaps faster than that along the inclined plane AB ? It seems so; in fact, equal spaces are traversed more quickly along AD than along AB. Still it seems not so; in fact, drawing the horizontal BC, the time along AB is to the time along AC as AB is to AC, then the moments of velocity [momenta velocitatis] along AB and along AC are the same. And effectively, that velocity is one and the same which, in unequal times traverses unequal spaces which are in the same proportion as the times" (Opere, VIII, p. 375.14-22; Galilei, 1979, p. 78). A B C Folio 164v [ Fig. 22 ] D This note can be paraphrased as follows : 1. The motion along the vertical must be faster than the motion along the inclined plane, since "equal spaces are traversed more quickly" (or in less time) along the vertical than along the oblique path. 42 Wisan (1974), pp. 206-07; Renn (1992), p. 174. 2. But, according to Theorem III: t (AB) / t (AC) = AB / AC, which contradicts the first statement. 3. Now, the mom vel (AB) = mom vel (AC). This equality is then expressed in the form of a general definition of equal velocities, which are those that "in unequal times traverse unequal spaces which are in the same proportion as the times". Such a reflection on velocity with relationship to Theorem III is similar to the one recor-ded on f. 177r, but without reference here to uniform motion. In the Mirandum fragment, Galileo is preoccupied with another aspect of his velocity concept, trying to solve the incompatibility between the two first statements of his argument. Noticing this incompatibility, he did let it open as one more paradox of the treatment of velocity: how could it be that in accelerated motion too, equal velocities are characterized by equal proportions between distances and times43. 2. Derivation of the Law of fall: The crisis of 1604 The law of free fall states that distances from rest are proportional to the squares of elapsed times from rest. In 1604, Galileo sought to prove this important theorem on the basis of an erroneous principle: the proportionality between the growth of velocity and the space traversed from rest. In the Discorsi, he opened the De motu naturaliter accelerato by the definition attesting the proportionality between the degrees of velocity and the times of fall, then made an allusion to his ancient error and tried to refute it by a reasoning considered generally by historians as erroneous44. Then, the law of free fall was stated and demonstrated as Theorem II of accelerated motion, followed by two corollaries which constitute different formulations of the same law: the rule of odd numbers45 and the mean proportional corollary46. We don't find a manuscript version of the demonstration of the Timessquared theorem as it was presented in the Discorsi. Instead, there exists in Vol. 72 a direct demonstration of the theorem on f. 128 and two mathematical arguments related to the mean-proportional corollary on ff. 85v and 147r. It is possible that I rely in the interpretation of f. 164v on Wisan (1974), pp. 201-204 and Renn (1992), pp. 197-199. 44 On this question, see Cohen (1956), Hall (1958), Drake (1970 a), pp. 28-42, (1970b), pp. 229237, Finnochiaro (1972), (1973), Sylla (1986), pp. 81-83. 45 The successive spaces traversed in successive equal intervalls of time in the motion of fall are as the odd numbers from the unity (Opere, VIII, p. 210). 46 If at the beginning of motion there are taken any two spaces whatever, run through in any two times, the times will be to each other as either of these two spaces is to the mean proportional between these two given spaces (Ibid, p. 214). 43 Galileo performed his final deduction of this important proposition in the stage of the final composition of his treatise on motion. The historical and epistemological debate about the 1604 documents has been thoroughly discussed by historians. In his classical study of this episode of the Galilean thought, Koyré (1966) concluded that Galileo has accorded to space what must be attributed to time and his error may be characterized as a "géométrisation à outrance". Hence, his error was mathematical and conceptual, and, in sum, a trivial one, because it was favorised by the visual and empirical advantage of space. But the errors of a Galileo are instructive. They are helpful in the appre-ciation of the inherent difficulties raised by a scientific problem in a defined historical context. It does import to characterize them conveniently, and to scrutinize the functioning or dysfunctioning of the systems of thoughts and concepts which provoked them47. The scenario I propose for the way in which Galileo may have discovered and demonstra-ted the squared-time theorem in Padua around 1604 is the following. First, he formulated it as a relation of the mean proportional, more compatible with Euclidean geometry and specially with the theory of proportions (Elements, Book V), which was the main mathematical theory he worked with. Then he tried to demonstrate his theorem directly. This line of reasoning is reflected by his work on ff. 147, 85 and128. 2. 1. Official announcement of the Times-squared theorem The famous letter addressed by Galileo on October 16, 1604, to his Venitian friend Paolo Sarpi constitutes the act one of the "1604 affair." In it he announced his discovery of a law of free fall in the form of the times-squared theorem, and he stated his theorem on the basis of a "natural and evident principle", namely the proportionality of degrees of velocity in natural motion to the space traversed (v S). The general line along which he presented his thought is as follows: if we accept as true this principle, then the theorem (the space traversed is proportional to the square of the time elapsed in fall: S T2) can be proved. The 1604-episode in the genesis of Galileo's thought is well known. The documents associated with the letter to Sarpi were analysed widely. In a previous work (Abattouy, 1989, chap. V) I examined extensively all the aspects related to this point. In the following, my aim will be the simple presentation ofa general overview on the debate concerning these documents. 47 A B C Letter to Sarpi [ Fig. 23 ] D "Thinking again about the matters of motion, in which, to demonstrate the phenomena [accidenti] observed by me, I lacked a completely indubitable principle to put as an axiom, I am reduced to a proposition which has much of the natural and the evident: and with this assumed, I then demonstrate the rest; that is, that the spaces passed by natural motion are in double proportion to the times, and consequently the spaces passed in equal times are as the odd numbers from one, and the other things. And the principle is this: that the natural movable goes increasing in velocity with that proportion with which it departs from the beginning of its motion; as, for example, the heavy body falling from the terminus A along the line ABCD, I assume that the degree of velocity that it has at C, to the degree it had at B, is as the distance CA to the distance BA, and thus consequently, at D it has a degree of velocity greater than at C according as the distance DA is greater than CA. I should like your reverence to consider this a bit, and tell me your opinion. And if we accept this principle, we not only demonstrate (as I said) the other conclusions, but I believe we also have it very much in hand to show that the naturally falling body and the violent porojectile pass through the same proportions of velocity" (Opere, X, p. 115)48. In the letter Galileo didn't expose any demonstration of the Times-squared theorem; the proof is contained in a document of Vol. 72, the famous folio 128r-v which is chronologically very close to the letter to Sarpi. In effect, many elements, theoretical and material, confirm that the two documents belong to the same intellectual stage in the evolution of Galileo's thought, and were written very probably in the last quarter of 160449. Namely, that "it is manifest that the impetus at the points D, C, B goes decreasing in the proportions of the lines DA, CA, BA; whence, if it goes acquiring degrees of velocity in the same (proportions) of the lines DA, CA, BA; whence, if it goes acquiring of velocity in the same (proportions) in natural fall, what I have said and believed up to now is true" (ibid, p. 115). 49 Folio 128 is one of the rare documents of Vol. 72 to be dated very undoubtedly. Besides the similarity of the mahematical argument in the folio and in the letter to Sarpi, the same watermark is found in a cover sheet of the letter to Sarpi, in folio 128 and in f. 4 of Mss. Gal. 47, on which Galileo recorded some notes related to the nova of October 1604. On this point, see Drake, 1972a, pp. 60-61 and Drake, 1978, p. 76, n. 6. Moreover, J. Renn (1992, pp. 16948 2. 2. Kinematical demonstration of the Mean Proportional As conjectured above, it is possible that Galileo dealt with the Times-squared theorem at first in the form of the mean proportional formula. The traces of this preliminary investigation is recorded on ff. 147r and 85v. Let's begin by outlining the reasoning entered on the first of these documents50. "After it has been demonstrated that the times through AB and AC are equals, it must be shown that the time through AD is to time through AE as DA is to the mean [proportional] between DA and AE. For the time through DA is to the time through AC as line DA is to AC; but the time through AC (which is that through AB) is to the time AE as line BA is to AE, which is as SA is to AD. Therefore, by equidistance of ratios in perturbed proportionality [ex aequali in analogia perturbata], the time through AD is to the time through AE as line SA is to line AC. And since AC, as has been demonstrated, is the mean [proportional] between SA and AB, while as SA is to AB, so DA is to AE, therefore the time through AD is to the time through AE as DA is to the mean [proportional] between DA and AE, which was to be proved" (Opere, VIII, 380.1-12; Galilei, 1979, 24). In this document, we have probably indications on how Galileo's work on the law of fall gave birth to a precise formula for the characterization of acceleration in natural motion, which was expressed in terms of the Mean Proportional Rule, in such a form that the times-squared relation can be deduced automatically from it. The demonstration is founded on two presuppositions: the law of chords and the Theorem III [Fig. 24]. Beginning by assuming the law of chords, the conclusion to be deduced is said to follow from it. For t (AD) /t (AC) = DA / AC, but t (AC) [= t (AB)] / t (AE) = BA / AE = SA / AD. Therefore, by the application of a technique of the Euclidean theory of proportions, the equidistance of ratios in perturbed proportionality, t (AD) / t (AE) = SA / AC. 170) attaracted attention to the close relationship devoted by the two Galilean documents (the letter to sarpi and f. 128) to the symmetry between projectile motion and the motion of fall. This argument can be considered as a supplementary argument of datation. 50 This reconstrcution of Galileo's discovery and demonstration of the law of fall along these lines (that is, at first in terms of mean-propoprtional, then as the Times-squared relation, and finally with an experimental corroboration, as the one recorded on f. 107v) was presented in Abattouy, 1989, p. 367 ff and pp. 431-450. Assuming that AC = m (SA, AB) and SA / AB = DA / AE, therefore, t (AD) / t (AE) = DA / m (DA, AE). As noted by J. Renn (1992, p. 158), in this demonstration Galileo derived "a quantitative law of acceleration from two premises which by themselves do not presuppose an analysis of the internal structure of the motion of fall". Although it didn't constitute a proof in the strict sense, since it said nothing on the law of motion and on the crucial question of the mode in which the speed grows in fall, the demonstration developed in f. 147r constituted undoubtedly an important step in Galileo's search for a complete proof of the law of fall. 2. 3. Physical proof and indications on the resolution of the crisis The third document which may be associated with the letter to Sarpi is f. 85v, a Latin copy by Guiducci of a paduan original of Galileo, now lost. The contents of the note recorded on this paper can be an intermediary stage between the mathematical arguments constructed on the ff. 147 and 128. On f. 85v, the timessquared theorem was formulated in terms of the Mean Proportional Rule, and its deductive structure was founded on the proportionality of velocities to spaces traversed from rest. "I assume that the acceleration [accelerationem]of the falling body along the line AL is such that the velocity [velocitas] increases in the ratio of the space traversed so that the velocity in C is to the velocity in B as the space CA is to the space BA, etc. Matters standing thus, let the line AX be drawn at some angle to AL, and, taking the parts AB, BC, CD, DE, etc. To be equal, draw BM, CN, DO, EP, etc. If therefore the velocities of the body falling along AL in the places B, C, D, E are as the distances AB, AC, AD, AE, etc., then they will also be as the line BM, CN, DO, EP. But because the velocity is successively increased in all points of the line AE, and not only in B, C and D, which are drawn, therefore all these velocities [velocitates illae omnes]are to one another as the lines from all the said points of the line AE, which are gene-rated equidistantly from the same BM, CN, DO. But those are infinite and constitute the triangle AEP: therefore the velocities in all points of the line AB are to the velocities in all points of the line AC as the triangle ABM to the triangle ACN, and so for the remaining, i.e., in double proportion of the lines AB, AC. But because in the ratio of the increase [of velocity due] to acceleration the times in which the motions themselves occur must decrease, therefore the time in which the moving body traverses AB will be to the time in which it traverses AC as the line AB is to that line which is the mean proportional between AB and AC" (Opere, VIII, pp. 383.1-23; Galilei, 1979, 43). As it is extant now in the Manuscript 72, this note is crossed out by cross lines, eventually by Galileo himself. It is possible that this Latin memorandum was wrongly copied in Florence. If this conjecture is correct, the error may have been done by Galileo himself (who included it among the fragments to be reproduced) or by Guiducci. It is in effect very difficult to think that Galileo continued to hold very probably the copies were executed. On the contrary, that the note on f. 85v was crossed out can be interpreted as a decisive indication o Moreover, there is another indication as much significative as this one. Effectively, the obvious and logical function of the line marked "S" near the diagram [fig. 25] should be that the vertical line in the triangle of speeds must represent time, while the graphical representation of the spaces traversed is to be drawn on an independant line. By this, Galileo corrected implicitly, at least for himself, his old error, and perthaps conceived at this occasion the argument by which he rejec-ted in the Discorsi the proportionality of the changing velocities to space. 2. 4. Formal deduction of the Times-squared theorem The document represeting the attempts of Galileo in 1604 in order to produce a deductive treatment of acceleration, and precisely to demonstrate mathematically the Times-squared theorem is recorded on f. 128. The text of this paper is two pages long and well structured. "I suppose (and perhaps I shall be able to demonstrate this) that the naturally falling heavy body goes continually increasing its velocity according as the distance increases from the terminus from which it parted, as, for example, the heavy body departing from the point A and falling through the line AB. I suppose that the degree of velocity at point D is as much greater than the degree than AC; and so the degree of velocity at E is to the degree of velocity at D as EA to DA, and thus at every point of the line AB it [the body] is to be found with degrees of velocity proportional to the distances of these points from the terminus A. This principle appears to me very natural, and one that corresponds to all the experiences that we see in the instruments and machines that work by striking, in which the percussent works so much the greater effect, the greater the height from which it falls; and this principle assumed, I shall demonstrate the rest. Draw line AK at any angle with AF, and through points C, D, E and F draw the parallels CG, DH, EI, FH: and since lines FK, EI, DH, and CG are to one another as FA, EA, DA, CA, therefore the velocities at points F, E, D and C are as lines FK, EI, DH and CG. So the degrees of velocity go continually increasing at all points of line AF according to the increase of parallels drawn from all those same points. Moreover, since the velocity with which the moving body has come from A to D is compounded from all the degrees of velocity it had at all the points of line AD, and the velocity with which it has passed through line AC is compounded from all points of line AC, therefore the velocity with which it has passed the line AD has that proportion to the velocity with which it has passed the line AC which all the parallel lines drawn from all the points of line AD over to AH have to all the parallels drawn from all the points of line AC over to AG; and this proportion is that which the triangle ADH has to the triangle ACG, that is the square of AD to the square of AC. Then the velocity with which the line AD is traversed to the velocity with which the line AC is traversed has the double proportion that DA has to CA. And since velocity to velocity has contrary proportion [contraria proportione] of that which time has to time (for it is the same thing to increase the velocity as to decrease the time), therefore the time of the motion along AD to the time of the motion on AC has half the proportion that the distance AD has to the distance AC. The distances, then, from the beginning of the motion are as the squares of the times, and, dividing, the spaces passed in equal times are as the odd numbers from unity. Which corresponds to what I have always said and to experiences observed; and thus all the truths are in accord" (Opere, VIII, pp. 373.1-374.22; Galilei, 1979, pp. 41-42) . The line ACDEFB represents the trajectory of the body falling from rest at A; the parallels CG, DH, EI, FK are between them as the degrees of velocity in C, D, E, K respectively. After the graphical representation is set out, the demonstration can be resumed in the following way. 1. The degrees of velocity are proportional to the spaces traversed: deg vel (C)/ deg vel (D) = CG / DH. 2. Representing the velocity at any point of AB by a parallel line, V(F), V(E), V(D) and V(C) are proportional to FK, EI, DH and CG. 3. Moreover, since V(AD) = all the instantaneous velocities on AD, then V(AD) / V(AC) = all the vi (AD) / vi (AC). 4. That is, D ADH / D ACG = AD2 / AC2. 5. Therefore V(AD) / V(AC) = AD2 / AC2. 6. And since velocity has contrary proportionality to time, then t (AD) / t (AC) = ÷ AD / AC. 7. Therefore AD / AC = t (AD)2 / t (AC)2, and by the division of ratios we obtain the rule of odd numbers. In this deduction, Galileo made use of two concepts of velocity: instantaneous velocity and a velocity acquired when the moveable passes through a given space in a time. Galileo linked these two concepts in step 3, when he considered that V is composed by numerous v. This allowed him to represent graphically V by the area of the triangle constituted of all parallel lines representing v at all points of AB. Historians considered that the error of Galileo is situated at steps 5 and 6, when he considered that velocity is proportional to the square of the distance and that velocity had contrary proportionality to time, from which he deduced the theorem finally. In other terms, Galileo derived a relation between space and time from a proportionality between velocity and space. In fact, he was helped in this procedure by the second of his two concepts of velocity: the velocity acquired on a distance, which was defined in Galileo's days along the lines of what was allowed by Euclidean theory of proportionality: in the case of equality of velocities, the spaces are as the times; in the case of equality of the times, the velocities are proportional to spaces. From these relations, he could generalize, as he does in Theorem IV of De motu aequabili . It remains to understand Galileo's use of the contrary proportionality. It seems that there Galileo made an error in manipulating ratios, or at least that he made use of a technique of the theory of proportions that have not yet been clearly identified by historians. Perhaps he founded his assertion on a trivial conception that the relation of velocity with time in motion is a relation between an increasing magnitude with a decreasing one. In effect, conceiving that "it is the same to increase velocity as to diminish time", he transcribed this proportionality in a relation of square root. On this ground, step (6) of the paraphrase can be translated in: Since V1 / V2 = ÷ Tl / T2, then Tl / T2 = ÷ S1 / S2; therefore S1 / S2 = T12 / T22. After he has finished his work on free fall as it is documented by the papers of 1604, Galileo must have continued his interrogations and speculations on the growth of velocity in the motion downward. It is in reality hard to admit that he was satisfied with the demonstration recorded on the f. 128 or on the paduan original of f. 85v. But failing to find an alternative way to demonstrate the Timessquared theorem, he gave up his search in this direction, and began working on other problems of motion, in the direction of researches recorded on the documents that will be analyzed in the next section . But before this, let's look briefly at another aspect of Galileo's investigations on the fall of bodies around 1604. I mean the experimental investigation he conducted in order to confirm the times-squared theorem. An important element of information in this perspective is provided by a set of calculations and diagrams on folio 107v where Galileo recorded probably the data obtained in the course of an experiment performed in order to confirm the law of fall. In this experiment, he measured the distances traversed in equal times along an inclined plane, then confronted the successive distances with the sequence of square numbers starting from the unity. The fact that he also entered several other simple sequences of integers in this manuscript page suggests that he had a precise idea about the acceleration along the plane. Besides the different sequences of numbers, folio 107v contains indeed two diagrams which may suggest that when drawing them Galileo was thinking of acceleration, precisely of the change of velocity in motion; at least one of the diagrams evokes the graphical representation proper to the medieval technique of configurations applied to the motion of fall . In fact, in f. 107v as in the other documents pertaining to 1604, the acceleration is explicitly and entirely admitted. In sum, these papers reveal an idea of acceleration which is incompatible with the one elaborated in De motu, in the sense that acceleration is no longer considered as a transitory accident, but as an essential property of the natural fall, to which it is worthwhile to look for a precise mathematical formula. IV. AFTER 1604 : NEW RESEARCHES ON FREE FALL AND FURTHER RESULTS The failure of the demonstration of the Times-squared law in folio 128 generated a sort of crisis in Galileo's work on motion. The obvious decisive consequence of such a crisis was that our scientist seems to start a new process of researches, in order to proove some other propositions emerged in the previous work on the fall of bodies. As far as the documents of Vol. 72 can inform us, these new investigations led him to the deduction of mathematical proofs of two important propositions, Theorem III and Theorem XXII . The analysis of the papers on which he recorded his exercises on these propositions reveals that he couldn't erase all the traces of the principle v s. Moreover, it is possible that he sought for a while to found his theory of motion on this principle, since several of his propositions were based on the proportionality of the velocities and the spaces traversed. If this interpretation is correct, we can suppose that the note concerned with the Rule of Double Distance on f. 163 emerged in this post-1604 crisis context. Indeed, on the verso of this document was entered a fragment devoted to the deduction of Theorem III as a consequence of the law of fall and of the law of chords. 1. Demonstration of the Length-Time Theorem The Theorem III of accelerated motion in the Discorsi stated a Length-Time proportiona-lity: in the motion from rest along the vertical and along the inclined plane of the same height, the times are as the lengths. The full manuscript demonstration of this proposition is built on the recto of f. 179, where the theorem is deduced in a way similar to the one in which it was demonstrated finally in the Discorsi. But we find in Vol. 72 other proofs of this theorem, as the one recorded on the verso of f. 163 and which seems to be of early date. The fragment on Theorem III in f. 163v follows the note related to the Rule of Double Distance discussed above and it is obviously written in a different handwriting: "The time of fall through an inclined plane is to the time of fall through the line of its height as the length of the same plane is to the length of its height. Let there be an inclined BA to the horizontal line AC such that the vertical line of heights is BC; I say that the time of fall in which a movable runs through BA is to the time in which it falls through BC as BA is to BC. Let a perpendicular AD to the horizontal be erected from A, and let [another] perpendicular to AB drawn from B, that is BD, meet it at D. Let a circle be circumcribed around triangle ABD. Then, since DA and BC are both perpendicular to the horizontal, it is clear that the time of fall through DA is to the time of fall through BC as the mean proportional between DA and BC is to the same BC. But the time of fall through DA is equal to the time of fall through BA, while the mean proportional between DA and BC is BA itself. Therefore the proposition is evident (Opere, VIII, pp. 384.25-386.20). In order to demonstrate Theorem III, the law of fall and the Mean Proportional Rule are introduced. t (DA) = t (BA), t (DA) / t (BC) = m (DA, BC) / BC. Since m (DA, BC) = BA, then t (BA) / t (BC) = BA / BC. On f. 179r, the demonstration of the same theorem followed another way. It was founded on the consequences of the Postulate and of a proposition on uniform motion. First, the theorem is stated: "If the same body is carried in the vertical and in an inclined plane, of which the height is the same, the times of motions are to one another as the lengths of the inclined planes and of the vertical". Then it is enunciated in terms of the diagram: "I say that the time of motion along AB is to the time of motion along AC as lenght AB is to length AC." "For, since it is assumed that in natural descent the {same} moments of velocity {are always found in points equally distant from the horizontal according to the vertical distances}, [and] grow continually according to the ratio of the vertical removal from the horizontal in which the beginning of motion was, it is clear tha producing the horizontal line AM which will be parallel to BC, and taking in the vertical any number of points E, G, I, and L, through which are drawn the parallels to the horizontal ED, GF, IH, and LK, then the moment or degree of velocity at point E of the body moving along AB will be the same with the degree of velocity at point D of the body carried along AC, since points E and D have the same vertical distance from the horizontal AM; and it is likewise concluded that the moment of velocity is the same at points F and G, and then again at points H and I, K and L, C and B. (And since velocity is always intensified in the ratio of the removal from the terminus A, it is clear that in motion AB there are many different degrees or moments of velocity [tot esse velocitatis gradus seu momenta diversa] as there are in the same line AB points distant from the terminus A, to which there correspond as many [points] in line AC, and these are determined by the parallel lines in which the same degrees of velocity exist). "Therefore there are in line AB, so to speak, innumerable tiny spaces [innumera spaciola], and the others, being equal in a certain sense to them in multitude and, {taken in pair}, corresponding [to them] in the same ratio, are designated in AC by innumerable parallel lines extended from points on line AB to line AC. {For the intercepted spaces AD, DF, FH, etc. correspond one by one to the spaces AE, EG, GI etc., according to the ratio of AC to AB}. And there exist the same degrees of velocity in particular corresponding pairs. "Therefore from the preceding, all the times taken together of all the motions along AB will have to all the times likewise taken of all the motions along AC the same ratio that all the spaces of line AB [have] to all the spaces of line AC. But this is indeed identical with the case that the time of fall along AB [tempus casus per AB] is to the time of fall along AC as line AB is to AC, which was to be demonstrated" (Opere, VIII, p. 387. 16-388. 28). This document is composed of many parts, as it is obvious, and one important feature of its structure is the existence of some signs revealing the revision to which it was submitted. This revision is manifest by the underlining of two passages and the addition of marginal notes, destinated to be inserted at precise places in the text. The first marginal note was intended evidently to be inserted in the third paragraph between the words velocitatis momenta and the following underlined passage. In this note was presented the famous Postulate, according to which the same moments of velocity are acquired at points equally distant from the horizontal after descents from rest. On the other hand, the two underlined passages refer to the principle v s, attesting that the velocities grow continually according to the distance from the initial point of motion. The underlining may indicate that Galileo intended to suppress these two passages, in order to annulate the effects of the false principle of the law of fall. But it was sufficient to substitute the Postulate to the first passage, and the effect of this controversed principle should be counterbalanced. In this case, the second underlined passage should be understood as developing the consequences of the Postulate, as it is clear from the analysis of the successive steps of the demonstration. What was to be proved is the proportionality t (AB) / t (AC) = AB / AC. The demonstration began properly by the introduction of the Postulate, after which a first result was obtained: the moment or degree of velocity acquired by the moveable on AE is the same as the one acquired on AD, since the points D and E are equally distant from A. Then, mom vel (F) = mom vel (G), mom vel (H) = mom vel (I), mom vel (K) = mom vel (L) and mom vel (C) = mom vel (B). In the next step, accounted for by the second underlined passage, AB abd AC are decomposed in many points in which are acquired different velocities. The points on AC correspond one-to-one to the points on AB. In the extremities of the parallel lines joining each pair of them two identical degrees of velocity are generated. In the last two paragraphs, a new and radical shift is introduced. Galileo proceeded to compare infinitesimal times in which are traversed, on the lines AB and AC, infinitesimal corres-ponding spaces. In this way, the two lines were decomposed in "innumerable tiny spaces" which correspond between them by pairs, each two spaces of the same pair holding between them the same ratio of AB to AC. Finally, he refered to the proposition elaborated on f. 138v: since the moments or degrees of velocity in each pair of the tiny spaces are equal, we can consider the velocity on each of these infinitesimal segments as if it was uniform. Therefore, the times on all the spaciola on AC will have the same ratio to all the spaciola on AB as the spaciola AC to the spaciola AB. It was not necessary to introduce in this demonstration any law of motion. As supposed by Wisan (1974, p. 219),this document reveals probably that at a certain time Galileo identified his Postulate with the erroneous law v s. An important aspect of the conceptual analysis conducted on f. 179r is represented by the infinitesimal method to which Galileo had recourse. Indeed, he began by associating the infinitude of instantaneous velocities acquired during the motion on the points of the vertical line to the infinitude of instantaneous velocities acquired on the inclined plane. But the points of motion on the two paths are not considered as mathematical points, but as little tiny spaces, an infinitude of which exists on each path of motion. Between these two infinite sets of spaciola a one-toone correspondence was established and represented by the infinity of parallel lines, on the extremities of each one of them two identical degrees of velocity are supposed to exist. Du-ring the motion along each corresponding two tiny spaces, the times elapsed are in the same ratio as these spaces and as the inclined plane is to the vertical. Therefore, on each one of these innumerable little segments, the motion can be considered as uniform. So the sum of the times along the two paths of motion would be as the sum of the segments; finally, by summation it could be concluded that t (AB ) / t (AC) = AB / AC. The shift from the "infinite points" to the "quasi innumera spaciola" allowed the application of the theorem recorded on f. 138v. As it was mentioned before, this proposition is a gene-ralization of Theorem I of uniform motion, elaborated in order to apply it to any two spaces of which the parts or segments correspond to each other if they are taken in successive pairs. Indeed, since Galileo specified that his geometrical reasoning on f. 179r took into account finite tiny spaces traversed in finite times, it didn’t matter how short was their duration. Even if they were very short intervalls of time, it was still possible to apply the Theorem stated in folio 138v. In this context, on each segment the velocity could be considered as uniform, and, hence, the times are as the distances (by Theorem I of DML1). It remained only to sum up the times and the tiny spaces and to infer the proportionality between the total times and spaces. 2. Return to a dynamical foundation On the verso of f. 179 are recorded two notes. The first note establishes a corollary to Theorem III (direct proportionality between times and lengths along any two inclined planes of the same height) (Opere, VIII, p. 389.1-14 ; Galilei, 1979, p. 65 ), while the second one was abondoned before its completion and two slips of paper were pasted over its text. Here is the text of this second note: "If in the line of natural descent two unequal distances from the starting point of the motion are taken, the moments of velocity [momenta velocitatis] with which the moving body traverses these distances are to one another in double proportion of those distances. Let AB be the line of natural descent, in which from the starting point A of the motion two distances AC and AD are taken: I say, that the moments of velocity with which the moving body traverses AD are to the moments of velocity with which it traverses AC in double proportion of the distances AD and AC. Draw line AE in an arbitrary angle with respect to AB..." (Opere, VIII, p. 380.15-24; Galilei, 1979, p. 65). Evidently, this unfinished note is related to a new speculation about free fall in which Galileo tried to demonstrate the relationship between moments of velocity and the square of the distances through which they are acquired. This proportionality was one of the crucial steps in the process of deduction of the Times-squared theorem in f. 128. It is possible that Galileo sought to prove it independently in order to prepare the tools by which he could return to a new analysis of the law of fall. In this fragment on f. 179v, the principle v s is implicitly assumed, at least in the geometrical representation, identical to the one which governed the mathematical reasoning in the 1604 papers. The fact that Galileo abondoned his argument before completion is a controversed question among historians. He did so probably because of his sudden awareness that he was repeating the same reasoning which he developed on f. 128. As it is preserved in Vol. 72, the incomplete fragment on f. 179v is covered by two sheets of paper on which are written two propositions. Here are the statements of these propositions: "The moments of heaviness [momenta gravitatis] of the same body on the inclined plane and on the vertical correspond to the length and elevation of the plane. (...) This is already proved in mechanics. "The moments of heaviness of the same body on the planes of different inclinations have to one another the same ratio as the lengths of the planes, provided that they correspond to the same elevation"(Opere, VIII, p. 376. 1-377. 2; Galilei, 1979, p. 8). The first proposition (mom grav (CA) / mom grav (CB) = CB / CA) was familiar to Galileo, and he declared that he proved it mechanically. It is, in fact, the De motu theorem, expressed –as in f. 172v– in terms of momenta gravitatis. The second is a corollary of this same proposition, generalizing it to any two inclined planes of the same height. Galileo’s act of pasting the two slips of paper bearing the De motu theorem on the verso of f. 179 can be interpreted as a search for a dynamical foundation, assuming probably that in this way he should not have recourse to any law of fall. If this explanation is correct, such a decision would mean that he decided to discard the kinematical methods with which he worked, and which led him to such paradoxes and confusions he experienced in the successive stages of his physical investigations. 3. Deduction of the proportionality Time-Velocity The destiny of the fragment written on the recto of f. 179 is illuminating about the struggle in which Galileo was engaged in order to solve the problems linked to his work on a law of fall. An important episode of this struggle is recorded on the verso of f. 164, where we find the paradox on velocity revealed by the Mirandum fragment (discussed above in Section III.1.3). Just after this fragment, a little note of two lines was added at the end of the document. It shows the emergence in Galileo's mind of a new formula for the characterization of velocity in free fall. This time, velocities in accelerated motion are considered to be proportional to square root of the distances. This formula was certainly considered by Galileo as a mean to resolve the 1604 crisis and the subsequent consequences of the analysis of motion bearing on the principle v s. His work of this new relation took the double form of theoretical analysis and experimental test, as it is revealed by some manuscript documents like the famous two folios 152r and 116v. The little note marked on the verso of folio 164 is composed of two lines. It stated that: "The moments of velocities [momenta velocitatis] of a body falling from a height are to one another as the square roots [radices] of the distances traversed, namely, [they are] in a subduplicated ratio of those" (Opere, VIII, pp. 380.13-14; Galilei, 1979, p. 78) . Written as a result obtained probably after intense investigations, this note corrected the error of 1604, and provided a mathematical relation that allows to calculate the rate of variation of the velocity in the motion of fall and the ratio existing between the velocity and the distance. Mathematically equivalent to the fundamental relation of the proportionality of velocity to the time (v t), it eliminated the possibility of referring directly the growth of velocity to the spaces traversed from rest and established the kind of relation that must be established between velo-cities and distances: a relation of square root. Evidently, this result is very important and should have made an end in principle to the crisis of 1604. The tortuous and difficult itinerary that led Galileo to the substitution of time to the space as the independent parameter for the growth of speed in free fall found here probably its first great achievement. With this new formula in hand, it was possible for Galileo to obtain the fundamental relation v t by a simple combination of his various theorems related to free fall: The folios 91v and 152r document Galileo’s discovery of the proportionality of degrees of velocity to the times elapsed in accelerated motion, and the way in which he demonstrated it. In f. 91v, the deduction of such an important result is conducted in full and all the steps of the demonstration are made explicit, which may suggest that the note recorded on this document represents the final stage of a long investigation, of which the traces are apparent on folio 152r. Folio 152 is composed of scattered notes, of two diagrams and of the text of a little geometrical demonstration [fig. 32]. Its fragmentary structure gave rise to many controversies. But recently, the debate on this document has been renewed by the discerning analysis of J. Renn (1992, pp. 181-194) who produced the most comprehensive and coherent analysis of all the material recorded on this paper. Considering it as one of the documents revealing Galileo’s discovery of the proportionality of degrees of velocity to times, he recognized the relationship linking it to f. 91. Consequently, he was able to produce a global interpretation of all the scattered notes disseminated on the folio and to describe the way in which Galileo found his way out of the puzzles he met in his long search for a law of fall. The experimental aspect of Galileo’s work on the formula v s can be found on the folio page 116v (Galilei, 1979, p. 79). This manuscript seems to be the most important unpublished document of the Vol. 72. Since its first publication in 1973, it was very discussed among historians in the recent Galilean studies. It is very likely that we have on this page a brief and sketchy protocol of a sophisticated experiment (according to the standards of Galileo's time and even to his own work) in which our scientist intended to test the formula which he discovered in his previous work, namely v s . Folio 116v, as f. 152r, seems to have been composed at the end of the Paduan period. It consists in a simple sheet of paper written only on the verso, comprising a set of arithmetical operations, two diagrams and some scattered numbers and words. For the interpretation of the document, it is necessary to account for these calculations disseminated, to link them to the main diagram and to give a coherent interpretation of all this material. The main diagram is particularly important and constitutes the key for the interpretation of the document. It consists of a rough drawing made of a vertical to which two parallel line representing the ground and the top of a table are perpendicular. Between these two lines five curved trajectories are displayed, which have the same origin and the same horizontal tangent. The dotted part of the vertical line is crossed by an important assertion: 828 punti, altezza della tavola. Since the punto is equal to 0.95 cm, this assertion means that the expriment was very probably performed on a real table of a height of 78cm. This information is very important because of its signification for the understanding of the experiment accounted for on f. 116v. Beside the vertical line, Galileo marked the distances of 300, 600, 800 and1000 punti. Another height of 828 punti was taken into account in the calculations that we find on the document, but it was not marked explicitly like the others. Therefore, we have five heights for vertical descent; a curved trajectory corresponds to each one of them and to each trajectory two numbers are associated. These numbers were inscribed in two superposed sets along the horizontal lower line. The first group of values comprises the numbers 800, 1172, 1328, 1340 and 1500, which are the experimental measures of horizontal projections from the extremity of the table, after initial vertical falls on an inclined plane from heights of 300, 600, 800, 828 and 1000 punti. The second group of numbers is composed by the theoretical predictions that Galileo obtained after he performed the calculations which are disseminated on the page and which are founded on a precise mathematical formula. These data are represented by the numbers 1131, 1306, 1330 and 1460. Each one of these is accompanied by the word "doveria" (should be) and by the difference which separates it from the value of the experimental measure that corresponds to it in the first group of data. These differences are, respectively, of 41, 22, 10 and 40 punti. The fact that there are two sets of numbers between which differences exist and that these differences are stressed by Galileo himself proves, undoubtedly, that the two sets of data were obtained by distinct methods. The experiment may have been performed in the following way. A spherical and round ball, composed of solid material, is let to descend along a grooved inclined plane AB put on a table [fig. 35]. In B, the inclined plane is connected to a little curved deflector intended to direct the trajectory of the ball towards the horizontal. In C, at the end of the deflector, the ball begins to describe a horizontal motion which is soon transformed in a semiparabolic trajectory, before reaching the ground at F. The components of this trajectory are the vertical height h and the ho-rizontal projection D. In order to obtain different horizontal projections, Galileo could change the initial point from which the ball starts to fall on the same inclined plane, or he could use many inclined planes of different heights. In the two cases, this implies different values for the height H from which the ball begins to roll down. In the first part of the experiment, Galileo was concerned exclusively by measuring the data of the different rollings and projections of the ball. First, he let the ball roll from a height of 300 punti and obtained a horizontal projection of 800 punti, then he changed the vertical heights, giving to for H the values of 600, 800 and 1000 punti successively. The projection D measured after each of these descents was respectively of 1172, 1328 and 1500 punti. Seeking to test the Rule of Double Distance, he performed a fifth test in which H = 828 punti, which is exactly the height of the table. According to the Double Distance Rule the ball should be projected along a distance D equal to 1656 punti. But Galileo obtained 1340 only, and when he calculated this value with his mathematical formula, he got no more than 1329. This discrepancy from the theoretical predictions must have disappointed him and remained one of the mysteries of the experiment recorded on f. 116v. This could be one of the reasons why this experiment was never described in Galileo’s later public works. The second part of the investigation was represented by the control to which the experimental data were submitted. In this control, Galileo made the calculations which are recorded on f. 116v, using a specific formula. The results of these calculations were reported beside the group of experimental data. He considered H = 300 and D = 800 as the standard against which to compare the other values of horizontal projections. That this was precisely his choice is clearly attested by the examination of the arithmetical operations disseminated on the folio page in which the numbers 300 and 800 play a decisive rôle. As it is obvious on the document that the number 800 is the only one to which was associated a dotted curved line and to which is lacking any theoretical prediction [see fig. 34]. Moreover, a remark connected to the second experimental result (D = 1172 punti) affirms: it "should be, to correspond with the first, 1131" (doveria per rispondere al primo esser 1131). This primo is no other than D = 800, which is the value of the horizontal projection D for H = 300. The calculations performed on f. 116 were founded on two fundamental assumptions: a) the principle of the independence of vertical and horizontal motions, which also includes the possibility of their composition, and b) the principle of conservation of velocity in horizontal projection. On the ground of these two basic assumptions, known to Galileo at the time of this experiment –as it is attested by some of his documents belonging to the last years of his Paduan period–, the time of the projection from C is constant, whatever is the initial height from which the ball rolls along the inclined plane. This time is the one which should be consumed if the moveable fell along the height of the table in a free descent to the ground. In other terms, since the vertical component of the projection (h) is always the same (i.e. the height of the table), the ball takes the same time to pass over the different distances of the projection D, according to the different initial heights H. It follows that the horizontal projections are as the final velocities of the descent along AC. This presupposes that during the projection on CF, the velocities are not diminished and remain constant. The velocity with which the ball leaves the plane ABC is the instantaneous velocity which should be produced if the fall was through the height H. Since the time of descent is not affected by the horizontal component of the projection, therefore the horizontal distance of projection (D) should be the exact measure of the instantaneous velocity with which the body leaves the inclined plane at C. Thus, D must be proportional to the instantaneous velocity acquired during the descent on the plane AC of height H. Now, this velocity is proportional to the square root of H. From this we can disengage the mathematical formula which Galileo intended to test in his experiment: it is the law of fall formulated in the form of direct proportionality of velocities to the square root of the distances. On f. 116v, this law was expressed as: v1 / v2 = ÷ H1 / ÷ H2 . As D v (C) and v (C) H, v1 / v2 = D1 / D2 and D1 / D2 = H1 / H2. This is the fundamental equation behind the work recorded on f. 116v. It states that the instantaneous velocities in C are proportional to the square root of the distance H and are measured by the horizontal projection D. Indeed, the comparison of this equation is evidently a direct test of the law v s and of the Times-squared theorem. Precisely, the formula with which Galileo performed his calculations is the following: v1 / v2 = H1 / H2 v12 / v22 = H1 / H2 v2 = (H2 . v12 )/H1. H1 and v1 being respectively 300 and 800, and H2 representing the various values of D = 600, 800, 828 and 1000, the formula became: D = ( H . 800 ) 2 / 300, by which Galileo obtained the values for D = 1131, 1306, 1329 and 1460 . Whatever was the conclusion Galileo drew from his experiment and the subsequent calculations by which he tried to control the results he obtained, there remain evidently notable differences between his experimental and theoretical data. Especially, the failure of the test of the Double Distance Rule must have disappointed him. Nevertheless, the main positive result he got was that he became more and more confident in the validity of v s and in its mathematical equivalence to v t, this last proportionality exactly which he demonstrated directly on folio 91v. In this document, he deduced successfully the fundamental relation of the law of fall, namely that in the accelerated free fall the moments or degrees of velocity grow proportionally to the times elapsed. Folio 91 v begins with the statement of a proposition on projectile motion which was numbered in the Discorsi Theorem I DML3; then comes the demonstration of the relation v t : "In motion from rest the moment of velocity [velocitatis momentum]and the time of this motion are intensified in the same ratio. For let there be a motion through AB from rest in A, and let an arbitrary point C be assumed; and let it be posited that AC is the time of fall through AC, and the moment of the acquired speed in C is also as AC, and assume again any point B: I say that the time of fall through AB to the time through AC will be as the moment of velocity in B to the moment in C. Let AS be the mean [proportional] between BA and AC; and since the time of fall through AC was set to be AC, AS will be the time through AB: it thus has to be shown that the moment of speed in C to the moment of speed in B is as AC to AS. Assume the horizontal [line] CD to be double CA, but BE to be double BA; it follows from what has been shown, that the [body] falling through AC, deflected into the horizontal CD, will traverse CD in uniform motion in an equal time as it also traversed AC in naturally accelerated motion. And, similarly, it follows that BE is traversed in the same time as AB; but the time of AB itself is AS: therefore, the horizontal [line] BE is traversed in the time AS. But let EB be to BL as the time SA is to the time AC; and since the motion through BE is uniform, the space BL will be traversed in the time AC according to the moment of speed in B. But according to the moment of speed in C, in the same time AC the space CD will be traversed; but the moments of speed are to one another as the spa-ces, which according to these moments are traversed in the same time. Therefore the moment of speed in C is to the moment of speed in B as DC to BL. But as DC to BE, so are their halves, i. e., CA to AB; but as EB to BL, so BA to AS. Therefore, ex aequali, as DC to BL, so CA to AS: that is, as the moment of speed in C to the moment of speed in B, so CA to AS, that is, the time through CA to the time through AB. Which was to be proved" (Opere, VIII, pp. 281-282n.; Galilei, 1979, p. 83; Wisan, 1974, p. 227) . What was to be proved is that the velocities acquired in the motion of fall from rest are in the proportion of the times. Precisely, that t (AB) / t (AC) = mom vel (B) / mom vel (C). This fundamental proposition is underlined in the course of the demonstration and it is deduced in terms of direct proportionality between momenta celeritates and times. The demonstration is founded on three propositions obtained by Galileo in his previous work: the Mean Proportional Rule, the Double Distance Rule and Theorem I of uniform motion. The first rule was introduced in the beginning of the demonstration in order to represent the times of fall. Since CA = t (AC), then AS = m (AB, AC) = t (AB). The final conclusion was reformulated in this sense: it has to be shown that mom vel (C) / mom vel (B) = AC / AS. The Double Distance Rule was necessary to account for the deflections of the free fall on the horizontal lines CD and BE traversed in uniform motion. Since CD and BE are respectively double CA and AB, the times to traverse them in uniform motion are equal to the times of fall along CA and AB. Of course, the uniform speed on CD and BE is equal to the degree of velocity acquired in accelerated motion at the points C and B. Finally, Theorem I on uniform motion was needed to find the distance along BE that is passed through in t (AC) with the degree of velocity acquired in C. This distance is BL, since the moments of velocity are to one another as the spaces traversed in the same times. Therefore, mom vel (C) / mom vel (B) = DC / BL. In the last part of the demonstration, where he deduced his conclusion, Galileo returned once again tot the law of fall, making use this time too of the Mean Proportional Rule: DC / BE = CA / AB, but EB / BL = BA / AS, therefore ex aequali DC / BL = CA / AS, that is mom vel (C) / mom vel (B) = CA / AS = t (AC ) / t (AB). With this result in hand, Galileo corrected the ancient principle v s and was able to make rapid progress in the study of different properties of projectile motion. His work in this perspective resulted in a complete theory presented later in the Fourth Day of the Discorsi. Indeed, there exists a tight link between the proportionality v t and the parabolic shape of the trajectory of projectile motion. In the Discorsi, the demonstration of this property was grounded on the basis of the composition of a vertical accelerated motion and a horizontal uniform motion (Opere, VIII, DML3, Theorem I, p. 269). 4. Final stage In the last years of his stay in Padua, Galileo seems to have performed a lot of work on projectile motion, as it is revealed by many documents of Vol. 72. His interest in "violent motion" of projectiles is quite apparent in the Pisan De motu (see Section I.3.1). Moreoever, it is almost sure that he participated to an experiment performed by Guidobaldo about 1600. Consisting of the throwing of a ball colored with ink on a plane where it traces the shape of a semiparabolic trajectory, it is very similar to the one described by Galileo in the Second Day of the Discorsi (Opere, VIII, p. 185), by which –he said– is demonstrated the parabolic form of the trajectory of projectile motion. So the first hint of Galileo on the parabolic trajectory can be traced to the first years of the XVIIth century. J. Renn (1992, pp. 151-156) suggested convincingly that this experiment must have drawn Galileo's attention to the falsity of his treatment of projectile motion in the old De motu as on the falsity of his ancient treatment of acceleration in the natural fall of bodies. Moreover, it must have played an important rôle in the concomitant discovery of the parabolic trajectory and the quadratic relation between times and spaces in the fall: in effect, the recognition of the parabolic shape of the trajectory for projection may have implied the recognition of the Times–squared relationship for the motion of falling bodies and vice versa. One important element of Galileo’s work on projectile motion is the idea of conservation of motion. Now, we know that there existed in his papers, since the pisan De motu and paduan Mecaniche a proto-inertial notion according to which on a horizontal plane the movable bodies can be put in motion by a very small force, and that on this plane the body may be indifferent to rest as well as to motion. In a letter of Benedetto Castelli to Galileo of April 1607 we learn that the Master has taught to his pupils a similar concept of proto-inertia: "From your Excellency's doctrine that although to start motion the mover is necessary, yet to continue it the absence of opposition is sufficient..." (Opere, X, p. 170). At about 1609, Galileo, having the feeling that his work on motion is very near to completion, he began to entertain a campaign of public relations about his discoveries. He behaved in this sense in two directions: towards the scientific authorities (Luca Valerio, in instance) and political power (some members of the Medici family and some officials of the Florentine court). In this context, he sent to Valerio, the Roman mathematician, whom he knew from many years ago, some of his results and asked him for his opinion. Unfortunately, Galileo’s letters are lost, but the subject of his correspondence with Valerio can be roughly reconstructed from the extant answers he received from him. In his letter dated 23 May 1609, Galileo’s correspondent said: "Your Lordship complies to send me his excellent work on bodies naturally moved and on projectiles, a subject that Your Lordship rightly thinks never dealt with so far. Therefore, I beg Your Lordship to go on with it, and to bring it to an end sooner as possible, because he is going to give to the world a very useful and admirable thing" (Opere, X, pp. 244-245). Receiving another letter from Galileo, Valerio answered on July 18, 1609. In this letter, he is concerned with the discussion of two "principles" submitted to him by Galileo. On the other hand, Galileo’s correspondence with the representatives of Florentine autho-rities can be illustrated by the letters he exchanged with Antonio de’ Medici and with Belisario Vinta, secretary of the Grand-Duke of Tuscany. These letters beared on scientific matters and on projects and research programs for the future as well. For illustration, let’s quote two excerpts of Galileo’s intense and rich correspondence in 1609-1610. The first one is extracted from a letter to Antonio de' Medici of February 1609: "Since my return from Florence I have been occupied in some contemplations of various experiments pertaining to my treatise on mechanics, in which I hope that the greater part will consist of new things not touched on by others before. And just recently I have completed the discovery of all the conclusions, with proofs, pertaining to the strengths and resistances of wooden beams of various lengths, sizes and shapes; how much weaker those are in the middle than at the ends, and how much greater weight they can sustain if distribu-ted evenly rather than put in one plane, and what shape they should have in order to be equally strong throughout –a science most necessary in the construction of machines and of all sorts of buildings, nor has anyone treated of this" (Opere, X, p. 229). In one of his many letters to Belisario Vinta, he proposed his services at the Medicean Court and described the program of the publications that he wished to complete if he was appointed as "mathematician and philosopher" in Florence: "Three books on local motion, an entirely new science in which no one else, ancient or modern,has discovered any of the most remarkable laws which I demonstrate to exist in both natural and violent movement, whence I may call this a new science and one discovered by me from its first principles. Three books on mechanics, two relating to its principles and one concerning its problems; and though other men have written on this subject, what has been done is not onequarter of what I write, either in quantity or otherwise" (Opere, X, pp. 351-352). As it is clearly testified by these letters and by many other documents, before he left to Florence, Galileo has accomplished the greatest part of the program of his work on motion in Padua, namely, the creation of a new science of motion. Founded on results linked to the medie-val discussions on natural philosophy, it was mathematical in method and in spirit. The program announced in the letter to Belisario Vinta was in no sense mere exaggeration, but effectively Galileo had in hand already a new treatise on problems of de motu locali. The manuscripts of Vol. 72 show without any doubt that what was still missing concerned only the general conceptual framework and some particular propositions, obtained by Galileo in Florence during the following years, and especially during the creative years 1630-1634 where he composed the major part of the Discorsi. In the middle of 1609, the news of the telescope reached Galileo’s ears at the crucial time of completion of his work on motion. If he had had some pause, he would have envisaged to publish his De motu locali in Padua, at about 1610. But the events went differently, and this publication had to wait until the mitigated end of the Copernican campaign. BIBLIOGRAPHY 1. ABATTOUY, Mohamed, (1989). La Notion du Temps chez Galilée. Etude historico-épistémologique sur l'un des épisodes de la constitution de la Mécanique classique. Thèse de Doctorat. Paris: Université de Paris-I-Sorbonne, 672 pp. 2. ABATTOUY, M., (1992), "Deux aspects de la notion de temps dans l'École galiléenne : Mathématisation et mesure", in Geometria e atomismo nella scuola galileiana. A cura di M. Bucciantini e M. Torrini, Firenze: L. Olshcki, "Biblioteca di Nuncius, Studi e testi X", pp. 119-145. 3. ABATTOUY, M. (1995), "Le Style galiléen: 1. Galilée et la découverte de la loi de la chute des corps", Linguistica communicatio (Fez), vol. VIII, n° 1. 4. ABATTOUY, M. (1996a), "Genèse et développement de la théorie physique chez Galilée. Aperçu sur les manuscrits dynamiques du Volume 72", Actes de la Table Ronde "Comment faire de l'histoire des sciences?" (Marrakech, 8-11 déc. 1994). Rabat: Mohamed V University - Faculty of Letters Press. 5. ABATTOUY, M., (1996b), "Galileo Galilei (1564-1642) et la naissance de la physique moderne", Histoire des Sciences et Epistémologie. Etudes. Travaux du Séminaire du Groupe de Recherche en Histoire des Sciences du Département de Philosophie (Université de Rabat). Rabat: Faculty of Letters Press. 6. ABATTOUY, M. (1996c), "Les Mathématiques de l'isochronisme chez Galilée". [To be published in a book [Abattouy co-editor] dedicated to the memory of the late Jamal-Eddine ALAOUI. Fez: Department of Philosophy, Fez University, The Faculty of Letters Press 7. ABATTOUY, M. & MAZET, Edmond, (1996), "Les De motu antiquiora de Galilée: leur structure et leur classement chronologique". Communication to the Second Atelier De motu, (Nice, November 19-20, 1994). [Forthcoming in La Revue d’histoire des sciences, Paris]. 8. ALTIERI BIAGHI, Maria Luisa, (1965). Galileo e la terminologia tecnicoscientifica. Firenze: L. Olschki. 9. ANTINORI, Vincenzo, (1839). Della vita e delle opere di Galileo Galilei. Libri Quattro. Biblioteca Nazionale di Firenze, Ms. II. V, 111. 10. BARCARO, Umberto, (1980), "Il concetto di inerzia nei Discorsi di Galileo", Physis, vol. 22: pp. 325-342. 11. BARCARO, U., (1982), "Le proprietà del cerchio nei Discorsi di Galileo", Physis, vol. 14: pp. 5-16. 12. BARONCINI, G., (1992). Forme di esperienze e rivoluzione scientifica. Firenze: L. Olschki. 13. BERTI, Domenico, (1875-1876), "Storia dei manoscritti galileiani della Biblioteca Nazionale di firenze ed indicazione di parecchi libri e codici postillati da Galileo", Atti della Reale Accademia dei Lincei. Memorie della classe di scienze moralli, storiche e filologiche, Serie II, vol. 3, parte 3 : pp. 96-105. 14. BOFFITO, G., (1943). Bibliografia galileiana (1568-1895) raccolta ed illustrata da A. Carli ed A. Favaro. Supplemento... (1896-1940). Roma: Libreria dello Stato 15. BOZZI, P., MACCAGNI, C., OLIVIERI, L., SETTLE, T.B., (1995). Galileo e la Scienza Sperimentale. A cura di Milla Baldo Ceolin. Padova: Dipartimento di Fisica "Galileo Galilei". 16. BRIQUET, Charles, (1907). Les filigranes. Dictionnaire historique des marques du papier dès leur apparition vers 1282 jusqu'en 1600. Genève/Paris/London: A. Jullien/A. Picard/B. Quaritch. Reprinted with a Supplément by A. Stevenson, Amsterdam: The Paper Publications Society, 1976. 17. CAMEROTA, M., (1992). Gli scritti 'De motu antiquiora' di Galileo Galilei. Il Ms. Gal. 71. Un 'analisi storico-critica. Cagliari: CUEC. 18. CAMEROTA, Michele, (1995), "Alcune osservazioni sul Ms. Gal. 72 e sui problemi di una sua edizione". Typescirpt, 15 pp. [Forthcoming]. 19. CARLI, Alarico, e FAVARO, Antonio, (1886). Indice analitico dei Manoscritti Galileiani nella Biblioteca Nazionale di Firenze. Biblioteca Nazionale di Firenze, Mss. 20. CARVALHO, David N, (1971). Forty Centuries of Ink. Or a chronological narrative concerning Ink and its backgrounds ... New York: B. Franklin. 21. CAVERNI, Raffaelo, (1891-1900). Storia del metodo sperimentale in Italia. Firenze: G. Civelli, 6 vols. Vol. IV, 1895. Reprint New York: Johnson Reprints, 1972. Ristampa anastatica in Bologna : Forni, 1970, 7 vols., with an Introduction by Giorgio Tabaroni: "Raffaelo Caverni e la sua opera", vol. I, pp. I-XIX. 22. CLAVELIN, Maurice, (1968). La Philosophie naturelle de Galilée. Essai sur les origines et la formation de la Mécanique classique. Paris : A. Colin. English translation by A. J. Pome-rans, The Natural Philosophy of Galileo, Cambridge (Mass): MIT Press, 1974. 23. CLAVELIN, Maurice, (1984), "Galilée". In Dictionnaire des Philosophes, sous la direction de Denis Huisman. Paris : PUF, vol. I, pp. 991-1000. 24. COFFA, J. A., (1968), "Galileo's Concept of Inertia", Physis, vol. 10: pp. 261281. 25. COHEN, I. Bernard, (1956), "Galileo's Rejection of the Possibility of Velocity Changing Uniformly with Respect to Distance", Isis, vol. 47: pp. 231-235. [Followed by a discussion on this topic between Cohen, Drake and Hall, in ibid, vol. 49 (1958): pp. 342-346.] 26. COSTABEL, Pierre, (1975), "Mathematics and Galileo's Inclined Plane Experiment". In M. L. Righini Bonnelli & W. R. Shea, editors, Reason, Experiment and Mysticism, New York: Science History Publications, pp. 157-175, 303-305. 27. CROMBIE, Alistair C., (1975), "Sources of Galileo's Early Narural Philosophy". In M. L. Righini Bonnelli & W. R. Shea, editors, pp. 177-187. 28. CROMBIE, A. C., (1983), "The Jesuits and Galileo's Ideas of Science and Nature", Annali dell'Istituto e Museo di Storia della Scienza di Firenze, vol. 8: pp. 3-68. 29. DAL PRA, M., VASOLI, C., ROBINET, A., CRAPULLI, G., DIBON, P., editors, (1986). Le Edizioni dei testi filosofici e scientifici del '500 et del '600. Problemi di metodo e prospettive di ricerca. Milano: Angeli. 30. DRAKE, Stillman, (1958), "The Earliest Version of Galileo's Mechanics", Osiris, vol. 13: pp. 262-290. 31. DRAKE, S., (1964), "Galileo and the Law of Inertia", American Journal of Physics, vol. 32: pp. 601-608. 32. DRAKE, Stillman, (1969), "Galileo's 1604 Fragment on Falling Bodies", The British Journal for the History of Science , vol. 4, n° 16: pp. 340-358. 33. DRAKE, S., (1970a), "Uniform Acceleration, Space and Time", The British Journal for the History of Science, vol. 5, n° 17: pp. 21-43. 34. DRAKE, S., (1970b). Galileo Studies. Personality, Tradition and Revolution. Ann Arbor: The University of Michigan Press. 35. DRAKE, Stillman, (1972a), "On the Probable Order of Galileo's Notes on Motion", Physis, vol. 14: pp. 55-68. 36. DRAKE, S., (1972b), "The Uniform Motion Equivalent to a Uniformly Accelerated Motion from Rest", Isis, vol. 63 : pp. 28-38. 37. DRAKE, S., (1973a), "Galileo's Experimental Confirmation of Horizontal Inertia. Unpublished Manuscripts", Isis, vol. 64: pp. 290-307. 38. DRAKE, S., (1973b), "Galileo's Discovery of the Law of Free Fall", Scientific American, n° 228: pp. 84-92. 39. DRAKE, S., (1973c), "Galileo's 'Platonic' Cosmogony and Kepler's Prodromus", Journal of the History of Astronomy, vol. 4 : pp. 174-191. [On Galileo's "astronomical calculations" in f. 146 of Vol. 72]. 40. DRAKE, S., (1973d), "Velocity and Eudoxian Proportion Theory", Physis, vol. 15: pp. 49-64. 41. DRAKE, S., (1974a), "Impetus Theory and Quanta of Speed before and after Galileo", Physis, vol. 16: pp. 46-65. 42. DRAKE, S., (1974b), "Mathematics and Discovery in Galileo's Physics", Historia Mathematica, vol. 1: pp. 129-150. 43. DRAKE, S., (1974c), "Galileo's Work on Free Fall in 1604", Physis, vol. 16: pp. 309-322. 44. DRAKE, S., (1975a), "Galileo's New Science of Motion". In Righini BonelliShea, editors, pp. 131-156, 302-303. 45. DRAKE, S., (1975b), "The Role of Music in Galileo's Experiments", Scientific American, n° 232: pp. 98-104. 46. DRAKE, S., (1976), "New Light on a Galilean Claim about Pendulums", Isis, vol. 66: pp. 92-95. 47. DRAKE, S., (1978). Galileo at Work. His Scientific Biography. Chicago/London: Chicago University Press. [2nd. edit. New York:: Dover Publications, 1995, Dover Paperback Edition; Trad. ital. Galileo. Una biografia scientifica. Bologna : Il Mulino, 1988.] 48. DRAKE, S., (1980). Galileo. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press/Hill and Wang, ("Past Masters"). [Traduz. italiana Milano: Dall'Oglio, 1981; trad. française Galilée, Arles: Actes Sud, 1986.] 49. DRAKE, S., (1981), "Alleged Departures from Galileo's Law of Descent", Annals of Science, vol. 38: pp. 339-342. 50. DRAKE, S., (1982a), "Exact Sciences, Primitive Instruments and Galileo", Annali dell'Istituto e Museo di Storia della Scienza, Anno 7: pp. 87-107. 51. DRAKE, S., (1982b), "Analysis of Galileo's Experimental Data", Annals of Science, vol. 39: pp. 389-397. 52. DRAKE, S., (1982c), "Dating Unpublished Notes, such as Galileo's on Motion". In T. H. Levere, editor, Editing Texts in the History of science and Medicine. New York : Garland, pp. 13-37. 53. DRAKE, S., (1985a), "Galileo and the Mathematical Physics". In Scienza e filosofia. Saggi in onore di Ludovico Geymonat. A cura di Corrado Mangione. Milano: Garzanti, pp. 627-642. 54. DRAKE, S., (1985b), "Galileo's Accuracy in Measuring Horizontal Projections", Annali dell'Istituto e Museo di Storia della Scienza, Anno X: pp. 3-14. 55. DRAKE, S., (1986), "Galileo's Physical Measurements", American Journal of Physics, vol. 54: pp. 302-305. 56. DRAKE, S., (1987), "Galileo's Constant", Nuncius. Annali di Storia della scienza, Anno II: pp. 41-52. 58. DRAKE, S., (1989a), "Galileo's Gravitational Units", Physics Teacher, vol. 27: pp. 432-436. 59. DRAKE, S., (1989b). History of Free Fall. Aristotle to Galileo. With an Epilogue on p in the Sky. Toronto: Wall and Thompson. 60. DRAKE, S., (1990). Galileo Pioneer Scientist. Toronto/Buffalo/London: University of Toronto Press. [Trad. ital.: Galileo Galilei pioniere della scienza. La fisica moderna di Galileo. Padova : Franco Muzzio, 1992.] 61. DRAKE, S., and McLACHLAN, James, (1975a), "Galileo's Discovery of Parabolic Trajectory", Scientific American, n° 232: pp. 98-104. 62. DRAKE, S., and McLACHLAN, J., (1975b), "Reply to the Shea-Wolf Critique", Isis, vol. 66: pp. 400-403. 63. DUHEM, Pierre, (1913). Etudes sur Léonard de Vinci. Vol. III., Les précurseurs parisiens de Galilée. Paris : Hermann. Vol. I-II: Paris, 1906, 1909. Reprint of the three volumes at Paris : De Nobelle, 1955; Paris : Editions des archives contempoaraines, 1984. [Pp. 562-578: one of the first discussions of the contents of Galileo's letter to Sarpi and folio 128 of Vol. 72]. 64. FABRIKANT, V. A., (1991), "How the Concept of Acceleration took shape in the Mechanics of Galileo", Soviet Phys. Usp., vol. 34, n° 201. 65. FAVARO, Antonio, (1881), "Intorno ad una nuova edizione delle Opere di Galileo", Atti del Reale Istituto Veneto di Scienze, Lettere ed Arti, Serie V, Tomo 8: pp. 83-131. 66. FAVARO, A. (1883a). Galileo Galilei e lo studio di Padova.. Firenze: Le Monnier, 2 vols. [Ristampa Padova: Editrice Antenore, 1966, 2 vols.] 67. FAVARO, A. (1883b),"Alcuni scritti ineditti di Galileo Galilei tratti dai Manoscritti della Biblioteca Nazionale di Firenze", Bolletino di bibliografia e di Storia delle Scienze Matematiche e Fisiche, vol. 16: pp. 1-112, 151-230. 68. FAVARO, A., (1885), "Documenti inediti per la storia dei Manoscritti Galileiani della Biblioteca Nazionale di Firenze", Bolletino di bibliografia e di Storia delle scienze matematiche e fisiche, vol. 18: pp. 1-112, 151-230. 69. FAVARO, A. (1886), "Intorno ad alcuni documenti galileiani recentemente scoperti nella Biblioteca Nazionale di Firenze", Bolletino di bibliografia e di storia delle scienze matematiche e fisiche, vol. 19: pp. 1-54. 70. FAVARO, A. (1887). Miscellania Galileiana inedita: Studi e ricerchi. Venice: Tipografia di G. Antonelli. 71. FAVARO, A. (1888a). Per la Edizione Nazionale delle Opere di Galileo Galilei sotto gli auspici di S. M. Il re d'Italia. Esposizione e disegno. Firenze : Barbèra. 72. FAVARO, A. (1888b), "Nuove contribuzione alla storia dei manoscritti galileiani", Atti e memorie della Reale Accademia di Scienze, Lettere ed Arti di Padova, Serie terza: pp. 111-131. 73. FAVARO, A., (1899a), "Delle Meccaniche lette in Padova l'anno 1594 da Galileo Galilei, per la prima volta pubblicate ed illustrate da Antonio Favaro", Memorie del Reale Istituto Veneto di Scienze, Lettere ed Arti, vol. 16, n° 5: pp. 226. 74. FAVARO, A., (1899b), "Intorno alle opere scientifiche di Galileo Galilei nella Edizione Nazionale", Atti del Real Istituto Veneto delle Scienze, Lettere ed Arti, vol. 58: pp. 151-158. 75. FAVARO, A., (1891). Nuovi studi galileiani. Venice: Tipografia di G. Antonelli. 76. FAVARO, A. (1908-09), "Galileo e le edizioni delle sue opere", Atti della Reale Accademia della Crusca, Serie decimoterza : pp. 27-72. 77. FAVARO, A. e CARLI, Alarico, (1896). Bibliografia galileiana (1568-1895)... Firenze: Fratelli Bencini. 78. FAVARO, A. (1983). Amici e corrispondenti di Galileo Galilei . A cura e con nota introduttiva di Paolo Galluzzi, Firenze: Istituto e Museo di Storia della Scienza-Libreria Editrice Salimbeni, 1983, 3 vols. 79. FINOCCHIARO, Maurice A., (1972), "Vires acquirit eundo: The Passage where Galileo Renounces Space-Acceleration and Causal Investigation", Physis, vol. 4: pp. 125-145. 80. FINOCCHIARO, M. A., (1973), "Galileo's Space Proportionality Argumen: A role for Logic in Historiography", Physis, vol. 15 : pp. 65-72. 81. FOLINO GALLO, Raffaele, (1973). I principi della dinamica galileiana (15841604). Framma Sud: Chiaravalle. 82. FREDETTE, Raymond, (1969). Les "De motu plus anciens"de Galileo Galilei: Prolégomènes. Thèse présentée en vue de l'obtention du grade de Philosophiae Doctor (Ph. D.) en sciences médiévales. Montréal: Institut d'Etudes Médiévales, Université de Montréal, 2 vol. 83. FREDETTE, R., (1972), "Galileo's De motu antiquiora", Physis, 14: pp. 321350. 85. FRAJESE, A., (1964). Galileo matematico. Roma: Editrice studium. 86. GALILEI, Galileo, (1890-1909). Le Opere di Galileo Galilei. Edizione Nazionale. A cura di Antonio Favaro. Firenze: Tipografia di Giunti Barbèra editore, 20 vol. [Ristampa Firenze: G.Barbera, 1929-1939, nuova ristampa dell'edizione nazionale, Firenze: G. Barbèra, 1964-68]. 87. GALILEI, G., (1898). Opere, Ediz. Naz. Vol. VIII: "Avvertimento", pp. 11-38; Discorsi, pp. 39-313; Frammenti attenenti ai Discorsi, pp. 365-448; Frammenti di data incerta, pp. 618-642. 88. GALILEI, G., (1958). Discorsi e dimostrazioni matematiche intorno a due nuove scienze. A cura di A. Carugo e L. Geymonat. Torino: Boringhieri. [With Introduction, Notes and the Edition of many of Galileo' Notes on Motion]. 89. GALILEI, G., (1960). On Motion and On Mechanics. Comprising 'De motu' (ca. 1590), Translated with Introduction and Notes by I. E. Drabkin, and Le Meccaniche, (ca. 1600), Translated with Introduction and Notes by S. Drake. Madison: The University of Wisconsin Press. 90. GALILEI, G., (1970). Discours et démonstrations mathématiques concernant deux sciences nouvelles. Introduction, traduction et notes par M. Clavelin. Paris: A. Colin. 91. GALILEI, G., (1974). Two New Sciences, Including Centers of Gravity anf Force of Percussion. Translated with Introduction and Notes by S. Drake. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press. Second Edition with a new Introduction and new Notes in Toronto: Wall and Tompson, 1989. 92. GALILEI, G., (1979). Galileo's Notes on Motion, Arranged in Probable Order of Composition and Presented in Reduced Facsimile by Stillman Drake. Firenze : Istituto e Museo di Storia della scienza. Supplemento agli Annali dell'Istituto..., Anno 2, 1979. 93. GALILEO, G., (1990). Discorsi e dimostrazioni matematiche... A cura di Enrico Giusti. Torino : Einaudi. 94. GALLUZZI, Paolo, (1979). Momento. Studi galileiani. Roma : Edizioni dell'Ateneo & Bizari. 95. GALLUZZI, P., (1988), "La fondazione galileiana della moderna scienza del movimento. Una vicenda esemplare". In P. Galluzzi, G. Michelli, A. Porta, L. Rosino, G. Taborelli, Galileo. La Sensata esperienza. Pizzi: Cinisello Balsamo, pp. 15-54. 96. GALLUZZI, P., TORRINI, Maurizio, editors, (1979, 1984). Le Opere dei Discepoli di Galileo Galilei. Carteggio. Firenze : Giunti Barbera, 2 vol. Vol. I (1979): 1642-1648; vol. II (1984): 1649-1656. [Vol. I, pp. I-XLIV: "Indice Generale"]. 97. GAPAILLARD, Jacques, (1992), "Galilée et l'accélération de la pesanteur", Physis, vol. 29: pp. 319-374. 98. GIUSTI, Enrico, (1981), "Aspetti matematichi della cinematica galileiana", Bolletino di Storia delle Scienze Matematiche, vol. 1: pp. 3-42. 99. GIUSTI, E., (1986), "Ricerche Galileiani: Il trattato De motu aequabili come modello della teoria delle proporzioni", Bolletino di Storia delle Scienze Matematiche, vol. 6: fasc. 2, pp. 89-108. 100. GIUSTI, E., (1990), "Galileo e le leggi del moto", in Galilei, (1990), pp. IXLII. 101. GIUSTI, E., (1992), "La teoria galileiana delle proporzioni". In La matematizzazione dell'Universo: Momenti della cultura matematica tra '500 e '600. A cura di Lino Conti. Assissi : Porziuncola, pp. 207-222. 102. GIUSTI, E., (1993). Euclides reformatus. La teoria delle proporzioni nella scuola galileiana. Torino: Bollati Boringhieri. 103. GRILLI, M., (1981), "Galileo e il principio d'inerzia", Giornale di fisica, vol. 22: pp. 215-232. 104. HALBWACHS, F., and THORUNCZYK, A., (1985), "On Galileo's Writings on Mechanics: An Attempt at a Semantic Analysis of Viviani's Scholium", Synthese, vol. 62: pp. 459-484. 105. HALL, Alfred Rupert, (1958), "Galileo's Fallacy", Isis, vol. 49: pp. 342-344. 106. HALL, A. R., (1959), "Another Galilean Error", Isis, vol. 50: pp. 261-262. 107. HEAWOOD, Edward, (1950). Watermarks, Mainly of the XVII th and XVIII th Centuries. Hilversum (Holland): Paper Publications Society. 108. HILL, David K., (1979), "A Note on a Galilean Worksheet", Isis, vol. 70: pp. 269-271. 109. HILL, D. K., (1986), "Galileo's Work on F. 116v", Isis, vol. 77: pp. 283-291. 110. HILL, D. K., (1988), "Dissecting Trajectories: Galileo's Early Experiments on Projectile Motion and the Law of fall", Isis, vol. 79: pp. 646-668. 111. HILL, D. K., (1994), "Pendulums ans Planes : What Galileo didn't publish", Nuncius. Annali di storia della scienza, Anno IX: fasc. 2, pp. 499-515. 112. HUMPHREYS, W. C., (1967), "Galileo, Falling Bodies and Inclined Planes. An Attempt at Reconstructing Galileo's Discovery of the Law of Squares", The British Journal for the History of Science, vol. 3: n° 11, pp. 226-244. 113. HUNTER, Dard, (1930). Papermaking through Eighteen centuries. New York: W. E. Rudge. 114. HUNTER, Dard, (1947). Papermaking: the History and Technique of an Ancient Craft. New York: A. A. Knopf. [Reprinted, 1967]. 115. ITARD, Jean, (1947-48), "Sur une prétendue erreur de Galilée", Revue d'histoire des sciences, vol. 1: pp. 355-356. 116. KOYRE, Alexandre, (1966). Etudes galiléennes. Paris: Hermann, 2nd edit. [First Edition, 1939. Reimpressed 1986. Trad. ital. di M. Torrini, Studi galileiani, Torino: Einaudi, 1976. Part II: Discussion of Galileo's documents of 1604 (letter to Sarpi and folio 128)]. 117. LEHNER, Sigmund, (1902). Ink Manufacture. Including Writing, Copying, Lithographic, Marking, Stamping and Laundry Inks. English Transl. London: Scott, Greenwood and C°. 118. LEVERE, Trevor H., editor, (1982). Editing Texts in the History of Science and Medicine. Papers given at the Seventh Annual Conference on Editorial Problems, University of Toronto, November 6-7, 1981. New York/London: Garland. 119. LEVI, Eugenia, (1968). Indice delle fonti dell'Edizione Nazionale delle Opere di Galileo Galilei. Firenze: G. Barbèra. 120. LIBRI, Guglielmo, (1838-41). Histoire des sciences mathématiques en Italie, depuis la renaissance des lettres jusq'à la fin du dix-septième siècle. Paris: Jules Renouard et Cie, 4 vol. [Reprint: Hildesheim: Olms, 1967.] 121. LIBRI, G., (1841). Galilei, sua vita e sue opere. Milano: Presso la Società degli Annali Universali delle Scienze e dell'Insdustria. 122. MACH, Ernst, (1883). Die Mechanik in ihrer Entwicklung historisch-kritisch dargestellt. English transl.The Science of Mechanics. A Critical and Historical Account of its Development, 6th edition with new revisions through the 9th German edition, La Salle (Ill.): Open Court, 1960. French transl. La Mécanique. Exposé historique et critique de son développement. Paris: Hermann, 1904; reprinted Paris: Jacques Gabay, 1989. Ital. transl. by A. D'Elia. Torino: Boringhieri, 1968. 123. MACLACHLAN, James, (1976), "Galileo's Experiments with Pendulums: Real and Imaginary", Annals of Science, vol. 33: pp. 173-185. 124. MACLACHLAN, J., (1982), "Note on R. H. Naylor's Error in Analysing Experimental Data", Annals of Science, vol. 39: pp. 381-384. 125. MATTOZZI, Ivo, (1975). Produzione e commercio della carte nello stato Veneziano Settecentesco. Lineamenti e problemi. Bologna: Università degli studi di Bologna. 126. MATUSZZEWSKI, R., (1986), "On Galileo's Theory of Motion: An Attempt at a Coherent Reconstruction", International Studies in Philsophy of Science, vol. 1: pp. 124-141. 127. NAPOLITANI, Pier Daniele, (1987), "Galileo e due matematice napolitani : Luca Valerio e Giovanni Camillo Gloriosi". In Galileo e Napoli. Edit. by F. Lomonaco e M. Torrini. Napoli: Guida, pp. 161-195. 128. NAPOLITANI, P. D., (1988), "La geometrizzazione della realtà fisica: il peso specifico in Ghetaldi e in Galileo", Bolletino di Storia delle Scienze Matematiche, vol. 8: fasc. 2, pp. 139-237. 129. NARDI, Antonio, (1988), "La Quadratura della velocità: Galileo, Mersenne, la tradizione", Nuncius. Annali di storia della scienza, Anno III, fasc. 2: pp. 27-64. 130. NAYLOR, Ronald H., (1974a), "Galileo and the Problem of Free Fall", The British Journal for History of Science, vol. 7: pp. 105-134. 131. NAYLOR, R. H., (1974b), "Galileo's Simple Pendulum", Physis, vol. 16: pp. 23-46. 132. NAYLOR,R. H., (1974c), "The Evolution of an Experiment: Guidobaldo del Monte and Galileo's Discorsi Demonstration of the Parabolic Trajectory", Physis, vol. 16: pp. 323-346. 133. NAYLOR, R. H., (1975), "An Aspect of Galileo's Study of Parabolic Trajectory", Isis, vol. 66: pp. 394-396. 134. NAYLOR, R. H., (1976a), "Galileo: the Search for the Parabolic Trajectory", Annals of Science, vol. 33 : pp. 153-172. 135. NAYLOR, R. H., (1976b), "Galileo: Real Experiment and Didactic Demonstration", Isis, vol. 67 : pp. 398-419. 136. NAYLOR, R.H., (1976c), "Review of Wisan, (1974), The New Science of Motion", Annali dell'Istituto e Museo di Storia della Scienza di Firenze, Anno I: n°2, pp. 89-97. 137. NAYLOR, R., (1977), "Galileo's Theory of Motion: Processes of Conceptual Change in the Period 1604-1610", Annals of Science, vol. 34: pp. 365-392. 138. NAYLOR, R. H., (1979), "Mathematics and Experiment in Galileo's New Sciences", Annali dell'Istituto e Museo di Storia della Scienza, Anno IV: fasc. 1, pp. 55-63. 139. NAYLOR, R., (1980a), "Galileo's Theory of Projectile Motion", Isis, vol. 71: pp. 550-570. 140. NAYLOR, R. H., (1980b), "The Role of Experiment in Galileo's Early Work on the Law of Fall", Annals of Science, vol. 37: pp. 363-378. 141. NAYLOR, R. H., (1982), "Galileo's Law of Fall: Absolute Truth or Approximation", Annals of Science, vol. 39: pp. 384-389. 142. NAYLOR, R. H., (1983), "Galileo's Early Experiments on Projectile Trajectories", followed by : S. Drake, "Comment on the above Note..." and a "Correspondence" of R. Naylor, Annals of Science, vol. 40: pp. 391-396. 143. NAYLOR, R.H., (1989), "Galileo's Experimental Discourse". In D. Gooding et al., Editors, The Uses of Experiment: Studies in the Natural Sciences. Cambridge University Press, pp. 117-134. 144. NAYLOR, R. H., (1990), "Galileo's Method of Analysis and Synthesis", Isis, vol. 81: pp. 695-707. [Cf. subsequent discussion on certain points of this article between D. Hill and R. Naylor in Isis, vol. 83, (1992): pp. 80-81]. 145. NELLI, Giovanni Battista Clemente De', (1793). Vita e commercio letterario di Galileo Galilei ... Losanna, 2 vol. 146. OGAWA, Yutaka, (1989), "Galileo's Work on Free Fall at Padua: Some Remarks on Drake's Interpretation", Historia Scientiarum, vol. 37 : pp. 31-49. 147. OGAWA, Y., (1994), "Galileo and the Double Distance Rule law, in connection with the calculation on folio 189v1", Kagakusi kenkyu,vol. 33: pp. 6575. [En japonais]. 148. PROCISSI, Angiolo, (1959). La Collezione Galileiana della Biblioteca Nazionale di Firenze. Vol. I: "Anteriori" - "Galileo". Roma : Istituto Poligrafico dello Stato. 149. PROCISSI, A., (1985). La Collezione Galileiana della Biblioteca nazionale di Firenze. Vol. II: "Contemporanei" e "Discepoli". Parte I. Roma : Istituto Poligrafico dello Stato. 150. RENN, Jürgen, (1984), "Galileo's Theorem of Equivalence. Part I: Galileo's Calculations". Preprint Freie Universität Berlin, FUB / HEP, 84/85. 151. RENN, Jürgen, (1989), "Einige Paradoxien des Geschwindigkeitsbegriffes bei Galilei". In W. Muschik and W. R. Shea, editors, Philosohie, Physik, Wissenschaftsgeschichte: Ein gemeinsammes Kolloqium der Technische Universität Berlin und des Wissenschaftskollegs zu Berlin, 24-25, April 1989. Berlin: TUB-Dokumentation, pp. 30-67. 152. RENN, Jürgen, (1988), "Galileo's Manuscripts on Mechanics. The Project of an Edition with Full Critical Apparatus of Mss. Gal. Codex 72", Nuncius. Annali di storia della scienza, Anno III: pp. 193-241. 153. RENN, J., (1990), "Galileo's Theorem of Equivalence: The Missing Keystone of his Theory of Motion". In T. H. Levere and W. R. Shea, editors, Nature, Experiment and the Sciences: Essays on Galileo and the History of Science in Honour of Stillman Drake. ("Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science", 120). Dordrecht : Kluwer Academic, pp. 77-103. 154. RENN, J., (1992), "Proofs and Paradoxes : Free Fall and the Projectile Motion in Galileo's Physics". In P. Damerow, G. Freudenthal, P. McLaughlin, J. Renn, Exploring the Limits of Preclassical Mechanics. A Study of Conceptual Development in Early Modern Science: Free Fall and Compounded Motion in the Work of Descartes, Galileo and Beeckman. New York/Berlin, etc.: Springer Verlag, pp. 126-268. 155. ROMO FEITO, Josè, (1985). La fisica de Galileo. La problematica en torno a la ley de caida de los cuerpos. Seminario de Historia de las Sciencias. Bellaterra : Universidad Autonoma de Barcelona. 156. SEGRE, Michael, (1980), "The Role of Experiment in Galileo's Physics", Archive for History of Exact Sciences, vol. 23: pp. 227-252. 157. SEGRE, M., (1989), "Viviani's Life of Galileo", Isis, vol. 80: pp. 207-231. 158. SEGRE, M., (1991). In the Wake of Galileo. New Brunswick (New Jersey): Rutgers University Press. 159. SETTLE, Thomas B., (1961), "An Experiment in the History of Science", Science, vol. 133: pp. 19-23. 160. SETTLE, T. B., (1966). Galilean Science. Essaysin the Mechanics and Dynamics of the Discorsi. Ph. D. Dissertation presented to the Faculty of the Graduate School of Cornell University for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy. New York: Cornell University. 161. SETTLE, T. B., (1967), "Galileo's Use of Experiment as a Tool of Investigation". In Ernan McMullin, editor, Galileo, Man of Science. New York: Basic Books, pp. 315-337. 162. SETTLE, T. B., (1983), "Galileo and Early Experimentation". In R. Aris, T. H. Davis and R. H. Stuewer, editors, Springs of Scientific Creativity. Essays on Founders of Modern Science. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 320. 163. SETTLE, T. B., (1994), "Galileo's Experimental Research : An Experimental Approach". Typescript text distributed at Nice, in the First Atelier De motu antiquiora, 3-4 juin 1994, 46 pp. 164. SETTLE, T. B., (1995), "La Rete degli esperimenti galileiani". In Bozzi et al., a cura di M. Baldo Ceolin, pp. 11-62. 165. SHARRATT, Michael, (1994). Galileo: Decisive Innovator. Cambridge (Mass.): Blackwell. 166. SHEA, William R., (1972). Galileo's Intellectual Revolution. Middle Period, 1610-1632. New York: Science History Publications. Second Edition, 1977. [Trad. ital. di P. Galluzzi, Firenze: Sansoni, 1974; trad. franç. par F. De Gandt, La Révolution galiléenne, Paris: Seuil, 1992.] 167. SHEA, W. R., (1975), "Trends in the Interpretation of Seventeenth Century Science". Introduction to Righini-Bonell & Shea, eds., (1975): pp. 1-18. 168. SHEA, W. R., and WOLF, Neil S., (1975), "Stillman Drake and the Archimedean Grand-Father of Experimental Science", Isis, vol. 55: pp. 397-400. [Cf. Drake & MacLachlan, (1975), "Reply to Shea-Wolf critique"]. 169. SHEA, W. R., (1977), "Galileo and the Justification of Experiments". In R. E. Butts and J. Hintikka, editors, Historical and Philosophical Dimensions of Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science. Dordrecht/Boston: Reidel, pp. 81-92. 170. SHEA, W. R., (1983), "The Galilean Geometrization of Motion : Some Historical Considerations". In W. R. Shea, editor, Nature Mathematized. Dordrecht / Boston: Reidel, pp. 51-69. 171. SHEA, W. R., (1994), "Galileo in the Nineties", Perspectives on Science, 2: 476-487. [Review of recent works]. 172. SHERMANN, Paul D., (1974), "Galileo and the inclined plane controversy", Physics Teacher, vol. 12: pp. 343-348. 173. SOUFFRIN, Pierre, (1986), "Du mouvement uniforme au mouvement unfiromément accéléré: Une nouvelle lecture du Théorème du plan incliné dans les Discorsi de Galilée", Bolletino di Storia delle Scienze Matematiche, vol. 6: fasc. 1, pp. 135-144. 174. SOUFFRIN, P., (1991), "Galilée et la tradition cinématique pré-classique. La proportionalité velocitas-momentum revisitée", Cahiers du Séminaire d'épistémologie et d'histoire des sciences de l'Université de Nice, Cahier n° 22 , [Special issue containing the works of the colloquium Le concept de vitesse d'Archimède à Galilée (Nice, 1990)]: pp. 89-104. 175. SOUFFRIN, P. (1992a), "Sur l'histoire du concept de vitesse: Galilée et la tradition scholastique". In Le temps, sa mesure et sa perception au Moyen-Age. Sous la direction de B. Ribémont. Actes du Colloque, Orléans, 12-13 avril 1991. Caen: Paradigme, pp. 243-268. 176. SOUFFRIN, P., (1992b), "Sur l'histoire du concept de vitesse d'Aristote à Galilée", Revue d'histoire des sciences, vol. 45: n° 2-3, pp. 231-267. 177. SOUFFRIN, P., (1993), "Galilée, Torricelli et la loi fondamentale de la Dynamique: la proportionalité velocitas-momentum revisitée", Science et technique en perspective, vol. 25: pp. 122-134. 178. SOUFFRIN, P., et GAUTHERO, Jean-Luc, (1992), "Note sur la démonstration "mécanique" du théorème de l'isochronisme des cordes du cercle dans les Discorsi de Galilée", Revue d'histoire des sciences, vol. 45: n° 2-3, pp. 269280. 179. SOUFFRIN, P., et MANZOCHI, Marcos, (1992), "Histoire d'une erreur, erreurs de l'histoire: l'affaire de la 'Lettre à Sarpi' de Galilée", Cahiers du Séminaire d'épistémologie et d'histoire des sciences de l'Université de Nice, Cahier n° 23. 180. STENGERS, Isabelle, (1989), "Les affaires Galilée". In Eléments d'histoire des sciences, dirigé par M. Serres, Paris: Bordas, pp.223-249. 181. SYLLA, Edith D., (1986), "Galileo and the Oxford Calculatores: Analytical Languages and the Mean-Speed Theorem for Accelerated Motion". In W. A. Wallace, editor, Reinterpreting Galileo, Washington: The Catholic University of America Press, pp.53-108. 182. TAKAHASHI, Ken'ichi, (1993), "Galileo's Labyrinth: His Struggle for Finding a Way out of His Erroneus Law of Natural Fall. [Parts 1 and 2]", Historia Scientiarum, vol. 2: n°3, pp. 169-202; vol. 3: n°1, pp. 1-34. 183. TANNERY, Paul, (1901), "Galilée et les principes de la dynamique", Revue Générale des Sciences pures et appliquées, vol. 12: pp. 330-338. Reprint in P. Tannery, Mémoires scientifiques, vol. VI, Sciences modernes, 1883-1904. Paris: Gauthier-Villars, 1926, pp. 387-413. 184. VIVIANI, Vincenzo, (1674). Quinto libro degli Elementi d'Euclide, ovvero scienza universale delle Proporzioni, spiegata colla dottrina del Galileo, con un nuov'ordine distesa, e per la prima volta pubblicata da VINCENZO VIVIANI ultimo suo discepolo. Aggiuntesi cose varie e del Galileo, e del Torricelli; i ragguagli dell'ultime Opere loro, che dall'Indice si manifesta. Firenze: Alla Condotta. 185. WISAN, Winifred Lovell, (1972). Galileo's De motu locali. Ph. D. Dissertation, University of Flo-rida. 186. WISAN, W. L. (1974), "The New Science of Motion : A Study of Galileo's De motu locali", Archive for History of Exact Sciences, vol. 13: pp. 103-306. 187. WISAN, W. L., (1977), "Mathematics and Experiment in Galileo's Science of Motion", Annali dell'Istituto e Museo di Storia della Scienza, vol. 2: pp. 149-160. 188. WISAN, W. L., (1978a), "Galileo's Scientific Method: A Reexamination". In R. Butts and J. C. Pitt, editors, New Perspectives on Galileo. Dordrecht / Boston: D. Reidel, 1978, pp. 1-57. 189. WISAN, W. L., (1978b), "Review of "Clavelin, (1974)", in Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie, vol. 60: n° 1, pp. 71-74. 190. WISAN, W. L., (1979), "Review of S. Drake (1978), Galileo at Work", Physics Today, vol. 32 : pp. 54-56. 191. WISAN, W. L., (1980), "Galileo and the Emergence of a New Scientific Style". In J. Hintikka, D. Gruender and E. Agazzi, editors, Theory Change, Ancient Axiomatics and Galileo's Methodology. Proceedings of the 1978 Pisa Conference on the History and Philosophy of Science. Dordrecht / Boston : D. Reidel, 2 vols.; vol. I, pp. 311-339. 192. WISAN, W. L. (1983), "Galileo's De Systemate Mundi and the New Mechanics". In Novità Celesti e Crisi del Sapere. Atti del Convegno Internazionale di Studi Galileiani. Pisa-Venezia-Padova-Firenze: 18-26 marzo 1983. A cura di Paolo Galluzzi. (Supplemento agli Annali dell'Istit. Mus. Stor. Scienza, Anno 1983, fas. 2). Firenze: Istituto e Museo di Storia della Scienza, 1984, pp. 41-49. 193. WISAN, W. L. (1984), "Galileo and the Process of Scientific Creation", Isis, vol. 75 : pp. 269-286. 194. SPECTOR, Stephen, editor, (1986). Essays in Paper Analysis. Washington : Folger Shakespeare Library. 195. YAMAZAKI, Masakatsu, (1990), "Galileo's Law of Chords and Accelerated Motion", Kagakusi Kenkyu, vol. 29: pp. 167-171. [In Japanese]. Fez-Berlin February-October, 1996 View publication stats