ECO674: Behavioral Economics Punarjit Roychowdhury Shiv Nadar University, Delhi NCR 1 © Punarjit Roychowdhury These slides are copyright protected. Circulation, reproduction or transfer (online upload) of these slides without permission is a punishable offence. 2 Paul Samuelson to colleague: “Would you take a 50-50 bet where you win $200 if you win but lose $100 if you lose?” Colleague: “I won’t bet because I would feel that $100 loss more than the $200 gain. But I will take you on if you promise to let me make 100 such bets” 3 Paul Samuelson to colleague: “Would you take a 50-50 bet where you win $200 if you win but lose $100 if you lose?” Colleague: “I won’t bet because I would feel that $100 loss more than the $200 gain. But I will take you on if you promise to let me make 100 such bets” This is surprising! Yes, probability of loss is much smaller with 100 gambles (less than 1%) than with 1 gamble (50%), but the potential magnitude of the losses is much larger ($10,000 vs $100) 4 In general, this should not have been the case if the person’s preference followed the traditional expected utility model In the expected utility model, preferences exhibit segmentation independence, i.e., if a person is unwilling (willing) to take one bet, he should be unwilling (willing) to take two or more identical bets 5 In general, this should not have been the case if the person’s preference followed the traditional expected utility model In the expected utility model, preferences exhibit segmentation independence, i.e., if a person is unwilling (willing) to take one bet, he should be unwilling (willing) to take two or more identical bets Then, how can such behavior be explained? 6 Consider an individual with wealth w trying to maximize his portfolio He/she maximizes the expected utility of investing in the safe and risky assets will solve max𝑤𝑥 𝐸 𝑢 𝑤 − 𝑤𝑧 + 𝑤𝑧 𝑧 where wz is the amount of wealth invested in the risky asset, z is random variable denoting value of the risky asset at the time of sale 7 Let 𝜇 > 1 is the expected value of z The solution to the problem is wz 1 2 RA RA is the coefficient of risk aversion (𝑅𝐴 = −𝑢"(𝑤)/𝑢′(𝑤)) and the value 𝜎 2 = 𝐸 𝑧 − 𝜇 2 is the variance of z Higher RA, lower wz Higher 𝜎 2 (riskier asset), lower wz Higher 𝜇, higher wz 8 In the US, between 1871 and 1990 stocks (risky) have yielded 6.5% returns, while bonds (safe) have yield only 1% Then why did/do people still invest in bonds? Commonly explained by the notion that bonds are relatively less riskier (really? what is if the issuing body goes bankrupt?) However if we use the solution to the portfolio problem with relative risk aversion rate (𝑅𝑅 ) equal to 2 (note, 𝑅𝑅 =𝑤𝑅𝐴 ) and 𝜇 is 7, (recall 6.5% was the average value of stocks), then wz 3w 2 Since the variance of stocks is generally below 3, wz/w > 1 meaning that no wealth should be allocated to bonds 9 In the US, between 1871 and 1990 stocks (risky) have yielded 6.5% returns, while bonds (safe) have yield only 1% Then why did/do people still invest in bonds? Commonly explained by the notion that bonds are relatively less riskier (really? what is if the issuing body goes bankrupt?) However if we use the solution to the portfolio problem with relative risk aversion rate (𝑅𝑅 ) equal to 2 (note, 𝑅𝑅 =𝑤𝑅𝐴 ) and 𝜇 is 7, (recall 6.5% was the average value of stocks), then wz 3w 2 Since the variance of stocks is generally below 3, wz/w > 1 meaning that no wealth should be allocated to bonds Then why do still people invest in bonds? 10 Examples 1 and 2 can be explained by a combination of loss aversion and decision bracketing Definition: Bracketing refers to the grouping of decisions If a set of choices are made so as to take account of the impact of each individual choice in the set on all other choices, we say they are bracketed together Example If I choose to have a heavy breakfast, I might prefer to have a lighter lunch In this case, my decisions are bracketed together since when I decide to have a heavy breakfast, I anticipate the need for a lighter lunch I decide breakfast and lunch as a bundle 11 A decision is narrowly bracketed if it is bracketed together with only a small set of decisions A decision is broadly bracketed if it is bracketed together with a large set of decisions 12 Suppose an individual has the following value function if x v x 2.5 x if x0 x 0. Then expected utility of the gamble is: 𝐸 𝑣 𝑥 = 0.5𝑣 200 + 0.5𝑣 −100 = 100 − 125 = −25 Thus, the person would turn down the gamble since it would result in a negative value (potential loss of $100 looms larger than the potential gain of $200) Also, if the person were forced to take one gamble, and then asked if she would take a second, the calculation would be the same 13 Instead, suppose the person decides to play two of the gambles jointly, thus leading to a more broadly bracketed choice In this case, the expected value is 𝐸 𝑣 2𝑥 = 0.25𝑣 200 + 200 + 0.25𝑣 200 − 100 +0.25𝑣 −100 + 200 + 0.25𝑣 −100 − 100 = 100 + 50 − 125 = 25 Thus the person would choose to take two gambles jointly, although she would not choose to take any single gamble individually The same would hold true for 100 of these gambles 14 The equity premium puzzle might also be due to loss aversion and narrowly bracketed investment decisions Length of the planning horizon in investment affects the variance or the variation in the return of the portfolio If the planning horizon is short (e.g., a year), for risky assets, the variance is much larger relative to the average return In fact, over a short horizon, 𝜎 2 could be quite high compared to 𝜇 15 This could mean that 𝑤𝑧 𝑤 <1 Thus, if we assume investors bracket their portfolios on an annual basis (i.e., investors narrowly bracket their portfolios), then it might be sensible for investors to invest in bonds Each year when the investors evaluate the return, the variation and losses lead them to purchase bonds and ignore their longer planning horizon Instead, if investors don’t evaluate return each years but checks at the end of every 5 or 10 years (i.e., they broadly bracket their portfolios and try to adhere to their planning horizon), they purchase less bonds Thaler and others show that the more often we evaluate our portfolio, more narrowly we bracket, and more we tend to move more towards safe assets 16 Experiment: How does time bracketing affect investment decisions (Thaler et al., 1997)? A group of 80 participants were asked to allocate 100 units of portfolio between two investments A and B, with B being riskier and providing much higher mean return than A Participants randomly placed into treatments Design: Participants make investment choice (invest in A or B) for 200 periods under different conditions: Condition 1, participants made investment decision for each period separately after being able to observe the returns (make decision 200 times) Condition 2, participants made decisions for 25 periods at a time (make decision 8 times) In Condition 3 they made them in decisions for 40 periods (make decision 5 times) 17 All the subjects in all treatments were viewing the same return history in any decision period Result: The fewer the decisions they made, the more likely the participants were to invest in the risky fund B Narrower time bracketing, higher investment in safer asset 18 The notion that people would choose long-term investments (bonds or stocks) based on short term priorities is closely related to the notion of melioration Definition: Melioration is a concept from experimental psychology whereby an individual chooses the option that yields the highest utility in the current period, ignoring the impacts of their decision on choices and experiences available in future periods Decision bracketing is one explanation of melioration Investor makes investments that are attractive in the near term, ignoring the properties of the potential investments in the longer term 19 So far we have discussed the possibility that bracketing decisions by time sequence can affect investment choices But it is also possible to bracket decisions by individual investments in the portfolio 20 A broad bracketed investor should maximize her portfolio by 𝑛 max 𝑥1 ,→𝑥𝑛 𝐸 𝐶 + 𝑣 𝑥𝑖 𝑧𝑖 𝑖=1 subject to the constraint n C w xi i 1 where x represents investment in the asset, z is the random return, v is the loss averse value function with reference point equal to amount invested (Σ𝑥𝑖 ), C is the money spent on consumption, and w is wealth 21 A narrow bracketed investor, on the other hand, would maximize: 𝑛 max 𝑥1 ,→𝑥𝑛 𝐸 𝐶 + 𝑣(𝑥𝑖 𝑧𝑖 ) 𝑖=1 Each investment now is evaluated by itself in the value function with a reference point of 𝑥𝑖 22 If we assume a smooth value function, the solution to the broad bracketed portfolio choices is: xi i RA ii 1 x j ij v '' j i ii While the solution to the narrow bracketed portfolio is: xi i RA ii 1 v '' ii Where v” is the slope of the marginal utility function (negative over gains, positive over losses) 23 These terms differ in that the narrow bracketing ignores the covariance terms σij (covariance of return from investment i and j) Positive (negative) covariance indicates that 𝑧𝑖 and 𝑧𝑗 are positively (negatively) correlated Implication of this difference? When investment choices are narrowly bracketed, the investor will fail to recognize when the return of investment options are related Thus he/she cannot take advantage of diversification (i.e., invest in different types of asset, some safe and some risky) but rather seeks that all investments will have minimal risk of return (and possibly minimal return as well) 24 Observe if covariance is negative (positive), a broad-bracket investor will invest more (less) in the given asset However, since the narrow bracket investor ignores this term, when covariance is positive, she might end up over-investing in the assets and thereby end up taking much larger risk without realizing! 25 Experiment: (Read and Lowenstein) Its Halloween and you were trick-or-treating You visit three houses that happen to offer exactly the same three types of candy bars At the first house, you are allowed to take one candy bar, and you choose your favorite At the second house, you are also allowed to choose one, and you decide to take your favorite At the third house, you are allowed to choose two, and you decide to choose one of your favorite and one of the others What would you do? Result: Most people pick the same (favorite) candy bar from the first two houses, but pick two different types at the third This might be explained by bracketing 26 When people bracket broadly, the person values variety much more than when bracketing narrowly The subjects do not bracket the offered candies in first and second houses together, i.e., they do not broadly bracket, and thus they do not value variety When the subjects are forced to broadly bracket (in the third house), they end up choosing variety diversification bias Diversification bias actually can make people worse off In this case, diversification bias leads to subjects to not choose both favorite candy bars; had they chosen both favorite candy bars they would possibly be better off 27 Evident in many other contexts People tend to spread their retirement investments equally among all possible options in a retirement program, even if some are relatively unattractive In this case, people seek variety when broadly bracketing choices, even if it might make them worse off when consumption takes place 28 Cigarettes provide some immediate pleasure or high, making them highly attractive at any one point in time However, smoking may reduce the pleasure from anything that one has to do for long periods Moreover, cigarettes have a diminishing effect on the body as the smoker builds up a resistance to nicotine implying that someone who has been smoking for years do not get the same high or pleasure from nicotine in a single cigarette that a new smoker receives Thus, although there might be some short term ‘benefit’ of smoking, in long term the loss in utility due to smoking is massive Then why do people keep on smoking? What can explain addiction? 29 Bracketing may play a role At any one time, a smoker might consider the high of smoking (and perhaps other immediate social advantages) But narrowly bracketing the choice to the single cigarette ignore the future impact of the cigarette on the utility of all future activities Thus narrow bracketing could lead to melioration: a focus on the now at the expense of long term goals 30 Consider a decision problem between choosing to consume cigarettes x and other consumption y A rational consumer would behave as if she has to solve max u1 x1 , y1 u2 x2 , y2 , x1 x1 , x2 , y1 y2 subject to px x1 x2 p y y1 y2 w However, narrow bracketed consumer on the other hand would solve max u x , y max u x , y , x x1 , y1 1 1 1 x2 , y2 2 2 2 1 31 The narrow bracketed consumer will thus ignore all the future consequences of her consumption in period 1 (as a smoker does) 32 The condition for the solution of the narrowly bracketed individual finds the the point where marginal utility of consumption divided by the price of consumption is equal for cigarettes and other consumption in the first period but this ignores the added cost that cigarettes impose on future consumption If cigarettes reduce the utility of future consumption, then this cost should be considered Thus the proper solution (solution to the first equation) equates the marginal consumption of cigarettes in period 1 plus the marginal impact of period 1 cigarette consumption on period 2 utility, all divided by the price of cigarette consumption with the marginal utility consumption of other items divided by their price 33 By ignoring the future cost of cigarettes, the smoker consumes more than optimal number of cigarettes in the first period Further, if consumption of cigarettes in the first period makes consumption of cigarette in the second period more attractive than consumption of other goods in the second period (suppose the other goods in sports; cigarette consumption may make the person extremely unfit to participate in sports in the second period), then the person also overconsumes cigarettes in the second period 34 Suppose 𝑢1 𝑥1 , 𝑦1 = 𝑢𝑥1 𝑥1 + 𝑘𝑦1 If the smoker displays melioration or narrow bracketing, cigarette consumption in period 1 would be determined by ′ ′ 𝑢𝑥1 = 𝑢𝑦1 =k If that was not the case, period 1 consumption of cigarette would have been determined by ′ ′ 𝑢𝑥1 + 𝑢𝑥2 =k ′ If 𝑢𝑥2 <0, then the optimal level of cigarette consumption (without bracketing),𝑥1∗ would be lower than the melioration optimum (𝑥1𝑀 ) 35 u1i u2 ' x1 < 0 u1 y ' y1 k ′ 𝑢𝑥1 x1 * + ′ 𝑢𝑥2 x1M u1x '( x1 ) x1 36 People often use narrow bracketing to achieve large goals Narrow bracketing could be used as a self control device May be easiest to start a difficult task with small steps Broad bracketing can make it difficult to verify progress on the goal If one’s goal is to save $2400 annually, it may be easier to overspend in the interim because “there is so much time left until the goal must be reached”; on the other hand, if one’s goal is to have $200 per month, one quickly knows whether one is one track 37 A company has 8 divisions. Each had to choose between a safe project and a risky project. Each division had a budget of $20 million. Each risky project would gain $20 million with probability ½ and would lose $10 million with probability ½ Each division has a budget of $20 million. So each division manager chooses the safe project instead. The president approves of these choices The CEO fires the president Why? Is the CEO justified? Does bracketing play a role in this story? 38