╇ i The Anatomy of Myth ii ╇ iii The Anatomy of Myth The Art of Interpretation from the Presocratics to the Church Fathers michael herren 1 iv 1 Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide. Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and certain other countries. Published in the United States of America by Oxford University Press 198 Madison Avenue, New York, NY 10016, United States of America. © Oxford University Press, 2017 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, by license, or under terms agreed with the appropriate reproduction rights organization. Inquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the address above. You must not circulate this work in any other form and you must impose this same condition on any acquirer. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-P ublication Data Names: Herren, Michael, author. Title: The anatomy of myth : the art of interpretation from the presocratics to the church fathers / Michael Herren. Description: New York, New York : Oxford University Press, 2017. | Includes bibliographical references and index. Identifiers: LCCN 2016017087 (print) | LCCN 2016028998 (ebook) | ISBN 9780190606695 (hardback)| ISBN 9780190606725 (ebook) | ISBN 9780190606718 (ebook) Subjects: LCSH: Myth. | Mythology. Classification: LCC BL312 .H47 2017 (print) | LCC BL312 (ebook) | DDC 201/.3—dc23 LC record available at https://lccn.loc.gov/2016017087 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 Printed by Sheridan Books, Inc., United States of America ╇ v Contents Preface╇ vii Abbreviations╇ xiii Introduction╇ 1 1. The Paradigm of the Poets╇ 13 2. What Makes a Work Authoritative?╇ 27 3. Physis—╉Redefining the Gods╇ 37 4. Flirting with Atheism╇ 51 5. Attacking Poetry╇ 63 6. The Beginnings of Allegory╇ 73 7. Finding History in Myth╇ 83 8. Theos—╉Rediscovering God╇ 97 9. The Growth of Allegory╇ 109 10. Saving the Poets without Allegory╇ 123 11. From Allegory to Symbolism╇ 131 12. Greek Exegesis and Judaeo-╉Christian Books╇ 147 13. Reflection: How Lasting Was the Greek Achievement?╇ 165 vi vi contents Notes 171 Bibliography 189 Glossary of Names and Terms 199 General Index 219 vii Preface This is a book for students. By students I mean anyone interested in learning how ancient ideas influence modern thought and modern ways of being. My book, though written for students, is not a textbook; that is, it is not a simple summary of the main lines of myth interpretation as explained by previous scholars. Rather, it is a fresh attempt to look at the methods of interpreting the myths contained in ancient authoritative texts in the context of the history of ideas. I attempt to weave the strands of myth interpretation with those of shifting paradigms in ancient thought and culture, particularly as they relate to ideas about god, nature, the origins of the cosmos, and the fate of the soul. I also relate developments in interpretative methods to issues such as literacy, authority, the agenda of the philosophical schools, and attitudes to poetry. I touch on the large questions of freedom of expression, the effect of myth criticism on religious belief and social cohesion, and the impact of critical interpretations developed by pagans on the understanding of Jewish and Christian scriptures. The notion of a “paradigm” requires an explanation. By “paradigm” I mean the bundle of ideas prevailing at a given time that encompass the divine, its relation to nature, the origins of the world and humans, the beginnings of society, and the concept of the good life. Such ideas can be documented for any literate age. But one must keep in mind that they are the creations of elites; they cannot be taken as evidence for the universal beliefs of a given society. The most influential teachings prevailing in our own society might be captured by words and phrases such as evolutionism, secularism (“humanism”), religious and philosophical skepticism, individualism (anti-authoritarianism), viii viii preface and faith in progress through science—to name some. Such notions form the assumptions and working hypotheses of pundits and public intellectuals, and are disseminated in popular books, print journalism, television, blogs, and social media. They are not accepted by everyone, and eventually invite a backlash that leads to culture wars and a new paradigm. For the ancient world I have hypothesized three paradigms that correspond roughly to three eras: (1) the Paradigm of the Poets (ca. 800–600 b.c.e.), (2) the Paradigm of Physis (Nature, ca. 600–350 b.c.e.), and (3) the Paradigm of Theos (god, 350 b.c.e. onward). Each was succeeded in turn when its ideas were perceived as exhausted or inadequate. Myth and poetry gave way to natural philosophy, which in turn was undermined by the criticism that it did not adequately explain causation or account for god. The theism that replaced it, however, did not sweep away everything with it. The critical spirit, the Greek idea of historia (“investigation,” “inquiry”), survived and endured even through “the triumph” of Christianity. Remarkably, the greatest debt to ancient Greek thought incurred by Christianity was not a particular philosophical doctrine, but the habit of reading its scriptures critically—much as a pagan Greek might read Homer. This book entertains a thesis: the exposure of the most authoritative works of the ancient Greeks to public criticism and discussion was a decisive step toward creating the open, pluralistic society that we in the Western nations enjoy today. I do not mean to over-spin this. The speculative thinkers of the sixth and fifth century b.c.e. were not proto-secularists, or precursors of today’s “humanists.” Very few of them engaged in open assaults on religion, even in times when it was safe to do so. With few exceptions, they did not attempt to rid their world of gods, but rather to make the gods better, more worthy of emulation. Their idea of a rational cosmos included the divine, but it opened the debate over what the nature of the gods really was and what their role in the operation of the universe may have been. Whatever their opinions on these momentous questions, the early Greeks agreed on one issue: it was just fine to disbelieve myths, and to criticize portions of what the ancient poets Homer and Hesiod had to say about the gods. The poets may have been inspired in some way, but that was no guarantee against misrepresentation of the divine. The image invoked by the title word Anatomy refers to the cutting up (Greek ana-tomē) of the body (that is, the literal meaning) of a myth to see what lies inside. We can imagine—in good Roman fashion—that a reading of the entrails is to follow. And like all such efforts in divination, interpretations varied. Because myths were often coupled with poems, the anatomy of a myth became closely linked to the dissecting of words (especially names) in the poems that contained them. I trace the main lines of these different anatomies, insofar as they can be documented. I emphasize the importance of “public interpretation,” as I focus on the origin and growth of the open criticism of ix preface ix myth and poetry and attempts to interpret them in published form. The advent of literacy brought with it the possibility of publication. For the ancient Greeks, any book in the public domain, regardless of topic, was open to discussion and criticism, even scorn when warranted. Freedom of expression was abetted by freedom of movement also, as early Greek thinkers moved from place to place and brought their books with them. There were indeed attempts at repression, but these were localized, sporadic, and in the long run unsuccessful. I have designed my book as a narrative. There is a story to be told, and stories involve advances and reversals, vicissitudes and progress. They do not always end happily; this one does not end unhappily. I am naive enough to believe that the appropriation of pagan Greek methods of critiquing ancient myths by Jewish and Christian interpreters of the scriptures had a long-term beneficial effect on later readers of religious books. However, the frame of my story will be limited to an initial impulse from Jewish scholars to adopt the tools of pagan Greek myth criticism, followed by their appropriation by the Greek Christian Fathers. The methods established by the pagan Greeks and adapted by Jewish and Christian scholars passed into the Western Middle Ages and the Renaissance, when they were once again applied, with some variations, for interpreting the pagan classics. “Classical exegesis” (my term for the bundle of ancient interpretative methods) served first to hedge the scriptures against fundamentalism, then to preserve the pagan classics against assaults by zealous Christians.1 The historical era covered, as the subtitle suggests, is the entire ancient world. I begin with Homer and end, in the Greek domain, with the Neoplatonist Proclus, who died in 485; in the Latin world I stop at Augustine, who died in 430. The geographical confines are, unsurprisingly, set in cities around the Mediterranean. I start in Ionia (western coastal Turkey), and proceed to South Italy, Athens, Rome, Alexandria, Carthage, and back to Athens. While one can mark certain turning points where paradigms shift, the reader is cautioned against expecting absolute breaks between one paradigm and another. There is evidence of scientific thinking in the early poets, theistic dogmatism among the natural philosophers (the Presocratics), and continuity of scientific thought in the period when theism is predominant. Although the present book has been gestating for about two decades, I felt some urgency to complete and publish it in the light of the events in Paris in 2015. I believe the pundits are correct about one thing at least: although the series of attacks differed in outcome, their purpose was the same. They were all assaults on freedom. I do not leap from that assertion to an indictment of Islam or religion in general. But I do fear that there is a link between irrational acts of cruelty and misguided understandings of religious texts. In that light, I believe that the ancient Greeks have something of benefit to offer today’s world. Their methods of interpreting their authoritative poets may strike modern literary scholars as primitive or naive, but they were infused with a healthy x x preface skepticism, a refusal to believe what appeared irrational, or accept myths at face value. The idea for this book springs, first and foremost, from my years of teaching courses on the ancient humanities at York University and graduate seminars on the classical tradition and the Latin Bible at the University of Toronto. Several of these courses are directly related to the interpretation of myth: “Myths and Their Meanings,” “Greek Mythology,” and “Texts and Interpretation.” Matters related to the interpretation of authoritative books also arise in the seminar I regularly teach on St. Augustine. By teaching the survey course “Myths and Their Meanings,” I became acquainted with the methods developed in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries for dealing with myths cross-culturally and the various modern schools of myth interpretation—the “myth and ritual school,” structuralism, functionalism (based on historical linguistics), and the different psychoanalytical approaches. Perhaps one of the most surprising features of this book is that it is short, containing chapters of moderate length. I had a great deal more documentary evidence at my disposal than I use here, but many passages illustrate the same exegetical points. And so, rather than write a 600-page book that people might use for reference, but not really read, it seemed wiser to write a shorter book that could be read and absorbed in a few sittings. The strategy of brevity also serves the pedagogical aims of the book, one with chapters of manageable length that can be used in conjunction with primary sources in a college or university setting. A short book also supports the aim of presenting a thesis. The development of a variety of interpretative methods is a worthy subject, but I would not want this to obscure the central point that it is the activity of interpreting authoritative texts, and the freedom to do so, that has helped create the society that we currently enjoy. Thus, I draw upon the Greek poet Callimachus: a small book is a great virtue. My research has been generously supported at various stages by the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada, the Killam Foundation, the Guggenheim Foundation, and the Alexander-von-Humboldt Stiftung. I am especially grateful to the Alexander-von-Humboldt-Stiftung for a research prize in 2004 that enabled me to investigate a large number of manuscripts in the Bayerische Staatsbibliothek in Munich. The many hours needed to collect the large number of slips containing excerpts from Greek and Latin texts relative to myth interpretation were afforded me by the Killam Foundation of the Canada Council, which awarded me a Killam Fellowship (1996–1998) and by a Guggenheim Fellowship (1998–1999). As freedom is one of the leitmotifs of my work, I express my gratitude to York University, and especially to Atkinson College, for the freedom it gave me to teach what I saw fit, and to take leaves when I needed them to pursue my research. I would like to thank my longtime colleague and friend Ross Arthur for reading the manuscript and suggesting a publisher; Florence xi preface xi Silver for decades-long encouragement to write a book on Greek myth; John Magee, Brad Inwood, and Brian Stock for stimulating and helpful discussion; the readers for Oxford University Press for their very helpful reports preventing error and initiating improvement; executive editor Stefan Vranka for his faith in this project; and, most of all, my wife, art historian Shirley Ann Brown, for many wise suggestions over the course of preparing and revising this book, and for meticulous editing and proofreading of the final draft. xii xiii Abbreviations For full bibliographical information consult the Bibliography. Deut. DK (Bible) Deuteronomy Diels, Hermann and Walter Kranz, eds., Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker Epid. (Cornutus) Epidrome FGrH F. Jacoby, ed., Die Fragmente der griechischen Historiker Gen. (Bible) Genesis H.P. (Heraclitus the Younger) Homeric Problems Il. (Homer) Iliad KRS G. S. Kirk, J. E. Raven, and M. Schofield, The Presocratic Philosophers LCL Loeb Classical Library Lev. (Bible) Leviticus Meta. (Aristotle) Metaphysics N.E. (Aristotle) Nicomachean Ethics Od. (Homer) Odyssey Phys. (Aristotle) Physics Rep. (Plato) Republic SVF H. von Arnim, ed., Stoicorum veterum fragmenta Theog. (Hesiod) Theogony Tim. (Plato) Timaeus xiv ╇ xv The Anatomy of Myth xvi 1 Introduction “The Greeks’ most important legacy is not, as we would like to think, democracy; it is their mythology.” So begins Mary Lef kowitz’s Book, Women in Greek Myth.1 The statement rings true. Certainly, when we think of the ancient Greeks, we think first of their gods and heroes. Their statues abound in museums, and kitschy plaster copies of them can still be found in people’s houses and gardens. Movies and animated cartoons about Hercules or Perseus are regularly released, while novelists and short story writers continue to probe the ancient stories for their insights into the human condition. Some of the very great stories, for example, the tale of Odysseus (Roman Ulysses), cross artistic boundaries. Ulysses’ tale provided the impetus for one of the first operas, Claudio Monteverdi’s Return of Ulysses, and also for one of the masterpieces of the twentieth-century novel, James Joyce’s Ulysses. 2 Like the daimōn Proteus, myths are plastic: they can assume almost any shape at will. And like Proteus, they can’t be wrestled down. They will wriggle out of any straitjacket you contrive in order to assume some new form. Myths shape-shift into paintings on vases, morph into poems, then take musical form as Pan plies the pipes. If this does not convince one of the enduring power of Greek and Roman myths, consider their influence on our language. Our astral bodies from Mercury to Pluto are named after the Greek gods dressed in Roman garb; the names have not changed in more than two millennia. The names of several months—March from Mars, May from Maia, and June from Juno—reveal Roman or Greek origins. The French tried to change the month names during the Revolution and for a time under Napoleon, but to no avail. The Romance languages, for example, French, retained the names of the Roman gods for the last four weekdays: mardi (Mars), mercredi (Mercury), jeudi (Jupiter), and vendredi (Venus), while in English Saturday (< Saturn) displaced the Sabbath (samedi, sabbato), leaving Sun and Moon as common ground. However, the planets and the times they generate are not the end of the matter. Consider our psychological states: jovial (“cheerful, merry”), saturnine (“gloomy”), and 2 2 introduction mercurial (“volatile”), the last named after an element, which in turn got its name from the god. The heroes come into it as well. A hard job is a Herculean task, while a fatal flaw is an Achilles heel. All of these names and expressions are hard wired. They are not going to be replaced any time soon. Myths take hold of the minds of young people in a way that ordinary history cannot. Alexander the Great, who was deservedly famous for what he did, became even more famous for what he didn’t do, which was to travel in a submarine, sail into the frozen sea, and fly. (These events are recorded in the pseudo-histories that grew up after his lifetime.3) Such extraordinary feats are the stuff of younger children’s fantasies. They incite young imaginations to dream about the possibilities of human life. At a later stage, tales such as Perseus and Medusa, Odysseus and the Cyclops, and Theseus and the Minotaur enthrall children’s minds with their focus on bravery and cunning. Later still, teenagers coming to grips with their own identity are attracted to darker stories such as Oedipus’s quest for his beginnings, or to the mystery of the Golden Bough that gained Aeneas entry to the underworld and the enlightenment that resulted from his journey. These and similar stories continue to play an important role in our current pedagogy. They are valued not so much because they come from great works of literature as because they are great stories. They excite the imagination as they teach. They function well in the educational systems of our multicultural Western societies because they transcend particular cultures and value systems. Because the cults to which the Greek gods and heroes were attached are long dead, their stories rarely give offence. It is little wonder, then, that children who have never heard of Noah or his ark can tell you all about Jason and the Argonauts. What differentiates the Greeks from other earlier civilizations is that they not only gave us their wonderful narratives, but they also provided the elementary tools for interpreting them. We know that other civilizations, many of them much older than the Greek, produced rich mythologies. Think of the Hindus, the Sumerians and Akkadians, and the Egyptians, to name only some. But their stories were left to speak for themselves—or at least we have no evidence to the contrary. If their tales were simply about heroic feats or the love affairs of human beings, one might reasonably say that nothing more is needed. But myths are often much more complex, as they introduce different types of divine beings (e.g., gods, daimones, nature spirits) and describe the interactions between these beings and humans. Moreover, myths are often grouped into larger constellations that begin with the origin of the cosmos, the creation of men and women, and descriptions of an earlier age when things could happen that cannot happen now. For us, such claims immediately raise problems of belief. For adults of our time, a horse named Pegasus was no more able to fly than Santa’s reindeer. Both are fables fit for young children; they are the stuff of the nursery. 3 introduction 3 Our earliest records of disbelief in hallowed stories come from the sixth century b.c.e. There were two basic critiques of the stories: (1) Many of them were unbelievable for rational human beings. (2) The traditional tales misrepresent the true nature of the gods, as they depict them committing theft and adultery and all manner of deception; they also show them shifting shapes and performing deeds contrary to their natures. On the one hand, we see skeptical minds that are struck by the disconnect between a transmitted story and one’s knowledge, based on human experience, of what is possible. On the other, we see developing a new concept of what a god should be. Far from shunting the gods aside, the earliest Greek critics of myths sought to incorporate the gods into a new paradigm: one that allowed for the operation of the divine, but within the constraints of reason and the laws of nature. For the pioneers of interpretation, myths were false stories about the gods and heroes. When we think of myths today, if we think of them as anything other than fairy tales, fictions, or propaganda, we imagine them as stories that originated in the distant past—a phenomenon beyond the reach of historians. Most of us do not think of them as coming from specific writers. Poetry and literature have authors; myth comes from somewhere else. Myths may belong to racial memory, or may embody some universal truth. We know, for example, that a primeval flood myth is not unique to the Book of Genesis. There is a flood story that comes from Sumeria, is repeated in Akkadian literature, and is later adapted by the compilers of Genesis. The Greeks also have a flood story that Ovid recounts as the tale of Deucalion and Pyrrha. 4 It is perhaps not surprising that these geographically connected cultures have a common account of a cataclysm that preceded history. It is more surprising that similar tales arise in North and South American mythology. One might explain all this as caused by the common experience of mankind distributed throughout the continents. The stories might have arisen from the destruction caused at the end of the Ice Age when the glaciers covering much of the earth’s surface began to melt. But there are other modern explanations. Tales of a destructive catastrophe brought on by flooding could be rooted in a nightmare of the collective unconscious. Modern theories of the origins of myth appear to have originated in the age of exploration. Christian missionaries of the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, hoping to convert the “primitive peoples” whom their political masters were colonizing, began to collect and translate their stories. Classically educated scholars quickly realized that a number of these “primitive tales” bore an uncanny resemblance to the Greek and Roman myths with which they were acquainted.5 From the German Romantics of the nineteenth century came the insight that myth must be taken on its own terms and understood for its unbreakable bond with the development of the human spirit.6 Meanwhile, the idea of the connectedness of myth across cultures grew alongside the 4 4 introduction development of the new science of anthropology, which focused on the nexus between primitive religion (ritual) and myth.7 In contrast to modern thinking about myth, most ancient Greek interpreters associated myths with the poems that contained them. Myth making was the business of poets. Homer and Hesiod, the earliest Greek poets whose works have survived, were widely regarded as the authors of the stories. Accordingly, they were blamed for deception—foisting lies on unsuspecting youth—or praised for their wisdom. With some important exceptions, the Greeks saw poets as the inventors of myth. At the start, the Greeks did not possess the advantage we have of being able to gather myths from different cultures and different ages and compare them. Had they been able to do this, they would have realized that their own stories had much in common with stories from neighboring cultures that were older than their own. Although willing to attribute much of their wisdom to the Egyptians, the Greeks never had an inkling that many of their myths were derived from the Middle East and the Levant.8 We today see poets as shapers of stories that already existed, and think of myths as having a life of their own. This was not the mainstream view in ancient Greece. Poems and myths were inseparable; myths are false stories; therefore, poets are liars. Solon, the famous lawgiver of Athens, was, I believe, the first to make the accusation in the early sixth century b.c.e. That poets were the inventors of myths and that they were liars were the dominant views of the Greeks, not only at the beginning, but well into late antiquity (down to the sixth century c.e.). However, alternative views were advanced against both. Regarding the origins of myths, two very different ideas came on stream. The earlier one came from the sophists of the later fifth century b.c.e. Some believed that the earliest men lived under terrible conditions, in constant need of food and shelter and protection against those who were stronger. They argued that myth making reflected this primitive state— an idea that is strikingly akin to modern anthropological theories as well as to Thomas Hobbes’s view of man’s early life as “nasty, brutish, and short.” Stories about the gods arose collectively through fear or superstition, or from need, or else were invented by early lawgivers in order to limit the excess of the strong. In that view, the poets might be regarded as transmitters, rather than inventors, of myths. Whether one belonged to the “enemies of poetry” group, or to the more modern-seeming social theorists, the conclusion about myths was the same: they could not be taken literally. An alternative view, developed in the fourth century b.c.e., also relates the origin of myths to the origin of mankind. Against the idea that human life advanced from misery to a more prosperous condition, it claimed that the opposite was true. Ironically, it relied on a myth as its basis. The poet Hesiod had depicted three quite different conditions of human life deriving from the myth of initial blessedness: (1) in a “Golden Age” as Zeus’s first humans; (2) under the benign rule of Zeus’s father, Kronos; or (3) initially 5 introduction 5 in close contact with the gods prior to an unfortunate rupture. Related to this original happiness is the concept of original wisdom. In the beginning the gods revealed an ancient wisdom containing truths about the cosmos and the nature of the divine. This truth was wrapped in myths. As the myths were passed down through the generations they were corrupted. The main agents of this corruption were the poets who distorted the divine truths by inventing fictions about the gods and their actions. The poets still bore responsibility in the process of myth making, but their contribution was baneful. It was the job of the philosophers to see through their distortions and reconstruct the ancient wisdom.9 Around the same time as the above theory was being developed, a radical thesis claiming that the gods were originally men who had done great deeds to benefit their communities was advanced in a fictional travel account called Sacred Scripture. Its author was a certain Euhemerus, about whom little is known. Euhemerus claimed that he learned on his voyage that the gods were only men who were worshipped as gods after their death. He reported that the deeds of Ouranos, Kronos, and Zeus were inscribed on a golden column. Accordingly, myths are stories that arise from the cult of heroes. Finally, there is the theory that the ancient poets, not the gods, invented the myths, but did not tell lies. Rather, they used myths to conceal the deep cosmological and spiritual truths that were available to them. This “defense of poetry” can be traced to an early date (sixth century b.c.e.), but was more widely accepted in the centuries after Christ. In that view the poets were philosophers who communicated deep truths in the form of fables. Thus, the poets did not distort “the ancient wisdom,” but preserved it. Some adherents of this idea thought that the poets deliberately concealed their truths so that they would not be profaned by the masses, while leaving them accessible to those with deep understanding.10 We might summarize these four theories of myth origins as follows: I. Authorship Model A. Poets as Liars B. Poets as Sages II. “Evolutionary” Model A. Needs of Primitive Man B. Cult of the Heroes III. “Revelation” Model In terms of chronology, the authorship model is the oldest, and begins with I.A. It is also the most enduring of the models, with I.B becoming predominant in the early Christian era. The “evolutionary” model is the child of the fifth century b.c.e., a model that received new impetus from the theory of Euhemerus 6 6 introduction in the third century. It fits well with the paradigm of physis (nature), as it sees myth as a natural development appropriate to the challenging conditions of the earliest humans. The Roman poet Lucretius, who also saw myths as arising out of the abject conditions of human origins, attributed ideas about gods and their attributes to terrifying dreams.11 The “revelation” model that arose in the following century might be understood as a reaction to the pessimistic picture of the human condition sketched by the “evolutionists.” It is a good fit for the paradigm of theos (god). In the fourth century three of the major philosophical schools adopted some form of “creationism” (a broad generalization that include theories that god had either a direct or an indirect role in the creation of the world and humans). Accordingly, a benevolent god or gods revealed his wisdom to mankind in the form of myths at the beginning of human existence. The criticism and interpretation of myth was begun by the early cosmologists and philosophers and quickly became their monopoly. The thinkers of the sixth and fifth centuries were interested primarily in cosmology (the origin and makeup of the universe) and theology (the nature of god or the divine). They were also very much concerned with the question of how god was related to nature. The writings of the poets provided the catalysts for analyzing these questions. As a result, the study of myth stayed focused on the origins of things and their makeup. Myths were worth studying for what they might potentially yield for understanding these big issues. As intellectual interests broadened into the examination of human society and individual psychology, it was again the philosophers who made them their property. When philosophers in later antiquity undertook to classify myths, they treated them, unsurprisingly, as types of philosophical fable. All this had a positive side: the philosophers deserve much of the credit for saving myths from the attacks of critics and censors by explaining them as disguised philosophy.12 This defense proved to be especially valuable in the early Christian and medieval eras. The natural philosophers were followed by the earliest historians. Some of these, like Hecataeus, also pursued mathematical and philosophical interests. (In the history of Greek thought, multidisciplinarity preceded specialization.) The historians, too, were imbued with the spirit of Greek skepticism and regarded many popular beliefs as foolish. When they analyzed accounts of the deeds of great heroes, or the interactions of gods and men, they invariably posed the question of whether what was described was possible according to natural criteria. Because humans could do only what was humanly possible, and gods could do only what conformed to nature, many stories were declared to be unbelievable.13 The Greeks knew what myths were, but they had no single word for “myth.” The closest to it was muthos (the origin of our word “myth”). However, Greek muthos had far too many meanings to be useful as a descriptor of what we mean by “myth” in the general sense. It could mean any kind of talk or 7 introduction 7 conversation, the subject matter of a conversation, design or purpose, and, of course, a story. Thus it was no more useful than logos, which had a similar, perhaps even broader, range of meanings. A third term, plasma, was also used to indicate clearly that a story was contrived, i.e., fictitious. The Greeks were also late in developing narrative theory. They developed a sophisticated terminology for distinguishing genres of literature (epic, lyric, tragedy, comedy, etc.), but took little or no interest in distinguishing one kind of story from another. The earliest writers on myth did not distinguish between a set allegory within an epic, an Aesopian fable, or a philosophical myth composed to illustrate a philosophical doctrine. These distinctions had to await the early fifth century c.e., when Macrobius, a philosopher and literary theorist, addressing the question of the value of myths for teaching philosophy, proposed a division of fable into the following: (1) stories filled with the imaginary doings of lovers (comic plays and novels or “romances”); (2a) fictitious tales such as the stories of Aesop that call the reader’s attention to kinds of virtue; (2b) the fabulous narrative (narratio fabulosa), which under a cover of fiction contains real truth. His examples of the last (and best) type include stories of the gods by Hesiod and Orpheus,14 and the mystical teachings of the Pythagoreans.15 All is directed to the usefulness of myth for philosophy without any serious examination of the narrative structure of the different types of story. The above may help to explain why the Greeks did not consider myth a category of thought that could be investigated. Although they were very interested in the origin and meaning of myths, they never asked the basic question, “What is myth?” Moderns have asked this question many times, but no answer has appeared yet that is to everyone’s satisfaction. Moderns have also tried to differentiate myth from such categories as religion and literature; such attempts were rare among Greek thinkers. Moderns also ask, “How does myth function in particular societies?”16 —another question that did not occur to the Greeks, except to those who saw myths as instruments of social control. And while some Greeks were aware of religious and cultural similarities and differences between themselves and other peoples, they rarely noted similarities between stories. They might have observed, for instance, the close narrative similarities between the doings of Hercules and the biblical Samson, had they been interested in the stories of their neighbors.17 However, they did question their own myths and they did interpret them. We do not mean to claim that the Greeks were the first people on the planet to question or disbelieve their myths. It is hard to think that the Babylonian astronomers who could plot the course of the planets and divide the circle into 360 degrees believed that humans were created out of the carcass of a monster slain by a god, as claimed in the “Babylonian Creation Story.” It is just as difficult to think that the Egyptian architects, who knew enough geometry to create the enormous pyramids that stand to this day, believed that Isis literally 8 8 introduction gathered the body bits of the dismembered Osiris, put them back together, and restored him to life. There were doubtless always those who disbelieved myths, even those that were part of a people’s most sacred tenets of faith. Yet if these moments of disbelief were ever recorded, the documents have been lost. So much (too much) history is based on the fate of books. We should keep in mind that the Greeks learned much from the surrounding peoples whose civilizations were much older. They adapted the alphabet invented by the Phoenicians. They must surely have learned some geometry from the Egyptians, even if we have only the writings of Pythagoras and Euclid. The same would apply to the Babylonians as a source for Greek astronomy, even though we must depend on Hipparchus and Ptolemy for our knowledge of ancient astronomy. But if they learned skepticism from their neighbors, no document has surfaced to prove it. Given this gap in our knowledge, we must rely on the Greeks to teach us about the earliest questioning of traditional myths, and more importantly, about how they found ways of understanding them so that they accorded with new hypotheses about the cosmos. Because the Greeks experienced a long period of illiteracy after the Mycenaean Age, we know next to nothing about their ways of thinking about myth until the appearance of written versions of Homer and Hesiod in the sixth century b.c.e. This is not to suggest that literature did not exist in oral form in “Dark Age” Greece before writing was rediscovered, probably in the eighth century c.e. Indeed, a great deal of work has been done on the oral composition and oral transmission of literature.18 We even have evidence for oral interpretation of Homer’s poems from Plato’s dialogue Ion.19 Unfortunately, Plato does not allow Ion to speak his interpretations of Homer, so we have no idea what they were like. For all practical purposes, poetry and criticism appeared almost simultaneously in written form. At that point, the criticism and interpretation of literature became a public matter. Critiques were written and shared and became part of the public domain. A writer could relay his thoughts on a poet’s teaching from his home in, say, Ephesus (western Turkey) to a friend in Sicily or southern Italy. A common language, literacy, and navigation made the sharing of ideas a real possibility in the far-flung colonies of the Greeks. But written communication was not simply a private matter between friends. The spread of literacy soon led to the notion of publication: making one’s views public and accepting the consequences. The beginnings of public criticism occurred roughly at the same time as the earliest authoritative texts came to be in a fixed written form. This may be pure coincidence, since the earliest expressions of critical opinion are couched in very general terms and might be based on oral reception. Yet it is interesting that the works of Homer were published in versions commissioned by political authority at about the same time as the earliest attacks on Homer’s veracity and moral values were issued. Pisistratus, the tyrant of Athens, who 9 introduction 9 ruled between 560 and 527 b.c.e., is credited with the role of patron of an “edition,” which was doubtless already far removed from the “original.” Also around the middle of the sixth century or not much later, Xenophanes of Colophon and Pythagoras of Samos, whom we shall meet later in this book, issued their attacks on Homer and Hesiod. Only a short time later Theagenes of Rhegium rose to Homer’s defence by proposing that his works be interpreted allegorically. We know virtually nothing about conditions surrounding freedom of expression in the different parts of Greece in the sixth century. We have no evidence of the “heresy trials,” i.e., the charges of atheism or impiety that were fairly common in Athens in the fifth and fourth centuries b.c.e. However, the fact that a critic of the poets such as Pythagoras left his respective homeland points to the possibility that he incurred public disfavor, if not official censure. The two events, of course, may not have been connected. It is just as likely he was attracted by patronage offered by the rulers of the southern Italian town to which he migrated. We shall probably never know for certain. What is certain is that public criticism of the most authoritative texts of ancient Greece was under way. The initial attacks on the early poets were harsh. However, because the works of Homer and Hesiod had long been known (Homer doubtless in oral form) and were regarded by many as foundational, a poets’ defense league quickly sprouted up. There was simply too much at stake to allow them to be discarded. Hesiod was respected for his attempts at explaining the origins of the cosmos, and Homer’s saga of the Trojan War and its aftermath constituted all that the Greeks had that could tell them about their early history. The poets had to be saved at all costs. The main objective of practically all Greek critics was to determine whether a work or part of a work was true or not. (This was thought of as completely different from determining whether a work of literature was beautiful or not— that was the business of grammarians and rhetoricians.) Interpretation in antiquity took various forms, but its chief aim remained constant: to establish the truth of a text. If a myth or group of myths could not be certified as literally true, that is, if the events they mention could not have happened as described, then could they be true in some other way? The question opened doors for several kinds of speculation, and the solutions given depended on the kinds of study in which critics were engaged (we cannot yet refer to these studies as disciplines). The early cosmologists looked for hidden messages regarding the origins of the universe; philosophers looked for teachings about the divine or about the soul; historians looked for “kernels of truth” regarding the past. Practically all resorted to nonliteral interpretations of the poems. Interpretations also shifted with the times. In the nearly two centuries before Plato, thinkers concentrated on nature (physis). What were things made of? Was there a single primary substance that explained everything, or were 10 10 introduction there several? How did the universe come into being? Was it always there, and will it always be, or did it have a specific origin, and if so, was it made by a god (theos)? While there was much disagreement about the primary stuff of being, there was a general consensus about the origin of the universe. It was always there (because nothing can come from nothing), and it always will be. It was not made by any god, though god or gods could play a role in its governance— at least for some thinkers. I refer to this in later chapters as “the paradigm of physis.” Homer and Hesiod (and any other poetic voice) had to be made to fit into this paradigm. In the fourth century, theism emerged as the dominant theme of philosophy and cosmology. It is unmistakable in Plato’s late work Timaeus, Aristotle’s Metaphysics, and the earliest writings of the Stoic School, which arose around 300 b.c.e.. The gods, or God, were rescued from their servitude to physis. They were now able to create, regulate, and animate the universe. Here we witness a major paradigmatic shift from nature to god, from physis to theos. In one particular, Aristotle was the most revolutionary of all the theists. Unlike Plato and the Stoics, whose theological language vacillated between “god” and “gods,” Aristotle spoke of a single God who set the cosmos in motion. But Plato was the real game changer. Although previous thinkers may have hinted at an immaterial substance (i.e., something that exists that contains no matter), Plato posited an entire world that can be known by the mind alone, and it exists not just in the mind but also in reality. It is eternal and unchanging, standing in contrast to the changing insubstantial world of matter that is always in flux. Similarly, humans are composed of two disparate things: matter, which is the stuff our bodies are made of, and some kind of nonmaterial essence, from which our souls are made. All things material are born, grow, die, and decay. But whatever is made of the stuff of souls is eternal. Our individual souls always were and always will be, even though our bodies perish and decay. While the importance of this idea to the development of Christian theology is obvious, its relevance to the history of interpretation was also great, as we shall see. In this book we begin and end with the methods of the ancient Greeks for interpreting their own myths. The details of these methods and their development will be explored fully in the following chapters. However, if the methods devised had had no other application than to ancient literature, ancient exegesis (a Greek term for “interpretation”) would be of significance today mainly to students of literary theory. What gives the methods much greater importance is that Greek ways of understanding Homer and Hesiod’s myths were adopted first by Jews, then Christians, and applied to the interpretation of the Sacred Scriptures. They were incorporated into books on “How to Read the Bible” by the Jewish philosopher Philo and by Christian thinkers such as Origen and Augustine. The tradition of reading the Bible with an eye to more than one layer of meaning became firmly embedded in the scriptural exegesis 11 introduction 11 embraced by Christians in antiquity and transmitted to the Western Middle Ages, surviving to the Reformation and well beyond. A double benefit resulted from this appropriation. First, Holy Writ was spared the deadening hand of literalism. From the earliest times the Christian fathers realized that there were many passages in scripture that could be taken literally only at the expense of reason. They sought for figurative meanings in these passages and encouraged others to do so. Biblical texts were seen as multilayered, with meaning to be found on several levels. This is not to argue that there were no literalists among ancient and medieval biblical exegetes, or that there was no one who insisted on conserving the letter of the text while allowing other interpretations. But we have to thank Philo and Origen, who learned their exegesis from the pagan Greeks, for preventing Christianity from becoming “a religion of the book” in the oppressive sense of that term. Whatever the source of the biblical literalism that flourishes in parts of America today, its roots are not to be found in the early Christian centuries, or in the Catholic Middle Ages. The continuity of ancient interpretative methods brought a second boon to the world of letters. When the pagan classics came under challenge in some quarters during the Middle Ages, ways of interpreting them figuratively were revived and used in the West for defending the secular books written in Latin. These defenses were only occasionally needed for pagan philosophical works, but were often vital for the poems that preserved the pagan myths—especially myths of an erotic nature. Although many of these interpretations strike us today as naive, we are as much in debt to the commentators as we are to the scribes who copied out the poems. These interpreters played a crucial role in preserving the pagan classics that we have today. In presenting my study of the origins and growth of the public interpretation of myth, I have deliberately avoided a schematic approach. Although I try to describe the kinds of mental operations involved in the different ways of understanding myths, I am conscious of both their ambiguity and their interrelatedness. I am also aware that readers who know very little about classical culture, or are just beginning their studies, require context. Accordingly, the chapters follow a rough chronology as far as possible. I have also included chapters (or sections thereof) on the poems of Homer and Hesiod, ideas of authority and inspiration, changing notions about nature and god, modes of belief and skepticism, the link between poetry and myth, theories about the origin of myths, the interrelationship among modes of interpretation, and the influence of these modes on Jewish and early Christian thought. Out of these various themes I have tried to create a narrative that binds the leitmotiv of interpretation with the themes of Greek literature, religion, and philosophy. My hope is that readers will appreciate the importance of these early public experiments in the interpretation of authoritative texts, and understand how they contributed to the making of the open intellectual climate in which we are fortunate to live. 12 13 1 The Paradigm of the Poets Our subject is Greek myth, but it will be helpful here to begin with some generalizations about how myths are organized into the books that play a vital role in forming their societies. We shall therefore look briefly at the role of such books in other ancient societies to see what they tell us about social foundations. Many ancient societies reserved a special place for their most authoritative texts. These were the books that contained and sanctified, so to speak, the dominant ideas and beliefs of a given society—or at least of its elite. The sum of these ideas and beliefs might be termed “the paradigm”—the set of guidelines into which beliefs and social practices must fit. These books, or “great codes,”1 were written or handed down by lawgivers or sages whose alleged lifespan marked the beginning of the validity of the paradigm. The biblical Moses epitomizes this type of figure. He handed down the Ten Commandments given to him by God. Both Jews and Christians believed that Moses was at the same time the author of the Torah, the first five books of the Jewish Bible, which the Greek Jews and Christians call the Pentateuch. These five books are also known as “the Law” (though the Hebrew word Torah means “teaching”). They contain not only the law codes that regulated so many details of behavior, but also a description of the origin of the cosmos, the human race, and the people marked out as God’s chosen. Most importantly, they establish Yahweh as the one and only god of the Jews. These books also report the earliest history of this special people. No limit—no “sunset law”—is placed on the validity of the paradigm sanctioned by these writings. The paradigm was meant to be accepted forever by the people for whom it was intended. The collection of the five books is thought by scholars to have been made in the reign of King David, ca. 1000–962 b.c.e. But it is treated as timeless. To believers, the Torah was always there and always will be. The Torah is by no means unique in presenting a description of origins, a law code or codes, and the beginnings of a national history. We find a similar group of texts in the older civilization of the Babylonians. Although the books 14 14 the anatomy of my th were never brought together into a collection such as the Torah, Babylonian sages were responsible for the poem known as the Enuma Elish (“When on High”) and the law codes attributed to King Hammurabi (ca. 1951–1913 b.c.e.). Like the Book of Genesis, the first book of the Torah, the Enuma Elish describes the origins of the cosmos, the creation of humans, and the emergence of the great god Marduk, who will be the god of the people forever. The Babylonians also appropriated and translated the even more ancient Sumerian epic called Gilgamesh, which describes the transition of the human condition from a natural to a civilized state, sets the limit of human life, and portrays the fate of the “person” after death. There are glimpses of early national history in the episode of Gilgamesh and his companion Enkidu’s expedition into the land of cedars, where the heroes cut down wood and bring it back to ornament their temples. Well after the Babylonians and Jews had created their foundational literature, the Greeks created theirs in the eighth century b.c.e. Not all of it was immediately set down in writing. Although the Greeks had known literacy at an earlier stage,2 this skill was lost for centuries after the destruction of the Mycenean citadels ca. 1200 b.c.e. It is now thought that the Iliad and the Odyssey, the two great poems attributed to Homer, were composed orally, or else orally with the aid of writing. Nothing is known for certain about the identity of this poet, and a number of scholars today believe that the two epic works named were written by separate poets. Two other important poems, the Theogony (“Origin of the Gods”) and Works and Days, were composed by Hesiod, probably toward the end of the eighth century. This poet identifies himself and provides autobiographical notes in the Works and Days. As Hesiod’s poetry displays fewer of the hallmarks of oral composition, it is likely that he composed by writing. Among them, the four poems cover many of the same topics included in the Torah and the Babylonian material, and modern scholars have detected a number of their influences on the Greek works, particularly with regard to cosmology.3 The Theogony in particular shows Eastern influence, as it begins with the creation of the natural world, treats the creation of women as an afterthought on the part of the gods (compare the creation of Eve in Genesis), portrays the loss of favor with the gods (compare the Garden of Eden story in Genesis), describes a fierce battle between the older and younger generations of gods (compare Marduk’s revolt against Tiamat in the Enuma Elish), and traces the ascent of the great god Zeus, who will rule forever as king of gods and men (compare Marduk’s rise to power in the Enuma Elish). Some of the gaps that occur in Theogony are filled in by Works and Days, notably the creation of mankind as a complete species (implied in the Greek anthrōpōn, “of humans,” line 109) and the theme of a golden age followed by steady decline due to the worsening of human morals (the “Fall of Man” as described in Genesis). 15 the par adigm of the poets 15 For the early history of the Greek peoples, one has to turn to Homer. Compared to Genesis, Homer’s Iliad encloses a much more compressed time period. Genesis offers a sweeping account of history from the creation of the first man and woman down to the flood, followed by the division of mankind into three races through the three sons of Noah. The story then becomes the Jewish story when it introduces the narrative of Abraham and his descendants, their covenant with the one God, and their migration into Egypt. The Iliad, on the other hand, recounts only the events of the last year of the Trojan War, although it introduces much additional material in the form of genealogies and the local origins of the different Greek warriors who took part in the war. The Odyssey treats the (mis-)fortunes of the Greek heroes returning from Troy. The Iliad came to be perceived as the epic of national unity because it portrays the disparate tribes of the Greeks united in a single purpose. In Homer’s day there was no Greek nation—and there was not to be anything like a “national” entity until four centuries later, when Alexander the Great briefly united “Hellenes,” the name for the peoples speaking different Greek dialects. (From Hesiod’s time on, the name “Hellene” came to signify the entire Greek-speaking population.) In Homer’s story, all these independent peoples as well as people from the Aegean Islands united in a single cause to rescue Helen, the beautiful Mycenean princess who had been abducted by Paris, the playboy scion of the king of Troy. The Trojan War (whether fact or legend) was always seen as the true beginning of Greek history. It marked the start of a people’s collective sense of themselves in much the same way as the exodus out of Egypt was the true start of Jewish history, the French Revolution initiated a collective “classless” ideal of Frenchness, or the War of Independence created a sense of American identity from which there was no longer any turning back. All these peoples experienced other wars—some triumphant, others tragic—but none of them could claim the status as foundational. The Greeks acknowledged heroes who lived before the Trojan War. Heracles and Theseus were the greatest of these; indeed, Theseus was even given the role of first admiral of the Athenian navy by later historians (odd as this may seem). But the Trojan War was the watershed; it was the beginning of history. What happened before that time was obscured by haze. And so Homer was made the first Greek historian. But he also came to be perceived as a theologian. 4 Foremost, perhaps, is the fact that Homer attributed the victorious outcome of the Trojan War to the will of Zeus. Zeus was no longer “first among equals,” but the supreme god, as Hesiod also depicted him. Zeus was able to see through and thwart the intrigues of the other gods who sought to undermine his plan to engineer a Greek victory at Troy. His terrible threat aimed at disobedient gods (Il. 8, 13–27) underscores Homer’s position perfectly. They will be hurled into Tartarus, whose depth below the earth is as great as Mount Olympus’s height above 16 16 the anatomy of my th it. The will of Zeus acknowledged no limitation except, perhaps, that of fate. (Homer is a little muddy on this point, because in some passages he shows the gods as subject to fate, but in one famous passage he depicts Zeus as the author of it.5) We also learn much from Homer about the nature of the gods in both the Iliad and the Odyssey. Their most important characteristic is their immortality. This is attributed to the special quality of their blood substitute, which is called ichor, and their special diet, which is composed of nectar for their drink and ambrosia for their food. (The word ambrosia means “immortality.”) They can, however, be injured and suffer pain. The gods also have special powers. They can shift their shape, fly, pass through solid walls, appear to mortals in dreams and visions, move extremely quickly from one spot to another, deflect arrows and spears, and much else. They live a happy life on the peak of Mount Olympus, ever feasting and drinking and making love to their legitimate partners—at least while on the premises. Apart from being immortal and stronger, smarter, and more beautiful than humans, they are like them in all other respects.6 Not only are their bodies those of glorified humans (just look at the ancient statues), but their characters also have human traits, particularly the bad ones. When not at home under the watchful eye of their lawful spouses, they fly about the earth, engaging in romantic liaisons with humans or stirring them up. Both hetero-and homosexual love affairs between gods and mortals are rife, and some female deities have their share of the fun as well as the males. However, a good many of these liaisons are undertaken not just for fun, but also with the intent of creating great heroes. The heroes are the crucial link between gods and mortals. Being part mortal, part god, they complete the chain of being, for the world would be an utterly desolate place without heroes to remind us of our own spark of divinity. There is nothing specifically Greek about this type of interbreeding. It was a feature of Babylonian mythology and noted famously in a passage in Gen. 6:4: “The Nephilim [“giants”] were on the earth in those days—and also afterward—when the sons of God went into the daughters of humans, who bore children to them. These were the heroes that were of old, warriors of renown.” The Jewish narrative is linked to God’s placing a limit on life of 120 years. In the Greek paradigm the supernatural heroes who would correspond to the biblical “warriors of renown” had long died out or else, like Heracles, had been granted immortality. Such heroes will not be seen again. Even the heroic fighters of the Trojan War were utterly human; they belonged to history, not legend, or so it was deeply believed. The gigantic “warriors of renown” of the Bible remind us of the heroes mentioned by Nestor in the Iliad 7; their powers vastly exceeded those of even the bravest and strongest fighters on the Trojan expedition. But they lived and fought before the dawn of history. 17 the par adigm of the poets 17 The Trojan War marked the watershed between myth and history, at least to the Greek mind. On this side of the watershed, time flows in a workaday sort of way, in which everything happens more or less predictably. Events unfold according to the laws of cause and effect. Every being has its peculiar nature, and this does not change except by natural means. People are born, grow old, and die. They can neither be rejuvenated when old nor resurrected once dead. People cannot live under water (therefore, nymphs or mermaids cannot exist), and fish cannot live on land. Animals do not talk. Time itself moves in only one direction and can be measured in a predictable way; it cannot be stopped or reversed. On the other side of the temporal watershed, almost anything can happen. People can live for indefinitely long periods, animals can talk, and gods and humans can communicate with one another directly, as they do in Hesiod’s description of a banquet attended by Zeus and humans (lines 535–41). For Jews and Christians, it was the time when God spoke directly to Adam and Eve (Gen. 3:8ff.). Afterward people had to rely on prophets, oracles, or dream interpreters to learn the mind of the gods. It is true, of course, that Homer depicted direct interactions between gods and a few highly favored mortals, but for the great mass of humanity, including kings and prophets, the gods made their wishes known through dreams and oracles, or appeared in disguise. The Homer of the Iliad shows restraint in his use of miraculous or supernatural motifs. He concentrates chiefly on the events of the war and the interaction among the heroes. This is not to say there are no divine interventions: The nymph Thetis conceals Achilles in a watery place to keep him out of the war; Aphrodite intervenes in battle to save her son Aeneas and suffers a wound for her pains. The gods sometimes guide the spears and arrows of their favorite mortals, but the heroes themselves, powerful and skillful as they may be, wage battle by natural means. Unlike “pre-historic” heroes such as Perseus, they have no magic weapons or armor and possess no flying horses, nor can they fly or make themselves invisible. When they cannot save themselves, they require the aid of the gods. The Odyssey is less restrained in respect of the supernatural, but even there most of the strange happenings are attributable to the gods. In that tale the war is already finished and the heroes are on their way home. This was the perfect opportunity for a poet to concentrate on an individual hero and his adventures at sea. Anything can happen on a voyage, and many strange things do. The hero Odysseus engages in lengthy love affairs with island goddesses. At the end of his dalliance with the goddess Calypso he rejects her offer of immortality for the simple pleasure of returning home to his dear wife. The second liaison is with the witchlike Circe, who transforms his crew into swine, but Odysseus manages to restore them with the magic plant “moly,” which Hermes gave him. In another episode the hero gains access to the shades of the underworld (a feat allowed only to the heroes on the other side 18 18 the anatomy of my th of the temporal threshold, Orpheus, Heracles, and Theseus).8 There he sees and converses with the shades of departed heroes, including Achilles; he also receives detailed advice as to how to handle his homecoming. Odysseus’s journey to the edge of the underworld or Hades (book 11) surely reinforced Homer’s reputation as a theologian, that is, an expert on all things supernatural. The poet’s picture of existence after death is a cheerless one, almost as bleak as that found in Gilgamesh. Hades offers neither rewards for heroism nor punishment for sin. Only the worst of the “pre-historical” offenders against Zeus—Tantalus, Tityus, and Sisyphus—undergo punishment. Minos, the judge of the underworld, is there to assign their fates. The “souls,” or “shades,” enclosed in Hades are a sorry lot who possess only a dim consciousness.9 However, they can be revived temporarily and made to speak by drinking from a pool of sacrificial blood. The effects last only for a short time before the shades revert to their habitual stupor. The main paradigm of the afterlife offered by Homer in book 11 of the Odyssey can be supplemented by his account in book 24 and in Iliad book 8, as well as Hesiod’s description of Tartarus in the Theogony. This is where Zeus imprisoned the enemy Titans in the battle of the gods. Both poets agree that Tartarus is in the deepest part of the earth, and Hesiod adds the information that it lies at the very end of the world and offers no means of exit. Both poets speak of “brazen gates” or doors. The Elysian Fields, which is the abode of the virtuous souls in later Greek and Roman thought, receives a passing mention at Od. 4, 563ff. It has been identified with the “Isles of the Blest,” where virtuous souls enjoy a life of ease and tranquility.10 Homer places Helen and her husband, Menelaus, in that setting. Menelaus gets in, while more famous heroes like Agamemnon, Achilles, and Ajax endure the lot of ordinary mortals in Hades. Menelaus’s good fortune was most likely due to Helen’s divine connections. Homer’s and Hesiod’s works together gave the Greeks not only their paradigms of history and theology, but also their concepts of geography and cosmography. The earth is flat and shaped like a disc. The three known continents—Europe, Asia, and Africa—are like a huge island surrounded by the stream of Ocean.11 The possibly genuine Hesiodic poem Shield of Heracles describes the border of the shield: “And around the rim Ocean was flowing, with a full stream as it seemed, and enclosed all the cunning work of the shield” (lines 314–15). Ocean itself is described as “boundless,” and the earliest poets did not seem concerned with the problem of how the water was prevented from flowing over the edges.12 Colchis (of Argonauts fame) marked the eastern edge of the known world, while Elysium (Homer’s equivalent of Hesiod’s “Isles of the Blest”) marked the western. The entrance to the underworld (Hades) was at the northern limit of the earth, and Odysseus had to pass through Ocean to reach it (Od. 10, 507). In between these places that marked the limits between the known and unknown worlds lay the familiar islands of 19 the par adigm of the poets 19 the Mediterranean and Aegean. The challenge of reconciling the known world with Homer’s mythical isles still exercised the ingenuity of the geographer Strabo in the first century b.c.e. For the origins of the cosmos we must turn primarily to Hesiod’s great Theogony. The title of the work means “Origin of the Gods,” but the poet seeks to explain much else: the earliest state of the cosmos; the origin of natural features such as sun and moon, mountains and rivers; and the creation of women. It might be argued that Hesiod’s cosmological assertions provided a starting point for all further Greek speculation about the universe. The first line of Hesiod’s account of the beginnings of the cosmos (line 116) has been a source of confusion. The poet tells us that the very first thing that came into being was Chaos. For moderns, “chaos” means a “jumble” or “confusion,” or generally, “a state of disorder.” Thus we might be inclined to think that the earliest state of the cosmos consisted of confused objects or matter that required some extraneous force to bring order to them. This assumption is almost certainly wrong. The basic meaning of the Greek word chaos is a “void,” or “gap.” Thus, Hesiod’s chaos is the space in which objects can move. The next two things “to happen” were earth and erŌs (sexual desire). These events were followed by the genesis out of the void of darkness and night. Counterintuitively, it seems, the aether (light) and day were generated from the union of darkness and night. Earth unaided produced Sky to “cover her” on all sides; she also produced the mountains and seas on her own. After this she generated things through union with Sky, including great Ocean itself. We need not pursue the details of creation further, but one more episode of the story will be important for what follows in this book. Ouranos (sky) and Gaia (earth) produced a number of children, including the Titans and various monsters. But Ouranos became jealous of his children and crammed them into the bowels of Gaia, causing her great distress. She conspired with her son, the Titan Kronos, to liberate her and the children by cutting off the testicles of Ouranos with a steel sickle at the very moment when Ouranos was making love to Gaia. The plot was successful, and the children were liberated. A new goddess, Aphrodite, was created from the foam issuing from Ouranos’s testicles, and the avenging Furies were created from their blood. Hesiod at this point abandons his bloody tale to tell us about Aphrodite and her wonderful powers. On the cosmological level, however, earth and sky are once again separated, and there is space between them in which other things can move. Here we find a parallel with the cosmology of Gen. 1:7, which describes the separation of the waters above the vault of heaven from the waters below. What distinguishes the Theogony from Genesis, however, is its “evolutionist” approach to origins. The first things simply “come into being”—they are generated, but there is no mention of a generator or creator. From these first beings, others are generated over time. In a line widely regarded as spurious (118), Chaos, Gaia, and Eros are described as immortal and as inhabitants of 20 20 the anatomy of my th Olympus, but there is nothing very godlike about them. Instead, they appear to be largely unconscious beings (rather like the watery Apsu and Tiamat in the Enuma Elish). It is in the next generation—the generation of the Titans—that a sense of plan and purpose can be glimpsed. They have a hint of divinity about them, but the male Titans, at any rate, are mostly large and brutish, with little regard for anything beyond their own needs. The Olympian gods—the gods we recognize from Homer—do not come into existence until the third generation. They mark the end of evolution. The offspring they generate are like themselves. With the ascent of Zeus to supreme rulership, the notions of law (Themis) and justice (Dikē) enter the world. The combination of unmatchable physical power coupled with stunning intellectual gifts created a divine being beyond which it was not possible to conceive a greater. One of the most arresting ideas in Richard Dawkins’s The God Delusion is that if God exists, he, she, or it must come at the end of the evolutionary process.13 To theists and atheists alike, such a thought appears to be counterintuitive. Either God was there at the start of the world, or doesn’t exist at all—in which case the origin of the world requires a different explanation. But each of these alternatives would have been abhorrent to Hesiod. For him, a world without gods was unthinkable. But gods had to represent the apex of being (and thus the epitome of physical power and rationality), and therefore come at the end of the evolutionary process. However, as they were generated naturally (that is, from the Titans in the ordinary way), they belonged to nature. As such, they could not have created the world—they were not even around when the world happened. This evolutionist pattern was to set the paradigm for the early Greek physical philosophers from the late seventh to the end of the fifth century, as we shall see in c­ hapter 3. At odds with Hesiod’s account of the origin of the world and the gods is his depiction of the beginnings of men and women. Like the authors of Genesis, who give two accounts of the creation of humans, the first being their creation as a complete species (Gen. 1:27), the second describing separate creations of male and female (Gen. 2:7, 20–24), Hesiod does the same. In Works and Days (lines 109ff.) Hesiod describes the creation of the complete species by the Olympian gods at the time when Kronos was reigning in heaven. This was a golden race and it lived in a kind of paradise where all was provided. Humans lived free from every toil and care, always in a state of merriment—like the gods themselves. Their strength never failed them, and when they died (for they were created mortal), “it was as though they were overcome with sleep” (line 116). Importantly, they were “loved by the blessed gods” (line 119). They were followed by four more generations, each worse than the last except for the fourth generation, which raised up the heroes who fought at Troy. An important shift came with the third generation. By then Zeus was king of heaven, so he took on the creative task himself, putting an end to the second generation and creating the next three by himself. Unlike the first two 21 the par adigm of the poets 21 generations under Kronos, which were peaceable but indolent, the generations made by Zeus were all addicted to war and violence, though the fourth generation is described as noble because it produced the Greek heroes. In the Theogony Hesiod presents an entirely different story. Males already existed without any explanation of how they came to be.14 Because the Titan Prometheus stole fire from Zeus and gave it to men, Zeus created a beautiful young woman as “the first of the race of women and female kind: of her is the deadly race and tribe of women living amongst mortal men [andrasi, ‘males’] to their great trouble.”15 The story of the first female’s creation is told in greater detail in Works and Days, where she is given the name Pandora, “the recipient of every gift” (lines 80–81). This is followed by the well-known fable of Pandora’s box, in which evils enter the world through the curiosity of a female. It is tempting to dwell on the details of Hesiod’s account of the origin of humans and their fall from favor and that of Genesis. But what is important for our narrative is that Hesiod departed from his evolutionist explanation of origins and change and introduced creationism. In Works and Days the gods or Zeus alone made each new race, then put it away. (The last generation, the tribe of iron, will also perish, according to Hesiod’s prophesy.) In both the Theogony and Works and Days it was Zeus who ordered the creation of woman, who was manufactured, so to speak, by Hephaestus with the help of Athena. Why were humans not a part of the evolutionary process? Why were they not simply born out of the earth like some other beings, or else procreated in the usual way by the gods? An attempt at that explanation is given in a separate myth of the “Sown Men,” who sprang up from dragon’s teeth planted in the earth; but as soon as they appeared they set to fighting and killed one another. Like trees planted outside their usual environment, they didn’t take root. Presumably, humans cannot be generated in the usual natural ways, because they are not fully part of nature. The problem for Hesiod was that the Olympian gods were the last generation to arise through generation. When the gods had intercourse with each other, they could produce only other gods— even if they sometimes produced them in unorthodox ways, as Zeus did when he generated Athena from his head. The two Hesiodic myths of the creation of humans constitute an etiology of human apartheid. Humans are neither gods nor part of nature. Their weakness and mortality separate them from the first, their exceptional reasoning power from the second. Humans are the only things that the gods created, as opposed to generated. Pandora in the version given in Works and Days was made by the craftsman Hephaestus out of earth and water, just as Adam, the first man, was fashioned out of moistened earth by God in Gen. 2:6–7. Thus humans are made of earth and return to earth,16 but they are not generated autonomously from earth. Hesiod had to find a different explanation for the existence of humans, and somehow knew a myth akin to the creation of humans account in Genesis that provided it. 22 22 the anatomy of my th The fable of the races named after metals (gold, silver, bronze, iron) works on a number of levels. Its most obvious point is that humans grow worse over time as they become less religious and less dependent on the gods. Violence is the theme of the generations three through five made by Zeus. The third generation self-destructs—much as the generation of “sown men” of the Cadmus myth (though in that story at least there are survivors). The fifth generation, the age of iron, in which Hesiod lives, is by far the worst. An obvious message is that human depravity is caused by impiety and neglect of the gods. Another reading of the story is that humans are a failed experiment, and one can only wonder why the gods keep on trying to make it work. We might think of the gods as scientists in a lab, ever tweaking the last formula to get it right. But nothing works. Zeus takes over the lab when Kronos is deposed, and things only get worse from there. Zeus tries planting human seed in the ground, grafted to ash trees (meilan),17 but that ends up in the bronze generation that self-destructs (a comparison with the “sown men” myth is unavoidable). The fourth experiment goes well, but is short lived. The fifth brings fresh disaster. The moral to the story is that humans are not self-sustaining (being neither divine nor part of nature), so they must be continually recreated. The idea that the human race cannot sustain itself and requires repeated restarts is not unique to the Greeks; it is also biblical. Before Yahweh decided to destroy the race with a flood on account of the evil in them, he attempted a couple of refinements. He allowed his sons to make a better race by mating with the daughters of men. The sons, noting that the daughters of men were fair, were not reluctant to do the Lord’s bidding. The daughters of men bore children to them, who became mighty, “men of renown” (Gen. 6:1–4). This should have been viewed as a successful experiment, much as the heroes of the fourth generation in the Hesiodic myth were successful. Yahweh, however, did not see it that way, but saw only persistent evil. He next decided to limit human life to 120 years. This short-lived experiment did not work, either, so a more drastic solution was needed. At that point Yahweh conceived his plan for the cataclysm that would wipe out the human race. However, it is uncharacteristic for a god to abandon his handiwork altogether, so he included in his scheme a plan to save the virtuous Noah and his family. But after the flood, corruption followed almost immediately. Noah himself was a bit of a letdown, succumbing to drunkenness and engaging in some kind of inappropriate act with his son Ham (Gen. 9:21–22). In a later story God wiped out the cities of Sodom and Gemorrah with fire, in the end saving only Lot and his daughters. The daughters resourcefully restarted the race by committing incest with their father. There is, however, a third way of reading the Hesiodic fable. True, humans cannot evolve, because they are not a sustainable species. However, not all knowledge vanishes with the disappearance of each generation. With his mention of bronze armor and implements, Hesiod has introduced the concept of 23 the par adigm of the poets 23 homo faber (“man the craftsman”). Humans have emerged from their dependence on the gods and have undertaken to do things for themselves. In the course of this development, they make weapons that increase human efficiency in hunting and warfare. This, in turn, encourages greater violence. Men become morally worse, but at the same time, smarter and more resourceful. By acknowledging that men of the bronze age did not know “black iron,” Hesiod demonstrates his awareness of advances in technology brought about by a fundamental change in the material used for manufacturing things. He was probably the first writer to use the terms “bronze age” and “iron age” in the sense they are used by archaeologists and anthropologists today. In sum, the grim picture of a steady decline in morals that appears to be the main point of the fable of the metals is offset by the liberation of humans from their dependence on the gods, advances in the use of reason, and technological progress. The above account of mankind’s liberation from dependence on the gods is retold in another myth: the tale of Prometheus and the meeting of gods and men at Mecone (Theog., lines 534ff.). Mortals and gods had gathered for a banquet to settle a dispute, a clear indication of a time when humans and deities could converse directly with each other. The cunning Titan Prometheus divided the portions of the barbecued ox so that humans received the choicest pieces, while the gods were given the bones covered in fat to disguise them. The result was predictable. Zeus was furious and refused to share his fire with mortals so that they could cook and do other things for themselves. Prometheus, not to be thwarted, stole fire from Zeus, concealing it in a fennel stock, and gave it to the mortal men. Zeus avenged himself on humans by creating Pandora. But there was another important result glossed over in silence. Mortals lost their direct contact with gods and had to reach them through prayer and sacrifice. The age of innocence (and helplessness) came to an end with the acquisition of the arts that can be practiced by using fire. Religion itself, invented to compensate for loss of contact to the gods, needed fire for burning the bones of animals—a reminder of the treachery committed at Mecone (Theog., lines 556–7). We have seen that “creationism” was introduced to solve a specific problem that the overall model was unable to solve. Evolution cannot be invoked to explain humans, because humans are incapable of evolving. They cannot evolve, because they are self-destructive. The gods, on the other hand, have reached the end of the evolutionary process. Zeus thwarted a plot to succeed him by swallowing his wife Metis (Counsel) who was pregnant with a potential usurper, and in the would-be successor’s stead, Zeus produced Athena from his head. The succession of usurpations that began with Kronos’s castration of his father Ouranos and Zeus’s imprisoning Kronos in Tartarus has come to an end. The attempted revolt of the Titan generation in the person of Prometheus was also swiftly and harshly dealt with. A thoroughly chastened 24 24 the anatomy of my th Kronos, released on bail from Tartarus, could be trusted to rule benignly over the Isles of the Blest. Zeus can now reign unopposed forever. The evolution of the gods has reached its end. Whereas the vast bulk of the Torah is devoted to codifying legal and ethical matters (in comparison to the number of words given over to history or cosmology), there is much less in the way of a systematic treatment of these central issues in the early Greek material. The making and recording of law codes occurred relatively late in the history of the Greeks. The only text offering ample discussion of ethical issues is Hesiod’s Works and Days (lines 293–382 and 695–763). These passages on good conduct are not set out as laws with attached penalties, but rather as a series of admonitions with an eye to consequences. Originally delivered as stern advice to Hesiod’s lazy brother, Perses, the moral portions of the poem may remind some of Benjamin Franklin’s proverbs and advice, such as “Early to bed and early to rise make a man healthy, wealthy, and wise,” or the clever Italian saying, “Bacco, tobacco, e venere riducono l’uomo in cenere” (“Booze, tobacco, and sex turn fellows into wrecks”). Hesiod loathed idleness above all other vices. But he also railed against base gain and stinginess (those who love to take but never give). Fear of Zeus should prevent anyone from violently acquiring another’s property, lying with his own brother’s wife, or abusing his aged parents. Hesiod also recommends regular sacrifice and propitiation of “the deathless gods.” The poet offers clearly worded advice on the subject of women: “Nothing is better than a good wife, and again, nothing worse than a bad one.” He also advises men to stay away from “flaunting women”— they are just “after your barn.” By the end of the eighth century b.c.e., the Greek-speaking world possessed a somewhat loosely knit system of teachings about the world and the gods and, perhaps, the beginnings of a code of conduct. The world was ruled by the great god Zeus, to whom all the other gods as well as men were subject; his will reigned supreme. However, this great God did not create the world. The careful reader of Hesiod will note that Zeus was the child of the Titans Kronos and Rhea, and so belonged to the third generation of gods. He is immortal, but not eternal, as he had a defined beginning. Moreover, unlike Yahweh, who was there “in the beginning” when he created heaven and earth, none of the gods of the Greek pantheon had anything to do with the creation of the universe. It was already fully formed when they were born. An outstanding difference between Zeus and Yahweh is that Zeus, who is committed to upholding law and justice (dikē), is not himself the author of the law, or at least not directly. Rather, this function belonged to the older goddess Themis (“law,” “custom”), the child of Gaia and Ouranos, and thus Zeus’s aunt. Zeus took this same aunt to be his second wife, and she produced Good Order, Justice, and Peace. A similar set of ambiguities affects the moral world and the role of the gods in rewarding or punishing wrongdoing. In the absence of a defined legal 25 the par adigm of the poets 25 or ethical code in the works of Homer and Hesiod, most offences against the gods fall into the category of hubris, that is, a personal insult against a particular divinity. Accordingly, Prometheus is punished for cheating Zeus out of the best portions of sacrificial meat and for stealing fire (Zeus’s personal property). Odysseus is hounded by Poseidon because of the blinding of Polyphemus, Poseidon’s son; furthermore, the hero’s crew had stolen and eaten the cattle belonging to Helios (the sun), Poseidon’s close friend. Apollo sends a plague upon the camps of the Greek forces assembled before Troy, because King Agamemnon, the leader of the expedition, had dishonored the god by refusing to surrender a concubine, who happened to be the daughter of Apollo’s priest. It is true that Hesiod speaks of fearing Zeus, who will be angry with those who commit adultery or wrongfully seize others’ property, but Zeus himself is not credited with handing down a code of ethics or law. The notion of an afterlife in which good people are rewarded and the wicked punished was not yet developed, although one gets glimpses of it. In the Odyssey the miscreants Tityus, Tantalus, and Sisyphus are sentenced to everlasting punishments in Hades for their offenses against Zeus (Od. 11, 604–29). However, everyday robbers of widows and orphans, or common murderers, are not singled out for punishment in the afterlife. Similarly, in the Theogony the Titans are consigned to Tartarus forever because they warred against Zeus; Tantalus and others are punished in Hades for their personal affronts on Zeus. Written evidence for a belief in a judgment followed by reward and punishment emerges in the fifth century, when we find it in Pindar’s “Second Olympian Ode,” although it is not impossible that the belief was imported into Greece much earlier. A defining characteristic of Greek and, later, Roman religion was that it did not require any particular beliefs about the gods, or set out a code of ethics.18 Religion could be either a social or an individual matter. It had to do with worshipping the various “national” gods either in a civic ceremony— often taking the form of public sacrifice—or privately in one’s home. Whatever the case, one sacrificed or paid honor to the gods in order to receive favors from them, or to avert disaster. A religious act was basically viewed as a contract: worshippers sacrifice and the god pays up, or else worshippers repay the god who has done them a favor or saved them from some calamity. The individual worshipper was under no obligation to accept any tenets of belief about the gods they cultivated, or even to honor them through good behavior. This is not to say that a social code of behavior did not exist, or that people felt free to do exactly as they chose. The Homeric works set forth a social code based on status. The gods were at the top of the hierarchy and were to be honored at all times (certainly never insulted or challenged). The kings came next, followed by the nobles. Below these were ordinary people— tradesmen and merchants, for instance, followed by tenant farmers and slaves. Wives were subject to their husbands in all matters, and children 26 26 the anatomy of my th subject to their fathers. Virtues and vices were represented as behaviors dictated by one’s station. Hubris, or arrogance toward one’s superiors, was the supreme crime, and was swiftly avenged. A salient example occurs in Il. 2, 212ff, when a foot soldier named Thersites (who is described as ugly) speaks up in the assembly against King Agamemnon, and is roundly beaten by Odysseus for his insolence. The “code” also set great store on hospitality. Zeus himself guaranteed the safety of travelers, and enforced the rules regarding their proper treatment. Zeus was also known as the “protector of oaths.” Such were the interlocking teachings inherited by the panhellenic world at the turn of the seventh century b.c.e. These systems were promulgated by a group of highly authoritative texts. The texts themselves were composed by poets using the language of myth. The language of myth is the language of imagination and the improbable. It tells of the things that cannot happen in the ordinary world, and of beings whose very existence is questionable. Yet these texts and the myths they contained were buttressed by great authority. We shall now look at the factors that conferred that authority on them. 27 2 What Makes a Work Authoritative? The four Greek poems discussed in ­chapter 1 were widely regarded as didactic works. They were meant for the instruction of everyone. This should be obvious in the case of Hesiod’s Theogony, a poem about the origins of gods, the world, and the things in it. His other poem, Works and Days, is a practical manual on agriculture and also a primer of good conduct: it teaches a mixture of moral principle and the kinds of shrewd behavior needed to be successful in an unforgiving world. But it also contains a more detailed version of the creation of woman than the one given in the Theogony and follows it with the fable of Pandora’s Box. It contains as well the very important “allegory of the metals,” which employs the metals gold, silver, bronze, and iron to symbolize stages of human devolution, or evolution—depending on one’s point of view. The fable might be represented as a kind of graph, where lines going in different directions, one representing human morality heading downward, the other representing technological progress moving upward intersect, let us say, at the non-metallic heroic age. Homer’s two poems are less obviously didactic. Both are narratives that have been famous through the ages for their entertainment value. But they, too, have a great deal to teach about right conduct, and the examples they afford make up the moral code as it was known. The Iliad and the Odyssey together provide the descriptions of the physical and moral character of the gods that were familiar to all Greeks. As importantly, the Iliad stands as the prime textbook of Greek history. The record shows that Greeks took Homer to be their teacher—whether for good or for ill. The regard for Homer as the teacher of the Greeks begins in the sixth century b.c.e. A fragment of Xenophanes of Colophon records, “… since from the beginning all have learned according to Homer.”1 A factor that added considerable weight to the reputation of Homer was its transference to written form. It can be argued that literacy in itself is not essential to provide authority for a work. Nonliterate societies preserved their important works for centuries, and these works served as the lawgivers and models 28 28 the anatomy of my th of conduct to their respective people. But this model can work only on a small scale, where there is a cohesive people circumscribed by a small geographical area. However, between the eighth and the sixth century b.c.e. Greek-speaking peoples had settled in areas as far apart as the Black Sea (present-day Ukraine) and southern France (Marseilles), with many of the most important settlements located in Sicily and Italy. Until Alexander there was no great king or ruler to unite them into a single “state” or empire, yet these far-flung peoples participated in a common civilization. They not only spoke a common language (allowing for dialects) but also worshipped the same gods. The remains of buildings and sites still extant and others being excavated reveal that they built similar buildings and organized their cities in a similar way wherever they went. Most importantly, the Greeks took their books with them when they migrated to new homes. The Greek alphabet was surely in existence in the first half of the eighth century. It is now believed by some to be a century older.2 This alphabet was not derived from the syllabary script of Mycenean times,3 but was the kind of alphabet with which we are familiar, that is, in which one letter (theoretically) represents one sound. It was adapted from the Phoenician alphabet and modified so that vowels also had their own distinct symbols. An alphabet has a clear advantage over syllabaries (in which each syllable has its own symbol) and logographs (in which things and ideas are represented by pictures and symbols, and there is no relation between symbol and sound). Logographic systems often involve hundreds of symbols that must be committed to memory, thereby limiting the number of users to a relatively small few. Syllabaries were more efficient, but even they involved a relatively large number of symbols. By contrast, an alphabet of twenty-t wo to twenty-six symbols can be much more easily memorized and applied. Ease of learning “democratizes” the reading process by making it accessible to a much larger number of people than, in particular, a logographic system would permit. In countries such as Egypt and China that used or still use a logographic system, knowledge of writing was confined to experts (scribes, Mandarins), who exercised a monopoly on literacy and were usually under ecclesiastical or state control. 4 Despite a good deal of uncertainty about the use of papyrus rolls in the seventh and most of the sixth centuries, these objects are depicted on Greek vases around 500 b.c.e., and it is reasonable to assume that they were in use before then. In any case, the Greeks also knew the use of writing on leather (parchment) and wood as well as on stone and ceramic.5 Athens had a written law code in the 620s, and the use of writing by mercenaries is documented in the year 593–592 b.c.e.6 Evidence for early Greek literacy is also distributed widely; it is found in Rhodes, Thera, Crete, Naxos, Athens, Aegina, and Corinth, and as far away as Cumae on the west coast of Italy.7 Literacy was thus a unifying factor in the widespread world of the Greeks. It not only stabilized 29 what makes a work authoritative? 29 communication across a large geographical area, but it also made possible the sharing of ideas and the creation of a common literary culture.8 As noted in the Introduction, a fixed written text of Homer’s works was commissioned around the middle of the sixth century b.c.e. We learn from the Roman writer Cicero (De oratore 3.137) that the tyrant Pisistratus of Athens “arranged the books of Homer as we now have them, when they were previously confused.” Cicero’s comment implies that written copies of Homer’s poems were already in circulation, and a further claim that Pisistratus inserted new lines implies tampering with a written version or versions. Whatever happened exactly, it is clear that the works of Homer had become so authoritative that a ruler felt it important to insure them against further corruption. In other words, there must be one version of Homer that all the rhapsodes (reciters) follow and readers use. It was doubtless the Pisistratan text that was performed every four years at the Panathenaia. However, a late tradition records that the recitation of Homer at that festival was instituted even earlier by Solon (ca. 600), the famous Athenian lawgiver who required the rhapsodes to pick up the recitation wherever the last person left off.9 Whatever the case, and whatever the political reasons for associating the reciting of Homer with a festival honoring Athens’ guardian goddess, the desire of this “upstart” city to take ownership of the poems surely points to the authority they already enjoyed. For it was only Homer who could be recited. This was not the last time a political figure was to be involved in publishing an authoritative version of an authoritative work. The Greek Egyptian King Ptolemy II Philadelphus (285–247 b.c.e.) is said to have commissioned a translation into Greek of the Jewish Bible (Old Testament). According to the legend, it was carried out by seventy-t wo Jewish scholars (six were chosen from each of the twelve tribes) working for seventy-t wo days in isolation. When the time came to compare their translations, it was found that they agreed with each other down to the last jot and tittle. The Septuagint—so called because of the number of scholars and days—was regarded as perfect in every respect. It could no longer be changed in any way.10 More genuinely historical examples of the same theme can be found in Charlemagne’s request to Alcuin to establish a pure text of the Vulgate Bible,11 and the role played by King James I of England in commissioning and approving a translation of the entire Bible to be used by all members of the English Church.12 The great advantage of a text that is literally set in stone is that it anticipates and wards off potential arguments over what an author actually said. The example par excellence is the stone inscription entitled Res gestae divi Augusti, which enumerates in the first person the achievements and honors accorded to the Emperor Augustus.13 An authorized version of a work written on soft material attempts to do the same thing, but of course it is subject to forgery once it has been copied. (This is a problem that has plagued both classical and biblical studies down to the advent of printing.) 30 30 the anatomy of my th But we can imagine that before the edition commissioned by Pisistratus, there were copies of Homer’s poems made from divergent oral recitations. Squabbles doubtless arose, once the genie of critical interpretation got out of the jar, over what Homer had actually said. An authorized version of Homer’s works had the effect of enabling Homer’s critics to “sing from the same hymn book.” To be sure, criticism of certain myths in the poems could have arisen simply from hearing them recited, and the remarks of the earliest Homer critics are very general. However, there is evidence that Theagenes of Rhegium read a text of Homer around 525 b.c.e.14 Scattered fragments tell us about his activity. One informs us that he was the first to write about Homer’s family (or race) and the time when he flourished. Another tells us that the newer sort of grammar, distinguished from the older that dealt with the rudiments, began with Theagenes, who was concerned with the niceties of style (hellenismos). A third, which we shall deal with more fully in a subsequent chapter, alleges that Theagenes interpreted Homer allegorically.15 One concludes from this that Theagenes was an early grammarian who practiced the close reading of texts in order to make judgments about style. He also wrote on Homer’s life. It seems reasonable to assume that Theagenes was working from a written text rather than on relying on his memory of recitations by rhapsodes. Moving from a set written text of Homer to a written analysis of his works exemplifies perfectly the theory of Walter Ong regarding the origin of study: All thought, including that in primary oral cultures, is to some degree analytic: it breaks materials into various components. But abstractly sequential, classificatory, explanatory examination of phenomena or of stated truths is impossible without writing and reading. Human beings in primary oral cultures, those untouched by writing in any form, learn a great deal and possess great wisdom, but they do not “study.”16 Homer’s and Hesiod’s poems are authoritative because they are the oldest works known to the Greeks that were written down—even if they may have been composed orally.17 The names of older poets, however, are recorded. For example, Musaeus and Orpheus and a few others were believed to have existed before Homer and Hesiod.18 Orpheus, in particular, was famous because of the legends attached to him. The son of Apollo and a Muse, and his power of song was so great that it even overcame the Sirens. He is the chief protagonist in the tragic tale of Orpheus and Eurydice. It is said that he was torn apart by Thracian women, but after his death his head continued to sing. Fragments of a theogony attributed to Orpheus have been discovered, but these have been shown to be a forgery of the fifth century b.c.e. 31 what makes a work authoritative? 31 or later. However, as these poets (and the works attributed to them) were attached to particular cults, they never achieved the universality—and thus not the authority—of Homer and Hesiod, whose study required no religious initiation. Homer and Hesiod recited the beginnings. Hesiod sang of the origins of the gods and the first things, while Homer recorded the earliest history. Other ancient legends were known—especially stories about Heracles—but no saga was so deeply Greek as the tales of the Trojan War and the homecomings of its heroes. As noted, for the Greeks the events of the Trojan War were the beginnings of Greek history, and no other extant account provided so much detail about the names and pedigrees of the great heroes. The expedition against Troy is a foundation legend of the Greek people in the same way that the Exodus from Egypt was the foundation story of the Israelites. These analogous accounts record how scattered peoples were brought together under great leaders and a sense of nationhood was formed. The Achaeans came together to liberate a kidnapped princess; the Jewish tribes coalesced to liberate themselves. Of course, the analogy cannot be pushed too far. The Greeks remained politically and religiously divided, while the Hebrews, at least according to the biblical account, became a single nation under a single God. However, it is worth noting that Homer and Hesiod both promote the idea that Zeus is, in every way, the greatest of gods and men, and thus the greatest god for all Greeks. Despite the poets’ attachment to the cult of Zeus and the promotion of Zeus as a “national god,” it is crucial to note that none of the writings of Homer and Hesiod received religious sanction—at least as far as we know. All of their works dealt with the gods and promoted their worship, but they had no priestly authority. We have seen that the recitation of Homer’s poems enjoyed a central role in the festival of the Panathenaia. It is possible that the so-called Homeric Hymns, written later, were used at religious festivals, though their metrical form did not lend itself to choral singing.19 But the foundational books by Homer and Hesiod, for all that they taught about the gods, were not used as religious books. Most importantly, their teachings about the gods were not regarded as articles of faith.20 Were the foundational poems divinely inspired? Inspiration of writers is a complicated topic, and it is not always easy to translate an ancient claim to inspiration into modern understanding. Inspiration, or at least the wish to be inspired, was commonly expressed in ancient Greece by a direct invocation of the poet’s Muse in the opening lines of a poem. Homer’s allusions to his Muse appear to be conventional; they occur in the form of simple requests to the Muse to “sing” (Iliad) or “relate” (Odyssey). Thus, they strike us today as little more than poetic devices. However, Homer was not content to invoke his Muse only at the beginning of his poems. In the middle of book 2 of the Iliad the poet calls upon his Muse again, this time to give the names 32 32 the anatomy of my th of the chiefs of the Danaans, the Greek forces assembled at Aulis on their way to Troy: Tell me now, you Muses who have your homes on Olympus. For you, who are goddesses, are there, and you know all things, And we have heard only the rumour of it and know nothing. Who then of those were the chief men and the lords of the Danaans?21 Homer complains that if he had ten tongues and mouths, an unbreakable voice, and a heart of bronze, he could not accurately relate the catalogue of leaders, unless the Muses recounted to him “all those who came beneath Ilion” (Il. 2, 492). For Homer, at least, this passage shows that the Muses not only confer the gift of beautiful song but are also guarantors of the truth. They, after all, live on Olympus, and know everything that is going on. They have true knowledge, not just opinion (kleos). Hesiod’s more nuanced description of inspiration seems to be at odds with Homer’s. The opening of Theogony purports to describe how the Muses taught beautiful song to the poet as he was tending his sheep below sacred Helicon (the mountain that is said to be the home of the Muses). Hesiod says that the Muses breathed into him “a divine voice” so that he could celebrate the things that will happen and things that have happened before. This appears to mean that the poet possesses a prophetic power that can access both the future and the past. Present events are presumably omitted from the list because they do not need a special gift, but future and past are equally inaccessible to the common human experience. The Muses who confer this power are divine; they are daughters of Zeus himself. But does this mean that poets are nothing more than mouthpieces for divine utterances? Hesiod makes no claim to recite words that are breathed into him by the goddesses. Rather, it is a divine voice that is instilled in him; the poet is to use it “to sing of the race of the blessed gods that are eternally” (lines 33–34). The Muses thus provide the poet with his subject matter and the talent to do it justice. The words remain the poet’s own. Even so, we are left with some doubts about the subject matter itself. Hesiod punctuates his claim to divine inspiration with a question mark by making his Muses say, “We know how to speak many false things as though they were true; but we know, when we shall, to utter true things” (lines 26–27). The ambiguity in these lines was later exploited by the critics of poetry. In the case of Hesiod, a poet’s claim to be inspired by a Muse added little to the authority of his work, at least in respect of its truthfulness. The Muses’ job was to make poems more beautiful. Is it possible to explain these apparently divergent views of inspiration? I suggest that the differences are owed to subject matter. Homer is dealing primarily with the lives of men—indeed, particular men, the Danaans (Greeks) who fought bravely at Troy. These men deserved to be remembered. People 33 what makes a work authoritative? 33 alive in his day thought of them as their ancestors; they felt a strong connection. Without the services of a poet strictly guided by Memory, all knowledge of the heroes’ deeds would be lost forever. Some parts of Homer’s Iliad are therefore commemorative,22 and proper commemoration demands complete accuracy. Just as today an obituary writer is not content to pen generalities about his subject’s life, but inquires into the particulars and does his best to verify them, so Homer trusted the daughters of Memory to recount the names of each captain, the places where his fighters came from, and the exact number of ships he brought to the campaign. Because we are led to believe that the Muses in these cases complied with the poet’s request, none of the information could be subject to doubt. Hesiod’s Theogony is all about gods—gods in every form imaginable. As we noted, humans are an afterthought in this epic. They are unnamed, and their presence unaccounted for. They are not commemorated. The point here is that commemoration applies only to mortals; gods cannot be commemorated, because they do not die. Moreover, one cannot have certain knowledge of divine beings; one must be content with kleos (“rumor,” in this context). That is why a poet cannot be certain when the Muses are willing “to utter true things.” He can claim only to have received a beautiful voice. Several centuries after Hesiod, the Athenian philosopher Plato took a different tack on the topic of inspiration, with devastating results: Thus the Muse herself makes people possessed, and from these possessed persons there hangs a chain of others, possessed with the same enthusiasm. All good epic poets produce all their beautiful poems not by art but because they are inspired and possessed. So too with good lyric poets: just as the Corybantic dancers perform when they are not in their right mind, so the lyric poets compose these beautiful songs when they are not in their right mind; once involved in harmony and rhythm, they are in a state of possession and it is then … that the lyric poets have the experience they describe to us … Now this is perfectly true: a poet is a light, winged, holy creature, and cannot compose until he is out of his mind, and his reason is no longer in him.23 Hesiod and Plato agreed that Muses are needed for writing beautifully, but neither believed that they were much help for the truth. Hesiod saw the poet as potentially susceptible to the Muses’ lies (not knowing whether the Muses were lying or not), whereas Plato viewed the poet as simply out of his mind. Plato’s pupil Aristotle contradicted his master’s view on the poet’s state of mind: “Poetry is the work of a genius rather than that of a madman.”24 However, as we shall see, Aristotle also held a different view from his master’s about the kind of truth poetry teaches. 34 34 the anatomy of my th All of this is a far cry from the Jewish and Christian teaching that sees scripture as a revelation from God. In the case of the Bible, it is God who initiates the revelation. The human search for answers to questions does not play a role. Revelation is essential to God’s plan for the conduct of his creation. It involves covenants, laws, and—in the Christian view—God’s plan for human salvation. In the case of direct revelation, God treats the human recorder as a typist responding to a dictaphone: God’s chosen secretaries have no other task than to record the exact words of God in their books and transmit them to the people. In the case of indirect revelation, God or his agent (an angel?) allows his recorders to exercise their creative talents, but guides their minds and hands, and guarantees the truthfulness of the results. Because God is all good, he cannot lie. The inference from this is that all of scripture must be true. Scripture is also a holy thing because it comes from God. The doctrine of divine inspiration thus greatly enhances the authority of scripture. It provides firewall protection for God’s word. The wall, though damaged, persists to this day. Even without the claim to represent God’s own words, and without priestly sanction, the writings of Homer and Hesiod exercised great authority. They formed the basis of education throughout the Hellenic world, and they were pored over by early philosophers and historians as diligently as the Torah was by rabbinical students. Indeed, the vast majority of surviving commentaries and collections of scholia are directed to the Iliad and the Odyssey. Serious philosophers undertook to write commentaries on them and interpret them by their own lights. The answers lie in the poems themselves, in their content, and in their style. Their content speaks for itself. These early poems laid claim to the secrets of the universe, the nature of the gods, and the beginnings of the Greeks. Like Genesis, the two poets’ works collectively move from the genesis of the cosmos to the story of “the people.” And importantly, Homer and Hesiod were the first to do this. Together they created the paradigm of the poets. Whereas Hesiod’s continuing authority depended largely on the content of the Theogony and the interest it held for philosophers of a later age, Homer’s gained greatly from its style. The grandeur and beauty of Homer’s poetry caused even skeptical minds and haters of myth to temporarily suspend disbelief and allow themselves to be engulfed by its magic. Homer gave the world its first taste of the classical hexameter, a metrical line that is at once complex and majestic. Unlike familiar English rhythms that can turn monotonous in a long work, the hexameter can accommodate a great deal of variation within it without losing its metrical form. It is thus an ideal medium for sustaining a long epic poem. Add to its effect Homer’s frequently “mysterious” vocabulary. Out of the approximately 7,600 words that are not proper names, over 2,300 are attested only once—and that “once” is in Homer. Even in Pisistratus’s day these words would have been felt as rare and archaic—both learned and mysterious. 35 what makes a work authoritative? 35 The effect on the listener then would not have been so different from the effect of Shakespeare on listeners now. When we go to a play by Shakespeare, we have to be extra attentive at first to catch what is said, as it takes a few minutes to adjust the ear. Many of Shakespeare’s words have long passed out of everyday usage, and we need to be taught their meanings. (We need to study, in other words.) But the effect of the best speeches Shakespeare gave his characters can bring us to tears. We are carried away; we know that we are hearing something deep, something venerable, something important— even if we don’t understand every single word. The rhapsodes, like the best Shakespearean actors, devoted their talents to producing the same effects. Homer gave the Greeks something new: he gave them the Sublime. 36 37 3 Physis—Redefining the Gods The Greek sophists who challenged conventional thinking about the gods and morality in Athens in the later fifth century b.c.e. would have felt a kinship with the skeptical minds of the European Enlightenment of our era who questioned the absolutist claims of religion. In both cases, the rise of skepticism and freethinking was based on major changes in thinking about the nature of the world and its origins. The protagonists of the Enlightenment were able to build upon the scientific advances of Galileo and Kepler. In a similar vein, the Greek sophists did not just pop up like Athena springing from the head of Zeus. They drew deeply on the writings of the natural philosophers who had been active in the century and a half before them. These were the Presocratics.1 For the French rationalists the line of battle was drawn between science and religion; for Greek intellectuals the line was between science and myth. The political conditions, however, were very different. For the brave soldiers of the Enlightenment in France an established Church was an obstacle to progress, as it could use its power to burn books and its authors with them. Conditions were not so extreme in preclassical Greece; it was only in the latter part of the fifth and the fourth century, and then only in Athens, that we find attempts to suppress free expression. For the pioneers of Greek science the chief target was the myths of the poets, not the cults of the gods. As we shall see, the first phase of the campaign concentrated on the myths themselves. At a later phase, starting with Plato, it turned against poetry, the medium of myth. One of the major aims of the Presocratic philosophers was to demythologize religion. A similar effort was made in the twentieth century by Christian theologians who believed that Christianity would be more attractive to rational people without the requirement to believe in implausible stories such as the resurrection and ascension of Jesus.2 (Bodies, once dead, cannot be resuscitated, and humans do not fly.) It is theoretically possible for religion, understood as the worship of supernatural beings, to exist without the trappings of myth. But there is a nexus between myth and religion that is very difficult to 38 38 the anatomy of my th break.3 This is because it is the wondrous deeds and achievements of supernatural beings attested in song that inspire belief in them and promote their cults. Liturgies and prayers connect the praise of the gods, or petitions to them, with their power to perform miracles or bring a benefit to the devotee. That power is demonstrated by the wonders they achieved in the past that are “remembered” in prayers and hymns like the so-called Homeric Hymns. 4 After complaints about the immorality of the Homeric gods, the chief criticisms involved the supernatural actions that were ascribed to them. These included shape shifting, instantaneous relocation, changing humans into animals or trees, placing them in the sky as constellations, and every other kind of action that compromised the gods’ own nature or the nature of other beings. In other words, rational men could not believe in gods that performed actions contrary to nature. God cannot do what is impossible. In this context it is instructive to read the words of a contemporary Christian theologian cited by Richard Dawkins in his book The God Delusion: What the theist claims about God is that he does have power to create, conserve, or annihilate anything, big or small. And he can also make objects move or do anything else … He can make the planets move in the way that Kepler discovered that they move, or make gunpowder explode when we set a match to it; or he can make planets move in quite different ways, and chemical substances explode or not explode under quite different conditions from those which now govern their behaviour. God is not limited by the laws of nature; he makes them and he can suspend them—if he chooses.5 For believing Christians, the above statement enjoyed long sanction. Augustine made very similar statements in The City of God—most alarmingly in his attempt to prove that physical bodies can “live” forever in hellfire.6 The notion that divine miracles contravene the laws of nature worried a rationalist Irishman in the seventh century c.e., who went to great lengths to show that God did not violate nature, but exploited its properties to work his miracles. More to our purpose, it worried Galen (129?–199 c.e.), physician to the Emperor Marcus Aurelius and the most famous medical writer of antiquity. Galen was deeply interested in religion and philosophy. By the end of the first century c.e. the Jewish and Christian scriptures were beginning to attract the attention of Greek and Roman thinkers.7 Here is what Galen had to say on Jewish versus Greek ideas on God/god: It is precisely this point in which our own opinion and that of Plato and the other Greeks who follow the right method in natural science differs from the position taken up by Moses. For the latter it seems enough to say that God simply willed the arrangement of matter and 39 physis—r edefining the gods 39 it was presently arranged in due order; for he believes everything to be possible with God, even should he wish to make a bull or a horse out of ashes. We, however, do not hold this; we say that certain things are impossible by nature and that God does not even attempt such things at all but that he chooses the best out of the possibility of becoming.8 The phrase “impossible by nature” says it all. From the beginning the idea of nature was deeply ingrained in the Greek mind. A large proportion of the philosophical works written in the sixth and fifth century b.c.e. were entitled On Nature. The study of nature involved both the study of natural phenomena and speculations as to the origin and nature of the cosmos—what we today call “theoretical physics.”9 The early Greeks did not yet speak of the “laws of nature,” because the usual word for law (nomos) was bound up with the notion of a convention, something that could arbitrarily change. Indeed, nomos (law, custom) was thought of as being in antithesis to physis (nature) or anankē (necessity). At the same time, the Greeks conceived of nature as behaving according to unchangeable laws—even though they would not have used the word “law” with its connotation of arbitrariness. Thus, for example, when a natural being dies, it cannot come back to life—or be brought back to life by some agent. And so, as Galen makes clear, God cannot make a bull or a horse out of ashes. Nor—to return to Dawkins’s theologian—can God cause the planets to behave in any way other than they habitually do. The gods may have a sphere of operation, but it is within the confines of nature, which should be defined as “the way things are,” or as we say today, “it’s hard wired.” Centuries before Galen, an anonymous Greek physician, who was probably a contemporary of the earliest atomists, wrote a treatise entitled On the Sacred Disease. The “sacred disease” was the common Greek phrase for epilepsy, so- called either because it was inflicted by the gods, or because the gods had a special care for epileptics. Because of its divine associations it was thought that it could not be cured by normal medical procedures, but only through incantations or purifications. The author of On the Sacred Disease attacked this notion in the following way: I do not believed that the sacred disease is any more divine or sacred than any other disease, but on the contrary, just as other diseases have a nature from which they arise so this one has a nature (physis) and a definite cause (prophasis).10 The author proceeded to attack the authors of these superstitious ideas, labeling them “magicians” (magoi) and “charlatans” (alazones). At the end of his treatise he explains the general cause of diseases: 40 40 the anatomy of my th Each disease has its own nature [physis] and power [dunamis] and there is nothing in any disease which is unintelligible or insusceptible to treatment. The majority of maladies are cured by the same things as caused them.11 The emphasis on natural causes and the dislike of supernatural explanations for medical conditions found here is manifested in other areas investigated by the thinkers of the sixth and fifth centuries b.c.e. The greater part of them had well-developed interests in mathematics and natural science. The first wave hailed from Ionia, the name for a group of Greek-speaking cities on or near the western coast of Turkey. Thales of Miletus (ca. 600 b.c.e.), the earliest of the Ionians, was said to be a mathematician, astronomer, and engineer. He is credited with predicting an eclipse and diverting the bed of a river. His successor Anaximander was a geometer and cartographer. Pythagoras is well known for his theorem of the right triangle, still taught today in schools. Xenophanes’ study of fossils taught him that the sea had once been where land is now. All of these early thinkers employed writing, and fragments of their books are quoted by later philosophers such as Aristotle; historians of thought including Diogenes Laertius, who covered the lives of the philosophers from Thales to Epicurus; and even the Fathers of the early Christian Church, who often cited them in order to refute their teachings. None of the sixth-century cosmologists tried to rid the universe of gods, or replace God with a particle. The main reason for this is that no thinker or writer of the sixth or fifth century believed that a god or gods created the world. Their interest, rather, lay in separating what belonged to nature from the activities and powers of the divine. This was no easy task, and it often resulted in transferring divine powers to nature. To reach that understanding, it was first necessary to abolish or reinterpret the gods of the poets, then to demythologize the language of cosmology and replace it with “natural” language. This was a slow and difficult process. Doing away with the poets’ gods as real gods was widely agreed upon, but what does one do about gods in general or the existence of the divine? Only a very few were prepared to do without god altogether. For the most part, the earliest Greek intellectuals were engaged in regularizing or rationalizing the activities of the gods within a preexistent cosmos. Theology could not be separated entirely from cosmology. It was only with the atomists in the latter part of the fifth century that a cosmos was posited in which divine activity was thought superfluous to requirements. The process was unsteady, moving in zigzag fashion, but one can see at least a hint of movement from the idea that gods were in everything to the idea that a godlike force was involved in some kind of ordering process, and finally, to the notion that the gods really had nothing to do with the cosmic workings at all. 41 physis—r edefining the gods 41 The cosmologists who spanned the long Presocratic period (about 200 years) disagreed with one another about many things, but they seem to have settled on four points: (1) The stuff that constitutes the world, in some form or other, always was and always will be. (2) Everything that is is made of some material, i.e., has weight and measure. (3) And—this is the point to be stressed—matter or the prime substance was not created by any god. Some sort of Mind could give a kick-start to the swirl, but it could not make the stuff that is in it. Heraclitus put it most succinctly: “This world order (the cosmos) did none of gods or men make, but it always was and is and shall be.”12 (4) As a corollary of point 3, the gods are secondary phenomena; they are generated, but do not create. The big disagreements were over the question what the basic stuff is from which everything else is derived, and the related question, if that stuff is one or many, or simply everything all at once. The debate revolved around the term archē, the principle that explains both the stuff out of which things are created and simultaneously the cause of their creation. Even Plato, who, in the form of a fable,13 posited a creator god, believed that the elements (earth, air, fire, and water) were always there for the demiurge to work with. We can see the beginnings of the discussion of the archē in Thales of Miletus (born in the seventh century b.c.e.), who maintained that water was the principle (archē) of all things.14 He also stated that “all things were full of gods”15—and that is why a magnet works! It would seem that for Thales, divine operation was still needed to explain mysterious natural events. But Thales’ “gods” are not external to the magnet; they belong to it. “They” are its nature; they make it work. Aristotle interpreted Thales’ remarks to mean that a magnet is ensouled because it has “kinetic” power,16 that is, it can move something else. But I think that the point for Thales is that natural objects can have inexplicable properties that cause things, in every case, to happen in a particular way. We say that a plant has a certain property that always has the same effect on a human who ingests it, for example, hemlock in a potion invariably causes death. If one were to refer to the fatal property as the hemlock’s nature, we are no further ahead in understanding how it works than if we say that the property is divine. The difference between Thales’ thesis and primitive animism is that in the first instance, things always work in a predictable way because of their “divine” properties; in the second, one must resort to incantation or some form of manipulation to make them work. Greek empiricism could observe only that things regularly work in certain ways; it was unable to advance to why they work as they do. Modern biochemistry and molecular biology can now solve questions surrounding a plant’s properties, just as the science of magnetic fields explains the why or how of magnets. But god and nature remained commingled as far as Aristotle (and beyond). Both Plato and Aristotle thought of the cosmos as ensouled, and referred to it as “divine.”17 The great advance made by the early Greek philosophers, as we shall see, was not the abolition of the divine element, but the 42 42 the anatomy of my th removal of the anthropomorphic gods. However, the gods had to be accommodated, and so, from Thales onward, they were (1) embedded in nature; (2) given a role in organizing the cosmos without creating it; (3) in the case of the atomists, declared redundant. Thales’ successor Anaximander had nothing to say about the gods per se, but held some very interesting ideas about astronomy (the sun is twenty-eight times the size of the earth) and about the origin of animals and humans. He hypothesized that the first living things came from moisture enclosed in bark,18 while humans originated from a nonhuman species that differed from that of other animals because human infants take so long to be self- sufficient.19 He also taught that all things ultimately came from an infinite (material) substance called the apeiron (“unbounded”).20 But he too called the apeiron “divine,” for that was the descriptor needed for that which is eternal and the source of everything else. Gods are explicitly mentioned by Anaximenes, the successor to the “chair” of Thales after Anaximander. Anaximenes taught that air (the archē, or first principle of things) did not come from the gods, but the gods came from air. Yet he would also refer to air as a god.21 The philosophers who posited a single element as the source of all things were confronted with the problem of how this element changed into, or produced, other things that were different from it. If you say, as Anaximenes did, that “all things come into being from air and into it they are again dissolved,”22 you must explain how this can occur of itself (that is, naturally), or attribute some type of creative force to the element—in which case you are flirting again with the idea of god. Since the archē (air in this case, water and fire in others) is uncreated, and everything comes from it, then it must possess special generative powers that could be equated with the divine.23 The principle enjoys the advantage of self-containment. One might here invoke “Ockham’s razor”: it is better to explain a phenomenon by a single hypothesis than by two or more. One does not need a god or gods that are separate from nature to explain coming into being or change. The appeal to the archē would also seem to exclude any kind of exterior cause of change or motion. The concept of the archē in its varieties was critically reviewed by Aristotle in the first book of his Metaphysics (983b – 984a), and found wanting (984a).24 Indeed, he argued that it satisfied only the first (the material) of the four necessary causes of things: material, formal, efficient, final (Phys. 194b). These can be briefly explained as (1) the stuff out of which a substance is made; (2) the shape or form of a substance (that which makes it recognizable as what it is); (3) the action or series of actions that are the immediate cause of a substance’s existence; (4) the end for which a specific substance is made.25 The early thinkers, especially the Ionians, probably believed that all of these were included in the gift of the archē. They disagreed with one another on whether its operations involved the divine or were completely natural. 43 physis—r edefining the gods 43 Philosophers use the term “monist” (from monos, “one,” “only”) to refer to the tradition of positing a single element (archē) as the explanation of everything else. The last of the monists was also from Ionia, though not from Miletus. Heraclitus was born in Ephesus, ca. 540 b.c.e. Heraclitus’s reputed arrogance and his riddling pronouncements made him a target for abusive remarks over the centuries. Even the manner of his death was derided: Having fallen … into a dropsy he came down to town and asked the doctors in a riddle if they could make a drought out of rainy weather. When they did not understand he buried himself in a cow-stall, expecting that the dropsy would be evaporated off by the heat of the manure; but even so he failed to effect anything, and ended his life at the age of sixty.26 For Heraclitus, fire was the single uncreated principle that is the explanation of everything else: “All things are an equal exchange for fire and fire for all things, as goods are for gold and gold for goods.”27 Like his predecessors, Heraclitus believed that the cosmos was a unity, and that opposition between things was only apparent (“The way up is the way down”). Heraclitus also introduced the concept of logos (“reason”) and gnōmē (“thought,” “judgment”) into his universal view. These principles were not differentiated from the archē, but were inherent within it. Heraclitus was innovative in attributing a mental function to his archē, everlasting fire, but he remained loyal to his Ionian predecessors by excluding external factors of causality. One did not require a transcendent god. External gods, then, were superfluous to requirements. They had no involvement in creating the cosmos, or in keeping it running. Cosmic fire was itself divine and rational because it contained logos. This notion may well account for the puzzling “Thunderbolt steers all things.”28 Thunderbolt is self-sufficient cosmic fire; there is no need to introduce the god who throws it. Heraclitus introduced metonymic language when he said, “One thing, the only truly wise [hen to sophon], does not and does consent to be called by the name of Zeus.”29 How and why did the marginalization—or redefinition—of the gods begin? To answer this question, it helps if we think of the poems of Homer and Hesiod not as mere works of fiction (as we now tend to read them), but (as noted in the previous chapters) as authoritative sources on cosmology, theology, and history that were available in written form. Heraclitus gives us a clue as to how he and other thinkers of his day might have read them. He writes, “Learning of many things does not teach intelligence; if so, it would have taught Hesiod and Pythagoras, and again Xenophanes and Hecataeus.”30 To understand the import of this quotation we must say something about the three individuals mentioned after Hesiod. Pythagoras was a mathematician and moral philosopher; Xenophanes of Colophon wrote on natural science 44 44 the anatomy of my th and theology; Hecataeus (ca. 500 b.c.e.) was an early cartographer, geographical writer, and collector of legends. All three therefore had good credentials in mathematics or science—subjects we now call “the hard sciences.” Why would Heraclitus lump these respectable men together with a “mythological” poet? I suspect that the answer is that he thought of Hesiod as one of his predecessors in cosmological theory. In this he was not alone; later Aristotle was to think of Hesiod in the same way, describing him as though he had been a philosopher like Thales, with his own school and successors.31 A fragment of Heraclitus’s writings survives that tells us one of the reasons for his scathing remarks regarding Hesiod: For very many people Hesiod is <their> teacher. They are certain he knew a great number of things—he who continually failed to recognize <even> day and night <for what they are> ! For they are one.32 The criticism made here is based on Heraclitus’s theory of the unity of apparent opposites (illustrated by “The road up is the road down” and similar statements). We can only guess his other reasons for dismissing Hesiod. I suspect Heraclitus also wanted to pick a bone with the poet over the principle of causation. Whereas the older writer posited erōs (attraction) as the principle of causation, Heraclitus opted for its opposite, eris (strife or repulsion): “all things happen by strife and necessity.”33 (However, Heraclitus very likely believed that strife was already inherent in everliving fire, and not a separate agent.) Had Heraclitus’s dismissal of Hesiod survived as the only negative comment on either of the two authoritative poets, we would never have had any inkling of an important shift in thought and expression between the eighth century and the sixth. Fortunately, we have a group of fragments from a book written by Xenophanes of Colophon, whom we just met as one of Heraclitus’s targets. Xenophanes, who was apparently older than Heraclitus (who cites him), was born in Ionia, the same region that had produced Thales, Anaximander, Anaximenes, and Heraclitus. After some traveling about, Xenophanes moved to Elea (modern Velia), a Greek colony on the southwest coast of Italy. We have no exact dates for him, but it seems that his life spanned much of the sixth century b.c.e. and some of the fifth—we know from his own words that he was still alive at age 92.34 Xenophanes gives us a few hints about his character in the surviving fragments of his poems. He makes himself out to be an affable fellow who enjoyed food, wine, and pleasant conversation: The mixing bowl stands full of cheer and another wine, mild and flower fragrant in the jars, is at hand— which says it never will give out.35 45 physis—r edefining the gods 45 Xenophanes was a product of his age and his Ionian heritage. Like his contemporaries and near-contemporaries (Thales, Pythagoras, Heraclitus), he pursued a wide range of interests: the study of fossils, speculative cosmology, theology, and the theory of knowledge—all this in addition to writing poetry of a non-philosophical character. It is generally agreed that his claim to fame rests with his innovative theology. This includes both a repudiation of the gods of the poets and a revolutionary (for Greeks, at least) rethinking of the nature of god. Whether Xenophanes had read a copy of Homer’s writings, or simply knew them from gists or by hearing rhapsodes, cannot be proved from the evidence we have. However, the fragments are worth quoting in full: 1. Homer and Hesiod have attributed to the gods everything that is a shame and reproach among men, stealing and committing adultery and deceiving each other. 2. But mortals consider that the gods are born, and that they have clothes and speech and bodies like their own. 3. The Ethiopians say that their gods are snub-nosed and black, the Thracians that theirs have light blue eyes and red hair. 4. But if cattle and horses or lions had hands, or were able to draw with their hands and do the works that men can do, horses would draw the forms of the gods like horses, and cattle like cattle, and they would make their bodies such as they each had themselves.36 It is obvious here that Xenophanes is attacking the anthropomorphic conception of gods that was taught by the poets and probably accepted by most people. Homer and Hesiod, as the first of the poets, must own up to the blame. Xenophanes goes beyond these bald statements and develops a theory that explains human ideas of god that is strikingly modern. We humans project not only our physical traits, but also our moral characteristics onto our gods. The philosopher might have added that we do this in order to excuse and justify our worst traits. If a god can steal or commit adultery, why shouldn’t we? (This conclusion, however, was drawn later.) We also detect the philosopher’s insight into the sociological fact that different cultures create different gods for themselves. He reduces the idea to absurdity by imagining animals doing the same. However, Xenophanes is no cultural or moral relativist. Quite the contrary. There is a god. There is one who is the greatest. And he bears no resemblance to humans: 1. One god, greatest among gods and men, in no way similar to mortals either in body or in thought. 2. Always he remains in the same place, moving not at all; nor is it fitting for him to go to different places at different times, but without toil he shakes all things by the thought of his mind. 46 46 the anatomy of my th 3. All of him sees, all thinks, and all hears. 4. (Zeus) hurls mortals to destruction from their high towered expectations, but puts forth no force: everything of gods is without toil. Sitting he nevertheless at once accomplishes his thought, somehow, from his holy resting place.37 These statements are drawn from the body of commonly accepted fragments of Xenophanes. But other ancient witnesses expand the testimony. One comes from Aristotle, who ascribes to Xenophanes the statement “those who say that the gods are born are as impious as those who say that they die; for it follows on both views that there is a time when the gods do not exist.”38 The statement fits Xenophanes’ theology if only because it is consistent with his anti-anthropomorphic views of divinity. Homer and nearly all other poets referred to the gods as athanatoi, “deathless,” but they did not call them aiōnioi, “eternal.” Moreover, Homer and especially Hesiod record the circumstances of their births. Xenophanes does not tell us that his “one greatest god” created the world; he says only that he “shakes all things by the thought of his mind.” But this god is not an archē as the Milesians conceived it.39 He is described as a living being, not as an inanimate element or undefined matter. Because he sits, he is not entirely free of anthropomorphic features; he apparently has a body. The break with the Ionian tradition I mentioned above is the introduction of a god who stands (or in this case, “sits”) apart from nature. His thinking god is to be contrasted with Heraclitus’s all-pervasive logos, which is subsumed in the archē that is everliving fire, or with Anaximenes’ air, which is divine and even produces gods from itself. In one respect, however, Xenophanes has not progressed beyond Homer and Hesiod. He still speaks of a plurality of gods, among whom one is by far the most powerful. But, of course, it is possible that his use of the plural is simply a concession to popular belief, and the word “gods” is intended as a substitute for a unified divinity. 40 However, elsewhere Xenophanes speaks of “gods.” Monotheism versus polytheism was not a dilemma for the early Greeks. Even in Homer and Hesiod, where polytheism is the normal state, one god (Zeus) is “greatest of gods and men.” In every other way Xenophanes’ thoughts are revolutionary. His influence in the area of theology was certainly profound, 41 even if his cosmological musings had little impact. We can credit Xenophanes with three achievements: (1) detaching a belief in the gods from the popular myths about them; (2) substituting mythological language with the language of natural philosophy; (3) creating a new concept of god altogether—one freed from anthropomorphic misconceptions and thus from moral imperfection. Let us add a word here regarding Xenophanes’ second contribution: replacing mythological language with the language of natural philosophy. 47 physis—r edefining the gods 47 Xenophanes seems to have been the earliest Greek thinker to apply the term “fiction” to myths. The Greek word for fiction is plasma (plural plasmata). At the end of the poem about a banquet (cited above), he writes in praise of the man who after taking drink recites noble and virtuous deeds: Praise the man who when he has taken drink brings noble deeds to light, as memory and a striving for virtue bring to him. He deals neither with the battles of Titans nor Giants nor Centaurs, fictions [plasmata] of old, nor furious conflicts—for there is no use in these. But it is good always to hold the gods in high regard. 42 Here we have what might be the earliest example of a Western thinker making a clear distinction between deeds that are assumed to be true and the fictions of mythology. Another of the fragments makes the distinction between the natural properties of a thing, in this case, a rainbow, and the personification attached to it in received mythology: And she whom they call Iris, this too is by nature a cloud, purple, red and greenish yellow to behold. 43 Xenophanes is telling his readers that the name Iris is just a figure of speech (that is, personification) used to denote a natural phenomenon. The statement can also be pushed further to mean that when you look at a rainbow, you are just seeing a cloud composed of many colors, not the appearance of a goddess. Xenophanes might as well have said the same of Helios, the sun god, for he advanced the theory that the sun is made of ignited clouds. 44 One might speculate that by removing god from natural objects (gods taken out of the magnet, Iris taken out of the rainbow), Xenophanes was able to contemplate a nature that was truly “natural.” We do not know how he reconciled all this with his notion of “one god who shakes all things.” We have seen that mind, or some form of mental agent, is the common element that links Heraclitus to Xenophanes, whom the former at least had read, if only to disagree with. Heraclitus calls this mental process logos, while his predecessor had called it nous. Anaxagoras followed in chronological order. He thought of mind as one of two first principles, the other being “all things mixed together” (the One). Anaxagoras’s term for mind is also nous. Yet his use of this word differs markedly from that of Xenophanes. For the latter, nous was a faculty possessed by god. It was the organ that god used to “shake all things.” In ordinary language we would call it “the mind of God.” The word “god” does not occur at all in Anaxagoras’s vocabulary. Nous (“mind”) exists in the abstract; it is not owned by any being. And unlike Heraclitus’s logos, Anaxagoras’s nous is not common to everything (that is, inside it), 48 48 the anatomy of my th but exists outside everything— it is “infinite,” “unmixed,” and “all alone by itself.”45 Yet it functions analogously to Heraclitus’s “thunderbolt” (“the aether” = fire = logos?), which steers, and to Xenophanes’ “one god” who rules by shaking. Nous is the principle that starts things whirling. We know little about the man Anaxagoras. He provides no helpful glimpses into his personality as Xenophanes did, nor does the biographical information from later sources reveal any distinguishing characteristics. Like his forerunners in cosmology, he hailed from Ionia, specifically from the town of Clazomenae, which lies on the west coast of Turkey north of Ephesus. By all accounts, he was the first of the Presocratic philosophers to settle and teach in Athens. He was credited with predicting the fall of a stone out of the sky that landed by a river and was later erected as an object of worship. Doubtless he was describing a meteorite because a comet had been observed not long before the stone’s fall. He was the first Greek to be brought up on a charge of impiety in Athens, but escaped the death penalty (the prescribed punishment for this crime), possibly because he was on friendly terms with the tyrant Pericles, or, as other sources say, because the jury took pity on him. He moved afterward to Lampsacus, where he was held in high honor. Legend has it that his death day was made a civic holiday there. More is known about Anaxagoras’s teachings that show his penchant for naturalist explanations of phenomena: In the beginning the stars were carried around as though in a dome, so that the celestial pole which is always visible was directly over the earth, but later the axis was inclined. The Milky Way is the reflection of the light of those stars that are not illuminated by the sun. Comets are a conglomeration of planets that throw out flames, and shooting stars are the sparks hurled out by the air. Winds arise from the air rarefied by the sun. Thunder is the clashing of clouds; lightning, the friction of clouds; an earthquake, the sinking of air into the earth. Animals first came to be from moist, hot, and earthy stuffs, but later from one another; and males come from the right side and females from the left side [of the uterus]. 46 One notes that his hypothesis on the origin of animals may owe something to Anaximander, and that his other thoughts about the origin of natural phenomena ascribe nothing to divine operation. Anaxagoras also taught that the sun was “a fiery mass of burning metal,”47 and it was for saying this he was charged with impiety. One is left to wonder if Anaxagoras’s claim was interpreted as a denial of the divinity of the sun god Helios, since speculation about the composition of a natural object in itself could scarcely amount to impiety. Still, he was no more impious than the pious Xenophanes, who had taught that the sun was a mass of burning clouds. 49 physis—r edefining the gods 49 Anaxagoras speaks for all early Greek cosmologists when he asserts that nothing comes into being or passes out of being. The atomists were later to say, “Nothing can come from nothing.” No name of a god, or even the word “god” can be detected in the extant set of quotations held to be genuine. However, Anaxagoras introduces an external cause for motion. The archē is not sufficient to explain movement by itself. Yet nous does not create, but simply instigates motion and separates the things that are already there. Anaxagoras’s Mind differs in an important way from Xenophanes’ One God, who shakes all things with his mind, or from the logos of Heraclitus, which is still somehow bound up with god. Nous is a completely abstract principle: a mind without an owner. The fact that it stands apart from the rest of being and controls it leaves open the possibility of someone saying, “Anaxagoras, you describe a thing that has all the powers of god, yet you shrink from giving it the name.” In this he deviated from his predecessors. The most striking phase in the marginalization of god came toward the end of the fifth century b.c.e. with the theories of the early atomists Leucippus and Democritus. Democritus is usually described as the pupil of Leucippus. The two atomists collectively took certain elements of Anaxagoras’s teaching. One of them is the idea that matter (for them, atoms) escaped from an initially confined space and expanded into a boundless universe (the great whirl). Another is that there are infinite worlds. Still another is the idea that the seeds of all things were always in existence. The atomists, however, avoided a dilemma that had caused Anaxagoras so much grief. The latter appears to have been influenced (indeed, dogged) by Parmenides’ teachings that being is one and continuous, and the void does not exist. (“Nothing cannot exist.”) This is why he posited everything (or almost everything) as eternally fully formed, and existing in a jumble. The atomists suffered from no such difficulty. Matter always existed, and so did the void (otherwise how could there be movement?). Moreover, although the constituent pieces of matter (atoms) are eternal, they continually form new combinations of things, so that things change and increase (and also decrease). Most importantly, these constituent parts move on their own accord; they require no exterior principle of motion. On the other hand, just as for Anaxagoras there was an initial state of things, so too for Leucippus: “The world came into being as follows: many bodies of all sorts of shapes move by abscission from the infinite into a great void; they come together there and produce a single whirl, in which colliding with one another and revolving in all manner of ways, they begin to separate apart, like to like.”48 The essential differences from Anaxagoras’s model are that matter exists in the form of atoms, not as fully formed things; and no part of the process described is steered by Mind. But how does it occur? Two apparently contradictory explanations are provided: chance (or randomness) and necessity. But the final word should go to Leucippus himself, who claims 50 50 the anatomy of my th necessity as the reason: “Nothing occurs by chance, but everything for a reason and by necessity.”49 “Necessity” (anankē) we take to mean the invisible law of the cosmos that is eternal, but no god created it or administers it. Nearly two hundred years of continuous cosmological speculation came to a temporary pause with the work of the atomists. But the implication for theology and religion were profound. In the last stages of this long process, when the early Milesians had faded from memory, three possible conclusions were left: (1) God did not create the universe, but a single god guides it with his mind (or according to a plan). 2) God did not create nor does he steer the universe, but a mysterious force called Mind began the process of separation of things and controls the process eternally. (3) God had nothing at all to do with the universe, which operates according to its own laws. The thinking man is left with the alternative of atheism, or accepting the “god of the philosophers.” The implications of these early ideas about god and nature on the interpretation of myth were profound. They established a new paradigm. Although Hesiod’s ideas on the origins of everything retained some relevance, his stories about the gods as well as Homer’s had to be rejected. They contained serious misrepresentations of the divine nature and retailed narratives that defied credibility. Either they had to be jettisoned or reinterpreted in ways that accorded with the new paradigm. But the price of removing the anthropomorphic gods was steep: the gods had to be stuffed back into nature, whether as the divine element of the archē, or as the principle of a magnet. There may not have been a “god delusion,” but there surely was a god trap. If the old gods were to be removed, what was going to replace them? People could worship Homer’s Zeus, “who wears the aegis,” but could they relate to Xenophanes’ god, who just sits and thinks? Could the “man in the street” sacrifice to Anaxagoras’ Mind (assuming that it was interpreted as divine)? Or would he prefer to offer incense to the divinized elements of the Ionians? Somehow the gods had become unglued ever since Xenophanes rendered the poets’ gods as fictions (plasmata). There were no longer just different gods, but different sorts of gods. Philosophers could declare god to be one with the world, but divinity was no longer at one with itself. 51 4 Flirting with Atheism The work carried out over two centuries by the so-called Presocratics had profound and irreversible effects on Greek thought, and indeed on the entire history of Western philosophy and science. The cosmos was material and its mysteries could be revealed only by discovering the laws of nature. Even Anaxagoras’s nous was material.1 Its superiority over the rest of the material world lay in the fact that it was “unmixed”—it was some kind of pure material substance. Plato in the fourth century was able to retard the exclusively materialist view of the world.2 He was the first to argue that there could be being that was wholly separate from matter; this type of being could not be grasped by the senses, but by the mind alone. The Good, arguably identifiable with god, was the highest expression of this nonmaterial being. Plato’s pupil Aristotle, who appears resolutely materialist in most of his writings, softened his stance when it came to God, positing a divine being without magnitude (Meta. 1073a). But all this came later. Other segments of the population with limited education were probably aware of new trends in religious thought, but skeptical of them. The popular playwright Aristophanes pandered to this particular crowd in his play Clouds. In it the author hilariously lampoons scientific experiments, and depicts Socrates floating in a basket at the end of a rope as he attempts to observe the sun and the heavens. Socrates had indeed engaged in cosmological theorizing before he famously rejected natural science in favor of ethics. The satire shows that the radical new movements (Aristophanes lumps them together as “the School of Thinkery”) had penetrated popular consciousness to some extent. It would seem that the new scientific theories affected the beliefs of at least the educated classes, even if most of them were not themselves scientists or philosophers, but simply consumers of books and ideas. We recognize these people today. They are the busy professional people who read popular history in their spare time rather than play squash. They like to discuss their latest read with their professional friends, if only for the fun of one-upsmanship. That such a class existed at least in fifth-century Athens is shown by the demanding 52 52 the anatomy of my th nature of the dramas people attended. The proliferation of theater festivals and the expansion of the dramatic repertoire to include historical subjects and less familiar mythological themes point to the existence of a cultivated theater- going public.3 We also find descriptions of drinking parties where topics like the meaning of love were discussed in a serious way, as in Plato’s Symposium. The popularity of the Sophist movement, at least among the well-born youth, is another indicator of what might be called “popular intellectual life.” When the same class of people got around to discussing the nature of the gods, there were probably not too many who invoked Homer as their authority. While the worship of the gods was not bound up with ethics, or if so only loosely, the gods one worshipped were certainly attached to their myths. This is made most obvious by the fact that the images of the gods with all their attributes correspond to descriptions in the poems. Moreover, the Homeric Hymns—poems written in praise of individual gods and goddesses—provide the stories of the gods that are to be praised. However, Xenophanes, followed even more forcefully by Plato, left a deep tear in the fabric. Things could never be quite the same again. Whether one worshiped one god or many, he, she, or they did not engage in the immoral and disgraceful things Homer and Hesiod said the gods did. Moreover, a god did not rush all over the place, attending to this and that, but sat calmly in one place, accomplishing everything just by thinking about it. The result was that all the old myths about the gods had to be tossed out, or reinterpreted—but we’ll come to that possibility later. However, they could not be taken literally by sensible people. (The colleagues in the agora or at the gym would roll their eyes.) From Xenophanes’ day forward, there was a new class of gods for fashionable people who chose to believe in gods at all. These were the “philosophers’ gods.” We shall have more to say about them below. The foundations of Greek “atheism” had been laid in the sixth and early fifth centuries. They manifested themselves throughout the fifth. Whereas today there are many people who are proud to call themselves atheists and write books to convince others to join them, this is a new phenomenon. For centuries, indeed millennia, it was extremely dangerous to be labeled an atheist. Up to the 1960s, atheism, though legal in most Western countries, was socially frowned upon. Writing in the Victorian Age, Darwin held back from publishing his theory of evolution for fear that it would be labeled “atheist,” and this would break his dear wife’s heart. To this very day it is used as a term of reproach, especially when coupled with labels such as “Marxist” or “Communist.” Today we use the word “atheist” for those who assert categorically that god (God) does not exist, or claim that the chances of his nonexistence are much better than those of his existence. Modern atheists (the so-called new atheists4) also openly attack religion and catalogue the evils they believe it perpetrates. We reserve the word “agnostic” for those who aren’t sure of God’s existence, neither 53 flirting with atheism 53 affirming nor denying it. Agnostics are regarded as “part of the problem” by some new atheists, as they are seen as abetting the causes of theists and retarding the growth of a positive atheism.5 There is also a sizable group of people who claim to believe in “some kind of higher power,” though when pressed to say more, they have trouble explaining what they mean by the phrase. The use of the word “atheist” was different in Greek antiquity. Technically it referred to denial of the gods worshipped in a given polis, or like Zeus, throughout Greece. Atheism of that sort was a crime. There was also the crime of impiety, or asebeia, the failure to reverence the gods, or the showing of disrespect.6 The term atheos, “godless,” was also applied to a number of people who simply displayed casual or somewhat skeptical attitudes about religion. Practically all of the prosecutions for atheism we know about took place in Athens, and they occurred late in terms of our study so far. They began with Anaxagoras and continued to the end of the fourth century. In most cases, we do not have a clear idea of the basis for the charges. None of the philosophers or scientists mentioned so far came out and said, “I do not believe in Zeus.” The laws against atheism were well known, and people did not care to run afoul of them. Aristotle reputedly left Athens because he did not want the Athenians to sin twice against philosophy—an obvious reference to the execution of Socrates. The laws seemed to have been applied inconsistently and were directed against people who somehow had made themselves unpopular. In Aristotle’s case, the charge of impiety was particularly flimsy. Aristotle was accused of reciting a paian (“a hymn of praise”) to a mortal. The paian was supposed to be reserved for the gods.7 As we have already seen, a number of the philosophers “flirted” with atheism simply by ignoring the role of the gods in their cosmological schemes, or by redefining the traditional gods. In the last half of the fifth century, we find expressions of skepticism about the gods or religion among the sophists (itinerant teachers who taught the skills of argumentation) and the playwrights. They show the spread of such attitudes outside the class of professional philosophers. Let us start with the sophists. Perhaps the most famous of this group was Protagoras of Abdera (ca. 490–420 b.c.e.). His renown for wisdom was so great that Pericles invited him to draw up a constitution for an Athenian colony. His famous statement about the existence of the gods and their nature reflects a pure agnosticism: About the gods I cannot say either that they are or that they are not, nor what sort they are in their form; for there are many things that hinder knowledge: a lack of clarity [of the subject] and the brevity of human life.8 The same sophist also taught, “man is the measure of all things, the things that are how they are, and the things that are not how they are not.”9 The 54 54 the anatomy of my th statement was strongly disliked by thinkers as far apart in their views as Democritus and Plato. For both of them, things are as they are whether we know them or not. Yet Protagoras gives us an early preview of the falling tree paradox.10 If no one is there to know or observe things, in what sense do they exist? In other words, all things that are exist insofar as humans know them. (It is worth noting that even Einstein’s Special Theory of Relativity is based on the existence of a human observer.) This statement also has relevance to belief in the gods. If highly intelligent people cannot reach certainty about the nature of the gods, it is unlikely that it will ever be reached. Thus, humans are the judges of the things that are not. Because of his statement about the gods, Protagoras was charged with impiety, and his writings were publicly burned a little after 421 b.c.e. Around the same time, a little-k nown poet, Diagoras of Melos, who wrote in Athens in the last decades of the fifth century, was charged and condemned to death for impiety. The trial took place in 415 b.c.e. His alleged crime was revealing the Eleusinian mysteries, a breach that would indeed have been a terrible sacrilege if true. The most famous of the Greek mystery religions, the cult was dedicated to the goddess Demeter and had an especially close connection to Athens. Though some aspects of the ritual are known, its secret mysteries had to be guarded on pain of a charge of impiety.11 Diagoras escaped death by fleeing Athens. His surviving poetry does not betray traces of atheism. However, an anecdote is told about him that certainly would link him to the “atheists” of his day. It is said that he once stood before a bank of costly votive gifts dedicated to the gods for saving the donors from drowning at sea. Diagoras remarked that the gifts “would have been much more numerous if all those who had drowned had also been able to set one up.”12 If present-day atheists had wit of such quality, they would probably attract more converts. Two writers of the same period, one a sophist, the other a playwright, explored the theory that primitive man developed his concept of god either as a power for satisfying basic human needs, or alternatively as an agent of justice in a brutal world. The first of these is Prodicus of Ceos, a sophist and contemporary of Socrates. Some sources refer to him as an atheist, but he apparently escaped prosecution. Little of his work survives, but the statement that led him to be branded atheos is preserved by several later sources (in several versions).13 One version says the following: The ancients called the sun, moon, and fountains gods, and all things in general that benefit our lives on account of the usefulness received from them, just as Egyptians called the Nile a god. And for this reason bread is called Demeter, wine Dionysus, water Poseidon, fire Hephaestus, and likewise each of the things that are beneficial.14 55 flirting with atheism 55 Prodicus’s statement raises a very interesting anthropological question— one too complex to be dealt with here at length, and possibly too difficult to be answered at all. This is the baffling issue of personification. Modern readers of poetry will be familiar with this term as a poetic device, a commonly used figure of speech (“O Death, where is thy sting? O Grave, where is thy victory?”—1 Cor. 15:55–6). For more than two millennia poets themselves were conscious of using this figure of speech. The Greek grammarians even gave it a name: prosopopoeia (to treat something that is not a person as a person). Homer and Hesiod’s works are filled with names of divine beings that look to us like nothing more than indicators of psychological conditions—Strife and Fear being good examples from Homer, Wisdom and Law and Memory from Hesiod. Yet these are called gods and goddesses, just as Night and Sleep and Death are gods in Hesiod’s work. Thus, some of the personifications represent psychological states; others represent physical conditions or even processes. Yet they are all gods, and some even get married and have children. Hesiod’s panorama of divine beings is particularly confusing. It includes natural phenomena like earth (Gaia), sky (Ouranos), and ocean (Oceanos), psychological or mental functions such as wisdom (Metis) and memory (Mnemosyne), abstractions such as law (Themis) and justice (Dike), and anthropomorphic gods (Zeus, Hera, Aphrodite).15 As late as the fourth century b.c.e., altars were set up and sacrifices made to things we would consider abstractions, for example, Rumor and Peace.16 Thales’ dictum “all things are full of gods” takes on an entirely different meaning in the context of Hesiod’s divine personifications. Prodicus was well aware of the different religious practices in his culture; he had also read his Homer and Hesiod. He would have realized that the human tendency to make divinities out of mental processes or abstractions could be transferred to physical things as well. To him it was all part of the “mythic” or primitive thinking process. Zeus needed wisdom, justice, and a good memory, so he married Metis, Themis, and Mnemosyne. But as a physical being he also needed bread, so he married Demeter, “the all-nourishing.” Either from reading Hesiod or by independent speculation, Prodicus, as cited above, attained the insight that the gods, whether representing mental or physical attributes, satisfied needs. Sextus Empiricus, a Skeptic philosopher of the second or third century c.e., lists Prodicus among the atheists, together with Diagoras of Melos and Euhemerus.17 It is easy to see how his contemporaries and posterity could construe Prodicus’s words to mean that gods are just names given to things in nature that benefit humans, and that humans deify them out of some kind of religious feeling. In that case, the association of Prodicus with Euhemerus, who had taught that gods were originally human kings or heroes whom men in ancient times deified after their deaths out of gratitude for their services, is understandable. 56 56 the anatomy of my th One can object, of course, that the inference is not a fair one, and that Prodicus’s theory about the mental processes of early men does not of itself constitute denial of the gods.18 There is no irreverence in recognizing that the gods were identified and named by the benefits they confer on humans—Demeter as bread, Aphrodite as sexual love, Dionysus as wine— or in claiming that these were all beneficial to humans. The gods retained these associations with nature even after they received their human shape in the poetic works, and even after they became the subjects of myths. This is shown by a fragment of an earlier fifth-century writer, Epicharmus, known as a writer of mythological satires. The following passage survives in a Latin paraphrase: This is that Jupiter whom I name, whom the Greeks call the air; he is also wind and cloud, and later rain; and from the rain comes cloud and wind afterwards, and finally air (again). And so all the things I mention to you are Jupiter, because Jupiter helps mortal men and cities and animals.19 While the case of Prodicus is discussable, there can be no doubt about the atheism of Critias, an associate of Socrates and a contemporary of Prodicus, or at least about the atheism of the character whom he portrays in his play, Sisyphos Satyrikos. About forty lines of the play survive.20 The beginning of the passage will remind some readers of Hobbes’s state of nature, in which life is described as “nasty, brutish, and short.” There was a time when the life of men was disordered, brutish in strength, and servile, when there was no reward or anything for the noble, or punishment for the wicked. It was then, it seems, that men established laws to punish in order that justice might rule and also hold insolence in bondage, and a man suffered loss if he committed a crime. It was then when laws were made manifest, and they prevented (men) from committing acts of violence. But it seems to me they did them secretly at that time. It was then that some clever-t hinking assemblyman discovered the fear of the gods for mortals, so that there might be terror for evil-doers, even if they do or say or think things in secret. Thereupon the divine being would move like a daimon flourishing in imperishable life, hearing and seeing with his mind, reflecting deeply as he notices these things, being possessed of a divine nature. He will hear everything spoken amongst mortals and shall be able to see everything done by them. Even should you plot your wickedness in silence, this will not escape the notice of the gods, for their power of thought is exceptional.21 57 flirting with atheism 57 Critias’s statement would have been highly offensive to Xenophanes, had he lived to hear it. Xenophanes had given the Greek world his one, quiet, thinking, and all-seeing god as a great improvement on the immoral Homeric deities. Yet about a century and a half later his divinity—or one resembling it—was savagely deconstructed by a writer of satyr plays. The gods who spy on us are only bogeymen, dreamed up by cynical politicians as a means of keeping people in check. They exist only in the human imagination. That Critias’s statement reflects a true atheism is undeniable, whether we receive it as Critias’s own conviction, or simply as a sentiment attested by a fictional character. As Drachmann says of the speech, “… it is our first direct and unmistakable evidence of ancient atheism.”22 Critias’s bogeyman deity added fresh fuel to Aristophanes’ parody of the critics of the traditional gods. He lumps them all together in his riotous comedy, Frogs: Dionysus: (to Aeschylus and Euripides): Now you two pray, before you speak your lines. Aeschylus: Demeter, who informed and fed my mind, may I prove worthy of the Mysteries. Dionysus: (to Euripides): It’s your turn now. Put some incense on. Euripides: No, thank you. The gods I pray to are other ones than these. Dionysus: Personal gods, new coinages? Euripides: For sure. Dionysus: Pray, then, to your private, nonconformist gods. Euripides: Upper Air, my nutriment! Pivoted, wagging Tongue! Intellectual Power! Nostrils that scent our faults!23 In a single stroke, Aristophanes managed to lampoon Anaximenes’ air gods (enhanced by allegory to extend into the aether), Anaxagoras’s Mind, and Critias’s bogeyman, itself meant as a reductio ad absurdum. The comic playwright obviously assumed that his audience was au courant with the fashionable, but controversial, views of divinity that were circulating in Athens; how else could he draw a laugh? But he also knew that satire could be a dangerous weapon, and that it is safer to draw a laugh at the expense of innovators than offend the larger body of traditionalists. He clearly made the right choice, as Frogs won first prize at the Lenaean Festival in 405 b.c.e. Although Frogs is centrally concerned with the conceits of poetic style, and each of the three great tragedians receives a fair share of the drubbing, Euripides is singled out here for special attention because of his reputed atheism. There is no direct evidence that Euripides denied the existence of the gods, or that he believed in any of the “personal gods” or “new coinages” that Aristophanes mentions. Rather, Euripides’ reputation as an atheist seems to have been based on his frequent portrayal of the gods as cruel or unjust in his plays. Then, as today, the argument was advanced that if the gods committed 58 58 the anatomy of my th injustice, or allowed it to happen when they had the power to prevent it, then they are no gods. This is the argument referred to as theodicean (that is, related to the justice of god) that has dominated religious debate for aeons. It is made explicit in a surviving fragment of Euripides’ play Bellerophon: And then to say that there are gods in the heavens! Nay, there are none there, if you are not foolish enough to be seduced by the old talk. Think for yourself about the matter, and do not be influenced by my words. I contend that the tyrants kill the people wholesale, take their money and destroy cities in spite of their oaths; and although they do this, they are happier than people who, in peace and quietness, lead god-fearing lives. And I know small states which honour the gods, but must obey greater states, which are less pious, because their spearmen are fewer in number.24 Euripides thus gives us evidence that people expressed atheistic views based on the alleged injustice of the gods and the fact that the wicked and powerful lead happy lives, while the rest of humankind suffers miserably in order to support the happiness of the few. One can draw several conclusions from the passage in Bellerophon: (1) the gods do not exist, or they would have put a stop to such behavior long ago; (2) gods exist, but they are impotent to suppress evil, and therefore are unworthy of our veneration; (3) gods exist, but they are wicked and cruel. Readers of Euripides’ plays Bacchae and Hippolytus would be justified in drawing conclusion 3 from the dénouements of those plays.25 Today, however, we would be bound to exonerate Euripides from a charge of atheism, as we distinguish between the views of an author and those of characters represented in his works. The Athenians were not so charitable. The most controversial case surrounding ancient atheism is that of Epicurus. He was widely maligned as an atheist in antiquity not only in the Christian period, but also by “pagan” philosophers of his own day and later. Even those who were aware that he taught the existence of the gods and regarded them as good accused him of being disingenuous, claiming that he made them up just so that he would not be accused of atheism.26 Born in Athens (340/1–272/1 b.c.e.), Epicurus later established a school there called “the Garden,” where women were admitted along with men. During his youth in Ionia (near Colophon, the home of Xenophanes), he studied with a philosopher who espoused atomist teachings. In his own philosophy Epicurus modified the atomism of Leucippus and Democritus in at least one important way: he replaced necessity (anankē), which restricted the motion of atoms to a downward movement, with his notion of the swerve, so that the atoms, through trial and error, could find their like and form permanent things. Because atoms were hooked, an irreverent person today might say that they engage in temporary “hook-ups” until they settle down in a permanent 59 flirting with atheism 59 relationship. However, Epicurus remained true to the masters’ doctrine that the only things that exist are atoms and the void, the empty space needed for the movement of atoms. Atomism played directly into Epicurus’s ethical philosophy. Since all existent things are made of atoms that come together and eventually come apart, the human soul must also be made of atoms and come apart when the body dies. At that point all consciousness ceases. Because there is no longer any sensation after death, humans need not fear what will happen to them. By removing the fear of death, one has the chance to attain happiness (defined as the absence of perturbation) in this life. The gods exist and are immortal, but they have no care for the affairs of mortals; they neither reward nor punish, nor can they be prayed to. Epicurus allowed for the veneration of the gods and their emulation as models of unperturbedness (ataraxia); he even condoned participation in civic rituals. He also censured the atheists just discussed, including Prodicus and Diagoras. But like the earlier atomists he saw no role for the gods in the creation or sustenance of the cosmos. He did not believe in any form of providence—even the limited kind one finds in Plato or Aristotle, in which god (Plato) or nature (Aristotle) makes everything for the best. The gods are happy because they have nothing to do with the affairs of men. God is happy “because he cares for nothing.”27 Epicurus’s reputation was also not helped by the work of his most fervent disciple, the Roman poet Lucretius (94–55 b.c.e). Little is known of Lucretius’s life apart from the doubtful report of St. Jerome in the fourth century c.e. that he suffered from insanity and committed suicide by overdosing on a love potion. Lucretius’s poem On the Nature of Things, which more or less accurately encapsulates Epicurus’s teachings, harks back to the tradition of Empedocles in using poetry as a medium for philosophical ideas. Modern research shows that many lines of the poem are close translations of the Epicurean texts that survive. But on one crucial point Lucretius deviated from his master. Epicurus had urged tolerance of religion, even recommending participation in order to contemplate the happiness of the gods. Lucretius would have none of that. Religion, which he equated with superstition, was the root of all human evils.28 If there ever was a poster boy for ancient atheists, Lucretius was it. In a famous passage near the opening of book 1, he wrote: When human life lay foul before men’s eyes, crushed to the dust beneath religion’s weight (from the high realm of heaven she showed her face an hideous grimace of terror to mortal men) a man of Greece [Epicurus] first dared to raise the eye of mortal against her, first stood ground against her. … And now religion in turn beneath our feet is trampled; the victory makes us match for heaven.29 60 60 the anatomy of my th Epicurus and Lucretius were generally viewed as a single soul and mind by almost everyone from Roman antiquity onward until separated by modern scholars. Lucretius had attributed to his mentor many of the vehement anti- religious feelings that were his alone. Anaxagoras, Diagoras, Protagoras, Socrates, and Aristotle—all faced or were threatened with a charge of atheism or impiety. Anaxagoras, Diagoras, Euripides, and Aristotle fled Athens, thereby very likely escaping a death sentence. Protagoras was tried, but exonerated. Epicurus was never charged. Socrates alone suffered the extreme penalty. There is no clear evidence in the surviving writings of any of these thinkers (Socrates left no writings, but there are several reports of what he supposedly said) of categorical denials of the existence of the gods. Outright expressions of atheism were confined to characters in literary works: Critias’s Sisyphus and Euripides’ Bellerophon. Protagoras’s statement about the gods is agnostic. For the rest, their “crimes” consisted of debunking of popular myths, redefining the gods in accordance with current standards of justice and morality, and naturalistically explaining the workings of the universe that dispense with divine agency. The tally of executions in Athens was one, and book burnings two. In comparison to the reign of terror that occurred under the Inquisition, the religious persecutions in sixteenth-and seventeenth-century England, or the Salem witch trials in America, life for intellectuals in Athens was not so bad. But the fact that oppression and censorship occurred at all is clear proof that the intellectuals had made a strong impact on traditional beliefs, especially beliefs about the gods. More than a century of revolutionary developments in natural philosophy followed by a half century of the sophistic movement had made an indelible mark. The schools of philosophical skepticism that developed in the late fourth century b.c.e. and continued into late antiquity were the heirs of the sophists.30 What rattled the authorities as much as atheism was the pervasive idea of the sophists that truth was relative to the perceptions of individuals. The notion that hot and cold as determined by each person’s perception of them31 might be extended, like elastic, into the realms of physics and theology was deeply unsettling to many. So was the idea that every people considers its own customs the best, and that it is madness to mock or deride the customs of others, even when they appear to be absurd or barbarous.32 Some of the oppression was politically motivated; some can be explained by a climate of fear induced by the long Peloponnesian Wars and their aftermath. But every society has its share of anti-intellectuals and traditionalists—people who are not amused by anti-religious jokes like that of Diagoras, or the reputed epitaph on the tomb of Anaxagoras, which claimed that the deceased was now the equal of a god, because neither of them existed. There are some probable explanations for the fact that persecution of intellectuals was not worse. There was no real “religious right” like that found in 61 flirting with atheism 61 America today. The religion of the polis had prescribed sacrifices, but it had no prescribed creed. There were no articles of faith in which everyone was compelled to believe. Most importantly, there were no sacred books, no revelation, no Word of God. Philosophers were not required to validate their arguments by citing passages from the Iliad or the Theogony in the way that medieval theologians were expected to justify their teachings with scripture. This relatively free climate created in ancient Greece cleared the path for public discourse about the things people held most sacred and allowed for the dissemination of ideas in published form. The ancient world remained open to discussion and debate regarding ideas about god and the origin of the cosmos. Rome, provincial and conservative in its early years, became a champion of intellectual freedom, welcoming Greek intellectuals of all persuasions to Rome after its conquest of Greece in 146 b.c.e. However, even though the Romans learned to speak and think in Greek,33 they did not adopt Greek law. Atheism was not a capital crime in Rome. Vergil, Rome’s greatest poet, studied with an Epicurean philosopher at Naples (though the doctrine left little if any trace in his writings). Cicero’s philosophical treatises were heavily influenced by Greek skepticism. This state of affairs lasted until Christianity achieved complete hegemony in the Roman Empire at the end of the fourth century c.e. Even then, the state was mainly interested in suppressing pagan religious practices and Christian heresy. This, of course, would have included open expressions of atheism, but not the books that supported it. Philosophy limped on in Athens until the Emperor Justinian shut the Academy in 529 c.e. However, the books of the ancient philosophers were never banned, either in the East or in the West, while the poets continued to be read and studied in medieval monasteries. Even Lucretius survived, thanks to the dedication of the ninth-century monks who copied his work in “barbarian” Europe. For the most part, Christians seemed interested in burning one another’s books, not the pagan classics. The infamous “Index of Prohibited Books” had to await the glories of the Renaissance; it was first published in 1559. 62 63 5 Attacking Poetry As we saw in previous chapters, the attacks on the two poets “who educated Greece” began very early. Criticisms by Xenophanes and Heraclitus have already been discussed. Another of the great thinkers of that period was the mathematician Pythagoras, best known for his theorem of the right triangle. Born on the Isle of Samos in the sixth century, he later migrated to southern Italy to the settlement of Croton, where he became “a legislator for the Italians.”1 As Pythagoras, like Socrates, left no writings, very little that is certain is known of his genuine teachings or his life. One apocryphal tale relates how he descended into Hades and encountered the shades of Homer and Hesiod. He saw the spirit of Hesiod, tied to a column of iron, howling; Homer’s shade is suspended from a tree and surrounded by snakes. Such were their punishment for the vile things they had said about the gods.2 The legend reinforces the impression that there was growing criticism of the two great poets on the basis of what they said about the gods. Heraclitus’s criticism was somewhat more “philosophical”; he criticized Hesiod for failing to understand the unity of opposites. He also rebuked Homer for not understanding that strife was not only necessary but good.3 However, it did not occur to anyone of this early period to bring poetry itself into disrepute. There is a very good reason for this. Poetry was the preferred medium of a number of the early cosmologists and philosophers. Xenophanes, Parmenides, and Empedocles all employed verse for the discussion of philosophical issues. The use of verse was believed to be a more effective medium than prose for impressing the memory. Poetry was also believed to lend “sweetness” to thoughts and provide natural pleasure. Finally, it added a feeling of gravity, or dignity, to words that expressed the great mysteries of the cosmos. Moreover, if indeed some sixth-century thinkers viewed Homer and Hesiod as the earliest cosmologists, those thinkers would have seen themselves as following in a great tradition, even if the purpose of their writing was to contradict the earlier poets. This speculation received support from Aristotle writing two centuries 64 64 the anatomy of my th later. He was willing to entertain the notion that “one might suspect that Hesiod was the first to look for such a thing [that is, the cause of the cosmos].”4 Aristotle, however, also recognized that by his day the word “poetry” had become ambiguous. For some it continued to mean simply a particular medium of speech involving a particular way of arranging words and sounds in rhythmical patterns. Any writer who employed verse was by definition a poet, and his work, poetry. For others, a new meaning had emerged. Poetry was the medium for expressing myths. Greek epic was about myths and legends, and drama even more so. Lyric poets like Pindar also incorporated myths into their poems. On the other hand, writers who purported to treat a subject factually were turning to the medium of prose. Even before Plato, philosophers had begun to use prose, and prose was the medium for both Plato and Aristotle. Aristotle attempted to disambiguate the problem of the content of poetry; however, he did not pose a dichotomy between poems that contained myths and those that did not, but rather between poems that contained mimēsis (imitation) and those that do not. In his preliminary discussion of the concept of poetry in the Poetics he wrote: True, people do attach the making to the name of a metre and speak of elegiac-makers and hexameter-makers; they think, no doubt, that “makers” [that is, poets] is applied to poets not because they make mimēseis but as a general term meaning ‘verse-makers,’ since they call ‘poets’ even those who publish a medical or scientific theory in verse. But as Homer and Empedocles have nothing in common except their metre, the latter had better be called a scientific writer, not a poet, if we are to use ‘poet’ of the former.5 The Greek word mimēsis means literally “an act of imitation.” For Aristotle, this presumably included everything that we call fiction. It is possible that he felt that it was no easy task to disentangle the historical from the mythical material in the early poets, and so avoided the division “mythological” and “non-mythological.” It seems that his teacher Plato had suffered no qualms about doing just that. Plato does not explicitly refer to the didactic (scientific and philosophical) poetry mentioned by Aristotle. Rather, he simply equates the term “poetry” with mythological content, and “poets” with purveyors of myth. Thus the subject matter of poetry is fiction. And fiction is, well, false. And what is false cannot be good, unless placed in the service of some noble purpose (Plato’s “noble lie”). At the end of his long discussion of poetry in book 10 of the Republic, Plato refers to the “old quarrel between poetry and philosophy.”6 He then cites several disparaging comments about poetry that apparently were proverbial: “the yapping bitch that barks at her master,” “a great man amid the vanity of fools,” and “the rabble of know-all heads,” and “thin thinkers starve.” Myths are 65 at tacking poetry 65 fictions (plasmata), as Xenophanes had already noted, and the creators of these fictions are poets. Plato writes in reference to Homer and Hesiod, “For it’s the poets who told men, and still tell them, the false stories they themselves compose [emphasis added].”7 The responsibility for telling lies to men is laid directly at the door of the poets. Plato does not refer here, as he does elsewhere, to inspiration (Ion 533– 34) or madness (Phaedrus 245a)—the notion that the gods (Apollo, the Muses) plant a voice in poets and tell them what to sing. On the contrary, he imagines poets sitting at home consciously thinking up lies to spread to their unsuspecting neighbors. This is not unlike the thought process that Critias attributed to his politician, who, faced with unsolved crimes on his watch, stayed up all night fretting, until he found a way to frighten men into virtue by instilling fear of a god who could see everything. There is something jarring to current thinking about the origin of myths in all this. We are accustomed to think of myths as stories that belong to an untraceable past. We can sometimes identify innovations in these stories— intrusions of elements that can be pinpointed to a particular time and culture (for example, aetiologies of institutions, mention of a particular local type of dress or diet)—but the main structures nearly always elude dating and localization. It is now known that a good many myths we think of as Greek come from elsewhere, particularly the near East. We prefer to think that the Greeks adapted these “inherited” stories to their own conditions. Accordingly, poets— whether epic writers like Homer or dramatists like Sophocles—took stories that were once transmitted orally and put them into a new form. Today we would call this process “repackaging.” However, Plato was not the first Greek thinker to espouse the theory that myths were invented by poets. About three generations before Plato, the historian Herodotus spoke of Homer and Hesiod as “the poets who composed (poiēsantes) our theogonies and described the gods for us.”8 And three or four generations before Herodotus, Xenophanes had attacked Homer and Hesiod for telling shameful stories about the gods. However, Plato was well aware of another theory of the creative process. Plato knew his Hesiod well. Yet he chose to ignore Hesiod’s narrative of the Muses who chided him on Mount Helicon into composing his song. Hesiod essentially says to his readers, “Even if you don’t believe in the Muses, please realize that the stories I am about to tell aren’t really my own. I didn’t make them up. They are old stories that were recited long before me. All I did was to put them together in a new way.” Plato’s oversight here is all the more strange, since in other works he showed that he was clearly conscious of the notion of poetic inspiration, and believed it to be indispensable for poetry of true genius: “Third is the possession and madness of the Muses. Gripping the delicate and untouched mind, it rouses it to frenzy in songs and other poems, and by its adornment of innumerable deeds of the ancients, it educates posterity.”9 There his words appear to approach Hesiod’s description of the process: the 66 66 the anatomy of my th Muses insert a divine voice in the poet so that he can fittingly sing the things they order. We find a contemporary echo of this idea in the words of Claude Lévi-Strauss, who wrote in his Myth and Meaning, “I don’t have the feeling that I write my books. I have the feeling that my books get written through me.”10 Aristotle seems to have anticipated our modern distinction between repackaging old stories and inventing new ones. In advising would-be dramatists, he writes, “So one need not try to stick at any cost to the traditional stories, which are the subject of tragedies; indeed, the attempt would be absurd, since even what is well known is well known only to a few, but gives pleasure for all that.”11 Just before that he mentioned a play by Antheus, where “both the names [of characters] and the events are made up.” Thus, Aristotle distinguished between traditional stories (he used the Greek word for “handed down”) and those that are invented by writers of his day or just before. Because Plato was pursuing a distinctly moral agenda in the Republic, he chose to ignore the distinction between traditional and invented stories, of which he was surely aware. In the first part of his discourse on poetry (Rep., book 2) Plato brings two accusations against the poets: (1) poets tell untrue things (myths); (2) the myths are harmful to people, especially the young. In making the first charge Plato shows his awareness that myths need not be understood literally. He raises the possibility of understanding stories allegorically, and then discards the technique as unhelpful, since children cannot distinguish the allegorical from the non-allegorical. It is instructive to note that his pupil Aristotle expressed no interest in the literal truth of stories and made no reference to allegory: In answer to the charge of not being true, one can say, “But perhaps it is as it should be”: Sophocles, for example, said that he represented people as they should be, and Euripides as they are here; this is the answer. If it is neither true nor as it should be, one can reply, “But it is what people say.”12 Aristotle knew that the charge came initially from Xenophanes, who, he admitted, may have been right, but his reaction was to shrug. The shrug is part and parcel of Aristotle’s appeal to today’s readers and “consumers” of other forms of mimetic culture such as film. We realize when we approach fiction, we must suspend our disbelief, and look for a different kind of truth. Aristotle put this most forcefully when he wrote, “That is why poetry is at once more like philosophy and more worthwhile than history, since poetry tends to make general statements, while those of history are particular.”13 Plato, however, had he debated with his pupil, would not have been satisfied with the words just quoted. It is well and good for poets to make general statements, but they have a duty to ensure that the statements are true. There is a disjunction between what Homer and Hesiod said about the gods and 67 at tacking poetry 67 what the gods truly are. This is the essence of Xenophanes’ original critique on which Plato built. Xenophanes was the first to realize that the idea of god espoused by enlightened men of his generation was radically different from the images projected by the epic poets. The paradigm had undergone a seismic shift. God was not like men either in physical form or mental activity. There is one who is the most powerful. He is stationary and accomplishes everything with the power of his mind. He doesn’t have to rush about from one place to another to see what is going on, because he is able to know everything “from his holy resting place.” Plato took this insight and developed it. A common motif of the Iliad and the Odyssey is the shape-shifting god. Homer seemed to insist that this power belonged to the nature of divinity when he wrote, “in guise of foreign strangers gods visit cities in every manner of shape” (Od. 17, 485–86). Plato portrays Socrates discussing this passage in an exchange with his disciple Adimantus: S. Then in general whatever is in a good condition, as a result of art or nature or both, admits the minimal change from external influence? A. So it seems. S. But god and what is god’s is in every way exceedingly good? A. Of course. S. So from this point of view god can’t have “many shapes”? A. No. S. But might he change and vary himself? A. He must if he varies at all. S. Well, then, does he change himself for better or for worse? A. For worse, inevitably, if he does vary: for we can’t say that a god is defective in beauty or goodness. S. Quite right. And that being so, Adimantus, do you think any god, or man, would voluntarily make himself worse in any way? A. Impossible. S. Impossible, therefore, for god to want to vary himself. Every god, being exceedingly beautiful and good, remains always simply, so far as possible, in his own shape. A. Necessarily so.14 We are left with this conclusion: God being god has the power to change himself, but because he is both exceedingly good and beautiful, he would never desire to do this. Any change from perfection would be a change for the worse. The true nature of god remains constant, and any story that says otherwise is false. Aristotle and Plato were surely talking at cross purposes. Aristotle would not care if a play contained an episode in which a god appeared in disguise. “Such is the story,” he would say, and probably add that shape shifting is not 68 68 the anatomy of my th the point of the play. What matters is the general statement about human character and action that can be derived from the mimēsis. This is what people in the audience take home with them. This is what brings poetry close to philosophy. However, even if we dismiss Plato’s concern with the literal truth of poetry as wrongheaded, it is harder to disregard his second point, namely, that many of the traditional myths are harmful. In arguing the case he goes well beyond Xenophanes, whose sole concern was the truth quotient of the poets’ portrayal of the gods. Xenophanes notes that the poets attribute to the gods everything that is disgraceful among men, but stops short of pursuing the moral implications for society. Plato’s objective is very different. In the Republic he is envisioning the ideal polity. The correct education of its citizens is central to this aim. It does no good to put a philosopher-king in charge, or install a police force (Plato’s “guardians”), if the majority of the citizens cannot tell right from wrong. The means to right moral conduct is right education. Every harmful influence must be removed. The gods must be portrayed in the best possible light, and likewise the mortal role models, that is, the heroes. These models must be impressed on the malleable minds of children like seals on wax. In Plato’s day (and long afterward) the poems of Homer and Hesiod were at the heart of the curriculum. Children grew up with these poems and learned portions of them by rote. Nursemaids responsible for educating children at home would have provided another source of fable. Such were called “old wives’ tales” then as they are now.15 When children got older, they would become acquainted with other myths by attending the theater. Thus, a knowledge of many traditional stories was not dependent on literacy, though doubtless by the fourth century there was an educated class, at least in Athens, that wanted their children to learn to read. But just as the Old Testament contains a good number of stories you would not like your children to hear uncensored, the same holds true for the Iliad, the Odyssey, and the Theogony. Plato gives a notorious example from the Theogony: To begin with, the greatest falsehood, involving the greatest issues, was wrongly told by the person who said that Ouranos did what Hesiod said he did and that Kronos took his revenge upon him. What Kronos did and what happened to him at his son’s hands is something I should not want to be told without precaution to the young and foolish, even if it had been true.16 Plato alludes here to the notorious episode near the beginning of the Theogony in which Gaia complains to her son Kronos of Ouranos’s brutality, and Kronos takes a sickle of iron and removes Ouranos’s testicles. An equally rebarbative episode follows: Kronos, in order to forestall attempts by his children to overthrow him, swallows them whole (Theog. 137ff., 453ff.). Plato gives other 69 at tacking poetry 69 examples concerning family violence in the Olympian household: Hera tied up by her son, Hephaestus thrown out by his father for defending his mother, and the battles of gods. He adds, “All this is inadmissible, whether it was composed allegorically or not. Young people can’t distinguish the allegorical from the non-allegorical, and what enters the mind at that age tends to become indelible and irremovable.”17 The argument will resonate with many people today. Psychologists and other experts seem to be locked in a never-ending debate over the effects of films, television, and video games on children and young adults. For adults who predate the video game era, the levels of violence portrayed is often shocking. However, a direct link between heavy use of these media and violent crime has so far eluded proof. Yet many adults continue to worry that even if their kids who enjoy blowing up heads on screens don’t become axe murderers, they might still suffer effects on their moral development. The same type of debate carries over into pornography and sexuality. Plato’s response to the danger was censorship. All the stories of the poets that present negative stereotypes of the gods or of the heroes must be snipped out. Today parents block their children’s channels and time the Internet access to go off before bedtime. They give their darlings wholesome books and learning games as Christmas and birthday presents. Sometimes it works; sometimes it doesn’t. Plato’s attack on poetry presented a quandary for legislators and educators in his day. It was easy to applaud his deep concern for morality in education and his desire to foster the best values (respect for the gods, one’s parents, the homeland) in young citizens. On the other hand, he wanted to black out large stretches of text in Greece’s two greatest poets, the ones “who educated Greece.” Let us see what that would mean in our terms. Many jurisdictions in North America are familiar with cases in which groups of parents (often only a few people) appear before school boards and demand that a book be withdrawn from the curriculum or from school libraries. But imagine groups of parents going to pastors of churches or teachers in Bible schools and demanding that large swaths of text in the Bibles used by the children be blacked out. These would be the stories that portray God as cruel or unjust, or the patriarchs engaged in immoral or inappropriate behavior—there is no shortage of passages that would qualify. Imagine the reaction! The poems of Homer and Hesiod may not have had religious sanction, but they were the most authoritative books the Greeks possessed. No one, even Plato, would be allowed to tamper with them. Whether his fellow citizens agreed with him or not, Plato surely touched a chord when he leveled his moral criticism of poetry. The arguments he put forth in book 2 of the Republic are easy for a lay person to understand. Plato, however, reserved the last part of his critique for the philosophers. His most original and lasting contribution to philosophy was his theory of ideas (forms). According to this doctrine, which Plato formulates in book 10 of the Republic, 70 70 the anatomy of my th ideas, which have no material reality of any kind, are the most real “things” that exist. They are permanent and unchanging and therefore the only things of which one can have true knowledge. (Plato gives the examples of numbers and geometrical objects.) They are also the causes of material things, which are merely copies of the ideas. These material copies are in a constant state of change and for that very reason cannot be apprehended by the mind. They belong to the realm of opinion. Plato illustrated his theory with his famous “Allegory of the Cave.” In this parable we are all like persons imprisoned in a dark cavern illuminated only by a fire that causes shadows to be cast on the walls of the cave. These shadows constitute everything that the prisoners in the cave are able to perceive. The prisoners naturally regard these shadows not as representations but as real objects. However, one of the prisoners manages to escape and ascend to the earth, where he can see things in the light of the sun (which Plato identifies with “the Good”). He returns to the cave to teach the prisoners how things “really” are, but they just laugh at him. In book 10 of the Republic Plato applies his theory of ideas to the philosophy of art. He asserts that every art form, be it visual or verbal, is based on imitation (mimēsis). Painters and poets alike strive to imitate things in the material world as best they can. But these material objects are themselves only copies of the reality in which they “participate,” namely, ideas or forms. Works of art are therefore nothing but copies of copies—at a third remove from reality.18 We can infer from this that mimēsis by its nature bears responsibility for falsifying reality. An argument of this type would most likely not make much impact on ordinary citizens. Aristotle, however, was very aware of it and countered Plato’s dismissive notion of mimēsis with his own more positive theory: Mimesis is innate in human beings from childhood—indeed we differ from the other animals in being most given to mimesis and in making our first steps in learning through it—and pleasure in instances of mimesis is equally general.19 Aristotle, who liked to base his conclusions on observation, had probably noticed that infants learn to walk and speak by imitating adults or older children. He also realized that imitation was a source of pleasure in humans: “We enjoy looking at the most exact portrayals of things we do not like to see in real life, the lowest animals, for instance, or corpses.”20 Rather than oppose his former teacher head on by attacking his theory of ideas, Aristotle opted for presenting a more attractive alternative. Had ordinary people followed this debate on aesthetic principles, they would have most likely sided with Aristotle against Plato. What Aristotle had to say was tangible; it appealed to everyday experience. But this philosopher did not attempt to deviate too far from Plato’s 71 at tacking poetry 71 moral critique of the poets. The heroes represented in his ideal tragedies had to be “first and foremost morally good.”21 Epicurus, whom we met in the previous chapter, was another “enemy of poetry.” He would surely have been unhappy with Lucretius’s choice of poetry as a medium, and worse, his invocation of the goddess Venus as his Muse.22 He would, however, have approved of Lucretius’s attack on mythical accounts of the afterlife in book 3 of his poem, in which he discounts the terrors of the underworld described by Homer in the Odyssey: “No Tityos lies there, target of hellish buzzards.”23 Epicurus had no use for poetry and discouraged his disciples from reading it. It was a waste of time and took one’s attention away from philosophy. I surmise that Epicurus, like Plato, equated poetry with mythology, and mythology with lies about the gods’ true nature. Epicurus’s gods had bodies, yes, because all things that exist are material. But they were not the anthropomorphic gods of Homer. Nor did they have anything to do with humankind at any point, contrary to Homer’s interfering gods and Hesiod’s claim in the Theogony that gods and men once dined together. Poetry and the myths should be left alone. Nor would Epicurus have approved of Plato’s decision to write “better myths,” for any type of fable distorts the truths of philosophy. The complete rejection of myth and its uses such as we find in Epicurus (and earlier in Xenophanes) must be counted as one of the approaches used in the anatomy of myth. If myths do not represent “the things that are,” but rather “the things that are not,” only a foolish person would want to investigate them. In this view, all attempts to interpret myths are moot. To conclude, Aristotle may have won the battle over the theory of art, but the larger war over the moral nature of poetry ended in a stalemate at best. Moreover, Plato’s identification of poetry with myth, and myth with falsehood (seconded by Epicurus), was to survive the centuries. In the early part of the Renaissance of our era, the humanist and novelist Boccaccio felt himself impelled to mount up and tilt lances with the enemies of poetry once again. The adage “poets are liars” enjoyed a long shelf life. Not only the content of poetry, but poetry itself, was placed under lasting suspicion. 72 73 6 The Beginnings of Allegory We have just seen that Plato rejected the understanding of a work as “allegorically composed” as a suitable means of defending the traditional myths. He did not attack allegorical interpretation itself, but simply excluded it from the toolkit used for teaching literature to children. (Children take things literally; they do not understand figurative speech until they are older.) Plato’s statement is revealing for two reasons. First, it teaches us that because some people assumed that authors composed allegorically, it was legitimate to interpret allegorically. There was thus an assumption that there was a close relationship between the act of communicating and the process of reception or, stated otherwise, that a reader’s understanding of a text corresponded to the author’s intention. Second, his statement tells us that the assumption of a bond of meaning between the writer and the reader, or the speaker and the listener, was not new. Plato’s mention of allegory (composing and understanding) suggests that it was a familiar notion.1 Two questions pop up immediately: First, what did Plato mean by “allegory”? (His word for it was hyponoia, “the thought beneath”). Second, what do we know about the application of allegory before Plato? The basic concept is quite simple. The Greek term hyponoia (literally, “underthought”) refers to a thought or idea lurking below the surface of what is spoken or written that is at odds with what is expressed on the surface. Several centuries later, the term was replaced by allegoria, “to say something different,” that is, different from what the speaker or writer really means. Plutarch, in his On the Study of Poetry, was, I think, the first to signal that allegoria had replaced hyponoia as a hermeneutic term.2 They are really two words for the same thing. Initially, allegoria was a rhetorical term that meant to express a thought as an extended metaphor. But it came to mean to create an entire narrative in metaphorical speech; it simultaneously meant to understand a narrative in that way. Thus, both terms include both the compositional and interpretative aspects of the act of communication. 74 74 the anatomy of my th Modern scholarship has largely done away with the confusion between the compositional and interpretative sense of the term by introducing the word “allegoresis” to cover interpretation, reserving “allegory” for the literary genre, or for parts of a work thought to be allegorically “encoded.” The process of encoding an allegory entails a system of substitutions. The ancients regularly substituted the name of a god for the element with which the god was associated. If, for example, we parse the proverb from Terence (Eunuchus 729), “Without Bacchus and Ceres Venus grows cold,” we should not be tempted to feel pity for a shivering goddess who has lost her friends, but understand that we are being advised to eat bread and drink wine as fuel for sexual intercourse. The code is simple. For Bacchus, Ceres, and Venus we should understand wine, bread, and sex in that order. The god and goddesses in the saying lose all trace of individuality, and are reduced to a single product of nature or natural function. We continue to employ code to exclude individuals or groups that we do not want to understand a message, while including those with whom we wish to share it.3 Fables and myths (the first term is just the Latin equivalent of the second, which is Greek) break down into different types, as modern students of mythology and narratology are aware. In the fables of Aesop, animals represent particular human character types. For example, in the fable of the fox and the crow, the fox represents human cunning, while the crow is a victim of her own vanity. In the “myths” of Plato different symbols are used to represent the mind and soul and psychic activities. In the Phaedrus the soul is represented as a chariot driven by a winged charioteer who is trying to control two winged horses flying in different directions. In the works of the major poets certain passages can be isolated from the main narrative and treated as fables. A prime example is Homer’s lascivious tale of the adultery of Ares and Aphrodite (Od. 8, 266–366), sung by the bard Demodocus for the entertainment of the guests. The three types mentioned belong to different genres of literature, and are not identical in their structure. However, they share a common element that is easily perceived. None of them can be understood literally. The ancient critics, aware of these fabrications, could readily believe that the earlier writers made up fables and deliberately encoded them. All of the stories are true once it is determined that they contain coded messages. Foxes and crows do not talk, and crows do not usually feed on cheese (nor would a fox dream up a plan to get cheese from a crow), but people are indeed vain and easily deceived by flattery. The tale could be reset as an allegory in which the fox is named Cunning, and the crow Vanity. Winged charioteers do not guide chariots pulled by winged horses, but human souls do experience inner conflict between higher and lower emotions, and such conflicts make it difficult to live rationally. The charioteer is Reason, and the horses are Indignation and Appetite (corresponding to Plato’s division of the soul in the Republic). Real gods do not commit adultery, but war and sex are 75 the beginnings of allegory 75 often found together. Ares is War and Aphrodite is Sex. Once the underlying meanings (the hyponoia) of these stories are revealed (once the codes are cracked), they cease to be lies. Each of the authors employed allegory, or so goes the reasoning. Another type of narrative was available to Greeks. This type involves characters that are personifications of a mental function or moral quality. A prime example is “Heracles at the Crossroads,” attributed to Prodicus of Ceos, 4 whom we met earlier as one of several suspected atheists. Prodicus’s story involves Heracles in his teenage years. The young hero came to a crossroads, where he met two imposing female figures, one who called herself Happiness (eudaimonia), though her enemies call her Vice (kakia); the other is named Virtue (aretē). Each delivered a speech to the hero, presenting a path of life available to him: Happiness tells of easy living and a life full of pleasure; Virtue presents a life filled with hardships and challenges but rich in intangible rewards. The two figures engage in a brief debate with each other. Heracles is left with the choice. A modern reader might immediately react to this tale by asking, “Where is the allegory?” What could have a more obvious meaning than a story about people named Happiness and Virtue? It might take a modicum of wit to figure out that Aesop’s fable of the mouse and the lion is really about people, but where is the puzzle here? The veil of vice and virtue covering two large females is very flimsy indeed. Such would also have been a normal reaction from Greeks living in the age of the sophists. They would have noticed that fables composed by Prodicus and Aesop are different from each other. Prodicus’s fable requires no interpretation. It interprets itself. The name given to the characters defines them in such a way as to exclude all other attributes or activities. Thus, Happiness can only be happy and only do things that are pleasurable, while Virtue must be virtuous at all times, and only perform virtuous acts. This type of fable is constructed so that one personified character is paired with another; the pairs can be conceived as oppositional or as complementary. Greek rhetorical theory, coming into adolescence in that age, would have provided them the name for this process: prosopopoeia, “creating a persona.” This figure was a trick of poets and rhetoricians and would have been recognized by educated persons for what it was. All of the above is true, but it is not completely satisfying. One must be ready to allow that the young hero en route to dispatch a lion or tidy up someone’s stables did not literally encounter two large ladies, one of whom was tarted up to a T, the other dressed in hand-me-downs. The encounter at the crossroads was doubtless meant by its author as an allegory of inner psychological conflict—a conflict between the natural urge to satisfy one’s bodily appetites and the appeal of reason to hold them in check so as to achieve greater things. The conflict is extended into a division between body and soul when Virtue says to Happiness, “While thy votaries are young their bodies are weak, when 76 76 the anatomy of my th they wax old, their souls are without sense.”5 Clearly the sophist Prodicus, a contemporary of Socrates, is revealing his awareness that body and soul are different things.6 But the description nonetheless counts as an allegory or code, for an action is described that could not have occurred, and the reader or listener must realize for himself that the story refers to a psychological event, not a real one. A naive mind, or one from an earlier time, might have heard Prodicus’s tale and believed that Heracles had had a real conversation with two oversized females blocking his path. “Heracles at the Crossroads” raises another problem. Happiness (also called Evil) and Virtue are abstractions, concepts of the mind, unless, of course one thinks of them as daimones, or spirits. But Heracles was a real person, or so most Greeks believed. (Even the skeptical Herodotus believed in his existence, though he doubted that the hero could singlehandedly overcome a large crowd of Egyptians intent on killing him.) We are left with the odd mixture of a character who is a “real person” and others who are not. For an enlightened interpreter, the two unreal characters are names of attributes that are self-explanatory. But is Heracles meant to be the actual hero known by that name, or rather as a symbol for all humans who must make the choice presented to them? And if the figure is meant to represent Everyman, what is the significance of the choice of Heracles rather than some other hero? Whatever the answers, Prodicus’s tale represents one type of the composed allegory: this consists of a god or great hero in situations in which the other characters are abstractions, or personifications of one concept or another. The other type dispenses with personified abstractions, and employs gods only, or gods and heroes together, but in such a way that each figure is restricted to a single meaning. An example is the “Judgment of Paris,” which has a cast that includes a hero (Paris) and three goddesses (Aphrodite, Athena, and Hera), each serving as a personification of a particular virtue.7 In both types only two kinds of action can be represented in the narrative: conflict or harmony. The first can be shown as represented by debate or physical battle, the second by a love affair or marriage. We need to push further back to answer the question of how earlier thinkers devised the theory that Homer and Hesiod were writing fables that were meant to be read allegorically. We need look no further than Hesiod’s Theogony for examples. Numerous passages of Hesiod’s masterpiece are rich in personification. The personified figures embrace natural phenomena such as air, earth, or sky, or attributes of the soul or mind such as reason, emotions, virtues, and vices. Following the principles for composed allegories, the tale of the natural pair Earth and Sky that occurs at the beginning is framed as conflict; at the end of the work, Zeus’s successive marriages to goddesses are lodged in complementarity. Three of Zeus’s brides are personifications of mental functions or virtues: Themis (Right or Good Order), Metis (Wisdom), and Mnemosyne (Memory). These attributes of the soul are required in order to 77 the beginnings of allegory 77 ensure that Zeus will reign forever, and “to the end that no other should hold royal sway over the eternal gods” (Theog. 892–93). Because Zeus is wedded to these divine paragons of virtue, the narrative fulfills the principle of complementarity. In the initial allegory in Theogony, the character Earth can only be the earth, and the character Sky can only be the sky; the story of their violent separation is apparently a poetic way of saying that earth and sky were at one time intermingled, and then became separated. There we have an allegory of physical conflict, showing that allegories can relate to physical as well as psychological phenomena. Homer, too, engaged in what we would call personifications. In a much discussed passage in book 9 of the Iliad, the aged horseman Phoenix, who takes part in the embassy to assuage Achilles and persuade him to rejoin the battle, includes a fable that includes the personifications Ate (“Ruin”) and the Litai (“Suppliant Prayers”): For there are also the spirits of Prayer (Litai), the daughters of great Zeus, and they are lame of their feet, and wrinkled, and cast their eyes sidelong, who toil on their way, left far behind by the spirit of Ruin (Ate): but she, Ruin, is strong and sound on her feet, and therefore far outruns all Prayers, and wins into every country to force men astray; and the Prayers follow as healers after her. If a man venerates these daughters of Zeus as they draw near, such a man they bring great advantage, and hear his entreaty; but if a man shall deny them, and stubbornly with a harsh word refuse, they go to Zeus, son of Kronos, in supplication that Ruin may overtake this man, that he be hurt, and punished. Homer concludes with the moral of the tale: So, Achilleus; grant, you also, that Zeus’ daughters be given their honour, which lordly though they be, curbs the will of others.8 In terms of structure, the “Ate and Litai fable” is a close parallel to “Heracles at the Crossroads.” In each fable a god or great hero (Zeus and Heracles, respectively) is asked to arbitrate between the rival claims of personified mental forces: those of Ruin versus Spirits of Prayer, or Happiness versus Virtue. A topsy-t urvy instance is the “Judgment of Paris,” when a mortal (Paris) is asked to arbitrate a beauty contest (Miss Olympus) among three goddesses (Aphrodite, Hera, and Athena). While we may safely assume that in the age of the sophists a writer such as Prodicus meant to compose an allegory, we cannot be sure that the oldest poets, Homer and Hesiod, had any such idea. It can be argued that they thought of the characters we call “personifications” as real gods or daimones (though I personally am skeptical). However, for the 78 78 the anatomy of my th history of interpretation none of this matters. What matters is that interpreters believed that the poets were concealing physical or mental forces with the name of a god or daimōn. Both poets employed a code of substitution. Not only were minor daimones such as Ate to be understood as names for a mental disturbance, but the great gods themselves were made a part of the code. The gods could represent elements of the cosmos or forces of the mind or soul, as context demanded. This is the view we encounter in a text generally thought to be the earliest example of allegorical interpretation; it is a fragment of a work on Homer by the grammarian Theagenes of Rhegium: There is an ongoing discussion about the gods with regard to the discordant, likewise the unseemly, for he [?]says that the myths about the gods are unseemly. With respect to that allegation there are those who release from exact wording, thinking that everything was said allegorically and pertain to the natural elements, for example, in the case of their opposition. For they say that the hot struggles against the cold, and the light against the heavy. Moreover, water is what puts out fire, while fire is that which dries up water. Similarly, opposition exists among all the elements out of which the whole is constituted and undergoes destruction in part at certain times, but persists forever as a whole. And he [Homer] sets out various battles, giving fire the names Apollo, Helios, and Hephaestus, water the names Poseidon and Scamander, the moon Artemis, the air Hera, and so forth. In a similar way names of the gods are distributed to [mental] conditions, e.g. Athena to reasoning, Ares to immoderation, Aphrodite to desire, Hermes to speech, and they [the poets?] ascribe them to these ones. This mode of defence is very ancient, and [comes] from Theagenes of Rhegium, who was the first to write about Homer, and this [method] is away from literal interpretation.9 The information contained in this fragment passed through several stages of editing. Even before the Homer scholiast excerpted Porphyry, and Porphyry (fourth century c.e.) excerpted Theagenes, philosophers may have inserted their own version of what Theagenes said. Moreover, the fragment leaves important questions unanswered, as we don’t know who is meant to be the subject of “says” in the first sentence, and in other places it is not clear who is speaking. But there are, however, a few takeaways: (1) there has been an accusation (katēgorian) that an unnamed writer spoke inappropriately about the gods; (2) a group of defenders argued against literal interpretation and proposed that everything was spoken allegorically; (3) the names of the gods were given by an unnamed writer to the battling elements and also to some mental conditions; (4) the defense of allegory was first used by Theagenes of 79 the beginnings of allegory 79 Rhegium. It is likely, then, that allegorical interpretation arose out of the need to defend the ancient poets. If Theagenes worked in the final quarter of the sixth century b.c.e., as is generally agreed,10 he could well have been responding to Xenophanes of Colophon, who, as we will recall, had accused Homer and Hesiod of saying everything shameful about the gods, accusing them of theft, adultery, and deceiving one another. The hypothesis gains credibility if we suppose that Xenophanes was already active in Elia, as his book could easily have reached a reader in Rhegium (modern Reggio di Calabria). The discussion of the opposition of the elements just cited brings Heraclitus back into discussion. Heraclitus had rebuked the author of the line (Homer), “ ‘Would that strife might be destroyed from among gods and men’: for there would be no musical scale unless high and low existed, nor living creatures, without male and female, which are opposites.”11 Strife (eris) was also Heraclitus’s principle of motion; it stood in opposite to Hesiod’s catalyst for movement, Attraction (erōs). Strife among the gods (theomachia), portrayed in Hesiod’s battle of the gods, was later censured by Plato as a tale unworthy of the divine nature, even though he was aware that it was among the tales that had been interpreted allegorically. We may imagine that before Plato, and probably even before Xenophanes, the theomachia had been added to the catalogue of bad stories about the gods. These would include the castration of Ouranos by Kronos, Kronos swallowing his children (both from Theogony), Zeus suspending Hera in the sky and hurling Hephaestus from Olympus (Iliad), and the adultery of Ares and Aphrodite (Odyssey). To these “bad stories” was added the unbelievable ones. Chief among these was Odysseus’s description of the doings in the underworld and the punishments allotted to the Titans who had offended Zeus. It is possible that there were earlier efforts to interpret the names of the gods allegorically. It has been argued that Pherecydes the Syrian, born around 600 b.c.e., was an early exponent.12 But I believe we are on more solid ground with Theagenes, as a treatise on Homer is ascribed to him, and according to the author of the fragment cited, “he was the first to write about Homer.”13 His work can be dated after the Pisistratan text of Homer and arguably after Xenophanes’ critique of Homer and Hesiod. Moreover, because the strife of the gods is a central point in the fragment, we can connect him to the arguments of Heraclitus, who flourished not much later than Xenophanes. Between Theagenes and Plato there were others who engaged in allegory of both the physical and moral type delineated by Theagenes. Among these were the Cynic philosophers Antisthenes and Diogenes. According to Antisthenes, Odysseus was a symbol of self-control, which enabled him to overcome the spells of Circe. Diogenes allegorized Circe as the embodiment of pleasure.14 The defenders of poetry adhered to the position that Homer and Hesiod, “the teachers of all of Greece,” could not have erred; certainly they could not 80 80 the anatomy of my th have deliberately lied. Hence, the poets doubtless had something else in mind when they related the stories that Plato and others objected to. The job of the critic was to preserve the authority of the poet and the text by uncovering the text’s true meaning. At the same time, it was intuited that people who lived earlier held childish views about the origins of the world, the gods, and the afterlife. The causes of their simple ideas could be explained by applying rationalist principles. A common modus operandi consisted in interpreting the name of a monster as a misunderstanding of some natural phenomenon. Practically all ancient allegorical criticism assumes that the intention of the poet can be recovered. It also assumes that the intention contains a truth that has been obscured by ambiguous language. As we have seen, the earliest critics of the poets thought of them not only as great teachers (thus Xenophanes, Herodotus), but also as serious cosmologists (Heraclitus); thus, it was possible to believe their poems contained deep philosophical and cosmological truths that only awaited decoding. However, well before the new discipline of rhetoric introduced the figure of personification—a kind of magic wand that could turn a god or daimōn into a figure of speech—t he interpreters of myths knew how to decode the anthropomorphic gods of the poets as little more than symbols of natural phenomena. Xenophanes, who detested the poets’ anthropomorphic gods, also said that Iris was just a name for a rainbow, and Helios (“the sun”) was just a ball of burning clouds. Prodicus, who gave us the fable of “Heracles at the Crossroads,” also theorized that early humankind had given the name of “god” to the things beneficial to human life. He was followed in his opinions by the curious Metrodorus of Lampsacus, thought to be a student of Anaxagoras.15 Whereas Prodicus’s interest lay in explaining how humans came to their conception of the gods, Metrodorus was concerned with interpreting the poets. Several fragments survive that attest to his physical explanations of Homer. And with regard to the customs and laws that are relevant to men, (he said that) Agamemnon is the aether, Achilles the sun, Helen the earth, and Paris the air, Hector the moon, and the others analogously named for such things. Of the gods Demeter is the liver, Dionysus the spleen, Apollo the gall.16 Although the association of divinities with parts of the anatomy is startling, a partial explanation can be derived from Metrodorous’s statement of principle in the following: And Metrodorus of Lampsacus in his work on Homer discoursed, quite cheerfully reducing everything to allegory. For Zeus and Hera 81 the beginnings of allegory 81 and Athena are not what those who dedicate precincts and sanctuaries think, but are natural phenomena and arrangements of the elements. And you can say that all Hector and Achilles and Agamemnon and all the Greeks in general as well as the barbarians, together with Helen and Paris, all being of the same nature, were introduced for the sake of (literary) management, as none of the people just mentioned existed.17 Metrodorus, like Theagenes, made his remarks in a (lost) treatise on Homer. He taught that Homer disguised the gods as something else and invented fictitious humans—all for the sake of art. It is useful to remember that the anthropomorphic gods were latecomers to the scene. However, these gods—even as represented by the poets—never lost their association with the physical attributes with which they were associated. Zeus was forever connected to lightning (the Thunderbolt) and the weather; Poseidon was intimately bound up with the sea and water; Hades was the underworld and not much else; and Helios was always just the sun. Even when these gods developed human-like characteristics and stories expanding their personalities grew up around them, they retained a large portion of their original identities. Their natural aspects were preserved in their cults, and humans worshipped them because they provided all the benefits of nature (as Prodicus maintained). From there it is an easy step to reduce the gods to these associations, and to see them merely as metaphors for natural phenomena. If that is the case, then Metrodorus took a big step in the direction of atheism, breaking his ties with Ionian thinkers such as Anaximenes and Heraclitus, who, I think, genuinely believed their respective archai air and fire to be divine, endowed with the power of thought and the ability to initiate change and motion. As long as the gods retained “mind” they could be persons in some respect; this identity as persons ceased when they were metamorphosed into elements. In the leap from the Ionian archai to Metrodorus’s empty elements we can see the nexus between cosmology and literary criticism, between alterations of a paradigm and modes of interpretation. Doubtless the intellectuals who attempted to interpret the poets were aware of how the gods were received in popular cult. Recall, moreover, that the earliest attacks on the Homeric gods were related, not to their nature aspects, but to the human traits ascribed to them. These human traits consisted not only of their bodily characteristics but, more importantly their moral traits as well. Such indeed was the gist of Xenophanes’ and Plato’s attacks on Homer and Hesiod. Metrodorus pointedly makes use of this critique when he claims that the gods have been misrepresented. This is his message: the gods should be reduced to their nature associations, and all of the anthropomorphic trappings should be stripped away. Homer added them just to make a good story. 82 82 the anatomy of my th As already noted, Plato himself composed new “myths” to illustrate his philosophical doctrines. The noetic world is illustrated by the analogy of the charioteer and horses and the creation by the story told by Timaeus.18 If the greatest philosopher of antiquity—or so Plato was regarded—could adumbrate his deep doctrines with myths, why should the greatest sages before him (so runs the ancient logic) not have done the same? For the ancient interpreter, the bond of meaning between what was signified and how it was interpreted had to be unbreakable; otherwise, all attempts to find meaning in a text would be in vain. For those who believed that the poets were the authors of myths, poetry was the equivalent of myth, and myth the equivalent of allegory. Thus, for ancient exegetes it was theoretically possible to read entire poems allegorically, and so to decode them. Modern theory, however, does not assume that allegoresis is a legitimate mode of interpretation for every story, but only those narratives that structurally show the components of a composed allegory (such as “Heracles at the Crossroads,” or Homer’s tale of the Litai). Certainly, whole works should not be read as allegories. Most ancient critics, in practice, did not attempt to do that, and in most cases restricted interpretations to saving the appearances of passages in Homer and Hesiod that were criticized as immoral or unworthy of belief. In the final analysis, there can be little doubt that allegory as a mode of interpretation was born of a deeply felt need to defend the reputations of the founding poets—even to defend poetry itself. 83 7 Finding History in Myth Let us hope that Fable may, in what shall follow, so submit to the purifying processes of Reason as to take the character of exact history.1 With these words Plutarch begins his “Life of Theseus” in his great work, Lives of the Noble Greeks and Romans, or Parallel Lives. Plutarch (46–post 120 c.e.) was a talented essayist who turned his hand to numerous subjects, including philosophy, religion, and myth. However, his lasting fame is due to the Lives. There he pairs Theseus with Romulus, the respective founders of Athens and Rome. In doing this he recognizes that he is stepping beyond verifiable history into the realm of fable. Plutarch is fully cognizant of the risks facing him. He likens the venture to the work of geographers who “crowd into the edges of their maps parts of the world which they do not know about, adding notes in the margin to the effect that beyond this lies nothing but Scythian ice and frozen seas … prodigies and fictions.”2 Undeterred by either “Scythian ice or frozen seas,” Plutarch plunges into the cold murky waters of fable with the hope of reducing it to probable fact. It is one thing to collect what has been said about mythical figures who lived before the age of written documents. The Greeks were experts at this: mythography, the gathering of myths and genealogies, had been a respectable profession for centuries. However, it is quite another to make a selection of stories told about a particular hero and weave them together into anything like a credible biography. Now Plutarch had a great advantage, or so he thought. In his day there existed a number of accounts of Theseus thought to be reliable, as they were attached to authoritative names. Plutarch cites Demon, Philochorus, Paeon the Amathusian, and Dicaearchus, who are virtually unknown even to classical scholars, and the more familiar Pherecydes, Hellanicus, and Herodorus (though these names, too, would be “Greek” to all but the initiated). Sometimes he cites his sources to show that there was a consensus, as he does when he wanted to prove that Theseus made a voyage to the Amazons and 84 84 the anatomy of my th took one (Antiope) a prisoner. At other times, he cites a disagreement between the older accounts, and ventures to choose the more plausible story.3 In one instance Philochorus is judged more reliable than Demon, when he claims that Theseus bested Taurus, Minos’s general, in physical combat of some sort (wrestling?) rather than killing him, as Demon claimed. Plutarch’s treatment of the combat incident just cited requires both context and analysis. The biographer is relying on sources of which the oldest, Pherecydes of Athens, flourished in the fifth century b.c.e. 4 However, we have no idea quite how many centuries fell between this scholarly figure and Theseus, if Theseus existed at all. If he did exist, he has to be placed before the Trojan War, ca. 1200 b.c.e. One has to wonder what the source was of Pherecydes’ information, and what kind of information it was. We seem to be faced with a long succession of “authorities,” including Demon and Philochorus, who copied from one source or several, changing this or that detail as they saw fit. It would seem that everyone before Plutarch was skating on thin Scythian ice.5 But there is more to unpack than discrepancies in Plutarch’s sources. The account accepted by Plutarch of Theseus, Minos, and Taurus is a breathtaking bowdlerization of the traditional story: Minos, King of Crete, on account of an offense against him by the Athenians, demanded a yearly tribute of so many youths and maidens. These were shipped off to Crete, imprisoned in a labyrinth constructed by Daedalus, and devoured by the Minotaur, a monster held to have a human body and a bull’s head. Theseus, the son of Aegeus, king of Athens, volunteered to slay the Minotaur and rescue the surviving youths and maidens. On arrival in Crete he befriends Ariadne, daughter of Minos, who plants a string in the labyrinth for Theseus to follow so that he can find and dispatch the Minotaur. All goes as planned, including the slaying of the Minotaur. Theseus frees the youths and maidens and sails back to Athens with the tributary youths and maidens along with Ariadne, whom he has abducted. Before reaching home he dumps Ariadne on the Isle of Naxos. He nears the port in Athens, but having forgotten to hang out the white sail agreed upon, must suffer the death of his father, who saw a black sail instead and died. There is an intriguing piece of the story omitted in the synopsis above. Pasiphaë, the wife of Minos, conceived a passion for a bull (tauros in Greek). She enticed the artisan Daedalus to construct a figure of a cow in wood, which she entered in order to have intercourse with the bull. The coupling was successful, and the Minotaur resulted. If we examine Plutarch’s account of the entire saga, which he has pieced together from Philochorus, Damon, and perhaps others, we note the following: the Minotaur has entirely disappeared. The bull that impregnated Pasiphaë has become Minos’s general named Taurus, a fellow of nasty disposition and a skirt chaser (“he was accused of too near familiarity with Pasiphae,” thus Plutarch), but not 85 finding history in my th 85 an ogre. Theseus overpowers Taurus in a contest, but does not kill him. Ariadne falls madly in love with Theseus and goes with him willingly. Minos voluntarily relinquishes the tributary youths, being pleased at the humiliation of Taurus. Plutarch has magically transformed a tale of bestiality, cannibalism, bloodshed, and rape into a cartoon suitable for viewing by children twelve and under. His hero whips the bad guy’s hind parts, saves the world, and gets the girl. The processes employed here of making a tale that is both incredible and immoral into an account that might be believed, and is also morally acceptable, may strike us today as a silly exercise for anyone who does not work for Disney. However, if the intention is to turn a myth into a believable biography, then the processes gain some justification. First of all, minotaurs do not exist now. Plutarch did not believe in their existence, since neither he nor any of his friends had seen one nor knew anyone who had. If that is so, they probably never existed, for there is no reason to believe that the past was qualitatively different from the present.6 Minotaurs are a fiction, but that a man can be called Taurus is a fact. Moreover, if there is no monster in the labyrinth, then the youths and maidens were not eaten. Next, women as a rule don’t have intercourse with bulls, even inside the protective cover of a wooden cow. Fear of pain or physical damage would suppress the most powerful lust in almost every case. And even if the sex could be managed, it would not produce a hybrid monster. Whereas some ancient historians and collectors of myths took it for granted that mythical monsters existed, philosophers are not so easily satisfied. They would want to know if it was at all possible for hybrid creatures to come into being. Lucretius, though aware that nature produced its share of aberrations, set out to prove that nature could not make something out of unrelated parts: But there were no Centaurs, nor could at any time creatures of two double natures and two bodies, be built out of unrelated parts and substance on both sides; and here is the proof for even the dull of mind. First: at about three years, the horse has reached its prime; not so the child: for often still In sleep he’ll seek his mother’s milky breasts. Later, when horses are aging, and their strength and muscle are failing, as life runs toward its close, then, for the boy, the bloom of youth is just beginning, just starting to clothe his cheeks with down. Don’t then imagine that from the seed of man and horse, Centaurs could be confected and exist… . 7 86 86 the anatomy of my th Lucretius leaves his readers to conclude that, even if centaurs existed, no one would want to be one. Elsewhere (4, 722–47), he explains how images of hybrid creatures such as centaurs and scyllas are formed by the human mind. Plutarch, who was widely read in the philosophical literature, may well have known the Lucretian passages. However, it was not necessary to invoke a philosopher’s authority when he edited the minotaur out of his script. He could simply draw on a long Greek tradition of regarding such fantastic beings as ridiculous. Plutarch deals with another myth attached to Theseus in much the same way. He relates how he journeys with his close friend Pirithoüs to Epirus in order to abduct Cora, the daughter of King Aidoneus and his wife Persephone. The royal couple keep a large dog named Cerberus with whom potential suitors of their daughter must fight to gain her hand. This account is transparently a bowdlerization of the myth in which Theseus and Pirithoüs descend to the underworld (Hades) to abduct Persephone, also called Cora, or Kore. (The story, incidentally, is a riff on the tale of Heracles’ descent to Hades to steal Cerberus and bring it back to King Eurystheus). Plutarch doesn’t believe in the underworld or three-headed guard dogs, so he sets the story in a remote, but recognizable part of Greece (Epirus) on the surface of the earth, turns Hades, god of the underworld, into Aidoneus, an earthly king, and neglects to tell us how many heads the dog has. He also separates the traditional figure of Persephone (also called Kore) into mother and daughter, Persephone and Kore. Even though this is a myth of an abduction, I suspect that Plutarch the moralist may have wished to avoid inserting the additional crime of adultery into his account. Plutarch’s aim is to purify myth with reason. Once incredible or rebarbative details have been removed from a story, or explained as something else, a fable can be turned into history. The process is based on the premise that what is impossible today was always impossible. There never was a time when things were qualitatively different from what they are today. Humans may have been a little bigger in the past, but there were no giants. If perverse humans mate with animals today, they do not produce hybrid monsters. This means that there were never any minotaurs, centaurs, satyrs, or three-headed dogs. Moreover, there is no such thing as the underworld, where dead souls continue to exist in some state, and if there is, you can’t get there from here. Plutarch, on the other hand, was willing to put his faith in Amazons, who might threaten males but not credulity. They are, after all, human women. Like other women, they need males to impregnate them and provide them with offspring, even if they get rid of the males and rear the females. They live in remote places around the Black Sea, but then the Greeks already had planted some colonies there. Hate them and dread them if you like, but there is no reason to think they did not exist somewhere in Scythia.8 87 finding history in my th 87 I have spent some time on Plutarch’s “Life of Theseus” because it neatly exemplifies what had long been the practices of Greek writers attempting to capture an unreachable past—a past disconnected by centuries of illiteracy. If we place Homer in the eighth century b.c.e., we must accept the conclusion that five centuries intervened between the traditional date of the war and the oral composition of the Iliad. We must then believe that the preceding oral poets were capable of preserving details of the battles along with the names of the Greek heroes and their Trojan enemies in some semblance of a stable form for five centuries. We must allow additional time before Homer’s poem was written down before the work of writing “history” could begin. For the Greeks of the sixth century b.c.e., Homer provided the earliest account of people who spoke Greek, had recognizable Greek names, and could claim Greek descent through their genealogy. This presented a serious dilemma when the attacks on the poet and his poems began. Homer was all one had to cling to. Throw him out, and the baby goes out with the bathwater. The dilemma was even more serious when dealing with matter considered to predate the Trojan War, for which there were no sources that could be traced back even as far as Homer. What we know of the labors of Heracles, the career of Theseus, and the adventures of Jason are all dependent on written sources no older than ca. 500. The process of ordering, classifying, and rationalizing the earliest figures of Greek myth began in the fifth century with figures such as Hecataeus of Miletus, Pherecydes the Athenian, Herodorus, and Hellanicus. However, we detect in these very early mythographers the same confidence in the ability to purify myth as we find in Plutarch five centuries later. A fragment of Hecataeus tells us the following: Hecataeus of Miletus speaks thus: “I record these matters in a way that seems to me to be true. For the fables of the Greeks are as numerous as they are laughable, as it seems to me.”9 We learn this from another fragment: On the peak of Tainarus there is a temple that can be likened to a cave and before it a statue of Poesidon. Certain of the Greeks fabricated the story how Heracles brought up the hound of Hades to that place. Hecataeus of Miletus was not prepared to believe there was a path in a cave under the earth, nor was he persuaded there was an underground dwelling for the gods where shades are gathered. However, he discovered a likely explanation for the fable. A frightful snake was raised on Tainarus that was called “the hound of Hades” because anyone bitten by it died immediately from the 88 88 the anatomy of my th poison. And he stated that this same snake was brought by Heracles to Eurystheus.10 Neither Hecataeus nor Plutarch believed that there was a ferocious dog living underground to guard the dwelling of gods. Plutarch “solved” the problem of the “Theseus in the Underworld” episode by setting the story in a Greek kingdom on earth. Hecataeus used another device, asserting that the “hound of Hades” (Cerberus) was merely a name for a deadly snake. Neither Plutarch nor Hecataeus believed in the existence of Hades (the place). However, neither of them doubted the existence of Heracles (Plutarch frequently compares Theseus to him), or any of his exploits, provided that they could be explained as natural happenings. It is humanly possible for someone with sufficient courage to hunt down and kill a poisonous snake. Even the idea of having to perform a series of dangerous exploits for a cruel king is believable. But if one will purify a myth with reason, one must remove every trace of the supernatural and of divine interference with mortals. It is all right to depict mortals worshipping the gods, as religion is natural to humans. Just don’t let the gods do anything. As noted above, Hecataeus unravels the myth of the underworld with the explanation that “hound of Hades” was merely a name given to a baneful serpent. The idea of explaining away a prodigy as nothing more than a name had a long history. It was familiar to Plutarch, who uses it to explain an episode in the life of Theseus. One of the savage beasts alleged to be killed by Theseus was “the Crommyonian sow, which they called Phaea, a savage and formidable wild beast, by no means an enemy to be despised.”11 For some reason Plutarch did not believe the account to be entirely credible, or sufficiently impressive, so he appended another version of the tale: Others related that Phaea was a woman, a robber full of cruelty and lust, that lived in Crommyon, and had the name of Sow given her from the foulness of her life and manners.12 Here we have the sleight of hand that is the gift of etymology. Phaea means “dusky” in Greek. The lady in question was known for her sooty appearance, so her neighbors dubbed her “the Sow.” In the end, Theseus did not kill a big pig, but dispatched a woman who was accused of robbery and a messy life. Techniques of this type were later to be a boon to the Fathers of the Church, whose motivation to deconstruct pagan myths surpassed the pagans’ search for mere rationality. A much more important objective was to destroy paganism in all its forms and supplant it with Christian beliefs. Accordingly, the topos that such-and-such has no reality, but is just a name for something else, was appealing to ecclesiastics engaged in polemic against pagan poetry. 89 finding history in my th 89 Three centuries after Plutarch, St. Augustine used the same device to explain away the myth that the Muses were the daughters of Jupiter (Zeus). Ignoring the obvious fact that the word “music” is derived from “Muse,” not the other way around, he asserted that the Muses were portrayed by triple statues because the sound of music is produced by three instruments: the voice, horns or flutes, and percussion instruments. On that account the Muses were given their name.13 Make of it what you will. The techniques whereby a critic can discredit some parts of myths and reduce others to credible history have often been ascribed to Euhemerus, third-century b.c.e. author of a voyage tale entitled Sacred Scripture. The author claims that he sailed to an island in the Indian Ocean, where he saw a column in a temple dedicated to Zeus, on which the names of the gods and their deeds were inscribed. He learned that the gods had once been great kings and heroes who were worshipped after their death: There is no doubt that those who are worshipped as gods were first human beings; this was the case for the first and the greatest of kings; but this was also the case for those whose courage had served the human species, and who, once they were dead, were given divine honors… .14 Although Euhemerus himself is not known for any applications of this idea, he is credited as the source of the types of reductionism and naturalizing of myths we have been discussing. Whereas the phrase “to euhemerize a tale” has stuck and is a useful shortcut for describing the refashioning of a story in a naturalistic way, the process of interpreting myths euhemeristically began earlier. We have already seen it in Hecataeus. The view that the gods and stories about them were human inventions created to serve a variety of social needs had a long history in Greece. From at least the fifth century the Greeks were interested in the beginnings of civilization and its evolution from a primitive state. Not unlike our nineteenth- and twentieth-century anthropologists, they theorized about the state of the “primitive mind” and its thought processes. They raised questions as to how earlier peoples conceived of the gods and other supernatural beings. We have already encountered the theory of Prodicus of Ceos as to how humans gave the name of god to all the things that benefited human life. Critias, or whichever poet composed the satyr play Sisyphus, was an early “conspiracy theorist”: the gods were invented by politicians who endeavored to control human behavior through fear. For the atomist Democritus, human beings were terrified by natural phenomena, and so they venerated all that happened in the sky by the name of Zeus. Euhemerus, with his idea that gods were originally exceptional human beings who were deified after their death, was part and parcel of this tradition. Somewhat later the universal historian Diodorus of Sicily put his 90 90 the anatomy of my th seal on the usefulness of piety for social harmony, a theme that other writers such as the historian Polybius had explored. Especially intriguing is the “anthropological” theory of the geographer Strabo, who compared the credulous minds of uneducated people to those of children: Now every illiterate and uneducated man is, in a sense, a child, and like a child, he is fond of stories; and for that matter, so is the half- educated man, for his reasoning faculty has not been fully developed, and, besides, the mental habits of his childhood persist in him.15 Strabo did not accuse the poets of inventing the myths; rather, they came originally from the lawgivers, who possessed “an insight into the emotional nature of the reasoning animal.” 16 Long before Strabo, or even Euhemerus, Herodotus contrasted the Greek belief that men could be descended from a god to the teachings of the Egyptians. Herodotus of Halicarnassus, aptly called “the father of history,” lived from roughly 480 to 425 b.c.e. He ranks with Thucydides as one of the two greatest Greek historians. He traveled as far as Scythia (roughly equivalent to modern Ukraine) and reported the beliefs and ways of thought of the peoples he visited. These can be read in his great work, the Histories, which has survived intact. He credits the Egyptians with ideas that will remind us of Euhemerus. In refuting Hecataeus for asserting that he could trace his genealogy to a god sixteen generations back, Herodotus invokes the authority of the Egyptian priests whom he visited in Egypt: When Hecataeus traced his genealogy and connected himself with a god sixteen generations back, the priests refused to believe him, and denied that any man had ever had a divine ancestor. They countered his claim by tracing the descent of their own high priests, pointing out that each of the statues represented a “piromis” (a word which means something like “gentleman”) who was the son of another “piromis,” and made no attempt to connect them with either a god or demigod. Such, then, were the beings represented by the statues; they were far from being gods—they were men.17 As already noted, Herodotus relied on his knowledge of Egyptian customs derived from the priests to debunk the tale of the sacrifice of Heracles at the hands of Egyptians. According to the priests, the Egyptians did not practice or allow human sacrifice. The rest of the story asserting that Heracles broke free and killed all his captors was obviously false for the simple reason that a mere human could not do this single handedly. Herodotus can also be credited with drawing a line dividing the chronology of history and myth. He, too, took up the Theseus saga with the following: 91 finding history in my th 91 “Polycrates was the first Greek we know of to plan the dominion of the sea, unless we count Minos of Cnossus and any other who may possibly have ruled the sea at a still earlier date. In ordinary human history [emphasis added], at any rate, Polycrates was the first.18 Polycrates belongs to human history, Minos to the time of myth. Not only was Minos involved in the business with Pasiphaë, a wooden cow, and a minotaur (a story as tawdry as it is incredible), he was also accorded a role as a judge in the underworld after his death. History has no place for hybrid beings such as minotaurs or frightening tales of life after death. The most discredited story in all antiquity (excepting, perhaps, the doings of Kronos) involved Odysseus’s experiences at the edge of Hades (Od., book 11). If there is an afterlife—itself a debatable proposition among Greek intellectuals—it does not take place under the ground. We have seen how Hecataeus reacted to the story of Herakles’ venture into the realm of the dead. But the intellectuals had their hands full. As soon as they managed to swat down one “descent” tale, another one would pop up. Not only did Heracles and Theseus essay a visit to Hades, but also Orpheus, who went there looking for his wife. As late as the first century b.c.e. the Roman poet Lucretius was still railing at such bogies.19 The scorn with which “descent into Hades” stories was greeted by intellectuals of all stripes may explain why the Roman poet Vergil had to dress his own version of it as a philosophical revelation.20 The ancient Greeks were happy to disbelieve many things. They prided themselves in discerning fact from fiction. Xenophanes called Homer’s tales plasmata. Hecataeus thought that Greek stories as a rule were ridiculous, but he in turn was rebuked by Herodotus for believing that a human could descend from a god. Just as there was no road to the underworld for mortals, there was no way back into mythical time. No matter how many generations your family went back, your ur-ancestor was still a man, not a god. The past was never different from the present in terms of what was possible. Since most Greeks who claimed to be historians were very skeptical about the events connected to the great heroes, to say nothing of the gods, one must wonder what sorts of evidence persuaded them that an alleged occurrence was true. Perhaps our best guide is Pausanias, a second-century c.e. author of a travel guide to the regions of Greece. Pausanias took great interest in religious beliefs and legends, and frequently paused to test the veracity of the latter. He was convinced that there was a skirmish between Amazons and Theseus in Athens. Antiope, one of the Amazon queens, had fallen in love with Theseus, and came to his aid in the battle. For her pains she was shot by another Amazon, Molpadia, whom Theseus slew. Pausanias had no trouble swallowing the whole story, even though his sources gave different versions. As noted above, Plutarch also did not question stories about Amazons, if only because Amazons were described as human women. Pausanias did not doubt 92 92 the anatomy of my th their existence, either, and believed that there was a battle with the Amazons because he had seen two monuments erected in their honor: one to Antiope, the other to Molpadia. After all, as the logic runs, who would go to the trouble and expense of erecting monuments to persons who did not exist?21 In a similar vein we learn from Pausanias that Theseus was a king of Athens who brought democracy to the polis and bestowed sovereignty upon the people, and that his descendants remained rulers to the fourth generation. In the same passage he repeats the old refrain that “there are many false beliefs among the masses of mankind, since they are ignorant of historical science and consider trustworthy whatever they hear from childhood in choruses and tragedies.”22 He then mentions that one of these false stories was about Theseus. What Pausanias probably had in mind was the expedition to Crete and the incidents with Minos, the Minotaur, the labyrinth, and Ariadne—none of which was believable. However, the report that Theseus was a king and brought equality to his people was believable. We can accept this as true because in Athens there is “a portico built behind with pictures of gods called the Twelve. On the wall opposite are placed Theseus, Democracy, and Demos (“the people”).23 The wall painting was proof enough for Pausanias. Facts did not seem to trouble Pausanias excessively. He was quite willing to believe that the democracy created by Theseus lasted down to the time of the tyrant Pisistratus in the sixth century b.c.e. Yet all of the legends about Theseus make him a near contemporary of Heracles and thus set him before the Trojan War. He was the son of Aegeus—a parentage that at least is more believable than the rumor that he was the child of Poseidon. The mention of Aegeus connects him to the timeframe of Jason (he of the Golden Fleece) and Medea, since Medea is supposed to have found refuge with Aegeus after she slew her children. How, then, do we calculate a mere four generations between Theseus and the reign of Pisistratus (560–527 b.c.e.)? Pausanias was even more credulous when it came to accepting portable objects as evidence of an event. It is one thing to place one’s faith in monuments and wall paintings with inscriptions. At the least these are indications of community belief that an event occurred in a particular place. It is quite another matter to believe in portable objects as tokens of a historical truth. Pausanias gives the following account of King Midas (the king with the “golden touch”): Now this people [the Galls] occupied the country on the farther side of the river Sangarius, capturing Ancyra, a city of the Phrygians, which Midas son of Gordius founded in a former time. And the anchor, which Midas found, was even as late as my time in the sanctuary of Zeus, as well as a spring called the Spring of Midas, water from which they say Midas mixed with wine to capture Silenus.24 93 finding history in my th 93 Pausanias appears to accept the first part of the account without comment. The second part, involving the capture of Silenus (a satyr-like woodland spirit), is tagged with a skeptical “they say.” This part can be quickly discounted because it presents a mythical character. Now, of course, the spring was real, as Pausanias had seen it with his own eyes (and who can doubt the existence of springs?). Only the attempted capture of Silenus is to be discounted, because sileni do not exist. In the first part there appears to be a connection between a city called Ancyra (now Ankara in Turkey), which Midas is said to have founded and an anchor that Midas found. There is a wordplay here, which the translator accommodates with a play on “found” and “founded.” But the wordplay in Greek is between Ancyra, the name of a city, and ancyra, “anchor.” Behind this there must lurk an etymology such as “Ancyra got its name from an anchor found on the site.” (Never mind that Ankara is a long way from the sea.) Since Ancyra/Ankara was founded by Midas, it must have been Midas who found the anchor. Pausanias could think of no reasons to doubt that the anchor exhibited in the sanctuary of Zeus was identical to the anchor discovered by Midas on the site of Ancyra. And so, in circular fashion, the continued existence of the anchor gives proof that Midas founded the city that is named after an anchor. We began our chapter with the legend of Theseus, and we return to him to learn what happened to his famous ship. Plutarch believed in portable objects as proofs of fact as much as Pausanias did, and he tells the following story: The ship wherein Theseus and the youth of Athens returned has thirty oars, and was preserved by the Athenians down even to the time of Demetrius Phalereus, for they took away the old planks as they decayed, putting in new and stronger timber in their places, insomuch that the ship became a standing example among the philosophers for the logical question of things that grow; one side holding that the ship remained the same, and other contending that it was not the same.25 Demetrius Phalereus was a politician and writer who governed Athens for ten years in the late fourth century. After being forced to flee, he had a soft landing in Alexandria, where he became head librarian. His writings include histories and collections of fables, so it is a manageable assumption that he was the source of the information that Theseus’s ship was still exhibited in Athens in his time there. But even if all of the planks of Theseus’s ship had been replaced by Demetrius’s time (Plutarch does not tell us that), and philosophers debated the question of its identity with the original, we must still believe that the Athenians had preserved the original ship from the time it touched the shores of the Piraeus down to Demetrius’s day. The ship remains a proof of Theseus’s great adventure, whether it is to be set before the Trojan War, or 94 94 the anatomy of my th about a century before Pisistratus. In the former case, it is likely that all the planks had to be replaced. From the sixth century b.c.e. to the end of antiquity in the sixth century c.e., people, with few exceptions, believed that the great heroes existed and did many of the exploits attributed to them, provided one understands their stories in a naturalistic way. Heracles existed and could slay terrible beasts in single combat, but he could not kill a horde of men who were attempting to sacrifice him. As for the beasts, they had to be real animals that everyone knew existed, not hybrid creatures such as minotaurs or centaurs. Dogs could be huge and terrifying, but they could not have three heads or a hundred eyes. The gods of Homer and Hesiod as well as their abodes on Olympus, or in the sea or under the earth, belonged to fable. Mountains, seas, and underground caves all existed, but the gods did not live there. They did not change their shape, or rescue favorites from a battle, or bring false dreams to captains. All such stories were plasmata—fictions. But fictions can be purified by reason. Remove all the parts that cannot be explained in a natural way, and reduce the doubtful cases to stories that are plausible. Theseus set out to visit King Aidoneus in Epirus in Greece. He did not go underground to visit Hades, the king of the underworld. Aidoneus’s dog did not have three heads. The application of these principles to the interpretation of Homer and Hesiod should be obvious. Most of the stories in Hesiod were put down as fable, but a great deal of Homer could be salvaged and treated as a true chronicle of the past. The Achaeans and their allies assembled their ships at Aulis and mounted an expedition against Troy more or less exactly as Homer said. Book 2 of the Iliad contains the famous “Catalogue of the Ships”: a detailed inventory of the Greek peoples assembled (named by city or island), the names of their captains, and the number of ships contributed to the expedition. We learn, for example, that the ships from Rhodes were captained by Tlepolemos, son of none other than Heracles (Il. 2, 653). What information could be more helpful to people who wondered when Heracles lived? He must have died just before the Trojan War, or he would have joined the foray himself along with his son—or so it could be believed. Homer elsewhere is solicitous of his readers in pinpointing chronology. In Homer’s (in)famous description of existence in the underworld, we learn that Oedipus’s mother, Jocasta (there named Epicaste), had already checked into Hades, but Oedipus was still alive and on his throne (Od. 11, 271–79). Homer was viewed as an authoritative source for geography as well. The geographer Strabo, whom we met just above, was convinced of Homer’s reliability on the subject, and believed him to be more accurate in his localization of places than Hesiod. Strabo engaged in an extensive and, to moderns, rather silly debate with Eratosthenes, an Alexandrian polymath from an earlier day, who championed Hesiod. Strabo admitted that Homer may have got some 95 finding history in my th 95 details wrong, but what he wrote about the wanderings of Odysseus was, on the whole, accurate: For apart from what I have said concerning the type of myth which it was proper for Homer to employ, most of the writers who discuss the same topics that Homer discusses, and also most of the local traditions, can teach us that these matters are not fictions of poets, nor yet of prose writers, but are traces of real persons and events.26 He goes on to say that Homer, of course, added “mythical elements to actual occurrences” … “but to hang an empty story of marvels on something wholly untrue is not Homer’s way of doing things.” Strabo fleshes out his argument with a bit of detail. Readers today who are familiar with the stories of the Cyclops and the Laestrygonians will write them off as entertaining myths, nothing more. But Strabo was determined to prove that the stories contained a kernel of historical truth: Accordingly, he took the foundations of his stories from history. For instance, history says that Aeolus was once king over the islands about Lipara, and that the Cyclopes and the Laestragonians, inhospitable peoples, were lords over the region about Aetna and Leontine; and for this reason the region about the Strait might not be visited by men of that time, and that Charybdis and the Rock of Scylla were infested by brigands.27 Strabo did not think it necessary to reveal the sources from which he derived his “history.” Rather, he passed on his information as though it has been authorized by a consensus of writers, whom it was unnecessary to identify. He did not expect to be challenged.28 With a single stroke he managed to eliminate four classes of monster—Cyclopes, Laestragonians, Scylla, and Charybdis— and replace them with inhospitable peoples and ordinary brigands. The tactics employed by Plutarch to turn a mythical bull into a nasty fellow named Taurus, and a many-headed hound named Cerberus into an ordinary guard dog were already known to Strabo, who a century earlier transformed Homer’s monsters into just plain nasty folks. Homer’s poetry was based on history, and included philosophy as well, but these difficult subjects were made palatable by the inclusion of entertaining stories. As the educator of the Greeks, Homer had the job of engaging everyone, including the young and women (!). If Strabo were asked if he could identify the location of the Isles of the Blest, I am certain that he would give a categorical “no!” for an answer, and assert that they never existed. Strabo explicitly denies “the whole of theology,” by which he excludes more than mythical monsters. He discounts Odysseus’s romps with goddesses, metamorphoses (gods in various guises), divinely 96 96 the anatomy of my th owned cattle herds (the cattle of the Sun), and the underworld (1.2.11)—in other words, everything that is supernatural or derived from an anthropomorphic depiction of the gods. Human survival post mortem belongs to the supernatural— that conviction would exclude Homer’s story of Hades, in which dimly conscious ghosts flit about in idleness. It would more than likely also exclude the Isles of the Blest, where, according to Hesiod (Works 167– 74), Zeus granted a blessed life to certain heroes who fought great wars, and according to Homer (Od. 4, 590–99) will be the happy abode of Helen and Menelaus, the son-in-law of Zeus. Homer in the same passage identifies the Isles with the Elysian Fields. But for crusty old Strabo, who had more than a drop of atheism in him, both Hades and the Isles of the Blest are poppycock. They are nothing more than old wives’ tales, Hades being a convenient bogeyman for lawgivers to use to frighten wrongdoers, the Isles of the Blest a will- o’-the-wisp to inspire virtue: Now since the portentous [i.e. the supernatural] is not only pleasing, but fear-inspiring as well, we can employ both kinds of myth for children, and for grown-up people too. In the case of children we employ the pleasing myths to spur them on, and the fear-inspiring myths to deter them, for instance, … the Gorgon.29 Feel free to disregard all such stories, as long as you believe that Odysseus slew the suitors “precisely as described by the poet.”30 Modern readers of ancient critics of myth will find much with which to agree, but much else to raise a smile of condescension. One admires their skepticism, but all too often the ancients were not skeptical enough. They too easily accepted the existence of a monument or some physical object like an old boat or an anchor as proof that an ancient event occurred. They never seem to have raised the question of whether physical evidence was genuine or a forgery, or if it might have been tampered with. (They had much keener noses for forged writings.) They also tended to accept an old story as true from the mere fact that it did not relate any supernatural events or interferences from the gods, as if presence or absence of those factors were enough to guarantee truth. In other cases, they disbelieved too much. In the fifth century c.e., St. Augustine made a list of monstrous creatures and mythical races in which he included pygmies, doubtless because he had never seen one.31 Much of this is understandable: the ancients lacked the easy access to verification of phenomena and events that we all enjoy today. There was no Internet or television, and travel was arduous and dangerous. Still, for all their faults, the rationalist critics of myth, who sought to salvage what they took for history and discard the rest as superstition, deserve a great deal of credit for their part in liberating humanity from the tyranny of the letter. 97 8 Theos—Rediscovering God Readers of the last chapter can hardly be blamed for thinking that nothing ever changed in the inventory of interpretative tools available to the Greeks. Great philosophical schools could come and go, gods could be dethroned and new ones established, but the critics bent on making history out of Homer continued to think in the same way, and employ the same strategies. Even the gap of nearly a thousand years between the pagan Hecataeus and the Christian Augustine did not leave any noticeable landmarks. One just keeps the humanly believable and discards the rest, or reduces its scale. But the view that nothing changed would be deceptive. It applies strictly to the critics who wanted to turn myth into history. It does not apply to the allegorists affected by the vagaries of philosophical trends. As we shall see in the next chapter, there were major developments in exegesis that grew out of a seismic shift in the prevailing paradigm. With the work of the atomists at the end of the fifth century the paradigm of physis was complete. Thales’ dictum that “all things are full of gods” had been gradually replaced by “there are gods, but what they do is limited by nature or necessity.” Physis (nature) governed everything with little or no need of divine aid from external gods for the very reason that “the divine” (to theion) had been blended into nature. From Anaximenes to Democritus—a good century and a half—t he common wisdom stated that the world was uncreated; it always existed and always will exist, whatever changes it may undergo. Anaximines asserted that air was not created by the gods, but the gods were created out of air. Heraclitus claimed that no god or man created the world, but it was, is, and ever will be everlasting fire. Cosmic air and fire contained their own causes of being and movement within them, and lacked for nothing. For Democritus there were only two things: atoms and void, and these are eternal. No cause is needed to set atoms into motion, since atoms fall by their own weight. Perhaps ironically, the thoughts of the cosmologists are indebted to the “mythological” poet Hesiod, who tells us that the first things, void and earth (Chaos and Gaia), 98 98 the anatomy of my th simply came into being. They were somehow generated, but there was no generator. The first gods just happened, and the later gods were generated by them. There was no one around to get it all started. Aristotle, of course, later challenged the old poet and his Presocratic heirs with his notion of an ultimate cause.1 There was firm consensus on another point. The cosmos and all of its contents were composed of a material substance. All being was material, even though there was contention over what the primary substance was, as outlined in ­chapter 3. Even Anaxagoras’s nous was material. That philosopher may have defined it as eternal and unmixed and apart from everything else, but it was still the finest of substances, and what is fine implies measurement, and therefore extension and weight. Melissos of Samos, a pupil of Parmenides, described the idea of the One as asōmaton, “bodyless,” but it was by no means clear whether he meant the universe as understood by his teacher, or the Pythagorean number form.2 Apart from numbers understood as mental concepts, there was no thought of incorporeal being before Plato. During the reign of physis, the physical allegorization of poetry was in fashion, except for historians such as Hecataeus and Herodotus, who applied the kind of rationalizing historiography to myths discussed in the previous chapter. Of the allegorists, Theagenes of Rhegium defended Homer’s tales of contention among the gods as warring among the elements, and Heraclitus believed that Homer was wrong to lament these battles, since “all things happen by strife and necessity.”3 To this paradigm, add Prodicus of Ceos’s claim that mortals call gods all things in nature that bring benefit to them. These include the products of nature like bread and wine, which men call Demeter and Dionysus. The hypothesis can be applied to the reading of myths, so that when we encounter the name of Dionysius in a tale we should say that this is just a story about wine. 4 The Stoic philosophers later followed the same path with their physical allegory. When they encountered the name Zeus in a myth, they did not think of Superman with lightning rods, but of the aether, that fiery substance outside the earth’s atmosphere. In this view, myths are codes, and codes are broken by recognizing a pattern of substitutions. However tightly the paradigm of physis was constructed, the seeds of its dissolution were already present. In the age of the first natural philosophers there was already a strong undercurrent of theism—theism, that is, defined as a doctrine that placed the gods outside of nature. Of course, for most people external gods continued to exist in the form of the traditional anthropomorphic gods. But for one important thinker, at least, an external god played a significant role in the workings of the cosmos. Xenophanes, the most openly theist of the Presocratics, asserted that there was “one god, greatest of all … who shakes all things by the thought of his mind.”5 He did not go so far as to say that this one god created the cosmos, but he did endow him with the capacity to govern it. The notion that a single god moves the cosmos through 99 theos—r ediscovering god 99 a mental process, clearly asserted by Xenophanes, appears to have influenced Anaxagoras. Nous (Mind), according to Anaxagoras, … controls all things, both the greater and the smaller, that have life. Mind controlled also the whole rotation, so that it rotates first from a small area, but now rotates over a wider and will rotate over a wider area still. And the things that are mingled and separated and divided off, all are known by Mind. And all things that were to be, all things that were but are not now, all things that are now or shall be, Mind arranged them all, including the rotation, in which are now rotating the stars, the sun and moon, the air and aither that are being separated off.6 Interestingly, we learn that Mind is not only responsible for the ordering of things, but also remains conscious of what it has ordered and will order. Mind exists, and therefore must be a being; it is also a conscious being. It is also made of some type of matter, though Anaxagoras does not use a word for “matter,” but simply describes Mind as the “finest” (that is, most subtle) and “purest” of all things.7 Is it then a living thing, or a person? More importantly, is it a god? Anaxagoras does not say. Nevertheless, his notion of an intelligent substance that starts and controls the cosmic process must have encouraged others to carry his thought further and identify Mind with God. It is surprising that Anaxagoras was a stumbling block for the Athenian censors and witch hunters, who charged him with the capital crime of impiety. Possibly his reticence about mentioning the gods, when other natural philosophers did so, led to the charge.8 The paradigm of physis was intact at the beginning of the fourth century. It had been developed by the natural philosophers from the sixth century on and bolstered by the sophists in the fifth. It dissolved almost completely in the fourth. There may be underlying social causes for this shift, including the disheartenment that ensued during the long Peloponnesian Wars and the political instability that occurred in Athens afterward. Those factors, at least, are sometimes given by earlier scholars as the reason for the upsurge of theism.9 Whatever the cause, it is interesting that the founders of three of the four major philosophical schools that came to dominate Greek thought were decidedly theist in outlook. I refer to Plato, Aristotle, and Zeno, who founded the Academy, the Peripatetic School, and the Stoa, respectively. These were three of the four great schools that were to dominate philosophy in antiquity. The fourth school, named after its founder, Epicurus, built its doctrines on the cosmology of the atomists, and thus remained resolutely nontheistic, though it cautiously avoided atheism (see ­chapter 4). The three theistic philosophers disagreed on many important issues, but they were of a single mind when it came to god. God existed. Plato and the 100 100 the anatomy of my th Stoics could still speak of god in the plural; for Aristotle, god was decidedly singular. For all of them, god was a conscious living being, not some kind of mechanical cosmic force. Most importantly, he created or started the cosmos. Plato and the Stoics believed that he created it according to a plan and guides it accordingly, while Aristotle hypothesized that he is the final cause of motion in the universe. None of the three schools attempted to make their respective gods into personal gods to whom one could pray; that was to come later. But it was clear that by the start of the third century b.c.e., a new paradigm had taken hold. Physis (nature) had been replaced by or subsumed into theos (god). Nature could still claim her prerogatives, but she could not function independently of god. The shift began with Plato, but it did not happen all at once. While Plato mentions gods sporadically in his dialogues, he did not advance any speculation about the true nature of the divine (to theion) until he wrote his great work, the Republic, in mid-career. The aim of the book was to delineate the ideal society and form of government. But in discussing the character of education needed to support this ideal polity, he attacked the ancient myths, as we saw in ­chapter 5. In the same work Plato limns his theory of ideas, otherwise called “forms.” These are notions of both physical and nonphysical things in their ideal state. They cannot be sensed, and are knowable only to the mind. Yet human minds do not generate the ideas. The ideas/forms simply exist and are available for minds to know. The forms constitute a world that exists on its own. It is separated from things that are knowable by the senses. They exist independently of the sensible world, and like the tree falling in the forest, they would remain knowable, even if there were no one left to know them. Plato illustrates his theory with the famous “Allegory of the Cave.” Plato does not advance these hypotheses any further. He does not identify the Good with god, though it was tempting for later thinkers to jump to that conclusion. Nor does he define the forms as notions in the mind of god. That was left to his successor Xenocrates to formulate.10 Even in Plato’s later work, the forms remained detached. He does, however, advance a fully fledged theism in his late dialogue, Timaeus. This dialogue is one of the most enigmatic of all Plato’s writings, yet it was to establish the pattern for theism, creationism, teleology (intelligent design), and a highly divinized cosmology for the remainder of antiquity. One could even say that it later became equated with Platonism itself. The dialogue is presented in the form of a fable by a certain Timaeus. Timaeus relates how a creator (demiourgos), also called god (theos), being good, wanted to share that goodness by creating the cosmos. He made a world that was “a living being” and as close to perfect as it could be without impinging on the divine. However, it was not eternal. But the creator made an image of eternity, which is called Time. Time is reckoned by the motions of the astral bodies in a group of three and another of four (sun, our Mercury, Venus, then 101 theos—r ediscovering god 101 Moon, Saturn, Mars, Jupiter). Their motions are coeval with the cosmos and would cease, should the world disintegrate. The stars are “ensouled” and the fixed stars described as “living animals.” The astral bodies that orbit the earth are ensouled by the gods whose names they carry. The universe itself is a sphere, which means that it contains all being within it. For that reason, there cannot be multiple worlds, or infinite worlds, as the atomists claimed. There is only one world, created by the demiurge, and regulated by the various divinities. But this world, the sensible world that was generated, was created according to the pattern of the eternal nature.11 In that sense, one could speak of two worlds. The first world is perfect; the second as close to perfection as possible, insofar as it imitates the first, and “participates” in it. In his Timaeus Plato did not neglect the authority of the old poets. He invokes Hesiod, but with a scheme to undermine him. After paraphrasing the beginning of the Theogony, Plato has his god address an assembly of gods that included all the generations from Gaia (Earth) to Zeus and Hera. He addresses them all, “both those who visibly appear in their revolutions [that is, the gods of the planets] as well as those gods of a more retiring nature”: “Gods, children of gods, who are my works and of whom I am the artificer and father, my creations are indissoluble, if so I will. All that is bound may be undone, but only an evil being would wish to undo that which is harmonious and happy. Wherefore, since ye are but creatures, ye are not altogether indissoluble, but ye shall certainly not be dissolved, nor be liable to the fate of death, having in my will a greater and mightier bond than those with which ye were bound at the time of your birth.”12 Thus, the universe is not by nature indissoluble, but indissoluble because of the will of the demiurge. Plato, through Timaeus, not only establishes a clear hierarchy of divinity, but he also gives a solution to an ancient problem that Hesiod had raised. For the poet, the gods did not always exist; they came into being at different times: the first ones mysteriously generated, the subsequent generations through parthenogenesis (“virgin birth”) from Earth or from the natural method of conception. They may be immortal, but they are not eternal. Xenophanes first pointed to the paradox: “Those who say that the gods are born are as impious as those who say that they die.”13 How is it possible that the gods are immortal, but not eternal? Timaeus’s fable solves the problem raised by the poets. There is only one truly eternal god. Because of his goodness, he creates the other gods to share his happiness and serve as governors of the world. Simultaneously, the fable challenges the Hesiodic teaching, set in stone, that the first gods generated themselves. (In this Plato is followed by Aristotle.) And Plato through Timaeus challenges Heraclitus’s dictum that no god or man created the universe. As for the universe itself, it is no longer to be 102 102 the anatomy of my th seen as eternal, neither at the “beginning” nor at the “end.” It was created by god at the very moment time was created through the astral bodies, and it is held together, not by its own bonds, but by the will of god. One must conclude that the fable of the Timaeus, which scholars in antiquity equated with Plato’s real views, runs directly counter to the vast majority of the teachings of the sixth-and fifth-century physical philosophers. Certainly, it stands in opposition to the Ionians (the Milesian school as well as Heraclitus), and to the atomists. It overturns the paradigm of physis and substitutes the new paradigm of theos, in which the will of god is absolute. Everything is god’s creation, and god can do with it what he wants. Plato pushes even further the idea of intelligent design, a notion cast into disrepute in the early twenty-first century, as it is seen to be opposed to Darwin’s theory of evolution.14 Plato opposes the reason (logos) of the designer to necessity (anankē), what we would call “the laws of nature.” He even describes necessity as “the errant cause,” a force or forces that must be restrained by reason. The errant cause includes the four elements and their motions; these existed before the creation of heaven. But they are as unintelligent as the elements (letters) that make up words (Plato plays on the meanings of Greek stoicheia, “elements”).15 The elements (or “necessity”) left to their own devices run amok and create disorder. They represent the principle of randomness espoused by the later atomists, in which atoms collide and briefly hook up with other atoms until they find suitable partners, from these stable relationships are born permanent things. Plato wants none of that. All must be arranged for a better purpose, and that is the job of reason.16 It is easy to see why Christian intellectuals of a later age embraced Platonism as represented in the Timaeus with almost unbridled enthusiasm. They understood the fable literally, as did the secular philosophers. The “Platonists,” as Christians casually referred to the school—when in fact they meant the Plato of the Timaeus—had provided them with a creator god, who existed from all eternity and made a single cosmos that had a definite beginning. Its end depended on the will of the same god. All things within the cosmos were created by that god and contingent upon his existence. The cosmos was created according to a perfect plan, and it was just one easy step to locate that plan in the mind of god. When that happened, god became God. As an added boon, the “Platonists” provided the philosophical foundations for the immaterial soul, which, because it was immaterial, could endure forever. Christian intellectuals were so impressed with Plato’s teachings that they believed that he must have received some kind of private revelation from God, or else had learned from the prophet Jeremiah when he visited Egypt!17 Plato’s theological ideas received qualified support from an unexpected quarter. Aristotle, his greatest pupil, had challenged many of the master’s theories. The central challenge was aimed at Plato’s theory of ideas. However, Aristotle was deeply taken by Plato’s insight that the mere existence of matter 103 theos—r ediscovering god 103 does not explain things as they are. Why are there rivers and mountains and seas, animals and people, and recognizable things, and not just meaningless coagulations of matter? Plato raised and answered the question: it was form. But for Aristotle the answer was wrongly formulated. One cannot separate form (eidos or idea) from matter or stuff (hylē). All things require a formal and a material cause. The form is inherent in things, and inseparable from the function of a particular thing.18 Similarly, a thing cannot be if it does not contain matter. No provision is made for immaterial things. Forms or ideas cannot simply float in the aether. Plato claimed that souls are akin to the ideas; they are separate from bodies. For Aristotle souls were simply the forms of bodies (though he considered the notion that the rational portion of the soul might be eternal).19 When souls were sundered from bodies at death, they had no further function. Indeed, they no longer existed. To some it would seem that Aristotle’s train ran off the track when it came to the subject of god—or should we say God? Aristotle was a close observer of nature, and had a deep belief in physical laws that operate by necessity. Aristotle stood squarely in the tradition of the Ionians who looked to nature for explanations. His work on biology and physics show a scholar not easily given to mysticism. The causes of things are to be found in nature herself. When it came to the topic of the origin of motion, however, Aristotle was unpersuaded by the atomist Leucippus and Plato (unlikely bedfellows indeed!) that motion was eternal, and didn’t require its own cause. “For how will there be movement if there is no actually existing cause?”20 Aristotle consistently opposed the notion of randomness or chance in favor of an argument from necessity (although not “necessity” in the sense used by Plato, who had called it “the errant cause”).21 One observes that everything that moves is moved by something else. But there cannot be an indefinite series of motions. There must therefore be something that moves other things, but is not moved itself; in other words, a final cause of motion. This is Aristotle’s unmoved mover. Now Aristotle could have stopped there and said that the unmoved mover is some indefinable principle of nature: we do not know what it is, only that it is. Or he could have simply called it a god, without going any further. Astonishingly, he goes much further: We say therefore that god is a living being, eternal, most good, so that life and duration continuous and eternal belong to god; for this is god.”22 And that is not all. Aristotle goes on to describe his god in a way that would make some Christian scholastic philosophers of the thirteenth century very happy: It is clear then from what has been said there here is a substance which is eternal and unmovable and separate from sensible things. It 104 104 the anatomy of my th has been shown also that this substance cannot have any magnitude, but is without part and indivisible … But it has also been shown that it is impassive and unalterable; for all other changes are posterior to change of place.23 If god is a substance without magnitude, then he is immaterial, for even the smallest conceivable substances have magnitude. This can only mean that Aristotle has made a huge concession to Plato in accepting the hypothesis of an immaterial substance—even if there is only one such substance, namely, god (God). A happy consensus between a master and a recalcitrant pupil was reached, at least on one crucial point. We should not be tempted, however, to equate Aristotle’s unmoved mover with Plato’s demiurge, or designer-god. Aristotle tells us very little about what god actually does apart from exercising his mind in contemplation. Although described as “good,” unlike Plato’s demiurge, Aristotle’s god does not translate his goodness into the act of creating or sustaining the world. The functions of the origins, growth, and end of things are left to nature (physis). It appears that nature takes over where god has left off. In book 5 of the Metaphysics, Aristotle discusses two basic senses of the word “nature”: (1) the genesis of growing things (physis comes from a Greek verb meaning “to grow”); (2) the primary material out of which any natural object is made. However, a more comprehensive insight into Aristotle’s concept of nature can be gleaned from book 2 of the Physics. In ­chapter 5 (198b –99a) he distinguishes between the ideas of randomness and necessity—both being answers to the question of why things happen. Aristotle sets out two scenarios to exemplify his distinction. In the case of randomness, a farmer’s crops grow as a result of the rain; growth simply happens. (If one were to personify rain, Rain would be indifferent to the fate of the farmer’s crop.) In the second scenario, rain falls in order to make the farmer’s crop grow. (Rain would rejoice.) Aristotle summarizes as follows: If then, it is agreed that things are either the result of coincidence or for an end, and these cannot be the result of coincidence or spontaneity, it follows that they must be for an end; and that such things are all due to nature even the champions of the theory before us would agree. Therefore action for an end is present in things which come to be and are by nature.24 Thus, Aristotle retains a firm footing in the paradigm of physis, while introducing the new element of a theos who gives the first impulse to the movement of the cosmos. (Recall that the earlier physical philosophers assumed the eternity of motion as well as of matter.) It would seem that Aristotle’s god, left to the joys of contemplation, does not interfere in any way with the workings of nature, which operate according to the iron dictates of necessity (which 105 theos—r ediscovering god 105 includes purposefulness). And if god does not intervene, the function of providence must be left to a benign nature, which (who?) always ordains things for the best. Still, Aristotle does not entirely divorce God from nature. In a passage in On the Heavens he portrays them as close associates: “But God and nature create nothing that has not its use.”25 Aristotle, however, did not ask the question we would expect a physicist to ask of himself: how can a being without any magnitude—and therefore without a body—do anything at all, not to speak of setting the entire physical cosmos in motion? The Presocratic cosmologists remained steadfast in their conception of god as a body, not just because they could not conceive of an immaterial substance, but also because they believed that material bodies could be moved only by other material bodies. (How does a ghost manage to do stuff?) To say otherwise is to introduce the supernatural element, magic, or hocus-pocus—the very thing that the critics strove to excise from myths. Plato saw the difficulty. He tried to get around it by infusing the material universe with an immaterial soul that would rule over the universe and make it divine. The soul would fill every part of the cosmos (Tim. 34). But for the materially minded, that would just raise a new question: how can two substances occupy the same space at the same time? Plato attempted a kind of mechanical hypothesis for explaining the connection of the human body to its soul. The creator inserted invisible pegs composed of the four elements to fuse them together: These [the four elements] they took and welded them together, not with the indissoluble chains by which they were bound, but with little pegs too small to be visible, and fastened the courses of the immortal soul in a body which was in a state of perpetual influx and efflux.26 The champions of physis would just laugh and ask, “How do the pegs grip, if what they are fastening is thinner than the thinnest air?” The Stoics, who were aware of the problem, wanted to insure that they would never be caught in that metaphysical trap. Their cosmos was also infused with a soul that they identified with god, but both were material. There was no other kind of substance. The dualists could counter with “how then do you distinguish between god and ordinary matter? Is everything god?” The problem seemed to be insoluble. But there was agreement among the three schools on several important points: God preceded the universe and created it, or started it moving (Plato, Aristotle), or else is the cause of its existence by being inherent in it (Stoics). God is eternal, not merely immortal (all three). God is good (all three). God (Plato, Stoics), or nature (Aristotle) created the best possible world, and all its parts are created to serve an intelligent purpose (all three). There can be little doubt that by the end of the fourth century a new paradigm was in place, certainly among the intellectual class. Physis had ceded 106 106 the anatomy of my th large tracts of its territory to theos. Plato’s divine world soul and the Stoic god, also called the logos (a debt to Heraclitus), were both inherent in the cosmos and governed it for all time. The universe did not just “happen,” but was brought into being, or in some way initiated, by a god who is good. Plato and Aristotle were in agreement that god preceded the cosmos in a causal sense, though neither challenged the old wisdom that the elements (Plato) or matter (Aristotle) were always “there.” On this issue, Aristotle went much further than Plato, asserting that the whole structure of the cosmos was eternal and uncreated.27 For the Stoics, god and the cosmos were always one, with god enjoying a causal priority, if not a temporal one. Hesiod’s paradigm, which had initiated the long reign of physis, was destined to disappear in the centuries that followed Plato. The randomness in nature observed in the first beings was curtailed by Aristotle’s “necessity,” Plato’s “will of God,” and the Stoic logos. Excepting Xenophanes, no Greek thinker ever ceded authority over nature to god until Plato. However, Aristotle’s decision to let god start things off, then retire to practice self-contemplation, reestablished the teleological function in nature. Unhappily, Aristotle’s voice was lost when his writings went missing for two centuries. When they resurfaced they largely failed to have the impact they deserved. Intelligent design was therefore the property of the Platonists, who attributed it to god/ God. Further, the possibility that the universe was infinite in extension, or that there could be multiple worlds, as the atomists hypothesized, was firmly squelched by the founders of the three schools. There was only one world (that is, cosmos), spherical in shape, and there was nothing outside it. A final point regarding the nature of god: the pre-C hristian Greeks never abandoned the notion that there are many gods. Indeed, polytheism was to be one of the main sticking points that separated pagans from Christians in late antiquity. In this respect the paradigm of the poets remained unaltered. Homer’s “father of gods and men” was “theologized” in Xenophanes’s “one god greatest of gods and men.” Plato spoke of god and gods indifferently; so did the Stoics. One god could be the most powerful by far, but that did not exclude the existence of other gods, or their importance. I can only hazard a guess why this might have been so. The gods of the Greeks never completely lost their human qualities. Even if one discarded the naughty gods of Homer and conceived of them as models of moral perfection, as Xenophanes and Plato wished, one could not disassociate them entirely from human nature. Humans live in families and societies; they are social animals, which I think is a legitimate translation of Aristotle’s politikon zōon (“an animal of the polis”). The gods, therefore, if they are to be happy (and happiness is an essential quality of divinity) must also live in families. A pure monotheism—like that suggested in Aristotle’s solitary god—is thinkable, but most unattractive. Even Epicurus’s gods, who do very little and have nothing to do with men, live in a community. This is perhaps 107 theos—r ediscovering god 107 the reason that Catholic Christianity, at any rate, depicts God in heaven with his Son at his right side and his Son’s mother nearby, surrounded by choruses of angels and the blessed saints. In a more restrained way they reenact the lives of Homer’s “happy gods” on Olympus. Despite the theists’ agreement on many points, the chasm between a dualist concept of the cosmos (nonmaterial forms separate from physical things) and a monist notion (there can be only matter) remained. This division was to play itself out in the interpretation of myth. The Platonists, disregarding the strictures of the master, went on to practice allegorical interpretation along with their Stoic rivals. But their focus understandably reflected the interests of their school: namely, God, the soul, and the objects of knowledge (the noetic world). The Stoics, remaining steadfast in their monist position, looked to myths for revelations about the physical world. They continued to look for god in nature, or nature in god—for they were the same. The development of the differing interpretative strategies of these schools will be the subject of the following chapters. 108 109 9 The Growth of Allegory As we saw in ­chapter 6, the beginnings of allegorical interpretation were closely bound up with attempts to reconcile Homer and Hesiod’s myths with a developing cosmology that based its theories of the origin and operation of the world on the laws of nature. In that paradigm the gods existed and had some role or other in governing things, but they did not make the world, and were themselves subject to the laws of nature. At the same time, a total makeover of the anthropomorphic gods of the poets was required. They could no longer look and act like mortal men with all their desires and frailties, nor could they perform wonders like tribal shamans. In order to preserve the authority of the poets, the defenders of poetry had to interpret the gods of the Iliad, Odyssey, and Theogony in ways that emphasized their connection to nature. No small task that, but with the aid of allegory it could be achieved. The squabbling gods of myth could be transmogrified into the warring elements of science. Kronos with his sickle could be made into venerable Father Time. The alchemy of allegory worked its magic. A new cosmology and new theology were established, while the authority of the poets remained intact. Myths, however, can be read either in the context of the poems—in which case the intention of the poet is up for discussion—or as freestanding stories. Not all interpretation of myth had to be related directly to the study of the poets; they could be discussed independently. This may have been the case with the earliest Stoic interpretations; it is hard to tell, as what survives of the earliest Stoic myth exegesis is mostly fragments.1 In any case, however one approached “myth” used in the broad sense, one had to follow a road that led through the poets. At all events, the survival and growth of allegory is closely related to developments in two of the three theistic schools, the Stoics and the Platonists. Both schools eagerly adopted allegory as a teaching tool for elucidating their respective doctrines. The Stoics believed that god and the cosmos were one, and thus the cosmos was divine. The Platonists who took the Timaeus as their central text believed that god created the universe and suffused it with his own being. On this last 110 110 the anatomy of my th point, Stoics and Platonists scarcely differed from each other. However, there was an unbridgeable gap between them with regard to matter. For the Stoics, all substances, including god, were material. No nonmaterial substance could exist. Platonists remained true to their founder in accepting dualism. They posited two worlds: the world of matter, which was unstable and therefore constantly changing, and the world of forms, which were eternal and immutable. God made a world of matter, which he ensouled, thus uniting what might have remained two irreconcilable worlds into a single cosmos. The soul of the cosmos was akin to the ideas; it had no dimensions or weight. Both schools believed that the cosmos was divine, and that god was imminent in the world. Both believed that god continued to sustain the world. For the Stoics, however, matter—the sole stuff from which the world was made— had to be divine, since god and the world were identical. The gods of the poets, interpreted as physical elements, could be put to use as the divine elements of the cosmos. The elements earth, air, fire, and water were all divine. The gods that symbolized them, which were neither anthropomorphic gods nor primitive nature spirits, could be repurposed as divinized elements (archai). Zeus now had new life as fire and the fiery aether, while his consort Hera was consigned to the lower air. The myths of the poets were cosmological fables that could be used to teach Stoic cosmology, much as Plato devised his own fables to teach Platonic philosophy. While soul had an important place in Stoic philosophy, for Plato, soul was paramount. Not only did he see soul as that which sustained the being of the cosmos, but he returned time and again to investigate the individual human soul. Soul is the central subject of the Phaedrus and the Phaedo, and it figures prominently in the Republic, Meno, Symposium, and Timaeus. The nous, the rational part of the soul, is not merely immortal; it is eternal, for it existed in the countless aeons before it descended into bodies and will live on forever after leaving them. Plato argued for its preexistence in the Meno, where he famously tried to show that all true knowledge is remembering—the recollection, prompted through questioning, of the forms imprinted from eternity on the rational part of the soul. Plato described “the other end of eternity” in the Myth of Er, which describes the fate of souls after death. The rational soul is able to survive death precisely because it is not made of matter—hence, not made of those very fine atoms that the Epicureans describe as dissolving at the moment of bodily death. Nearly all of the fables Plato composed to illustrate his philosophy have the soul as their subject. It is no wonder, then, that when Platonists turned to Homer, they looked for passages that could confirm Plato’s teachings on the soul itself, or the properties of the soul such as virtue. Not surprisingly, the Platonists concentrated their attention mainly on Homer’s poems, which contains a limited amount of cosmology, while the Stoics directed their efforts more to Hesiod precisely because his work is cosmological and was so recognized in antiquity. 111 the grow th of allegory 111 So began two types of allegorical interpretation that reigned in the world of letters in the Hellenistic age and later antiquity: the physical allegory of the Stoics and the psychological allegory of the Platonists. They came from a single source, the theistic impulse of the fourth century. They branched into two basic types, one reflecting the physical cosmology of the Stoics, the other concentrating on the rational soul theory of the Platonists. The two interpretative methods were not hermetically (or hermeneutically) sealed; the two types are often mingled.2 Indeed, we saw this mixing in the fragment of Theagenes that gives the earliest evidence for allegory. A defining feature of allegorical interpretation from the fourth century b.c.e. onward is etymology, the practice of tracing words or names to their roots in order to gain a fuller understanding of their meaning. In modern times, refinements in historical linguistics have raised the practice to a science. Languages are now classified into families and subdivided into branches. By working through the family genealogies (across the branches), one can discover the ur-ancestor of a word or name. As illustration, the modern French word dieu, “god,” comes from Latin deus (Latin is the head of a family branch called Romance), while deus, through comparison with Greek dios (“divine” or “belonging to Zeus”), Old Irish dí, and Sanskrit dīvā, establishes the Indo- European (name of the whole family) root *dy- ə -wo, meaning “bright” or “celestial.”3 The gods shine in the sky, so to speak. The Greeks had not advanced so far in their study of languages. They had to rely largely on guesswork based on their own language. Thus, they derived the name of Zeus from zēn, “to live,” perhaps because zen was an ancient form of the name Zeus in the accusative case (objective case in English), and it sounded the same as zēn, “to live.” However, according to the modern derivation, Zeus should be grouped with the words meaning “shining” and “celestial.” Greek exegetes were interested in etymology chiefly because they believed it could reveal the meanings of the names of the gods, and so teach them their functions and properties. At the same time, they grasped that because the gods were the chief actors in myths, uncovering the meaning of a god’s name would simultaneously decode the myth. As already noted, a catalogue of inappropriate myths had been developed at an early stage—certainly before Plato and even before Xenophanes, for that matter—and these stories sullied the reputation of the poets. Allegory could render the offensive stories harmless by substituting a natural phenomenon for an anthropomorphic god with human vices. This had already been established by Theagenes. But suppose a skeptic should quiz Theagenes, and ask, “How do you know that Poseidon is just a substitute for water?” Theagenes might reply, “Well, it’s always been that way; it is a natural association.” But if the skeptic is unhappy with the answer, etymology can be summoned to the rescue. One ancient etymology derives Poseidon from posis, “drink, drinking.”4 That is all the information needed to disprove Homer’s claim that a god called Poseidon tried to drown Odysseus; 112 112 the anatomy of my th the near drowning was caused by Odysseus drinking (posis) too much water. Homer is spared another beating. Perhaps the worst of all the “bad myths” is the tale of Kronos devouring his children. It was a topic that people with good manners would want to avoid. Hesiod’s account makes it clear that the god’s motives are quite wicked. Etymology to the rescue! Since the name Kronos bears a close resemblance to the Greek word chronos, “time,” the meaning of the tale is at once made clear and free of moral taint. “Kronos devouring his children” means nothing more than the fact that “time devours all of Earth’s children.” Similarly, the episode of Kronos’s castration of Ouranos could be interpreted to mean something like “Time severs the life force.” (Curiously, no one wondered why such banal truths were considered deep mysteries that required scurrilous stories to conceal them.) The task of the interpreter is simply to uncover the meaning of a name of the personified character with the aid of etymology, and once that was done, the meaning of the myth would be obvious. The method embraced the interpretation of the names of other gods. Hera, for example, could be reduced to the natural element air just by scrambling the letters of her name. In Greek her name is spelled HPA (pronounced hēra), which when reversed yield AHP (pronounced aër), the Greek word for air. Sound plays an important role in validating the substitution claimed. If I say, “Hera is the air,” you may well ask, “How do you know that?” I would answer, “Just use your ears. When I say Hera can’t you hear the word ‘air’ whistling through? The aural association became even stronger over time as the initial h-sound weakened. Homer could without a care substitute Hephaestus (the fire god) for fire, but I suspect that an etymologizer would feel obliged to invoke a connection to the close-sounding hephestios, “having to do with the hearth” (ep’ + hestia, “on the hearth”).5 Unlike the earliest physical allegorists such as Prodicus and Metrodorus, who banked on age-old associations between divinities and things in nature, the Stoics relied heavily on etymology to support their interpretations. They continued their practice of physical allegorization well after the beginnings laid by the founding fathers, Zeno, Cleanthes, and Chrysippus. The Stoics, to be sure, were not the pioneers of the etymologizing craze.6 Traces of name explanations can be found in Homer and Hesiod, as well as the dramatic poets, especially Euripedes, and in Heraclitus. Antisthenes and Cratylus, associates of Socrates, essayed a theory of language that holds that language is made up of just a few sounds, and individual sounds express meanings that correspond to the sounds. The idea is explored fully in Plato’s dialogue Cratylus, in which Socrates demonstrates that sounds by nature have little to do with meaning. Later Platonists seem not to have noticed what the master had to say on the subject, for they were as enthusiastic about the usefulness of etymology for decoding myths, or supporting interpretations, as were their Stoic counterparts. 113 the grow th of allegory 113 Whereas the few mythological interpretations ascribed to the Stoic founders (Zeno, Cleanthes, Chrysippus) are fragments and consist mostly of etymologies of gods’ names,7 a complete work on myth exegesis by the Stoic philosopher Lucius Annaeus Cornutus has survived. Cornutus was born in Leptis Magna (in Libya) and was active in Rome in the first century c.e. He was implicated in a conspiracy against Nero and exiled in 66 c.e. His work (in Greek) translates as A Summary [Epidrome] of the Traditions concerning Greek Mythology. Cornutus alludes to a number of the chief Stoic teachings, including the periodic conflagration of the cosmos, and uses familiar Stoic terminology. The interpretations are based almost entirely on Hesiod’s Theogony. They consist mostly of the etymologies of divine names, but, importantly, also include a few interpretations of whole myths. While much of Cornutus’s work, like that of his predecessors, is limited to the etymologies of names, there are several passages where he gives interpretations of whole myths. In the first book of his Summary, he gives an extended exegesis of the myth of Rhea and Kronos, followed by the story of Kronos and Gaia (Earth), stories that occur in reverse order in Hesiod’s Theogony. Cornutus begins with the standard etymology of Rhea’s name, Flowing, associating her with rainfall and thunderstorms and even with mountains, since waters flow down from them. He describes her as wearing a wreath decorated with towers, and speculates that that is because the first cities were built on mountains or because the archetypal city is the cosmos itself. She is honored with the poppy, because that flower is appropriate to the goddess who is the cause of the generation of living things. Other symbols appear on her bosom that represent the great variety of things that have being. After some remarks regarding Rhea’s similarity to Syrian and Phrygian goddesses, Cornutus proceeds to the kernel of the myth of Rhea and Kronos, the devouring of their children by Kronos. He explains that this is because everything that arises in the cyclical movement of the cosmos must disappear in the same way, and that the nature of Time (Kronos = Chronos, “time”) is such that everything born within her is devoured. The second part of the Rhea and Kronos story involves Rhea’s deceit of her monstrous husband. After giving birth to Zeus, Rhea spirits the infant away and substitutes a stone for Kronos’s dinner. Kronos seizes the bait and Zeus is saved to become the future ruler of the universe. Cornutus interprets the story thus: The episode of the swallowing of the stone should be understood otherwise. The story is really about the origins of the cosmos, in which a directing nature was nourished and ruled over it, when this stone, which we call the earth, was firmly anchored in his midst, as though it had been swallowed. For otherwise the things that are could not have come into being, if they had not been erected, so to speak, on this foundation, since all things come into being and are nourished here.8 114 114 the anatomy of my th Here we have what can properly be called an exegesis of a complete story. The interpreter assembled the interpretations in a way that corresponds to the actions in the original story. Here the directing nature (dioikousa physis) is Nature herself, who ruled the cosmos at that time, that is, in the age of Kronos. The stone is the earth. When the earth is swallowed [by Kronos] it is anchored in Time. The earth provides the foundation of everything that comes into being and is nourished. This part of the story is implicitly linked to the beginning. Since the earth is anchored in Time, everything that is born from her and nourished by her is devoured. Next, Cornutus turns to the lurid story of the castration of Ouranos by his son Kronos. Cornutus’s brief summary combines this episode with the overthrow of Kronos by Zeus, and the imprisonment in Tartarus of the father by the son. In his explanation of the episodes Cornutus resorts to a different etymology of Kronos, connecting the name to the verb krainein, “to bring to completion.” Cornutus expected his readers to know the whole story as related by Hesiod, so he does not tell the fate of the severed organs. Here is what Hesiod had to say about them: But that was not the end of them. The drops of blood that spurted from them were all taken in by Mother Earth, and in the course of the revolving years she gave birth to the powerful Erinyes [Spirits of Vengeance] and the huge Giants with shining armor and long spears. As for the organs themselves, for a long time they drifted around the sea just as they were when Cronus cut them off with the steel edge and threw them from the land into the waves of ocean; then white foam issued from the divine flesh, and in the foam a girl began to grow … She is called Aphrodite by gods and men, because she grew 9 in the froth. … It is obvious that these omitted details prompted the interpretation of the myth: Cronus/K ronos’s action resulted in the watering of the earth’s atmosphere, causing its exhalations to be finer. The reversal that followed, namely, imprisonment of Kronos in Tartarus, had the happy effect of extending the lifespan of the cosmos. I can only guess that Cornutus meant that, if Kronos had lived out his reign to the end, he would have brought a terminus to the age he ushered in, and the periodic interruption of the cosmic cycle with its entailed cosmic conflagration would have occurred. Zeus’s usurpation ensured a prolongation of the cycle. That interpretation, at least, would be consistent with Stoic cosmology. While the interpretation does account for the whole myth— allowing for the omission of coarse details that readers were expected to know (and better left unsaid)—we would probably regard such interpretations today as far-fetched, even counterintuitive. To the modern reader, the obvious point 115 the grow th of allegory 115 of Hesiod’s fable is that it “explains” the simultaneous origins of violence (the creation of the Spirits of Vengeance) and sex (the birth of Aphrodite). It is thus aetiological. It “explains” the human condition in the same way that the Garden of Eden story “teaches” us how death, labor, and childbirth came about. However, Cornutus gets credit for saving the face of his great authority and reconciling the myth with Stoic cosmology. That is his main task. In doing this he was following in the footsteps of his distant master, Chrysippus. It is said that when the great Stoic philosopher was confronted with a wall painting depicting Hera performing fellatio on Zeus, he explained the act as the interaction between divinity (Zeus) and matter (Hera).10 The ancient critics of myths tended to zero in on a restricted few stories, especially ones considered outrageous or morally disgusting. These included the same tales mentioned by Plato in the Republic. In addition to the antics of Kronos and the ejection of Hephaestus from Olympus with its crippling effect, the episode of Zeus’s suspending Hera from the sky was ever ripe for discussion. Zeus used golden chains for this and fastened anvils to her feet (Il. 15, 18–19). This was not the first time Zeus abused his devoted wife. But Cornutus takes no interest in the violent aspect of the tale, nor does he exploit the prurience of his readers by calling attention to Hera’s undignified posture. The story, for him, is purely of cosmological interest: the gold of the chains reflects the golden sheen of the stars, and the anvils symbolize the earth and the sea, both of which serve to hold down the air (Hera, of course) and prevent it (her) from being torn away from either of them. Cornutus labels the episode “as a paraphrase of a fragment of an ancient myth” (Epid. 17.1). Cornutus breaks with the Presocratic interpreters and with Plato by denying that myths are invented stories (plasmata). On that account one should not mix them up or take names from one myth and carry them over to another (Epid. 17.3) Rather, myths are products of great antiquity, a point just illustrated in his comment on the aerial suspension of Hera. This sets Cornutus in the company of Aristotle, who regarded myths as tales that are “handed down” (paradidomena); they are paraphrases of much older stories. What, then, do we make of allegory, if we do away with authorial intention? What happens to the idea that Homer and Hesiod “made things up,” or that they said one thing and meant another? Or that the poets placed a veil over their meaning, so that only the very wise could grasp it? Such questions are impossible to answer with certainty, but I suspect that Cornutus believed that cosmological meanings are inherent in the myths themselves; they are simply “there.” In other words, there is no real disjunction between myth and cosmological truth, though the poets had distorted them with their foolish tales that made the gods no better than men. In this view, since poets did not invent myths, there were no authorial intentions to be sussed out. The poet’s job was simply to tell the stories well. Such would be consistent with Hesiod’s own explanation of the poetic process: “They [the 116 116 the anatomy of my th Muses] breathed into me their divine voice, so that I might tell of things to come and things past, and ordered me to sing of the race of the blessed gods, who live forever… .”11 Cornutus proceeds to show the coherence of myth and true cosmology by summarizing Hesiod’s account of the origin of the cosmos in the order given by the poet. Myths are taken for what they are, neither for inventions (plasmata) nor for lies (pseudē). Cornutus does not contradict his source, nor does he suggest what the poet might have meant. He simply searches his source for statements that can be made consistent with Stoic cosmology. Accordingly, Hesiod’s “first thing,” Chaos, can be identified with the moist element that existed before the ordering (diakosmesis) of the cosmos. That identification had been posed already by Zeno.12 Moisture (water) was one of the two archai posited by the Stoics; the other was heat (fire).13 Alternatively, Chaos could be fire, the principle of the world’s origin. Both interpretations involve etymologies. However, the important point, I believe, is that the truth of the poem is right on the surface. Chaos is the first thing to come into being. Chaos belongs to the ancient myth; the poet (here Hesiod) did not substitute Chaos for something else. Cornutus’s book is a landmark in the history of interpretation. Because it is complete and sometimes deals with whole myths, it provides a window by which we can loosely reconstruct the procedures of earlier Stoic interpreters. (This has been shown by the sourcing of Cornutus’s text, which reveals numerous parallels with the fragments of the founders.) By Cornutus’s time (first century c.e.), etymological explanations had become indispensable for allegorical interpretation. There is no logical reason that this should be so, since allegories can be composed without them, as Plato proved. Moreover, etymologies could shift, as we noted in the interpretations of the Kronos stories, in which Cornutus starts with Kronos at first derived from Chronos (Time), then shifts to a derivation from krainein, “to bring to completion.” Roman authors had to accommodate etymologies to the Latin language, a process that entailed providing completely different explanations for the names of essentially the same god. Zeus and Jupiter were conflated in Roman times into a single god, but they had completely different names, one Greek, one Latin. This meant they had to have different etymologies. So, for example, the name Zeus is said to come from zen, “to live,” whereas Iovis (alternate form of Jupiter) was derived from iuvare, “to help.” These multiple possibilities of explaining the names of the same god did not seem to bother the Stoics. We see how one representative of Stoicism, Lucilius Balbus, managed to reconcile Greek and Latin etymologies in explaining the story of Kronos and his children: He is called Kronos, which is the same as Chronos, and means lapse of time, just as our Roman name Saturn means “sated with years.” In 117 the grow th of allegory 117 mythology he is said to have devoured his own children, just as age eats up the passing years and is fed but never satiated as the years go by.14 Stoic interpreters were content to adapt the etymology needed to suit the interpretation they wanted. If they wished to explain Kronos’s act of eating his children, they turned him into Time. Alternatively, if they wished to associate him with the completion of the natural order, they called him the Finisher. The name or etymology of a name in a given myth had what might be called a “one-to-one” relationship with the specific function of the god in the story. Zeus could be, by turns, the source of life (following his etymology from zen, “to live”), or the aether (the fiery upper air), or thunder (his attribute in iconography was the thunderbolt), or the whole sky (in expressions such as “Zeus rains”). Thus a single etymology is not always seen as essential to the interpretative process. Balbus provides a good illustration of this principle: Our soothsayers refer thunder and lightning to Jupiter, saying “Jupiter lightens” or “Jupiter thunders” … The air, however, as the Stoics argue, being interposed between the sea and the sky, is worshipped under the name belonging to Juno, who is the sister and wife of Jupiter. There is an affinity between the air and aether and they are closely linked together. The air was regarded as the softest and most feminine of the elements and was therefore assigned to Juno. The name, however, I believe to be derived from iuvare (“to help”).15 It is notable that in this passage only Juno (the Roman Hera) is given an etymology (“to help”), which is meant to underscore the claimed affinity between aether and air: the air can be seen as “assisting,” that is, supporting, the bright aether that is above it (just as a wife supports her husband). Etymology is frequently summoned as an aid to understanding, but often very ancient associations of divine names and things are simply taken as understood, even when there is no obvious etymology. The Stoics and everybody else had to accept that the name Zeus did not sound at all like aither (“aether”), astrapē (“lightning”), brontē (“thunder”), or ouranos (“sky”), and had to be content with traditional understandings based on the functions of a god in myth or religion. Lucilius Balbus is the spokesman for the Stoic position on the gods in the second book of Cicero’s dialogue, On the Nature of the Gods. That is about all that is known of him. Cicero has Balbus contend in a debate with an Epicurean and an Academician (essentially a skeptic) on the questions of the existence of gods, their nature, their governance of the world, and their care for mankind. Much of what he says undoubtedly reflects Cicero’s own understanding of Stoicism as well as his opinions on religion. Practically all of this falls outside the scope of our book. However, Balbus’s ideas on the nature of 118 118 the anatomy of my th the gods—what sorts of beings called gods are really gods—do impact on the interpretation of myth. Moreover, Balbus appears in a dialogue that is mostly intact. The upshot is that we have a coherent text, rather than a group of fragments, that gives us some idea of the positions of the various philosophical schools in the first century b.c.e. that have relevance to the interpretation of myth. Cicero’s dialogue is a very different kind of work from Cornutus’s Summary. Cicero’s book is directed to questions about the nature of the gods, while Cornutus wants to see how the names of the gods explain their function in particular myths. Balbus, after arguing the existence of the gods, attempts to classify all the different beings to which the name “god” is applied. Cornutus doesn’t have to worry about such questions. He simply takes the names of gods as given in the myths and builds his interpretations from them. Cicero via Balbus leads us back to basic questions about divinity that had been raised earlier. He gives a nod to Prodicus’s idea that those things which confer benefits on mankind were deified by men of old. Is Ceres truly something divine, or just plain bread? Balbus hints at Hesiod’s tale of Pandora’s box when he tells us that a Roman named Calatinus had set up a monument to Hope (2.61). This, of course, reprises the question of how to read abstractions when they occur in myths. Do we see Faith and Reason, or Virtue, as real gods to whom we can pray, as manifestations or emanations of the divine, or simply abstract concepts devised by the human mind? And, following Plato, by invoking the planets and stars as ensouled, Balbus prompts us to investigate traditional myths that involve the metamorphosis of a mortal into a star or constellation (Callisto turned into the Great Bear), or a life divided between the heavens and earth (Castor and Pollux). We have seen how Cornutus avoided attributing the authorship of a myth to a poet, and in one significant passage called a story “a fragment of an ancient myth.” Balbus appears to take the same tack, referring to the Kronos tale as “an old legend of the Greeks.” Moreover, the myths of the gods contain scientific truths in their nature, but these were turned into the fables of the poets that corrupted human life with superstition. A great number of gods have also been derived from scientific theories about the world of nature. Endowed with human shapes, they have provided fables for the poets and have permeated human life with every form of superstition. This subject has been treated by Zeno and explained in greater length by Cleanthes and Chrysippus. For example, it was an old legend of the Greeks that the Sky-God [Ouranos] was mutilated by his son Saturn [Kronos] and Saturn in his turn was made captive by his son Jupiter [Zeus]. These impious tales are merely the picturesque disguise of a sophisticated scientific theory. Those who invented them felt that the high and fiery nature 119 the grow th of allegory 119 of the Sky-God should have no use for those parts of the body which require intercourse with another to beget a child.16 The passage requires some unpacking. Working from the bottom line, we find a physical theory that asserts the Stoic claim that a fiery aetherial nature is responsible for the generation of everything. (The Stoics had taken on board Heraclitus’s idea that fire is the archē of all things.) Let us return to the top of the passage: the authors of myths had described this element as the source of a multitude of gods. (Afterward) the poets dressed these natural divinities in human garb, thereby spreading every kind of superstition. The founders of Stoicism uncovered the ruse and explained the original meaning of the stories. These original meanings, Balbus believes, would have been in the minds of the author of the myths (not the poets). In the refined “original” versions of the myths, procreation would not have proceeded according to human custom. Saturn (Ouranos) did not need a penis, and by extension, other gods did not require one, either. The conclusion simultaneously eliminates all the tales of the gods seducing mortal women to produce heroes. Interpreted thus, the passage sheds light on the early Stoic theory on the origin of myths. Myths are not the creations of poets (at least not in their original form); they were the brain children of a great cosmologist who lived in the distant past. This deep thinker (or thinkers) is not identified. The poets corrupted the stories with their anthropomorphic notions and turned the gods into fallible beings like humans, breeding superstition as their tales moved through human societies. Such was the conclusion of Zeno and his immediate followers. As we have seen, three centuries later Cornutus views myths as very ancient stories, and the intentions of their authors never come into focus. The act of interpretation is then no longer an act of uncovering the specific intention of a poet, but rather in finding a possible meaning or meanings in the “original” myth. Cornutus, at points, suggests that original meanings might be recoverable by comparing Greek myths with those of other cultures. He notes, for example, that the myth of Demeter and Hades shows parallels with the Egyptian story of Isis and Osiris and the Phoenician tale of Adonis. In other words, we may be able to recoup ancient wisdom by seeing beyond a purely local version of a myth.17 However, the ancient wisdom that Cornutus discovers more often than not turns out to be consistent with Stoic cosmological doctrine. Up to this point we have seen only hints by ancient writers at a proper discussion of allegory. Even the word “allegory” (allegoria) did not surface until the first century b.c.e., when Cicero, writing in Latin, classified it as a figure of speech. Cicero equated allegory with extended metaphor, and thus saw it as a tool available to writers (Orator 27.94). The word had not yet assumed the meaning “to understand something in a figurative sense.” To express this, the Greeks relied on Plato’s term hyponoia, literally, “underthought,” that is, 120 120 the anatomy of my th the sense that lies below the surface meaning. We had to wait until Plutarch to learn that hyponoia had been replaced by allegoria. One critic, possibly a Stoic, who left a full treatise illustrating the method of allegorical interpretation was a certain Heraclitus, thought to have lived in the first century c.e. (We shall refer to him as Heraclitus the Younger to avoid confusion with the more famous Heraclitus of Ephesus, who has figured prominently above.) Heraclitus the Younger’s book Homeric Problems consists of explanations of “problematic” passages in the Iliad. Heraclitus was the first to state unambiguously that allegory is “a method of composition [he calls it a ‘figure’] that speaks of a matter in such a way that it signifies a second thing that is entirely different.”18 For example, he interprets a description of a sea storm in a poem by Alcaeus (seventh–sixth century b.c.e.) as an allegory (metaphor) for a conspiracy to establish a tyranny.19 Elsewhere he explicitly stated that “since the trope of allegory is familiar to all other writers and even to Homer, what should prevent us mending his alleged wrong notions about the gods by this kind of justification?”20 Heraclitus believed that allegory belonged to the intention of the writer, and this fact justified an allegorical interpretation on the part of the reader. The assertion also illustrates faith in “the doctrine of present things”: the belief that what is true today must have been true in the past as well. This Heraclitus’s work stands firmly in a long tradition of treatises on Homer that concentrate on select passages, in particular ones that are morally problematic or challenge our credulity. It is likely that many of the bothersome Homer passages were the same from treatise to treatise (for example, a god sending a misleading dream, Hephaestus thrown out of heaven, Hera suspended by chains, the adultery of Aphrodite and Ares). Unfortunately, these are lost except for their titles and some quotations in later sources, leaving Heraclitus’s book as a precious witness to how earlier treatises were organized. The Homeric Problems are organized by work, Iliad first, then Odyssey, and generally follow the order of the narratives. Heraclitus sets out to rebut the attacks by Homer’s “enemies”—Plato and Epicurus belong to this group. In defending Homer, Heraclitus does not stick strictly to naturalistic interpretations, but also ventures into psychological explanations. Nor does he attempt to maintain consistent interpretations throughout, but changes his explanations to suit each individual myth. However, in contrast to Cornutus, Heraclitus was confident that myths came from poets, and poets disguised their real intentions. Heraclitus the Younger was nothing if not ingenious. His take on Apollo’s bow-and-arrow attack on the Greek army at the beginning of the Iliad might even today win plaudits for its cleverness. He points out that Homer’s usual name for Apollo is Phoebus “the shining or radiant one.” (Heraclitus is right about that.) Accordingly, Homer is talking about the sun. Homer describes Phoebus as “far-working,” which is logical, given that the sun, even though distant from the earth, has a great effect on it. Apollo’s arrows are the rays of 121 the grow th of allegory 121 the sun, which are the main source of epidemics. Plagues are caused by corruption of the atmosphere when summers are too hot and dry. Accordingly, the event described by Homer should not be attributed to the anger of a god, but to natural changes in the atmosphere (H.P. 8.1–7). At a single stroke Heraclitus has shown that Homer is knowledgeable about medicine (as well as many other subjects) and should not be accused of attributing shameful acts to the gods. In discussing the “bad myth” of Zeus’s suspension of Hera in the sky, he writes: It has escaped their notice that this passage contains a theological account of the creation of the universe, and that the order of these lines corresponds to the constantly celebrated four elements, of which I have already spoken: first aether, then air; then water; and finally earth: the creative elements of the universe. Combined with one another, these create animals and are the origin of inanimate things.21 Fire is not mentioned among the elements in the passage, because Zeus, as aether, is fire. So much at least is Stoic. So is his exegesis of the Homeric “unbreakable bond” (desmon … arrēkton): “since the harmony of the universe is secured by unbreakable bonds.”22 Whether or not Heraclitus was a dyed-in-the-wool Stoic seems beside the point. He concentrates on cosmology and frequently invokes Stoic doctrines. Heraclitus not only argues in favor of authorial intention, but also frequently interprets by substitution. Apollo does not shoot arrows at the Greeks to avenge his wronged priest, but the sun (that is, Apollo) in the summer months causes a plague by means of its rays (arrows): “It is not the wrath of Apollo angry without cause, but a philosophical idea related to scientific speculation.” (16.5). Interestingly, even though Heraclitus the Younger attributes the authorship of the myth to the poet, he confesses a Stoic attachment to the notion that a philosophical or scientific theory lies behind the fable. Heraclitus the Younger was no stranger to etymology. He used it adeptly to explain the many-faceted character of Proteus, the shape shifter who would metamorphose into a new form even as one wrestled with him and tried to pin him down. Proteus’ daughter is Eidothea—justly so called, for she is the vision [thea] of every form [eidos]. This is why Proteus, originally a single being [physis] was divided into many forms, being so fashioned by providence.23 Heraclitus proceeds from his etymology to define the true nature of Proteus. We should not believe that such a supernatural being existed. Homer, rather, is weaving another allegory of creation: 122 122 the anatomy of my th It is reasonable then that formless matter should be called Proteus, that the Providence which formed everything should be called Eidothea, and that everything which derives from these two principles, once separated out, should be divided into continuous masses which are constitutive of the universe.24 The notion of constituent elements that are “continuous” is Stoic.25 Heraclitus, then, is not so different from Cornutus in concentrating on cosmological myths and relating them to Stoic doctrine wherever he can. What differentiates him from Cornutus, and perhaps the older Stoics, is his consistent attribution of the origin of the myths to Homer (not an anonymous mythoplast), and his deep conviction that Homer not only created the myths but also instilled them with hidden cosmological meanings: It seems to me that the reason why Homer allegorizes so constantly about these matters is to make the obscurity which seems to threaten his lines more intelligible by continuous inculcation of the lesson.26 Myth criticism and philosophy were joined at the hip. Just as Plato did, the poets before him employed fable to make the inculcation of deep philosophical truths easier and more enjoyable for students. For Heraclitus the Younger, Homer was a philosopher. Despite Stoic influences on Heraclitus’s exegesis, his regard for the wisdom of the poets distinguished him from mainstream Stoicism. The truths the philosophers taught, of course, depended on the doctrines of the particular philosophical school engaged in their exegesis. The Stoic tradition from its founder Zeno to Cornutus posited an initial revelation, an ancient wisdom that was corrupted by the poets. The doctrines of this ancient wisdom are principally “scientific,” that is, centered on cosmological and physical truths. They happen to coincide with the physical doctrine of the Stoics. The ancient wisdom can be recovered only by clearing away the tissue of falsehoods engendered by the poets.27 Allegory, coupled with etymology, became the primary tool for achieving that objective. For Stoics, the application of allegory did not recover the intention of the poet, as Heraclitus the Younger believed, but rather the ancient wisdom that was revealed in a distant age. In their search for a definitive revelation the Stoics demonstrate how far they had come from the progressive ideal of Xenophanes: “Yet the gods have not revealed all things to men from the beginning; but by seeking, men find out better in time.”28 123 10 Saving the Poets without Allegory All of the types of interpretation we have dealt with up to now are in some sense species of allegory. Allegory goes to work whether or not it is employed in defense of the poets or the interpretation of a myth detached from an author. It stays true to its basic definition: it searches for a meaning that is different from what is said. It digs below the surface, and ferrets out the underthought, the hyponoia. It works the same way whether dealing with the physical cosmos or the microcosmos, which is the soul. Even the attempts to reduce myth to history are a type of allegory. When interpreters use this technique, they are claiming that the author meant something different from the surface text, because he meant something less than what was said or written. If he says that Cerberus is only a guard dog, he is saying that it is something different from its mythical description. All of these varieties of allegory work on the principle of substitution. When I say that Hera is the air, Odysseus is the soul, or Cerberus is an ordinary guard dog, I perform this operation in order to make what I think is better sense out of something confusing or incredible. In the process of substituting, I remove the thing replaced. We are left with a question: was allegory the only approach to interpreting myth? For the Greeks, it was the most commonly used, at least if allegory is understood to include all the species of it that we have discussed. But there is, and was, an alternative. One could follow Aristotle, shrug one’s shoulders, and say, “Such is the tale.” All forms of allegory are directed to addressing the problem of literal truth in myth and legend. But one could counter this and assert that the literal truth of a tale doesn’t matter; what counts is the moral message. The argument over literal truth in poetry and the intention of the poets had so obsessed Greek thought since the sixth century that it was very difficult to break outside the box. But if one sees poetry as more akin to philosophy than to history, one can derive value from its universal truths. Aristotle laid the foundations for this approach in his Poetics. In the Nichomachaean Ethics he built examples into his structure. The actions and reactions of the gods and heroes of the “great myths” become prototypes of 124 124 the anatomy of my th behaviors to be emulated or avoided. Plato had anticipated this idea; however, as he believed that the depictions of the deeds and emotions of gods and heroes in the myths were universally objectionable, he pleaded for censorship. But Aristotle obviously concluded that there was truth to be gleaned from bad examples as well as good. The personae of myth (both divine and human) can be used to exemplify instances of virtue and vice. Characters derived from myth can be mixed indiscriminately with historical figures, as it doesn’t matter whether the person existed or not. Aristotle cited the words given to Homer’s goddess Calypso for avoiding extremes (N.E. 1109a)1, while the diet of the wrestler Milo, an attested six-time winner at the Olympic games, was used to illustrate the idea that what is good for one person to eat is not necessarily good for another (N.E.1106b). In discussing high-mindedness, that is, avoiding boasting about the favors one has done for someone, he praised the goddess Thetis for not calling attention to the favors she had done for Zeus (Il. 1, 504), and lauded the Spartans for mentioning the good they had received from the Athenians while avoiding a mention of the benefits they brought to the latter. The Spartans obviously existed and their embassies were recorded, whereas Thetis, like Calypso, belonged to the world of myth. None of that mattered. It is the life lessons they were said to teach that count, as shown again by the juxtaposition of the attested politician Pithacus (seventh–sixth century b.c.e.) with Euripides’ mythical scions of Oedipus in the Phoenician Women (N.E. 1167a). Pithacus exemplifies concord in a state, while Eteocles and Polyneices are examples of faction. Most of Aristotle’s examples are drawn from specific actions or speeches in specific contexts. So and so should be praised or blamed when he or she did such and such. The philosopher praised the hero Philoctetes for breaking his vow to Odysseus because the vow involved telling a lie (N.E. 1140a). Aristotle did not praise Philoctetes in a general way or hold him up as a “type” of honesty. However, on occasion Aristotle slips into generalization, as he does with Aphrodite: Moreover, the more underhanded a person is, the more unjust he is. Now a hot-tempered man is not underhanded; nor is anger: it is open. But appetite has the same attribute as Aphrodite, who is called “weaver of guile on Cyprus born.”2 Similarly, arbitrariness in dealing with one’s wife and children is cited as a general characteristic of the Cyclopes, in contrast to the orderly practice of the Spartans, who raise their children according to laws (N.E. 1180a). Here we have a comparison between a historically attested people and a mythical race. The myths of the poets are vindicated. They provide immediately recognizable comparanda for evaluating the morality of human actions, be they good or bad. 125 saving the poets without allegory 125 While in the majority of cases, Aristotle validates the poet’s judgment of his characters, he is on occasion capable of issuing censure on a poet when the poet appears to defend an evil action by one of his characters: There are some instances in which such actions elicit forgiveness rather than praise, for example, when a man acts improperly under a strain greater than human nature can bear and which no one could endure. Yet there are perhaps also acts which no man can possibly be compelled to do, but rather than do them he should accept the most terrible sufferings and death. Thus the circumstances that compel Alcmaeon in Euripides’ play to kill his own mother are patently absurd.3 Aristotle’s tendency to treat historical and mythical personages indifferently as examples of character types was reflected in the work of Dio Chrysostom, a rhetorician and philosopher of the first century c.e. 4 Born in Bithynia (Asia Minor), he was active as a rhetorician in Rome. Like Cornutus, who fell afoul of Nero, Dio was banished from Rome by Domitian, and led the life of a wandering teacher of Stoic philosophy until rehabilitated by Nerva. His writings consist of a series of Discourses. In his Fourth Discourse he presents a comparison of the characters of Achilles and Alexander (the Great): Now Alexander was again hurt and vexed, for he did not care to live at all unless he might be king of Europe, Asia, and Libya, and of any islands that might lie in the ocean. His state of mind, you see, was the opposite of what Homer says was that of Achilles’ ghost. For that hero said that he preferred to live in bondage to “some man of mean estate … rather than reign over all who have gone down to death” (Od. 11, 490 ff.). But Alexander, I doubt not, would have chosen to die and govern even a third part of the dead rather than become merely a god and live forever, unless, of course, he could become king over other gods. Perhaps, too, Zeus is the only one for whom he would have shown no contempt, and that because men call him king.5 Today we would recognize Dio’s nice distinction as that between a proud man who values life and freedom and a megalomaniac whose ego and ambition know no bounds—the total “control freak” who stops at nothing to get his or her way. The description of Alexander’s character is simply chilling. Our instinct is to stay out of his way at all costs. The value of this kind of moralizing was recognized by Dio’s contemporary Plutarch. Plutarch would have been about a generation younger than Cornutus and possibly a contemporary of Heraclitus the Younger. He was a teacher at both Athens and Rome, and spent the last thirty years of his life as a 126 126 the anatomy of my th priest at Delphi. We met him earlier as the biographer of Theseus who sought to purify myths with reason (logos) so as to reduce them to plausible history. In his Life of Theseus, Plutarch employs the methods of rationalizing criticism discussed in c­ hapter 7, but does not use either the physical allegory favored by the Stoics or the psychological method beloved of the Platonists. Indeed, he tells us nothing about his attitude to allegory in that work. We learn more about him as a critic of poetry and myth in his treatise On the Study of Poetry. After encountering the often far-fetched interpretations of the Stoic allegorists, we find it refreshing to meet a critic who might be considered sane by modern standards. Siding occasionally with Plato, more often with Aristotle, Plutarch manages to defend poetry against its detractors without resorting to allegory. But in the treatise cited he does not ignore the subject; indeed, as we shall see, Plutarch is openly disdainful of that method of interpretation.6 Plutarch follows in the tracks of Plato by treating the study of literature as a pedagogical matter. His treatise On the Study of Poetry is aimed at those charged with teaching poetry to young men. Near the beginning he compares poetry to drinking wine and eating: “It is nice to eat, but it results in sleep disturbed by dreams, with confused and outlandish visions, or so they say. Similarly with poetry: it contains much that is pleasant and profitable to the young mind, but just as much that is confusing and misleading, if study is not properly directed.”7 As for guarding against over-imbibing, Plutarch recommends mixing water with the wine rather than cutting down vines: “Mixing destroys the harm in wine, but not its usefulness. Let us not therefore cut out or destroy the vine of the Muses.”8 Solon’s dictum “poets tell many lies” receives Plutarch’s assent. However, some lies are deliberate, others involuntary. The deliberate lies are caused by poets believing that truth is drier than fiction. However, more often poets deceive themselves with their own false beliefs, “which then rub off on us.”9 They are fooled, for example, into believing that gods lay dooms of death on scales, and that when the scale tips, the soul with the heavier doom goes down to Hades. After presenting a series of what he regards as false and superstitious beliefs endorsed by poets, Plutarch concludes that the best way to guard against being infected by them is to acknowledge “that poetry is not concerned with the truth.”10 Here he stands close to Aristotle who, as we noted, was indifferent to the literal truth of myth. In defense of the poets, Plutarch invokes Empedocles, Xenophanes, and even Socrates, to the effect that truth about divine matters (including life after death) is unattainable. Far from being a true description of divine truths, poetry, according to Plutarch, should be understood as “an art of imitation, a capacity analogous to painting.” Here we are back in familiar territory. Let us recall that both Plato and Aristotle treated poetry as a form of mimēsis (imitation). However, the two philosophers disagreed sharply over the meaning of mimēsis, and whether it was good or bad. Plato believed imitation (whether poetry or painting) to be 127 saving the poets without allegory 127 artificial and seriously misleading. Aristotle thought imitation to be innately natural and good. It is the principal means by which we learn. Perhaps a bit intimidated by his old teacher, Aristotle did not openly assert that the imitation of bad things in art was good. Plutarch was unfazed by such inhibitions. He follows on with a compelling defense of mimēsis in both the visual arts and poetry based on the pleasure of the recipient in recognition of the like: Let us explain that when we see a picture of a lizard or a monkey or Thersites’ face [a man portrayed as ugly in Il. 2, 212ff.], we feel pleasure and admiration not because it is beautiful but because it is like. In reality, ugliness cannot become beautiful, but imitation is commended if it achieves likeness, whether of a good or a bad object. Indeed, if it produces a beautiful image of an ugly thing, it fails to provide propriety [to prepon] or probability … The young student must be educated especially in this kind of thing, and be taught that we praise not the action represented by the imitation but the art shown in the appropriate reproduction of the subject.11 A potential critic of Plutarch could raise the objection that one cannot admire the art of a poet’s description of the Olympian gods, because by Plutarch’s own admission it is impossible to know the truth about them; hence there would be only the “copy” without any way of verifying its likeness to the original. This would be a valid criticism, but not completely fatal. The criterion of the fitting would still apply to human behavior. There are enough examples of good and bad conduct in life to enable the critic of literature to judge when a writer has imitated them “beautifully”—to use Plutarch’s word. Plutarch gives samples of speeches from plays that illustrate bad character, then remarks: All these remarks are wicked and false, but they are in character for Eteocles, Ixion, and an old money lender. If therefore we remind our children that the poets do not commend or approve this kind of thing but simply attribute queer and vicious words to vicious and queer characters, they will not be harmed by the poets’ opinion.12 Plutarch raises the objection that the punishments for wicked deeds are often not portrayed on the stage, or are left unmentioned in the epics. He alleges that these omissions are often the reason for allegorization of episodes. If bad deeds are not seen being explicitly punished, then they must be explained away. Plutarch rants against the physical allegorists, highlighting the absurdity of their interpretations: Some critics in fact have so forced and perverted the meaning of these [tales] by using what used to be called hyponoia and is now called 128 128 the anatomy of my th allegory, as to interpret the revelation by Helios of Ares’ adultery with Aphrodite as meaning that the planet Mars in conjunction with the planet Venus produces adulterous births, which are revealed by the return of the sun on his course to discover them; or again, to interpret the way in which Hera beautified herself for Zeus, and the magic of the cestus [a stitched or embroidered girdle], as symbolizing a purification of the air coming into proximity with the fiery element.13 The second interpretation brings to mind the efforts of the Stoic cosmologists to demythologize by desexualizing. But Plutarch’s central point is that allegory distorts and serves no useful purpose. The stories carry their own moral lessons with them, and that is enough. The passage should also be noted because, as far as I know, Plutarch was the first to equate the term “allegory” with hyponoia as pertaining to interpretation rather than composition. As we saw, Cicero classed allegory as a figure of speech, thus a literary device available to writers, while Heraclitus the Younger also saw it as belonging to composition, but added that it is a figure that signifies something different from what is thought. Plutarch clearly held strong reservations about allegory as a mode of interpretation, but he did not disapprove of mixing the fables of poetry with philosophy to make the study of philosophy easier and more attractive for young men. As noted, the philosophical fable was well entrenched because of Plato’s widespread use of it. Indeed, critics who thought that the past was not very different from the present believed that the fables of the early poets also contained philosophical truths. If Plato used fables to teach philosophy, why should Homer not have done the same? The replacement of the old term hyponoia (the meaning beneath) by allegoria, reported by Plutarch, brought about the convergence of meanings of allegory as a mode of composition with allegory as a mode of understanding. One composed allegory so that it could be understood allegorically. One understood allegorically because one was convinced that it was composed that way. The same convergence occurred later with the verb “to theologize.” It could mean either to write about the gods in some disguised way or to interpret writing about the gods as containing veiled meanings.14 Plutarch was the clearest exponent of Aristotle’s principle of taking a myth on its own terms. Literal truth was unimportant. The myths of the poets contained examples of good and bad behavior that were highly valuable for the education of the young. These examples included things to be avoided as well as to be imitated. However, Plutarch was not the last to espouse these notions. Basil of Caesarea (St. Basil), who lived in the middle of the fourth century c.e., propounded very similar teachings to those of Plutarch.15 Although he is known as one of the founders of eastern Christian monasticism, like many 129 saving the poets without allegory 129 Greeks of his era Basil had received a thorough education in the classics. He left behind a famous treatise entitled “Address to Young Men on How They Might Derive Benefit from Greek Literature.” Himself a debtor to Greek literature, he limns the debt of Moses to the Egyptians for the gift of “the contemplation of Him who is,” and of Daniel to the Chaldeans “for their divine teachings.”16 The Christian Basil does not seem remote from the pagan Plutarch when he writes: First, then, as to the learning to be derived from the poets, that I may begin with them, inasmuch as the subjects they deal with are of every kind, you ought not to give your attention to all they write without exception; but whenever they recount for you the deeds or words of good men, you ought to cherish and emulate these and try to be as far as possible like them; but when they treat of wicked men, you ought to avoid such imitation, stopping your ears no less than Odysseus did, according to what those same poets say, when he avoided the songs of the Sirens.17 Basil reveals himself as a student of Aristotle by his tacit praise of Odysseus, who set an example of how to avoid temptation. Also like Aristotle, he got his story mixed up (and ironically, the confusion involved Circe). Following Circe’s advice, Odysseus commanded his crew to stuff their ears with wax while binding him tight to a mast so that he might hear the Sirens’ songs without being physically able to succumb to them (Od. 12, 38–60, 160–61). But the point is that pagan poetry provides salutary lessons for avoiding temptation and supplies role models to be followed in specific ethical situations. No less daunting a figure than St. Augustine, who railed often and long against the evils contained in pagan poetry, selected archetypes from Greek and Roman literature to guide him in his difficulties. Meditating on the death of his closest boyhood friend, he wrote: True or not, the story goes that Orestes and Pylades were ready to die for each other’s sake, because each would rather die than live without the other. But I doubt whether I should have been willing, as they were, to give my life for a friend.18 The words “true or not” in this case render Augustine a catechumen under Aristotle’s tutelage. It didn’t matter to Augustine whether Orestes and Pylades were real or fictional. The two young heroes were embedded in his and everyone’s consciousness as the archetypes of absolute loyalty in friendship. They were the first to come to mind when one was confronted by a parallel in one’s own life. They provided the gnōmōn, the yardstick, by which one measured one’s own character. 130 131 11 From Allegory to Symbolism As we saw in c­ hapter 5, Plato was convinced that the myths in Homer and Hesiod’s epics could not be rendered suitable for children’s education. Allegory was of no use. Better fables were required, so Plato set out to write them himself. Practically all of Plato’s myths dealt with the soul and its attributes. Two dialogues, the Symposium and the Phaedrus, accorded a special place to the soul and Eros, the great god of love. Eros, of course, had enjoyed a good run with the cosmologists, going back to Hesiod, but the Stoic interpreters of myth studiously avoided erotic interpretations when dealing with sexual episodes in poetry. All was reduced to physical cosmology. Plato put Eros back in orbit, and treated him as the sexy god he really is. He taught us that our souls can never attain to the possession of Beauty in its pure form, if they do not first experience the attraction to a beautiful physical form, which Eros alone makes possible. Such is the message of the Symposium. Centuries elapsed before any other philosopher stepped forward to use fable as a vehicle for philosophical instruction. Plutarch, who is often grouped with the Middle Platonists, applauded the practice of teaching philosophy through myth. But the world of letters had to wait for a North African writing in Latin to come forward with a new philosophical fable. The work is all the more astonishing because it is embedded in a comic novel with the alternative title The Golden Ass. “Out of Africa always something new,” as the saying goes, and Apuleius’s tale, “Amor and Psyche,” was and is breathtakingly new. Indebted to Plato for its central philosophical message, it reverted to a Hesiodic model of allegory, leapfrogging over the parable-type of fable that Plato produced, and embracing old-style personification. Had Apuleius stopped there, his work would have ended in failure. We can only imagine a yawn-inducing, expanded version of “Heracles at the Crossroads,” or a Platonic recasting of the Psychomachia (“Battle for Mansoul”), easily the best soporific on the market before the invention of barbiturates. The characters that populate “Amor and Psyche” may be symbolic, but they are not made of cardboard. Amor is 132 132 the anatomy of my th indeed Love personified, but he is motivated by instincts that are anything but abstract. He behaves like any teenaged boy who likes to indulge in sex but is still afraid of being caught by his mother. Psyche is Soul, but like any teenaged girl, Psyche responds to her situation with a mixture of excitement and apprehension. Moreover, she is gullible, naïve in every way, and flawed. Twice she is nearly undone by her curiosity. Apuleius makes us think of Pandora’s Box when Psyche opens a vial of Hades’ perfume, which she was forbidden to sense. If one did not know better, one would think that Apuleius had read Cinderella and Snow White, or at least had seen the movies. Venus begins as the haughty queen of Snow White and morphs into the cruel stepmother of Cinderella. Amor is the prince whom three sisters want to marry, but only Psyche succeeds in gaining. Psyche is saved from a bad fate by Amor, just as Snow White is saved from the Queen’s appointed assassins, but the girl later undergoes Cinderella’s fate as a char in the house of her stepmother. While there is little or no comedy in modern fairy tales, “Amor and Psyche” is full of ironic wit. Amor forbids Psyche to know his godlike identity not for mystical reasons, but because he is afraid Psyche will tattle, and he will be scolded and grounded by his mother for disobeying her orders. And if pathos is wanted, what could be more heart-rending than the tale of a beautiful girl ordered to be wedded to Death by the oracle of Apollo? The tale begins with the widespread recognition of Psyche’s exceptional beauty—such that she is treated as a goddess and the rites of Venus are neglected. Venus realizes that she has been surpassed in beauty by a mortal girl and flies into a rage. She orders Psyche to be inflamed with passion and married to a man of low estate; she tasks her son Amor to work his usual mischief with the girl. Psyche meanwhile is driven to despair. Her sisters have already married, but no suitor can be found for her because her godlike beauty renders her untouchable. She laments her state to her father, who consults the oracle of Apollo. The oracle orders that Psyche be wedded to Death. She is led by a wedding-funeral procession to the crag from which she must leap. But Psyche does not die. She wakes up in a lovely place and enters a beautiful palace, where she is treated as the mistress and receives every service she could wish for. Needless to say, tricky Amor was behind all this. His mother had shown him Psyche’s outstanding beauty and he wanted her for himself. He came to her at night in the palace and immediately “made her his wife.” Psyche can sense her “husband” in every way except by sight; she cannot know his identity. In the morning an invisible Amor advises her sternly not to make contact with her sisters, for they will cause her destruction. But Psyche grows lonely, as she is left by herself all day. She prevails upon Amor to let her sisters visit. The sisters, riven with envy, inveigle Psyche to admit she does not know her husband’s identity. They make her think that her spouse may be a monster and urge her to kill him in his sleep. Persuaded by her sisters, Psyche waits 133 from allegory to symbolism 133 for Amor to fall asleep, then, holding a razor in her hand, lights a lamp to get a good look at him. Alas, hot wax drips down from the lamp on to the god’s face; he wakes and flees to his mother’s bedchamber to assuage the burn he has suffered. Meanwhile, a little bird has told Venus, who is not at home, all about what her darling son has been up to. Infuriated, she makes a beeline for her palace, finds her rascal son, gives him a good piece of her mind, and grounds him. Then she heads out to find Psyche. Psyche had discovered her husband’s identity from the bow and arrows the god left behind in his haste. One of the arrows pricked her finger, which ensured that she would fall desperately in love with Love. Despairing over her loss, she manages to get home and tell her sad story to her sisters. The sisters can barely conceal their glee and, assuming that Love is single again, go severally to the crag where Psyche first leapt. Thinking they would be wafted across the chasm to Amor’s bower, they fall to their deaths. Venus, tiring of searching for Psyche, enlists the help of her father, Jupiter, who sends Mercury on the errand. Psyche, knowing she is being hunted down, surrenders to Venus. The vindictive goddess sets the girl four tasks, the last of which requires a trip to Hades to bring back a vial of Venus’s favorite perfume. Psyche encounters great dangers in the process, but succeeds in performing them all. However, on her way back from Hades she is overcome by curiosity, opens the vial, and immediately falls into a deathlike swoon. Amor, desperate to be reunited with Psyche, escapes from his room through a window, finds Psyche, and revives her in the nick of time. Psyche takes the vial to Venus, while Amor flies to heaven to enlist the aid of Jupiter. After making a comical speech blaming Amor for all his adulteries, Jupiter assents, calls an assembly of the gods, and proclaims the union of Amor and Psyche. Psyche is made immortal and joined to Amor in eternal union. A wonderful story, you will say, but where is the allegory? True, Apuleius has composed a fable that is far longer and more complex than any of the fables composed by Plato. It incorporates many elements of the fairy tale, or Märchen, including hateful sisters and a cruel stepmother (mother-in-law in this story). It also features a handful of ordinary human beings, such as Psyche’s parents and sisters. Its mystical content is obfuscated by comic episodes, nor can one overlook the fact that the tale is told by an aged crone who cooks for bandits. To lower the tone even further, the author himself labeled it a “Milesian tale,” a genre of stories of sexual adventures, allegedly originating in Miletus. This disconnect in register was jarring to ancient critics, though far less so to modern sensibilities inured to bizarre intrusions of foreign register and genre. The fact remains that the story is about a god named Love and a mortal girl named Soul who end up united for all time. Love achieves his aim, which is the possession of beauty. Soul, who suffers near-death experiences, regains her wings and immortality through love. The only obstacle to this reading is the very last 134 134 the anatomy of my th sentence, where we learn that their immortal child is a girl called Pleasure. With that, Apuleius reminds us that his tale is Milesian—the genre demands an ironic ending. Written by a Platonist writer,1 the work references Plato’s core teachings on love and soul. Love is incomplete without the possession of beauty; soul grows her wings through love. For an example of the first, let us look at what Plato had to say in the Symposium: Socrates: Now we have agreed that Love is in love with what he lacks and does not possess. Agathon: Yes. Socrates: So after all Love lacks and does not possess beauty? Agathon: Inevitably. Socrates: Well, then, would you call what lacks and in no way possesses beauty beautiful? Agathon: Certainly not. Socrates: Do you think then that Love is beautiful, if this is so? Agathon: It looks, Socrates, as if I didn’t know what I was talking about when I said that. Socrates: Still, it was a beautiful speech, Agathon. But there is just one more small point. Do you think that what is good is the same as what is beautiful? Agathon: I do. Socrates: Then, if love lacks beauty, and what is good coincides with what is beautiful, he also lacks goodness. Agathon: I can’t find any way of withstanding you, Socrates. Let it be as you say.2 To be sure, Apuleius left no autobiography behind to tell us that he was leafing through the Symposium when a voice told him to “take and read” as he scrolled down to this passage. Such evidence from antiquity turns up but rarely.3 But the passage is surely a text that Apuleius would have known, and could have served as his inspiration. Similarly, a passage from the Phaedrus may have been a catalyst for his allegory4 of Soul: Next, with the passing of the shudder, a strange sweating fever seizes him: for by reason of the stream of beauty entering through his eyes there comes a warmth, whereby his soul’s plumage is fostered; and with that warmth the roots of the wings are melted, which for long had been so hardened and closed up that nothing could grow; then as the nourishment is poured in, the stump of the wing swells and hastens to grow from the root over the whole substance of the soul: for aforetime the whole soul was furnished with wings.5 135 from allegory to symbolism 135 In a similar vein, the sisters’ fall to their deaths may be explained as the unfitness of their souls’ wings for flight. They are driven by lust rather than the longing for divine Love. Hear again what Plato had to say in the Phaedrus, a dialogue on love and the soul: The natural property of a wing is to raise that which is heavy and carry it aloft to the region where the gods dwell; and more than any other bodily part it shares in the divine nature, which is fair, wise and good, and possessed of all other such excellences. Now by these excellences the soul’s plumage is nourished and fostered, while by their opposites, even by ugliness and evil, it is wasted and destroyed.6 Psyche’s descent into the underworld is another element that warrants Platonic exegesis. In Plato’s “Myth of Er” the underworld is where the reincarnation of souls condemned to rebirth, or the release of purified souls, begins. Psyche returns to the upper air not yet purified, for she falls victim again to her curiosity and opens Proserpina’s vial of perfume intended for Venus. She experiences death or something akin to it, and can be saved only by an adventitious rescue by Amor, who has broken free from his imprisonment. Apuleius has composed the ideal psychological allegory, with Psyche (Soul) herself as the subject. But he has also given the world a tale that is touchingly beautiful and richly comic. The work is true to Plato, and despite its fairy-tale aspect, true to life. Love does indeed save the soul from death. The personifications in “Amor and Psyche” belong to the psychological or noetic world. From the beginning, personified abstractions were at the heart of composed allegories. Invariably, these represent persons and things that have no concrete existence. They are forces we know from their effects without being able to sense them as corporeal beings. They include virtue and vice, every kind of emotion (love, fear, panic—c hildren of Ares and Aphrodite), law and justice (both gods in their own right), and the soul and mind themselves. As we saw in c­ hapter 6, Zeus, an anthropomorphic god, “married” Metis (Counsel), then swallowed her in order to keep wisdom to himself. He also “married” two of his aunts, Themis (Law) and Mnemosyne (Memory). It is a partial truth that personification is the opposite of allegory on the grounds that personifications are self-e xplanatory, whereas allegory entails some concealed second meaning. But personified abstractions are not real people. You don’t see Faith standing on the street giving Reason a piece of her mind. Personifications, then, are metaphors for concepts in the mind, or they symbolize virtues (or vices) in the soul, so in that sense they do entail two levels of meaning. Apuleius mimetically represented the Soul itself in the character of Psyche. Psyche is both a beautiful teenaged girl and the Soul. He also enlisted gods as personifications of particular attributes. Ceres (bread), for example, refuses to come to Psyche’s aid because of 136 136 the anatomy of my th her loyalty to Venus, giving a nod to the proverb “Without Ceres … Venus grows cold.” By contrast, the great phenomena of the cosmos, which appear as anthropomorphic gods, are rarely personified as characters in a myth (Hesiod’s Gaia is an exception). Earth, Air, Fire, and Water do not populate stories, though the gods who represent them (for example, Zeus as aether, Hera as air, Hephaestus as fire) do. Because composed allegories introduce characters drawn from the noetic world (the world that can be experienced only by the mind), they remain attached—strongly or loosely—to Platonism. When interpreting, Platonists focus on those aspects of myths that evoke the noetic world, the things of the mind; when writing, they do the same. Belief in the close relationship between the intent of the composer and the interpretation of the critic remains consistent throughout the history of Platonism after Plato. The poets allegedly intended to portray truths about the noetic world under the guise of myth. This is most apparent in Neoplatonism, the latest phase of Platonism (beginning in the third century c.e.). The Neoplatonists were convinced that poetry concealed the deepest truths of metaphysics in symbolic form and devoted much of their writing to uncovering what was concealed.7 One of the most famous pieces of Neoplatonist exegesis still intact is Porphyry’s essay on Homer’s “Cave of the Nymphs,” which appears in Book 13 of the Odyssey. Let’s begin with Homer’s text: And at the head of the harbor is a slender-leaved olive and nearby it a lovely and murky cave sacred to the nymphs called Naiads. Within are kraters and amphoras of stone, where bees lay up stores of honey. Inside, too, are massive stone looms and there the nymphs weave sea-purple cloth, a wonder to see. The water flows unceasingly. The cave has two gates, the one from the north, a path for men to descend, while the other, toward the south, is divine. Men do not enter by this one, but it is rather a path for immortals.8 The only divine figures that appear in this passage are the nymphs called Naiads. The rest of the passage consists in the description of the cave, the objects in it and near to it, and its two entrances. In choosing the passage, Porphyry embarks into new territory. He concentrates on the symbolism of things rather than people (whether divine or human). In doing so, he must incorporate objects that belong to the world of the senses as well as the noetic world of the gods. He exploits these objects as a way of discussing, in symbolic terms, the doctrine of his teacher Plotinus on the relation of matter and soul, and the fall of the soul into matter: 137 from allegory to symbolism 137 Matter is an existing thing. Soul is an existing thing. They occupy, as it were, one place. There is no place of Matter distinct from the place of Soul; thus, Matter is not confined to earth and Soul to air. Yet Soul has its place apart in this sense, that it is not in Matter, that is, it is not united to Matter; that is, no unity is produced out of Soul and Matter; that is, Soul does not arise in Matter as in a subject. That is the Soul’s apartness.9 Plotinus, like Plato before him, felt obliged to confront the problem of how soul and matter are related: This entry into Matter is the Fall of the Soul; this, and the weakness which ensues because Matter, invading the Soul’s domain, and as it were forcing her to narrower bounds, does not permit all her powers to be actualized, but filches away a part and makes it evil, until it have strength again to escape upwards. Matter is thus the cause both of the soul’s weakness and of her vice.10 However one deals with the difficulty of compressing something that cannot be measured into a physical space, the contamination of the soul by matter is a central Neoplatonic dogma: “Matter invades the Soul’s domain.” The two do get mixed up, much to the disadvantage of soul. And even if “Soul is not confined to air,” air is nevertheless the place where soul wants to go—it is her natural habitat. Porphyry, in his exegesis, does not “wish away” all the material aspects of the cave, or treat them all as symbols of the noetic world, but gives each its proper place. At the same time, he follows his teacher in seeing matter as somehow corrupting. Those who are reborn into a body are unfortunate in comparison with the pure souls who free themselves forever from bodily influence. Porphyry begins with an interpretation of the cave itself: “Not only did they [the theologians] make the cave a symbol of the generated and perceptible cosmos, but likewise the ancients took it as a symbol of all the unseen powers11 … That the theologians made caves symbols of the cosmos and of the encosmic powers has been demonstrated, but it has also been asserted that they made them symbols of the noetic substance … They made them symbols of the cosmos because they are dark and rocky and damp … they made them symbols of the noetic universe, on the other hand, because they are not easily grasped by the senses.”12 Thus, for different reasons, the cave can symbolize both worlds, and Pophyry is intent on showing their relationship to each other. By resorting to the term “symbol” (symbolon) Porphyry is using a mode of interpretation that differs from that of the early physical allegorists and 138 138 the anatomy of my th the Stoics. In the strict sense, allegory operates like a code involving a substitution: When I say “Hera,” I really mean “air,” not some goddess real or imagined; or, when I say “Kronos,” I really mean “time,” not some monstrous being with a scythe. We have to delete the files of Hera and Kronos and save those of Air and Time. To do otherwise would be to insult Homer or Hesiod’s intelligence. However, Porphyry does not understand Homer’s cave as a substitute for the cosmos; rather, because of certain qualities, it suggests, hints at, or points to some characteristics of now the sensible universe, now the noetic world. The difference between the two types of interpretation can be underscored by inserting the word “only” before the intended meaning. A strict allegorist like Heraclitus the Younger would say, “When I say ‘arrows of Apollo’, I mean only ‘the rays of the sun.’ ” Porphyry would be inclined to put it, “The arrows of Apollo make us think of the rays of the sun.” Allegory is a species of metaphor, as Cicero following Aristotle taught, while symbolic language is akin to simile. Porphyry then skillfully connects the dampness of caves that symbolizes their material aspect to the central Neoplatonic idea that matter is the cause of the weakening of souls: There is a compulsion for souls, whether they are embodied or disembodied but still dragging along some corporeal material—and most of all for those souls that are just about to be bound to blood and moist bodies—to descend to moisture and, once they have been moistened, to become embodied.13 He summons to his aid Heraclitus the Elder, who claimed that “dry souls are the wisest,” arguing that “in this world the spirit becomes damp or saturated as a function of its sexual desire, and the soul drags a damp vapor along with it from its descent toward genesis.”14 The souls coming into genesis are symbolized by the Naiad nymphs. The olive tree mentioned in the first line of Homer’s text is kept to the last. Porphyry’s exegesis combines the conventional association of the olive tree with Athena, moves to thoughtfulness (via the goddess’s birth from the head of Zeus), and from there to the function of the tree in Homer’s account refashioned as Platonic fable: The olive tree belongs to Athena and Athena is thoughtfulness. In view of the fact that Athena was born from the head [of Zeus] the theologian [i.e., Homer] found an appropriate place, when he enshrined the tree at the “head” of the harbor and he indicated through the tree the fact that the universe did not come to be spontaneously nor was it the work of irrational chance, but rather that it is the result of noetic nature and of wisdom. At the same time, the tree is something separate from the 139 from allegory to symbolism 139 cave [as divine wisdom is something separate from the world], but set nearby at the head of the entire harbor.15 By emphasizing the separateness of the olive tree and interpreting it as a symbol of the noetic world, Porphyry references Plotinus’s dictum “matter is an existing thing. Soul is an existing thing. They occupy, as it were, one place.” “One place,” because the tree is at the “head” of the harbor and nearby to the cave. They are separate, but connected. There are other fascinating aspects of Porphyry’s interpretative essay, but perhaps we should concentrate on what Porphyry has to say on interpretation itself. At the very end of the essay he writes a short defense of his method: This sort of exegesis should not be considered forced, nor should it be equated with the sort of thing fanciful interpreters try to render plausible. When one takes into consideration the ancient wisdom and vast intelligence of Homer, along with his perfection in every virtue, one cannot reject the idea that he has hinted at images of more divine things in molding his little story. It is impossible that he should have successfully created the entire basis of the story without shaping that creation after some sort of truth.16 The first sentence of Porphyry’s defense is a shot across the bow at the enemies of allegory, at least allegory as defined by certain Neoplatonists. It is possible that when he wrote this, Porphyry had Plutarch in mind. As we saw above, Plutarch had taunted the allegorists in his On Teaching Poetry. Strictly speaking, Porphyry was not an allegorist in the sense of the term used up to this point. All the same, meanings detected by the symbolist interpreter must bear some relation to the meaning in the mind of the author, though, at least for Porphyry, the relation need not be exact. Porphyry’s allegiance to the language of symbolism forbids any single interpretation. Homer “hints at images of more divine things,” but he does not use myth to conceal philosophical truth. There is no imputed substitution.17 For that reason the language of symbolism does not need etymology for support. While etymologies involve our sense of hearing, symbolic language entails our sense of sight. We see with the eye of the mind the resemblance between a concept of the mind and an object in nature. A cave with two entrances can express the dichotomy between the noetic and material worlds,18 just as the sun can express the idea of the good (the sun illuminates the physical cosmos, while the good illuminates the universe of forms). Porphyry’s technique in his exegesis of the “Cave of the Nymphs” is worth a little more scrutiny. He extracts a description from Homer and lays out a literary canvas that can be called a tableau. He asks us to look at a particular cave and the objects in it and near it. He wants us to relate one 140 140 the anatomy of my th object to another, to see connections. Other writers, in a way, did this, too, when they described paintings and statues, as Philostratus did in his work The Images. Cornutus accomplished something similar when he described the attributes of the goddess Rhea, and the North African writer Martianus Capella followed suit when he described in detail the appearance and accessories of the female figures who represented the liberal arts. Porphyry asks us to look at the objects in the tableau as symbols of the physical cosmos and of the life of souls, and succeeds in this, even if he does not convince us today, that these symbols were in Homer’s mind. Porphyry skillfully draws his symbols from Neoplatonic doctrine and embeds them in a Homeric framework. Porphyry’s technique of laying out a grand tableau for the eye, then taking the viewer through the objects and persons depicted one by one, was not original. It was anticipated by a work that was once very popular, now rarely read. This is the Tabula Cebetis (“Tableau of Cebes”), a Greek work of uncertain date, but known and cited before Porphyry’s time. The historical Cebes was a disciple of Socrates who was allegedly present at his execution, but it is more than doubtful that it was that Cebes who was responsible for the work. There is almost nothing by way of a plot; all is description. Two visitors to the temple of Cronus (Kronos) come across an unusual painting in front of the shrine of the god. They find the fables depicted in it mystifying. A guide comes along to serve as an interpreter and take them through the images in the tablet: We happened to be strolling in the temple of Cronus, looking at the many different votive offerings in it. In front of the shrine was set up a tablet, on which there was an unusual painting with peculiar fables, and we were not able to make out what they could possibly be. For what was depicted seemed to us to be neither a walled city nor a military camp; it was, rather a circular enclosure having within itself two other circular enclosures, one larger and one smaller. There was also a gate in the first enclosure … Then, while we were questioning one another at length as to the meaning of the fable, an old man who was attending nearby said, “If you have any questions about this picture, O strangers, your reaction is not unusual.”19 There are, of course, very important differences between the Tabula and “The Cave of the Nymphs.” Porphyry finds his material in Homer, while the “Tabulist” invents his own. Porphyry has chosen a passage that is a description of things; the “Tabulist” populates his painting with people, personifications of the vices and virtues. Porphyry’s investigation is, one might say, metaphysical: an exploration into the nature of things. The “Tabulist” is essentially a moralist; his self-interpreting personifications are all related to the question of the good life. 141 from allegory to symbolism 141 What unites the two images is their static quality. There is no real movement in either of these tableaux. Although people mill about and come and go in the Tabula, nothing really happens. What the “Tabulist” calls a fable (mythos) is nothing more than a landscape with objects and people in it. The same can be said of Homer’s description of the Cave of the Nymphs. The two verbal images can be translated into visual art, with the objects and people in them transposed into the subjects of iconography. Iconography requires that the image depicted and the interpretation be inseparable. They belong to a single intuition. The symbolist mode thus relies on the continued presence of the symbol. We need the symbol constantly before us in order to perceive what it means with the eye of the mind. Nothing is substituted for anything else, because there is nothing false in the symbol that needs to be erased or replaced. We can look at a statue of Zeus with his lightning rod without thinking that it is only natural fire we are seeing and wishing the statue away. For we must look at the statue carefully—and for a long time—to see how it is connected to its meaning or meanings. Returning to Apuleius’s use of imagery, we see the adolescent girl named Psyche and psyche at the same time. Plato’s own fables are best interpreted through the symbolist mode. The fables he makes up are not properly called myths, because nothing really happens in them. His famous cave is a tableau laid out for study in the same way that Porphyry conceived of Homer’s. We are asked to look at the walls of the cave, the fire, the shadows, and the people; then we are asked to look at the sun. The people in the fable do nothing more than look; they do not act. The same can be said of Plato’s allegory of the soul in the Phaedrus. The soul is compared to a chariot, with a charioteer and a pair of steeds. “One of the steeds is noble and of good stock, while the other has the opposite character, and his stock is opposite. Hence the task of our charioteer is difficult and troublesome.”20 The charioteer is, of course, the governing part of the soul, while the horses represent our immortal and mortal natures in a struggle with each other, one lifting us upward to immortality, the other dragging us down into the continuing cycle of rebirth. But nothing happens—certainly nothing as interesting, say, as Phaethon falling out of the sky with the chariot of the sun. As a journalist might say, “There is no story there.” I think that C. S. Lewis’s characterization of symbolist thought can be applied to Plato’s fables: they do indeed “work from the given to find what is more real.”21 For Plato and Platonists, the soul is more real than a chariot, and the good is more real than the sun. The soul is more real than the girl named Psyche. It is hardly any wonder, then, that the few composed allegories surviving from antiquity have souls as their subject. One can interpret an existing myth as a struggle between the elements, but it is hard to make up a new story about that subject (admittedly possible, but would anyone want to read it?). To have a true myth, the characters must act. Here we face a serious limitation on the range of possibilities. Unlike a story about people in real 142 142 the anatomy of my th life, where action can take many forms, souls are able to do much less. According to Angus Fletcher, whose book on allegory remains authoritative, there are only two patterns of action: “The two may be labeled battle and progress.”22 I would add, however, a third: sexual union and/or marriage. While the progress of Soul (Psyche) certainly is central to “Amor and Psyche,” the tale culminates in the marriage of the pair, fulfilling love’s longing for the good and the beautiful. The last full-scale allegory to be composed in antiquity is also about a marriage. The Marriage of Philology and Mercury was written in Latin by another North African, Martianus Capella, at some time in the fifth century c.e.23 The heroine, Philology, is a maiden who represents erudition; indeed, her knowledge embraces the entirety of the seven liberal arts. Mercury, her husband-to-be, is the god of wit and fluent speech, but lacking the gravitas of real learning. Each partner needs the other to be complete. It is a marriage made in heaven, as we are later to learn. Although the main part of the work is an encyclopedia of the liberal arts, the title is drawn from the first two books, ostensibly an introduction to the textbook that follows, but in fact a freestanding allegory. It is impossible to do justice to the outrageous farrago of gods, virtues and vices, academic disciplines, and philosophers who appear as characters in Martianus’s book. C. S. Lewis justly compares the work to a curiosity shop.24 It is composed in the symbolist mode, with descriptions of persons and things abounding everywhere. As Philology progresses through the spheres in preparation for her marriage, she enters the circle of the moon. In the light reflected by the moon there appeared “the sistra of Egypt, the lamp of Eleusis, Diana’s bow, and the tambours of Cybele”25—a ll attributes of goddesses and mysteries associated with the night and the moon. Very few characters enter the tale without a full description of their attributes: There came also a girl of great beauty and of extreme modesty, the guardian and protectress of the Cyllenian home, by name Themis or Astraea or Erigone; she carried in her hand stalks of grain and an ebony tablet engraved with this image: in the middle of it was that bird of Egypt which the Egyptians call an ibis. It was wearing a broad- brimmed hat, and it had a most beautiful head and mouth, which was being caressed by a pair of serpents entwined… .26 That is hardly the end of the ecphrasis; more animals are tossed into the potpourri. Unlike Cornutus, Martianus does not explain these attributes with their symbols. He expects us to know them. His is a book dedicated to pedants everywhere—a call for them to unite and throw off their chains! Sometimes 143 from allegory to symbolism 143 his bookishness dissolves into parody and invites us to chuckle. Philology’s meeting with Venus (who is both a planet and a goddess, following the Timaeus) is a trifle strained, given Philology’s virginity and Venus’s reputation. But though the encounter goes well, Philology can’t hold her girlish cattiness in check: “She is said to have perceived in Venus that, fair though she was, she had her forelocks curled about with snakes and her thick hair flowing loosely.”27 Here we see allegorical writing deftly leavened with a dash of mimēsis. The symbols of Venus’s wicked, wicked ways are set in plain view, and Philology shows that she is just a normal girl in calling attention to them. We catch a whiff of the divine Apuleius. Before Philology can be granted immortality and begin her journey through the spheres, she is compelled to undergo a vomiting ritual! Immortality herself, described as “a woman of reverend countenance, shining with holy and celestial light in all the dignity of a priestess,” discovered that Philology’s breast was greatly swollen, and ordered her “to void this matter which is choking your breast.”28 But Philology, virginity intact, is not suffering from morning sickness. No, her stomach is overburdened with books, and it is these she vomits up—myriads of them. Here is what transpired: But while the maiden was bringing up such matter in spasms, several young women, of whom some are called the Arts, and others the Disciplines, were straightway collecting whatever the maiden brought forth from her mouth, each one of them taking material for her own essential use and her particular skill. Even the Muses themselves, especially Urania and Calliope, gathered countless volumes into their laps. In some of these books the pages were marked with musical notation and were very long, in others there were circles and straight lines and hemispheres, together with triangles and squares and polygonal shapes drawn to suit the different theorems and elements; then a representation joined together the limbs of various animals into a particular species. There were also books which continued the harmonies of music and the notations of rhythms and some pieces for singing.29 Here we have a transparent allegory of the origin of the liberal arts. Philology (Erudition) vomits the books of the arts and disciplines, which are gathered by the Arts and Disciplines. Each of these maidens will make an appearance in Martianus’s book and expound on the material she has collected for herself. Grammatica will recite grammar, Rhetorica rhetoric, and so on. Martianus has managed simultaneously to introduce his encyclopedia and to serve the tale of Philology. Because Philology is about to join the ranks of the gods, she 144 144 the anatomy of my th will no longer need her books. The gods know all things intuitively; it is only mortals who must learn by reading. The allegorical books of the Marriage end with Philology drinking the cup of immortality, her journey through the spheres, and the beginning of the ceremony of her wedding to Mercury (Wisdom). Martianus borrows two motifs from “Amor and Psyche”: the proffering of the cup of immortality and the approval of the marriage by Jupiter and the senate of the gods (the story is, after all, Roman). But another allusion to Apuleius’s tale brings us back to the central soul fable, the union of Amor and Psyche. In Martianus’s tale of Mercury’s search for a bride, the god has set his heart on the beautiful Psyche, only to find to his sorrow that she has already been snatched away by Amor, who bound her in shackles of adamant (a riff on the myth of Zeus shackling Hera?). The choice settles on Philology. Juno is convinced that the girl will be good for her gadabout nephew, as she will keep him awake at night, teaching him all the facts he needs to know. Just as Apuleius knew Plato’s truth that Love finds its completion in Soul, the sly Martianus was aware that the god who represented the gift of gab required more than a dollop of hard data to be complete. Philology followed Psyche into the empyrion, was made immortal, and enjoyed an eternal union with her divine mate. Martianus’s clunkily droll allegory of the noetic world found its inspiration in Apuleius’s beautiful and comic tale. Martianus interpreted Apuleius’s psychological allegory and fashioned a new one out of it. One final representative of symbolist exegesis will claim our attention. This is the Neoplatonist Proclus (410 c.e.?–485). Born in Lycia (southern Asia Minor) and educated at Alexandria, Proclus spent the greatest part of his life (430–485 c.e.) in Athens, as the Academy neared its last years of existence. Influenced by Porphyry, Proclus devoted a great deal of scholary attention to developing a poetic and a symbolic exegesis of mythology, most notably in his fifth and sixth books of his Commentary on Plato’s Republic, which survive, and in his lost “On the Symbols of Myth.”30 David Konstan refers to his method as “psychagogic, leading the mind on to intuitions of higher reality.”31 Movement from lower levels of meaning to higher is reflected in Proclus’s tripartite division of poetry with soul functions appropriate to each, that is, each level is equated with a level of knowledge.32 At the third, or lowest, level are myths that are mimetic, operating at the level of doxa (opinion). There are two divisions of this level, the lower being illusion (the phantastikon), where there are descriptions of things that seem to be, based on aphomoiōsis, “resemblance.” A mythic example is Homer’s description of the sun rising out of the sea (Od. 3, 1). The higher subdivision is the mimetic, also operating at the level of doxa, but with a greater claim to accuracy, in which descriptions are representational (eikastikon). Mythic examples include warriors fighting or otherwise behaving in character. The second, or middle level, which is non- mimetic, is graspable through epistēmē (true knowledge), in which soul turns inward and focuses on mind (nous). An example is the description of Heracles 145 from allegory to symbolism 145 in the underworld (Od. 11, 601–4). These lines, marked as spurious by editors, tell us that it was only an image (eidōlon) of Heracles that Odysseus recognized in Hades, as the hero’s true self was feasting with the gods, wedded to the goddess Hebe. The questionable lines would doubtless have held a deep appeal for Proclus, lauding Homer for demonstrating that “the true being of Heracles is in his soul, while the ‘image’ attached to the soul should be considered a ’tool’ (organon) of Heracles that bears a resemblance to him but is not he himself [Commentary, pp. 247–49].” The third level is difficult to describe, as it introduces a level of mysticism that we have not encountered thus far in this study. Proclus envisions the soul on the level of the gods, “transcending,” to quote Lamberton, “individual mind (nous) and attaching its ‘own light to the transcendent light … to the One beyond all being and life’ (Commentary., p. 257).” This level of poetry appears to operate beyond epistēmē and involves the fusion of subject and object. It is created through inspiration or possession by the Muses. Here Proclus invokes Plato’s theory of poetry advanced in the Phaedrus (245a), which uses words like “possession,” “madness,” and “frenzy.” In Proclus’s words, these are what “fills the soul with symmetry.” The poet abandons every form of representation or imitation, and turns to symbols. Proclus’s example is the myth of the sexual encounter of Ares and Aphrodite and the chains of Hephaestus, for which he provides a detailed exegesis involving the Neoplatonic treatment of the monad and the dyad. (In Rep., pp. 193–99). Proclus does not engage in substitutions and does not always explain the specific meanings of symbols. Even the interpretations of individual myths are only of interest insofar as they lead to a higher understanding of poetry and the nature of divinity. Indeed, the individual myths about the gods that are treated as separate events in the poems belie the fact that for the gods, all phenomena occur simultaneously. In his Commentary on the Republic Proclus wrote, “For these things that exist simultaneously [for the gods] with one another the mythoplasts have separated, disguising the truth.”33 Proclus went on to say: [The mythoplasts] fashion likenesses of the indivisible by way of division, of the eternal by what moves in time, of the noetic by the perceptible; they represent the immaterial by the material, what is without extension by way of discontinuity, and that which is steadfastly established through change.34 Proclus has embraced the symbolic mode and turned Plato on his head. Myth and poetry (for they are one) do not remove us from the divine; they connect us to divinity through symbols—to use the language of St. Paul—“as through a glass darkly” (I Cor. 13:12). Like Porphyry before him, he lays out a tableau and selects from it the warring images of time and generation and the still symbols of eternity. 146 147 12 Greek Exegesis and Judaeo-Christian Books “What has Athens to do with Jerusalem?” “What has the academy to do with the Church?” We can imagine these words thundered from a pulpit and punctuated with lightning bolts in place of question marks. In fact, the words are to be found in a work entitled On the Proscribing of Heretics (7.9) written by Tertullian, a Christian polemicist resident in Carthage in the late second to early third century. The same writer expressed his distrust of Greek philosophy in various writings; he preferred to rely solely on the authority of the Bible. The notion that there was no meeting of the minds between Christians and pagan thinkers was also accepted by a number of pagans, notably Celsus, who wrote a comprehensive treatise entitled Against Christianity. As we noted in c­ hapter 3, a parallel dichotomy between the intellectual cultures of Greeks and Jews had been posited by Galen, the famous medical writer. For Galen, the all-important difference could be reduced to the answers given to the question of what it was possible for God to do in a universe governed by natural laws. Jews and Greeks, apparently, held irreconcilably diverse opinions on the subject. If we were to accept the views of writers such as Tertullian, Celsus, and Galen as representative of social reality, we would conclude that pagans, Christians, and Jews lived in walled intellectual ghettos. The truth of the matter was far different. Except for rigorist sects, pagans, Christians, and Jews all read one another’s writings. Celsus may have strongly disliked Christianity, but he knew its scriptures.1 The same can be said of the Neoplatonists who flourished from the latter third to sixth century c.e. One might be surprised to learn how often Plotinus and Porphyry, the founding fathers of Neoplatonism, quote Christian scripture. Their writings, in turn, were absorbed by Christian thinkers in both the Greek-and Latin-speaking parts of the empire.2 Pagans and Christians shared a single world. They may not have participated in the same rituals, but they read the same books. They read the same 148 148 the anatomy of my th books because they went to the same schools. Until the fourth century c.e. their teachers were invariably pagans. From the fourth century c.e. Christians were allowed to teach in state schools, and the trend persisted despite the attempt of the Emperor Julian (361–363 c.e.) to bar them. However, even after the introduction of Christian teachers, schools throughout the Roman Empire remained under state control. Christian education, apart from private tutoring, never gained a footing—even in the fifth and sixth centuries, by which time all forms of pagan practice had been made illegal. But the curriculum remained more or less static over the centuries. The books on the syllabus, all pagan works, stayed the same. Students wishing to study the Bible were directed to their churches or synagogues. In the Middle Ages, when the Bible finally took the central place in the curriculum, Christian students in the East continued to read their Homer, while Christian students in the West read Vergil (and not only in Ireland!). There were fairly large areas of intellectual concord between the two groups, certainly on the philosophical level. Christians early on recognized similarities between Plato’s teachings and their own. Timaean Platonism gave Christians a god/God who created the world. This god was both outside the world and present in it through the world soul. This same god wanted to share his happiness, and to do that made the world as nearly perfect as possible. Plato also bequeathed the notion of the immortal soul (though for Plato the soul was not simply immortal, but also eternal). Christians wedded the notion of the immortality of a spiritual soul to their own teaching of the resurrection of the body, a concept that they had inherited from the intertestamental Jews. Christians also felt a kinship with the Stoics on many points. Above all, the Stoics bequeathed the idea that virtue is the highest good; it is the very purpose of life. And, of course, Christians shared with Platonists and Stoics an intense dislike for the coarseness and “errors” of the Epicureans. The congruence of some central doctrines of the pagans with Judaeo- Christian teaching is explained by a somewhat elaborate historical myth. Ancient thinkers held the idea of a primitive wisdom that, though lost in its archetypal form, was dispersed into the world in bits and pieces, as it were.3 As the second-century writer Celsus expressed it, “An ancient doctrine has been handed down, which has always been maintained by the wisest nations and cities and wise men.”4 Some believed that these fragments of wisdom had been turned into myths, thereby distorting the ancient truth. The task of the philosopher was not to come up with new ideas, but to reconstruct the archetype of ancient wisdom from the remaining fragments—much as a classical philologist might reconstruct the work of an author. The locus of this wisdom was often situated in Egypt. On this much, pagans and (Judaeo-)Christians agreed. But here the myth splits into two contradictory narratives. Pagans traced the wisdom of Plato to Pythagoras, who had allegedly acquired wisdom in Egypt. Jews and Christians both argued that their wisdom was far 149 greek exegesis and judaeo-christian books 149 more ancient. Philo claimed that Moses was the dual heir of God’s revelation and Egyptian doctrine, and that Pythagoras and Plato had gleaned what they knew indirectly from Moses. In some of the Christian accounts the Greeks are accused of plagiarizing Moses.5 Other Christians, such as Justin Martyr in his First Apology, explained the congruence of pagan philosophical ideas with Christian teachings by the Stoic concept of “seminal reasons,” that is, seeds of truth.6 These are distributed as the logos to all humankind, even to those who lived before Christ the Logos. That pagans also had a hint of the Logos himself was believed to be clearly shown by the poet Vergil, who in his Fourth Eclogue appeared to echo the prophesy of Isaiah that allegedly predicted the birth of Christ.7 All of these apparent congruities, however, could not paper over the serious differences between pagans and Christians.8 Pagans were willing to tolerate the “foolish” beliefs and practices of Christians (within limits, of course), but Christians did not return the favor. They and they alone possessed the truth. Beyond the issue of tolerance or lack of it were serious divisions of dogma. Pagan philosophers, with the exception of the Stoics, did not believe in providence, except in the sense that god or nature made the world for the best. They continued to believe (with the possible exception of Plutarch9) that God did not interfere with nature, or intervene in human affairs; what happens to people occurs through some combination of fate and free will. This implies that prayer is useless (despite the fact that non-philosophical pagans continued to pray as fervently as they ever did). Some late Stoics allowed that one might beseech the gods to strengthen one’s virtue or rationality, but that was as far as it went.10 Although Christians accepted that the soul is immortal, they did not agree that it was eternal; it was created by God in time. Plato’s arguments for the preexistence of the soul were rejected along with his doctrine of reincarnation. (The great biblical scholar Origen fell into grave disrepute for accepting such ideas.) The greatest gap of all, however, was between polytheism and monotheism. Whatever one makes of the Christian idea of the Trinity, Christians themselves believed they were strict monotheists, and they accepted the first commandment of the decalogue as absolute: “Thou shalt not have other gods before me” (Exod. 20:2). The current assault by the new atheists on the Old Testament God has its basis in the ancient debate between pagans and Christians over the impassiveness of God, that is, the idea that God cannot undergo any kind of change, because his nature is perfect, therefore constant. The three “theist” schools of pagan philosophy, beginning with Plato himself, taught that god is unchangeable and unmovable in the emotional sense. Stoics, Peripatetics (followers of Aristotle), and even the Epicureans believed that god is apathēs, literally “without suffering.” This means, above all, that god does not become angry and vindictive. Homer and the ancient poets erred when they spoke of Zeus as angry. But North African Christians, starting with Tertullian, and extending 150 150 the anatomy of my th to Augustine, rebuked pagan arguments that god is impassive.11 Lactantius (early fourth century c.e.) sought to justify divine anger as an aspect of divine justice in his treatise On the Wrath of God. For pagan thinkers, of course, such attempts constituted a huge step backward intellectually: it undid the advances of Xenophanes and Plato in giving the world a nobler idea of god. The ancient philosophers, after consulting their dictionaries, would likely have agreed with Dawkins about the following: The God of the Old Testament is arguably the most unpleasant character in all fiction: jealous and proud of it; a petty tyrant; a petty, unjust control freak: a bloodthirsty ethnic cleanser; a misogynistic, homophobic, racist, infanticidal, genocidal, filicidal, pestilential, megalomaniacal, sadomasochistic, capriciously malevolent bully.12 Clearly this God does not meet the Greek philosophical standard of impassivity. Moreover, even if one discounts the annoying personality flaws attributed by Dawkins to the Old Testament God (Yahweh), there is the other difficulty that God must be immutable. But the God who spoke to Moses in the form of a burning bush (Exod. 3:2) is but little different from Athena appearing to Odysseus in the guise of Mentor. Thus Yahweh is alleged to do what Plato said god cannot do: he cannot change his nature, for god must by definition be a perfect being, and any change from perfection is a change for the worse. The myths of the Jews had to be held accountable to the same standard of morality and believability as the myths of the Greeks. We return to a crucial point: for pagans, god cannot do the impossible, nor does he interfere with nature. Even if god had a role in creating the world (agreed upon by Plato, Aristotle, and the Stoics, as noted in ­chapter 8), he created it in such a way that it functioned on its own without interference from heaven. God cannot “make a bull or a horse out of ashes.” Christians, however, believed with Jews that there was no limit to the will and power of God; he could even change the nature of what he created. The issue came to a head over Christian insistence on the resurrection of the body—an idea derived from intertestamental Judaism. This notion was ludicrous to most pagans, for whom the only kind of immortality possible was that of the soul. What would prevent the body from decaying? How could a dead body, with its weight, ascend into the heavens? But Christians remained adamant that all things are possible with God. He will make new “spiritual bodies” that will bring eternal bliss to the elect, eternal pain to the damned.13 Educated pagans, for the most part, had disposed of such “superstitions” as the Isles of the Blest and Hades long ago. The divide between pagans and Christians on the powers of God/ god was unbridgeable. In the centuries just before the rise of the Roman Empire and also during the Empire, Alexandria in Egypt, founded by Alexander (d. 323 b.c.e.) himself, 151 greek exegesis and judaeo-christian books 151 became the intellectual and cultural capital of the ancient world, eclipsing both Athens and Rome. Alexandria might be likened to Paris as the scene of the avant-garde. It was where everything interesting happened; it was where many with intellectual or artistic ambitions went. It could equally well be compared to New York for the same reasons. Moreover, and importantly, Alexandria was like New York in its broad ethnicity and religious diversity. From the beginning, Alexandria was a multiethnic society. Its population would have included native Egyptians, Greeks, Persians, peoples from surrounding North African areas, and a growing Jewish diaspora. In the centuries after Christ it embraced a significant Christian population. All would have attended the same schools. Origen, the great Christian exegete, and Plotinus, the founder of Neoplatonism, sat at the feet of the same teacher, Ammonius Saccas. For all that, Alexandria was not a peaceful place. It was the site of Jewish pogroms and Christian persecutions; it was later the scene of rioting by Christian factions. Alexandria was also the site where the Septuagint, the Greek translation of the Jewish Bible (the Christian Old Testament), was said to be compiled in the third century b.c.e. The Jews who migrated to Alexandria read their scriptures in that version, as fewer of them, with the passage of time, were able to read Hebrew or Aramaic. It is in this milieu that we meet Philo (better known as Philo Iudaeus, “Philo the Jew”). Philo was a prominent leader of the Jewish community in Alexandria. As an old man he led a delegation to Rome in 39 or 40 c.e. to protest the mistreatment of Jews that had resulted from their pleas for citizenship. Beyond this, we have no knowledge of his dates or activity.14 But his voluminous writings survive, mostly preserved by the Christian writer Origen for his library in Caesarea in Judaea. Apart from his Life of Moses and voluminous writings on Jewish scripture (the Old Testament), he wrote works of a philosophical character. He was intimately familiar with the major Greek philosophers and with Greek literature, including Homer. Not only had he read his Homer, but he was also familiar with Greek modes of interpreting the poet, as the following passage from his work On Providence shows: If you apply the mythical story of Hephaestus to fire, and the account of Hera to air, and what is said about Hermes to reason, and in the same way that which is said of others, following in order, in their theology, then in fact you will become a praiser of the poets you have just been condemning, so that you will realize that they alone have glorified the divine in a seemly manner.15 The interpretation of Hephaestus as fire, Hera as air, and Hermes as reason point to Philo’s knowledge of the kind of allegoresis that had been expounded in the sixth century c.e. by Theagenes of Rhegium. Like Theagenes’ list of allegorizations, Philo’s included both physical and mental (psychological) 152 152 the anatomy of my th phenomena. It is of the substitutionist type and operates without appeal to etymology. However, Philo’s considerable fame in subsequent eras did not depend on his remarks on Homer, but rather on his willingness to apply to the scriptures the same methods of allegoresis as the Greeks used to interpret pagan literature. In a remarkable passage interpreting the trees of life and knowledge that stood in the Garden of Eden, Philo writes: And these statements appear to me to be dictated by a philosophy which is symbolical rather than strictly accurate. For no trees of life or of knowledge have ever at any previous time appeared upon the earth, nor is it likely that they will appear hereafter. But I rather conceive that Moses was speaking in an allegorical spirit, intending by this paradise to intimate the dominant character of the soul, which is full of innumerable opinions as this figurative paradise was of trees. And by the tree of life he was shadowing out the greatest of the virtues— namely piety towards the gods.16 In a passage in another work, Questions on Genesis, he allows for the existence of the Garden, but emphasizes its symbolic meaning: Of Paradise, so far as the literal meaning is concerned, there is no need to give an explicit interpretation. For it is a dense place full of all kinds of trees. Symbolically, however, it is wisdom or knowledge of the divine and human and of their causes.17 In the first passage, Philo applies the doctrine of plausibility to deny the existence of the Garden as described. This is based on the principle that only the things that are possible now were possible in the past, or will be in the future. After rejecting the credibility of the Garden myth, he proceeds to salvage it through psychological allegory: Moses (who was widely believed to be the author of Genesis) was contriving a fable about the soul and the virtues of the soul. In the second passage, Philo accepts the possibility of the coexistence of a literal meaning and an allegorical one in the same passage. Modern critics—as well as some ancient Greeks—might well bridle at such inconsistency. However, one must simply accept the fact that apparent contradictions of this nature typified much of what was acceptable criticism in the Greek and Roman worlds.18 Of course, apparent contradictions in interpretations of the same passage may reveal growth or development in exegetical method. In fact, in his second trial of interpreting the passage, Philo seems to have foreshadowed Porphyry’s approach to Homer’s “Cave of the Nymphs.” Porphyry does not deny the existence of the cave, but retains its existence while exploring its symbolic meaning. Philo’s second approach in interpreting the Garden is markedly different from the substitutionist method of the first passage cited. 153 greek exegesis and judaeo-christian books 153 Like Porphyry’s cave, Philo’s Garden retains its existence. It must remain in our line of vision as a physical object all the while we seek with the mind’s eye to interpret it. Philo interests us as well, because in his great work On the Creation of the World, an exegegis of the six days of creation as described in Genesis, he strove deliberately to reconcile the biblical text with the doctrines of Plato’s work on creation, Timaeus. The reconciliation was eased by the fact that the translators of the Septuagint had rendered Hebrew words describing the creation with the familiar Greek philosophical terms genesis, kosmos, and archē—e xactly the terms used by Plato at the opening of part II of Timaeus. 19 Then there are the very important resemblances of one to the other in content. The God of Genesis, like the demiurge, made the world before the start of time. God had already created heaven and earth and light, and had separated the waters of the firmament from the waters below before setting lights in the sky to rule over night and day. That did not happen until “the fourth day.” Philo also believed he saw glimpses of Plato’s forms in Genesis situated in the mind of the creator, for he describes the process of creation thus: Then, having received in his own mind, as on a waxen tablet, the form of each image he carries in his heart the image of a city, perceptible as yet only to the intellect … engraving them in his mind like a good workman [demiourgos], keeping his eyes fixed on his model, he begins to raise the city of stone and wood, making the corporeal substances to resemble each of the incorporeal ideas.20 The allusions to the Timaeus are unmistakable. At places, one has the impression that the Timaeus account of creation overlays the Torah’s account like a transparency. One can read the Torah through Plato. Philo refers to Moses—regarded by Jews and Christians alike as the author of the Torah or Pentateuch—as one “who had early reached the summits of philosophy, and who had learnt from the Oracles of God” (1.8). Thus, Moses was twice an heir: he had received instructions in philosophy from the Egyptians and the direct inspiration of God. These combined into a single unimpeachable teaching. The restoration of the “archetype” of the ancient revelation is thus assisted by the use of Plato’s Timaeus, a later, but nevertheless trustworthy, witness to it, because he too was inspired by the ancient wisdom of Egypt.21 With Philo, we witness a significant instance of cultural transference. Philo was not the first to publish a demonstration that allegorical interpretation—a method developed by pagan Greeks—could be used to elucidate God’s Word as received by Jews. The practice was begun more than a century earlier by Aristobulus of Panaeas, who also argued that Plato could 154 154 the anatomy of my th have known the Torah.22 However, it is from Philo’s interpretative work that we can draw a straight line to the Christian Origen (ca. 185–ca. 255). Origen was also an Alexandrian who was steeped in Platonism. When he moved from Alexandria to Caesarea to establish his own school, he brought with him the works of Philo that he had collected. Philo’s works exercised a direct influence on Origen. as we can see by comparing yet another of Philo’s interpretations of the Garden of Eden tale with Origen’s exegesis. Philo wrote: For let not such impiety ever occupy our thoughts as for us to suppose that God cultivates the land and plants paradises, since if we were to say so, we should presently be raising the question of why he does so; for it could not be that he might provide himself with pleasant places of recreation and pastime, or with amusement. Let not such fabulous nonsense ever enter our minds; for even the whole world would not be a worthy place or habitation for God, since he is a place to himself… .23 The sentiment is closely echoed by Origen somewhat more sardonically: “And who will be found simple enough to believe that like some farmer ‘God planted trees in the garden of Eden, in the East’ and that He planted ‘the tree of life’ in it, that is a visible tree that could be touched… .24 Like Philo, Origen knew pagan literary works as well as he knew the philosophers, as his Contra Celsum (“Against Celsus”) reveals. Also like Philo, Origen was fully conversant with Greek mythology and Greek methods of exegesis. He was cognizant of the fact that biblical stories were derided as implausible by pagan critics. He addresses both issues synoptically in his attack on the pagan Celsus: He who approaches the stories [i.e., Homer’s] generously and wishes to avoid being misled in reading them will decide which parts he will believe, and which he will interpret allegorically, searching out the intentions of the authors of such fictions, and which he will refuse to believe, and will consider simply as things written to please someone. And having said this, we have been speaking in anticipation about the whole story of Jesus in the Gospels. We do not urge the intelligent in the direction of simple and irrational faith, but wish to advise them that those who are going to read this story need to be generous in their approach, and will require a great deal of insight … [the] power of penetration into the meaning of the Scriptures in order that the intention with which each passage was written may be discovered.25 155 greek exegesis and judaeo-christian books 155 Origen is addressing the historicity of the Trojan War, and the claim that it never happened on the ground that Homer’s narrative contained unbelievable stories “such as Achilles having had Thetis, a sea-goddess, as his mother” or that Aeneas was the child of Aphrodite.26 Similarly, one could deny the truth of the story of Oedipus and Jocasta because it contains an episode involving a mythical monster, the Sphinx. Origen counters effectively by appealing to the same principles used by Plutarch and others before him. The overarching principle is that of plausibility. The job of the interpreter is to purify mythos with logos. One accepts what is possible for rational humans to believe, discards the completely unbelievable, and reinterprets the rest. The same principle can be carried over to the interpretation of scripture. Origen, like Philo, was prepared to adopt the methods devised by pagan Greeks to deal with the difficulties posed by many passages in scripture. Philo’s title “Questions regarding Genesis” reminds us of the books titled “Homeric Problems.” The job of the interpreter is to collect the passages (whether in Homer or the Bible) that have caused problems for others, and address them head on. Origen’s work “Against Celsus” is interesting for another reason. Origen deals with the comparison of biblical tales and pagan myths, refuting charges by pagans that the biblical stories are even more nonsensical or immoral than pagan ones. He defends the account of the creation of woman from Adam’s rib against Celsus, arguing that it has as much claim to having been composed allegorically as Hesiod’s fable that Zeus created woman as a punishment for Prometheus’s theft of fire (Against Celsus 4.38). In answering the charge regarding the story in Genesis that the sons of God entered into the daughters of men (Gen. 6:4), Origen replied that the tale was far less offensive than that of the “father of gods and men” having intercourse with his own daughter.27 A much more challenging proposition for Origen was dealing with the taunt that the resurrection of Christ was no more real than the numerous katabases (descent into Hades stories) in pagan mythology. Origen was trapped here. He could not allow the claim that Christ’s resurrection was a myth, for it was the central doctrine of Christianity. It had to be accepted as historical fact. He met the challenge squarely. He argued that there was no evidence for any of the claims that the heroes named really descended into Hades and returned. On the contrary, Christ’s death, at least, was witnessed publicly. As for his resurrection, Origen does not rely on the witness of the disciples, but argues that the same disciples believed it so deeply that they were willing to die for their belief (2.56). Even though the argument is far from convincing, it is grounded in a rational theory of human psychology. For the study of exegesis, Origen’s most important work was his On First Principles, of which the fourth book is devoted entirely to principles of interpretation supported by examples. Origen at times appears to be even more aggressive than Philo in pursuing rationalizing approaches to the interpretation of the Holy Scriptures. While Philo at times allows literal and allegorical 156 156 the anatomy of my th meanings to coexist, Origen notes cases in which literal interpretations are impossible to accept, “ … since we often discover that the letter is impossible or insufficient in itself because by it sometimes not only irrationalities but even impossibilities are described.”28 Origen balances this statement by then remarking that “in a great many cases the truth of the narrative meaning both can and ought to be preserved.” For example, there is surely no reason to doubt statements such as Jerusalem being the chief city of Judaea or that Solomon built the temple of God in that city. Origen applies his rationalist principles to both narratives and laws. As an example of an impossible happening in a narrative he cites the beginning of Genesis (1:5–13): To what person of intelligence, I ask, will the account seem logically consistent that says there was a “first day” and a “second,” and “third,” in which also “evening” and “morning” are named, without a sun, without a moon, and without stars, and even in the case of the first day without a heaven?29 He goes on to discuss impossible laws: But if we must ask also about impossible laws, we find an animal called the “goat-stag,” which does not even exist, listed among the clean animals Moses orders to be eaten; and the lawgiver prohibits eating the “griffin,” which no one has ever mentioned or heard of being able to fall into human hands (cf. Deut. 14:5; Lev. 11:13 LXX). Moreover, concerning the quite well-known observance of the sabbath, it says: “You shall sit, each one of you, in your houses; no one shall move from his place on the seventh day” (Ex. 16:29). It is impossible to observe this commandment according to the letter, for no human being can sit for a whole day so as not to move from the place where he is sitting.30 However, Origen’s most lasting contribution to the interpretation of the Bible did not consist in his deconstruction of the literal sense of passages that presented difficulties for educated readers; it was, rather, the authority he lent to the possibility of multiple interpretations of passages and his famous analogy between the human body and the letter of a text, and the human soul and spirit and various figurative meanings: “Thus, just as a human being is said to be made up of body, soul, and spirit, so also is sacred Scripture, which has been granted by God’s gracious dispensation for man’s salvation.”31 Origen does not fully address his tripartite division, as he makes no clear distinction between soul and spirit, but treats them in places as if they were synonymous. Moreover, he calls attention to the fact that there are passages where multiple interpretations are impossible (4.2.5). His great authority in the West 157 greek exegesis and judaeo-christian books 157 resonated through a Latin translation, and it was not long before exegetes were speaking of a threefold meaning of scripture, assigning an allegorical meaning to the soul, and a moral sense to the spirit of Holy Writ.32 Origen, who dedicated his life to the study of the scriptures, also gave the world the Hexapla, a six-version edition of the Old Testament, of which only a few fragments remain. The six versions were arranged in six columns as follows: 1. 2. 3. 4. Septuagint in Hebrew in Hebrew script Septuagint in Hebrew transliterated into Greek script the translation of Aquila (literal translation, finished 130 c.e.) the translation of Symmachus (tending to paraphrase, late second century c.e.) 5. the Septuagint (revised by Origen using Theodotian’s revision with editorial marks showing divergences from Hebrew) 6. translation of Theodotian (revision of the Septuagint, late second century c.e.) What, conceivably, was the purpose of such a labor-intensive project that must also have been labor intensive for its readers? I can think of two possibilities: (1) Origen was intent on establishing or facilitating a translation of the Hebrew Bible that was as close as humanly possible to the original. (2) Origen believed that God’s word had more than one meaning and thus allowed for more than one possible interpretation (that is, translation), and that divergences could inspire different insights in different readers. There is probably some truth in both these suggestions, but I think that Origen would have inclined more to the second, while admitting the utility of the first. At any rate, the second possibility fits well with his endorsement of multiple meanings of passages in On First Principles. Just as one and the same passage can produce different readings, a single passage in differing translations can give rise to fresh insights into its meaning. In that case, meaning is to be found not in the mind of the author (whether God or Moses or a scribe), but in the mind of the reader. If we may be permitted a bit of chronological leapfrogging, it is interesting to look at Origen’s Hexapla in the light of the Latin-speaking Augustine’s ideas on translation. Unlike Origen and his contemporary Jerome, Augustine was not a philologist. He admitted to his difficulty in learning Greek, as well as to his distaste for that language.33 He did not even attempt Hebrew. Thus, like many of his contemporaries, he was held to ransom by the defective Latin translations circulating in his day. He finished the larger portion of On Christian Doctrine in 397 c.e., just a few years before Jerome published his authoritative Latin translation known as the Vulgate. Thus, in On Christian Doctrine, a guide to biblical studies, Augustine was forced to deal with the 158 158 the anatomy of my th problem of divergent translations of the same passage. In his effort to guide readers through this difficulty, he wrote: Again, a text of the prophet Isaias reads: “If you will not believe, you shall not understand,” and in another translation: “If you will not believe, you shall not continue.” Which of these is to be followed is uncertain unless the text is read in the original language[?]But both of them contain something of great value for the discerning reader. It is difficult for translators to become so disparate that they do not show a similarity in one area of meaning.34 It would be hard to show how the almost Greekless Augustine could have been influenced by Origen—the entirety of the Hexapla contained Hebrew and Greek texts exclusively. But seminal ideas, wafting over seas, have a way of implanting themselves in unexpected places. Augustine’s ideas on the value of differing translations jibes nicely with Origen’s thought and his own semiology: a sign or symbol points to something different from itself while retaining its identity. The same scriptural text can be translated in different ways and still retain its identity and value. It may be worthwhile to explore another early Greek Christian writer who used Greek methods of interpretation, not to defend scriptural stories but to impugn Greek myths. This is Clement of Alexandria, born ca. 150 c.e., thus more than a generation before Origen. A convert to Christianity, he attended classes for catechumens in Alexandria. But he had obviously received a full education in a regular state school, as his writing reflects close familiarity with pagan Greek literature and philosophy. His magnum opus, Stromateis (“Miscellanies”), is a bold attempt to present Christianity as a philosophy. Clement was one of a number of Christian writers known as “apologetes,” who were engaged in defending Christianity against pagan attacks. Origen, as we have seen, was another. A significant part of the apologete’s task was to counterattack the attackers. One prong of attack was moral criticism: the apologete underscores the violent and obscene nature of certain myths and ridicules the idea that they can be used as models of behavior. The other was deconstruction. Clement, like other Christians intellectuals, had mastered the repertoire of techniques developed by pagan Greeks to disprove the literal truth of their own stories.35 A single principle guided the deconstructionists: myths are the result of intellectual errors. They were invariably the products of simple minds that, in an earlier time, gave the name of god to things in nature, including humans, or else were deceived by a name. In his Exhortation to the Greeks, Clement employs a critique that harks back to Prodicus of Ceos; the gods are just names given to things in nature that are beneficial to men: “Others, when gathering the fruits of plants that spring from the earth, called the corn Demeter, as the 159 greek exegesis and judaeo-christian books 159 Athenians, and the vine Dionysus, as the Thebans.”36 He expands the critique to include the deified abstractions Fear, Love, Joy, and Hope, which “the philosophers themselves, following the men of poetry, came to represent as types of your emotions.”37 Euhemerus provided Clement with material for his explanation of the deification of Aphrodite: “For I would never be beguiled by the claims of the islander Cinyras of Cypris, who had the audacity to transfer the lascivious orgies of Aphrodite from night to day in his ambition to deify a harlot of his own country.”38 Euhemerus’s idea that gods are exceptional humans who were deified after their deaths is obviously at work here. Clement also knew that an entire myth can be generated from the misunderstanding of a name; the motif can be traced as far back as Hecataeus (ca. 500 b.c.e.) and his take on the story of Heracles at Taenarus. Recall that Plutarch had used the technique to disprove the existence of a monstrous sow marauding in Crommyon, arguing that it was just the name of a fat slovenly woman of the region. The learned Clement, unconvinced about the existence of the Muses, cited a chronicle from Lesbos that gave the “real” story of their beginnings. In his Exhortation Clement doubted the traditional story of their origin given by Alcman (and, of course, also Hesiod) that they were the daughters of Zeus and Mnemosyne. Instead the Muses were nine Mysian maids (note the etymological wordplay) serving in the house of Macas, king of the Lesbians. Their beautiful singing voices soothed the king (who had a quarrelsome nature). His daughter commissioned nine bronze statues to be erected in their honor and placed in all the temples. Because their names were pronounced Moysae (Mousae) in the Aeolian dialect, they were honored ever afterwards as the Muses.39 This rationalization of the Muses’ origin offers the perfect segue to Augustine, who gave a variant version of Clement’s interpretation in his On Christian Doctrine. 40 Augustine was born in Thagaste (now in Algeria) in 354 c.e., and died in Hippo Regius (also in Algeria) in 430 c.e. He had served as its bishop for over thirty years at the time of his death. In his youth he had been attracted to philosophy by reading Cicero’s lost dialogue Hortensius, an exhortation to pursue philosophy. Like other classically educated people of his generation he was put off by his early encounter with the Bible. Not only did the Latin translations of the time reflect a low literary standard, but their content was also repulsive to him. The young Augustine had not yet learned to read for the spiritual sense of the words, but understood them literally. His years in Italy (383–388), and especially his tutelage under Bishop Ambrose at Milan, introduced him to ways of reading scripture for figural meanings; at the same time he became acquainted with Neoplatonism. He used a period spent in retreat at Cassiciacum (near Milan) to enlarge his understanding of the Bible and to deepen his acquaintance with philosophy (through Latin intermediaries). His writings stemming from that period can be characterized as philosophical. 160 160 the anatomy of my th It was as a Romanized North African that Augustine wrote his On Christian Doctrine immediately before embracing the rigors of his long bishopric. The work is essentially a textbook on how to approach and understand the Bible. Augustine’s experience in Italy ensured that he would bring a wider culture to the Christianity he had embraced than the Bible-focused religion of his fellow countrymen. This breadth of vision filtered into his scriptural exegesis. He had abandoned his profession as a teacher of rhetoric, but he never turned against the proper use of rhetoric in Christian education—and its application to tropes in the Bible. Like St. Basil, whom we met earlier as a defender of the usefulness of secular literature, he believed in taking what was good from secular learning and putting it to Christian use: If those who are called philosophers, especially the Platonists, have said things which are indeed true and well accommodated to our faith, they should not be feared; rather, what they have said should be taken from them as from unjust possessors and converted to our use. Just as the Egyptians had not only idols and grave burdens which the people of Israel detested and avoided, so also they had ornaments of gold and clothing which the Israelites took with them secretly when they fled, as if to put them to a better use. 41 Augustine’s great achievement in On Christian Doctrine lies in his theorizing the idea of a sign. Porphyry had given a brilliant demonstration of how the understanding of signs (symbols) could be applied to Homer’s “Cave of the Nymphs,” and Philo had done this even earlier. But no one before Augustine had explained what a sign actually meant. The idea that a thing can remain a thing while signifying something else did not have to wait for twentieth-century semioticians. 42 Augustine writes: Strictly speaking, I have here called a “thing” that which is not used to signify something else, like wood, stone, cattle, and so on; but not that wood concerning which we read that Moses cast it into bitter waters that their bitterness might be dispelled, nor that stone which Jacob placed at his head, nor that beast which Abraham sacrificed in place of his son. For these are things in such a way that they are also signs of other things … Thus every sign is also a thing, for that which is not a thing is nothing at all; but not every thing is also a sign. 43 The simultaneity of reception of a thing and a second thing signified by the first is at the heart of the symbolic mode. The use of a symbol requires that the receiver be familiar with the thing signified. Thus, a Christian on seeing an ox will be reminded of St. Luke, while a pagan encountering an olive tree will recognize Athena as the goddess signified. 161 greek exegesis and judaeo-christian books 161 Augustine also writes, “Figurative signs occur when that thing which we designate by a literal sign is used to signify something else; thus we say ‘ox’ and by that syllable understand the animal which is ordinarily designated by that word, but again by that animal we understand an evangelist.”44 In this aspect, the symbolic mode and substitution allegory share a common principle: both the symbolist reader and the substitutionist encountering the name Hephaestus would know that it signifies a particular god, but the god also signifies fire. All of this is established by convention as agreed upon in individual societies, as Augustine pointed out in book 2, c­ hapter 24 of On Christian Doctrine. But there is an essential difference between the two types of interpreter, as already noted: the symbolist reader will understand both the animal and the man when running across the word “ox,” while the substitutionist reader, assuming that a code is at work, will understand only the man, and discard the animal. 45 By favoring the symbolic mode over substitutionist allegory, the Christian exegete could maintain the authority of the letter of the text. At times, however, Augustine seems to overlook the full implications of his sign theory, as he devotes considerable attention to distinguishing those passages that should be taken literally from the ones that should be understood figuratively. Recall that Origen had done much the same thing. But in contrast to Origen, who used the tried and true pagan principle of plausibility, Augustine sets out a different criterion: To this warning that we must beware not to take figurative or transferred expressions as though they were literal, a further warning must be added lest we wish to take literal expressions as though they were figurative. Therefore, a method of determining whether a locution is literal or figurative must be established. And generally this method consists in this: that whatever appears in the divine Word that does not literally pertain to virtuous behavior or to the truth of faith you must take to be figurative. 46 Augustine elaborates “virtuous behavior” by returning to his central idea that scripture can teach only love of neighbor and of God, and whatever contradicts these two loves must be taken figuratively. In these cases, the figural must exclude the literal. Elsewhere in his book he significantly downplays the notion of discarding the literal meaning: Therefore, although all, or almost all of the deeds which are contained in the Old Testament are to be taken figuratively as well as literally, nevertheless the reader may take as literal those performed by people who are praised… . 47 162 162 the anatomy of my th The passage can leave little doubt that Augustine intends that both levels of meaning of scripture be preserved. As his thought evolved over the decades, Augustine showed an ever greater attachment to the letter of the text. By the time he was midway through his monumental On the City of God, he insisted that the literal sense had to be preserved at all costs. Discussing the various interpretations of the Garden of Eden he wrote: This is the kind of thing that can be said by way of allegorical interpretation of paradise, and there may be other more valuable lines of interpretation. There is no prohibition against such exegesis, provided that we believe in the truth of the story as a faithful record of historical fact. 48 One might be willing to speculate that this reattachment to literalism was occasioned by melancholy reflection on the history of the pagan religions. The skepticism of the philosophers regarding the literal truth of the Homeric myths spread to the less educated segments of the population and eventually undermined faith in the gods. The pagan rituals had become merely a good excuse for a community barbecue, or a pornographic mime masquerading as a divine mystery. Augustine, like Clement and Origen before him, was all too aware that the pagan spin doctors regarded the narratives of the Bible as being in no way different from the poets’ stories—they were all fables. Augustine knew that his role as a Christian teacher was to instruct his congregation and his readers that the pagans had myths, but Christians had truths. Arion of Methymna did not ride on the back of a dolphin, but Jonah did escape from the belly of a whale. 49 We have taken our story of the methods of interpretation developed by the Greeks as far as we can. Just as the Hebrews had despoiled the Egyptians, so now the Christians took the techniques of Greek exegesis and put them to a “better” use. Christianity had its own story to tell when it came to the exegesis of the Bible. It is apparent that Christians developed new methods, including some that were very different from their classical antecedents. However, in the process of creating their own strategies, Christian interpreters had first to master all the techniques developed by their opponents, the pagan Greeks. The two factions had attended the same schools, learned from the same masters, and read the same books. Each side knew how to deconstruct the other’s stories, as is shown by Origen in his Against Celsus and by Clement in his Exhortation. In the end, however, it was the defensive strategy that mattered for Christians as it had for pagans. The symbolist method favored by the Neoplatonists and earlier Platonizing writers like Philo was to prove more successful for Christian exegetes than the substitutionist method that characterized Stoic and earlier allegoresis. As we learn from Augustine, signs or symbols had the advantage of preserving the letter 163 greek exegesis and judaeo-christian books 163 simultaneously with the spirit, that is, the figurative meaning, of the text. At the same time, it opened the door to other layers of meaning, including the moral, and the anagogical—t he meaning of a text that leads us upward to God. This meaning, too, had come from the pagan Greeks. It is most obvious in the hermeneutics of the Neoplatonist Proclus, who saw in myths the symbols that lead the mind upward to the world of Nous, and even to a state described as “beyond being” (hyperousia). 164 165 13 Reflection: How Lasting Was the Greek Achievement? For those who believe in freedom of religion, free expression, and the separation of church and state, the fourth century c.e. had to be accounted one of the worst centuries in human history, perhaps the worst. It was the century that saw the beginning of an established church, the end of open debate on religious issues, and, perhaps worst of all, the assumption of the right of the state both to control religion and enforce its laws. By the end of that century, Christianity was the only religion that could be openly practiced, and any opposition to the teachings of its councils invited severe penalties, which the state undertook to administer. How this all happened has been the subject of numerous books, and no one answer has proved to be definitive. By the death of Theodosius I in 395, all pagan ritual had been outlawed (including even ceremonies in private houses), all doctrines running counter to the Nicene Creed proscribed, and pagan temples either demolished or refurbished for Christian worship. Pagans, understandably, were shocked, angry, and resentful. They could hardly be expected to understand how such radical changes affecting so many aspects of public and private life had come about so rapidly. Many felt condescension toward Christians for their “ignorant,” poorly written scriptures, their “barbarous” rituals, and adherence to the cult of an executed criminal. They pitied them much as they pitied the self-castrating adherents of the goddess Cybele. But they were willing to tolerate them within limits: they did not wish to be proselytized, and they tired of the riots and other disturbances caused by Christian factions in large urban centers. What they expected from Christians was tolerance, if not respect, in return. That is what Christians refused to offer. 166 166 the anatomy of my th Once Christians knew they were firmly in power, their leaders called for the extirpation of every species of heretic—and heretics included pagans. Christians wanted nothing less than a theocracy, and they got it. But for two main reasons, it was not absolute: (1) Christians did not attempt to replace the imperial secular educational system with Christian schools; (2) they allowed only a limited use of the Bible. That work was not really suitable as a self-study guide for Christians in their quest for salvation. It was too full of dangers to be left to the untutored. Moreover, it was only one source of authority; the other was the magisterium (teaching authority) of the Church. In their haste to institute broad religious and social reform, Christian “heads” overlooked two crucial factors: books and education. They smashed the idols of the pagan gods and turned their temples into churches, but they did not touch their books. The intricate theology they constructed was made from the building stones of Greek philosophy, especially Platonism and Stoicism. Christians never thought to burn the books of their mentors. They were, on the one hand, all too conscious of their debt; on the other, much too busy burning the books of Christian heretics. When it came to education, nothing changed with the introduction of anti-pagan sanctions. The state was not pushed to interfere with the schools or their curriculum, with the result that the books taught in the fourth century were the same as those taught centuries before (though the curriculum had shrunk). In other words, state education remained exclusively secular. The schools of pagan philosophy were left alone for more than a century after the Theodosian reforms. Religious schooling was not subsidized by the state, and even as late as the sixth century those wanting an education in the Christian scriptures had to seek it privately, at least outside of eastern centers such as Alexandria.1 The texts of the pagan classics continued to be copied, and new commentaries undertaken. While artists may have been encouraged to represent Christian themes, it remained perfectly legal to carve or paint or make a mosaic of a pagan mythological motif. You just were not allowed to offer a sacrifice to it once it was finished. Equally important to limiting theocracy was the restriction of the authority accorded to The Book. To pagans and Christian converts from paganism, there was something distinctly alien about the scriptures, particularly the Old Testament, a collection of books that Christians were compelled to accept as the first part of “salvation history.” Christian theologians never managed to work out in any degree of detail what parts of the Law the faithful were required to accept. From the beginning, Paul assured gentiles that they were exempt from circumcision. Few, apart from Jewish Christians, took the dietary regulations seriously. Fewer still, I suspect, asked the elders of the community to have their children stoned to death for disrespect. The ten commandments were just about all that could be salvaged out of the Law, and they, 167 reflection 167 too, were subordinated to Christ’s two great commandments regarding love of God, neighbor, and self. The Old Testament was a document that ordinary Christians should read with caution. There appeared to be a consensus that its chief value consisted of its perceived prophesies of Christ, and the examples given by figures that could be regarded as “types of Christ” such as Moses, or as archetypes of particular virtues such as Abraham (faith) and Job (patience). Much else had to be disregarded or somehow explained. The authority of the entire Bible as a sure and infallible blueprint for salvation was brought into question in a crucial theological debate. The first three decades of the fifth century witnessed a harsh theological dispute that encompassed Gaul, Italy, North Africa, and Syria, and reverberated in distant Britain. This was the Pelagian controversy, instigated by the Briton Pelagius, who challenged the idea that God’s grace was offered to some, but not others. He claimed that all received God’s grace equally through their created good nature, which included a free will, and the gift of the law. For the Pelagians, the law included both testaments of the Bible, and provided the sure path to salvation. It was the duty of all Christians to obey all of God’s commands, both great and small, in both testaments: “Do everything, so we are not to select some of God’s commandments as if to suit our fancy, but to fulfill them all without exception.”2 (Pelagius’s writings never tell us exactly how this was supposed to work, or give advice on how to deal with contradictory laws.) While most of Pelagius’s opponents thundered against his deficient notion of God’s grace, others attacked Pelagius for positing the Bible as the indispensable guide to salvation. If Pelagius’s views on scripture were to prevail, only the literate would have a chance of being saved, and out of that elite group, only those who could have had access to scriptures. For the “orthodox” side, the scriptures, properly used, could be an aid to salvation, but were not indispensable. Augustine had already addressed that point when he published the first portion of On Christian Doctrine: Thus a man supported by faith, hope, and charity, with an unshaken hold upon them, does not need the Scriptures except for the instruction of others. And many live by these three things in solitude without books.3 Those who felt the need to read them were warned that they were not writings for the untutored. The scriptures were chock full of obscure passages and apparent contradictions, and should be approached with great caution. Specialized training was required, and Augustine’s book offered precisely that. At the very least, one must know how to recognize passages that can be understood literally, and those that cannot. One cannot simply hand people a Bible and tell them to read it to procure their salvation. Were Augustine able to 168 168 the anatomy of my th drive through America today, he would be horrified to find a Gideon Bible in every motel room where he stayed. As a loving father of his only son, he would be concerned before all else that it might fall into the hands of children, or young people, or those mentally incapable of using it properly. For the Church, forced to come to terms with the requirement to include the Old Testament in its most authoritative document, there were three basic problems: (1) An unbiased reading of scripture would reveal that its words either do not support or else explicitly contradict the theology of the Church (for example, the doctrine of the Trinity, the perpetual virginity of Mary). (2) The scriptures, especially the Old Testament, contain numerous examples of immoral behavior by the patriarchs (for example, Lot’s incest with his daughters, Jacob’s defrauding of Esau) and examples of God behaving in a vindictive manner (for example, punishing a king who did not slay every one of his captured enemies). Augustine was all too aware of problems 2 and 3 when he wrote, “Whoever, therefore, thinks that he understands the divine Scriptures or any part of them so that it does not build the double love of God and of our neighbor does not understand it at all.”4 The pious reader, following Augustine, had to ignore those passages that encouraged the collection of enemy foreskins or else find a way to interpret them figuratively. The idea of figural interpretation ( figurate), broadly understood to include different levels of meaning and to operate in different ways, was the salvation of both the Bible and of intellectual freedom. Rational people could learn how to understand scripture in non-literal ways, just as Augustine learned from the sermons of Ambrose. Intelligent pagans of the fourth and fifth centuries were just as aware as Origen and Celsus that the biblical tale of the sons of God having intercourse with the daughters of men was as much a fable as the stories of Zeus and his earthly amours. Such stories were plasmata, “fictions,” whatever their source. If one was going to retain rather than censor them, new meanings had to be found. (Augustine struggled valiantly for an exegesis of the “sons of God and daughters of men” story, but in the end declared it “apocryphal.”5) Christians were not compelled to declare belief in biblical stories that were clearly implausible, or assent to narratives that appeared to condone immorality or portray God as cruel and capricious. Even the account of creation given by Genesis did not have to be understood literally as occurring in six normal calendar days. The restrictions placed on the use and understanding of scripture was the heritage of the pagan Greeks. The manifold ways in which Christians could interpret the Bible mirrored the ways in which pagans could read Homer and Hesiod. The process worked by accretion. No one method completely excluded another—w ith the exception that, for the early Greeks, a passage regarded as historically true would hardly be read allegorically, although it could contain a moral lesson. (Here pagans and Christians differed, with Christians granting the possibility of a simultaneous literal and 169 reflection 169 allegorical interpretation.) But Greek exegetes must be credited with devising substitutionist allegory (of both the physical and psychological types), rationalist historiography (euhemerizing), moral interpretation (akin to typology), and the symbolist mode (which allowed for retaining a literal and a figurative meaning simultaneously). All of these were products of the philosophical schools or movements beginning with the Presocratics and advancing through the Greek Stoics, Peripatetics, and Platonists. They were first adopted by Jewish Platonists, passed on to the Greek Christian Fathers, and transmitted into the West through Ambrose, Jerome, and Augustine. I have attempted in this book to document significant parts of that narrative and show where the turning points occur. An assessment of the net benefits is more difficult. No one can claim that Greek philosophy kept open the gates of intellectual freedom in the upheavals of the fourth century. One could even argue the opposite: Greek philosophy, reduced to dogma, expedited the triumph of Christianity. The architects of this victory had anticipated Augustine’s principle of “despoiling the Egyptians” and put their goods to a “better use.” As has been shown here, Greek philosophy provided the building stones of Christian theology. Today we would call the process “cooption.” But because Christians also adapted the methods invented by the Greeks for performing anatomies on myths, they were unable to erect a theocratic edifice that was airtight. The old Roman saying, “Captured Greece captured its captors,” coined originally to express the paradox of the conquered Greek people dominating the culture of Rome, applies here, too. Once Christian intellectuals had learned to read like Greeks, they had to think like Greeks when reading their own books. They were as driven as their pagan counterparts to investigate meaning. That was the essence of historia. The evil demons of skepticism and criticism had got out of the box, and there was no way to put them back in. The pagan classics were also saved: at first, out of sheer pietas; later because it was possible to show that they were not merely not incompatible with Christian teaching, but in fact supported and enhanced it. Augustine maintained his love of Vergil throughout life, and Jerome, who had sworn never to read another pagan work, cited a wide assortment of classical works through the whole range of his letters, often to show how they supported a teaching of scripture. Indeed, the classics were retained as a type of propaideusis (preparatory study) to the scriptures and made the basis of the liberal arts. The ancient writers were still needed as models of correct Latin grammar and good style, which the scriptures, even in the “new and improved” version known as the Vulgate, often lacked. The classical writers (auctores) were rescued from their service as handmaidens in the ninth century c.e. with the “rediscovery” of allegory. That story remains to be told in full.6 170 ╇ 171 Notes Preface 1. I give an outline of this thesis in my article “Classical Exegesis—╉From Theagenes of Rhegium to Bernard Silvestris,” Florilegium 30 (2013 [2015]), 59–╉102. Introduction 1. Mary R. Lef kowitz, Women in Greek Myth, 2nd ed. (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 2007), p. 9. 2. For an excellent review of the treatment of this story from ancient to modern times see W. B. Stanford, The Ulysses Theme: A Study in the Adaptability of a Traditional Hero (Oxford: Blackwell, 1963). 3. The incidents are found in the different recensions of so-╉ called Pseudo-╉ Callisthenes. See George Cary, The Medieval Alexander, ed. D. J. A. Ross (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1956), pp. 9–╉61. 4. Ovid, Metamorphoses 1, 313–╉415. 5. Bernard de Fontenelle, De l’origine des fables, 1724; see further references in Jaan Puhvel, Comparative Mythology (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1989), p. 11. 6. Puhvel, Comparative Mythology, p. 12. 7. For a review and critique of these theories see G. S. Kirk, Myth: Its Meaning and Functions in Ancient and Other Cultures (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp. 10–╉31. 8. See Walter Burkert, The Orientalizing Revolution: Near Eastern Influence on Greek Culture in the Early Archaic Age, trans. Margaret E. Pinder and Walter Burkert (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1992), pp. 89–╉127. 172 172â•… notes to pages 5–16 9. See especially G. R. Boys-╉ Stones, Post-╉ Hellenistic Philosophy: A Study of Its Development from the Stoics to Origen (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001). 10. For the story of this development, see Robert Lamberton, Homer the Theologian: Neoplatonist Allegorical Reading and the Growth of the Epic Tradition (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1989). 11. Lucretius, On the Nature of Things, 5, 1161–╉74, trans. Copley. 12. The thesis of Luc Brisson: How Philosophers Saved Myths: Allegorical Interpretation and Classical Mythology (Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press, 2004). 13. For an excellent study of the ancient Greek historians and ethnologists’ approaches to myth, see Paul Veyne, Did the Greek Believe in Their Myths?: An Essay on the Constitutive Imagination, trans. Paula Wissing (Chicago and London: Chicago University Press, 1988). 14. In antiquity Orpheus was regarded as a real poet and works were attributed to him. See M. L. West, The Orphic Poems (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983), pp. 1–╉38. 15. Macrobius, Commentary on the Dream of Scipio 1.2.6–╉12, trans. William Harris Stahl (New York: Columbia University Press, 1952), pp. 84–╉85. 16. See generally Kirk, Myth: Its Meaning and Function. 17. For the Greeks’ late discovery of their Jewish neighbors and their literature, see Arnaldo Momigliano, Alien Wisdom: The Limits of Hellenization (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1975), pp. 74–╉96. 18. The classic works are A. B. Lord, The Singer of Tales (Cambridge, MA; Harvard University Press, 1960) and Milman Parry, The Making of Homeric Verse: The Collected Writings of Milman Parry (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1971). 19. Plato, Ion, 530. Chapter 1 1. Northrop Frye, The Great Code: The Bible and Literature (Toronto: Penguin Books, 1990), p. xiii, argues in favor of the reading of the Bible as a unitary work. This reflects the historical reading of the scriptures as a single inspired narrative of “salvation history.” 2. The language of the documents written in the so-╉called Linear B was shown to be Greek. See Michael Ventris and John Chadwick, Documents in Mycenaean Greek, 2nd ed. (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1973). 3. See M. L. West, Early Greek Philosophy and the Orient (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1971) and the Introduction to his edition of Hesiod’s Theogony (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1966). 4. The story of the reverence paid to Homer over the centuries and the ascription to him of every kind of knowledge is beautifully limned by Lamberton, Homer the Theologian. 5. Iliad 24, 527–╉33 describe the “two urns that stand on the door-╉sill of Zeus,” trans. Richmond Lattimore, in The Iliad of Homer (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1961), p. 489. Zeus fills them, mingling good and evil and bringing blessings to one, ruin to another. 6. Walter Burkert, Greek Religion, trans. John Raffan (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1985), pp. 119–╉ 215. W. K. C. Guthrie’s description of the ╇ 173 notes to pages 16 –28 â•… 173 7. 8. 9. 10. 11. 12. 13. 14. 15. 16. 17. 18. Homeric gods is as pertinent as when it was written: The Greeks and Their Gods (Boston: Beacon Press, 1950), pp. 117–╉27. Iliad 1, 260–╉74. Theseus and Perithoüs are placed in this group. They fought and destroyed the beast-╉men. Unlike the “old” heroes Heracles, Theseus, and Orpheus, who actually descend into Hades, Odysseus, who was born on this side of the temporal watershed, converses with the shades of the underworld through a hole in the earth. Homer describes a kind of necromancy that is not very different from King Saul’s consultation of the dead prophet Samuel in I Sam. 28:13–╉15, except that no prophetess is involved. See the recent discussion of the Homeric psyche (“shade”) by A. A. Long, Greek Models of Mind and Self (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2015), pp. 15–╉ 48, and passim. See Pindar’s description of the “Isle of the Blest” (where “Isle” is singular) in Olympian Odes 2, 68–╉83. It is inhabited by those who keep their souls pure and by heroes such as Achilles. See James S. Romm, The Edges of the Earth in Ancient Thought (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1992), pp. 13–╉17. This problem worried the anonymous author of a cosmographical work written in the eighth century c.e. See The Cosmography of Aethicus Ister: Edition, Translation and Commentary, ed. Michael Herren (Turnhout, Belgium: Brepols, 2011), chapter 23. Richard Dawkins, The God Delusion (Boston and New York: Houghton Mifflin, 2008), p. 52. A late tradition claims that Prometheus himself, aided by his brother, Epimetheus, created men. Theogony, lines 589–╉91, ed. and trans. H. G. Evelyn-╉White, in Hesiod, the Homeric Hymns and Homerica, LCL (London: William Heinemann Ltd; Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 1967), p. 123. This may explain Hesiod’s own belief that gods and humans came from the same source (Works and Days, line 108): the gods came indirectly from their grandmother Gaia (Earth), and humans were made of earth. My interpretation of Hesiod’s text. The origin of bronze-╉age men from ash trees has another layer of complexity. Ash is the wood out of which spears are made—╉ hence the association with warfare and violence. See Bruno Snell, The Discovery of the Mind: The Greek Origins of European Thought, trans T. G. Rosenmeyer (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1953), pp. 25–╉26. Chapter 2 1. DK 21, B.10 (1:59); trans. J. H. Lesher, in Xenophanes of Colophon: Fragments; A Text and Translation with a Commentary (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1992), p. 20. 2. Jack Goody, The Interface between the Written and the Oral (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1967, rept. 1987), p. 61. 174 174 notes to pages 28 –33 3. An example can be seen in John Chadwick, The Decipherment of Linear B, 2nd ed. (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1976), p. 59. 4. Goody, The Interface, p. 64. 5. “Books,” in Oxford Classical Dictionary, ed. Simon Hornblower, Antony Spawforth, and Esther Eidinow, 3rd ed., pp. 250–51. 6. William V. Harris, Ancient Literacy (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1989), pp. 47–48. 7. Harris, Ancient Literacy, pp. 48–49. 8. For more discussion of this topic, see Brisson, How Philosophers Saved Myths, pp. 7–9. 9. The various traditions of reciting Homer at the Panathenaia have been critically examined by Gregory Nagy, Homer the Preclassic (Berkeley, Los Angeles, and London: University of California Press, 2010), pp. 20–28. 10. The story of the translation by seventy-two scholars was regarded as a fiction by St. Jerome. However, a twentieth-century scholar doubted even the involvement of Ptolemy II Philadelphus. See Momigliano, Alien Wisdom, p. 91. 11. Christopher de Hamel, The Book: A History of the Bible (London: Phaedon Press Ltd., 2001), pp. 36–38. 12. A very readable account is given by Adam Nicholson, God’s Secretaries: The Making of the King James Bible (New York: HarperCollins Publishers, Inc., 2003). 13. The text is available with an English translation in P. A. Brunt and J. M. Moore, Res gestae divi Augusti (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1967). 14. His dating is dependent on a comment by Tatian (frag. 1 cit. in n. 15) that he was active in the time of King Cambyses (530–522 b.c.e.). 15. Hermann Diels, Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker: Griechisch und deutsch, ed. Walther Kranz. [DK] 12th edition (Dublin, Ireland, and Zürich, Switzerland: Weidmann, 1966), 72, nos. 1–3, vol. II, p. 205. 16. Walter Ong, Literacy and Orality: The Technologizing of the Word (London and New York: Routledge, 1982, rept. 2002), pp. 8–9. 17. Harris, Ancient Literacy, p. 62. 18. West, The Orphic Poems, pp. 81–82. 19. See “Hymns (Greek),” Oxford Classical Dictionary, 3rd ed., p. 736. 20. See especially G. E. R. Lloyd, Magic, Reason and Experience: Studies in the Origin and Development of Greek Science (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1979), pp. 13–14; also, most recently, Tim Whitmarsh, Battling the Gods: Atheism in the Ancient World (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 2015), pp. 28–39. Whitmarsh (p. 28) states, “When gods reveal their thoughts to mortals in written form, then mortals can be held to account by reference to fixed texts.” 21. Iliad 2, 485–87, trans. Lattimore, p. 89. 22. See Louise H. Pratt, Lying and Poetry from Homer to Pindar: Falsehood and Deception in Archaic Greek Poetics (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1993), pp. 12–14. 23. Plato, Ion 533–34, ed. and trans. D. A. Russell and Michael Winterbottom, in Ancient Literary Criticism: The Principal Texts in Translation (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1972), p. 43. 24. Aristotle, Poetics 1455a, trans. Russell and Winterbottom, in Ancient Literary Criticism, p. 113. ╇ 175 notes to pages 37–42 â•… 175 Chapter 3 1. Not really a satisfactory term, because it implies that little of importance in philosophy or science happened before Socrates. However, the term is too deeply embedded in the literature to attempt to replace it. 2. Notably by Rudolf Bultmann and his school. See, for example, Jesus Christ and Mythology (London: SCM Press, 1960). 3. Burkert, Greek Religion, pp. 8–╉9. 4. These are poems addressed to a variety of gods. They “sing” the god or goddess addressed and recount their deeds and benefits to mortals. Sometimes they end with a petition or a warning. The hymns are handily consulted in Hesiod: The Homeric Hymns and Homerica, ed. and trans. Hugh G. Evelyn-╉ White, LCL (London: William Heinemann; Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1967), pp. 286–╉463. 5. Dawkins, The God Delusion, p. 82, citing Richard Swinburne, Is There a God? 6. St. Augustine Concerning the City of God against the Pagans, 21.4–╉5, trans. Henry Bettenson (London: Penguin Books, 1984), pp. 968–╉74. 7. Momigliano, Alien Wisdom, p. 91, states that the earliest use of the Bible by a Greek philosopher is by the author of On the Sublime [Longinus?], a work usually assigned to the first century c.e. 8. Cited from R. Walzer, Galen on Jews and Christians (London: Oxford University Press, 1949), p. 1. 9. Jonathan Barnes, Early Greek Philosophy (London: Penguin Books, 1987), p. 13. 10. Cited from Lloyd, Magic, Reason, and Experience, p. 16. 11. Cited from Lloyd, Magic, Reason and Experience, p. 25. 12. G. S. Kirk, J. E. Raven, and M. Schofield [KRS], The Presocratic Philosophers: A Critical History with a Selection of Texts (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1983), no. 217, p. 198. 13. In his late work Timaeus. Modern philosophers are divided on how seriously to take the fable as representative of Plato’s actual thoughts about the origin of the world. However, philosophers and commentators from Aristotle to the twelfth century c.e. never had the least doubt that Plato meant every word of it. 14. KRS nos. 84–╉85, pp. 88–╉89. 15. KRS no. 91, p. 95, 16. Aristotle, On the Soul 405a. 17. Plato, Tim. 36–╉37. Aristotle, On the Heavens 279a ad fin. 18. KRS no. 133, p. 141. 19. KRS no. 134, p.141, 20. KRS no. 110, pp. 117–╉19. For a summary of theories about this substance see Elizabeth Asmis, “What is Anaximander’s ‘Apeiron’?,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 19.3 (July 1981), 279–╉97, at p. 279, n. 1. 21. KRS no. 146, p. 150 (gods come from air); KRS nos. 144–╉45, p. 150 (the air is a god). 22. KRS no. 160, p. 158. 23. See the detailed discussion of the archē in L. P. Gerson, Gods and Greek Philosophy: Studies in the History of Natural Theology (London and New York: Routledge, 1990), pp. 5–╉32. 176 176 notes to pages 42–48 24. See generally Harold Cherniss, Aristotle’s Criticism of Presocratic Philosophy (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins Press, 1935; rept. Octagon Books, 1971). 25. The four causes can be illustrated by the homely example of making a chair: The final cause (4) is the purpose of the chair: to provide humans comfort and relief from standing. The purpose is achieved by designing a form (2) or shape to accommodate the human bottom, legs, arms, and back. But since one cannot sit on air you need matter (1), or stuff, from which to make the chair. However, since a pattern and a pile of wood by themselves won’t make a chair, you need an efficient cause (3), that is, a carpenter, to cut the pieces of wood and assemble them into a chair. 26. KRS no. 190, p. 181. Stories of this type belong to a long tradition of slandering one’s philosophical opponents by disparaging their appearance or way of life. They should be taken with a grain of salt. The more salient point of the anecdote is that even doctors cannot perform feats that are by nature impossible. 27. KRS no. 219, p. 198. 28. KRS no. 220, p. 198. 29. KRS no. 228, p. 202. 30. KRS no. 190, p. 181. 31. Aristotle, Meta. 1.3 (984a); more fully in On the Heavens 3.1 (298b). 32. DK 22, B57 (1:163); T. M. Robinson, trans. Heraclitus. Fragments. A Text and Translation with a Commentary (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1987), p. 39. 33. KRS no. 211, p. 193. 34. DK 21, B8 (1:26–27); trans. Lesher, p. 21. 35. DK 21, B1 (1:126–27); Lesher, p. 11. 36. KRS nos. 166–9, p. 168. 37. KRS nos. 170–72, p. 169. 38. Aristotle, Rhetoric 2.23, (1399b); cit. Lesher, p. 200. 39. Gerson, God and Greek Philosophy, p. 19, calls him an archē-god. I have reservations about this name, as it is not clear from the texts that Xenophanes’ god creates. Moreover, even if god did create, he would still have required some type of preexistent (or coexistent) matter to work with. (Creation ex nihilo was unknown at that time.) A god would thus not satisfy the requirements of an archē as understood by Ionians. Xenophanes also said, “We come into being from earth and water” (DK 21, B33 [1:136]); trans. Lesher, p. 37). These elements might be regarded as Xenophanes’ archai, but the issue is complicated by his positing an external god. 40. Werner Jaeger, The Theology of the Early Greek Philosophers (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1947), pp. 43–4 4. 41. For an assessment of his influence see again Jaeger, The Theology of the Early Greek Philosophers, pp. 38–54. 42. DK 21, B1, lines 19–24 (1:127–28); trans. Lesher, p. 13. 43. DK 21, B32 (1:136); trans. Lesher, p. 37. 44. KRS no. 177, p. 172. 45. KRS no, 476, p. 363. 46. Diogenes Laertius, Lives of the Philosophers 2.6.9, trans. Patricia Curd, in Anaxagoras of Clazomene: Fragments and Testimonia; A Text and Translation with Notes and Essays (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2007), p. 78. ╇ 177 notes to pages 48 –55 â•… 177 47. DK 59, A72; trans. Patricia Curd, Anaxagoras of Clazomenae. A Text and Translation with Notes and Essays (Toronto, Buffalo, and London: University of Toronto Press, 2007), p. 110. 48. KRS no. 563, p. 417. 49. KRS no. 569, p. 420. Chaopter 4 1. On this point I follow Jonathan Barnes, The Presocratic Philosophers (London: Routledge, 1982), pp. 406–╉9. 2. It is true that Melissos of Samos, a pupil of Parmenides, claimed that the One is incorporeal (asōmaton); cf. KRS, no. 538; however, see the commentary, pp. 400–╉1. 3. See the still useful article by A. W. Cambridge-╉Pickard, “Tragedy, Greek,” in The Oxford Classical Dictionary, 2nd ed., especially pp. 919–╉20. 4. See J. E. Taylor, “The New Atheists,” in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy [2010; peer-╉reviewed]: http://╉w ww.iep.utm.edu/╉n-╉atheis. 5. See especially Dawkins, The God Delusion, pp. 69–╉7 7. 6. A. B. Drachmann, Atheism in Greek Antiquity (Chicago: Ares Publishers, Inc., 1977), pp. 1–╉7. For more recent work on atheism in antiquity see Jan N. Bremmer, “Atheism in Antiquity” in The Cambridge Companion to Atheism, ed. Michael Martin (Cambridge, UK: University Press, 2007), pp. 12–╉32; Tim Whitmarsh, Battling the Gods. 7. For details see Andrew Ford, Aristotle as Poet: The Song for Hermias and Its Context (New York: Oxford University Press, 2011), pp. 56–╉67. Aristotle’s defenders claimed that the verses lacked the characteristics of a paian, and in fact was a skolion, a poem composed for a symposium. 8. DK 80, B 4 (2:265). 9. DK 80 B1 (2:263). 10. The complete paradox is “if a tree falls in a forest and no one is present to hear it, did it make a sound?” The correct answer is “no,” because sound by definition requires a receptor to occur. The paradox was wrongly attributed to the British philosopher George Berkeley. Berkeley’s question, as formulated in section 45 of his A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge (1710), poses the more difficult problem of whether the flowers he saw in a garden continued to exist after he left the garden. 11. Burkert, Greek Religion, pp. 285–╉90; see also George Mylonas, Eleusis and the Eleusinian Mysteries (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1961). 12. Burkert, Greek Religion, p. 316. 13. DK 84, B 5 (2:317). 14. Cit. n. 10. 15. Walter Burkert, “Hesiod in Context: Abstractions and Divinities in an Aegean-╉ Eastern Koiné,” in Personification in the Greek World: From Antiquity to Byzantium, ed. Emma Stafford and Judith Herrin (Aldershot, UK: Ashgate, 2005), pp. 3–╉20, shows convincingly that the personification of abstracts is a feature of the Near Eastern world, embracing Hebrew and Akkadian, among other literatures. 178 178â•… notes to pages 55– 64 16. T. B. L. Webster, “Personification as a Mode of Greek Thought,” Journal of the Warburg and Courtauld Institutes 17 (1954), 10–╉21, at p. 14. 17. See Whitmarsh, Battling the Gods, pp. 166–╉72, with references. 18. The view of Drachmann, Atheism, pp. 43–╉4 4. 19. DK 23, B 53 (1:207). 20. The play has also been attributed to Euripides. 21. DK 25, B1 (2:386–╉87); my translation. 22. Drachmann, Atheism, p. 50. 23. Aristophanes, Frogs, lines 885–╉92, trans. Russell and Winterbottom, in Ancient Literary Criticism, p. 17. 24. Cited from Drachmann, Atheism, p. 53. 25. See now Mary R. Lef kowitz, Euripides and the Gods (New York: Oxford University Press, 2016), who reminds us that Euripides’ depiction of the gods as cruel, unjust, volatile, and fickle is meant as a description of their true natures. It does not imply disbelief in their existence. See especially her concluding chapter, pp. 193–╉204. 26. See Dirk Obbink’s excellent review of Epicurus’s teachings about the gods and religion and the reasons for the accusations against him: “The Atheism of Epicurus,” Greek, Roman and Byzantine Studies 30 (1989), 187–╉223. 27. The statement is attributed to him by the Church Father Lactantius, On the Wrath of God, Â�chapter 17. 28. See Christopher Hitchens, God is Not Great: How Religion Poisons Everything (Toronto: McClelland and Stewart Ltd., 2007), chapter 2, “Religion Kills,” pp. 15–╉36. 29. Lucretius, On the Nature of Things, book 1, lines 61–╉67, 78–╉79, trans. Frank O. Copley (New York: W. W. Norton & Co., 1977), p. 2. 30. Whitmarsh, Battling the Gods, pp. 156–╉72. While it is true, as Whitmarsh states (p. 165), that the Skeptics contributed mightily to philosophical atheism by laying its logical foundations, the principle established by the Academics (a branch of Skepticism) that one cannot assent to the truth of propositions leads to the conclusion that one cannot assent to the proposition that god does not exist. 31. See Plato, Theaetetus 151E–╉152A), where Plato begins a long discourse against relativism. 32. The expression of this notion par excellence is to be found in Herodotus, Histories 3.38. 33. See Momigliano, Alien Wisdom, pp. 1–╉21, especially p. 21. Chapter 5 1. Diogenes Laertius, Lives of the Philosophers, 8.3. 2. Diogenes Laertius, Lives 8.21; see Jean Pépin, Mythe et allégorie: Les origines grecques et les contestations judéo-╉chrétiennes (Paris: Études augustiniennes, 1976), p. 93. 3. KRS no. 213, p. 194. 4. Aristotle, Meta. 1.4 (984b), trans. Richard McKeon, in Introduction to Aristotle (New York: The Modern Library, 2001), p. 696. ╇ 179 notes to pages 64–74 â•… 179 5. Aristotle, Poetics 1447b, trans. Russell and Winterbottom, in Ancient Literary Criticism, p. 91. 6. For a lively discussion of the topic see W. B. Stanford, Enemies of Poetry (London, Boston, and Henley: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1980). 7. Plato, Rep. B.377, trans. Russell and Winterbottom, in Ancient Literary Criticism, p. 52. 8. Herodotus, Histories 2.53, trans. De Sélincourt (Harmondsworth, UK: Penguin Books, 1965), p. 124. 9. Plato, Phaedrus 245a, trans. Russell and Winterbottom, in Ancient Literary Criticism, p. 75. 10. Claude Lévi-╉Strauss, Myth and Meaning (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1978), p. 3. 11. Aristotle, Poetics 1451b, trans. Russell and Winterbottom, p. 103. 12. Poetics 1461a, trans. Russell and Winterbottom, p. 128. 13. Poetics 1451b, trans. Russell and Winterbottom, p. 102. 14. Plato, Rep. B.381–╉82, trans. Russell and Winterbottom, p. 55. 15. See the fine survey of the topos by Jan Ziolkowski, “Old Wives’ Tales: Classicism and Anti-╉Classicism from Apuleius to Chaucer,” The Journal of Medieval Latin 12 (2002), pp. 90–╉113. The title is somewhat misleading, as the article includes a significant amount of Greek and Roman material before Apuleius. 16. Rep. B.378, trans. Russell and Winterbottom, p. 54. 17. Ibid. 18. Rep. 1. 597–╉99, trans. Russell and Winterbottom, pp. 67–╉69. 19. Poetics 1448b, trans. Russell and Winterbottom, p. 94. 20. Ibid. 21. Poetics 1454a, trans. Russell and Winterbottom, p. 110. Elsewhere in the work, however (1453a) Aristotle modifies this stance: “[The tragic hero] is not pre-╉eminent in moral virtue, who passes to bad fortune, not through vice or wickedness, but because of some piece of ignorance…â•›.” (trans. Russell and Winterbottom, p. 106). 22. For changing attitudes to literature in the Epicurean tradition see Elizabeth Asmis, “Epicurean Poetics,” in Philodemus and Poetry: Poetic Theory and Practice in Lucretius, Philodemus, and Horace, ed. Dirk Obbink (New York: Oxford University Press, 1995), pp. 15–╉34. 23. Lucretius, The Nature of Things 3, 984, trans. Copley, p. 79; cf. Odyssey 11, 604–╉10. Chapter 6 1. I recognize that modern scholars are generally skeptical that ancient authors consciously encoded their poems with allegorical messages, except, perhaps in scattered passages. 2. Plutarch, On the Study of Poetry, trans. Russell and Winterbottom, in Ancient Literary Criticism, p. 516: “Some critics in fact have so forced and perverted the meaning of these [passages] by using what used to be called hyponoia and is now called allegory…â•›.” 3. An amusing illustration of the principle occurred some decades ago on the long-╉ running BBC political satire, “Yes, Prime Minister.” In one episode, the Prime 180 180â•… 4. 5. 6. 7. 8. 9. 10. 11. 12. 13. 14. 15. 16. 17. 18. notes to pages 74–85 Minister heads a delegation to Saudi Arabia, where alcohol is strictly forbidden. During the negotiations with the Saudis, the Prime Minister’s secretary periodically interrupts business with the message that there is a delegation of teachers who urgently need to see him. The P.M. would abruptly leave and return a few minutes later—╉each time a little more intoxicated than the last. Most viewers understood that the code involved substituting the name of an occupation for Teachers, a brand of Scotch whiskey. Reported in Xenophon, Memorabilia 2.1.20–╉32. A synopsis without the speeches can be found in Basil, On Reading Greek Literature, Â�chapter 5. Memorabilia 2.1.31, trans. Marchant, LCL, p. 99. On the growing awareness of opposition between soul (mind) and body in the fifth century b.c.e., see Long, Greek Models of Mind and Self, pp. 88–╉124. It is true that the Judgment tale can be read literally and understood as the prime cause of the Trojan War, as Vergil portrays it in the opening lines of the Aeneid. But Homer (Il. 3, 39; 13, 769) calls Paris “woman-╉crazed” (gynaimanēs), a moral flaw that determines his choice of Aphrodite (Sex) over Athena (Wisdom), and Hera (Family Values), the attributes most commonly associated with these goddesses. Il. 9, 502–╉14, trans. Lattimore, pp. 211–╉12. DK 8, frag. 2 (1:51–╉52). Ibid., frag. 1 (from Tatian). KRS no. 213, p. 194. J. Tate, “The Beginnings of Greek Allegory,” Classical Review 41 (1927), 214–╉15. Cit. n. 9. Brisson, How Philosophers Saved Myths, pp. 37–╉38. Not to be confused with the later Metrodorus of Lampsacus, who was an Epicurean philosopher, or Metrodorus of Chios, who was a disciple of Democritus. DK 61, frag. 4 (2:49). DK 61, frag. 3 (2:49). For recent observations on Metrodorus see Dirk Obbink, “Allegory and Exegesis in the Derveni Papyri,” in Metaphor, Allegory, and the Classical Tradition, ed. G. R. Boys-╉Stones (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003), pp. 177–╉88, at 180. For Plato’s myths see Luc Brisson, Plato the Mythmaker, trans. Gerard Naddaf (Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press, 1998). Chapter 7 1. Plutarch, proem, “The Life of Theseus,” trans. Edmund Fuller, in Lives of the Noble Greeks. A Selection (New York: Dell Publishing, 1968), p. 10. 2. Ibid. 3. Veyne, Did the Greeks Believe in their Myths?, p. 8. 4. Not to be confused with Pherecydes the Syrian, who flourished in the sixth century or earlier. 5. See Veyne, p. 7. 6. On the criterion of the present as a means of judging what happened in the past, see Veyne, pp. 71–╉74. ╇ 181 notes to pages 85– 99 â•… 181 7. Lucretius, On the Nature of Things 5, 878–╉91, trans. Copley, p. 133. 8. Recent work based on excavations has confirmed the existence of warrior women in the region. See Adrienne Mayor, The Amazons: Lives and Legends of Warrior Women across the Ancient World (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2014). 9. Hecataeus, frag. 1a; Felix Jacoby, Die Fragmente der griechischen Historiker [reprinted with additions and corrections], [FgrH] (Leiden, The Netherlands: Brill, 1957), 1:7–╉8. 10. Hecataeus, frag. 27; Jacoby, FGrH 1:14. 11. Plutarch, Life of Theseus, trans. Fuller, p. 16. 12. Ibid. 13. Augustine, On Christian Doctrine, trans. D. W. Robertson, Jr. (The Library of the Liberal Arts. Indianapolis, IN; New York: Bobbs-╉Merrill, 1958), 2.17. 14. Lactantius, De ira Dei 2.7–╉8, cit. Brisson, How Philosophers Saved Myths, p. 49. 15. The Geography of Strabo, 12.8, ed. and trans. Horace Leonard Jones, LCL (London: Heinemann, 1917–╉1933, 1:67. 16. Ibid. 17. Herodotus, Histories 2. 143, trans. De Sélincourt, p. 159. 18. Herodotus, Histories 3, 122, cit. Veyne, p. 134, n. 24. 19. Lucretius, On the Nature of Things 3, 978–╉1023. 20. Vergil, Aeneid 6, 719–╉51. 21. Pausanias, Descriptions of Greece 1.2.1, trans. and ed. W. H. S. Jones, LCL 93–╉97 (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, repr. 1931), 1:7–╉9. 22. Descriptions of Greece 1.3.3, trans. W. H. S. Jones, 1:15–╉17. 23. Ibid. 24. Descriptions of Greece 1.4.4, trans. W. H. S. Jones, 1:23. 25. Plutarch, Life of Theseus, trans. Fuller, p. 27. 26. Strabo. Geography 1.2.13–╉15, trans. H. L. Jones, 1:85. 27. Geography 1.2.9, trans. H. L. Jones, 1:73. 28. See Veyne, pp. 5–╉15. 29. Geography 1.2.8, trans. H. L. Jones, 1:69. 30. Geography 1.2.11, trans. H. L. Jones, 1:79. 31. Augustine, The City of God 16.8. See Michael Herren, “The Cosmography of Aethicus Ister and Ancient Travel Literature,” in The World of Travellers: Exploration and Imagination, edited by Kees Dekker, Karin Olsen, and Tette Hofstra (Leuven, Belgium: Peeters. 2009), pp. 5–╉30, at pp. 12–╉13. Chapter 8 1. 2. 3. 4. 5. 6. 7. Aristotle, On the Heavens 298b. KRS no. 538, p. 400. KRS no. 211, p. 193. Not the only allowable interpretation of the statement; see above, p. 56. KRS 171, p. 169. KRS no. 476, p. 363. Ibid. 182 182â•… notes to pages 99 –111 8. The opinion of Drachmann, Atheism, pp. 26–╉27. 9. See, for example, Gilbert Murray, Five Stages of Greek Religion (Garden City, NY: Doubleday Anchor, 1951), Â�chapter 4, “The Failure of Nerve,” pp. 119–╉65. 10. See John Dillon, The Middle Platonists: A Study of Platonism (London: Duckworth, 1977), p. 29. 11. Plato, Tim. 38, trans. Benjamin Jowett (Indianapolis, IN: Bobbs Merrill, 1949), p. 20. 12. Tim. 41, trans. Jowett, pp. 23–╉24. 13. Cited by Aristotle, On Rhetoric B 26, 1399b5, trans. Lesher, p. 200. 14. See the article “Intelligent Design” [https://╉ en.wikipedia.org/╉ wiki/╉ Intelligent_╉ design] in Wikipedia, which begins by characterizing its topic as “pseudo-╉ scientific.” The author traces the concept to the Middle Ages (the usual suspect for crimes against reason) without acknowledging the crucial roles played by Plato and Aristotle. 15. This is a pointed critique of the archē, the divine element that is the source and cause of things including motion. 16. Tim. 48. See the discussion of this passage by F. M. Cornford, Plato’s Cosmology: The Timaeus of Plato Translated with a Running Commentary (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul Ltd, 1937), pp. 161–╉77. 17. Augustine, On Christian Doctrine 2.43; City of God 8.11; see G. R. Boys-╉Stones, Post-╉ Hellenistic Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 116–╉17. 18. Aristotle, Phys. 199a–╉b; in greater detail: Meta., book 7. 19. Aristotle, On the Soul, book 3, Â�chapter 5 (430a), trans. McKeon, p. 592. 20. Aristotle, Meta. 12.6, 1071b, trans. McKeon, p. 878. 21. Aristotle’s idea of necessity seems identical to that of Leucippus, namely, that nothing happens in vain, and everything happens for a reason (DK, B2 (2:81)). His quarrel with Leucippus was over the need for a final cause. Democritus “tweaked” Leucippus’s notion of necessity, adding that events happen from causes, but the causes are not purposeful; see Daniel W. Graham, The Texts of Early Greek Philosophy: The Complete Fragments and Selected Testimonies of the Major Presocratics (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2010), p. 621. 22. Meta. 12.7, 1072b, trans. McKeon, p. 880. 23. Meta. 12.7 (1073a), trans. McKeon, p. 881. 24. Phys. 2.8 (199a), trans. McKeon, p. 249. 25. On the Heavens 1.4 (271a) ad fin., trans. J. L. Stocks in Richard McKeon, Basic Works of Aristotle, p. 404. 26. Tim. 43, trans. Jowett, p. 25. 27. See especially On the Heavens 279b –╉283b. Chapter 9 1. See the interesting article by A. A. Long, “Stoic Readers of Homer,” in Homer’s Ancient Readers: The Hermeneutics of Greek Epic’s Earliest Exegetes, ed. R. Lamberton and J. J. Keaney (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1992), pp. 41– ╉66. 2. A third type of allegory was introduced later, and mainly in a Roman context. This is historical allegory, in which mythical or folkloric characters are substituted for 183 notes to pages 111–122 183 prominent figures of history. But we shall have enough to do discussing the two basic types described. 3. See, for example, Pierre Chantraine, Dictionnaire étymologique de la langue grecque, rev. ed. (Paris: Klincksieck, 2009), pp. 273–74. 4. Pépin, Mythe et allégorie, p. 406n, citing Clement of Alexandria. 5. Hephaestus and Hestia (guardian of the hearth) were associated in classical mythology, making a folk etymology a possibility. Cf. W. H. Röscher, Lexikon der griechischen und römischen Mythologie (Leipzig: Teuber, 1884–1893), 1.2, col. 2037. An attested etymology of the name is from hēphthai (“to kindle, set afire”). 6. J. Tate, “Plato and Allegorical Interpretation,” Classical Quarterly 23 (1925), 142–54, at pp. 142–43. 7. See Pépin, Mythe et allégorie, pp. 127–31. 8. Cornutus, Epid. 1.6.6, in Heinz-Günther Nesselrath et al., ed. and trans., Die griechischen Götter: Ein Überblick über Namen, Bilder, und Deuthungen, Scripta Antiquitata Posterioris ad Ethicam Religionemque Pertinentia (Tübingen, Germany: Mohr Siebeck, 2009), p. 36. 9. Hesiod, Theog., lines 182– 97, trans. Norman O. Brown (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall, 1953), p. 58. Some editors omit the last line with its etymological explanation as interrupting the sense. 10. Hans Friedrich August von Arnim, ed., Stoicorum veterum fragmenta [SVF]. 4 vols. (Leipzig: Teubner, 1900–1910 [reprint 1960–1969]), 2:1071–74. 11. Hesiod, Theog., lines 31–33, trans. Brown, p. 54. 12. See nn. 191–92 in Nasselrath’s edition. 13. See Michael Lapidge, “Stoic Cosmology,” in The Stoics, ed. J. Rist (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1978), pp. 161–85, at p. 165. 14. Cicero, C. P. McGregor, trans., The Nature of the Gods (Harmondsworth, UK: Penguin Books, 1972), 2.64, p. 148. Curiously, the Latin etymology of Saturn as “sated” was recycled into Greek. In Neoplatonic cosmology, Kronos (Saturn), who stands for Nous (Mind), is “sated” with his offspring, who stand for the plenitude of the intellectual principle; see Brisson, How Philosophers Saved Myths, pp. 76– 7 7. 15. The Nature of the Gods 2.65–66, trans. McGregor, pp. 149–50. 16. The Nature of the Gods 2.63–64, trans. McGregor, p. 148. 17. See the insightful study of Cornutus in G. R. Boys- Stones, Post-Hellenistic Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001), pp. 49–59. 18. H.P. 5.1, ed. and trans. Russell and Konstan, p. 9. 19. Ibid. 20. H.P. 6.1, ed. and trans. Russell and Konstan, p. 13. 21. H.P. 40.2–4 , ed. and trans. Russell and Konstan, pp. 72–73. 22. H.P. 40.13, ed. and trans. Russell and Konstan, pp. 74–75. 23. H.P. 66.1, ed. and trans. Russell and Konstan, p. 105. 24. H.P. 66.7, ed. and trans. Russell and Konstan, p. 107. 25. H.P., ed. and trans. Russell and Konstan, p. 106, n.1. 26. H.P. 41.12, ed. Russell and Konstan, p. 77. 27. See Boys-Stones, Post-Hellenistic Philosophy, pp. 28–43. 28. KRS, no. 191. 184 184â•… notes to pages 124–135 Chapter 10 1. Aristotle was working from memory here and got it wrong. The episode actually involved Circe (Od. 12, 219–╉20), and the words are spoken by Odysseus to his crew. 2. Aristotle, N.E. 1149b, trans. Martin Ostwald (Indianapolis, IN: Bobbs-╉Merrill, 1962), p. 192. Aristotle is citing Il. 14, 214. 3. N.E. 1110a, trans. Ostwald, pp. 53–╉54. Alcmaeon may be a reference to Euripides’ play Alcmaeon in Psophis, of which a fragment survives. 4. Not to be confused with the later historian Dio Cassius. 5. Dio Chrysostom, Fourth Discourse, ed. and trans. W. Cohoon and H. L. Crosby, 5 vols., LCL (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1961–╉1971), 1:191–╉93. 6. Consistency was not one of Plutarch’s virtues. Plutarch shamelessly engaged in allegorizing in his essay Isis and Osiris. 7. Plutarch, On the Study of Poetry, trans. Russell and Winterbottom, p. 509. 8. Ibid. 9. On the Study of Poetry, trans. Russell and Winterbottom, p. 511. 10. Trans. Russell and Winterbottom, pp. 512–╉13. 11. Trans. Russell and Winterbottom, p. 513. 12. Trans, Russell and Winterbottom, p. 514. 13. Trans. Russell and Winterbottom, p. 516. 14. Lamberton, Homer the Theologian, p. 24. 15. See Jeffrey Beneker, “Plutarch and St. Basil as Readers of Greek Literature,” Syllecta Classica 5.22(1) (2010), 95–╉111. 16. Basil, “Address to Young Men,” in Saint Basil: The Letters, edited and translated by Roy Deferrari and Martin McGuire, 4 vols. LCL (London: William Heinemann and Cambridge, MA; Harvard University Press, 1934), 1:387. 17. Basil, “Address to Young Men,” Â�chapter 4, trans. Deferrari, 1:387–╉89. 18. Augustine Confessions 4.6, trans. Pine-╉Coffin (London: Penguin Books, 1961), p. 77. Chapter 11 1. Apuleius is credited with the Platonist tracts On the Daimon of Socrates and On the Teaching of Plato; the authenticity of the second is disputed. 2. Plato, Symposium, trans. William Hamilton (Harmondsworth, UK: Penguin Books, 1951), pp. 78–╉79. 3. See the famous example in Augustine, Confessions 8.12, trans. Pine-╉ Coffin, pp. 177–╉78 describing Augustine’s prompting by the voice of a child to open the Bible to a life-╉changing passage. 4. Not all scholars are agreed on treating “Cupid and Psyche” as an allegory. For an excellent history of the interpretation of the story, see Claudio Moreschini, Il mito di Amore e Psiche in Apuleio (Naples: M. D’Auria Editore, 1994), pp. 7–╉96. From Fulgentius (sixth century c.e.) through the Renaissance, readers understood the fable as a Platonic allegory. Dissent from this view is largely modern. 5. Plato, Phaedrus 250E, trans. R. Hackforth (Indianapolis, IN: Bobbs Merrill, 1952), p. 96. 6. Plato, Plato’s Phaedrus 246E, trans. Hackforth, p. 70. 185 notes to pages 136 –145 185 7. For a helpful introduction, see Robert Lamberton’s essay “The Neoplatonists and the Spiritualization of Homer,” in Homer’s Ancient Readers: The Hermeneutics of Greek Epic’s Earliest Exegetes, ed. Robert Lamberton and John Jay Keaney (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1992), pp. 115–33. 8. Odyssey 13, 102–12, trans. Robert Lamberton, in Porphyry on the Cave of the Nymphs (Barrytown, NY: Station Hill Press, 1983), p. 21. 9. Plotinus, Enneads 1.viii.14, trans. E. R. Dodds, Select Passages Illustrating Neoplatonism (Chicago: Ares Publishing, 1923), pp. 80–81. 10. Ibid. 11. Cave of the Nymphs 61, trans. Lamberton, p. 25. 12. Cave of the Nymphs 62, trans. Lamberton, p. 26. 13. Cave of the Nymphs 64, trans. Lamberton, p. 28. 14. Ibid. 15. Cave of the Nymphs 78, trans. Lamberton, p. 38. 16. Cave of the Nymphs 81, trans. Lamberton, p. 40. 17. Porphyry did not deny the existence of the cave; in fact, he asserted that it existed. See Brisson, How Philosophers Saved Myths, p. 84. 18. Cave of the Nymphs 76, trans. Lamberton, p. 37. 19. Tabula Cebetis 1–2, ed. and trans. John T. Fitzgerald and Michael White, The Tabula of Cebes (Chico, CA: Scholars Press, 1983), p. 61. 20. Plato, Phaedrus 246A, trans. Hackforth, p. 69. 21. C. S. Lewis, The Allegory of Love: A Study in Medieval Tradition (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 193), p. 45. 22. Angus Fletcher, Allegory: The Theory of a Symbolic Mode (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1964), p. 151. 23. For an excellent study of the life and thought of Martianus, see Danuta Shanzer, A Philosophical and Literary Commentary on Martianus Capella’s De nuptiis Philologiae et Mercurii Book 1 (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1986). 24. Lewis, Allegory of Love, p. 79. 25. Martianus Capella, The Marriage 2.165, trans. William Harris Stahl, in Martianus Capella and the Seven Liberal Arts, 2 vols. (New York: Columbia University Press, 1971), p. 55. 26. The Marriage 2.174–76, trans. Stahl, pp. 56–57. 27. The Marriage 2.181, trans. Stahl, p. 57. 28. The Marriage 2.135, trans. Stahl, pp. 47–48. 29. Ibid. 30. See Robert Lamberton, Proclus the Successor on Poetics and the Homeric Poems (Atlanta: Society of Biblical Literature, 2012), p. xxiii. Lamberton notes that he treats the same subjects in his commentary on the Timaeus and in his work Platonic Theology. 31. Konstan in H.P., ed. Russell and Konstan, p. xxiii. 32. I paraphrase the helpful schema laid out by Robert Lamberton, Proclus the Successor, pp. xxi–iii, but in reverse order. See the translation, pp. 259–61. 33. Proclus, Commentary on Plato’s Republic 1.40.4–6, translated in Lamberton, Homer the Theologian, pp. 172–73. 186 186â•… notes to pages 145–153 34. Proclus, Commentary on the Republic 1.77, translated in Homeric Problems, ed. Russell and Konstan, p. xxiii. Chapter 12 1. Momigliano, Alien Wisdom, p. 91, points out that “Longinus,” author of On the Sublime, was the first Greek to quote from Jewish scripture (first century c.e.). 2. On this subject one can do no better than read Henri Marrou’s A History of Education in Antiquity, trans. George Lamb (New York: Sheed and Ward, 1956), especially part III. 3. See Boys-╉Stones, Post-╉Hellenistic Philosophy, especially Â�chapter 6, “The Authority of Plato and Primitive Wisdom,” pp. 99–╉122. 4. Cited from Boys-╉Stones, Post-╉Hellenistic Philosophy, p. 107. 5. For a detailed account of the variations of the “dependency theme,” see Boys-╉ Stones, Post-╉Hellenistic Philosophy, Â�chapter 9, pp. 176–╉202. 6. Boys-╉Stones, Post-╉Hellenistic Philosophy, pp. 184–╉88. 7. Jaroslav Pelikan, What Has Athens to Do with Jerusalem?: Timaeus and Genesis in Counterpoint (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1997), p. 2. 8. See the articles by Henri Marrou and Pierre Courcelle in Arnoldo Momigliano, ed., The Conflict between Paganism and Christianity (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1963). 9. This is expressed most clearly in Plutarch’s On the Face of the Moon. See Dillon, The Middle Platonists, pp. 208–╉11. 10. See Kempe Algra, “Stoic Theology,” in The Cambridge Companion to the Stoics, ed. Brad Inwood (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2003), pp. 152–╉78, at pp. 74–╉76. 11. See Stephen Butler Murray: Reclaiming Divine Wrath: A History of a Christian Doctrine and Its Interpretation (Oxford: Oxford University Press, and New York: Peter Lang, 2011), especially Â�chapter 2, pp. 47–╉65. 12. Dawkins, The God Delusion, p. 51. It is rather unfortunate that this ancient debate was not referenced in Dawkins’s book. 13. See the clever defense of the doctrine of bodily resurrection by Augustine, City of God, book 13, Â�chapters 17–╉19, in which Plato is used to refute Plato. 14. For a comprehensive picture of his life, writings, and ideas see Dillon, The Middle Platonists, pp. 139–╉83. 15. Philo, On Providence 2.40–╉41, trans. in Lamberton, Homer the Theologian, p. 50. 16. Philo, On the Creation 54, trans. C. D. Yonge, The Works of Philo (Peabody, MA: Hendrickson Publishers, 1993), p. 22. 17. Philo, Questions and Answers on Genesis 1.6, ed. and trans. Ralph Marcus, LCL (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1953), pp. 4–╉5. Marcus’s translation is from the Armenian. 18. See Veyne, Did the Greeks Believe in Their Myths?, pp. 41–╉57. 19. See Pelikan, What Has Athens to do with Jerusalem?, pp. 25–╉26. 20. Philo, On the Creation of the World 4.18, trans. Yonge, p. 4; cf. Plato, Tim. 29. 21. Boys-╉Stones, Post-╉Hellenistic Philosophy, pp. 90–╉95, emphasizes Philo’s debt to the Stoic tradition, and notes passages where Philo considers Greek learning inferior to Jewish. But one cannot fail to be impressed by Philo’s reverence for Plato’s theory 187 notes to pages 153–162 187 of ideas and his insistence that Plato’s teachings are congruent with the Torah in the opening pages of On the Creation of the World. 22. Momigliano, Alien Wisdom, pp. 115–16. 23. Philo, On the Creation of the World 14.43–4 4, trans. Yonge, p. 7. 24. Origen, On First Principles 4.3.1, trans. Rowan A. Greer (Mahwah, NJ: Paulist Press, 1979), p. 189. 25. Origen, Contra Celsum 1.42 ad fin., trans. Owen Chadwick (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1953), pp. 139–40. 26. Ibid. 27. Origen, Contra Celsum 1.17, trans. Chadwick, p. 19. 28. Origen, On First Principles 4.3.4, trans. Greer, p. 192. 29. On First Principles 4.3.1, trans. Greer, p. 189. 30. On First Principles 4.3.2, trans. Greer, p. 190. 31. On First Principles 4.2.4, trans. Greer, p. 182. 32. See the detailed exposé and critique of this development by Henri de Lubac, Exégèse médiévale: Les quatre sens de l’écriture, vol. 1 (Lyon: Aubier, 1959), pp. 198–219. 33. Augustine, Confessions 1.14. 34. Augustine, On Christian Doctrine 2.12 (17), trans. Robertson, p. 45. 35. For Clement and the classics, see David Dawson, Allegorical Readers and Cultural Revision in Ancient Alexandria (Berkeley, Los Angeles, and Oxford: University of California Press, 1992), pp. 199–205. 36. Clement, Exhortation to the Greeks, The Rich Man’s Salvation, To the Newly Baptized, ed. and trans. G. W. Buttersworth. LCL (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press; London: William Heinemann, 1982), pp. 51–53. 37. Ibid. 38. Clement, Exhortation, trans. Buttersworth, p. 33. 39. Exhortation, trans. Buttersworth, p. 65. 40. Augustine, On Christian Doctrine 2.17 (27), trans. Robertson, pp. 53–54. 41. On Christian Doctrine 2.40 (60), trans. Robertson, p. 75. 42. For Augustine’s possible debt to an Aristotelian concept of sign, see Karla Pollmann, Doctrina Christiana: Untersuchungen zu den Anfängen der christlichen Hermeneutik unter besonderer Berücksichtigung von Augustinus, De doctrina christiana (Freiburg, Switzerland: Universitätsverlag, 1996), pp. 195–96. 43. Augustine, On Christian Doctrine 1.2, trans. Robertson, pp. 8–9. 44. On Christian Doctrine 2.10 (15), trans. Robertson, p. 43. 45. The distinction is discussed by David Dawson, “Sign Theory, Allegorical Reading, and the Motions of the Soul in De doctrina christiana,” in De doctrina christiana: A Classic of Western Culture, ed. Duane W. H. Arnold and Pamela Bright (Notre Dame and London: University of Notre Dame Press, 1995), pp. 123–41. 46. Augustine, On Christian Doctrine 3.10 (14), trans. Robertson, pp. 87–88. 47. On Christian Doctrine 3.22 (32), trans. Robertson, p. 98. 48. Augustine, On the City of God 13.21, trans. Bettenson, p. 535. 49. On the City of God 1.14, trans. Bettenson, pp. 23–24. 188 188â•… notes to pages 166 –169 Chapter 13 1. See the complaint of Cassiodorus in the preface to book 1 of his Divine and Human Readings, trans. Leslie Webber Jones, in An Introduction to Divine and Human Readings by Cassiodorus Senator (New York: Octagon Books, 1966), p. 67. 2. Pelagius, “Letter to Demetrias” 16.1, trans. B. R. Rees, in The Letters of Pelagius and His Followers (Woodbridge, UK: Boydell and Brewer, 1991), p. 227. 3. Augustine, On Christian Doctrine 1.39, trans. Robertson, p. 32. 4. On Christian Doctrine, book 1, chapter Â� 36, trans. Robertson, p. 40. 5. Augustine, City of God, book 15, Â�chapters 22–╉23, trans. Bettenson. 6. There have a number of important studies of the interpretation of classical myths in the later Middle Ages and Renaissance; however, much remains to be done for the period between ca. 500 and the early twelfth century. For a sketch of the history of the post-╉classical myth exegesis in the Middle Ages, see Herren, “Classical Exegesis” (cit. Preface, n. 1), especially pp. 88–╉95. I am planning a book-╉length study of this development up to and including the twelfth century. 189 Bibliography (LCL indicates Loeb Classical Library bilingual editions) Texts and Translations Arnim, Hans Friedrich August von, ed. Stoicorum veterum fragmenta. 4 vols. Leipzig: Teubner, 1900–1910 [reprint 1960–1969]. Bettenson, Henry, trans. St. Augustine Concerning the City of God against the Pagans. London: Penguin Books, 1984. Brown, Norman. O., trans. Theogony. By Hesiod. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall, 1953. Brunt, P. A., and J. M. Moore, eds. and trans. Res gestae divi Augusti. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1967. Bury, R. G., ed. and trans. Sextus Empiricus against the Professors. LCL, vol. 3. London: William Heinemann; New York: G. P. Putnam’s Sons, 1933. Buttersworth, G. W., ed. and trans. Exhortation to the Greeks; The Rich Man’s Salvation; To the Newly Baptized. By Clement of Alexandria. LCL. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press; London: William Heinemann, 1982. Chadwick, Owen, trans. Contra Celsum: Translated with an Introduction. By Origen. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1953. Cohoon, W., and H. L. Crosby, ed. and trans. Dio Chrysostom. LCL, 5 vols. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1961–1971. Copley, Frank O., trans. On the Nature of Things. By Lucretius. New York: W. W. Norton & Co., 1977. Curd, Patricia. Anaxagoras of Clazomene: Fragments and Testimonia: A Text and Translation with Notes and Essays. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2007. De Sélincourt, Aubrey. Histories. By Herodotus. Harmondsworth, UK: Penguin Books, 1965. 190 190 bibliogr aphy Deferrari, Roy, and Martin McGuire, ed. and trans. Saint Basil: The Letters. 4 vols. LCL. London: William Heinemann; Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1934. Diels, Hermann. Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker: Griechisch und deutsch. Edited by Walther Kranz. 12th ed. Dublin and Zürich: Weidmann, 1966. Dodds, E. R. Select Passages Illustrating Neoplatonism. Chicago: Ares Publishing, 1923. Dombart, Bernardus, and Alphonsus Kalb, eds. Sancti Aurelii Augustini episcopi Hipponensis de civitate Dei libri XXII. Corpus Christianorum Series Latina 47. Turnhout, Belgium: Brepols, 1955. Evelyn-White, Hugh G. Hesiod, the Homeric Hymns and Homerica. LCL. London and Cambridge MA: William Heinemann Ltd and Harvard University Press, 1967. Fitzgerald, John T., and L. Michael White, ed. and trans. The Tabula of Cebes. Chico, CA: Scholars Press, 1983. Fowler, Robert L., ed. Early Greek Mythography. Vol. 1: Text and Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000. Fowler, Robert L., ed. Early Greek Mythography. Vol. II. Commentary. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013. Fuller, Edmund, ed. “Life of Theseus.” In Lives of the Noble Greeks. A Selection. New York: Dell Publishing, 1968. Fyfe, W. Hamilton, ed. and trans. Aristotle: The Poetics. LCL. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 1965. Görgemanns, Herwig, and Heinrich Karp, eds. and trans. Origenis de principiis libri IV/ Origenes vier Bücher von den Prinzipien. Darmstadt, Germany: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, 1976. Graham, Daniel W. The Texts of Early Greek Philosophy: The Complete Fragments and Selected Testimonies of the Major Presocratics. Part I. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2010. Greer, Rowan A., trans. An Exhortation to Martyrdom, Prayer and Selected Works. By Origen. Mahwah, NJ: Paulist Press, 1979. Hackforth, R. Plato’s Phaedrus. Indianapolis, IN: Bobbs Merrill, 1952. Hamilton, William. Symposium. By Plato. Harmondsworth, UK: Penguin Books, 1951. Helm, Rudolf, ed. Fabii Planciadis Fulgentii V.C. Opera. Leipzig: Teubner, 1898; rept. Stuttgart, 1975. Herren, Michael W., ed. and trans. The Cosmography of Aethicus Ister: Edition, Translation and Commentary. Turnhout, Belgium: Brepols, 2011. Jacoby, Felix. Die Fragmente der griechischen Historiker. [Reprinted with additions and corrections]. 13 vols. Leiden, The Netherlands: Brill, 1957. Jones, Horace Leonard, ed. and trans. The Geography of Strabo. LCL, 5 vols. London: Heinemann, 1917–1933. Jones, Leslie Webber Jones, trans. An Introduction to Divine and Human Readings by Cassiodorus Senator. New York: Octagon Books, 1966. Jones, W. H. S., ed. and trans. Pausanias Descriptions of Greece. 5 vols. LCL 93-97. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, repr. 1931. Jowett, Benjamin, trans. Timaeus. By Plato. Indianapolis, IN: Bobbs Merrill, 1949. Keaney, J. J., and Robert Lamberton, eds. and trans. Essay on the Life and Poetry of Homer. By Plutarch. Atlanta: Scholars Press, 1996. 191 bibliogr aphy 191 King, Peter, trans. Against the Academicians and The Teacher. By Augustine. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing, 1995. Kirk, G. S., J. E. Raven, and M. Schofield. The Presocratic Philosophers: A Critical History with a Selection of Texts. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1983. Lamberton, Robert, trans. Porphyry on the Cave of the Nymphs. Barrytown, NY: Station Hill Press, 1983. Lamberton, Robert, trans. Proclus the Successor on Poetics and the Homeric Poems. Atlanta: Society of Biblical Literature, 2012. Lattimore, Richmond, trans. The Iliad of Homer. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1961. Lesher, J. H. Xenophanes of Colophon: Fragments; A Text and Translation with a Commentary. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1992. Lindsay, W. M., ed. Isidori Hispalensis episcopi etymologiarum sive originum libri XX. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1911. Long, H. S., ed. Diogenes Laertius Vitae Philosophorum. 2 vols. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1964. Marchant, E. C., ed. and trans. Xenophon Memorabilia. LCL, 7 vols., Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press; London: William Heinemann, 1923. Marcus, Ralph, ed. and trans. Philo, Questions and Answers on Genesis. LCL. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1953. Martin, Joseph, ed. De doctrina christiana Libri IV. Corpus Christianorum 34. Turnhout, Belgium: Brepols, 1952. McGregor, C. P., trans. The Nature of the Gods. By Cicero. Harmondsworth, UK: Penguin Books, 1972. McKeon, Richard, ed. and trans. The Basic Works of Aristotle New York: The Modern Library, 2001. Nesselrath, Heinz- Günther, ed. and trans. Die griechischen Götter: Ein Überblick über Namen, Bilder, und Deuthungen. By Cornutus. Scripta Antiquitata Posterioris ad Ethicam Religionemque Pertinentia. Tübingen, Germany: Mohr Siebeck. 2009. Ostwald, Martin, trans. Nicomachaen Ethics. By Aristotle. Indianapolis, IN: Bobbs-Merrill, 1962. Perrin, Bernadette, ed. and trans. Plutarch, Life of Theseus. LCL. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1959. Pine-Coffin, R. S., trans. Saint Augustine Confessions. London: Penguin Books, 1961. Rees, B. R. The Letters of Pelagius and His Followers. Woodbridge, UK: Boydell and Brewer, 1991. Robertson, D. W., Jr., trans. On Christian Doctrine. By Augustine. The Library of the Liberal Arts. Indianapolis, IN; New York: Bobbs-Merrill, 1958. Robinson, T. M., trans. Heraclitus: Fragments; A Text and Translation with a Commentary. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1987. Russell, D. A., and David Konstan, eds. and trans. Heraclitus: Homeric Problems. Atlanta: Society of Biblical Literature, 2005. Russell, D. A., and Michael Winterbottom, eds. and trans. Ancient Literary Criticism: The Principal Texts in Translation. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1972. Shorey, Paul, ed. and trans. Plato: Republic, LCL. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1963. 192 192 bibliogr aphy Stahl, William Harris, trans. Macrobius Commentary on the Dream of Scipio. New York: Columbia University Press, 1952. Stahl, William Harris, trans. Martianus Capella and the Seven Liberal Arts. 2 vols. New York: Columbia University Press, 1971. Stocks, J. L., trans. “On the Heavens.” In Basic Works of Aristotle. Ed. and trans. McKeon. Ventris, Michael, and John Chadwick. Documents in Mycenaean Greek. 2nd ed. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1973. Walzer, R., ed. Galen on Jews and Christians. London: Oxford University Press, 1949. West, M. L., ed. Iambi et elegi ante Alexandrum cantati. Oxford Clarendon Press, 1971–72. West, M. L., trans. and ed. Theogony: Edited with Prolegomena and Commentary. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1966. Yonge, C. D., trans. The Works of Philo. Peabody, MA: Hendrickson Publishers, 1993. Secondary Works Algra, Kempe. “Stoic Theology.” In The Cambridge Companion to the Stoics. Edited by Brad Inwood, pp. 152–78. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2003. Asmis, Elizabeth. “Epicurean Poetics.” In Philodemus and Poetry: Poetic Theory and Practice in Lucretius, Philodemus, and Horace. Edited by Dirk Obbink, pp. 15–34. New York: Oxford University Press, 1995. Asmis, Elizabeth. “What Is Anaximander’s ‘Apeiron?’” Journal of the History of Philosophy 19.3 (July 1981), 279–97. Barnes, Jonathan. Early Greek Philosophy. London: Penguin Books, 1987. Barnes, Jonathan. The Presocratic Philosophers. London: Routledge, 1982. Beneker, Jeffrey. “Plutarch and St. Basil as Readers of Greek Literature.” Syllecta Classica 5.22(1) (2010), 95–111. Boys-Stones, G. R. Post-Hellenistic Philosophy: A Study of Its Development from the Stoics to Origen. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001. Boys-Stones, G. R., ed. Metaphor, Allegory, and the Classical Tradition: Ancient Thought and Modern Revisions. Oxford: University Press, 2003. Bremmer, Jan N. Bremmer. “Atheism in Antiquity.” In The Cambridge Companion to Atheism. Edited by Michael Martin. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2007, pp. 12–32. Brisson, Luc. How Philosophers Saved Myths: Allegorical Interpretation and Classical Mythology. Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press, 2004. Brisson, Luc. Plato the Mythmaker. Translated by Gerard Naddaf. Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press, 1998. Bultmann, Rudolf. Jesus Christ and Mythology. London: SCM Press, 1960. Burkert, Walter. Greek Religion. Translated by John Raffan. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1985. Burkert, Walter. “Hesiod in Context: Abstractions and Divinities in an Aegean-Eastern Koiné.” In Personification in the Greek World: From Antiquity to Byzantium. Edited by Emma Stafford and Judith Herrin, pp. 3–20. Aldershot, UK: Ashgate, 2005. 193 bibliogr aphy 193 Burkert, Walter. The Orientalizing Revolution: Near Eastern Influence on Greek Culture in the Early Archaic Age. Translated by Margaret E. Pinder and Walter Burkert. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1992. Cambridge-Pickard, A. W. “Tragedy, Greek.” In Oxford Classical Dictionary. 2nd ed. Edited by N. G. L. Hammond and H. H. Scullard. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1970. Cameron, Alan. Greek Mythography in the Roman World. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004. Cameron, Alan. The Last Pagans of Rome. New York: Oxford University Press, 2011. Cary, George. The Medieval Alexander. Edited by D. J. A. Ross. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1956. Chadwick, John. The Decipherment of Linear B. 2nd ed. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1960. Chantraine, Pierre. Dictionnaire étymologique de la langue grecque. Rev. ed. Paris: Klincksieck, 2009. Cherniss, Harold. Aristotle’s Criticism of Presocratic Philosophy. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins Press, 1935; rept. Octagon Books, 1971. Cornford, F. M. Plato’s Cosmology: The Timaeus of Plato Translated with a Running Commentary. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul Ltd., 1937. Cornford, F. M. From Religion to Philosophy. New York: Harper Torchbooks, 1957. Coulter, James A. The Literary Microcosm: Theories of Interpretation of the Later Neoplatonists. Leiden, The Netherlands: E. J. Brill, 1976. Dawkins, Richard. The God Delusion. New York: Mariner, Books, 2008. Dawson, David. Allegorical Readers and Cultural Revision in Ancient Alexandria. Berkeley, Los Angeles, and Oxford: University of California Press, 1992. Dawson, David. “Sign Theory, Allegorical Reading, and the Motions of the Soul in De doctrina christiana.” In De doctrina christiana: A Classic of Western Culture. Edited by Duane W. H. Arnold and Pamela Bright. Notre Dame and London: University of Notre Dame Press, 1995. De Hamel, Christopher. The Book: A History of the Bible. London: Phaidon Press, Ltd., 2001. Dillon, John. The Middle Platonists: A Study of Platonism. London: Duckworth, 1977. Dorson, Richard M. “The Eclipse of Solar Mythology.” In Myth: A Symposium. Edited by Thomas A. Sebeok, pp. 25–63. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, 1968. Drachmann, A. B. Atheism in Pagan Antiquity. London: Gyldendal, 1922; rept. Chicago: Ares Publishers, 1977. Eliade, Mircea. The Sacred and the Profane. New York and London: Harcourt Brace, 1959. Fletcher, Angus. Allegory: The Theory of a Symbolic Mode. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1964. Ford, Andrew. Aristotle as Poet: The Song for Hermias and Its Contexts. New York: Oxford University Press, 2011. Frye, Northrop. The Great Code: The Bible and Literature. Toronto: Penguin Books, 1990. Gerson, P. P. Gods and Greek Philosophy: Studies in the Early History of Natural Theology. London and New York, 1990. Goody, Jack. The Interface between the Written and the Oral. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1967, rept. 1987. 194 194 bibliogr aphy Guthrie, W. K. C. The Greeks and Their Gods. Boston: Beacon Press, 1950. Guthrie, W. K. C. In the Beginning: Some Greek Views on the Origins of Life and the Early State of Man. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1957. Harris, William V. Ancient Literacy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1989. Havelock, Ellis. The Oral and the Written Word: A Reappraisal. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1982. Herren, Michael W. “Classical Allegoresis—from Theagenes of Rhegium to Bernard Silvester. Florilegium 30 (2013 [2015]), 59–102. Herren, Michael W. “Classics in the Middle Ages.” Oxford Bibliographies Online. New York: Oxford University Press, 2014. Herren, Michael (W.). “The Cosmography of Aethicus Ister and Ancient Travel Literature.” In The World of Travellers: Exploration and Imagination. Edited by Kees Dekker, Karin Olsen, and Tette Hofstra, pp. 5–30. Leuven, Belgium: Peeters, 2009. Hitchens, Christopher. God Is Not Great: How Religion Poisons Everything. Toronto: McClelland and Stewart Ltd., 2007. Hornblower, Simon, Antony Spawforth, and Esther Eidinow, eds. Oxford Classical Dictionary. 3rd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005. Hyland, Drew A. The Origins of Philosophy: Its Rise in Myth and the Pre-Socratics. Amherst, NY: Humanity Books, 1998. Inwood, Brad, ed. The Cambridge Companion to Stoicism. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2003. Jaeger, Werner. The Theology of the Early Greek Philosophers. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1947. Jones, J. W., Jr. “Allegorical Interpretation in Servius.” Classical Journal 56 (1960– 1961), 216–26. Kirk, G. S. Homer and the Epic: A Shortened Version of “The Song of Homer.” Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1965. Kirk, G. S. Myth: Its Meaning and Function in Ancient and Other Cultures. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press; Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973. Lamberton, Robert. Homer the Theologian: Neoplatonist Allegorical Reading and the Growth of the Epic Tradition. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1989. Lamberton, Robert. “The Neoplatonists and the Spiritualization of Homer.” In Homer’s Ancient Readers: The Hermeneutics of Greek Epic’s Earliest Exegetes. Edited by Robert Lamberton and John J. Keaney, pp. 115–33. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1992. Lapidge, Michael. “Stoic Cosmology.” In The Stoics. Edited by J. Rist, pp. 161–85. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1978. Lef kowitz, Mary R. Euripides and the Gods. New York: Oxford University Press, 2016. Lef kowitz, Mary R. Women in Greek Myth, 2nd ed. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press, 2007. Lévi-Strauss, Claude. Myth and Meaning. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1978. Lévi-Strauss, Claude. “The Structural Study of Myth.” In Myth: A Symposium. Edited by Thomas A. Sebeok, pp. 81–106. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, 1968. 195 bibliogr aphy 195 Lewis, C. S. The Allegory of Love: A Study in Medieval Tradition. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1936. Lloyd, G. E. R. Magic, Reason and Experience: Studies in the Origin and Development of Greek Science. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1979. Long, A. A. Greek Models of Mind and Self. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2015. Long, A. A. Hellenistic Philosophy: Stoics, Epicureans, Sceptics. London: Duckworth, 1974. Long, A. A. “Stoic Readers of Homer.” In Homer’s Ancient Readers: The Hermeneutics of Greek Epic’s Earliest Exegetes. Edited by Robert Lamberton and John J. Keaney, pp. 41–66. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1992. Long, A. A. “The Stoics on World-Conflagration and Everlasting Recurrence.” In From Epicurus to Epictetus. Edited by A. A. Long, pp. 256–82. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2006. Lord, A. B. The Singer of Tales. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1960. Lubac, Henri de. L’exégèse médiévale: Les quatres sens de l’écriture. 3 vols. Lyon: Éditions Montaigne, 1959. Macey, David. The Penguin Dictionary of Critical Theory. London: Penguin, 2000. Marrou, Henri. A History of Education in Antiquity. Translated by George Lamb. New York: Sheed and Ward, 1956. Mayor, Adrienne. The Amazons: Lives and Legends of Warrior Women across the Ancient World. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2014. Momigliano, Arnaldo. Alien Wisdom: The Limits of Hellenism. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1975. Momigliano, Arnaldo, ed. The Conflict between Paganism and Christianity in the Fourth Century. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1963. Moreschini, Claudio. Il mito di Amore e Psiche in Apuleio. Naples: D’Auria Editore, 1994. Most, Glenn. “Cornutus and Stoic Allegoresis: A Preliminary Report.” Aufstieg und Niedergang der römischen Welt 2.36.3 (1988), pp. 2014–65. Murray, Gilbert. Five Stages of Greek Religion. New York: Doubleday Anchor, 1951. Murray, Stephen Butler. Reclaiming Divine Wrath: A History of a Christian Doctrine and Its Interpretation. Oxford: Oxford University Press; New York: Peter Lang, 2011. Mylonas, George E. Eleusis and the Eleusinian Mysteries. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1961. Nagy, Gregory. Homer the Preclassic. Berkeley, Los Angeles, and London: University of California Press, 2010. Nicholson, Adam. God’s Secretaries: The Making of the King James Bible. New York: HarperCollins Publishers, Inc., 2003. Obbink, Dirk. “Allegory and Exegesis in the Derveni Papyri.” In Metaphor, Allegory, and the Classical Tradition. Edited by G. R. Boys-Stones, pp. 177–88. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003. Obbink, Dirk. “The Atheism of Epicurus.” Greek, Roman, and Byzantine Studies 30 (1989), 187–223. Ong, Walter J. Orality and Literacy: The Technologizing of the Word. London and New York: Routledge, 2002. 196 196 bibliogr aphy Parry, Milman. The Making of Homeric Verse: The Collected Writings of Milman Parry. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1971. Parterie, Catalin, ed. Plato: Selected Myths. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004. Pelikan, Jaroslav. What Has Athens to Do with Jerusalem?: Timaeus and Genesis in Counterpoint. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1997. Pépin, Jean. Mythe et allégorie: Les origines grecques et les contestations judéo-chrétiennes. Paris: Études augustiniennes, 1976. Pollmann, Karla. Doctrina Christiana: Untersuchungen zu den Anfängen der christlichen Hermeneutik unter besonderer Berücksichtigung von Augustinus De doctrina christiana. Freiburg, Switzerland: Universitätsverlag, 1996. Pratt, Louise H. Lying and Poetry from Homer to Pindar: Falsehood and Deception in Archaic Greek Poetics. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1993. Puhvel, Jaan. Comparative Mythology. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1987. Reynolds, L. D., and Nigel Wilson. Scribes and Scholars. 2nd ed. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1974. Rist, John, ed. The Stoics. Berkeley, Los Angeles, and London: University of California Press, 1978. Romm, James S. The Edges of the Earth in Ancient Thought. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1992. Röscher, W. H. Lexikon der griechischen und römischen Mythologie. Leipzig: Teuber, 1884–1893. Seel, Otto. “Antike und frühchristliche Allegorik.” Festschrift für Peter Metz. Edited by Ursula Schlegel and Claus Jorge von Worteuffel, pp. 11–45. Berlin: W. de Gruyter, 1965. Shanzer, Danuta. A Philosophical and Literary Commentary on Martianus Capella’s De nuptiis Philologiae et Mercurii Book 1. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1986. Snell, Bruno. The Discovery of the Mind: The Greek Origins of European Thought. Translated by T. G. Rosenmeyer. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1953. Stanford, W. B. Enemies of Poetry. London, Boston, and Henley: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1980. Stanford, W. B. The Ulysses Theme: A Study in the Adaptability of a Traditional Hero. Oxford: Blackwell, 1963. Tate, J. “The Beginnings of Greek Allegory.” Classical Review 41 (1927), 214–15. Tate, J. “On the History of Allegorism.” Classical Quarterly 28 (1934), 105–14. Tate, J. “Plato and Allegorical Interpretation.” Classical Quarterly 23 (1925), 142–54. Taylor, J. E. “The New Atheists.” In the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2010; peer- reviewed: http://w ww.iep.utm.edu/n-athei. Veyne, Paul. Did the Greeks Believe in Their Myths?: An Essay on the Constitutive Imagination. Translated by Paula Wissing. Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press, 1988. Walzer, R. Galen on Jews and Christians. London: Oxford University Press, 1949. Webster, T. B. L. “Personification as a Mode of Greek Thought.” Journal of the Warburg and Courtauld Institutes 17 (1954), 10–21. West, M. L. Early Greek Philosophy and the Orient. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1971. West, M. L. The Orphic Poems. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1988. 197 bibliogr aphy 197 Whitman, Jon. Allegory: The Dynamics of an Ancient and Medieval Technique. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1987. Whitman, Jon, ed. Interpretation and Allegory: Antiquity to the Modern Period. Leiden, The Netherlands: Brill, 2003. Whitmarsh, Tim. Battling the Gods: Atheism in the Ancient World. New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 2015. Ziolkowski, Jan. “Old Wives’ Tales: Classicism and Anti-Classicism from Apuleius to Chaucer.” The Journal of Medieval Latin 12 (2002), 90–113. 198 199 Glossary of Names and Terms Academy: School of philosophy founded by Plato (see) at Athens. Achaeans: Name of people from region of Achaea, generalized to mean “Greeks” by Homer. Also used in Egyptian sources as a name for the Greeks. Achilles: Greek warrior at Troy, hero of Homer’s Iliad. Famous for his strength and bravery, but also for his impetuosity. Aeneas: Trojan warrior who appears in the Iliad. Refashioned by Vergil (see) as hero of the epic Aeneid, founder of the future Rome. Aeneid: Latin epic poem by Vergil (see). Deals with the escape of the Trojan remnant from Troy, dangers encountered on their wanderings, the romance of Aeneas and Phoenician queen Dido, and the long war in Italy ending in Trojan victory and settlement in the future Rome. Aesopian fable: Type of fable in which animals are given human characteristics, leading to a moral or generalization about human character. Origin ascribed to Aesop of Samos (6th century b.c.e.). Agamemnon: King of the Achaeans (see), leader of the Greek expedition against Troy in the Iliad. See also Trojan War. Alexander the Great (356–323 b.c.e.): Son of Philip II, king of Macedon. Tutored by Aristotle (see). Liberated the Greek cities of Asia Minor from Persian rule as well as cities of the Levant and Egypt, finally smashing the Persian Empire itself. Alexander’s conquests extended into India. In 331 he founded Alexandria. allegoresis: Modern literary term signifying the interpretation of a work as allegorically composed. Introduced to distinguish between act of writing allegory and that of judging works to be composed allegorically (interpretation); see allegory. 200 200 glossary of names and terms allegory: “To say or mean something different,” i.e., from what one appears to be saying. Term applied in antiquity both to the writing of an allegory and interpretation of a work as allegory. See also allegoresis, hyponoia. Amazons: Legendary female warriors living around the Black Sea. They are connected to the sagas of important heroes, including Hercules, Theseus, and the mythicized Alexander. Ammonius Saccas (3rd century c.e.): Teacher of Origen (see) and Plotinus (see) at Alexandria and generally regarded as the founder of Neoplatonism (see). anankē: Literally, “necessity”; by extension refers to the laws of nature or nature itself in the writings of the physical philosophers. Anaxagoras of Clazomenae (ca. 500–ca. 428 b.c.e.): Educated in Ionia, migrated to Athens, where he taught philosophy. Hypothesized that all things existed in a jumble in the beginning, becoming separated when Mind disassociated itself and instigated the cosmic whirl. Charged and convicted as atheos (see), but escaped punishment. Anaximander (b. 610 b.c.e.): Successor to Thales (see) as head of the Milesian school (see); authored the notion of the apeiron (see); also held evolutionist notions of the origin of humans and animals. Anaximenes (6th century b.c.e.): Successor to Anaximander (see) in Miletus; reverted to the monism of Thales. Posited air as the archē; even the gods are made of air and come from air. Antisthenes (ca. 455– ca. 360 c.e.): Disciple of Socrates. Regarded as founder of Cynicism (see Cynicism, philosophical). Believed etymology an important tool for understanding philosophical truths. apathēs: Literally, “without suffering.” Concept frequently applied to God or the gods, who, being immutable, do not experience emotions, particularly anger. apeiron: Literally, “without limit, boundless.” Used as a noun by Anaximander to designate an infinite undefined material substance out of which all things are made. Aphrodite (Venus): In mythology, goddess responsible for inciting sexual desire. According to Hesiod, she was born of the foam (aphros) spilling from the severed penis of Ouranos. apocryphal: From a Greek word meaning “hidden” or “obscure.” Term used to reference literature not sanctioned by the Jewish community or by Christians. Apollo: In mythology, son of Zeus and Latona; god associated with the arts (particularly music and lyre playing), prophecy, archery, and medicine. Epithet Phoebus associates him with the sun. apologist/apologete: One who defends a particular philosophical or religious movement from its attackers; term frequently applied to defenders of Christianity against pagan attacks. 201 glossary of names and terms 201 Apuleius (2nd century c.e.): North African novelist and philosopher; author of the novel Metamorphoses (aka The Golden Ass) and treatises on Platonism. archē: First principle or origin of things that exist. The Ionian philosophers (see) posited a single element (water, air, fire) as the archē in the belief that everything was reducible to one substance. See also monism. Ares (Mars): In mythology, the god of war. Aristobulus of Panaeas (2nd century b.c.e.): Jewish Platonist philosopher at Alexandria, who interpreted the scriptures allegorically. Aristophanes (450–ca. 385 b.c.e.): Athenian playwright, who wrote satirical plays on topical issues such as Athenian politics, religious beliefs, and literary criticism. Aristotle (383–322 b.c.e.): Philosopher. B. Macedon, served as tutor to Alexander the Great. Studied with Plato, later founded the school of Peripatetic philosophy (see Peripatetics). Wrote treatises on ethics, politics, poetics, rhetoric, logic, biology, physics, astronomy, metaphysics, and psychology, setting the parameters of these subjects for the ancient and medieval worlds. asebeia: “Impiety”; show of disrespect to religious images or rituals. Punishable by death in Athens in the 5th and 4th centuries c.e. asōmaton: Literally, “without a body.” Term designates nonmaterial substances such as numbers. ataraxia: “Without perturbation, calmness.” Describes the Epicurean ideal of happiness: freedom from pain in the body and in the soul. See Epicureanism. Athena: In mythology, goddess born from head of Zeus. Connected to warfare, but also to wisdom and the arts and crafts. Allegorized as reason (logos) by Porphyry (see) and others. atheos: Literally, “without god, godless.” In antiquity, applied to a range of beliefs and attitudes, including disbelief in mythology and acceptance of natural causes for phenomena to the exclusion of the divine or supernatural. atomism: Greek theory that matter is composed of invisible particles called “atoms” (see atomos) that move in the void and collide with one another to form objects. Atoms are eternal, and there is an infinite number of worlds. atomos: Literally, “without cutting.” In Greek atomic theory, refers to the smallest unit of matter, which cannot be divided further. Augustine, St. (354–430 c.e.): Philosopher and Christian theologian. Born and educated in North Africa, taught rhetoric in Rome and Milan; later bishop of Hippo Regius (Algeria). Made important contributions to sign theory and biblical exegesis. Defined Christian orthodoxy for the Latin West. Babylonian Creation Story/Enuma Elish: “When on High.”. Work describing the origin of existence in the sluggish watery principles Tiamat (female) and Apsu 202 202 glossary of names and terms (male). They were overthrown by the god Marduk, who created the cosmos out of the carcass of Tiamat, then made the first humans from the body of Tiamat’s vizier, Kingu. Basil of Caesarea, St. (ca. 330–379 c.e.): Monastic founder and theologian. B. Caesarea in Cappadocia (Turkey), later bishop there. Exegesis of scripture favors figurative interpretation. Author of “Address to Young Men on How They Might Derive Benefit from Greek Literature.” Berkeley, George (1685–1753 c.e.): Anglo-Irish philosopher who professed “immaterialism,” which holds that in order for something to exist it must be perceived. Boccaccio, Giovanni (1313–1375 c.e.): Italian humanist; wrote treatise On the Genealogy of the Gods, which defends pagan poetry on the ground that it is composed as allegory (see). Cadmus: In mythology, son of the Phoenician king Agenor. Slew a serpent that was the offspring of Ares (see); sowed its teeth on the advice of Athena (see). From them sprang the “Sown Men,” who fought one another, leaving only five survivors, who became founders of Thebes. Cadmus said to have introduced writing from Phoenicia to Greece. Callimachus (ca. 305–ca. 240 b.c.e.): Poet and literary critic active at Alexandria. To him is ascribed the saying “a big book is a big evil.” Celsus (2nd century c.e.): Anti-Christian polemicist rebutted by Origen in Against Celsus. C. influenced by Platonism and the Stoic idea of an original wisdom. centaurs: Mythical creatures comprising the heads and torsos of men and the bodies of horses. Chaos/chaos: One of Hesiod’s first “gods” to come into being. Name probably means the “gap”—the space needed to enable things to move. Later meanings are “jumble” or “confusion.” Cicero (106–43 b.c.e.): Roman orator, politician, and philosopher. Wrote treatises summarizing earlier Greek philosophical positions and preserving portions of writings now lost. Chrysippus (ca. 280–207 b.c.e.): Stoic philosopher; succeeded Cleanthes (see) as head of the school. Credited with elaborating earlier Stoic doctrine, especially with regard to logic and theory of knowledge. Established Stoic orthodoxy. Cleanthes (331–232 b.c.e.): Stoic philosopher; succeeded Zeno (see) as head of school. Laid special stress on ethics. Regarded the world (cosmos) as a living being and the sun as its ruler. Clement of Alexandria (2nd century c.e.): Christian theologian and apologist. Wrote a treatise addressed to pagans on the foolishness of pagan beliefs. His Stromata aimed at synthesis of Greek philosophy and Christian teaching. Commentaries on the Dream of Scipio: Work by Macrobius (see). Neoplatonist compendium of myth criticism, dream interpretation, soul theory, astronomy, and music theory. 203 glossary of names and terms 203 Cornutus (1st century c.e.): Philosopher and literary scholar. Born in Libya, active in Rome, wrote in both Greek and Latin. Preserved Stoic tradition of myth interpretation in his Epidrome (“Summary of Traditions according to Greek Theology”). Cratylus (5th century b.c.e.): Contemporary of Socrates. Ascribed the theory that words are linked to their referents by natural association, so that one can infer the meaning of a word from its sound. creationism: The doctrine, both ancient and modern, that a god or supernatural being created the world (universe). Critias (ca. 460–403 b.c.e.): Athenian politician and playwright. Ascribed the satyr play Sisyphus, which contains an explanation of the origin of the gods as bogeys invented by a statesman to instill fear in the citizens. Cyclops: In mythology, monstrous humanoid with a single eye in the middle of the forehead; reputed for cannibalism and lawlessness in Odyssey 9. Cynicism, philosophical: Not a school, but a loosely organized sect. Most famous exponent was Diogenes of Sinope (ca. 400–ca. 325 b.c.e.), who preached that happiness attained by limiting desires to the most basic needs. Ideal of life is attainment of self-sufficiency (autarkeia). Daedalus: In mythology, the master craftsman of Crete (name connected to Greek adjective meaning “skillfully wrought”). In the Theseus saga, D. the architect of the labyrinth and builder of wooden cow used by Pasiphaë. Credited with many inventions. Also made wings to enable human flight. daimōn: Greek word for god, sometimes synonymous with theos (see), at other times indicating lower divinities, or intermediaries between gods and mortals. Can be benign or malicious; note Christian treatment of daimōn as an evil being— whence “demon.” Danaans: Greek-speaking tribe of uncertain location. Homer uses name in alternation with Achaeans (see) and Argives to refer to the Greeks who fought at Troy; also used in Vergil’s Aeneid. Dark Age: Period from the end of the literate Mycenaean Age (ca. 1100 b.c.e.) to the 8th century b.c.e., when evidence for Greek literacy recommences (though in a different form). What is known of the age is derived from physical remains. Demeter: Goddess of fertility. In mythology, mother of Persephone (Proserpina) (see), married to Hades. Demetrius Phalereus (4th century b.c.e.): Author and politician active in Athens, later librarian at Alexandria. Wrote literary critical essays and collections of proverbs and myths. demiourgos: Plato’s term for the creator who first designed the cosmos according to the forms, then created a physical world that accords with the design. Democritus (ca. 470–ca. 380 b.c.e.): Atomist philosopher. B. Abdera (Thrace), active in Athens; student, then colleague of atomist Leucippus. Posited only two substances: atoms and the void, both eternal, and argued that everything happened 204 204 glossary of names and terms according to anankē (see). Taught that the number of worlds generated by the cosmic whirl was infinite. Deucalion and Pyrrha: Couple that restarted the human race after the cataclysm decreed by the gods destroyed humankind; story reported in Ovid, Metamorphoses 1. Diagoras of Melos (5th century b.c.e.): Lyric poet. Reputed for atheism, tried and convicted at Athens, but fled, thus escaping death. Dike/dikē: “Justice”: god (personification) of justice in the Theogony. Dio Chrysostom (40 c.e.–112 or later): Greek philosopher, orator, and literary critic. His philosophy, based on Stoicism (see) and Cynicism (see), was of a practical nature. Diodorus of Sicily (1st century b.c.e.–ca. 21 c.e.): Historian. Wrote a world history beginning with ancient Egypt to his own day, using mostly Greek plus a few Roman sources. Diogenes Laertius (3rd century c.e.): Author of The Lives of the Philosophers, which covers the lives and thought of ancient philosophers from Thales to Epicurus. doxa: “Opinion,” from Greek verb “to seem.” Plato contrasts doxa with epistēmē, “true knowledge” (see). Regarding the material world, one can have only doxa, as its objects are in constant flux. dualism: Hypothesis going back to Plato that there are two levels of reality: the ideal and the material. Opposed to monism (definition 2) (see). Eleatics: School of philosophy in southern Italy founded by Parmenides (see). Preferred logical proofs to sense knowledge for establishing metaphysical propositions. See metaphysics. Eleusinian mysteries: Yearly ritual in honor of Demeter (see) and Persephone (see). The ceremonies, involving initiation into the cult of the goddesses, were regarded as mysteries, and were supposed to be kept secret on pain of a charge of impiety. Elysian Fields/E lysium: Abode of dead heroes and righteous souls. Set in Homer’s Odyssey 4 at the edge of Ocean; in Vergil’s Aeneid 6 it was incorporated into Hades as a separate part. Also equated with the Isles or Isle of the Blest. Empedocles (ca. 493–ca. 433 b.c.e.): B. Acragas (now Agrigento, Sicily); after exile, lived on the Peloponnese. Accepted earth, air, fire, and water as “roots” of being. Posited love (erōs) and strife (eris) as causes of motion and change. Held evolutionist notions (see evolution) regarding origin and survival of animals. Professed transmigration of souls. Enuma Elish: See Babylonian Creation Story. Epicureanism (aka the Garden): School founded by Epicurus (see). Ethical philosophy positing pleasure (hēdonē) as aim of life. Pleasure defined negatively as freedom from disturbance in body and soul; positively, as pursuit of philosophy and friendship. No need to fear death, as dispersal of soul’s atoms marks end of 205 glossary of names and terms 205 consciousness; there is no afterlife. Gods exist, but have no care for humans. E.’s ethical theory grounded in atomism (see). Epicurus (341–270 b.c.e.): Founder of Epicurean school of philosophy (see Epicureanism) at Athens. Regarded as atheos, but not prosecuted. epistēmē: “Knowledge”; for Plato the objects of epistēmē were the ideas/forms (see); the sensible world was not knowable in the true sense, as it was constantly changing. Eris/eris: “Strife”; a god in Hesiod’s Theogony, cosmic principle in the teachings of Heraclitus. Eros/erōs: “Sexual desire”; third of the divine beings to come into existence in the Theogony. Adopted as a cosmic principle as counterpoint to eris by Empedocles (see). etiology: “Account of the origin.” Applied to myths and legends that purport to explain how things came into being or why things are done in a certain way. etymology: Investigation of the root meaning of a word or name; applied as an aid to allegorical interpretation to uncover the meaning of a myth. Euclid ( fl. ca. 300 b.c.e.): Greek mathematician active in Alexandria, best known for his work in geometry. euhemerism: Named after Euhemerus (see). Method of interpreting myths and legends in a rationalistic manner, for example, by reducing gods to human proportions, or monsters to ordinary animals. Euhemerus (3rd century b.c.e.): Author of a utopian travel novel entitled the Sacred Scripture. Taught that gods were originally great kings and benefactors deified after death. E. regarded as atheos (see) in antiquity. Euripides (ca. 485–406 b.c.e.): Tragic playwright active in Athens. Work characterized by a cynical outlook on the doings of the gods and their interactions with humans. Accused of atheism, E. fled Athens and died in exile. evolutionism, Greek: Theory of natural origins, opposed to creationism (see). Examples include Hesiod’s notion that first beings simply “happened,” Anaximander’s idea of origin of living things from moisture enclosed in bark, Xenophanes’ deductions from fossils, and Empedocles’ theories that simple organisms develop into more complex ones and those animals survive that adapt best. exegesis: Word derived from Greek meaning “interpretation.” Gaia/gaia: “The earth.” One of the first three gods to “come into being,” according to Hesiod. At first G. produced natural phenomena by herself, then with Ouranos (see) after mating with him. Galen (ca. 130–199 c.e.): Greek medical writer and philosopher; physician to Emperor Marcus Aurelius. Writings show commitment to empiricism based on dissections. Though a monotheist, G. believed that god’s power limited by the laws of nature. 206 206 glossary of names and terms Genesis, Book of: The first book of the Torah or Pentateuch. Describes creation of the cosmos, creation and fall of mankind, the primeval flood, and beginnings of civilized life. Gilgamesh: Ancient Sumerian writing dating from third millennium b.c.e. Deals with existential issues such as search for immortality and need to accept death as inevitable. Description of “existence” of the dead not unlike that of Hades in the Odyssey. Golden Age: Motif of an age at beginning of time when humans lived a life of ease and bliss. golden bough: In mythology, a branch with golden leaves needed to gain entrance to the underworld. Hades: God of the underworld; also the underworld itself, the abode of all the dead, good and bad alike, who receive burial. See also shades, Tartarus, Isles of the Blest, and Elysian Fields. Hecataeus of Miletus (ca. 500 b.c.e.): Geographer, genealogist, and logographer (collector of myths). His treatment of myths is generally skeptical. Helios/helios: In mythology, the sun god, the sun itself. In Plato’s “Allegory of the Cave,” used as a symbol of the Good; in Stoic cosmology, serves as ruler of the cosmos. As “eye of the sky,” equated with justice. Hellanicus of Mytilene (5th century b.c.e.): Wrote on myths and early history, including the history of cities. Hellene: Name of the entire nation of Greeks. Originally designated a local region and tribe like Achaeans, Argives, etc. Hellenistic period: Time frame from the death of Alexander the Great (see) in 323 b.c.e. to the Roman conquest of Ptolemaic Egypt in 31 b.c.e. Hephaestus (Vulcan): In mythology, god of fire, the forge, and technology. Son of Zeus and Hera, portrayed as lame and awkward. Name used as a metonymy for fire beginning with Homer. Hera (Juno): Daughter of Kronos and Rhea, sister and last wife of Zeus. Associated with marriage, the family, and childbirth. As Hera, allegorized as the air; as Juno, “she who helps.” Heracles (Hercules): “Glory of Hera.” Most famous of the pre–Trojan War Greek heroes. Renowned for the twelve labors performed for King Eurystheus. Homer places him with the gods on Olympus, leaving an image of his shade in Hades. Heraclitus of Ephesus ( fl. ca. 500 b.c.e.): Monist (see monism) philosopher who posited eternal fire as the ultimate substance. Taught that universe not created and all things happen by strife and necessity. Things are in constant flux, but cosmic order is provided by the logos. The logos is available to all, but most people act according to private understanding. 207 glossary of names and terms 207 Heraclitus the Younger (2nd century c.e.?): Grammarian and philosopher. Defended Homer against critics, declaring that Homer composed allegorically; influenced by Stoicism. See also Homeric Problems. hermeneutics: Discipline that deals with theory of interpretation. Hermes (Mercury): In mythology, son of Zeus and Maia. In Homer, Hermes functions as messenger of the gods and guide of souls (Od. 24). Associated with speech and eloquence. Herodorus ( fl. ca. 400 b.c.e.): Greek mythographer. Author of a life of Heracles, lost except for a few fragments. Herodotus (ca. 485– ca. 425 c.e.): Greek historian. B. Halicarnassus, active at Athens. Traveled to Egypt, Ionia (see), and the Middle East. History covers events from Trojan War to Xerxes’ campaign in Greece (479 b.c.e.); includes much ethnographical commentary. Attitude toward religion and myth tinged by skepticism. Hesiod (8th century?, 7th century? b.c.e.): Epic poet; author of the Theogony and the Works and Days. The first work gives the origin of the cosmos, the natural world, and the gods. The second has a catalogue of the different generations of humans and the myth of Pandora’s box. Hexapla: Edition made by Origen (see) of the Old Testament in six versions, including versions in Hebrew and Greek. Hipparchus (2nd century c.e.): Greek astronomer. B. Nicaea (modern Turkey). Improved estimates of the distances of sun and moon from earth, and approached modern calculation of the solar year. H. first astronomer known to have employed trigonometry for calculations. historia: Term meaning “enquiry, investigation.” Developed the meaning “history” in the modern sense, because history is an enquiry into the past. Hobbes, Thomas (1588–1679): English moral and political philosopher. In Leviathan H. developed the theory of the social contract. Homer (8th century b.c.e.): Epic poet, traditionally regarded as author of both the Iliad and the Odyssey. Reputed that he was from Ionia and blind. Modern scholarship inclines to theory that H. composed orally (see oral composition). Homeric Hymns: Hymns attributed to the Homeridae (“sons of Homer”) composed in epic meter in honor of individual gods, probably in the 7th and 6th centuries b.c.e. The Hymns are a rich source for the mythology of the gods. Homeric Problems: Work by Heraclitus the Younger (see). Heraclitus claimed that Homer composed allegorically. Applied substitutionist allegory to “problematic passages” in Homer’s work. hubris: “Insolence, arrogance.” Used in situations in which a person of humble station insults a superior or, more often, when a mortal commits affrontery against a god. 208 208 glossary of names and terms hylē: Literally, “wood.” Term used by Aristotle and practically all subsequent philosophers to signify matter. hyponoia: Literally, “the sense beneath.” Plato’s term for allegory (see) applied to both composition and interpretation. ideas/forms, theory of: Plato’s concept of eternal, nonsensible patterns of existent things that are knowable only to the mind. They can be likened to numbers and geometrical forms, but embrace all being. Ideas are the object of epistēmē, “true knowledge” (see). Iliad: Epic poem ascribed to Homer (see). Deals with events of the tenth year of the Trojan War (see). Narrative focused on the hero Achilles (see). inspiration, Greek: Notion that a muse or god inspires the work of a poet. Belief in inspiration varied between skepticism (Hesiod) and acceptance (Homer in “historical” passages). Later writers understood the notion as a literary convention. Ionians: Writers and intellectuals inhabiting Greek colonies along the western coast of Asia Minor (Turkey), including Miletus, Ephesus, Halicarnassus, and Colophon. Thought characterized as materialist and empirical, in contrast to the Eleatics (see). See also Milesians. Isle(s) of the Blest: See Elysian Fields. Jason: Pre–Trojan War hero. Famous for his voyage with the Argonauts and capture of the Golden Fleece. Jerome, St. (348–420 c.e.): Biblical scholar and theologian. B. Dalmatia (modern Croatia), studied in Rome, retired to monastery in Bethlehem. Besides translating the Vulgate (see), translated and updated Eusebius’s Chronicle; wrote numerous letters, treatises, and biblical commentaries. Julian, emperor (reigned 361–363 c.e.): Known to Christians as “the Apostate” because he had accepted baptism and then, as emperor, attempted to restore pagan practices abolished by Constantine and successors. Treatise Against the Galileans contains rationalist critique of biblical accounts. Juno: See Hera. Jupiter: See Zeus. Justin Martyr (2nd century c.e.): Christian apologist. Like others of his time (Philo, Origen, Clement of Alexandria) taught that Christianity was compatible with Platonism. Justinian, emperor in the East (reigned 527–565 c.e.): Closed the Academy because of reputed pagan practices. Attempted unsuccessfully to regain Italy for the Empire. Codified Roman law (the Digest, Pandects) and erected the church of Hagia Sophia in Constantinople. katabasis: Literally, “a going down, descent”; motif of the descent of a living hero into Hades. 209 glossary of names and terms 209 kleos: “Fame, renown.” Homer used word in the sense of “rumor” or “opinion.” Kronos (Saturn): In mythology, Titan son of Ouranos and Gaia, father of the Olympian gods. According to Hesiod, castrated his father and devoured his children. K. presided over the Golden Age; defeated by Zeus and imprisoned in Tartarus (see). Etymologized as chronos (“time”). Lactantius ( fl. ca. 300 c.e.): Christian theologian, active in North Africa. Wrote the Divine Institutes, the first summary of Christian theology in Latin, and On the Wrath of God, discussing whether the divine nature can be affected. Leucippus ( fl. ca. 440 b.c.e.): Atomist philosopher. With Democritus (see) devised the Greek theory of atomism (see). Taught that nothing happens randomly, but all things due to necessity. Linear B: Syllabary used in Mycenaean centers that was shown to contain the Greek language. It was deciphered by Michael Ventris in the 1950s. logographic system: Writing system that employs pictographs such as Egyptian hieroglyphics or Mandarin Chinese. See also syllabary. logographer: Term applied to collector of myths, legends, and genealogies. logos: Term with range of meanings including “word” and “myth.” Used by Heraclitus and later the Stoics to mean the rational element embedded in the cosmos, which is also accessible to humans. Appropriated by Christians and applied to Christ as the Word (logos) of God. Longinus: Name traditionally given to the author of On the Sublime, one of the most important works of literary criticism from antiquity. Lucilius Balbus: Relatively unknown Roman who serves as spokesperson for Stoic teachings about the gods in Cicero’s On the Nature of the Gods. Lucretius (95– 55 b.c.e.): Roman poet and philosopher. Work On the Nature of Things based on teachings of Epicurus (see), but more extreme in opposition to religion. All things for L. were material, including the soul, which dissolves at death. Dismissive of mythology, L. denied the existence of centaurs and Hades. Macrobius ( fl. ca. 400): Latin grammarian and philosopher. Wrote Saturnalia, a piece of symposium literature dealing with literary criticism and antiquarian lore, and the Commentaries on the Dream of Scipio (see). Marriage of Philology and Mercury: Work by Martianus Capella (see). Written in mixture of prose and verse, an encyclopedia of the seven liberal arts preceded by two books of allegory describing courtship and marriage of Mercury (eloquence) and Philology (erudition). Mars: See Ares. Martianus Capella (5th century c.e.): Encyclopedist, active at Carthage, author of The Marriage of Philology and Mercury (see). 210 210 glossary of names and terms Medusa: In Greek mythology, one of the three Gorgons, female monsters with snakes for hair, huge wings, and eyes that can turn persons into stone. Memory: See Mnemosyne. Mercury: See Hermes. metaphysics: The part of philosophy that purports to deal with questions relating to being and reality, including principles of causation. Parameters fully developed in Aristotle’s (see) Metaphysics. Metis/mētis: “Counsel.” In Theogony, married to Zeus, who swallowed her and produced Athena (see) from his forehead. metonomy: Figure of speech involving substitution of one name by another. Often entailed use of a god’s name thing with which god was associated, e.g., Hephaestus for fire, Bacchus for wine. Metrodorus of Lampsacus (5th century b.c.e.): Grammarian (?). Allegorized the gods and heroes of Homer’s works; not to be confused with a younger Metrodorus of Lampsacus, an Epicurean. Milesian tale: Scurrilous story, erotically tinged, with numerous plot twists. Name owed to the Milisiaca of Aristides of Miletus (2nd century b.c.e.). Milesians: The school of philosophy and science founded at Miletus by Thales (see). Associated with search for the archē (see). mimēsis: “Imitation, representation.” Process used in art and literature of rendering a subject as lifelike as possible. Minos: Legendary king of Crete. In mythology, the son of Zeus and Europa; figures prominently in the story of Theseus (see) and the labyrinth. In later tradition, a judge of the dead. Minotaur: Mythological monster comprising the head of a bull and body of a man. Figures prominently in the Theseus (see) legend. Mnemosyne/mnemosynē: Goddess (personification) of memory, memory itself.” In Theogony, married to Zeus; together they produced the nine Muses (see). monism: (1) Hypothesis that everything that exists can be reduced to a single element that also acts as a cause; (2) hypothesis that matter is the only substance; nonmaterial substances do not exist; opposed to dualism (see). monotheism: The worship in one God/god to the exclusion of all others. Differs from Greek polytheism, which acknowledged a “greatest god” (Zeus), but allowed for worship of others. Moses: Biblical leader of the Jews who rescued his people from captivity in Egypt and led them to the Promised Land. Regarded by Jews and Christians, well into the Middle Ages, if not later, as author of the Torah (Pentateuch) . Muses: The nine daughters of Zeus and Memory (Mnemosyne), who inspire the arts and sciences and collectively preserve the memory of human accomplishment. 211 glossary of names and terms 211 Mycenaean Age: Period extending roughly from 1600 to 1100 b.c.e. Its records in Linear B (see) show that inhabitants of Mycenae and other mainland citadels were Greek speakers. Neoplatonism: School of philosophy founded by Ammonius Saccas (see) at Alexandria. Combined elements of Plato’s philosophy (drawing on Republic and Timaeus), with Middle Platonic, Pythagorean, Aristotelian, and Stoic notions. Leading exponent was Plotinus (see). Nicene Creed: Set of Christian doctrines requiring belief. First formulated at the Council of Nicaea (325 c.e.), underwent revisions and additions in 4th century. All versions teach that Christ is both God and man and that the Father, Son, and Holy Ghost are equally divine. nomos: “Law,” “convention.” Not applied, at least originally, to a law that was unchangeable, e.g., “iron law of gravity,” but to laws that were arrived at by human assent. Opposed to physis (see). nous: “Mind.” Begins and directs the cosmic whirl in the cosmology of Anaxagoras (see), though not identified with god. For both Plato (see) and Aristotle (see), the rational part of the soul. Ockham’s razor: Problem-solving principle developed by William of Ockham (ca. 1287–1347 c.e.), favoring selection of hypothesis that entails fewest assumptions. Odysseus (Ulysses): Hero of Homer’s epic, the Odyssey; famed for cunning and resourcefulness. Allegorized as the soul in Neoplatonist exegesis. Odyssey: Epic poem ascribed to Homer (see). Describes Odysseus’s adventures and trials at sea after Trojan War (see), the fate of his companions, and events surrounding his homecoming. Rich in mythical material. Oedipus: Legendary king of Thebes, subject of tragic plays, e.g., Sophocles’ Oedipus Tyrannus. O. solved the riddle of the Sphinx, murdered his father, and married his mother. On the Sacred Disease: Greek medical writing of the 5th century b.c.e. Argues that diseases had natural causes and were curable by natural methods (as opposed to, say, incantations). oral composition: Theory that epics ascribed to Homer (see) were composed orally, passed on to reciters, and later recorded. Theory based on study of verbal patterns (set phrases, repetitions) in poems and comparison with techniques of oral composition in present-day societies. Origen (ca. 185– 254 c.e.): Biblical scholar, philosopher and theologian, active at Alexandria. Applied Greek exegetical methods to study of the Bible, which O. theorized in On Interpretation 4, and Against Celsus (see under Celsus). O. also responsible for the Hexapla (see). Orpheus: In mythology, singer who tamed animals with his beautiful voice. Attempted to rescue his bride, Eurydice, from Hades (see katabasis), but failed. Regarded 212 212 glossary of names and terms as a poet and religious thinker to whom writings were attributed and a cult established. Ouranos/Uranus: God of the sky, the sky itself. Wedded to Gaia (Earth); father of the Titans. Castrated and deposed by his son Kronos. Ovid (43 b.c.e.–17 c.e.): Roman poet. Active at Rome; exiled by Augustus to the Black Sea. Most famous for the Metamorphoses, a collection of Greek and some Roman myths grouped around the theme of transformation. Panathenaia: Festival at Athens in honor of Athena, begun under the rule of Pisistratus (see); consisted of games, sacrifices, and performances by rhapsodes (see). Pandora: “All gifts,” name given to the first woman in Works and Days. Overcome by curiosity, P. opened the forbidden chest (“Pandora’s box”) and released evils into the world. paradigm: Defined and discussed in the preface of this book, pp. viii–viii. Parmenides (5th century b.c.e.): Founder of the Eleatic school of philosophy (see) in southern Italy. Denied that things could change into other things, thereby rejecting the monism of the Milesians, who taught that all that exists comes out of a single constitutive element. Pausanias ( fl. ca. 150 c.e.): Greek geographer and ethnologist. Wrote a travelogue, Descriptions of Greece. Though often skeptical, P. regarded monuments and other physical objects as evidence that events happened as described. Pelagius ( fl. ca. 400): Christian theologian, condemned as a heretic. Probably from Britain, active in Rome and the East. Against Augustine (see) argued that God’s grace was given equally to all in the form of a good nature and the gift of the law. Pentateuch: Greek name for the first five books of the Torah (Genesis, Exodus, Leviticus, Numbers, and Deuteronomy). Pericles (ca. 496–429 b.c.e.): Athenian statesman and general. Known to have been on friendly terms with the philosopher Anaxagoras and the playwright Sophocles. Peripatetics (aka the Lyceum): School of philosophy founded by Aristotle (see) at Athens. Emphasized scientific experiment combined with inductive method. Pegasus: In mythology, name of winged horse that sprang from the neck of Medusa after Perseus (see) severed her head. Perseus: In mythology, slew the Gorgon Medusa (see) with aid of Athena; wore a magic cap that made him invisible to Medusa’s sisters, who pursued him. Legend makes him king of Tiryns. Persephone (Proserpina): In mythology, daughter to Demeter (see), married to Hades (see). Spent half the year above the earth united to her mother, the other half below the earth in Hades. Phaethon: In mythology, son of Helios and Clymene. Asked Helios to guide the sun’s chariot for a day; unable to control the horses, crashed and set the earth on fire. Killed by Zeus’s thunderbolt. 213 glossary of names and terms 213 Pherecydes of Athens ( fl. ca. 450 b.c.e.): Greek logographer (collector and synthesizer of mythological material) and genealogist. Pherecydes the Syrian ( fl. ca. 550 b.c.e.): Philosopher and mythographer. There is some evidence that he was an early user of allegorical interpretation. Philo Iudaeus (30 b.c.e.–45 c.e.): Head of the Jewish community at Alexandria; wrote widely on philosophical and religious topics. Exegesis of scripture shows influence of pagan Greek interpretative methods. In On Creation P. integrates the creation account of Genesis with Plato’s Timaeus and Stoic philosophy. physis: “Nature, growth,” derived from the Greek verb phyō, “I beget,” “I cause to grow.” The phrase “according to nature” means “the way things grow,” a fixed condition that cannot be changed by supernatural interference. Pindar (518–438 b.c.e.): Greek lyric poet; his odes contain a great deal of mythological material. Pisistratus (reigned 560–527 b.c.e.): Tyrant of Athens. Founder of the Panathenaia (see) and patron of the compilation of a standard edition of Homer’s works. plasma: “Fiction,” a term applied to myths; from a Greek verb meaning “to mould or shape.” Plato (ca. 429–347 b.c.e.): Greek philosopher. B. Athens and active there. Influenced by Socrates, P. cast writings in dialogue form, with each devoted to a central theme, e.g., the Republic (see) to justice, the Symposium to love. Most enduring contribution the theory of ideas (see) or forms. In Timaeus (see) P. described creation of the world according to the forms. Opposed the myths of the poets. Plotinus (205– ca. 270 c.e.): Neoplatonist philosopher. Educated at Alexandria by Ammonius Saccas (see); settled in Rome as teacher of philosophy. His Enneads ranges over whole of philosophy. Central notion is idea of the One, the ground of existence. Between the One and matter are the nous, the psychē (world spirit), and physis (nature). Plutarch (ca. 46–ca. 120 c.e.): Greek historian, philosopher, and essayist. Studied in Athens, active in Rome under Trajan. Wrote Parallel Lives, paired biographies of a famous Greek with Roman counterpart, e.g., Alexander with Caesar. His essays, Moralia, range over religion, myth, politics, literature, and education. Influenced by Platonism. polis: The Greek “city-state.” Autonomous political units comprising a citadel (walled town) and surrounding countryside with villages. Each polis had its own government and army and commanded the loyalty of its citizens. Porphyry (ca. 232–ca. 305 c.e.): Neoplatonic philosopher and scholar. B. Tyre (Palestine), disciple of Plotinus (see) at Rome; edited his Enneads. Wrote history of early Greek philosophy, life of Plotinus, commentaries on works of Plato and Aristotle. His essay on “The Cave of the Nymphs” is a model of Neoplatonic myth exegesis. Poseidon (Neptune): In mythology, brother of Zeus; god of the sea and of earthquakes. prepōn, (to): “the fitting”; term applied in ethics and aesthetics. 214 214 glossary of names and terms Presocratics: Term for Greek philosophers active before Socrates. Plato and Aristotle were heavily dependent on their writings, though Aristotle in particular criticized them. Proclus (412–485 c.e.): Neoplatonic philosopher. B. Constantinople, studied in Alexandria; disciple, then head, of the Neoplatonist school at Athens. Wrote a summary of Neoplatonism (see). P.’s Commentary on Plato’s Republic is an original contribution to myth interpretation. Prodicus of Ceos (5th century b.c.e.): Sophist, contemporary with Socrates. Posited theory that the ancients call gods all the things that benefit them; also author of allegory “Heracles at the Crossroads.” Prometheus: In mythology, Titan son of Iapetus; rebelled against Zeus. Stole fire from Zeus and gave it to mortals; for his offenses he was tied to a rock and suffered his liver to be eaten daily by an eagle. In one tradition he is credited with the creation of humans. Proserpina: See Persephone. prosopopoeia: “Personification.” A figure of speech used by writers to endow abstractions with human characteristics. Protagoras (5th century b.c.e.): Sophist. B. Abdera, active probably at Athens. His dictum “man is the measure of all things” regarded as an endorsement of relativity and a refusal to accept anything as absolute. Proteus: In mythology, a daimōn shape shifter that will answer questions or prophesy if one can immobilize it when it shifts into its original shape; described in Odyssey 4. Prudentius (348–after 405 c.e.): Christian Latin poet. B. Spain, later at Rome as court official. Most famous poem the Psychomachia, an allegory of a battle between personified virtues and vices. psychē: Greek for “soul.” In Homer psyche refers to the shades (see) of the dead in Hades (see). In Greek philosophy, beginning with Heraclitus, psyche refers to soul of living person. Encompasses both mental and emotional aspects of the human makeup; often identified with the self. Ptolemy (ca. 100–ca. 170 c.e.): Astronomer and geographer, active at Alexandria. His work in astronomy includes a map of the constellations and predictions when they would rise and set. His Geography includes maps of Europe and Asia, using curved lines of latitude and longitude. Ptolemy II Philadelphus (reigned 283–246 b.c.e.): King of Ptolemaic Egypt. Tradition holds that the Septuagint (see) was undertaken under his patronage. Pythagoras of Samos (6th century b.c.e.): Mathematician, astronomer, and philosopher active at Croton (southern Italy). Posited the theorem of the right triangle and the numerical ratios of the intervals of the musical scale. Believed numbers to be the principles of the cosmos. Apparently first Greek to posit a spherical earth. Accepted notion of the transmigration of souls. 215 glossary of names and terms 215 Republic: Dialogue by Plato centered on definition of justice. Expands outward to include discussion of the ideal society, the divisions of the soul, the theory of ideas (see), and literature and art as related to mimēsis (see). The “Allegory of the Cave” is used to illustrate the theory of ideas. P.’s censure of the myths of the poets occurs in book 2. rhapsode: Professional reciters of the works of Homer and other poets. They displayed their talents at important festivals such as the Panathenaia (see). Rhea: In mythology, Titan divinity, wife of Kronos, mother of Zeus and Z.’s siblings. Saved Z. from being devoured by Kronos by substituting a stone wrapped in swaddling clothes. After swallowing the stone Kronos disgorged the other children he had consumed. Sacred Scripture: Travel novel by Euhemerus (see) in which author claims to have seem a golden pillar with an inscription listing the deeds of Ouranos, Kronos, and Zeus. Because of the benefits they brought to men they were honored as gods after their deaths. Septuagint: “The Seventy.” Translation of the Old Testament into Greek at Alexandria, allegedly under patronage of Ptolemy II Philadelphus. Legend states that seventy scholars spent seventy days translating the Bible, and produced identical translations—to the last jot and tittle. Sextus Empiricus (2nd century c.e.): Skeptic philosopher; wrote treatises outlining the history and principles of philosophical Skepticism (see). shade: A translation of Homer’s psyche, a wraith of the dead in Hades. Its consciousness and memory are extremely dim, unless revived by animal blood. Once having drunk, it is temporarily revived and able to recall things and converse. Skepticism, philosophical: In general, a reaction against statements claiming certainty. Spread over several centuries and different movements (for example, the Middle and New Academies), skeptics generally agreed that real knowledge of things was not attainable. The most prudent position was to withhold consent to propositions. See also Sextus Empiricus. Socrates (469–399 b.c.e.): Athenian philosopher; executed on charge of impiety. Early work in physical philosophy; later turned to ethics and politics. S. pioneered technique of the elenchus (questioning an opponent, thus leading to refutation). As S. left no writings, what is known of his thought must be drawn from Plato, Aristotle, Xenophon, and others. Solon (ca. 640–ca. 560 b.c.e.): Athenian statesman, lawgiver, and poet. His poetry is moralistic, condemning corruption, injustice, and the arrogance of the rich and powerful. sophist: Private teachers in Athens in the 5th century b.c.e. They taught mainly rhetoric and techniques of argument to students preparing for public life; reputed for questioning traditional values, myths, and religious beliefs and for promoting relativism. 216 216 glossary of names and terms Stoa: “The portico.” The name refers to the Stoa Poikile in Athens, a hall in Athens where Zeno gathered with his students. By metonymy (see) the Stoic school of philosophy. See also Stoicism. stoicheia: “Elements”; term used for both the physical elements (earth, air, fire, water) and for the principles of a subject such as geometry. Stoicism: School of philosophy founded at Athens by Zeno of Citium (see). Mainly ethical, taught that virtue is the highest good. Though deterministic, Stoicism allowed for moral freedom. Taught that all things composed of matter. God and the world are one and contain the logos, the principle of reason governing everything. Stoics believed that ancient wisdom concealed in myth was corrupted by poets, but could be recovered by allegoresis supported by etymology. Strabo (ca. 63 b.c.e.–19 c.e.): Greek traveler and geographer, active at Rome. His Geography survives almost intact. In it he discusses places mentioned by Homer, whom he regarded as authoritative, and argued that Homer’s descriptions contained a kernel of truth. syllabary: Writing system in which symbols represent whole syllables rather than individual sounds. Linear B (see) is an example. symbolism: The employment of persons or things as signs of other things. In contrast to Stoic allegory, which is substitutive, the signifying person or thing is not erased. Tabula Cebetis (“Tablet of Cebes”): Pseudonymous work written in early centuries c.e. Author lays out a tableau and interprets its mysteries for visitors who do not understand it. Contains allegories of the virtues and vices. Tartarus: The deepest part of the earth in which Zeus imprisoned the Titans and their allies who opposed him, including his father, Kronos. See also Hades. Terence (ca. 195–159 b.c.e.): Roman author of comic plays. Tertullian (ca. 160–ca. 225 c.e.): Christian apologist and theologian, active at Carthage. Thales of Miletus (late 7th– 6th century b.c.e.): Astronomer and mathematician. Founder of the Milesian school (see), which concentrated on physical science. Proposed water as the archē (see). Theagenes of Rhegium ( fl. ca. 525 c.e.): Early grammarian who interpreted Homer’s poems allegorically. Theogony: “Origins of the Gods.” An epic poem by Hesiod describing the origins of the world and successive generations of gods, culminating in the unending reign of Zeus. Regarded by Aristotle as a pioneering work on cosmology. Themis/themis: “Law” or “right.” Represented in Theogony as a female Titan; aunt of Zeus, who later married her. Theodosius I, emperor (reigned 379–395 c.e.): Last emperor to rule over both the eastern and the western portions of the Empire. A strict Christian, T. established a series of laws prohibiting pagan practices and Christian heresies. 217 glossary of names and terms 217 theion, (to): “The divine”; a quality that belongs to both gods and exceptional mortals. theomachia: A battle among the gods, especially that described in Iliad 10. theos: See also daimōn. The standard Greek word for god; etymology uncertain. Theseus: Legendary hero of Athens. Conducted numerous exploits against monsters and robbers, like those of Heracles. Renowned for rescuing the Athenian hostages from Crete and dispatching the Minotaur. Subject of numerous “lives,” notably one by Plutarch. Timaeus: Late work by Plato that presents a “myth” containing an account of creation. In it the demiourgos (“builder”) first designs the cosmos according to the forms, then proceeds to build a physical cosmos based on the design. The physical cosmos is not to be eternal in itself, but contingent on the will of the demiourgos. Work influenced Neoplatonism and Christianity. Titans: In mythology, members of the second generation of gods, children of Ouranos and Gaia. Warred with Zeus in the titanomachia and lost. Number includes anthropomorphic beings (e.g., Kronos), natural phenomena (e.g., Ocean), and mental abstractions (e.g., Themis) Torah: Literally, “the Teaching”; equated with Jewish religious law as expressed in the first five books of the Old Testament. Trojan War (12th century b.c.e.?): Legendary ten-year siege of Troy (northwest corner of Turkey) by Greeks over Helen, Menelaus’s wife, abducted by Paris, son of Trojan king Priam. War forms basis of Homer’s two epics and Vergil’s Aeneid. Ulysses: See Odysseus. Venus: See Aphrodite. Vulcan: See Hephaestus. Vergil (70–19 b.c.e.): Roman poet famous for his epic Aeneid (see). His Fourth Eclogue was interpreted by Christians as a prophecy of the birth of Christ. Vulgate: Translation of the entire Bible into Latin by St. Jerome (see) ca. 400 c.e. Certain canonical books of the Old Testament were translated directly from Hebrew, others from Greek, or Hebrew with the aid of Greek. Works and Days: Epic poem by Hesiod (see). Deals principally with farming and husbandry, but contains valuable mythical material, including the allegory of the metals, representing successive ages of human development, and the myth of Pandora’s box. Xenophanes of Colophon (6th century b.c.e.): Cosmologist, theologian, and poet. Educated in Ionia, traveled extensively, migrated to the court of Hieron in Syracuse. Regarded myths as fictions (plasmata). Famous for his deconstruction of the Homeric gods and proposal for worthier divinities; influenced Plato. Yahweh: Name for the god of the Jewish kingdoms of Israel and Judah. Originally a warrior god who aided the Israelites in their battles, Yahweh became the sole god 218 218 glossary of names and terms of the Jews, and after the Babylonian exile was regarded as the creator of the world and one true God of the cosmos. Zeno of Citium (335–263 b.c.e.): Philosopher active in Athens, founder of Stoicism (see). Zeus (Jupiter): In mythology, son of Kronos and Rhea. The chief god and most powerful of the Greek pantheon. Overthrew Kronos and the Titans and imprisoned them in Tartarus (see). Married seven wives, including the allegorical figures Themis (Law), Mnemosyne (Memory), and Metis (Counsel). Produced Athena from his own head to forestall a usurper and rule forever. God of oaths and protector of travelers. 219 General Index Abraham, 15. See also biblical stories; Genesis Academy, 99, 144. See also Plato Achilles, 17–18, 77, 80–81, 125, 173n10. See also Homer; Trojan War Adam and Eve, 17, 21. See also biblical stories; Genesis Adimantus, 67. See also Plato Aegina, 28. See also literacy Aeneas, 2, 17. See also myth; mythology Aesopian fable, 7, 74–75. See also fable aether, 19, 103, 121. See also fire Agamemnon, 18, 25–26, 80–81. See also Homer agnostic, 52–53, 60. See also gods; God; religion Aidoneus, 86 Ajax, 18. See also Homer Akkadians, 2–3. See also mythology Alcaeus, 120. See also poetry; poets Alexander the Great, 2, 15, 28, 125, 150. See also Alexandria Alexandria, 93, 150–51, 154, 158, 166. See also Alexander the Great allegoresis, 74, 82, 151–52, 162. See also allegory allegory, 7, 9, 27, 30, 66, 69, 73–82, 98, 116, 131, 141–4 2, 161, 168–69, 179nn1–2; definition of, 120; as a figure of speech, 119; the growth of, 109–22; Hesiodic model of, 131; historical, 182n2; metaphorical nature of, 138; moral, 79; personification the opposite of, 135; physical, 79, 111, 126–27, 137; psychological, 111, 126, 152; rediscovery of, 169; saving the poets without, 123–29; substitutionist, 161, 169; to symbolism, 131–45. See also exegesis; hyponoia; interpretation; myth; symbol alphabet, Greek, 8, 28. See also Phoenicians Amazons, 83, 86, 91, 181n8. See also Plutarch; Scythia ambiguity, 11, 24, 80 Ambrose, 159, 168–69. See also Augustine Ammonius Saccas, 151. See also Origen; Plotinus Amor and Psyche, 131–33, 135, 144. See also Apuleius; fable anankê (necessity), 39, 50, 58. See also chance; necessity anatomy, viii, 80. See also Metrodorus of Lampsacus Anaxagoras, 47–51, 53, 57, 60, 80, 98–99. See also atheism; philosophy; Presocratics Anaximander, 40, 42, 48. See also natural philosophy; Presocratics Anaximenes, 42, 46, 57, 81, 97. See also natural philosophy; Presocratics 220 220 gener al index Ancyra, 93 Antheus, 66. See also playwrights; tragedians Antisthenes, 79. See also Cynicism apartheid, human, 21 apeiron (the infinite), 42 Aphrodite, 17, 19, 55–56, 77–79, 114–15, 124, 159. See also gods; Homer Apollo, 25, 30, 65, 78, 80, 120–21, 132. See also gods Apsu, 20. See also Babylonians Apuleius, 131–35, 143–4 4, 179n15, 184n1; The Golden Ass of, 131; imagery of, 141. See also Amor and Psyche; fable; Platonists Ares, 78–79. See also gods archê (principle), 41–43, 46, 49, 116, 119, 153, 175n23, 176n39; as divine element, 50, 110, 182n15; of the Ionians, 81. See also divine, the; element Ariadne, 84–85, 92. See also Theseus Aristobulus of Panaeas, 153–54. See also allegory; Philo Aristophanes, 51, 57; Clouds of, 51; Frogs of, 57 Aristotle, 10, 40–46, 51–67, 70–71, 98–106, 115, 123–29, 138, 177n7, 182n21; Metaphysics of, 10, 42, 104; Nichomachaean Ethics of, 123; On the Heavens of, 105; Poetics of, 64, 123, 179n21; on the poets, 33, 64, 126, 184n1; unmoved mover of, 103. See also Peripatetics; philosophy; Plato; theism art, 70, 81. See also mimêsis; poetry Artemis, 78. See also Diana; gods astronomy, 8, 42 Ate (Ruin), 77–78 atheism, 20, 40, 50–61, 75, 81, 99, 149, 177n6, 178n30; laws against, 53. See also Dawkins, Richard; impiety; philosophy; theism Athena, 21, 23, 37, 77, 81, 138, 150, 160. See also gods Athens, 4, 8, 28, 37, 48, 51–61, 68, 83–84, 91–99, 151. See also Greeks, ancient; literacy atheos (godless), 53–54. See also gods; impiety; religion atomists, 40, 49–50, 58–59, 97, 99, 101–3, 106. See also cosmology; natural philosophy; Presocratics Augustine, ix–x, 10, 38, 89, 96–97, 129, 150, 157–62, 167–69, 184n3, 187n42; On Christian Doctrine of, 157–61, 167; On the City of God of, 162; semiology of, 158. See also Church Fathers; exegesis; interpretation; symbol Augustus, Emperor, 29. See also Roman Empire; Rome authority, vii, 11, 26–27, 29; of the Church, 166; of Homer and Hesiod, 31, 34, 80, 101, 115; over nature, 106; of philosophers, 86; priestly, 31; of scripture, 34, 161. See also Hesiod; Homer; inspiration; magisterium authorship model, 5. See also myth origins Babylonians, 7–8, 13–14, 16; Enuma Elish of the, 14, 20. See also astronomy; Hammurabi, King; Marduk; mythology Bacchus, 74. See also Dionysius Basil of Caesarea, 128, 160; “Address to Young Men on How They Might Derive Benefit from Greek Literature” of, 129. See also Church Fathers being, 51, 98, 101; divine, 51; Mind as a, 99; nonmaterial, 51, 98. See also materialism; matter; substance belief, 2, 6, 11, 13, 88; about the gods, 25; in the gods, 54; in a judgment followed by reward and punishment, 25. See also myth Berkeley, George, 177n10. See also philosophy Bible, 16, 34, 69, 147–48, 155, 159–60, 162, 167–68, 175n7; authority of the, 167; Hebrew, 151, 157; unitary reading of the, 172n1. See also biblical stories; Christian scriptures; Jewish scriptures; Septuagint biblical stories, 7, 13, 22, 154, 168. See also Bible; Christianity; Jews biblical studies, 29. See also classical studies biography, 85, 126. See also history; myth Boccaccio, 71. See also Renaissance body, 75, 137. See also matter; soul books, 13. See also myth; literature Cadmus, 22. See also myth Callimachus, x. See also poetry; poets Calypso, 124. See also Homer Cassiodorus, 188n1. See also Church Fathers 221 gener al index causation, viii, 43, 80; Aristotle on, 103, 176n25; natural, 40; principle of, 44. See also naturalist explanations; natural philosophy Cebes, 140. See also Socrates; symbol; Tabula Cebetis Celsus, 147–48, 154, 168; Against Christianity of, 147. See also Christianity; Origen; Platonists censorship, 69. See also culture; Plato centaurs, 85–86, 94. See also monsters; myth Cerberus, 86, 88, 95, 123. See also Hades; monsters Ceres, 135–36. See also gods chance, 50, 104, 106. See also necessity chaos, 19. See also Chaos Chaos, 19, 97, 116. See also chaos; cosmology; gods character, 16, 124–25, 136, 141. See also fable; gods; myth Charlemagne, 29. See also authority; Bible Charybdis, 95. See also monsters Christianity, viii, 6, 10–11, 34, 37, 58, 61, 102–7, 147–51, 155, 158–62, 165– 69. See also Bible; Christian scriptures; Church Fathers; heresy; revelation; theology Christian scriptures, vii, 38, 165–67; interpretation of the, ix, 10–11. See also Bible; Christianity; interpretation; Jewish scriptures; Septuagint Chrysippus, 112–13, 115, 118. See also Stoics Church Fathers, 11, 40, 88; Greek, ix, 169; Latin, 169, 178n27. See also Christianity; Christian scriptures Cicero, 29, 61, 119, 128, 138; Hortensius of, 159; On the Nature of the Gods of, 117–18. See also allegory; rhetoric; skepticism Circe, 79, 184n1. See also Homer; Odysseus classical studies, 3, 29. See also biblical studies Cleanthes, 112–13, 118. See also Stoics Clement of Alexandria, 158–59, 162; Exhortation to the Greeks of, 158–59, 162; Stromateis of, 158. See also Church Fathers; Origen code of ethics, 24–25, 27. See also code of law; moral world; Torah 221 code of law, 24–25; Athenian, 28. See also code of ethics; law; lawgiver Colchis, 18. See also Jason commentaries, 11, 34. See also exegesis; interpretation; scholia communication, 73. See also media; narrative composition, 128. See also interpretation Corinth, 28. See also literacy Cornutus, 113–16, 118–20, 122, 125, 140, 142. See also allegory; cosmology; Stoics cosmography, 18 cosmologists, 63, 80, 105, 131. See also cosmology; Presocratics cosmology, 5–6, 9–19, 24, 40–53, 63, 99–100, 109, 116; the language of, 40; and literary criticism, 81; of the Stoics, 119–22, 128. See also cosmologists; natural philosophy; science; gods; myth; Platonists; Stoics cosmos, 5, 8, 10, 39–43, 51, 63, 98, 100–4, 106, 123, 136, 138; cause of the, 64; as divine, 110; elements of the, 78; as eternal and uncreated, 106; law of the, 50; origins of the, vii–v iii, 2, 9–10, 13–14, 19, 61. See also cosmology, Hesiod; myth; natural philosophy; universe Cratylus, 112. See also etymology; Socrates creation, 6, 23, 100, 152–53, 168, 176n39. See also cosmology; creator god; demiurge; God; intelligent design; theism creator god, 41, 50, 102. See also demiurge; God; gods Crete, 28, 84, 92. See also literacy Critias, 56–57, 65; Sisyphus of, 60, 89. See also atheism; Socrates Cronus. See Kronos cult, 2, 31, 37, 81; of heroes, 5. See also gods; heroes; religion culture, viii, 2–4 , 11, 45, 55, 65–66, 119, 147, 160, 169; oral, 30. See also media; religion; society Cumae, 28. See also literacy Cybele, 165. See also gods; religion Cyclopes, 124. See also monsters, Polyphemus Cynicism, 79. See also philosophical schools; philosophy Daedalus, 84. See also Minos daimon, 1–2, 56, 76–78, 80 222 222 gener al index Darwin, Charles, 52, 102. See also evolution Dawkins, Richard, 20, 38–39, 150, 186n12. See also atheism; theology Demeter, 54–56, 80, 98, 119, 158. See also Athens; gods Demetrius Phalereus, 93. See also Athens demiurge, 41, 100–1, 104, 153. See also creator god; gods; Plato; Timaeus democracy, 92. See also Athens Democritus, 49, 54, 58, 89, 97. See also atomists; Presocratics Demon, 83–84. See also Plutarch Demos, 92. See also Athens Deucalion and Pyrrha, 3. See also flood; myth; Ovid Diagoras of Melos, 54–55, 59–60. See also impiety; poets Diana, 142. See also Artemis Dicaearchus, 83. See also Plutarch didactic, 27, 64. See also Hesiod; poetry Dikê, 20, 24, 55. See also justice Dio Cassius, 184n4. See also history Dio Chrysostom, 125; Discourses of, 125. See also philosophy; rhetoric Diodorus of Sicily, 89. See also history Diogenes, 79. See also Cynicism; philosophy Diogenes Laertius, 40. See also history; philosophy Dionysus, 54, 56, 80, 98, 159. See also Bacchus; gods disbelief, 3, 8. See also belief; myth; mythology divine, the, 40–42, 97, 100. See also archê, gods divine nature, 50, 56. See also divine, the; God; gods; theology Drachmann, A. B., 57 dualism, 105, 107, 109–10. See also Platonists dunamis (power), 40 earth, 19, 55, 76–7 7, 101. See also Gaia education, 68–69, 100, 166. See also morality; Plato Egyptians, 2, 4, 7–8, 28, 54, 90, 102, 149, 153, 160. See also mythology Einstein’s Special Theory of Relativity, 54 elements, 42, 81, 102, 106, 141; divine, 110; empty, 81; opposition of the, 79. See also cosmology; natural philosophy Eleusinian mysteries, 54. See also mystery religions Elysian Fields, 18 emotion, 76. See also ethics; reason Empedocles, 59, 63–64, 126. See also philosophy; Presocratics empiricism, Greek, 41. See also natural philosophy Enlightenment, 37. See also skepticism epic, 7, 14–15, 34, 64–67, 127, 131. See also poetry Epicharmus, 56. See also gods; mythology Epicureans, 110, 148–49, 179n22. See also Epicurus; philosophical schools Epicurus, 40, 58–60, 71, 99; as critic of Homer, 120; gods of, 106, 178n26. See also atomists; Lucretius; philosophy Eratosthenes, 94. See also geography; Strabo eris (strife, repulsion), 44, 79. See also erôs erôs (attraction), 19, 44, 79. See also Eros Eros, 19, 131. See also cosmology; erôs; gods ethics, 51–52, 59, 75. See also happiness; morality; vice; virtue etymology, 111–12, 116–17, 121–22, 139; 183n9; of divine names, 113, 183n14; folk, 183n5. See also allegory Euclid, 8. See also geometry Euhemerus, 5, 55, 90, 159; Sacred Scripture of, 5, 89 Euripides, 57, 60, 66, 112, 125, 178n20, 178n25; Bacchae of, 58; Bellerophon of, 58, 60; Hippolytus of, 58; Phoenician Women of, 124. See also tragedians Eurydice, 30 evolution, vii, 20, 23, 27; of the gods, 23–24; theory of, 52, 102. See also creation; Darwin, Charles; evolutionary model evolutionary model, 5–6, 19, 21. See also evolution; myth origins exegesis, ix, 10–11, 97, 111, 122, 162; of Homer, 121, 136; method of, 152; of myth, 114, 188n6; scriptural, 10, 155; symbolist, 144, 162, 169. See also allegory; interpretation; literature; myth Exodus, 31. See also Jewish scriptures fable, 7, 27, 68, 74–87, 101–10, 118, 121–33, 141, 162, 168; of Hesiod, 22, 94; philosophical, 131; Platonic, 138; 223 gener al index of the races named after metals, 22– 23; of the temple of Cronus, 140–41. See also Aesopian fable; myth faith, viii, 8. See also belief fiction, 64, 66, 94–95. See also mimêsis; plasma figural interpretation ( figurate), 168. See also Augustine; exegesis; interpretation film, 66. See also fiction; mimêsis; plasma fire, 23, 25; cosmic, 43; as the single uncreated principle, 43; as Zeus as aether, 121. See also Heraclitus; Hesiod; Prometheus first things, 31, 34. See also theogony Fletcher, Angus, 142. See also allegory flood, 3, 22. See also Deucalion and Pyrrha; Genesis; myth forms, 100, 103, 139; in the mind of the creator, 153. See also Philo; Plato; Platonists; substance Franklin, Benjamin, 24. See also proverbs freedom, vii, ix–x, 9, 61, 125, 165; intellectual, 168–69. See also authority French Revolution, 15 Furies, 19. See also Ouranos Gaia, 19, 24, 55, 68, 97, 101, 113, 136. See also earth; gods; cosmos Galen, 38–39, 147 Garden of Eden, 14, 115, 152, 154, 162. See also Genesis genealogy, 15, 90. See also myth Genesis, 3, 14–15, 19, 21, 34, 155–56; creation of Eve in, 14; Garden of Eden story in, 14, 115, 152, 154, 162; six days of creation in, 153, 168; two accounts of the creation of humans in, 20. See also Jewish scriptures geography, 18, 83, 94. See also Eratosthenes; history; Strabo geometry, 8, 63. See also Euclid; Pythagoras of Samos German Romantics, 3. See also myth Gilgamesh, 14. See also Sumerians gnômê (thought, judgment), 43 gnômôn (yardstick), 129 God, 10, 13, 16, 20, 24, 31–38, 59, 99, 102–7, 168; of Aristotle, 51, 103–4; as a conscious being, 100; creation of the universe by, 50; of Genesis, 153; Mind identified with, 99; and 223 nature, 105; rediscovery of, 97–107. See also gods; religion; theism gods, 2–5, 10–11, 17, 20–25, 33–43, 49, 55, 76–81, 106, 159, 166, 173n6, 175n4; anthropomorphic, 50, 98, 136; battles of the, 69, 79; creation of the world by, 40; critics of the, 57; deathless, 24; denial of the, 53, 56; of Epicurus, 59; governance of the universe by the, 10; and humans, 17, 23–24; images of the, 52; inspiration of the poets by the, 65; king of the, 14; mind of the, 17; names of the, 111, 118; nature of the, 16, 52–54, 67, 118; origins of the, 31, 89; physical and moral character of the, 27, 69; of the poets, 20, 40, 45, 80, 127, 173n6; redefining the, 53, 60; worship of the, 37, 52, 81. See also atheism; cult; God; paian; Plato; polytheism; religion; theism; Xenophanes golden age, 14. See also Genesis; Hesiod good order, 24. See also cosmos Good, the, 51, 70, 100, 139. See also forms; Neoplatonists; Plato; Platonists grammar, 9, 30. See also grammarians grammarians, 55. See also grammar Greek gods, 1–2, 24. See also gods; Roman gods Greeks, ancient, viii–i x, 1, 4–10, 31–35, 69, 83, 91, 155, 168; colonies of the, 8; ethical codes of the, 24; law codes of the, 24. See also astronomy; mythology; philosophy; science Hades, 17–18, 25, 81, 86–87, 91, 94, 96, 119, 126, 133, 145, 155, 173n8. See also gods; underworld Hammurabi, King, 14. See also Babylonians happiness, 75–76. See also ethics; morality; virtue Hecataeus of Miletus, 6, 43–4 4, 87–91, 97–98, 159. See also history Hector, 80–81. See also heroes; Homer Helen, 15, 18, 80–81, 96. See also Homer; Menelaus Helios, 25, 47–48, 78, 80–81. See also gods; personification Hellanicus, 83, 87. See also Plutarch hellenismos, 30 224 224 gener al index Hephaestus, 21, 54, 69, 78–79, 112, 115, 151, 161. See also gods Hera, 55, 69, 77–80, 101, 110, 112, 115, 117, 121, 123, 144, 151. See also gods; Juno Heracles, 15–16, 18, 31, 75–7 7, 80, 82, 91–92, 94, 97–88, 173. See also Hercules Heraclitus of Ephesus, 41–4 4, 46–49, 63, 79–81, 97–98, 101–2, 106, 112, 119, 138. See also Presocratics Heraclitus the Younger, 120–22, 125, 128, 138; Homeric Problems of, 120. See also allegory; Stoics Hercules, 1, 7. See also Heracles heresy, 166. See also Christianity; theology Hermes, 17, 78, 151. See also gods Herodorus, 83, 87. See also Plutarch Herodotus of Halicarnassus, 65, 76, 80, 90–91, 98; Histories of, 90. See also geography; history heroes, 1–3, 16–17, 20–21, 33, 55, 68, 71– 76, 87–91, 94, 145; homecoming of the, 31. See also myth; mythology heroic age, 27. See also fable; heroes; myth Hesiod, viii, 4, 7–25, 32–4 4, 64–65, 76–7 7, 94–112, 118, 138, 149, 155, 168, 173nn16–17; authority of, 30–31; cosmology of, 44, 50, 64, 116; criticism of, 65, 79, 81–82; in the curriculum, 68; divine inspiration of, 32; the gods of, 45–46, 50, 52, 65–71, 79, 94, 109, 173n16; names of divine beings in, 55; paradigm of, 106; prophesy of, 21; shade of, 63; Shield of Heracles of, 18; Theogony of, 14–19, 21–27, 32–34, 61, 68, 71– 79, 101, 113–14; Works and Days of, 14, 20–22, 24, 27, 173n16. See also proverbs; myth; poetry; poets hexameter, 34. See also Homer; poetry hierarchy, 25. See also gods; society Hindus, 2. See also mythology Hipparchus, 8. See also astronomy historia, viii history, 2–9, 15–18, 24, 43, 64, 66, 95, 97–98, 165; Greek, 27, 31, 91, 172n13; in myth, 83–96, 123; rationalist view of, 169. See also myth origins; pseudo-history Hobbes, Thomas, 4, 56 Homer, viii–i x, 4, 8–11, 15–19, 25–35, 43, 64–65, 74–80, 95–96, 109, 138, 148, 155, 168; allegorical interpretation of, 30, 78, 121–22; authority of, 30–31, 52; the books of, 29; copies of, 30; criticism of, 30, 65, 79, 81–82, 91; in the curriculum, 68; the gods of, 20, 38, 45–46, 50–66, 71, 81, 94, 109; history in, 94; Iliad of, 14–18, 26–33, 61, 67–68, 77, 79, 87, 94, 120; monsters of, 95; names of divine beings in, 55; Odyssey of, 14–18, 25, 27, 31, 67–68, 71, 79, 94, 120; physical explanations of, 80, 120–22; recitation of, 31; scholiast of, 78; select passages of, 120; shade of, 63, 173n9; social code of, 25; the status of theologian of, 138–39, 172n4; symbols in the mind of, 140. See also myth; poetry; poets; war Homeric Hymns, 31, 38, 52, 175n4. See also Homer; religious festival hubris, 25–26 hyponoia (underthought), 73, 75, 119–20, 123, 127–28, 179n2. See also allegory image, 141. See also symbol; Tabula Cebetis impiety, 53–54, 99. See also atheism; gods; religion inspiration, 11, 31; divine, 34. See also authority; poetry intelligent design, 100, 102, 106, 182n14. See also creation; creator god; God; teleology interpretation, 2, 8–11, 80, 126, 139, 156; allegorical, 78–79, 82, 109, 151, 169; of the Bible, 156; contradictions in, 152; history of, 78, 116; literal, 78, 168; modes of, 11, 128, 162, 168; moral, 169; pioneers of, 3; of scripture, 155; Stoic myth, 119; tools of, 97. See also allegory; composition; figural interpretation; literature; poetry; symbol Iris, 47, 80. See also gods; mythology; personification Isis, 7. See also Egyptians; Osiris James I, King, 29. See also authority; Bible Jason, 87, 92; and the Argonauts, 2. See also heroes; myth; mythology Jerome, 157, 169, 174n10. See also Church Fathers; exegesis 225 gener al index 225 Jewish scriptures, vii, 13, 38; interpretation of the, ix, 10. See also allegory; Bible; Christian scriptures; interpretation; Old Testament; Septuagint; Torah Jews, 13–14. See also Jewish scriptures; Septuagint; Torah Joyce, James, 1; Ulysses of, 1. See also Odysseus Julian, Emperor, 148. See also Roman Empire Juno, 144. See also Hera Jupiter, 56, 89, 116, 118, 133. See also gods; Zeus justice, 20, 24, 60. See also Dikê Justin Martyr, 149; First Apology of, 149. See also Church Fathers Justinian, Emperor, 61. See also Christianity; Roman Empire literary criticism, ix, 81. See also interpretation; literature literature, 3, 7–8, 11, 129, 151, 160; criticism of, 8, 127; interpretation of, 8, 10, 126; Jewish, 172n17. See also myth; poetry logographic system, 28. See also Egyptians logos (reason), 43, 46–47, 49, 126, 149, 155. See also Heraclitus; philosophy Love, 132–33; divine, 135. See also gods; Amor and Psyche Lucilius Balbus, 116, 118–19. See also Cicero; Stoics Lucretius, 6, 59–61, 71, 85–86, 91; On the Nature of Things of, 59. See also Epicurus; myth origins; poets; poetry lyric, 64. See also myth; poetry knowledge, 45, 107. See also philosophy; Plato; Platonists; Xenophanes Konstan, David, 144 Kronos, 4–5, 19–24, 68, 77, 79, 91, 109, 111–18, 140. See also Gaia; Ouranos; Rhea; Zeus Macrobius, 7. See also fable; literary criticism; philosophy magisterium (teaching authority), 166. See also authority; Christianity mankind, 80; origin of, 4; primitive, 54. See also Hesiod; myth Marcus Aurelius, 38. See also Roman Empire; Stoics Marduk, 14. See also Babylonians Martianus Capella, 140; The Marriage of Philology and Mercury, 142–4 4. See also exegesis; symbol materialism, 51. See also being matter, 10, 49, 99, 102–3, 105, 110; soul and, 137–39. See also being; substance; universe meaning, 141, 169; anagogical level of, 163; figurative, 169; moral level of, 163; of the scriptures, 154, 162; symbolic, 152. See also exegesis; image; interpretation; signs; symbol Medea, 92. See also Jason media, 69. See also culture Melissos of Samos, 98, 177n2. See also Parmenides; Presocratics memory, 33; 55; racial, 3. See also Memory; Mnemosyne; myth Menelaus, 18, 96. See also Helen; Homer Mercury, 133, 144. See also gods metaphor, 135 Metis (Wisdom), 23, 55, 76. See also gods; wisdom; Zeus metre, 64. See also poetry Metrodorus of Chios, 180n15. See also atomists; Democritus Lactantius, 150; On the Wrath of God of, 150. See also Christianity; Church Fathers Lamberton, Robert, 145 language, 1. See also myth; mythology Latin, ix–xi, 11, 56, 74, 111, 116, 119, 131, 142, 147, 157, 159, 169 law, 20, 25, 55–56; author of the, 24; of the cosmos, 50; Greek, 61; operation of the universe according to its own, 50. See also code of ethics; code of law; lawgiver; reason; Themis lawgiver, 4, 27, 29, 63, 90. See also Pythagoras of Samos; Solon laws of nature, 3, 38–39, 51, 102, 109. See also science Lef kowitz, Mary, 1 legend, 30–31, 48, 63, 118. See also myth Leucippus, 49, 58, 103, 182n21. See also atomists; Presocratics Lévi-Strauss, Claude, 66. See also myth Lewis, C. S., 141–42. See also fable; symbol Litai (Suppliant Prayers), 77, 82 literacy, vii, ix, 8, 14, 27–28, 68. See also oral tradition; writing literalism, 11. See also exegesis; interpretation 226 226 gener al index Metrodorus of Lampsacus, 80–81, 112, 180n15. See also anatomy; Anaxagoras; interpretation; poetry Midas, 92–93. See also Silenus Middle Ages, ix, 11, 148, 182n14, 188n6. See also Christianity; Latin Miletus, 133 mimêsis (imitation), 64, 68, 70, 126–27, 143. See also Aristotle; fiction; poetry mind, 10, 47, 49, 74, 78, 81, 100; concepts in the, 135; eye of the, 141. See also Anaxagoras; Mind; nous; Plato; reality; soul Mind, 41, 49–50; of Anaxagoras, 49–50, 57, 99. See also mind; nous Minos, 18, 84–85, 91–92. See also gods; Minotaur; underworld minotaur, 84–85, 92, 94. See also Minos; monsters Mnemosyne (Memory), 55, 76, 159. See also gods; memory; Muses; Zeus monism, 43, 107. See also dualism; philosophy monotheism, 46, 106, 149. See also God; polytheism; theism; theology monsters, 19, 85–86, 94–95. See also gods; heroes, Titans Monteverdi, Claudio, 1; Return of Ulysses of, 1. See also Odysseus morality, 60, 69; of the gods of the poets, 68. See also education; ethics; justice moral world, 24, 27. See also code of ethics; gods; vice; virtue Moses, 13, 38, 149–50, 152, 157, 167. See also biblical stories; Genesis Mount Olympus, 15–16, 20, 32, 79, 107, 115. See also gods; myth Musaeus, 30. See also myth; poetry; poets Muses, 30–33, 65–66, 71, 89, 116, 126, 159. See also Mnemosyne muthos (myth), 6, 141, 155. See also fable; myth Mycenaean Age, 8, 14, 28, 172n2 mystery religions, 54. See also gods; religion myth, viii–x, 1–8, 11, 13, 46, 52, 56, 78, 116–17, 163, 169; across cultures, 3; anatomy of, viii; coherence of, 116; criticism of, ix, 3, 6, 30, 68, 96, 122, 152; debunking of, 60; defense of, 66, 69, 73; erotic, 11; and ethnology, 172n13; and history, 17, 83–96, 148, 172n13; interpretation of, vii, 6, 50, 82, 107, 109, 113; of the Jews, 150; language of, 26, 46; literal truth of, 126, 162; moral truths in, 124; origin of, 3–4 , 11, 65, 119; the personae of, 124; philosophy and, 7, 122; poetry a medium for expressing, 64; primeval flood, 3; scientific truths in, 118; Stoic interpreters of, 131. See also fable; Hesiod; Homer; muthos; mythology; myth origins; poetry; poets; symbol mythology, 1–2, 71, 154; fictions of, 47; North American, 3; South American, 3. See also myth; myth origins myth origins, 5; authorship model of, 5; evolutionary model of, 5–6, 19, 21; revelation model of, 5–6. See also myth; mythology narrative, 2, 16, 27, 50, 73, 77, 172n1. See also communication; narrative theory narrative theory, 7. See also narrative naturalist explanations, 48. See also causation; natural philosophy natural phenomena, 80–81. See also natural philosophy; nature natural philosophy, viii, ix, 6, 9, 37, 46, 51, 60, 98–99, 102. See also philosophical schools; philosophy; science natural properties, 47. See also personification nature, 6, 9, 11, 20, 39–41, 47, 100, 103, 114; and god, 50, 98; of the gods, viii; principle of, 103; transfer of divine powers to, 40; two basic senses of, 104. See also philosophy; physis; science Naxos, 28. See also literacy necessity (anankê), 50, 58, 102–4 . See also anankê, chance; reason Neoplatonists, 136–37, 140, 145, 147, 151, 159; cosmology of the, 183n14; exegesis of the, 136–39, 162. See also allegory; Plato; Platonists; Plotinus; Porphyry Nestor, 16. See also Homer; Trojan War Nicene Creed, 165. See also Christianity Noah, 2, 22; sons of, 15. See also biblical stories; Genesis nomos (law, custom), 39 nous (mind), 47–49, 51, 98–99, 110; 163. See also Anaxagoras; mind; Proclus 227 gener al index ocean, 18, 55. See also Oceanos Oceanos, 55. See also gods; geography; ocean Ockham’s razor, 42 Odysseus, 1, 17–18, 25–26, 79, 91, 95, 111–12, 123–24, 145, 150, 173n8, 184n1; and Calypso, 17; and Cyclops, 2; and the Sirens, 129. See also Homer; myth; mythology; Ulysses Oedipus, 2, 94, 124; and Jocasta, 155. See also myth; mythology Old Testament, 68, 150–51, 157, 161, 166–68. See also Bible; Jewish scriptures; Septuagint One, the, 98, 177n2. See also Melissos of Samos; Parmenides Ong, Walter, 30. See also study oral tradition, 8–9, 14, 27, 30. See also literacy; writing Origen, 10–11, 149, 151, 155–58, 161–62, 168; Against Celsus of, 154–55, 162; exegesis of, 154; Hexapla of, 157–58; On First Principles of, 155, 157; semiology of, 158. See also allegory; Church Fathers; exegesis; interpretation Orpheus, 7, 18, 30, 91, 172n14, 173n8. See also myth; poetry; poets Osiris, 8. See also Egyptians; Isis Ouranos, 5, 19, 23–2 4, 55, 68, 79, 112, 114. See also Gaia; Kronos; sky; Zeus Ovid, 3. See also myth; poetry Paeon the Amathusian, 83. See also Plutarch paian (hymn of praise), 53, 177n7. See also gods; religion Panathenaia, 29, 31, 174n9. See also Homer; recitation; religious festival; rhapsodes Pandora, 21, 23, 27, 118, 131. See also Hesiod papyrus roll, 28. See also literacy; writing paradigm, vii–i x, 13, 16, 20; of the poets, 13–26. See also authority; society paradox, 54, 177n10 Paris, 76, 80–81. See also allegory; Homer Parmenides, 49, 63, 98, 177n2. See also philosophy; Presocratics Pasiphaë, 84, 91. See also Daedalus; Minos; Minotaur 227 Paul, Saint, 145, 166. See also Christianity Pausanias, 91–93. See also geography; legend peace, 24. See also Peace Peace, 55. See also gods; peace Pegasus, 2. See also myth; mythology Pelagian controversy, 167. See also Christianity; Christian scriptures; scripture Peloponnesian Wars, 60, 99. See also Athens Pericles, 53. See also Athens Peripatetics, 99, 149, 169. See also Aristotle Perithoüs, 173n7. See also heroes; Theseus personification, 47, 55, 75–7 7, 80, 135, 140, 177n15. See also gods; natural properties; symbol Persephone, 86, 135. See also Hades; Proserpina; Theseus Perses, 24. See also Hesiod Perseus, 1, 17; and Medusa, 2. See also heroes; myth; mythology Phaea, 88 Pherecydes of Athens, 83–84, 87. See also Plutarch Pherecydes the Syrian, 79, 180n4. See also allegory Philo, 10–11, 149, 151–55, 160, 162, 186n21; Life of Moses of, 151; On the Creation of the World of, 153, 187n21; On Providence of, 151; Questions on Genesis of, 152, 155. See also Alexandria; allegory; Church Fathers; Platonists; Stoics Philochorus, 83–84. See also Plutarch Philoctetes, 124 Philology, 143–4 4. See also exegesis philosophers, 53, 58, 61–69, 78, 85, 93, 102, 149, 151; Christian, 103, 149; gods of the, 51–52. See also gods; philosophy philosophical schools, vii, 60, 97, 99, 107, 118, 122, 169. See also philosophy philosophy, 5–11, 50, 66, 68, 71, 123, 128, 159, 166; of art, 70; in late antiquity, 6, 169; truths of, 71; Western, 51. See also natural philosophy; philosophical schools; Plato; science; social theory; Socrates Philostratus, 140; The Images of, 140. See also exegesis; symbol 228 228 gener al index Phoenicians, 8, 28. See also alphabet Phoenix, 77. See also Homer physics, 60. See also cosmology; natural philosophy; science physis (nature), 6, 10, 37–50, 97–100, 102, 104–6; of diseases, 40; the paradigm of, 10. See also nature piety, 90. See also impiety; Polybius; religion Pindar, 64, 173n10; Second Olympian Ode of, 25 Pirithoüs, 86. See also Theseus Pisistratus of Athens, 8, 29–30, 34, 79, 92, 94. See also Athens; tyrant Pithacus, 124 plasma (fiction), 47, 50, 65, 91, 94, 115–16, 168. See also fiction; mimêsis Plato, 8–10, 37–41, 51– 64, 79– 82, 99–106, 111–18, 126–28, 148–50; on allegory, 66, 69, 73; Allegory of the Cave of, 70, 100; Cratylus of, 112; on the connection of body and soul, 105; incorporeal being of, 98; on inspiration, 33; Ion of, 8; Meno of, 110; Myth of Er of, 110, 135; myths of, 82, 131, 141; Phaedo of, 110; Phaedrus of, 74, 110, 131, 134–35, 141, 145; on the myths of the poets, 65–67, 81, 100, 120, 124, 131; Republic of, 64–70, 74, 100, 110, 115; Symposium of, 52, 110, 131, 134; teachings on love and soul of, 134; theology of, 102; theory of ideas of, 70, 100, 102; Timaeus of, 10, 100–2 , 110, 153, 175n13; world soul of, 105–6. See also Academy; forms; philosophy; Platonists; poets; soul Platonists, 100, 102, 106–10, 112, 136, 147–48, 154, 160, 166, 169; allegorical interpretation of the, 107, 111, 134; Jewish, 169; Plutarch grouped with the Middle, 131; Timaeus a central text for the, 109. See also Academy; dualism; Plato; Neoplatonists playwrights, 53–54, 57. See also theater; tragedians Plotinus, 136–37, 139, 147, 151. See also Neoplatonists; Porphyry; Proclus Plutarch, 73, 84–89, 91–95, 125–31, 149, 155, 159; Isis and Osiris of, 184n6; On the Study of Poetry of, 73, 126, 139; Parallel Lives of, 83, 87. See also allegory; history; Platonists; poetry poetry, vii–i x, 3–11, 33–34, 54, 63–64, 123, 136; allegorization of, 98; as an art of imitation, 126; criticism of, 8, 63–71; defenders of, 82, 109, 126; enemies of, 4; literal truth in, 68, 123; mythological content of, 64, 82; and philosophy, 64, 68, 71. See also literature; myth; poets poets, ix, 6, 18, 31, 44, 55, 61, 119; authority of the, 109; critics of the, 9, 33, 68–69; defense of the, 79–80, 82, 123–29; gods of the, 45, 63, 109; inspiration of the, 65; intention to portray truths in the, 136; as inventors of myth, 4–5, 65, 90; as liars, 4, 68, 126; myths of the, 37; as philosophers, 5. See also literature; myth; poetry political authority, 8. See also authority; society Polybius, 90. See also history Polycrates, 91 Polyphemus, 25. See also Cyclopes; monsters; Poseidon polytheism, 46, 106, 149. See also gods; monotheism; theology Porphyry, 78, 136–38, 144–45, 147; Cave of the Nymphs of, 136–41, 152–53, 160, 185n17; exegesis of, 138–40. See also interpretation; Neoplatonists; symbol Poseidon, 25, 54, 78, 81, 87, 92, 111. See also gods; Homer; ocean Presocratics, ix, 37, 40–41, 48, 51, 98, 115, 169. See also natural philosophy; philosophy Proclus, ix, 144–45, 163, 185n30; Commentary on Plato’s Republic of, 144–45. See also Neoplatonism; philosophy; Platonists Prodicus of Ceos, 54–55, 59, 75–7 7, 80– 81, 89, 98, 112, 118, 158; “Heracles at the Crossroads” of, 75–82. See also fable; sophists Prometheus, 21, 23, 25, 173n14. See also Titans; Zeus propaideusis (preparatory study), 169. See also education Proserpina, 135. See also Persephone prosopopoeia (creating a persona), 55, 75. See also rhetoric Protagoras of Abdera, 53–54, 60. See also sophists Proteus, 1, 121. See also daimon; Homer proverbs, 24, 136. See also code of ethics; Hesiod 229 gener al index providence, 59, 105, 149. See also gods; religion; theology Pseudo- Callisthenes, 171n3 pseudo-history, 2. See also history psychology, 6. See also soul Ptolemy, 8. See also astronomy Ptolemy II Philadelphus, King, 29, 174n10. See also authority; Septuagint Pythagoras of Samos, 8–9, 40, 43, 63, 148. See also geometry; philosophy; Presocratics; Pythagoreans Pythagoreans, 7. See also philosophy; Pythagoras of Samos randomness. See chance reality, 10. See also being; matter; substance reason, 3, 50, 76, 83, 86, 102. See also emotion; law; necessity recitation, 29–32. See also Panathenaia; religious festival Reformation, 11. See also Christianity religion, viii–i x, 7, 11, 23, 25, 37, 50–51, 61, 88, 117, 160; attacks on, 52, 59; freedom of, 165; Greek, 25; practices of, 55, 165; Roman, 25, 162; sanction of, 31, 69; skepticism about, 53. See also Christianity; Hesiod; Homer; impiety; piety; religious festival; theology religious festival, 29, 31. See also Homer; Panathenaia; recitation; religion Renaissance, ix, 61, 71, 188n6. See also Boccaccio Res gestae divi Augusti, 29. See also Augustus, Emperor revelation, 34; direct, 34; indirect, 34. See also Bible; scripture revelation model, 5–6. See also myth origins rhapsodes, 29–30, 35, 45. See also Homer; recitation Rhea, 24, 113, 140. See also Kronos; Titans rhetoric, 9, 53, 73, 75, 80, 160. See also sophists Rhodes, 28. See also literacy Roman Empire, 61, 148, 150. See also Rome Roman gods, 1. See also gods; Greek gods; Rome Rome, 61, 83, 151, 169. See also Roman Empire; Roman gods 229 Romulus, 83. See also Rome Rumor, 55. See also gods Samson, 7. See also biblical stories satire, 57. See also theater Saturn, 118–19. See also gods; Kronos Scamander, 78. See also Homer scholia, 34. See also commentaries science, viii–i x, 37, 51, 118; elements of, 109. See also allegory; natural philosophy scripture, 34, 61, 167; figurative sense of, 161–63; literal sense of, 161–63; as revelation from God, 34; unitary reading of, 172n1. See also Bible; Christian scriptures; exegesis; Jewish scriptures; revelation Scylla, 95. See also monsters Scythia, 86, 90. See also Amazons Septuagint, 29, 151, 153, 157, 174n10. See also authority; Bible; Jewish scriptures; Ptolemy II Philadelphus, King sex, 115. See also Aphrodite; Venus Sextus Empiricus, 55. See also skepticism Shakespeare, 35. See also poetry signs, 160–62; Aristotelian concept of, 187n42. See also interpretation; meaning; symbol Silenus, 92–93. See also Midas simile, 138. See also symbol Sisyphus, 18, 25 skepticism, vii, 3, 6, 8, 11, 37, 53, 60, 169, 178n30. See also disbelief; Sextus Empiricus Skeptics. See skepticism sky, 19, 55, 76–7 7. See also Ouranos social practices, 13. See also authority; society social theory, 4. See also philosophy; social practices; society society, 6–7, 13, 25, 68–69, 100, 106. See also Plato; social theory Socrates, 51, 53–54, 60, 63, 67, 126, 175n1. See also ethics; natural philosophy; Plato Sodom and Gemorrah, 22. See also biblical stories Solon, 4, 29, 126. See also Athens; lawgiver sophists, 4, 37, 52–55, 60, 75, 77, 99; heirs of the, 60; skepticism about religion in the, 53. See also philosophy; rhetoric 230 230 gener al index Sophocles, 65–66. See also poets; tragedians soul, 10, 74–75, 78, 103, 107, 110, 133–37, 141–45; of the cosmos, 105; and Eros, 131; immaterial, 102, 105; immortal, 148; and matter, 138– 39. See also body; daimon; mind; psychology; vice; virtue Spartans, 124 Sphinx, 155. See also monsters; Oedipus Stoics, 10, 98–100, 105–6, 116–22, 138, 148–49, 166, 169; allegorical interpretation of the, 107, 111–12, 116–22; cosmology of the, 114–16, 119–22, 128; god of the, 106; myth exegesis of the, 109, 162; theory of the origin of myths of the, 119. See also philosophical schools; philosophy; symbol; theism Strabo, 19, 90, 94–96. See also Eratosthenes; geography study, 30. See also writing sublime, 35. See also Homer; poetry substance, 9, 103; immaterial, 10, 104–5; Stoics on the materiality of, 110. See also mind; reality Sumerians, 2–3, 14; Gilgamesh of the, 14, 18. See also Gilgamesh; mythology symbol, 80, 136–37, 141–42, 145, 158, 160–63; language of, 139. See also allegory; exegesis; interpretation; signs; simile; symbolon symbolon (symbol), 137. See also symbol Tabula Cebetis, 140–41. See also Cebes; symbol Tantalus, 18, 25 Tartarus, 18, 23–25, 114. See also Hesiod; underworld taurus (bull), 84. See also Minos; Pasiphaë Taurus, 84–85, 95. See also Minos; Pasiphaë teleology, 100, 106. See also Aristotle; Plato Terence, 74. See also allegory Tertullian, 147, 149; On the Proscribing of Heretics of, 147. See also Christianity; Church Fathers Thales of Miletus, 40–42, 44, 55, 97. See also natural philosophy; philosophy; Presocratics Theagenes of Rhegium, 9, 30, 78–79, 81, 98, 111, 151. See also allegory; Hesiod; Homer; interpretation theater, 52, 68; festivals of, 52. See also playwrights theism, viii, 10, 20, 53, 98–100, 107. See also God; gods; theos Themis (Right Order, Good Order), 20, 24, 55, 76. See also gods; law; Zeus Theodosius I, Emperor, 165–66. See also Christianity; religion; Roman Empire theogony, 30, 65. See also first things; gods; Hesiod; myth theology, 6, 10, 15, 18, 43–50, 60, 95, 109, 137; Christian, 166–69. See also atheism; Christianity; Homer; theism theos (god), 6, 10, 97–107. See also God; gods; theism Thera, 28. See also literacy Thersites, 26. See also Agamemnon; Odysseus Theseus, 15, 18, 83–88, 90–91, 125, 173nn7–8; abduction of Persephone by, 86; and the Minotaur, 2; ship of, 93. See also heroes; myth; mythology; Plutarch Thetis, 17, 124. See also Homer Thucydides, 90. See also history Tiamat, 14, 20. See also Babylonians Timaeus, 82, 100–1. See also Plato Time, 100, 112, 114, 117, 138. See also universe; world Titans, 18–21, 23–25, 79. See also gods; Prometheus Tityus, 18, 25 Torah, 13–14, 24, 34, 153–54. See also Jewish scriptures; Philo; Septuagint tragedians, 57, 66. See also playwrights; theater Trojan War, 9, 15–17, 31, 84, 87, 92–94, 155. See also Homer; Troy Troy, 25, 31–32. See also Homer; Trojan War truth, 5, 9, 33, 66, 68, 145, 149, 155, 162; cosmological, 5, 80; literal, 123, 126, 128, 158; in myths, 5, 80, 96, 116, 123; philosophical, 139; relativity of, 60; universal, 3. See also belief; disbelief; skepticism tyrant, 8, 48, 58, 92, 120. See also political authority Ulysses, 1. See also Odysseus underworld, 17–18, 135, 145, 173n8. See also Hades; Homer; Minos; Odysseus 231 gener al index universality, 31. See also myth universe, 10, 40, 49, 101, 105; creation of the, 24, 50, 106; final cause of motion in the, 100; origin of the, 10, 109; sensible, 138; workings of the, 60. See also cosmos; natural philosophy; world Venus, 132–33, 135–36, 143. See also Aphrodite; gods; sex Vergil, 61, 91, 148–49, 169, 180n7. See also poetry; Rome vice, 26, 75, 124, 135, 140. See also moral world violence, 22, 115. See also war virtue, 26, 65, 75–76, 96, 110, 124, 135, 140. See also moral world vocabulary, 34. See also Homer; poetry war, 15, 17. See also Trojan War; violence War of Independence, 15 wisdom, 55. See also gods; Metis women, 24; creation of, 14, 19, 21, 27; Hesiod’s advice on, 24; men and, 20; subjection of, 25. See also society world, 50–51, 100–1, 107; best possible, 105; of the forms, 100; god as one with the, 50; material, 139; materialist view of the, 51; noetic, 231 135–39; sensible, 101. See also cosmos; matter; universe writing, 28–30. See also literacy; oral tradition; papyrus roll Xenocrates, 100. See also Academy; Plato Xenophanes of Colophon, 9, 27, 40, 43–57, 63–71, 79–81, 91, 101, 106, 111, 126, 150, 176n39; innovative theology of, 45–46, 50, 67, 98– 99, 122. See also Hesiod; Homer; natural philosophy; Presocratics Yahweh, 13, 22, 24. See also God; Jewish scriptures; Torah Zeno, 99, 112–13, 116–19, 122. See also philosophical schools; Stoics Zeus, 4, 14–18, 22–26, 37–55, 79–89, 96–101, 110–17, 121, 144, 159, 172n5; cult of, 31, 53; daughters of, 32, 77; generations made by, 21; and humans, 17, 168; marriages of, 76; ordering of the creation of woman by, 2; sanctuary of, 92–93; statue of, 141; as supreme ruler, 24, 31, 77. See also gods; Hera; Jupiter; Kronos; myth; Ouranos 232