On the Effects of Legislative Rules Author(s): Gary W. Cox Source: Legislative Studies Quarterly, Vol. 25, No. 2 (May, 2000), pp. 169-192 Published by: Comparative Legislative Research Center Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/440367 . Accessed: 27/06/2014 19:31 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. . Comparative Legislative Research Center is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Legislative Studies Quarterly. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 209.91.173.106 on Fri, 27 Jun 2014 19:31:22 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions GARY W. COX Universityof California,San Diego On of the Effects Legislative Rules In this essay, I consider how a legislature's rules of procedurecan affect both the process and the outcome of legislation. I begin by asking whetheror not rules of procedure should have any effects at all, given that they can often be changed by simple majorities of legislators. The second part of the essay classifies the effects that rules have. Rules can change the set of bills that plenary sessions of the legislature consider;they can change the menu of amendmentsto any given bill considered in the plenary;they can affect how membersvote; and-putting the first three effects together-they can affect which bills pass. I review evidence that rules do in fact have the suspected effects. Introduction In this essay, I considerhow a legislature'srulesof procedure canaffectboththeprocessandtheoutcomeof legislation.By legislative rulesof procedureI meanboththestandingordersthelegislaturemay establishforitselfandthosestatutoryorconstitutional provisionsthat materiallyaffectthe legislature'sprocessingof bills (e.g., urgency provisionsin LatinAmerica).Thediscussionis dividedintotwomain parts. First,I considerwhetheror not rulesof procedureshouldhave any effects at all, given thatthey can often be changedby simple majoritiesof legislators.Onewaythatthis concerncanbe expressed is intermsof policyinstability.Inmultidimensional spatialmodelsof legislativedecisionmakingunderpuremajorityrule,thegenericresult is instability-thatis, therealmostneverexistsa policythatcannotbe defeatedin a pairwisemajorityvoteby someotherpolicy(McKelvey and Schofield1986;Saari1997).Riker(1980) has arguedthatrules arevaluedprimarilyfor theiranticipatedeffect on policy outcomes, so thatgenericallytherewill be no stabilityin the choiceof rules,just as there is none in the choice of policies. By this argument,one cannot point to the rules as playing any systematic role in determining LEGISLATIVESTUDIESQUARTERLY,XXV, 2, May 2000 This content downloaded from 209.91.173.106 on Fri, 27 Jun 2014 19:31:22 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 169 170 Gary W. Cox legislative outcomes. Here, I do not consider Riker's "inherited instability"argumentbased on the multidimensionalspatialmodel but insteadfocus on a relatedargumentbasedon the unidimensionalspatial model. The second partof the essay classifies the effects thatrules have. Rules can change the set of bills that plenary sessions of the legislature consider;they can change the menu of amendmentsto any given bill consideredin the plenary;they can affecthow membersvote; andputting the first three effects together-they can affect which bills pass. I review evidence thatrules do in fact have the suspectedeffects. Can Legislative Rules Have Any Effects, If They Can Be Changed by the Assembly? In studying how rules of procedureaffect legislative outcomes, we mustmake an importantinitialdistinctionbetweenexogenous rules and endogenous rules. Exogenous rules are those that cannot legally be changedby the legislatureitself; changesrequirethe assent of some other actors separatefrom or externalto the legislature.Endogenous rules, in contrast,are those that can legally be changedby the legislature itself.' Most studies of the effects of legislative rules take them to be exogenous. For example, in the 1970s and 1980s, much of the literature stressing the importance of committees in the U.S. Congress assumed, either implicitly or explicitly, thatthe committees'jurisdictions were stableandthatthe senioritynormwas essentiallyinviolable. Studyingthe effects of rules by assumingthatthey are exogenous is a useful endeavor,butit can be analogousto studyingpresidentialvetoes in the U.S. under the assumptionthat vetoes cannot be overridden. When rules can be overturnedby the very actors whose behavior is supposedly constrainedby the rules, doubts are legitimately raised about how effective those rules can be.2 Suppose,for example,thatthe currentrulesof procedurein some legislature promote a particularpolicy choice, X, but that a majority exists in the legislaturethat would prefera differentpolicy, Y. In this case, the majority preferringY could replace the currentrules with ones consistent with passing Y, and then pass Y. Knowing this, any agents empoweredunderthe currentrules might acquiesce in Y's passage ratherthanobstructingit or amendingit, as they would be able to do were the rules exogenous. Thus, one might argue that stable rules of proceduremust either be inherentlyneutralas far as policy choice is concerned or they must be consistent with the equilibriumpolicy This content downloaded from 209.91.173.106 on Fri, 27 Jun 2014 19:31:22 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Legislative Rules 171 choice under majorityrule. For example, in the case of a unidimensional policy space, the equilibriumpolicy choice undermajorityrule is the medianvoter's ideal point(Black 1958). It shouldnot be possible to maintain rules that potentially interferewith the selection of the median voter's ideal policy unless that potential is never actualized. Although scholars used to take the effectiveness of rules of procedure for granted, arguments such as the one just given have suggested that rules might have no independentcausal force, at least when they can be changedby a simple majorityof those subjectto the rules (Krehbiel 1991, 1993). Reacting against this sort of argument, scholars have suggested a variety of ways in which the causal impact of rules, which continuesto be widely acceptedas an empiricalmatter, can be theoreticallyexplained. I consider three such argumentsnext. TheRules Are in the Constitution(or OtherwiseEntrenched) A first possibility is thatthe legislature's internalrules of procedure are stable because they are stipulatedin the constitutionand the constitutioncannotbe amendedby a simple majorityof the assembly. If some legislative rules are entrenchedin the constitution, and they lead to a policy choice, X, will that be stable?If a coalition (of legislators and nonlegislators) existed that was large enough to amend the constitution,preferredY to X, andcould find a set of rulesthatyielded Y, then X would not be stable and neitherwould the rules leading to it.3 But, if one continues to assume a unidimensional policy space, then constitutionallyentrenchedrules will enable the stabilizationof nonmedianpolicy outcomes. For example, if the constitutionrequires a three-fourthsmajorityof the assembly to amend, then the range of stable policies expands from the median to the interquartilerange; if the constitution requires another body to concur by majority, then anythingbetween the medians of the two bodies would be stable, and so forth. Empiricalexamplesof entrenchedrulesof procedureincludeboth constitutionalstipulationssuch as the vote bloque in France(cf. Huber 1996) or the urgency procedure in Brazil and Chile and nonconstitutionalstipulationssuch as the U.S. Senate's filibusterand cloture provisions (Binder 1997; Binder and Smith 1997). More generally, Doring (1995b, 36) reportsthat, of 16 countriescovered in a multiauthor study of Western European legislatures, 6 required supermajoritiesto changethe legislative rules of procedure,while Cox and Morgenster (2000) reportthat in 7 LatinAmericancountriesthe presidenthas entrenchedagenda-settingpowers of one sortor another. This content downloaded from 209.91.173.106 on Fri, 27 Jun 2014 19:31:22 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 172 Gary W. Cox TheRules Suit the MajorityParty and It Can Protect Them If party leaders can expel members from legislative caucuses, deny them renomination,or deny them future office opportunities, then the majorityparty(or coalition) may be able externallyto enforce a given set of rules. Cox and McCubbins(1994) tell such a story for the U.S. House of Representatives.Whateverone thinks of their story in the U.S. case, something like it seems plausible in countries such as Costa Rica, the United Kingdom, Venezuela, and Taiwan. TheLegislators Are Too Busy to Change the Rules Legislation is more like researchand developmentthan it is like choice among already known alternatives.Members of most major legislatures are thus constantly strappedfor time. But overridingany legislative decision made pursuantto the rules takes time and effort, and overturningthe rules themselves takes even more time and effort. The costs entailed in overturningrule-based decisions and rules are thus largely exogenous: they are the costs in terms of time and effort needed to constructa strategyfor overturning the decision andto assemblethe requiredcoalitionin supportof change. If one believes these claims-that it is costly to overturnrule-based decisions and more costly to overturnrules, andthatthe costs entailed are largely exogenous opportunitycosts-then one must also believe that rules have consequences. Consider, for example, the ability to "veto"bills that U.S. committees are routinely alleged to possess. As bills can be discharged, one might arguethat committee vetoes can be overriddenwhenever a floor majoritywishes. But supposea memberfiles a dischargepetition on a particularbill. She now tries to get other members to sign her petition but finds that hardly anyone knows what the bill is about. They are too busy with their own issues. When asked to sign, the other members face a choice. They can take the petitioner's word that it is in their intereststo sign. They can take the committee's word that it is in their interestsnot to sign. Or, they can allocate scarce resources to investigate the matterfor themselves. Unless the petitioner can find enough memberswho eitheralreadyknow aboutthe issue at stake and agree with her or are willing to take her cue over the committee's, the petition may stall because the other potential signatoriesare too busy to investigate the matter. Suppose that the petitionerthinks she might get enough signaturesfrom memberswho alreadyknow theirpreferencesor arewilling This content downloaded from 209.91.173.106 on Fri, 27 Jun 2014 19:31:22 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Legislative Rules 173 to take her cue. She now faces anotherhurdle. There is not enough time on the floor to pass every bill on the calendars,much less every bill in committee. Does a majorityof the House preferthat the to-bedischargedbill take an incrementof time on the floor, at the cost of not being able to proceedwith some otherbill (or bills) in the queue? Which other bill(s) will be sacrificed? Unless these issues can be negotiated as well, the petition will still fail, even if in a world of complete information(all members costlessly know their operative political preferences) and zero transaction costs (no time budget constrainton the floor) it would pass. For importantenough bills, the two costs suggested above will be lower: more members will already know about the bill and have clear preferences, and more will be willing to bump something else off the floor in orderto proceed with it. But for less importantbills, the costs can be prohibitive.Thus,even when vetoes can be overridden by a simple majority,and even when the bill vetoed would improve policy for some majorityon the floor, the veto can stand.If one wishes to reject this conclusion, one must believe that every bill that would improvethe statusquo policy for some majorityis identifiedandpassed in each Congress. The general point is this: Even "suspensoryvetoes" are important and consequential in an assembly in which time is short. As I shall argue below, positive agenda power-the ability to initiate the next step in a bill's progresstowardpassage, at a given time-is even more importantand harderto overturn.4 If Rules Have Effects... Supposethat one believes that rule-baseddecisions are costly to overturnand that the rules themselves are even more costly to overturn. This is enough to motivate a belief that rules will have causal effects butnot enough to say much aboutwhat those effects might be. In the next sections, I consider some of the effects that rules have. Rules can have proximal, intermediate,and final effects. The proximal effects of rules are to distributeresources (e.g., staff) and agenda power (e.g., a suspensory veto subject to discharge).5 The distributionof resources and agenda power stipulatedby the rules in turnaffects the menu of policy choices with which membersare faced and how members vote on any given policy choice (intermediate effects). Finally, the ability to set the menu of policy choices and to affect voting behavior may lead to an impact on the policy actually chosen. This content downloaded from 209.91.173.106 on Fri, 27 Jun 2014 19:31:22 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 174 GaryW. Cox The proximaleffects of rulesarethe easiest to describe,although even herethere is a wide rangeof specific techniques(see, e.g., Doring 1995c). In the next two sections, I will consider the intermediate effects-how rules affect the menu of choices and voting behavior. How Rules Affect the Menu of Choices Agenda powers can be classified in two broadcategories:6 1. The power to put bills on or keep them off the floor agenda (thereby determiningwhetheror not the floor has the chance to alter policy along a given dimension); 2. The power to protectbills from amendmenton the floor. Each of these species of agendapower is differentlyallocated in different assemblies. In each case, the question is whether the rules that allocate agenda power produceagendas that are consequentially different from those that would have been constructed by floor majorities(whetheror not these agendasthen lead to different policy outcomes is considered later). Setting the Floor Agenda In consideringhow the plenaryagenda is set, I shall build on the work of Shepsle (1979) and Cox and McCubbins(1999). Shepsle's model begins with two main elements: a set of w issues, or policy dimensions, thatthe legislaturemust decide, and a set of n legislators, each with strictly quasi-concave preferencesdefined over the policy space. The issues are partitionedinto a numberof jurisdictions. The membersare divided into a numberof committees (with membership on more thanone committee possible), each with its own jurisdiction. Committees are given the exclusive right to propose bills in their jurisdictions, but a committee'sjurisdictionmay itself be the union of smaller subjurisdictions(possibly, thoughnot necessarily, attachedto subcommittees).A committeewith a complexjurisdictionmay propose a separatebill for each of its subjurisdictions,but it cannot propose one omnibus bill dealing with all at once. The sequence of events in Shepsle's model is (1) the committees propose bills-i.e., put them on the plenary agenda,7(2) the plenary amends each of the bills put on its agenda by the committees, as its members see fit, and (3) each bill, as amended,is put to a final up or down vote. Although this particularsequence is not followed in all legislatures, something like it is followed in many. This content downloaded from 209.91.173.106 on Fri, 27 Jun 2014 19:31:22 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Legislative Rules 175 Cox and McCubbinsalter Shepsle's model in three main ways. First, they consider fully strategicactors instead of"sincere" legislators. In this respect, they follow Denzau and Mackay (1983) and Krehbiel(1985). Second, they divide Shepsle's committee stage into separateagenda-setting,amendment,andfinal passage substages.Just as the floor legislative process can be divided into these stages, so the committee legislative process can, too. Third,they considertwo polar distributionsof agendapower-the flooragendamodel andthe partisan agenda model. In the firstmodel,the floor agendais determinedas if by majority vote in the plenarysession. One way to interpretthis model is literally. In some cases (e.g., Denmark in the 1980s-see Damgaard and Svensson 1989; the U.S. in the 1790s), much of the plenaryagenda is decided by the plenary itself. Shepsle's model can formally accommodate such cases by assuming that there is just one committee-a committee of the whole. Another way to interpretthe floor agenda model is to say that there are in fact a numberof distinct committees but thatthe floor can extractbills from any committee it chooses (via a dischargepetition in the United States, for example);thus, the committees cannot bottle up bills that a floor majoritywishes to consider. In the second model, the floor agenda is determined as if by majorityvote in the majoritypartycaucus.8Again one might interpret this literally-as a model of those few periods in the U.S. House's experience when the majoritypartycaucus seemed to rule the roostor indirectly-as a model of committees which must anticipate the reaction of control committees or majority party leaders (Cox and McCubbins 1993). A key considerationin the model is the location of the statusquo point on each dimension.Normalizing,one can take Fj,the location of the median legislatoron the floor on thejh dimension,to be F== F= 0. That is, we locate the zero point on each dimension at the floor median on that dimension. This is done without loss of generality since the scale is arbitrary.The location of the status quo point, SQj,varies withj. Positive values of SQjindicateright-of-centerstatusquo points, while negative values indicate left-of-centerstatus quo points. Now consider how the plenaryagenda is set. Suppose first that there is a separatefloor vote on whetheror not to consider each of the w dimensions of policy. Suppose also that every membervotes his or her own constituents' interests (or his or her personal beliefs) rather than following the partyline. If the motion to consider dimensionj is passed, the ultimateconsequencewill be that policy on dimensionj is moved from SQjto F.9 If the motion fails, then policy will remain at This content downloaded from 209.91.173.106 on Fri, 27 Jun 2014 19:31:22 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 176 GaryW. Cox SQ.. Thus, a memberwill vote to consider dimensionj if and only if she prefersF to SQ.. An agenda formed by a sequence of floor votes on what to consider next would thus producean agendathat consisted of all dimensions with status quo points not equal to F. Nota bene thatconstructingagendasby puremajorityvote in the plenarydoes not offer any inherentadvantageto the majoritypartyor coalition. Suppose that a majorityparty exists and is left-leaning, so thatmost of its membersareto the left ofF, while most of the minority party's membersare to the right ofF. The bills that the median legislator decides to proceed with concernthe dimensions with status quo points not equal to F. These status quo points can be put in four basic categories. First, "farleft" status quo points are so far left that even a majorityof the left-leaning majoritypartyprefersF to the status quo (as does a majority of the minority party). Second, "nearleft" status quo points are such that a majorityof the majorityprefers the status quo to F (with a majorityof the minoritypreferringthe reverse).Third, "nearright"status quo points are such that a majorityof the majority prefersFto the statusquo, but a majorityof the minoritypartyprefers the status quo to F. Finally, "farright"statusquo points are such that majoritiesof both partiespreferF to the status quo.10 Fromthese fourpossible locationsfor the statusquo emergethree possible voting patterns.If the status quo is either far left or far right, then majoritiesof bothpartieswill supportplacinga bill on the agenda. If the status quo is near left, then a majorityof the majoritypartywill oppose placing the bill on the agenda,but lose. If the statusquo is near right,then a majorityof the minoritypartywill oppose placing the bill on the agenda, but lose. Thus,in thefloor agenda model, whetherthe majoritypartydoes betteror worse thanthe minorityin termsofsetting the agendafor plenary action depends entirely on the location of the status quopoints on the variousdimensions.If the distributionof status quo points is symmetricaboutF, then the majorityparty should lose as often as the minority party loses. If the distributionof status quo points is skewed to the right, then the majority party (assumed leftleaning) should lose less often thanthe minority.Finally, if the distribution of status quo points is skewed to the left, then the majority should lose more often thanthe minority. An alternativemodelof how the plenaryagendais set, the partisan agenda model, assumes that the majority party has a veto over the placement of any issue on the floor agenda. More specifically, if a majorityof the majoritypartyopposes placing a particularbill on the agenda, it can prevent its appearance.I shall be less concerned with how such an agendaselection mechanismmight arise1 thanwith what This content downloaded from 209.91.173.106 on Fri, 27 Jun 2014 19:31:22 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Legislative Rules 177 the consequences would be, were it to exist. The most obvious consequence would be that no status quo preferredby a majority of the majority party to the floor median-no near-left status quo in the example above-could gain a place on the floor agenda. Thus, under this model, one should never observe the majority party unsuccessfully opposing the placement of a bill on the plenaryagenda. ComparingPoint Estimates.Cox andMcCubbinspose two questions to assess the success of the majoritypartyin controllingthe floor agenda. First, how frequentlyis the majoritypartyrolled on agendasetting votes? A roll is countedwhen a majorityof the majorityparty opposes the placement of a bill on the floor agenda, but loses. If the majoritycan veto agendaitems,then its agenda-settingroll rateshould be zero. Second, how frequently does a majority of the majority coalition oppose the final passage of a bill, but lose? If the only issues thatwere placed on the agendaby a left-of-centerpartywere those on which the status quo was right-of-median,then the worst that could happen to these bills would be that they were amended to the floor median, in which case the median legislator and all to her left would still prefer passing the bill to rejecting it. Thus, the majority's final passage roll rate should also be near zero. To addressthe first question, Cox and McCubbinsexamined all 5,789 bills that originated in the House in eight selected congresses and were reportedout of committee. They found that in only four of these cases (or 0.07%)did a majorityof the majorityparty'scommittee membersdissent from the committee report.Indeed, majoritydissent of any magnitude was quite rare. Thus, in the House at least, the majority'srecordof avoidingissues thatproduceserioussplits on initial reportwas nearly perfect. What about the majority coalition's final passage roll rate? In the 45th to 99th Congresses, Cox and McCubbinsfind that the modal roll rate for the majoritypartyon final passage votes is zero, with an average of 3%. The majority's low roll rates-0.07% at the agenda-settingand 3% at the final passage stage-contrast with ratherhigher figures for the minority: about 5% at the agenda-setting and 25% at the final passage stage. Thus, in the U.S. case, the preliminaryevidence tends to reject the floor model in favor of the partisan(or "cartel")model. A similar study of the Japanese Diet (Cox, Masuyama, and McCubbins2000) finds a similar pattern.Governingparties in Japan arevirtuallynever rolled.Oppositionparties'roll ratesgenerallyrange from 7% to 50%. Although similar studies have not been performed for other legislatures, for many of them the expected result of a This content downloaded from 209.91.173.106 on Fri, 27 Jun 2014 19:31:22 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 178 GaryW. Cox comparablestudy seems clear. In the U.K. House of Commons, the French National Assembly, or the GermanBundestag, for example, the government seems clearly to control the agenda. Issues do not come out of committee unless the governmentwants them to come out, nor do governmentssustaindefeats on the floor. There are, however, assemblies where the agenda-settingand final passage roll rates for the government are much higher, such as Denmark (De Winter 1995, 145). ComparativeStatics. The conflicting point estimatesof the floor and partisanmodels are importantin indicatingthe centraldifferences between them. However, the equilibriumpoint estimates of the two models could be perturbedby any of a numberof small changes in the model, such as introducinga small amount of uncertaintyabout the location of status quo points or a small opportunitycost to action. Such amendmentsare less likely to affect the two models' comparative statics predictions than their point estimate predictions, and so the former are more importantfrom the point of view of empirical testing. To explain the two models' comparativestatics, we will let M denotethe majorityparty'smedianandm.the minorityparty'smedian. Underthe floor agendamodel, Cox and McCubbins(1999) show that the probabilityof the majoritypartylosing an agenda-settingor final passage vote increaseswith the distancebetweenM andF = F= 0 for all j, while the probabilitythat the opposition loses an agenda-setting or final passage vote increaseswith the distance between m.andF for all j. Underthe cartel agenda model, the second of these comparative staticsexpectationsholds-the oppositionshouldlose more often since its median member is more distant from the floor median-but the first does not-the majoritypartyshould never lose and any fluctuations in its roll rate should be unrelatedto the distance between the majoritypartyand floor medians. Cox and McCubbins(1999) find supportin the U.S. case for the cartel model and reject the floor agenda model. In particular,while the majorityparty's roll rate is unrelatedto the distance between the party's median (as measured by Poole-Rosenthal W-NOMINATE scores)12 and the floor median (measured in the same way), the minority's roll rate is significantly relatedto the distance between the minority and floor medians. In the United States,it is often said that it is not surprisingto find the majoritypartywinning votes-after all, they are the majority.But this observationis specious in the context of a unidimensionalspatial model in which membersareassumedto vote theirown interestssolely. This content downloaded from 209.91.173.106 on Fri, 27 Jun 2014 19:31:22 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Legislative Rules 179 Suppose the Democrats are in the majority. If the status quo on a particulardimension is to the left of the floor median, then the vote will go against the majorityparty(the Democrats).The median voter and all to her right will favor pulling the leftward status quo to the floor median,while many of those to her left will oppose such a move. Precisely how many oppose the move depends on how far left the statusquo is, but for statusquo points thatare preferredby the median Democratto the floor median, a majorityof the Democratswill vote against passing the bill. In that sense, the party will lose. If, on the other hand,the statusquo is to the right of the floor median, then the vote will go against the minority party. So, in a world in which all issues are unidimensional,most of the battle is to decide which issues to consider at all. Once a given issue is chosen, and assuming that nongermaneamendmentscan be beatenoff, the amendmentstructure and the twisting of armsat vote time are marginalconsiderations. The predictionthat governmentroll rates will not vary with the distancebetweenthe government'sandthe assembly's medians,while opposition roll rates will vary with the distance between the opposition's and assembly's medians, is also borne out in the case of Japan(Cox, Masuyama,and McCubbins2000). While there are thus far no other similar studies, it seems clear that for some, such as the U.K. House of Commons, the results will be comparableto those in the United States and Japan. Regulating Debate andAmendmenton the Floor But what happens if exogenous events (e.g., SaddamHussein's invasion of Kuwait) force an issue onto the agenda?What happens if the Senate is held by the otherparty,which does its best to force issues onto the agenda?Whathappens,in otherwords, if the majoritycoalition in a particularchambercannotperfectlycontrolits plenaryagenda and ensure that only unidimensionalbills of a coalition-friendlysort appearon the agenda? In these cases, controllingthe flow of amendmentson the floor may be especially important. The reaction of the majority to an unavoidable but unpleasantissue may be to package it with several otherissuesto createan omnibusthatis at leastpalatableto the majority. But then the majoritywill need to ensurethatthe packageis not picked aparton the floor, which will entail restrictingthe range and natureof amendmentsoffered. Do majority parties or coalitions actually have the ability to restrict amendmentson the floor in ways that the median voter (on This content downloaded from 209.91.173.106 on Fri, 27 Jun 2014 19:31:22 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 180 GaryW. Cox some particulardimension)mightnot agreewith?It seems clearenough that the French governmenthas such an ability via the package vote (Huber 1996), that the U.K. government has such an ability via the guillotine (Dion 1997), and that several Latin American presidents have a similar ability (Cox and Morgenster 2000). Even in the U.S. House, where there arenot constitutionallyentrenchedagenda-setting powers, there is a wide arrayof case-study evidence that the majority partyuses restrictiveprocedureson the floor to protectmajorityparty legislation. More systematically, Sinclair (2000) shows that bills reportedfrom committee on partisanvotes have been more likely to receive restrictiverules in the House.13 How Rules Affect Voting Behavior Rules affecting the distributionof resources and agenda power can affect the voting behaviorof members in two broadways: (1) by allowing agenda settersto manipulatewho can monitorvotes, and (2) by providingthe wherewithalto make side payments.Let us consider each of these points in turn. One way to view legislators' voting behavioris as the net result of variousdifferentconsiderationsthat can be divided into three main categories: constituents'preferences,personal preferences,and party preferences.If a legislator'sconstituents'interests,his or her personal beliefs, andhis or herparty'sdesirescoincide,voting decisionsareeasy (Kingdon1989).If these considerationsconflict,however,then manipulatingthe observabilityof members'actionsbecomesparticularlyimportant(Arnold1990).Governingor majoritycoalitionswithagendacontrol can frame issues in ways thatprotecttheir membersfrom the scrutiny of theirconstituentsor expose themto the scrutinyof theirpartyleaders. An exampleof protectionfromconstituents,or "providingcover," is an omnibusbill thatincludes a controversialprovisionor two, along with many popularor necessaryprovisions. Memberscan vote for the whole andjustify their votes as ways to secure the (locally) popular bits, while decrying or disowning the (locally) unpopular bits. Restrictive procedures can be used to ensure that the members are never faced with an amendment that proposes to remove just the unpopularparts.Anotherexample of protectionfrom constituentsis a vote of confidence. In the unlikely event that she is challenged, a member can apologetically explain that the vote was really aboutthe continuationin office of the government,so that she was not at liberty to vote simply on the merits of the issue (on which, of course, she is 100% in accordwith her aggrieved constituents). This content downloaded from 209.91.173.106 on Fri, 27 Jun 2014 19:31:22 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Legislative Rules 181 An example of exposure to party leaders' scrutiny is Willy Brandt's"stay in your seat"confidence vote. Worriedthat some of his backbenchersmight supportthe no-confidencemotion confrontinghis governmentif allowed to vote anonymously,Brandtorderedhis troops to stay in their seats and took advantageof the Germanrequirement thatan absolutemajorityof legislatorsmust supportthe no-confidence motion in orderto bring the governmentdown. Agendapowerandotherresources(e.g., staff) distributedby rules can also providethe wherewithalto make side paymentsto members. For example, if party leaders control assignment to committees or portfolios,desiredassignmentscan be held out as inducementsto good behavior. In the United States, Cox and McCubbins (1993) provide and review evidence showing how parties use party assignments to shore up loyalty on the margin. A similar story seems to play out in Europe,both in termsof the initialtradingof ministerialportfolios for party supportof a governmentand in terms of party leaders handing out plum assignments in the committee or party hierarchyto more loyal followers(Damgaard1995).Even in Brazil,Santos(1999) reports that party loyalty enhances a member's chance of being appointedto the more importantcommittees for some parties. Two furtherpoints aboutside paymentsought to be made. First, side paymentsareoften usedto clinch deals or clear legislative hurdles. Particularisticbenefits may be ends in themselves for the ordinary member,but for partyleadersthey are also means to the accomplishment of broadergoals. Second, positive and negative side payments intended to influence members' voting behavior are a part of any healthylegislative leviathan,butthey areof quitevariableimportance. In electoral systems that foster personal votes, it is not even in the party'sbest interestto "force"theirmembersto vote in particularways, sincethis substantiallyreducestheirprobabilitiesof reelection,thusdamagingthe party'sprospectof attainingor retainingmajoritystatus.In the UnitedStates,the typicalprocedureis formajoritypartyleadersto "buy" no morevotes thanthey mustin orderto securea legislativevictory. The bottom-line question, of course, is whetheror not attempts by parties to manipulate who can monitor members' votes and to distributeside paymentsdo in fact influencemembers'voting behavior. In parliamentary systems, the ability of parties to control their members' voting behaviorby making issues mattersof confidence is widely accepted (althoughquestions have been raised aboutthe credibility of governmentthreatsto resign). In contrast,legislative parties in presidentialsystems do not havethe big gun of confidenceto enforce discipline at the voting stage. Strong correlationsstill typically exist This content downloaded from 209.91.173.106 on Fri, 27 Jun 2014 19:31:22 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 182 Gary W. Cox between voting behaviorand partisanaffiliation in such systems, but it is hard to say whether these correlations arise simply because membersjoin partieswith which they tend to agree or whetherthere is also some partyinfluence above and beyond what would be expected on the basis of members' preferences. So, how can one detect the influence of partyon roll-call voting? Some headwayhas recentlybeen made in solving this methodological problem.If House membersvote with theirpartiesonly when the party position is congenial to their constituents and/or to their personal ideologies, then (I) theirvoting behaviorshouldnot change when they switch parties (unless their constituency or ideology changed when they switched);(2) there shouldbe no systematicrelationshipbetween members' reelection success and how frequentlythey vote with their partyon key partyvotes (by assumption,no one is casting "tough"i.e., electorally costly-votes for their party;thus, if one member is more loyal to the party than another on key votes, this can only be becausehis or herconstituencyis more in tunewith the party'sposition, and such memberswill be no more likely to suffer larger-than-average vote dropsor actualdefeat than less loyal members);and (3) members should be no more likely to supporttheirpartythanwould be expected on the basis of the positionsthey advocatein elections. Yet, (1) several analyses of party-switchersover the postwarerahave foundsignificant changes in voting behaviortoward greateragreementwith the newly joined party (see, e.g., Ansolabehere, Snyder, and Stewart 1999; McCarty, Poole, and Rosenthal 1999); (2) several studies find systematiccorrelationsbetween partyloyalty andelectoralrisk (Brady et al. 1996;Jacobson1996);and(3) Ansolabehere,Snyder,and Stewart (1999) find that membersof the U.S. House are more likely to support their party than would be expected from their responses to electoral questionnaires.It is hard to explain these results on the assumption that partiesdo not influence their members' voting behavior. How Rules Affect Final Policy Choices Inthis section,I considerhow rulesmightaffectfinalpolicychoices. I first consider how the rules enable the majoritypartyor coalition to get what it wants, then how they can simplify legislative negotiations. Helping the Majority "GetIts Way" Rules can empowerthe majoritypartyor coalition, when there is at one, three broad stages of the legislative process: at the agenda- This content downloaded from 209.91.173.106 on Fri, 27 Jun 2014 19:31:22 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Legislative Rules 183 setting stage, at the amendmentstage, and at the voting stage. I shall considereach of these stages,in reverseorder.In each case, the question addressed is how power at a particularstage can lead to final policy outcomes favoredby the majority. The WhipModel. Perhapsthe most frequentlymentionedway in which a majority party or coalition can get its way is by exerting discipline over its memberswhen they vote. While this techniquemay be importantin parliamentarysystems with strongparties,in some of the presidentialsystems of LatinAmerica and the United States, this technique is importantonly on the margins.Ratherthan insisting on a solid block of partyvotes to ensurepassageof their legislation, parties in some presidentialsystemsallow theirmembersto dissentmoreoften but still seek to corrala few pivotal votes when needed. The evidence thatpartiescan actuallypressuretheirmembersintovoting has already been reviewed. Are the votes in fact pivotal, so that they make the difference between winning and losing? The evidence here is largely anecdotal, but there are a lot of anecdotes, at least for the United States. The standardoperatingprocedure for Speakers in the U.S. House on close votes is to have a certain number of "vest pocket" or "just-in-case"votes lined up in advance. If the bill appearsready to fail, the Speakerthen calls in as many of these votes as are needed to ensure victory, in some cases even stopping the clock to providetime to find the needed votes.14 The Restrictive Rule Model. One step earlier in the legislative process than votes on final passage are votes on amendmentsto bills. And beforethe actualamendmentscome, decisionsmustbe madeabout which amendmentswill be in order.In cases where the government has the power to preventall amendmentsand hence presentmembers with take-it-or-leave-itchoices, it can clearly affect the final outcome. Theoretically,the impactof this sort of power on the legislative outcome is captured in the widely known setter model (Rosenthal 1990). In the United States, the partisaneffect of restrictiverules on outcomes is contested (Krehbiel 1991, 1997a, 1997b). But there is certainly evidence that the majority party uses restrictive rules on partisan issues and that the minority complains about it. More compellingly, members' voting behavior on (rule/bill) pairs is what one would expect on the hypothesisthatmembersbelieve thatthe rule will have an effect on the outcome. To explain this last point, due to Sinclair (2000), we must rememberthat underHouse procedurea "special rule" is sometimes adopted to regulate plenary debate and amendment activity on a particularbill. Members vote first on the issue of whether to accept This content downloaded from 209.91.173.106 on Fri, 27 Jun 2014 19:31:22 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 184 GaryW. Cox the rule, then on the substanceof the bill. Suppose the majorityparty fashions the proposedrules in orderto preventamendmentsthat the minoritywould like to move andthatall membersknow this. Suppose furtherthat the electoral consequences of votes on rules are murky: members can always talk about fairness or efficient transaction of business or minority stalling and majority bullying to shield themselves from any claim that a vote for a rule, R, that facilitates passage of a bill, B, is really a vote for B, or that a vote against R is really a vote against B. Suppose finally thatall membersbelieve that R will in fact facilitate passage of B and that both parties are pressuringtheir membersto supportthe partyposition. Giventhese threeassumptions,one expectsthe following patterns in voting behavioron (rule/bill) pairs. Some majoritypartymembers will have constituencies that supportthe substance of the bill. They will vote bothforthe ruleandforthe bill. Othermajoritypartymembers will have constituencies that oppose the substanceof the bill. These members are likely to vote against the bill because to do otherwise incurs electoral risk. Put anotherway, it will be relatively expensive for the party to buy these members' votes on the bill. In contrast, it may be considerablycheaperto buy theirvotes on the rule, depending on how securelyshieldedfromelectoralretributionthey feel. The party need offer no side paymentat all to memberswho personallyfavorthe bill. Members who are personally indifferentor mildly opposed can be bought by compensatingthemjust for their personaldistaste;they need not be compensatedfor electoral risk (or, at least, the electoral risk is reducedand hence the needed compensation). All told then, one expects majoritypartymembers whose constituentsoppose the bill eitherto vote againstboth the rule andthe bill or to vote for the rule but against the bill (with only a few voting for both). A similarargumentleads one to expect minoritypartymembers to fall mostly into two camps:those voting against both rule and bill, andthose voting againstthe rule butfor the bill. Sinclair(2000) shows that these opposed expectations about majorityand minority voting on (rule/bill) pairs do obtain, suggesting supportfor the underlying assumptionthatmembersbelieve rulesto have causalforce. At present, this is probablythe best statistical evidence we have that rules affect outcomes. The Partisan Agenda Model. Before a bill gets to the stage at which permissible amendmentson the floor are decided, it has to get out of committee. The powerto decide which bills make it to the floor is arguablythe least appreciatedbutmost fundamentalpower in terms of influencing final outcomes. This content downloaded from 209.91.173.106 on Fri, 27 Jun 2014 19:31:22 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Legislative Rules 185 Recall thatunderthe partisanor cartelagendamodel, the majority coalition monopolizes the plenaryagenda,in the sense thatit is able to prevent the appearanceon the floor agenda of any bill with which a majority of the majority would prefer not to deal. With this sort of agenda selection power, the issues that actuallymake it to the plenary will all have status quo points that are either to the minority's side of the floor median or so far to the majorityparty's side that a majority of the partywould preferpulling them backto the median. Thus, even if every separatedecision taken by the House is unidimensionaland ends up at the floor median, the policy location in the multidimensional space in which the whole sequence of decisions takes place will be substantiallybiased from what it would have been undera neutral agenda structure.If the majority is left-leaning, movements will be made leftwardon a good numberof dimensions with relatively fewer rightwardmovements (and those only to correct "far left" status quo points). Few rightwardmovements from the "near left" are passed because no resources are devoted to finding such moves, and if they do crop up, considerableresourcesare deployed againstthem. The net result is that policy will be more leftist than would have been the case undera neutralagenda. SimplifyingLegislative Negotiations Besides privileging the majoritycoalition over other legislative majorities, rules of procedurecan also make commitments to pass complex packages of legislation more credible, hence less costly to negotiate. ConcentratedAgendaPower Leads to Fewer butMore Complex ConflictualActs.Doring(1995a) andHenning(1995) considera model in which the government is a monopoly supplier of legislation. The government can choose either to produce fairly simple and nonconflictualbills, whose passage will not requirethe use of agenda power,or to producemorecomplexandconflictualbills, whose passage will be facilitated by agenda power. They argue that increasing the concentration and amount of agenda power in the hands of the governmentlowers the "price"of the more complex and conflictual bills, while leaving the price of simple nonconflictualbills unchanged. Accordingly, a governmentwill increase its "purchase"of complex conflictual bills when its agenda power increases, assuming that all else is equal and that complex conflictual bills are normal goods (in the economist's sense). Since (1) complex andconflictualbills always requiremoretime to processthansimple andnonconflictualbills, even This content downloaded from 209.91.173.106 on Fri, 27 Jun 2014 19:31:22 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 186 GaryW. Cox when the governmenthas strong agenda powers, and (2) the government faces a fixed, hardtime constraint,any increase in the percentof complex bills thatthe governmentundertakeswill necessarily mean a lower volume of legislation overall. Thus, all told, one expects fewer but more complex conflictual bills and acts (given the high success rate of governments)when agenda power is higher. Doring (1995a) provides some cross-nationalevidence for part of this story in a study of WesternEuropeanlegislatures.Ranking 18 European assemblies in terms of the agenda powers given to the government,then correlatingthis rankingwith the volume of legislation enacted in each country,Doring finds a negative and significant relationship.This finding addressesthe issue of the overall volume of legislation but not the issue of how conflictual the acts are, which Doring leaves for a latertime. Some evidence that agenda powers are in fact broughtto bear mostly on complex and conflictual bills can be gleaned from singlecountrystudies. Many studies of the use of restrictiverules in the U.S. House find that they are more often used on omnibus or multiplyreferred-which is to say, more complex-bills (Sinclair 1995, 2000). Similarly, some studies find these rules used more often in cases of partisanconflict (Sinclair 2000). Huber's (1996) study of the use of restrictiverules in Francefinds similar tendencies. ConcentratedAgendaPower Leads to QuickerNegotiationsover GovernmentFormation. De Winter(1995, 143) arguesthat "in countries where institutional arrangementsgive the executive extensive legislative agendasettingpowers,governmentformationwill consume less time, as most matterscan be settled 'on the road'. On the other hand, in countrieswhere the legislaturehas a relatively stronghold on its own agenda,coalitionpartieswill preferto settle all or most potential disputesbefore a cabinet is formedand,thus, formalize agreementsin a writtencontract...." De Winterfindssupportforthis ideain the factthat D6ring's index of governmentagendacontrolcorrelatesnegativelyand significantlywith the lengthof coalitionnegotiationsin WesternEurope. Therearedifferentpossible interpretations of this argument.First, perhapspartieswithout agendapower view themselves as not having any ability to implementagreementson the road.Thus, they negotiate more in advance.But why aretheirinitialnegotiationsableto be implemented? Second, perhapsit is possible for partiesto agree on a distribution of portfolios, ratherthana detailedpolicy platform,in systems with strong agenda power. Third,perhapssome of the contingencies thatmustbe negotiatedin systems withoutconcentratedagendapower can be preventedfromever arisingby appropriateuse of agendapower. This content downloaded from 209.91.173.106 on Fri, 27 Jun 2014 19:31:22 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Legislative Rules 187 Conclusion Legislative rules have effects because they distribute real resourceswhose effects cannotbe undonewithout incurringreal costs in time and effort, because they confer benefits thatpartiesfind worth preservingthroughextralegislativemeans,andbecausethey are sometimes entrenchedlegally. In a world in which time is short,the power to delay or expedite can be crucial, even if decisions to decelerate or accelerate a particularbill can be appealedto the plenary. In a world in which the effects of rules on final outcomes are obscure to voters, members fear electoral retributionfrom their constituents less than they would on straightforwardvotes on substance. Moreover, the obscurity of proceduralrules' effects makes it easier for parties to maintain control of procedural votes than to maintain control of substantivevotes. The actualeffects rules have are sortedhere into threecategories: effects on the menu of choices (which bills areconsideredon the floor? which amendments are allowed?), effects on voting behavior, and effects on the final legislative outcome (which bills pass?). Evidence of such effects is visible in most of the legislaturesthat have actually been studied, althoughthe qualityof the evidence varies widely, since it is difficult to make the necessary counterfactualcomparisons(e.g., whatwould the agendahave been hadthe rulesbeen different?)cleanly. Typically, the effect of rules is most visible in conjunctionwith a majority party or coalition's efforts to push through its legislative agendaagainstopposition.If one orderedthe world's legislative parties from those with the greatest incentives to push throughtheir legislative agendas to those with the fewest incentives, the orderingwould putparliamentarypartiesat the top (the governmentfalls if its program fails); proactive congressional parties, such as those in the United States, next (where the legislative parties are sometimes viewed as having electoral incentivesto prosecuteagendas[Cox andMcCubbins 1993]); and reactive congressional parties, as in Latin America, last (where the party label means less and, relatedly, there are fewer incentives to prosecutea partyagenda). It is interestingto examine the structureof agenda power across these three levels of incentive. Controlof the agenda is firmest in the parliamentaryregimes, especially the more Westminsterianones. It is lodged, moreover, in the handsof legislative partyleaders(who typically assume executive office). Controlof the agenda is next firmest in the United States. It is again lodged in the handsof legislative party leaders(who, due to the separationof powers,do not assume executive This content downloaded from 209.91.173.106 on Fri, 27 Jun 2014 19:31:22 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 188 GaryW. Cox office). Controlof the agendais weakest in LatinAmerica.It is lodged partly in the hands of the president, an executive official who often attempts to be "above parties,"and partly in the hands of the mesa directiva, typically composed of legislative partyleaders. It is interestingto note also thatthe meaningfulnessof partylabels, in terms of the policies that each party is likely to pursue, is ordered roughly the same way as are the incentives to legislate: European parliamentarydemocracies first, U.S. presidential systems second, LatinAmericanpresidentialsystemslast.Thereappears,in otherwords, to be a positive correlationbetween (1) legislative parties' incentives to legislate (and the frequencywith which they actually do legislate), (2) the extent to which agenda power is centralized in the hands of legislative partyleadersof the majoritycoalition, and (3) the electoral meaningfulnessof the partylabel in policy terms. Gary W. Cox is Professor of Political Science, University of California,San Diego, 9500 GilmanDrive,La Jolla, California920930521. NOTES I thankthe participantsat the ShambaughConference,University of Iowa, for theircommentson an earlierdraftof this paper,andChrisDen Hartogfor assistancein preparingthe manuscript. 1. The best examplesof exogenous rulesarethose stipulatedin constitutions,at leastwhen the constitutioncannotbe amendedby the legislaturealone butalso requires, say, presidentialapproval, approval by state assemblies, or approval in a national referendum.Clearexamples of endogenousrules would be the standingordersof the U.S. House of Representatives,which can be changedor maintainedat the sole discretion of the House (the courts have repeatedlydeclined to review these rules, citing Article I, Section 5 of the Constitutionwhich stipulatesthat "EachHouse may determine the Rules of its Proceedings...."). 2. An analogous concern has frequentlybeen raised about electoral rules. See Cox 1997, chapter2. 3. This would be the typical result if the policy space were of high enough dimensionality,since then even super-or concurrentmajorityrequirementswould not suffice to stabilize policy (see Cox and McKelvey 1984; McKelvey and Schofield 1986; Saari 1997). But note that these results from cooperativegame theory assume that it is costless to change the rules-no time elapses, no one needs to examine the consequences of changing to a particularnew set of rules as such consequences are utterlytransparentto all, and so forth.Note also that noncooperativeapproachescan give quite differentresults-consider Diermeierand Feddersen 1998. 4. If rule-baseddecisions-such as a committeedeciding not to proceedwith a bill-are costly to overturn,what about ripping up the rules themselves? Instead of discharging the committee of a particularbill, would it be cheaper to abolish the This content downloaded from 209.91.173.106 on Fri, 27 Jun 2014 19:31:22 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Legislative Rules 189 committee,pack it, or stripit of jurisdiction?One supposes thatthe answer is "no"in this particularexample and more generally. 5. Anotherimportantproximaleffectthatrulescan have,which I do not consider here, is to delineateinformationalrequirements-e.g., the requirementthatcommittees file writtenreportsto accompanybills, with documentationof those supportingand dissenting from the report. 6. Anotherimportantpowerthatmight be classified as an agendapower is that of settingthe reversionarypolicy outcome. 7. In some legislatures,such as the U.S. House, bills proposedby committees are not guaranteeda hearingon the floor; they are simply eligible for such a hearing but must still pass otherhurdles. 8. The model assumes the existence of a majoritycoalition. Here I consider the case of a majorityparty. 9. This follows if one assumes that nongermaneamendments(i.e., amendmentsthatbringin otherpolicy dimensions)arenot allowed andthatan amendmentto substitutethe policy F for whateverpolicy the bill proposes is in order. 10. The boundariesbetween these four regions can be defined as follows. Let Mjbe the median ideal point of the majoritypartyand m. be the medianideal point of the minoritypartyand assumethatM. < F< mj.Let R(MA)be the point to the majority median's left that gives utility equal to F (given symmetricutility functions, this will be the point 2M.-F). Similarly, let R(m.) be the point to the minority median's right that gives utility equal to F (given symmetricutility functions, this will be the point 2m.-F). Then every point to the left of R(Mj)is "farleft," every point between R(Mj) and F is "nearleft," every point betweenF and R(mj)is "nearright,"and every point to the right of R(mj)is "farright." 11. In the U.S. case, likely institutionalbases for a majoritypartyveto over the placement of items on the plenary agenda include: the scheduling power of subcommitteeandcommitteechairs,the requirementthatevery"spendingbill"passthrough bothan authorizingcommitteeandthe appropriations committee(on whichthe majority partyis disproportionatelyrepresented),the requirementthatmost importantbills pass throughthe Rules Committee(on which, again,the majoritypartyis disproportionately represented),andthe Speaker'sandMajorityLeader'scontrolover floor scheduling. 12. See Poole and Rosenthal 1997. 13. As Sinclair 2000 points out, this patternis precisely opposite to what a majoritarian(or "neutralrules")model would expect (cf. Krehbiel 1991). 14. The only argumentthat this does not representevidence that the majority partyis "buying"pivotal votes is Krehbiel'ssuggestionthatbothpartiesbuy aboutthe same numberof votes on any given bill, thus cancelingout each other's efforts. There is no evidence for this "canceling conjecture,"however, and there is considerable reasonto doubt it. For example, the majoritypartyhas more resourceswith which to rewardand punishthanthe minority,which should lead to bettersuccess in the votebuyingmarket.Also, if partyeffortsdo routinelycancelout, one would expectminority party leaders to be just as prominentin last-minutevote buying as majority party leaders, which is certainly not the picturepainted in the qualitativeliterature.Also, why are there not as many anecdotes about minority party leaders pulling out lastminutevictories as thereare aboutmajoritypartyleaders?Eitherthe agendahas been stackedor the majorityhas a bigger bag of side payments. This content downloaded from 209.91.173.106 on Fri, 27 Jun 2014 19:31:22 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 190 GaryW. Cox REFERENCES Ansolabehere,Stephen,JamesM. Snyder,andCharlesStewartIII. 1999. "TheEffects of PartyandPreferenceson CongressionalRoll-CallVoting."Unpublishedtypescript. MassachusettsInstituteof Technology. Arnold, R. Douglas. 1990. TheLogic of CongressionalAction. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Binder, Sarah. 1997. Majority Rule, Minority Rights. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Binder, Sarah, and Steven Smith. 1997. Politics or Principle? Filibustering in the UnitedStates. Washington,DC: Brookings InstitutionPress. Black, Duncan. 1958. TheTheoryofCommitteesandElections.Cambridge:Cambridge University Press. Brady, David W., John F. Cogan, Brian J. Gaines, and Douglas Rivers. 1996. "The Perils of PresidentialSupport:How the RepublicansTook the House in the 1994 MidtermElection."Political Behavior 18:345-67. Cox, Gary W. 1997. Making VotesCount.Cambridge:CambridgeUniversity Press. Cox, Gary W., and Mathew D. McCubbins. 1993. Legislative Leviathan. Berkeley: University of CaliforniaPress. Cox, GaryW., andMathewD. McCubbins.1994. "Bonding,Structure,andthe Stability of Political Parties: Party Government in the House." Legislative Studies Quarterly19:215-31. Cox, Gary W., and MathewD. McCubbins.2000. "AgendaPower in the U.S. House of Representatives,1877 to 1986." In Essays on the History of Congress, ed. David W. BradyandMathewD. McCubbins.Palo Alto, CA: StanfordUniversity Press (forthcoming). Cox, Gary W., and Richard D. McKelvey. 1984. "A Ham Sandwich Theorem for GeneralMeasures."Social Choice and Welfare1:75-83. Cox, Gary W., and Scott Morgenstern.2000. "Reactive Assemblies and Proactive Presidents:A Typology of Latin American Presidentsand Legislatures."In ComparativePolitics (forthcoming). Cox, GaryW., MikitakaMasuyama,andMathewD. McCubbins.2000. "AgendaPower in the JapaneseHouse of Representatives."Unpublishedtypescript.University of California,San Diego. Damgaard,Erik. 1995. "HowPartiesControlCommitteeMembers."InParliamentsand MajorityRule in WesternEurope,ed. HerbertD6ring.Berlin:CampusVerlag. Damgaard,Erik, and Palle Svensson. 1989. "Who Governs? Parties and Policies in Denmark."EuropeanJournal of Political Research 17:731-45. Denzau, ArthurT., and RobertJ. Mackay. 1983. "Gatekeepingand Monopoly Power of Committees:An Analysis of Sincereand SophisticatedBehavior."American Journal of Political Science 27:740-61. De Winter, Lieven. 1995. "The Role of Parliamentin GovernmentFormation and Resignation."In Parliamentsand MajorityRule in WesternEurope,ed. Herbert DOring.Berlin: CampusVerlag. Diermeier,Daniel, and Timothy Feddersen.1998. "Cohesionin Legislaturesand the Vote of ConfidenceProcedure."AmericanPolitical Science Review92:611-22. This content downloaded from 209.91.173.106 on Fri, 27 Jun 2014 19:31:22 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Legislative Rules 191 Dion, Douglas. 1997. Turningthe Legislative Thumbscrew.Ann Arbor:University of Michigan Press. Doring, Herbert.1995a. "FewerThough PresumablyMore ConflictualBills: ParliamentaryGovernmentActing as a Monopolist." In Parliaments and Majority Rule in WesternEurope, ed. HerbertD6ring. Berlin: CampusVerlag. Doring, Herbert. 1995b. "Institutionsand Policies: Why We Need Cross-National Analysis." In Parliaments and MajorityRule in WesternEurope, ed. Herbert Doring. Berlin: CampusVerlag. Doring, Herbert. 1995c. "Time as a Scarce Resource: GovernmentControl of the Agenda." In Parliaments and MajorityRule in WesternEurope, ed. Herbert Doring. Berlin: CampusVerlag. Henning, Christian.1995. "A FormalModel of Law Productionby Governmentas a NaturalMonopoly."In Parliamentsand MajorityRule in WesternEurope, ed. HerbertD6ring. Berlin: CampusVerlag. Huber,John. 1996. RationalizingParliament:LegislativeInstitutionsand PartyPolitics in France. Cambridge:CambridgeUniversity Press. Jacobson,GaryC. 1996. "The 1994 House Elections in Perspective."Political Science Quarterly111:203-23. Kingdon, John W. 1989. Congressmen's Voting Decisions, 3d ed. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press. Krehbiel,Keith. 1985. "ObstructionandRepresentativenessin Legislatures."American Journal of Political Science 29:643-59. Krehbiel, Keith. 1991. Information and Legislative Organization. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press. Krehbiel,Keith. 1993. "Where'sthe Party?"BritishJournalof PoliticalScience23:23566. Krehbiel,Keith. 1997a. "Rejoinderto 'Sense and Sensibility."'AmericanJournal of Political Science 41:958-64. Krehbiel, Keith. 1997b. "Restrictive Rules Reconsidered." American Journal of Political Science 41:919-44. McCarty, Nolan, Keith Poole, and Howard Rosenthal. 1999. "The Hunt for Party Discipline in Congress."Unpublished manuscript.Carnegie Mellon University. McKelvey, RichardD., and Norman Schofield. 1986. "StructuralInstability of the Core."Journal of MathematicalEconomics 15:179-98. Poole, KeithT., andHowardRosenthal.1997. Congress:A Political-EconomicHistory of Roll Call Voting.New York: OxfordUniversity Press. Riker, William H. 1980. "Implicationsfrom the Disequilibriumof MajorityRule for the Study of Institutions."AmericanPolitical Science Review 74:432-46. Rosenthal,Howard. 1990. "The SetterModel." In Advances in the Spatial Theoryof Elections, ed. James Enelow and Melvin Hinich. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Saari,Donald. 1997. "TheGenericExistence of a Corefor q-rules."Economic Theory 9:219-60. Santos, Fabiano. 1999. "Party Leaders and Committee Assignments in Brazil." Presentedat the annualmeeting of the AmericanPolitical Science Association, Atlanta,Georgia. This content downloaded from 209.91.173.106 on Fri, 27 Jun 2014 19:31:22 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 192 Gary W. Cox Shepsle, Kenneth. 1979. "InstitutionalArrangementsandEquilibriumin Multidimensional Voting Models."AmericanJournal of Political Science 23:27-59. Sinclair, Barbara. 1995. Legislators, Leaders and Lawmaking. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. Sinclair, Barbara.2000. "Do PartiesMatter?"In Essays on the History of Congress, ed. David W. Brady and Mathew D. McCubbins. Palo Alto, CA: Stanford University Press (forthcoming). This content downloaded from 209.91.173.106 on Fri, 27 Jun 2014 19:31:22 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions