Around 800 BC, am individual’s moral duties stemmed from his or her position in society. Society then was composed of very tightly knit clans which placed loyalty to clan above anything else. By around 500 BC in Athens, as strength of clans declined moral dilemmas crop up. What may be considered moral from the standpoint of the clan can be immoral from the standpoint of the Greek city-state. When the moral dilemmas arose, people found it difficult to resolve them. Thus, they resort to the intervention of the gods. However, some philosophers in ancient Greece, known as Sophists, were smart enough to realize that the gods don’t really intervene to help people resolve their moral dilemmas. Sophists argued that there are no foundations to ethics, and one must be able to argue for either side of the moral dilemma. The incoherence of such a view generated a reaction in the form of the great triad of Greek philosophy – Socrates, Plato and Aristotle. All of them argued for strong foundations of ethics. Teleology Utilitarianism Deontology From the Greek words “telos” – purpose and “logos” – study Ethics is important because it serves a purpose. The purpose (telos) is raising human nature from the raw to unfinished state of life. For Aristotle, the philosophical foundation ethics lay in its ability to transfer human nature from its raw form to its highest potential. It is the belief that human nature compels man to move towards pleasure and move away from pain. A good system of ethics will allow the maximum number of people to move towards pleasure and away from pain—in other words, “the greatest good for the greatest number.” It is the belief that morality must be followed for its own sake. According to the deontologists, a good act is intrinsically good, and that it must be performed without regard to consequences, but because it is the individuals’ duty as rational beings to perform good acts, the individuals must be aware of the consequences of their actions. Friedrich Nietzsche criticized these schools of thoughts. According to him, these schools of thoughts were nothing but mere rationalizations that concealed the Will to Power, that is the desire to dominate others. Anencephalic infants: ‘babies without brains’ o Cerebrum, cerebellum, and top of skull are missing o Have a brain stem, thus autonomic functions (breathing, heartbeat, etc.) are possible o Usually aborted in the US; otherwise, half are stillborn and usually die within days Florida law forbids the removal of organs until the donor is dead. Baby Theresa died after nine days. Her organs were too deteriorated to be harvested or transplanted. ? Should she have been killed so that her organs could have been used to save other children? (Thousands of infants need transplants each year.) “It just seems too horrifying to use people as means to other people’s ends.” “It’s unethical to kill person A to save person B.” “What the parents are really asking for is, ‘Kill this dying baby so that its organs may be used for someone else.’ Well, that’s really a horrendous proposition.” If we can benefit someone without harming anyone else, we ought to do so. Transplanting the organs would benefit the other children without harming Baby Theresa. Therefore, we ought to transplant the organs. Isn’t being alive better than being dead? Only if being alive allows one to ‘have a life’: to carry on activities and have thoughts, feelings, and relations with other people. In the absence of such things, ‘mere biological life’ is worthless. It is wrong to use people as means to other people’s ends. Taking Theresa’s organs would be using her to benefit other children. Therefore, it should not be done. Vague sense of ‘use.’ What does it mean? Violating Baby Theresa’s autonomy? Baby Theresa has no autonomy to violate. She has no preferences about anything, nor has she ever had any. It is wrong to kill one person to save another. Taking Theresa’s organs would be killing her to save others. So, taking the organs would be wrong. Shouldn’t there be an exception to the rule? Baby Theresa is not conscious; she will never ‘have a life’; she is going to die soon anyway; and taking her organs would help other babies. Should we regard Baby Theresa as already ‘dead’? Perhaps we should revise our definitions of ‘death.’ Conjoined twins, joined at the lower abdomen; spines fused; one heart and one pair of lungs between them. Without an operation to separate them, both twins would die within six months. This would save Jodie, but Mary would die. The parents refused permission for the operation, but courts okayed it. Jodie lived, and Mary died. There is a choice: save one or let both die. ? Isn’t it plainly better to save one? Not from the parents’ perspective. All human life is precious, regardless of age, race, social class, or handicap. The prohibition against killing innocent humans is absolute. Mary is an innocent human being. Therefore, she should not be killed. Mary would not be ‘killed’ during the operation but merely separated from Jodie. Her death would be due to her body’s inability to sustain her life. Perhaps it is not always wrong to kill innocent human beings. . . o If the innocent human has no future because she is going to die soon no matter what. . . AND. . . o She has no wish to go on living (perhaps because she has no wishes at all). . . AND. . . o This killing will save others who can go on to lead ‘full lives.’ 12-year-old victim of cerebral palsy, killed by her father with exhaust fumes while the rest of the family were at church. Tracy weighed less than 40 lbs. and was described as “functioning at the mental level of a three-month-old baby.” Robert Latimer was sentenced to 10 years in prison. ? Did Mr. Latimer do anything wrong? Wasn’t killing her an act of mercy? Handicapped people should be given the same respect and the same rights as everyone else. Tracy was killed because she was handicapped. Therefore, killing her was wrong. Tracy was not killed because of her cerebral palsy but because of her pain and suffering and because there was no hope for her. If we accept any sort of mercy killing, we will slide down a slippery slope, and in the end all life will be held cheap. Where will we draw the line? What about other disabled people, the elderly, the infirm, and other ‘useless’ members of society? ! This kind of argument is all too easy to abuse. If you are opposed to something but have no good arguments against it, you can always make up a prediction about what it might lead to; and no matter how implausible your prediction is, no one can prove you wrong. How do you define freedom? Can you consider yourself free if you have limitations? Many say that freedom is doing anything you want, wherever you want, whenever you want. External Freedom – doing anything we want anytime, anywhere Internal Freedom – expressing who we truly are From the Christian perspective, we are created in the image and likeness of God We are inherently “good” We are tailored to do good and be good. When we do something “wrong”, something in us tells us its wrong – our conscience. Moral judgments must be backed by good reasons. Morality requires the impartial consideration of each individual’s interests. We cannot rely on our feelings, no matter how powerful they might be. Our feelings may be irrational and may be nothing but products of prejudice, selfishness, or cultural conditioning. Our decisions must be guided as much as possible by reason. The morally right thing to do is always the thing best supported by the arguments. Get the facts straight. Bring moral principles into play. Are they justified, and are they being correctly applied? Each individual’s interests are equally important, and no one should get special treatment. If there is no good reason for treating people differently, then discrimination is unacceptably arbitrary. Morality is, at the very least, the effort to guide one’s conduct by reason— that is, to do what there are the best reasons for doing—while giving equal weight to the interests of each individual affected by one’s decision. Is concerned impartially with the interests of everyone affected by what he or she does. Carefully sifts facts and examines their implications. Accepts principles of conduct only after scrutinizing them to make sure they are justified. Is willing to “listen to reason” even when it means revising prior convictions. Is willing to act on the results of this deliberation. Share a dilemma you experienced. How did you resolve it? What moral foundation did you base on?