Foundations of American Law (an undergraduate course) This is the first draft of an undergraduate introduction to law and legal systems. Its basic purpose is to help you understand our legal system and the means and merits of legal argument. You will learn to appreciate the distinction between rhetorical argumentation on disputed issues, as might appear in editorial writing, and legal argumentation. Each weekly reading consists of an explanation of legal concepts paired with one or more important cases that either illustrate the concepts directly or provide a basis on which to discuss the concepts. The course culminates with a few weeks’ discussion concerning pending or recently decided Supreme Court cases so that you can appreciate the legal disputes of our time from the legal perspective. Each reading is covered in a podcast download and then discussed in a seminar session. Audio can be accessed at http://www.hydratext.com/foundations-2017. You can subscribe to these episodes in a podcast app on your phone by Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 adding the following URL in your app: http:// www.hydratext.com/foundations-2017?format=rss. The following is one good option for a weekly schedule: Meeting 1: Overview of the U.S. Legal System (3) Meeting 2: Legal Systems and Arguments (33) Meeting 3: What Is Good? (102) Meeting 4: Law and Economics (153) Meeting 5: Collective Action and Human Behavior (191) Meeting 6: Fairness and Distributive Justice (212) Meeting 7: Review and Midterm Test (239) Meeting 8: Courts and Precedent (no audio) (247) Meeting 9: The Administrative State (298) Meeting 10: Interpretation (341) Meeting 11: Deference and Scrutiny (344) Meeting 12: Discussion of a current Supreme Court case Meeting 13: Discussion of a current Supreme Court case Meeting 14: Review and Final Test (397) Christian Turner, November 7, 2017 2 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 Meeting 1: Introduction An Overview of the U.S. Legal System Everyone learns in grade school the basic structure of the government of the United States. We have a federal government, established by the U.S. Constitution, and state governments that operate under state constitutions. This dual structure, in which both the federal government and the states are sovereign entities, is called federalism. While the federal government is hierarchically superior to state governments on some issues, it lacks authority on others. As a result, the relationship between the federal government and the states is more complicated than a simple hierarchy. The internal structure of both of these sorts of governments is similar. Each consists of separately constituted branches that conduct the traditional functions of government. At a high level of generality: Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 – The legislative branch passes laws. – The executive branch carries out and enforces the laws. – The judicial branch resolves disputes between the state and citizens or between citizens by applying law. This simple model of separate institutions wielding separate powers turns out to be more complicated when we examine what governments actually do. Executive branch officials, for example, must make interpretations of statutes to enforce them. And judges inevitably create meaning when interpreting statutes. But this high level, grade-school model of government is a useful starting point. Legislatures The Feds Our national legislature is called Congress. It is created, defined, and regulated by Article I of the U.S. Constitution. The Congress is composed of two separate institutions that must reach agreement in order to act: the House of Representatives and the Senate. This feature is known as bicameralism. On the one hand, we have the House of Representatives, the members of which typically represent local districts defined by the state law. (These district maps are the subject of ferocious battles concerning racism, partisan entrenchment, and charges of corruption.) Each state may elect a number of representatives roughly proportional to its population, with each state’s being guaranteed at least one seat. For about a century, the number of representatives has been fixed by law 4 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 at 435. The upshot is that more populous states have more say in the House, and members are elected in smaller, more local elections than their state-wide counterparts in the Senate. The rules of the House are complex, and much business is conducted either by supermajority consensus to “suspend the rules” or by “special rules” that govern the consideration and debate of particular pieces of legislation. The Senate, in contrast, consists of two members per state. This gives the residents of small states disproportionate influence over the Senate. For example, there are fewer than 300,000 Wyoming residents per senator but more than 19 million residents of California per senator. Another stark contrast is the length of elected terms: senators serve six years per term, and House representatives serve two-year terms (which means, in today’s world, that they are never not running for reelection). The smaller Senate operates in a much less majoritarian fashion than does the House. Almost nothing can be accomplished without a 60-vote supermajority (enough to cut off debate after a cloture vote), and individual senators can delay, if not kill, legislation for days. Much in the Senate occurs by unanimous consent, with compromise and accommodation having characterized its practice - perhaps until recently. This very brief description of the two chambers of the national legislature is intended both to convey basic information to you but also to highlight how different legislatures can be, both in composition and in their rules for conducting business. Creating different structures for the House and Senate was a key design choice made by the Framers of the Constitution. They believed narrow interests 5 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 would have a harder time dominating the legislature if winning meant achieving passage in two representationally distinct bodies. And, indeed, the Constitution requires that any law must pass both houses of Congress in identical form and be signed by the President (or be approved by 2/3 of both Houses in the case of a presidential veto). The States Almost all state legislatures are similar in structure and composition to Congress. They are bicameral and representationally distinct. (Nebraska is a notable exception, having a unicameral legislature.) They have the equivalent of a House and a Senate, where senators are fewer in number and longer-serving than state House representatives. Unlike U.S. senators, though, state senators are constitutionally required to represent districts of relatively equal populations, a consequence of the “one-man, one-vote” principle the U.S. Supreme Court announced in Reynolds v. Sims. Another distinction worth noting in this brief summary is that more than a quarter of state legislatures place term limits on House and Senate members, a requirement that may not constitutionally be placed on federal lawmakers. See U.S. Term Limits, Inc. v. Thornton, 514 U.S. 779 (1995). There is another key distinction between federal and state legislatures: their powers. State legislatures are empowered to pass virtually any laws within the “police power,” defined as authority to legislate to improve public health, safety, welfare, or morals (sometimes called the “orthodox quartet”). This, as the definition suggests, is a very broad power to regulate. States may, of course, restrict legislative authority in their state constitutions. 6 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 Another constraint on state legislatures, which requires us to use the “virtually” modifier above, is federal law. The Supremacy Clause of Article VI of the U.S. Constitution provides: This Constitution, and the Laws of the United States which shall be made in Pursuance thereof; and all Treaties made, or which shall be made, under the Authority of the United States, shall be the supreme Law of the Land; and the Judges in every State shall be bound thereby, any Thing in the Constitution or Laws of any State to the Contrary notwithstanding. The effect of this clause is that any state law contrary to a valid federal law is preempted and void. Federal law includes constitutional provisions, statutes, and the decisions of federal courts interpreting federal law. No state legislature may pass a law abridging the freedom of speech, racially segregating schools, or providing for less restrictive pollution regulations than established under the federal Clean Water Act. No state court may order the same. Despite the Supremacy Clause, however, the federal government is not fully superior to the states. Among other reasons, this is because section 8 of Article I confers on Congress the power to legislate only on enumerated subjects. It provides that “Congress shall have Power to” legislate to do such things as levy and collect taxes, to borrow money, to regulate interstate and foreign commerce, to make immigration laws, to coin money, to create roads and post offices, and to declare war. By restricting congressional lawmaking to these enumerated powers, the Constitution 7 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 withholds from Congress the full scope of the police power. If Congress cannot point to an enumerated power to justify a piece of legislation, then Congress lacks the power to legislate on that topic. In addition to specifically listed subjects, article I, section 8 states that Congress has the power “to make all Laws which shall be necessary and proper for carrying” into effect the enumerate powers. We will discuss this issue further later in the course, but a major struggle over the division of power between the federal government and the states has been over the interpretation of the enumerated powers and what is necessary and proper to wielding them. In particular, and especially in response to the Great Depression and the statesponsored racism of the Jim Crow era, Congress has passed laws regulating intra-state activities, asserting such laws have been necessary to solve national problems and that the regulated activities affected interstate commerce. The Supreme Court continues to struggle to define the outer boundaries of congressional power. Executives The Feds Article II of the Constitution provides that the national Executive Branch is headed by the President of the United States, in whom the “executive Power shall be vested.” Presidents are elected by state-appointed electors, who are usually appointed to reflect the winner of the state-wide popular vote. This method of selecting the president is controversial, having arisen from an early compromise between slave and non-slave states. During the twentieth 8 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 century, the winner among state electors, and therefore the elected president, also won the national popular vote. However, since 2000, two of the five elections have resulted in a president who lost the national popular vote. Presidents oversee an executive branch that consists of many agencies, offices, and departments. The size and nature of the federal bureaucracy changed greatly in the twentieth century as a result of the Great Depression and the New Deal. There are fifteen Cabinet Departments, headed by Secretaries who report to the president and serve in the Cabinet. But there are also other agencies, including the Environmental Protection Agency, that are not cabinet agencies or White House offices but nonetheless function as other executive agencies. There are also independent agencies that are headed by commissioners who are protected from atwill presidential dismissal — and therefore have some policy independence from the administration. Examples include the Federal Reserve Board and the Federal Trade Commission. The rules promulgated by such agencies are not subject to the centralized process through which the White House reviews the regulations of other executive branch agencies. The agencies and departments of the Executive Branch engage in actions of many sorts, including rule-making, construction projects, policing, war-making, foreign policy talks and negotiations, and more. The president’s power comes from his or her authority as Commander in Chief of the military (section 2 of Article II) and from the authority to “take Care that the Laws be faithfully executed” (section 3 of Article II). And so while a presidential administration’s authority to make and enforce rules almost always arises from congressional statutes, presidents have also argued, especially 9 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 in the national security context, that they have inherent executive authority to undertake certain actions. We will cover administrative rule-making later in this course, but the upshot is that statutes often direct agencies to do certain things but without specifying precisely what to do in every instance. Agencies make rules to govern their enforcement of statutes. The process of rule making is public, includes public comment, and results in published regulations. For example, when Congress writes in a statute that the EPA shall establish such standards for air quality that are required to protect the public health, the agency studies the health effects of various pollutants, proposes detailed standards and regulations, solicits public comments, and then publishes a final set of regulations that it will then enforce. The States The executive branches of state governments differ from that of the federal government in several key ways. While the governor of each state is analogous to the president, most states provide for popular election of other executive positions, like the attorney general (the chief law enforcement officer), the lieutenant governor, and the commissioners of various other departments. While there has been much constitutional debate at the federal level over whether independent regulatory agencies are constitutional and whether the Constitution requires a unitary executive (meaning a system in which all executive power and control over executive officers ultimately rests in the president), many states have relatively weak governors and multiple sources of executive authority. Despite the plural nature of the executive in most states, the process of agency rulemaking to implement and enforce 10 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 statutes is broadly similar to that of the federal government. But there are some important differences among states and between some states and the federal government: whether courts defer to agency interpretations of statutes and whether the governor or the legislature can block agency rules before they take effect, for example. At this point, it is important to understand that, within the states, there are important sources and enforcers of law at the local level. City and county governments are responsible for the laws that impact many of us most directly, including zoning laws, traffic laws, business licensing, and noise and trash ordinances. Local governments take different forms, but they are often headed by an elected mayor and commission, sometimes called a city or town council or county commission. There are some important differences between cities (which might have a degree of independence from state government, in a kind of intra-state federalism) and counties, but we won’t go further into that here. One important feature of local government, though, is that the legislature and executive often are combined in a city council. The council both passes ordinances and directs the execution of ordinances. It sometimes even plays an adjudicative role, though its judgments may be appealed to local and state courts. The Judiciary The courts in both the federal system and the states share some common features. Most basically, when a party wants to compel another party to do something it believes the law requires (comply with a contract, pay damages, pay a fine, go 11 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 to jail, stop some conduct, etc.), it makes a complaint in a court. In civil actions (those between parties based on tort or contract - or otherwise not enforcing criminal statutes), a plaintiff will write a complaint that states the facts of the dispute and legal grounds upon which relief can be granted by the courts. The plaintiff serves this complaint on the defendant, thereby providing notice to the defendant, and then files the complaint with a court. Before getting into any dispute concerning the facts, the defendant may move to dismiss the complaint, either on grounds that the court lacks the power, or jurisdiction, to adjudicate the dispute or on grounds that, even if the facts alleged were all true, there is no legal basis for relief. If the complaint or some parts of it survive a motion to dismiss, the defendant must answer the complaint, setting out its version of the facts, denying or accepting the various assertions of liability, and setting out legal defenses. After this process of filing a complaint, adjudicating any motions to dismiss, and filing an answer, the case proceeds to discovery, during which the parties gather evidence from one another in the form of depositions, written questions, or demands to produce documents. After evidence is gathered, a party may move for summary judgment, arguing that, viewing the evidence in a light most favorable to the other side, no reasonable juror could possibly find for that other side. If the court does not grant summary judgment, a trial is held, either in front of a jury or only before a judge (known as a bench trial). After both sides have presented their evidence, the finder of fact will determine whether the legal standards at issue have been met, and the court will enter a judgment. For 12 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 most civil actions, the plaintiff must prove his or her case by a preponderance of the evidence, meaning only that it is more likely than not that the legal standard entitling him or her to relief was met. There are some laws, though, that require the plaintiff to prove the case by clear and convincing evidence. What burden a plaintiff must meet is called the burden of proof or standard of proof. In criminal prosecutions, a public prosecutor (a district attorney or United States Attorney), rather than a private plaintiff, makes the initial complaint. But filing a complaint with a court is not always sufficient in criminal law. Rather, there are generally two ways to start a criminal prosecution. For serious crimes, normally felonies that might subject a defendant to lengthy imprisonment, the prosecutor must present a case to a grand jury. The grand jury is composed of ordinary people, and it may or may not return an indictment depending on the strength of the evidence the prosecutor presents. (In practice, indictments are not at all difficult to secure.) After an indictment, the defendant may be arrested or summoned to appear in court. There, the defendant is arraigned, meaning subjected to a proceeding at which the defendant is informed of the charges and enters a plea. In most cases, the defendant will have made a plea bargain with the prosecution and so enters a guilty plea for the charges that have been negotiated. Less serious crimes, usually misdemeanors, may proceed by information, which is more like a civil complaint but filed here by a public prosecutor, and need not go through a grand jury for indictment. After arraignment, there is investigation, similar to civil discovery, and, ultimately, a plea or a trial. The trial, as in civil cases, may be before a jury or a judge. The burden of proof 13 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 the prosecutor must meet is, famously, guilt beyond a reasonable doubt. In both civil actions, the losing party may appeal to a hierarchically superior court after judgment is entered (whether after trial or on granting a motion to dismiss or for summary judgment – and with respect to some exceptional decisions, even during trial court litigation). After criminal convictions, the defendant may appeal, but the state generally may not appeal an acquittal, whether by jury or judge, on account of the constitutional prohibition on being “twice put in jeopardy.” The role of a court of appeals (or appellate court) is to determine whether something went wrong in the trial court that justifies reversing that court’s judgment or sending the case back down to the trial court for further litigation. Importantly, appellate courts are not concerned with re-determining the facts in a case. Rather, they are concerned with errors of law. Appellate courts may determine that the factual record does not support a trial court's legal conclusion or that a piece of evidence should not have been admitted as a matter of law, but they will not hear new evidence. And they generally reverse factual findings only in cases of clear error. Grounds for appeal can be, for example, that the instructions given to the jury misstated the law, that certain evidence should have been excluded or included, that a governing statute was misinterpreted, that the law applied was unconstitutional, or that the evidence was legally insufficient. Some of these judgments are within the discretion of the trial court, meaning that court is charged with exercising some judgment or engaging in some weighing and that its conclusions are given deference by reviewing courts of 14 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 appeals. Other judgments are purer issues of law that are reviewed by courts of appeals de novo, meaning with no deference to the judgment of the trial court. For example, appellate courts will review de novo a trial court’s interpretation of a statute. The standard of review refers to the method an appellate court will use to review the decision of the trial court: whether de novo, whether the trial court’s decision was an abuse of discretion, whether its factual judgment was clearly erroneous, and sometimes other formulations. The first job of an appellate advocate is to understand the standard of review an appeals court will apply to decide whether a trial court’s decision was wrong, as this will shape the type of arguments made to the court of appeals. In some states, there are only two layers of courts: trial courts and the state supreme court. But in most, as in the federal system, there are three layers: the trial or district court, the intermediate court of appeals, and a supreme court. Very often there is a right to appeal and to be heard (or at least read) by the intermediate appellate court, but the supreme court has discretion whether to hear an appeal from a decision of the intermediate court. The U.S. Supreme Court, for example, agrees to hear only about 1% of the cases submitted to it on appeal. The Feds The Judicial Branch of the federal government is defined in Article III of the U.S. Constitution. The judicial Power of the United States, shall be vested in one supreme Court, and in such inferior Courts as the Congress may from time to time ordain and establish. 15 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 Interestingly, the Constitution does not require the system of courts we have now that includes trial courts (called federal district courts) and intermediate appellate courts (called courts of appeals). Only the Supreme Court is created directly by Article III, but Congress has passed statutes establishing the lower courts per the power granted to it in the above clause. There are now over ninety judicial districts, each with a district court, and each district court is staffed by multiple districts judges. These districts fall within eleven federal circuits. Each circuit has a court of appeals that hears appeals from the districts within its territory. So, for example, federal cases in Athens, Georgia are brought in the United States District Court for the Middle District of Georgia. Any appeals from that district court are brought before the United States Court of Appeals for the Eleventh Circuit (which hears appeals from all district courts in Alabama, Florida, and Georgia). Appeals in circuit courts are usually heard by a panel of three judges, drawn from the court’s pool of judges. There are thirteen active judges on the Eleventh Circuit and a number of senior judges (who also sit on appellate panels). The Ninth Circuit, which includes California, has seats for twenty-nine active judges, and a large number of judges who have taken senior status. Decisions by circuit court panels are usually final and may be appealed only by petitioning for a writ of certiorari to the U.S. Supreme Court. As mentioned above, most such efforts at Supreme Court review are denied without explanation. Some cases, however, are first taken up by a larger panel of the circuit court of appeals, often all the active judges. This is known as an en banc proceeding. 16 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 The litigation process, in a nutshell, looks like this: There’s a complaint or criminal equivalent, efforts to dismiss the complaint, taking of evidence, motions for summary judgment, trial, and then appeals from any final judgments in the trial court. In the federal system, the ruling of a district court is appealed to the appropriate circuit court of appeals. A three-judge panel will hear the case. Its decision may be appealed to the whole circuit and an en banc proceeding requested, or that step can be skipped and a petition for a writ of certiori from the U.S. Supreme Court filed. Not every case, however, may be brought in every court. To hear and resolve a case, a court must have valid judicial power to do so. And so all courts, federal or state, must first decide whether they have the power to adjudicate the case. This judicial power is called jurisdiction. There are two types. First, the federal constitutional command to provide Due Process limits a court’s ability to subject a defendant to an adjudication where that litigant has had no significant ties to the court’s geographic range. To haul a litigant into court, the court must have personal jurisdiction over the litigant, meaning that the litigant’s ties to the jurisdiction must be sufficient, unless the litigant waives this protection. More importantly, though, and not subject to waiver by any parties is a court’s subject matter jurisdiction. This refers to the court’s power to speak to the issues raised in the litigation. Article III of the Constitution provides that federal courts have power over cases “arising under” the Constitution, federal laws, and treaties. Such disputes create a type of subject matter jurisdiction called federal question jurisdiction, because they call for an application of federal laws. Another common type of federal jurisdiction is diversity jurisdiction, 17 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 which gives federal courts the power to resolve any dispute between citizens of different states, even those arising only under state law, such as pure contract disputes. (Note that article III provides other grounds for federal jurisdiction, including in cases in which the United States is a party.) Article III also states that Congress may make exceptions and regulations to govern federal court jurisdiction. It has done so with respect to diversity jurisdiction, providing that disputes between citizens of different states that do not raise federal questions may only be brought in federal court if the amount in controversy exceeds $75,000. (It has also provided that there are some cases that may only be brought in federal courts, providing exclusive jurisdiction. One example is actions for bankruptcy.) One last word about federal courts for now. Federal judges are nominated by the President and confirmed by the Senate. They are then constitutionally protected from dismissal and given life tenure and salary protection. Only impeachment in the House and conviction in the Senate for high crimes and misdemeanors can result in removal from the bench. These protections from the other branches are efforts to promote the independence of the federal judiciary. The States State courts are where most disputes are litigated and most crimes prosecuted. Breach of contract, slip and fall torts, automobile accidents, zoning violations, murders, and many of the causes of action that come to mind are disputes over the application of state law and are resolved in state courts. Again, to exert judicial authority over a litigant, the court must have personal jurisdiction over that litigant. So someone 18 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 with no ties at all to West Virginia cannot be made to defend a lawsuit there. As noted above, the tripartite system of the federal courts is often mirrored in state courts. But there are in states specialized courts: small claims courts, family courts, probate courts (wills), local government courts, drug courts, misdemeanor courts, and the like. Often times, appeals from such courts are first heard in state trial courts before proceeding through the appellate courts. The procedures for bringing complaints and for conducting litigation differs substantially from state to state - but is broadly similar to the outline sketched above. One striking difference between federal courts and state courts is that in nearly all states some judges are elected by the people rather than nominated and confirmed. A final note: state courts may hear cases raising not only issues of state law but also of federal law. Sometimes when a litigant is sued in state court and there are issues of federal law (or any other ground for federal jurisdiction), the litigant can remove the case to a federal district court. Litigation then proceeds there, at least on those issues successfully removed. But if a case involving federal law is litigated through the state court system, then, after the highest state court has issued a judgment or refused to hear the case, a losing party may petition the U.S. Supreme Court for certiorari, just as if the case had been resolved by a federal court of appeals. The U.S. Supreme Court regularly hears cases appealing judgments of state supreme courts. The Common Law We have described courts thus far as though they adjudicate the application of laws created by other 19 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 institutions, most often legislatures. This is not so. For ages, courts have been a source of law’s content, not just a body charged with deciding cases under it. The “common law” refers to the body of law created by courts in case-by-case decisions over time. Almost all states in the U.S. are “common law” jurisdictions, meaning that courts will apply judge-made law to settle disputes where the legislatures have not superseded such law with statutes. The law governing liability for accidents (a part of a field of law called tort law), the law governing contracts, and even, in ages gone by, criminal law, have been the product of judicial development over time. To know what the law is, you need to read relevant cases that announce rules or read books that gather the cases and synthesize their resolutions into rules. We will talk more about rules and legal argument in the sections that follow. For now, it is enough to observe that when a court decides a case, it gives a rationale. The common law arises from applying such rationales in future cases. Next Steps This introduction has outlined the major structures of the legal system we have in the United States. But we have not yet discussed the substance of the law, how it is made and argued, or how to identify it. The next section broadens our inquiry. Instead of thinking about our law, we will turn to understanding the law a little better. 20 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 Marbury v. Madison, 1 Cranch 137 (1803) The famous case of Marbury arose following the election of 1801, in which President John Adams, a Federalist, was defeated by Thomas Jefferson, a Democratic-Republican. The Federalists, faced with losing control of the executive and legislative branches, passed the Judiciary Act of 1801. The Act expanded the number of district and circuit court positions, allowing these new and vacant seats to be filled by the lame-duck Federalist president and confirmed by the outgoing Federalist Congress. These last-minute appointees became known as the “Midnight Judges,” and the plaintiff, William Marbury, was one of them. In order to effectuate the appointment of the freshly-minted judges, newly-appointed Chief Justice John Marshall (who wrote this opinion) was asked to deliver to each judge their commission. (Chief Justice Marshall had been President Adams’ Secretary of State and continued acting in the role through the end of President Adams’ term, at the President’s request.) Most of the commissions made it into the hands of their recipients, but Marbury’s was among those that were not delivered before President Adams left office. After President Jefferson was sworn in, he ordered the new Secretary of State, James Madison, not to deliver the remaining commissions. Because Marbury could not assume his new judicial post, without the commission, he filed a petition for a writ of mandamus directly in the Supreme Court. (A writ of mandamus is a judicial order for a public official to do, or to 21 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 refrain from doing, some non-discretionary act.) In short, Marbury sought to have the Supreme Court order Secretary Madison to deliver the commission to which Marbury was entitled. One of the issues before the Court (which is discussed in the excerpt of the opinion below) is whether Marbury was authorized to file the writ directly with the Supreme Court. The Supreme Court's authority to hear cases – its jurisdiction – is defined by Article III of the Constitution. Writs of mandamus are not specifically contained within the list of cases or controversies over which the Court has original jurisdiction. Original jurisdiction means that the case can be submitted directly to the Supreme Court, rather than coming to the Court on appeal from a state supreme court or a lower federal court. Here is the relevant text: In all cases affecting ambassadors, other public ministers and consuls, and those in which a state shall be party, the Supreme Court shall have original jurisdiction. In all the other cases before mentioned, the Supreme Court shall have appellate jurisdiction, both as to law and fact, with such exceptions, and under such regulations as the Congress shall make. The other law relevant to the question whether the Supreme Court can issue a write of mandamus itself, without having the case come to it on appeal, is the above-mentioned Judiciary Act of 1801. It specifically states that the Supreme Court has the power to issue writs of mandamus. The Court agreed with Marbury that (a) Marbury was entitled to the commission, (b) that a writ of mandamus was 22 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 an appropriate remedy, and (c) that the Judiciary Act of 1789 purported to grant the Supreme Court original jurisdiction to issue writs of mandamus to public officials. But this raised two further – and critical – questions: 1. Is the grant of original jurisdiction in the Judiciary Act consistent with Article III of the Constitution, which contains a more limited definition of the Court’s original jurisdiction? 2. If a law is unconstitutional, do courts have the power and/or obligation not to enforce it? The answer to this question defines a basic allocation of authority between the courts and the political branches. What follows is the opinion for the Court by Chief Justice Marshall resolving these questions. Marshall, J.: .... The act to establish the judicial courts of the United States authorizes the supreme court “to issue writs of mandamus, in cases warranted by the principles and usages of law, to any courts appointed, or persons holding office, under the authority of the United States.” The secretary of state, being a person holding an office under the authority of the United States, is precisely within the letter of the description; and if this court is not authorized to issue a writ of mandamus to such an officer, it must be because the law is unconstitutional, and therefore absolutely 23 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 incapable of conferring the authority, and assigning the duties which its words purport to confer and assign. The constitution vests the whole judicial power of the United States in one supreme court, and such inferior courts as congress shall, from time to time, ordain and establish. This power is expressly extended to all cases arising under the laws of the United States; and consequently, in some form, may be exercised over the present case; because the right claimed is given by a law of the United States. In the distribution of this power it is declared that “the supreme court shall have original jurisdiction in all cases affecting ambassadors, other public ministers and consuls, and those in which a state shall be a party. In all other cases, the supreme court shall have appellate jurisdiction.” It has been insisted, at the bar, that as the original grant of jurisdiction, to the supreme and inferior courts, is general, and the clause, assigning original jurisdiction to the supreme court, contains no negative or restrictive words; the power remains to the legislature, to assign original jurisdiction to that court in other cases than those specified in the article which has been recited; provided those cases belong to the judicial power of the United States. If it had been intended to leave it in the discretion of the legislature to apportion the judicial power between the supreme and inferior courts according to the will of that body, it would certainly have been useless to have proceeded further than to have defined the judicial power, and the tribunals in which it should be vested. The subsequent part of the section is mere surplusage, is entirely without meaning, if such is to be the construction. If congress remains at liberty to give this court appellate jurisdiction, where the constitution has 24 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 declared their jurisdiction shall be original; and original jurisdiction where the constitution has declared it shall be appellate; the distribution of jurisdiction, made in the constitution, is form without substance. Affirmative words are often, in their operation, negative of other objects than those affirmed; and in this case, a negative or exclusive sense must be given to them or they have no operation at all. It cannot be presumed that any clause in the constitution is intended to be without effect; and therefore such a construction is inadmissible, unless the words require it. If the solicitude of the convention, respecting our peace with foreign powers, induced a provision that the supreme court should take original jurisdiction in cases which might be supposed to affect them; yet the clause would have proceeded no further than to provide for such cases, if no further restriction on the powers of congress had been intended. That they should have appellate jurisdiction in all other cases, with such exceptions as congress might make, is no restriction; unless the words be deemed exclusive of original jurisdiction. When an instrument organizing fundamentally a judicial system, divides it into one supreme, and so many inferior courts as the legislature may ordain and establish; then enumerates its powers, and proceeds so far to distribute them, as to define the jurisdiction of the supreme court by declaring the cases in which it shall take original jurisdiction, and that in others it shall take appellate jurisdiction; the plain import of the words seems to be, that in one class of cases its jurisdiction is original, and not appellate; in the other it is appellate, and not original. If any other construction would render the clause inoperative, that is an additional reason for 25 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 rejecting such other construction, and for adhering to their obvious meaning. To enable this court then to issue a mandamus, it must be shewn to be an exercise of appellate jurisdiction, or to be necessary to enable them to exercise appellate jurisdiction. It has been stated at the bar that the appellate jurisdiction may be exercised in a variety of forms, and that if it be the will of the legislature that a mandamus should be used for that purpose, that will must be obeyed. This is true, yet the jurisdiction must be appellate, not original. It is the essential criterion of appellate jurisdiction, that it revises and corrects the proceedings in a cause already instituted, and does not create that cause. Although, therefore, a mandamus may be directed to courts, yet to issue such a writ to an officer for the delivery of a paper, is in effect the same as to sustain an original action for that paper, and therefore seems not to belong to appellate, but to original jurisdiction. Neither is it necessary in such a case as this, to enable the court to exercise its appellate jurisdiction. The authority, therefore, given to the supreme court, by the act establishing the judicial courts of the United States, to issue writs of mandamus to public officers, appears not to be warranted by the constitution; and it becomes necessary to enquire whether a jurisdiction, so conferred, can be exercised. [And so the Court here has answered the first question, highlighted above, in the negative: this aspect of the Judiciary Act is unconstitutional. It must now answer the second, the question that makes this case the most famous case in U.S. constitutional law: Should or must courts enforce unconstitutional acts?] 26 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 The question, whether an act, repugnant to the constitution, can become the law of the land, is a question deeply interesting to the United States; but, happily, not of an intricacy proportioned to its interest. It seems only necessary to recognize certain principles, supposed to have been long and well established, to decide it. That the people have an original right to establish, for their future government, such principles as, in their opinion, shall most conduce to their own happiness, is the basis, on which the whole American fabric has been erected. The exercise of this original right is a very great exertion; nor can it, nor ought it to be frequently repeated. The principles, therefore, so established, are deemed fundamental. And as the authority, from which they proceed, is supreme, and can seldom act, they are designed to be permanent. This original and supreme will organizes the government, and assigns, to different departments, their respective powers. It may either stop here; or establish certain limits not to be transcended by those departments. The government of the United States is of the latter description. The powers of the legislature are defined, and limited; and that those limits may not be mistaken, or forgotten, the constitution is written. To what purpose are powers limited, and to what purpose is that limitation committed to writing, if these limits may, at any time, be passed by those intended to be restrained? The distinction, between a government with limited and unlimited powers, is abolished, if those limits do not confine the persons on whom they are imposed, and if acts prohibited and acts allowed, are of equal obligation. It is a proposition too plain to be contested, that the constitution controls any legislative act 27 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 repugnant to it; or, that the legislature may alter the constitution by an ordinary act. Between these alternatives there is no middle ground. The constitution is either a superior, paramount law, unchangeable by ordinary means, or it is on a level with ordinary legislative acts, and like other acts, is alterable when the legislature shall please to alter it. If the former part of the alternative be true, then a legislative act contrary to the constitution is not law: if the latter part be true, then written constitutions are absurd attempts, on the part of the people, to limit a power, in its own nature illimitable. Certainly all those who have framed written constitutions contemplate them as forming the fundamental and paramount law of the nation, and consequently the theory of every such government must be, that an act of the legislature, repugnant to the constitution, is void. This theory is essentially attached to a written constitution, and is consequently to be considered, by this court, as one of the fundamental principles of our society. It is not therefore to be lost sight of in the further consideration of this subject. If an act of the legislature, repugnant to the constitution, is void, does it, notwithstanding its invalidity, bind the courts, and oblige them to give it effect? Or, in other words, though it be not law, does it constitute a rule as operative as if it was a law? This would be to overthrow in fact what was established in theory; and would seem, at first view, an absurdity too gross to be insisted on. It shall, however, receive a more attentive consideration. It is emphatically the province and duty of the judicial department to say what the law is. Those who apply the rule 28 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 to particular cases, must of necessity expound and interpret that rule. If two laws conflict with each other, the courts must decide on the operation of each. So if a law be in opposition to the constitution; if both the law and the constitution apply to a particular case, so that the court must either decide that case conformably to the law, disregarding the constitution; or conformably to the constitution, disregarding the law; the court must determine which of these conflicting rules governs the case. This is of the very essence of judicial duty. If then the courts are to regard the constitution; and the constitution is superior to any ordinary act of the legislature; the constitution, and not such ordinary act, must govern the case to which they both apply. Those then who controvert the principle that the constitution is to be considered, in court, as a paramount law, are reduced to the necessity of maintaining that courts must close their eyes on the constitution, and see only the law. This doctrine would subvert the very foundation of all written constitutions. It would declare that an act, which, according to the principles and theory of our government, is entirely void; is yet, in practice, completely obligatory. It would declare, that if the legislature shall do what is expressly forbidden, such act, notwithstanding the express prohibition, is in reality effectual. It would be giving to the legislature a practical and real omnipotence, with the same breath which professes to restrict their powers within narrow limits. It is prescribing limits, and declaring that those limits may be passed as pleasure. That it thus reduces to nothing what we have deemed the greatest improvement on political institutions – a written 29 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 constitution – would of itself be sufficient, in America, where written constitutions have been viewed with so much reverence, for rejecting the construction. But the peculiar expressions of the constitution of the United States furnish additional arguments in favour of its rejection. The judicial power of the United States is extended to all cases arising under the constitution. Could it be the intention of those who gave this power, to say that, in using it, the constitution should not be looked into? That a case arising under the constitution should be decided without examining the instrument under which it arises? This is too extravagant to be maintained. In some cases then, the constitution must be looked into by the judges. And if they can open it at all, what part of it are they forbidden to read, or to obey? There are many other parts of the constitution which serve to illustrate this subject. It is declared that “no tax or duty shall be laid on articles exported from any state.” Suppose a duty on the export of cotton, of tobacco, or of flour; and a suit instituted to recover it. Ought judgment to be rendered in such a case? ought the judges to close their eyes on the constitution, and only see the law. The constitution declares that “no bill of attainder or ex post facto law shall be passed.” If, however, such a bill should be passed and a person should be prosecuted under it; must the court condemn to death those victims whom the constitution endeavors to preserve? 30 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 “No person,” says the constitution, “shall be convicted of treason unless on the testimony of two witnesses to the same overt act, or on confession in open court.” Here the language of the constitution is addressed especially to the courts. It prescribes, directly for them, a rule of evidence not to be departed from. If the legislature should change that rule, and declare one witness, or a confession out of court, sufficient for conviction, must the constitutional principle yield to the legislative act? From these, and many other selections which might be made, it is apparent, that the framers of the constitution contemplated that instrument, as a rule for the government of courts, as well as of the legislature. Why otherwise does it direct the judges to take an oath to support it? This oath certainly applies, in an especial manner, to their conduct in their official character. How immoral to impose it on them, if they were to be used as the instruments, and the knowing instruments, for violating what they swear to support? The oath of office, too, imposed by the legislature, is completely demonstrative of the legislative opinion on this subject. It is in these words, “I do solemnly swear that I will administer justice without respect to persons, and do equal right to the poor and to the rich; and that I will faithfully and impartially discharge all the duties incumbent on me as according to the best of my abilities and understanding, agreeably to the constitution, and laws of the United States.” Why does a judge swear to discharge his duties agreeably to the constitution of the United States, if that constitution forms no rule for his government? if it is closed upon him, and cannot be inspected by him? 31 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 If such be the real state of things, this is worse than solemn mockery. To prescribe, or to take this oath, becomes equally a crime. It is also not entirely unworthy of observation, that in declaring what shall be the supreme law of the land, the constitution itself is first mentioned; and not the laws of the United States generally, but those only which shall be made in pursuance of the constitution, have that rank. Thus, the particular phraseology of the constitution of the United States confirms and strengthens the principle, supposed to be essential to all written constitutions, that a law repugnant to the constitution is void; and that courts, as well as other departments, are bound by that instrument. The rule must be discharged. 32 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 Meeting 2: Legal Systems and Arguments The Law We’ve so far gotten an overview of the American legal system: what its parts are and what these parts do. But we’ve talked about the law as if we know what it is and as if we have only to look at what these parts have done to know what the law is. There is a more basic set of questions and more basic skills we need in order to understand “the law.” Isn’t that what law school is for? Frank Abagnale, the anti-hero whose adventures were chronicled in the film Catch Me If You Can, forged a transcript and passed the bar exam never having attended law school. Eight weeks of study, apparently, was enough for him to pass the exam on his third try. People I’ve heard discuss the film Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 often cite this fact as evidence of Mr. Abagnale's unusual gifts. I, too, was astounded by Mr. Abagnale’s resourcefulness and adventures, but I didn’t find it at all exceptional that he was able to pass the bar. You see, law is just not very hard. Any reasonably intelligent person can fairly quickly learn enough about law to understand its practice and to make legal arguments. Further experience can help perfect one’s sense of what makes arguments compelling or weak. But the basic skill and knowledge are within your grasp. Let’s get started For many outsiders, law is a discipline seemingly steeped in obscure methods and arcane procedures. Many entering law students think that a lawyer’s training is in knowing what the laws are. They believe they will be expected to master a list of laws in each subject and that lawyers are people who know these lists. The way we often teach it, as case after case illustrating discrete types of laws and disputes, may initially reinforce this assumption. But it could not be more wrong. As with most fields, expertise in law lies in knowing how to learn more of it, not in an encyclopedic knowledge of all its details. There are concepts and methods that, once acquired, allow you to do law: to read it, understand it, criticize it, and make it. Put simply, becoming a lawyer or a citizen versed in law is about learning a set of concepts and a language, not a list of laws or where to look laws up. Here’s as good a starting point as any: What is a legal argument? It would seem to be an argument about the law. And so we must ask what the law is and what sorts of arguments one could have about it. 34 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 At its most basic, and sweeping some philosophical problems under the rug for the moment, the body of law is a set of information that will be part of the grounds on which a court will decide whether to compel an entity – whether a private person, a corporation, or a government official – to do something it wishes not to do. Susan wants John to do something, and the rest of society, acting through a court, will force him to do it if the court identifies a law that says he must. When Susan says that the law compels John to do this undesired thing and John disagrees, they are having a legal dispute and will make legal arguments. A legal dispute involves a set of: – one or more laws, – facts, – and the undesired things the court may order if it finds, from the facts, a violation of the law. The body of information that is the law itself consists primarily of statutes (acts of legislatures), administrative rules (acts of governmental agencies), contracts (acts of private parties), and common law (the collected acts of courts that have made law to decide cases). These laws attempt to guide behavior by stating that if some class of facts occurs, then some official judgment should follow. No matter how long or convoluted their text or the judicial cases announcing them, all primary laws boil down to: If X occurred, then a court should order Y. The trick is translating the typically vague or ambiguous text in which a law is encoded into this simple form. The opinions of courts in other cases (or the informational outputs of other 35 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 legal institutions) can and sometimes must be used when deciding among possible translations. The facts of the case are another bit of input information that may be contested by parties. In the above formulation, whether X occurred, even if we agree about what the law means by X, might be uncertain. For example, we may agree that the victim was shot at point-blank range. But the defendant is only guilty of murder if, among other things, she was the one who killed the victim. To show a law violation is to show that the law’s criterion is satisfied by the facts to a given degree of certainty, called the standard of proof. For example, we must put on evidence that convinces us “beyond a reasonable doubt” that the criteria for murder, which include the fact that it was the defendant who caused the victim’s death, have been met in order to conclude the murder law was violated by the defendant. The undesired thing that the defendant is fighting to avoid might be paying money to another private citizen or the state, or serving a prison sentence, or ceasing to operate a factory. And the court’s judgment will come in the form of yet more information, orders and opinions, that may serve as part of the input for future judgments. When a court orders such an undesired thing, we call it a remedy. A legal argument The job of the lawyer, in the end, is to identify the relevant informational inputs – the applicable law and the relevant facts – and to argue about how they constrain the possible output (the judgment). “Your honor, facts x, y, and z occurred here. And law A says that if those three things happened, then 36 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 the defendant must pay the plaintiff damages.” Or: “Your honor, the law says that a fine of $100 must be paid by anyone driving between ten and twenty miles per hour above the speed limit on state highways. Here, radar shows the defendant was driving seventeen miles per hour above the posted speed limit of state highway four. Therefore, he must pay $100." A basic legal argument goes in several parts: 1. Separate the dispute between the parties into separate possible legal grounds for liability, i.e., the separate possible law violations. 2. For each possibly applicable legal ground, parse the law to determine the criteria, X, under which it will be found to be violated; and 3. Argue that HERE, X should or should not be found BECAUSE (at which point you apply the facts to determine whether the criteria have been met). Again, you must separate the overall dispute into component legal issues. Then, for each issue, formulate criteria that will suffice to prove a violation. Finally, apply the facts to determine whether the criteria were met. Your job as a lawyer is first to bring order to the stream of facts relating to a dispute (and, believe me, aggrieved parties will deliver an uncoordinated jumble of facts and outrages, and they will argue that all this means they should win a bunch of money). Identify the separate complaints that an aggrieved party is making, and match these with potential grounds for liability, whether based on contract or publicly- 37 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 made laws. This involves some skill and experience searching and sifting through laws. Fear not, we’ll return to why it’s not all that hard to understand law’s sources and to figure out, without studying a complete list, what the law probably is and where it is probably recorded. To reinforce how legal argument works, let’s imagine a lawyer as an archer. Your first task is to set up targets at which to shoot. Given a dispute, you need first to understand what laws are implicated, i.e. which targets to select. One by one, for each law, set up the target by explaining what the criteria are for proving a violation. This may involve acknowledging ambiguity or disagreement among other courts that have applied the law. Indeed, we might expend considerable energy arguing over what the target should be and what its criteria should be. Next, reach into your quiver (the set of facts) and fire arrows at the target. That is, explain why the law is or is not violated using the facts of our case. Set up targets. Describe what it means to hit one. Fire arrows and explain why they do or do not hit the target. The most basic legal argument goes: Plaintiff argues that Defendant is liable for violating law A. Law A is violated if criteria X is satisfied. HERE, X is (or is not) satisfied, BECAUSE the facts do or (do not) satisfy X. Step one: Identify the law that applies. Step two: Identify that law’s criteria. Step three: Apply the law to the facts. I have found that the archery analogy, emphasizing order, law identification, and deployment of facts, helps students to understand what makes for a good argument. Let us consider a concrete example of a fight and possible legal arguments. 38 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 Example Please read Orin Kerr’s blog post, Bad Answers, Good Answers, a n d Te r r i fi c A n s w e r s , a t h t t p : / / v o l o k h . c o m / p o s t s / 1168382003.html. Law is, to the contrary, hard What I've discussed is just the most basic part of the basic skill of arguing about law. Law itself is, to me, an intensely fascinating subject. I study it as the set of rules we use to govern ourselves. It could hardly get more interesting than to think deeply about why we have decided to govern ourselves this way and whether we could do a better job of it. Such questions call for the full use of other areas of knowledge: psychology, economics, statistics, sociology, physics, philosophy, and just about every field you can think of that grapples with what is really going on inside of and between us humans. Even though I’ve suggested here that law is easy, there is an important sense in which I’m wrong about that. While it is indeed easy to understand how we go about law, getting law right is very hard indeed. In fact, the most important piece of advice I got from a law school professor and that I continually turn over and keep at the forefront of my mind is: “Make the easy problems hard.” It may be easy to learn how to make a legal argument: Parties are fighting about something. Law A speaks to that thing and has criteria X. Here X is met or not met based on the given set of facts. 39 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 But to make a really great argument, we need to appreciate why the parties are fighting, what justifies their positions. It’s in understanding, deeply, the strength of the intuitions justifying your opponent’s position, that you can understand what law A really concerns, and why figuring out and applying criteria X is, in fact, a hard problem that may divide courts. My point here is only that it’s easy to be able to undertake this very hard work. What are the laws? In the last section, we started with an explanation of the basic skill of making an argument by connecting a law with the facts of a case. Like an archer, you set up a target (the law relevant to an aspect of the dispute), and you then fire your arrows (the facts of your case), arguing that they either do or do not hit the target BECAUSE (insert your argument for why the facts do or do not meet the criteria established by the law here). Rinse and repeat for each law applicable to the dispute. That's the core mechanic at the heart of litigationoriented practice. But how do we know what the laws are? And what kinds of arguments count as good "BECAUSE arguments"? There are three basic elements essential to a solid understanding of legal systems. First, you need to know how the legal system works so that you can tell what the laws are, what they should be, and how they are enforced. Second, you need to know, mechanically, how to make an argument (first introduced in the last section). And third you need to know how to judge 40 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 the quality of an argument. What kinds of arguments are “in bounds,” and what makes them relevant. In this section, I’m going to show you what the basic areas of a legal system are: Tort, Contract, and Criminal Law, all governed by Constitutional Law and Procedure. This subject arrangement is not arbitrary and knowing how to derive it will help you to develop intuitions for what the law should be in any give case. A legal system Let’s talk about legal systems. How do we know what the laws are or should be? You no doubt have some familiarity with contracts, lawsuits, prosecutions, and the like. You surely know, as well, of wills and gifts. All these things seem like possible subjects of court cases, all of them laws of one kind or another. How do we make sense of this jumble of things a court might have to deal with? It’s easiest if we go back to first principles, and so you’ll need some patience with abstraction. Start by thinking not of formal, developed legal systems, but of mere collections of people. “In the beginning,” suppose we have a group of people who decide that life will be easier if they work together. This group decides it will undertake certain joint projects and has some ability to coerce its members to cooperate. Maybe all they can do is kick you out. Maybe they can beat you up, imprison you, make you pay a fine, or make you compensate someone else in the group. A legal system is the set of rules – call them “laws” – for figuring out how this group, or “public,” will deploy whatever coercion it can muster. So we see that a legal system is an 41 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 attribute of just about any collective you can think of: a nation state, a corporation, a fraternity, or your local PTA. They all have legal systems, and, guess what, all of these systems have the same, basic structure. Let’s turn to what that foundational structure is. Classifying the Laws One of the very first things any “public” must decide is how its laws should be made and enforced. And the most basic element of each of those decisions is who should do so. You see, the business of law is the creation and transmission of information. For example, a legislature may draft a law, pass it, transmit it to the chief executive, who signs it. Then, when a case arises, a court reads that law, interprets it, and creates information in the form of a judgment, which is then the basis for action by others. So a legal system can be conceived as a set of rules to manage the creation and passing of messages among various groups within a public. (If you’re a computer programmer and are starting to think this sounds like objectoriented programming, yes, the connections are deep, because both endeavors are code-based efforts to manage complex systems.) To proceed further, we need a convenient term to describe subgroups within the public that will be making and passing on legal information. I’ll call these groups institutions. The Congress is an institution, with many sub-institutions. A corporation is an institution. They’re all over. But to understand the basic structure of legal systems – and to construct a simple atlas of the laws – we only need to talk about two fundamental types of institutions: public and private. 42 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 Public institutions, like legislatures, presidents or city councils, are established by the collective to work on behalf of the collective. Private institutions, like a corporation, a single individual, or contracting parties, are the creations of private individuals meant to serve the interests of those individuals, even if those interests are altruistic or publicly minded. Let’s match these two kinds of institutions, public and private, with two basic steps in applying law: making and enforcement. Law can be made by either (a) private institutions or (b) public institutions. Private institutions make contracts, wills, and gifts, for example. Public institutions, like legislatures, administrative agencies, and courts, make statutes, regulations, and common law rules. Next, law can also be enforced by (a) private institutions or (b) public institutions. By “enforced,” here, I mean control over whether a cause of action is brought. Can you, a private citizen, go to court and sue, privately prosecuting, or does the decision whether to enforce a law and prosecute rest with a public official, a public prosecutor? Private citizens often sue to enforce contracts or for compensation for injuries arising from the violation of some common-law or statutory duty, like employment discrimination or negligent injury. Arranging these possibilities in a chart, we can see that familiar legal fields, the ones you’d study in your first year of law school, emerge as categories from our “who makes and who enforces” questions. 43 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 These are the basic legal areas: Contract (privately made, privately prosecuted), Tort (publicly made, privately prosecuted), Parens Patriae (privately made, publicly prosecuted - and almost, but not quite, an empty set), and Criminal Law (publicly made, publicly prosecuted). Beware, these are my labels. Gifts are part of Contract Law in my atlas, and civil rights statutes giving individuals a right to sue violators are a part of Tort Law. Other academics and practitioners might not use these same labels, but our goal is understanding legal systems in general. Once you know that, then learning the particulars of any given system is just picking up jargon. So why is this a useful map? For one, it helps students of law understand why they take Contract, Tort, and Criminal Law as foundational, first-year courses. In doing so, you’re functionally covering the whole legal system. For us, it will 44 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 help to understand, in broad outline, why laws come from the institutions they do and what the limits on such laws should be. Put simply, the constraints on a contract, statute, or other type of law almost always come back to the characteristics of the institutions that made it. Therefore, whether you’re trying to argue that a law, contract, or regulation is valid, is invalid, should be interpreted in a particular way, or anything else, the right kinds of arguments will be found in thinking hard about the characteristics of the law’s drafter. A Functional Atlas The above is a classification of the laws of a legal system. But legal systems have rules, sometimes called secondary rules, that specify how a law must be made, how far it can go, how it should be interpreted, and how it should be enforced. Constitutional Law is the set of rules governing which institutions can make which kinds of laws (so-called structural rules, like voting rules, age requirements, and the like) and what the permissible contents of laws are (which you can perhaps lump together as “rights,” such as that the law may not abridge the freedom of speech). Similarly, we can call the rules governing who can bring and how they can bring actions to enforce law Procedure. Here's the full map of arbitrary legal systems: 45 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 To re-emphasize: Constitutional Law is the set of secondary laws governing the making of laws. Procedure is the set of secondary laws governing the prosecution of law violations. There is a public and private Constitutional Law and a public and private Procedure. One of the goals of my academic work has been to exploit this symmetry to show how these areas of law nicely mirror one another, with differences owing primarily to the generic difference between public and private institutions. For example, the private Constitutional Law of Contracts, or what all lawyers just call “contract law,” comprises making law according to doctrines of offer and acceptance and a body of of doctrine associated with “unconscionability” that can be used to invalidate unfair contracts. The public Constitutional Law often has more rulelike procedures for law enactment (such as passage of the same statutory text in the House and Senate) but also has a body of doctrine, here associated with specific rights and “due process” more generally, to invalidate statutes. 46 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 The key advantage to learning law in these terms is that we can develop intuitions and arguments about what the law should be based on the qualities of the institution at hand. For example, individuals typically act in their own self-interest. If we’re going to allow them to make a law that binds others, we should probably only do so if all those others consent. And, indeed, the basic structural provision of what I call the Constitutional Law of Contracts is consent: that a privately made law may only come from a unanimous private group containing all those who would be bound. Public agents are expected, in contrast, to act in the public interest. And our secondary rules governing the public making of law are tuned to trying to ensure good agency (by looking to see that proper and usually detailed procedures were followed and scrutinizing more closely than we do with contracts the fit of a law with our more basic norms - freedom of speech and equality, e.g.). Next Steps Importantly, we now have in hand a map of the legal system, Contract, Tort, Criminal Law, governed by Constitutional Law and Procedure. We’re going to need to go over some examples to see how the public or private identity of the institution plays a primary role in the content of Constitutional Law and Procedure. That will give us an abstract understanding of legal systems, a set of expectations about how laws are probably made and governed. Then, we can begin to look at how our system, in particular, is constituted. What are the public institutions? What kinds of 47 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 legal information does each produce, and how does information flow among institutions? Once you know these things, you’ll be able to take a dispute or an issue and know where to look and how to think about what the law is and what the law should be. Should we leave this issue to parties to contract over? Should we pass a law that creates rights to sue? Should we create a criminal law? What kinds of sanctions should there be? If you know what the law should be, then, because the law very often is what you think it should be, you’ll know where to find it and how to argue about it. Causes of action Let’s get to some nuts and bolts. How do legal actions work? Every suit, no matter the area, has the same form. There are discrete, but not air-tight, steps to convincing a court that the defendant should lose – meaning, be coerced to pay money or otherwise do something he or she wishes not to do. Here they are: Duty, Breach, Causation, Damages, Defenses. Whether it’s Contract, Tort, or Criminal Law, liability is established by showing that there existed a duty, established by a law, that the defendant breached that duty thereby causing harm to the plaintiff, and that there are no relevant defenses to the breach. If you know this legal workflow and you understand the institutional differences between the areas of law, you’ll have an easy time learning how the steps are a little different in each area, and you’ll be able to move between areas with relative ease. That’s the power of abstraction and why it’s 48 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 worth the effort. Rather than learn a large catalog of skills and procedures for accident law and a completely separate set for lease agreements, we learn the general structure for all lawsuits and how the institutional definition of an area might affect how the general principles are made into specific requirements. If we also know how to formulate legal arguments about these steps, we’re off to the races. Duty The very first question we must address is what the duty, if any, of the defendant was. Duties are what we might casually think of as “the law,” the things you must do or not do. Duties can be created in statutes by legislatures or administrative bodies (think speed limits and nearly all criminal laws), by courts refining the “common law,” or by private individuals in contracts. Each institution will have different rules governing how it can make duties and what kinds of duties it is permitted to create. For contracts, we examine whether the group of private entities that will be bound by the terms of the contract consented, usually by looking to see whether someone made an offer of terms that the others accepted. If so, the contract operates very much like a statute, specifying that one of the parties is under a duty, say, to deliver a car and that the other is under a duty to remit payment. There really isn’t much difference between this kind of duty, to deliver a car under a contract, and a duty to obey a speed limit under a public statute or regulation. Both are “laws” that courts will back up with coercion, though possibly using different remedies. 49 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 Courts explicitly create duties in certain areas not governed by legislation, and they do so by deciding cases. Historically, Tort, private lawsuits to recover for violations of publicly made law, has been composed primarily of judge-made duties. Suits for injuries sustained in various types of accidents, for example, are the bulk of what first-year students study in tort classes, and these are often governed by the body of prior cases courts have decided. Today, numerous legislatively enacted statutes also provide for and govern private lawsuits. For example, the Civil Rights Act, among other things, creates duties on public accommodations owners and employers not to discriminate against customers and employees on account of race, and it gives private individuals rights to sue if these duties are violated. (Also note that many duties prohibit conduct only if accompanied by a particular mental state, or mens rea in the dead language lawyers sometimes use. So, I've only violated the duty contained in some murder statutes if I purposefully or knowingly kill another human being.) No matter the source, the question is what conduct the law requires or prohibits. That is duty. Breach Just because the law imposed a duty on the defendant does not mean the defendant violated the law by breaching that duty. The question, here, is whether the facts show that defendant did something or failed to do something the law required. So if the law imposed on me an obligation when driving to operate my car with the care of an ordinary, competent driver under all the circumstances, whether I 50 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 breached the duty would turn on an analysis of the facts and an interpretation of the duty. Perhaps the court will compare my facts with those in other driving cases to see whether courts have further specified what kinds of driving fall short of the general duty of care. Same thing under Contract and Criminal Law. Regardless of the source, we look at the duty the law imposes and then at the facts of our case to see whether that duty was breached – by not performing a contract or by committing a crime, for example. As a matter of practice, the act of comparing a contractual, statutory, or judge-made duty with the facts will sometimes be impossible. The case in front of you may not clearly fall on one side of the violation/no-violation line, forcing you to look more carefully at what the duty is and perhaps sending you back to step one to restate, refine, or amend the duty. This can involve making new law either through interpretation – deciding what a written formulation of a duty “really” means – or through judicial amendment of rules from its own prior decisions. Consider this example. Suppose you have a case involving an accountant who did a bad job that resulted in your client’s losing a lot of money. Suppose further that your client never hired the accountant but had nonetheless relied on the accountant’s work for someone else. First, note that we are wondering whether there is some publicly created law that would allow your client to sue to recover damages. The question, then, is whether there is a tort duty to your client that the accountant violated. (Why is this not a contract case?) 51 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 Maybe some states have decided, on similar facts to the ones in your case, that the duty of accountants to perform analyses like “reasonably prudent accountants,” a judge-made tort duty, does not extend to plaintiffs who lack a contractual relationship with the accountant. In these states, although the customer of an accountant is owed a duty to perform accounting work like a reasonably prudent accountant would, that duty is not owed to non-customers. So if you got hold of an analysis written by someone else’s accountant, used it, and lost a lot of money, you’d have no legal remedy. That accountant owed you no duty. But other states have taken a different approach. These have allowed even non-customers to sue when the accountant should have foreseen those people would rely on his or her work. Notice that this duty might extend to your client if you can show facts establishing that the accountant should have foreseen your client would rely on his or her work. If our state has not decided the question, we will have to argue concerning what the duty of accountants should be. We are forced to consider more carefully the ambit of the duty (violation only if you also have a contract with the accountant or any foreseeable reliers – or something else?) before we can apply the facts to determine if there is a breach. Another example: In a contract for the sale of goods, suppose I receive the goods but pay you less than you think you are owed. Suppose also that the contract contemplated payment but failed to include an explicit price term. Did I violate (breach) a duty established by the contract? We need to go back to the first step and figure out what, specifically, I was obligated to pay. What was my legal duty? Under the law of most states (http://www.law.cornell.edu/ucc/2/2-305.html), 52 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 I'd be on the hook for a reasonable price at the time of delivery. Whether I breached that implicit obligation depends on what that duty is. So we’ll litigate it, offering evidence of what was reasonable to establish what our private law required me to pay. And then we will determine whether I breached that duty by failing to pay that amount. Causation Even if I “break the law,” I’m often not liable, that is not subject to fines, damages, injunctions, or imprisonment, unless my actions caused a result specified by the law. Even if I breached a duty to operate a machine with ordinary care, I do not have to pay you any money unless my failure of care caused you to be injured. This analysis is sometimes tricky, because in the law we use the word “causation” to serve both logical and policy ends. Two concepts, a single word. Logically, causation is straightforward to understand, if not always to apply. If I am under a duty to operate a car non-negligently and I breach that duty, I am only responsible to someone injured in a crash if I caused his or her injuries. At the very least, my breaching the duty the law established must be a but-for cause of the injury. That is, but for my breach, the injury would not have occurred. Sometimes this but-for causation is called “actual causation” or “cause in fact.” The problem is that this concept is greedy: it sweeps in lots of conduct that we probably don’t think of as causal. For example, if I injure someone in an auto accident, and but for my negligence the person would not have been injured, it’s also the case that my parents are a “but-for” cause 53 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 of the injuries. After all, no parents, no me. No me, no breach by me. Of course, my parents violated no duty, so the fact that they were but-for causes of the injury does not mean they are liable. Still, what if my breach of a contractual obligation to deliver certain goods to a shopkeep causes her to go shopping for those goods and to be killed in a car accident on the way to the store? Should her estate be able to recover damages for her death from me? What if I negligently cause an automobile accident that causes a minor injury to someone who is held up by the accident and, because of the hold up, misses work and is fired? Am I liable for the lost wages? In both cases, my breach of a legal duty was a but-for cause of the unexpected injuries. The law’s solution to these sorts of problems is to require something more than but-for causation. We will insist that the defendant’s conduct was a proximate cause, or substantial factor, in producing the injury. The language and exact analysis vary, but the idea is to restrict liability to violations that are connected in a fairly direct way to the injury. This is a matter of policy rather than logic. In both tort and contract law, the ability of the breaching party reasonably to foresee the injury is the key. They differ, though, in the kind and timing of the thing foreseen. Traditionally in tort, if you should have foreseen, at the time of the breach, damage of the kind that occurred, you will be liable for the damages caused even if you couldn’t foresee their magnitude. In contract law, the famous case of Hadley v. Baxendale (http://www.bailii.org/ew/cases/EWHC/Exch/ 1854/J70.html) decided that a defendant who breached a contract to deliver a crankshaft was not responsible for lost 54 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 profits that were not foreseen (contemplated) at the time of the contract and were not otherwise a “natural consequence” of the breach. The important thing to note for the moment is that, whatever the limits on causation, they are policy determinations that allocate responsibility for avoiding losses in ways thought best to serve the public interest. Because it’s a policy issue, the extent to which we permit plaintiffs to travel down the but-for path could also be understood as a definition of the scope of the duty the law has created. Consider, for example, the accountant’s liability to third parties. One could characterize the question as going to whether the accountant was a “direct enough” cause of their injuries or to whether we desire, as a matter of policy, to create a duty on an accountant enforceable by foreseeable reliers not in contract with him or her. The practical consequence of this distinction, between duty and proximate cause is that the definition of the duty is in the hands of the judge for such torts. But the question of causation is given to the jury. These distinct ways of seeing the same problem were the subject of a famous torts case, Palsgraf v. Long Island Railroad Co. (http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/ Palsgraf_v._Long_Island_Railroad_Co.). Also note that causation can sometimes be difficult to prove. Summers v. Tice (http://scholar.google.com/scholar_case? case=7084631840002460993) is a tort case in which the plaintiff was shot in the face by at least one of two negligent hunters but where it was unclear which shooter caused which injury. The court shifted the burden from the plaintiff to each hunter to prove that he was not the cause, lest the plaintiff be stuck unable to prove to a greater than 50% probability that a 55 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 particular one of them had caused his injury. As a matter of policy, the court did not want someone who was clearly harmed by the negligent actions of multiple parties to be denied a remedy simply because the victim was unable to prove which of the two actually caused the victim's harm. By shifting the burden of proving or disproving causation to the defendants, the court was making a policy decision that favors a plaintiff where multiple defendants have acted negligently in such a way that at least one of those defendants harmed the plaintiff. Damages and Defenses The final elements of a lawsuit are showing that there were damages, calculating them, and also examining any defenses the law may provide. Your intuition will get you a long way here. But there are some subtleties, some of which we will discuss in class. Defenses are generally policy-based limitations on a positively stated duty. They, like other aspects of the lawsuit, could easily be collapsed into the definition of the duty. For example, while it might generally be a violation of a publicly created duty to go onto another’s land without permission, I will not be liable for doing so if my entry was to save a life. This is the necessity defense to the trespass tort. If my trespass on your land was “necessary” within the meaning of that defense, you will not be able to sue me successfully for trespass. One could just as easily say that a trespass is defined so as not to included necessary entries. 56 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 Rules and Standards One last general topic about the business of law. And then we’ll dive into the substantive reasons courts and lawmakers might cite when making or resolving law. How should potential legal violations be measured? When we say something is illegal, how should we specify what that something is? Consider one way of doing so with which you are doubtlessly familiar. The speed limit on a public highway is almost always stated in terms of a particular, fixed speed that may not be exceeded. This is a quintessential legal rule. It specifies in advance and with precision the conduct that will subject you to fines or other punishment. You can feel safe from governmental sanction driving your car at fifty miles per hour on a road on which the speed limit has been declared by signage to be fifty-five miles per hour. The reason you feel this measure of safety is because fifty is less than fifty-five, not because you’ve made a prediction that courts would likely believe your speed to be reasonable or safe. It’s the same as confidently moving a piece on a board when playing a game. If you’re familiar with the rules, you will know in advance whether you can move the piece in that way. Contrast this with a legal standard. A standard sets out a way to determine legality that depends on judgments, not mere calculations. Perhaps the most famous legal standard is found in the law of torts. In general, you can be liable in tort, and therefore required to pay damages, to someone you injure through your own negligence. What is negligence? It is conduct that exhibits a level of care less than that a 57 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 reasonably prudent person would have taken under the circumstances. Basically, we’re asking whether you acted unreasonably in a situation. What’s unreasonable? There’s the rub: we have to take a lot of factors into account and make a judgment. Would a reasonable person under the circumstances have slammed on the brakes or used one surgical method instead of another or put up a sign saying the floor was slippery or locked a gate to keep kids away from an unmonitored swimming pool, etc.? One type of standard in law is the multi-factor balancing test, in which a court is asked, or asks itself, to consider several different interests or factors and weigh them. Justice Scalia was a harsh critic of this sort of approach to law, preferring rules whenever possible (but not in all cases). Consider this passage from a dissent of his in Bendix Autolite Corp. v. Midwesco Enterprises, 486 U.S. 888 (1988): Having evaluated the interests on both sides as roughly as this, the Court then proceeds to judge which is more important. This process is ordinarily called “balancing,” but the scale analogy is not really appropriate, since the interests on both sides are incommensurate. It is more like judging whether a particular line is longer than a particular rock is heavy. All I am really persuaded of by the Court's opinion is that the burdens the Court labels “significant” are more determinative of its decision than the benefits it labels “important.” Were it not for the brief implication that there is here a discrimination unjustified by any state interest, I suggest an opinion 58 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 could as persuasively have been written coming out the opposite way. Scalia’s critique here, and as he elaborated elsewhere, is more complex than it first appears. His attack on balancing interests, where a judge “weighs” some considerations against others, is against a particular kind of standard. Here, he attacks balancing tests that ask courts to weigh one kind of interest against another, such as an interest in efficient execution of administrative tasks against the interest in equal treatment of government employees. How is one to know whether a certain amount of inequality (and there must always be some) is “worth” the gains in efficient operations that would be lost if the agency had to put in place rules and monitoring to prevent it? A trade-off that seems reasonable to one intelligent person deliberating in good faith might seem unreasonable to another. And how can anyone say which of them is right? But the critique goes further. Any time we ask courts to apply standards, we ask them exercise discretion – to engage in judgments about which reasonable people might disagree. Standards ask whether something is too much, too little, too injurious to some other interests, or the like - but with no fixed measure of “too.” In such cases, law is less predictable. People are unable to plan their actions in anticipation of how the law might apply to them. And courts become policymakers, rather than impartial adjudicators. Given that rules enable prediction and compliance, why would we ever prefer to use standards to define illegal conduct? Getting law right, whatever else it may mean, depends on our ability to craft legal definitions that don’t 59 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 commit us to intolerable levels of injustice, danger, or inefficiency in the future. As famous legal philosopher H.L.A. Hart put it, we are people, not gods. And we are limited both in “fact” and in “aim.” That is, at the time we are making law, we are limited in what we know about the world and how events will unfold, and we are limited in knowing what it is we will want in the future. How can we responsibly lay down a mechanical rule to resolve some dispute in the distant future when we may be ignorant of crucial considerations and of what will even be important to us then. Sure we could make a rule that would resolve the case with relative certainty (flipping a coin would do the trick), but, as Hart wrote, “[w]e shall thus indeed succeed in settling in advance, but also in the dark, issues which can only reasonably be settled when they arise and are identified.” Consider the speed limit again. Should I be fined if I exceed the speed limit while rushing a dying friend to the hospital? What if I’m being pursued by aggressors? What if my car malfunctions or if I’m passing a vehicle driving at the speed limit but that presents a danger to traffic around it? We could attempt to define rule-like exceptions to cover these situations, something like: “It shall be illegal to exceed the posted speed limit except in the following situations: (a) when the driver or passenger is suffering the following medical emergencies: …., (b) when all other vehicles within 1/4 mile are traveling at least five miles per hour faster, [etc.]” This formulation of a law meant to make speeding illegal except when needed is, to put it mildly, a bit clunky. To craft the law well, we will either need to imagine and describe with specificity the category of speeding we’d like to permit or count on judges to bend the law in appropriate cases. 60 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 Perhaps it would be better to state a general rule and indicate there are exceptions that meet a standard. “It shall be illegal to exceed the posted speed limit except (a) when required preserve health or life, (b) when slower travel would be hazardous to the driver or surrounding drivers, or (c) when otherwise required to promote public safety.” The cost of such a statute is obvious. I may not be able to predict with certainty whether a police officer and ultimately a judge will determine my situation to fall within an exception. Additionally, there will be more litigation than there would be in a system of absolute rules. However, there are clear benefits. We will be able to avoid punishing people in situations we cannot now imagine but where speeding is clearly warranted. Knowing the exception exists could cause people to hesitate less to speed in such situations. A judge or jury can interpret the provision to do more exact justice in a given case. What is more, perhaps our “rule-like” approach would wind up being the standard-like approach in practice. Everyone knows that they will not be ticketed for traveling sixty miles per hour on a road limited to travel at fifty-five miles per hour. Police officers generally give tickets for speeding some ”significant” margin over the posted limit. How much could depend on conditions, whether the officer has a quota to meet, whether there are unusual safety concerns in the area (like a school speed zone), and the like. In practice, the speed at which you will be ticketed is a matter of judgment and can be predicted only generally. And if you take your ticket to court (defending the prosecution for speeding), whether a judge reduces the fine or otherwise shows leniency is not an event you could calculate with any exactness in advance. 61 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 Real legal systems tend to specify some laws in more rulelike fashion and others in more standards-like fashion. For example, in soccer, the international body FIFA defines a foul in such a way that it requires careless or reckless conduct or conduct imparting excessive force. The same body defines a goal as occurring when the entire ball reaches beyond the entire goal line. The former is quite standard-like, and the latter is a rule. But the laws of the game include both. Why? There are a few general observations we can make about rules and standards. Rules: – Retain power in rule promulgators; – Potentially reduce decision costs; – Reduce the quantity of litigation because the resolution of disputes is more predictable; – Provide wider safe harbors (zones of conduct that clearly do not run afoul of the rule) because there is less uncertainty about borderline cases, thus enabling more productive conduct. Standards: – Grant more power to adjudicators; – Enable decisionmakers to reach more just or efficient results in given cases than might application of a mechanical rule; 62 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 – Promote transparent weighing and considerations of reasonableness that might otherwise be used secretly by rule enforcers; – Promote planning and conflict avoidance if the standard more accurately describes the conditions of enforcement than the “official rule” would. That is enough for now for us to think about how law is specified and the trade-offs of describing conduct with particularity or leaving the contours of legality to decisionmakers confronted with a real case. But we will take up later in the course yet another type of legal authority: the legal principle. Rules and standards differ in how they specify what is legal or illegal, but both are all or nothing. That is, if a rule or standard is met, the legality of the conduct is determined. Whether speeding is determined by a rule or standard, when the criteria are met, we know whether the speeding was illegal. In contrast, a principle is a consideration in adjudicating or lawmaking that has weight but is not determinative. If we have a rule or standard establishing that no person shall be a judge in a case in which the judge has any appearance of partiality or conceivable interest, then we would probably insist the judge recuse from a case in which the judge’s social acquaintance is being sued for a breach of contract. If, though, we determine from the common law that one principle is that judges should not serve on cases in which they might be perceived to have an interest, then we would say that it weighs in favor of recusal that our judge is acquainted with the defendant. But there might be a competing principle that judges should not recuse when 63 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 public trust in the judiciary would not be threatened, perhaps because we want to discourage parties from “shopping” for judges by digging up only tenuous potential conflicts. That principle might weigh in favor of the judge’s service if the judge has many acquaintances. We would have to examine these principles together, and one would yield in our case. We will return to the idea of principles when we study courts in greater depth. Lee v. Weisman, 505 U.S. 577 (1992) A few words before we get to the Court’s decision in this case: Lee marked an opportunity for the Supreme Court, after several Republican appointees during the Reagan and Bush years, to reconsider its holding that the Establishment Clause generally prohibits official prayer in public schools. As you will read, a middle school student and her family sued to stop a prayer at her public middle school graduation ceremony, arguing that it violated the constitutional ban on governmental “establishment[s] of religion.” The First Amendment to the Constitution reads: Congress shall make no law respecting an establishment of religion, or prohibiting the free exercise thereof; or abridging the freedom of speech, or of the press; or the right of the people peaceably to assemble, and to petition the Government for a redress of grievances. 64 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 The particular portion of the amendment that interests us here is: “Congress shall make no law respecting an establishment of religion.” First things first: A public middle school is not the United States Congress. Does this provision of the Constitution even apply to public schools, which are part of state governments and are certainly not legislatures? The answer is yes, that all the provisions of the First Amendment apply to all state actors, whether legislative, executive, or judicial and whether federal or state. That the amendment applies to the states is uncontroversial. Even though people still disagree as to the exact mechanism, the Fourteenth Amendment’s prohibition of any state’s denial of Due Process rights has been held to include a prohibition of violations of the substance of the First Amendment. This critical amendment to the Constitution was one of several ratified after the Civil War that were intended to outlaw slavery, to prohibit states from treating citizens unequally, and to create a role for the federal government to guard the political and civil rights of its citizens. But does this mean that the amendment also applies to executive actors? In many ways, the fact that the First Amendment prohibits the President and governors from cracking down on speech or religions they dislike seems an obvious fact of our legal life. Indeed, arguing to a court that a governor can violate the First Amendment because he or she is not “Congress” or a legislature would get you nowhere. The law clearly bars any state actor from violating the amendment’s terms. A number of scholars, though, have 65 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 questioned this assumption.1 For the foreseeable future, though, this debate will be confined to academia. Given these legal facts, we can now ask how the constitutional rule, that the middle school is prohibited from undertaking any action that would establish a religion, would apply to this case. The Court’s job here is to make an interpretation of the Constitution, to derive from it a rule or standard that can be applied to resolve this case more transparently. Sure, the Court could just say, “We think an official prayer in a public school violates the Establishment Clause.” That would indeed resolve the case, but it would not explain the Court’s ruling or provide guidance for future cases. The very reason the Court grants certiorari is to provide such guidance, not, generally, to correct an error in the outcome of a single case. Indeed, this case, like nearly all Supreme Court cases, is primarily about the proper law, not the proper result. As you will read, the debate among members of the Court concerns how to translate the Establishment Clause into an administrable rule or standard (how to define the target, to pick up again our archer analogy). In fact, it’s even one step beyond that. Starting with a standard the Court adopted in a prior case, Lemon v. Kurtzman, how should that test be understood in the school prayer context. Why do you think they come to different answers to this question? Are multiple and conflicting answers to constitutional questions possible 1 See, e.g., Daniel Hemel, Executive Action and the First Amendment's First Word, 40 Pepp. L. Rev. 601 (2013) (http:// digitalcommons.pepperdine.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi? article=2130&context=plr). 66 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 without one side’s being wrong? What does it mean to be wrong here? After you read the case, see whether you can apply what we learned about rules and standards. Can you contrast the standard that Justice Kennedy derives and applies with the rule the dissent favors, explaining why the first is a standard and the second a rule? Ok, let’s read the decision. Justice Kennedy delivered the opinion of the Court. School principals in the public school system of the city of Providence, Rhode Island, are permitted to invite members of the clergy to offer invocation and benediction prayers as part of the formal graduation ceremonies for middle schools and for high schools. The question before us is whether including clerical members who offer prayers as part of the official school graduation ceremony is consistent with the Religion Clauses of the First Amendment, provisions the Fourteenth Amendment makes applicable with full force to the States and their school districts. I A Deborah Weisman graduated from Nathan Bishop Middle School, a public school in Providence, at a formal ceremony in June 1989. She was about 14 years old. For many years it has been the policy of the Providence School Committee and the Superintendent of Schools to permit principals to invite members of the clergy to give invocations and benedictions at 67 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 middle school and high school graduations. Many, but not all, of the principals elected to include prayers as part of the graduation ceremonies. Acting for himself and his daughter, Deborah’s father, Daniel Weisman, objected to any prayers at Deborah’s middle school graduation, but to no avail. The school principal, petitioner Robert E. Lee, invited a rabbi to deliver prayers at the graduation exercises for Deborah’s class. Rabbi Leslie Gutterman, of the Temple Beth El in Providence, accepted. It has been the custom of Providence school officials to provide invited clergy with a pamphlet entitled "Guidelines for Civic Occasions," prepared by the National Conference of Christians and Jews. The Guidelines recommend that public prayers at nonsectarian civic ceremonies be composed with "inclusiveness and sensitivity," though they acknowledge that "[p]rayer of any kind may be inappropriate on some civic occasions.” The principal gave Rabbi Gutterman the pamphlet before the graduation and advised him the invocation and benediction should be nonsectarian. Rabbi Gutterman’s prayers were as follows: INVOCATION God of the Free, Hope of the Brave: For the legacy of America where diversity is celebrated and the rights of minorities are protected, we thank You. May these young men and women grow up to enrich it. For the liberty of America, we thank You. May these new graduates grow up to guard it. 68 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 For the political process of America in which all its citizens may participate, for its court system where all may seek justice we thank You. May those we honor this morning always turn to it in trust. For the destiny of America we thank You. May the graduates of Nathan Bishop Middle School so live that they might help to share it. May our aspirations for our country and for these young people, who are our hope for the future, be richly fulfilled. AMEN BENEDICTION O God, we are grateful to You for having endowed us with the capacity for learning which we have celebrated on this joyous commencement. Happy families give thanks for seeing their children achieve an important milestone. Send Your blessings upon the teachers and administrators who helped prepare them. The graduates now need strength and guidance for the future, help them to understand that we are not complete with academic knowledge alone. We must each strive to fulfill what You require of us all: To do justly, to love mercy, to walk humbly. 69 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 We give thanks to You, Lord, for keeping us alive, sustaining us and allowing us to reach this special, happy occasion. AMEN . . . . The school board (and the United States, which supports it as amicus curiae ) argued that these short prayers and others like them at graduation exercises are of profound meaning to many students and parents throughout this country who consider that due respect and acknowledgment for divine guidance and for the deepest spiritual aspirations of our people ought to be expressed at an event as important in life as a graduation. We assume this to be so in addressing the difficult case now before us, for the significance of the prayers lies also at the heart of Daniel and Deborah Weisman’s case. B . . . . The District Court held that petitioners’ practice of including invocations and benedictions in public school graduations violated the Establishment Clause of the First Amendment, and it enjoined petitioners from continuing the practice. The court applied the three-part Establishment Clause test set forth in Lemon v. Kurtzman. Under that test as described in our past cases, to satisfy the Establishment Clause a governmental practice must (1) reflect a clearly secular purpose; (2) have a primary effect that neither advances nor inhibits religion; and (3) avoid excessive government entanglement with religion. The District Court held that petitioners’ actions violated the second part of the test, and so did not address either the first or the third. The 70 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 court decided, based on its reading of our precedents, that the effects test of Lemon is violated whenever government action “creates an identification of the state with a religion, or with religion in general,” or when “the effect of the governmental action is to endorse one religion over another, or to endorse religion in general.” The court determined that the practice of including invocations and benedictions, even so-called nonsectarian ones, in public school graduations creates an identification of governmental power with religious practice, endorses religion, and violates the Establishment Clause. . . . . II These dominant facts mark and control the confines of our decision: State officials direct the performance of a formal religious exercise at promotional and graduation ceremonies for secondary schools. Even for those students who object to the religious exercise, their attendance and participation in the state-sponsored religious activity are in a fair and real sense obligatory, though the school district does not require attendance as a condition for receipt of the diploma. . . . . The principle that government may accommodate the free exercise of religion does not supersede the fundamental limitations imposed by the Establishment Clause. It is beyond dispute that, at a minimum, the Constitution guarantees that government may not coerce anyone to support or participate in religion or its exercise, or otherwise act in a way which “establishes a [state] religion or religious faith, or tends to do so.” The State’s involvement in the school prayers challenged today violates these central principles. 71 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 That involvement is as troubling as it is undenied. A school official, the principal, decided that an invocation and a benediction should be given; this is a choice attributable to the State, and from a constitutional perspective it is as if a state statute decreed that the prayers must occur. The principal chose the religious participant, here a rabbi, and that choice is also attributable to the State. The reason for the choice of a rabbi is not disclosed by the record, but the potential for divisiveness over the choice of a particular member of the clergy to conduct the ceremony is apparent. Divisiveness, of course, can attend any state decision respecting religions, and neither its existence nor its potential necessarily invalidates the State’s attempts to accommodate religion in all cases. The potential for divisiveness is of particular relevance here though, because it centers around an overt religious exercise in a secondary school environment where, as we discuss below, subtle coercive pressures exist and where the student had no real alternative which would have allowed her to avoid the fact or appearance of participation. The State’s role did not end with the decision to include a prayer and with the choice of a clergyman. Principal Lee provided Rabbi Gutterman with a copy of the “Guidelines for Civic Occasions,” and advised him that his prayers should be nonsectarian. Through these means the principal directed and controlled the content of the prayers. Even if the only sanction for ignoring the instructions were that the rabbi would not be invited back, we think no religious representative who valued his or her continued reputation and effectiveness in the community would incur the State’s displeasure in this regard. It is a cornerstone principle of our 72 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 Establishment Clause jurisprudence that “it is no part of the business of government to compose official prayers for any group of the American people to recite as a part of a religious program carried on by government,” and that is what the school officials attempted to do. Petitioners argue, and we find nothing in the case to refute it, that the directions for the content of the prayers were a good-faith attempt by the school to ensure that the sectarianism which is so often the flashpoint for religious animosity be removed from the graduation ceremony. The concern is understandable, as a prayer which uses ideas or images identified with a particular religion may foster a different sort of sectarian rivalry than an invocation or benediction in terms more neutral. The school’s explanation, however, does not resolve the dilemma caused by its participation. The question is not the good faith of the school in attempting to make the prayer acceptable to most persons, but the legitimacy of its undertaking that enterprise at all when the object is to produce a prayer to be used in a formal religious exercise which students, for all practical purposes, are obliged to attend. We are asked to recognize the existence of a practice of nonsectarian prayer, prayer within the embrace of what is known as the Judeo-Christian tradition, prayer which is more acceptable than one which, for example, makes explicit references to the God of Israel, or to Jesus Christ, or to a patron saint. There may be some support, as an empirical observation, to the statement of the Court of Appeals for the Sixth Circuit . . . that there has emerged in this country a civic religion, one which is tolerated when sectarian exercises are not. If common ground can be defined which permits once 73 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 conflicting faiths to express the shared conviction that there is an ethic and a morality which transcend human invention, the sense of community and purpose sought by all decent societies might be advanced. But though the First Amendment does not allow the government to stifle prayers which aspire to these ends, neither does it permit the government to undertake that task for itself. The First Amendment’s Religion Clauses mean that religious beliefs and religious expression are too precious to be either proscribed or prescribed by the State. The design of the Constitution is that preservation and transmission of religious beliefs and worship is a responsibility and a choice committed to the private sphere, which itself is promised freedom to pursue that mission. It must not be forgotten then, that while concern must be given to define the protection granted to an objector or a dissenting nonbeliever, these same Clauses exist to protect religion from government interference. James Madison, the principal author of the Bill of Rights, did not rest his opposition to a religious establishment on the sole ground of its effect on the minority. A principal ground for his view was: “[E]xperience witnesseth that ecclesiastical establishments, instead of maintaining the purity and efficacy of Religion, have had a contrary operation.” These concerns have particular application in the case of school officials, whose effort to monitor prayer will be perceived by the students as inducing a participation they might otherwise reject. Though the efforts of the school officials in this case to find common ground appear to have been a good-faith attempt to recognize the common aspects of religions and not the divisive ones, our precedents do not 74 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 permit school officials to assist in composing prayers as an incident to a formal exercise for their students. And these same precedents caution us to measure the idea of a civic religion against the central meaning of the Religion Clauses of the First Amendment, which is that all creeds must be tolerated and none favored. The suggestion that government may establish an official or civic religion as a means of avoiding the establishment of a religion with more specific creeds strikes us as a contradiction that cannot be accepted. The degree of school involvement here made it clear that the graduation prayers bore the imprint of the State and thus put school-age children who objected in an untenable position. We turn our attention now to consider the position of the students, both those who desired the prayer and she who did not. To endure the speech of false ideas or offensive content and then to counter it is part of learning how to live in a pluralistic society, a society which insists upon open discourse towards the end of a tolerant citizenry. And tolerance presupposes some mutuality of obligation. It is argued that our constitutional vision of a free society requires confidence in our own ability to accept or reject ideas of which we do not approve, and that prayer at a high school graduation does nothing more than offer a choice. By the time they are seniors, high school students no doubt have been required to attend classes and assemblies and to complete assignments exposing them to ideas they find distasteful or immoral or absurd or all of these. Against this background, students may consider it an odd measure of justice to be subjected during the course of their educations to ideas deemed offensive and irreligious, but to be denied a brief, formal prayer ceremony 75 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 that the school offers in return. This argument cannot prevail, however. It overlooks a fundamental dynamic of the Constitution. The First Amendment protects speech and religion by quite different mechanisms. Speech is protected by ensuring its full expression even when the government participates, for the very object of some of our most important speech is to persuade the government to adopt an idea as its own. The method for protecting freedom of worship and freedom of conscience in religious matters is quite the reverse. In religious debate or expression the government is not a prime participant, for the Framers deemed religious establishment antithetical to the freedom of all. The Free Exercise Clause embraces a freedom of conscience and worship that has close parallels in the speech provisions of the First Amendment, but the Establishment Clause is a specific prohibition on forms of state intervention in religious affairs with no precise counterpart in the speech provisions. The explanation lies in the lesson of history that was and is the inspiration for the Establishment Clause, the lesson that in the hands of government what might begin as a tolerant expression of religious views may end in a policy to indoctrinate and coerce. A state-created orthodoxy puts at grave risk that freedom of belief and conscience which are the sole assurance that religious faith is real, not imposed. The lessons of the First Amendment are as urgent in the modern world as in the 18th century when it was written. One timeless lesson is that if citizens are subjected to statesponsored religious exercises, the State disavows its own duty to guard and respect that sphere of inviolable conscience and belief which is the mark of a free people. To compromise that 76 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 principle today would be to deny our own tradition and forfeit our standing to urge others to secure the protections of that tradition for themselves. As we have observed before, there are heightened concerns with protecting freedom of conscience from subtle coercive pressure in the elementary and secondary public schools. Our decisions in Engel v. Vitale and School Dist. of Abington . . . . recognize, among other things, that prayer exercises in public schools carry a particular risk of indirect coercion. The concern may not be limited to the context of schools, but it is most pronounced there. What to most believers may seem nothing more than a reasonable request that the nonbeliever respect their religious practices, in a school context may appear to the nonbeliever or dissenter to be an attempt to employ the machinery of the State to enforce a religious orthodoxy. We need not look beyond the circumstances of this case to see the phenomenon at work. The undeniable fact is that the school district’s supervision and control of a high school graduation ceremony places public pressure, as well as peer pressure, on attending students to stand as a group or, at least, maintain respectful silence during the invocation and benediction. This pressure, though subtle and indirect, can be as real as any overt compulsion. Of course, in our culture standing or remaining silent can signify adherence to a view or simple respect for the views of others. And no doubt some persons who have no desire to join a prayer have little objection to standing as a sign of respect for those who do. But for the dissenter of high school age, who has a reasonable perception that she is being forced by the State to pray in a manner her conscience will not allow, the injury is no less 77 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 real. There can be no doubt that for many, if not most, of the students at the graduation, the act of standing or remaining silent was an expression of participation in the rabbi’s prayer. That was the very point of the religious exercise. It is of little comfort to a dissenter, then, to be told that for her the act of standing or remaining in silence signifies mere respect, rather than participation. What matters is that, given our social conventions, a reasonable dissenter in this milieu could believe that the group exercise signified her own participation or approval of it. Finding no violation under these circumstances would place objectors in the dilemma of participating, with all that implies, or protesting. We do not address whether that choice is acceptable if the affected citizens are mature adults, but we think the State may not, consistent with the Establishment Clause, place primary and secondary school children in this position. Research in psychology supports the common assumption that adolescents are often susceptible to pressure from their peers towards conformity, and that the influence is strongest in matters of social convention. To recognize that the choice imposed by the State constitutes an unacceptable constraint only acknowledges that the government may no more use social pressure to enforce orthodoxy than it may use more direct means. The injury caused by the government’s action, and the reason why Daniel and Deborah Weisman object to it, is that the State, in a school setting, in effect required participation in a religious exercise. It is, we concede, a brief exercise during which the individual can concentrate on joining its message, meditate on her own religion, or let her mind wander. But the embarrassment and the intrusion of the 78 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 religious exercise cannot be refuted by arguing that these prayers, and similar ones to be said in the future, are of a de minimis character. To do so would be an affront to the rabbi who offered them and to all those for whom the prayers were an essential and profound recognition of divine authority. And for the same reason, we think that the intrusion is greater than the two minutes or so of time consumed for prayers like these. Assuming, as we must, that the prayers were offensive to the student and the parent who now object, the intrusion was both real and, in the context of a secondary school, a violation of the objectors’ rights. That the intrusion was in the course of promulgating religion that sought to be civic or nonsectarian rather than pertaining to one sect does not lessen the offense or isolation to the objectors. At best it narrows their number, at worst increases their sense of isolation and affront. There was a stipulation in the District Court that attendance at graduation and promotional ceremonies is voluntary. Petitioners and the United States, as amicus, made this a center point of the case, arguing that the option of not attending the graduation excuses any inducement or coercion in the ceremony itself. The argument lacks all persuasion. Law reaches past formalism. And to say a teenage student has a real choice not to attend her high school graduation is formalistic in the extreme. True, Deborah could elect not to attend commencement without renouncing her diploma; but we shall not allow the case to turn on this point. Everyone knows that in our society and in our culture high school graduation is one of life’s most significant occasions. A school rule which excuses attendance is beside the point. Attendance may not be required by official decree, yet it is apparent that a 79 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 student is not free to absent herself from the graduation exercise in any real sense of the term "voluntary," for absence would require forfeiture of those intangible benefits which have motivated the student through youth and all her high school years. Graduation is a time for family and those closest to the student to celebrate success and express mutual wishes of gratitude and respect, all to the end of impressing upon the young person the role that it is his or her right and duty to assume in the community and all of its diverse parts. The importance of the event is the point the school district and the United States rely upon to argue that a formal prayer ought to be permitted, but it becomes one of the principal reasons why their argument must fail. Their contention, one of considerable force were it not for the constitutional constraints applied to state action, is that the prayers are an essential part of these ceremonies because for many persons an occasion of this significance lacks meaning if there is no recognition, however brief, that human achievements cannot be understood apart from their spiritual essence. We think the Government’s position that this interest suffices to force students to choose between compliance or forfeiture demonstrates fundamental inconsistency in its argumentation. It fails to acknowledge that what for many of Deborah’s classmates and their parents was a spiritual imperative was for Daniel and Deborah Weisman religious conformance compelled by the State. While in some societies the wishes of the majority might prevail, the Establishment Clause of the First Amendment is addressed to this contingency and rejects the balance urged upon us. The Constitution forbids the State to exact religious conformity from a student as the price of 80 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 attending her own high school graduation. This is the calculus the Constitution commands. The Government’s argument gives insufficient recognition to the real conflict of conscience faced by the young student. The essence of the Government’s position is that with regard to a civic, social occasion of this importance it is the objector, not the majority, who must take unilateral and private action to avoid compromising religious scruples, hereby electing to miss the graduation exercise. This turns conventional First Amendment analysis on its head. It is a tenet of the First Amendment that the State cannot require one of its citizens to forfeit his or her rights and benefits as the price of resisting conformance to state-sponsored religious practice. To say that a student must remain apart from the ceremony at the opening invocation and closing benediction is to risk compelling conformity in an environment analogous to the classroom setting, where we have said the risk of compulsion is especially high. Just as in Engel v. Vitale . . . . and School Dist. Of Abington v. Schempp . . . . where we found that provisions within the challenged legislation permitting a student to be voluntarily excused from attendance or participation in the daily prayers did not shield those practices from invalidation, the fact that attendance at the graduation ceremonies is voluntary in a legal sense does not save the religious exercise. Inherent differences between the public school system and a session of a state legislature distinguish this case from. The considerations we have raised in objection to the invocation and benediction are in many respects similar to the arguments we considered in Marsh [a case upholding the practice of prayer to open state legislative sessions]. But there are also obvious differences. The atmosphere at the opening of a 81 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 session of a state legislature where adults are free to enter and leave with little comment and for any number of reasons cannot compare with the constraining potential of the one school event most important for the student to attend. The influence and force of a formal exercise in a school graduation are far greater than the prayer exercise we condoned in Marsh. The Marsh majority in fact gave specific recognition to this distinction and placed particular reliance on it in upholding the prayers at issue there. Today’s case is different. At a high school graduation, teachers and principals must and do retain a high degree of control over the precise contents of the program, the speeches, the timing, the movements, the dress, and the decorum of the students. In this atmosphere the state-imposed character of an invocation and benediction by clergy selected by the school combine to make the prayer a state-sanctioned religious exercise in which the student was left with no alternative but to submit. This is different from Marsh and suffices to make the religious exercise a First Amendment violation. Our Establishment Clause jurisprudence remains a delicate and fact-sensitive one, and we cannot accept the parallel relied upon by petitioners and the United States between the facts of Marsh and the case now before us. Our decisions in Engel v. Vitale and School Dist. of Abington v. Schempp require us to distinguish the public school context. We do not hold that every state action implicating religion is invalid if one or a few citizens find it offensive. People may take offense at all manner of religious as well as nonreligious messages, but offense alone does not in every case show a violation. We know too that sometimes to endure social isolation or even anger may be the price of conscience or 82 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 nonconformity. But, by any reading of our cases, the conformity required of the student in this case was too high an exaction to withstand the test of the Establishment Clause. The prayer exercises in this case are especially improper because the State has in every practical sense compelled attendance and participation in an explicit religious exercise at an event of singular importance to every student, one the objecting student had no real alternative to avoid. Our jurisprudence in this area is of necessity one of linedrawing, of determining at what point a dissenter’s rights of religious freedom are infringed by the State. "The First Amendment does not prohibit practices which by any realistic measure create none of the dangers which it is designed to prevent and which do not so directly or substantially involve the state in religious exercises or in the favoring of religion as to have meaningful and practical impact. It is of course true that great consequences can grow from small beginnings, but the measure of constitutional adjudication is the ability and willingness to distinguish between real threat and mere shadow." Our society would be less than true to its heritage if it lacked abiding concern for the values of its young people, and we acknowledge the profound belief of adherents to many faiths that there must be a place in the student’s life for precepts of a morality higher even than the law we today enforce. We express no hostility to those aspirations, nor would our oath permit us to do so. A relentless and allpervasive attempt to exclude religion from every aspect of public life could itself become inconsistent with the Constitution. We recognize that, at graduation time and throughout the course of the educational process, there will 83 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 be instances when religious values, religious practices, and religious persons will have some interaction with the public schools and their students. But these matters, often questions of accommodation of religion, are not before us. The sole question presented is whether a religious exercise may be conducted at a graduation ceremony in circumstances where, as we have found, young graduates who object are induced to conform. No holding by this Court suggests that a school can persuade or compel a student to participate in a religious exercise. That is being done here, and it is forbidden by the Establishment Clause of the First Amendment. For the reasons we have stated, the judgment of the Court of Appeals is affirmed. Justice Blackmun, with whom Justice Stevens and Justice O’Connor join, concurring. Nearly half a century of review and refinement of Establishment Clause jurisprudence has distilled one clear understanding: Government may neither promote nor affiliate itself with any religious doctrine or organization, nor may it obtrude itself in the internal affairs of any religious institution. The application of these principles to the present case mandates the decision reached today by the Court. . . . . There can be “no doubt” that the “invocation of God’s blessings” delivered at Nathan Bishop Middle School “is a religious activity.” In the words of Engel, the Rabbi’s prayer “is a solemn avowal of divine faith and supplication for the blessings of the Almighty. The nature of such a prayer has always been religious.” The question then is whether the government has “plac[ed] its official stamp of approval” on 84 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 the prayer. As the Court ably demonstrates, when the government “compose[s] official prayers,” selects the member of the clergy to deliver the prayer, has the prayer delivered at a public school event that is planned, supervised and given by school officials, and pressures students to attend and participate in the prayer, there can be no doubt that the government is advancing and promoting religion. As our prior decisions teach us, it is this that the Constitution prohibits. . . . . I join the Court’s opinion today because I find nothing in it inconsistent with the essential precepts of the Establishment Clause developed in our precedents. The Court holds that the graduation prayer is unconstitutional because the State “in effect required participation in a religious exercise.” Although our precedents make clear that proof of government coercion is not necessary to prove an Establishment Clause violation, it is sufficient. Government pressure to participate in a religious activity is an obvious indication that the government is endorsing or promoting religion. But it is not enough that the government restrain from compelling religious practices: It must not engage in them either. The Court repeatedly has recognized that a violation of the Establishment Clause is not predicated on coercion. The Establishment Clause proscribes public schools from “conveying or attempting to convey a message that religion or a particular religious belief is favored or preferred,” . . . . even if the schools do not actually “impos[e] pressure upon a student to participate in a religious activity.” . . . . The mixing of government and religion can be a threat to free government, even if no one is forced to participate. When the government puts its imprimatur on a particular 85 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 religion, it conveys a message of exclusion to all those who do not adhere to the favored beliefs. A government cannot be premised on the belief that all persons are created equal when it asserts that God prefers some. . . . . Madison warned that government officials who would use religious authority to pursue secular ends “exceed the commission from which they derive their authority and are Tyrants. The People who submit to it are governed by laws made neither by themselves, nor by an authority derived from them, and are slaves.” Democratic government will not last long when proclamation replaces persuasion as the medium of political exchange. Likewise, we have recognized that “[r]eligion flourishes in greater purity, without than with the aid of Gov[ernment].” . . . . When the government favors a particular religion or sect, the disadvantage to all others is obvious, but even the favored religion may fear being “taint[ed] ... with a corrosive secularism.” The favored religion may be compromised as political figures reshape the religion’s beliefs for their own purposes; it may be reformed as government largesse brings government regulation. Keeping religion in the hands of private groups minimizes state intrusion on religious choice and best enables each religion to “flourish according to the zeal of its adherents and the appeal of its dogma.” It is these understandings and fears that underlie our Establishment Clause jurisprudence. e have believed that religious freedom cannot exist in the absence of a free democratic government, and that such a government cannot endure when there is fusion between religion and the political regime. We have believed that religious freedom cannot thrive in the absence of a vibrant religious community and that such 86 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 a community cannot prosper when it is bound to the secular. And we have believed that these were the animating principles behind the adoption of the Establishment Clause. To that end, our cases have prohibited government endorsement of religion, its sponsorship, and active involvement in religion, whether or not citizens were coerced to conform. I remain convinced that our jurisprudence is not misguided, and that it requires the decision reached by the Court today. Accordingly, I join the Court in affirming the judgment of the Court of Appeals. [The concurring opinion of Justice Souter has been omitted.] Justice Scalia, with whom Chief Justice Rehnquist, Justice White, and Justice Thomas join, dissenting. Three Terms ago, I joined an opinion recognizing that the Establishment Clause must be construed in light of the “[g]overnment policies of accommodation, acknowledgment, and support for religion [that] are an accepted part of our political and cultural heritage.” That opinion affirmed that “the meaning of the Clause is to be determined by reference to historical practices and understandings.” It said that “[a] test for implementing the protections of the Establishment Clause that, if applied with consistency, would invalidate longstanding traditions cannot be a proper reading of the Clause.” These views of course prevent me from joining today’s opinion, which is conspicuously bereft of any reference to 87 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 history. In holding that the Establishment Clause prohibits invocations and benedictions at public-school graduation ceremonies, the Court – with nary a mention that it is doing so – lays waste a tradition that is as old as public-school graduation ceremonies themselves, and that is a component of an even more longstanding American tradition of nonsectarian prayers to God at public celebrations generally. As its instrument of destruction, the bulldozer of social engineering, the Court invents a boundless, and boundlessly manipulable, test of psychological coercion, which promises to do for the Establishment Clause what the Durham rule did for the insanity defense. Today’s opinion shows more forcefully than volumes of argumentation why our Nation’s protection, that fortress which is our Constitution, cannot possibly rest upon the changeable philosophical predilections of the Justices of this Court, but must have deep foundations in the historic practices of our people. I Justice Holmes’ aphorism that “a page of history is worth a volume of logic” . . . . applies with particular force to our Establishment Clause jurisprudence. . . . . “[T]he line we must draw between the permissible and the impermissible is one which accords with history and faithfully reflects the understanding of the Founding Fathers.” “[H]istorical evidence sheds light not only on what the draftsmen intended the Establishment Clause to mean, but also on how they thought that Clause applied” to contemporaneous practices. Thus, “[t]he existence from the beginning of the Nation’s life 88 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 of a practice, [while] not conclusive of its constitutionality ... [,] is a fact of considerable import in the interpretation” of the Establishment Clause. The history and tradition of our Nation are replete with public ceremonies featuring prayers of thanksgiving and petition. Illustrations of this point have been amply provided in our prior opinions, but since the Court is so oblivious to our history as to suggest that the Constitution restricts “preservation and transmission of religious beliefs ... to the private sphere,” it appears necessary to provide another brief account. [Justice Scalia lists the long tradition of religious invocations by the nation’s presidents at various events, including inaugurations and proclamations.] The other two branches of the Federal Government also have a long-established practice of prayer at public events. As we detailed in Marsh, congressional sessions have opened with a chaplain’s prayer ever since the First Congress. And this Court’s own sessions have opened with the invocation “God save the United States and this Honorable Court” since the days of Chief Justice Marshall. In addition to this general tradition of prayer at public ceremonies, there exists a more specific tradition of invocations and benedictions at public school graduation exercises. By one account, the first public high school graduation ceremony took place in Connecticut in July 1868 – the very month, as it happens, that the Fourteenth Amendment (the vehicle by which the Establishment Clause has been applied against the States) was ratified – when “15 seniors from the Norwich Free Academy marched in their best Sunday suits and dresses into a church hall and waited 89 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 through majestic music and long prayers.” As the Court obliquely acknowledges in describing the “customary features” of high school graduations and as respondents do not contest, the invocation and benediction have long been recognized to be “as traditional as any other parts of the [school] graduation program and are widely established.” II The Court presumably would separate graduation invocations and benedictions from other instances of public “preservation and transmission of religious beliefs” on the ground that they involve “psychological coercion.” I find it a sufficient embarrassment that our Establishment Clause jurisprudence regarding holiday displays[] . . . . has come to “requir[e] scrutiny more commonly associated with interior decorators than with the judiciary.” But interior decorating is a rockhard science compared to psychology practiced by amateurs. A few citations of “[r]esearch in psychology” that have no particular bearing upon the precise issue here cannot disguise the fact that the Court has gone beyond the realm where judges know what they are doing. The Court’s argument that state officials have “coerced” students to take part in the invocation and benediction at graduation ceremonies is, not to put too fine a point on it, incoherent. The Court identifies two “dominant facts” that it says dictate its ruling that invocations and benedictions at public school graduation ceremonies violate the Establishment Clause. Neither of them is in any relevant sense true. 90 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 A The Court declares that students’ “attendance and participation in the [invocation and benediction] are in a fair and real sense obligatory.” But what exactly is this “fair and real sense”? According to the Court, students at graduation who want “to avoid the fact or appearance of participation” in the invocation and benediction are psychologically obligated by “public pressure, as well as peer pressure, ... to stand as a group or, at least, maintain respectful silence” during those prayers. This assertion – the very linchpin of the Court’s opinion – is almost as intriguing for what it does not say as for what it says. It does not say, for example, that students are psychologically coerced to bow their heads, place their hands in a Drüer-like prayer position, pay attention to the prayers, utter “Amen,” or in fact pray. (Perhaps further intensive psychological research remains to be done on these matters.) It claims only that students are psychologically coerced “to stand ... or, at least, maintain respectful silence.” Both halves of this disjunctive (both of which must amount to the fact or appearance of participation in prayer if the Court’s analysis is to survive on its own terms) merit particular attention. To begin with the latter: The Court’s notion that a student who simply sits in “respectful silence” during the invocation and benediction (when all others are standing) has somehow joined – or would somehow be perceived as having joined – in the prayers is nothing short of ludicrous. We indeed live in a vulgar age. But surely “our social conventions” have not coarsened to the point that anyone who does not stand on his chair and shout obscenities can reasonably be deemed to have assented to 91 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 everything said in his presence. Since the Court does not dispute that students exposed to prayer at graduation ceremonies retain (despite “subtle coercive pressures”) the free will to sit there is absolutely no basis for the Court’s decision. It is fanciful enough to say that “a reasonable dissenter,” standing head erect in a class of bowed heads, “could believe that the group exercise signified her own participation or approval of it.” It is beyond the absurd to say that she could entertain such a belief while pointedly declining to rise. But let us assume the very worst, that the nonparticipating graduate is “subtly coerced” ... to stand! Even that half of the disjunctive does not remotely establish a “participation” (or an “appearance of participation”) in a religious exercise. The Court acknowledges that “in our culture standing ... can signify adherence to a view or simple respect for the views of others." (Much more often the latter than the former, I think, except perhaps in the proverbial town meeting, where one votes by standing.) But if it is a permissible inference that one who is standing is doing so simply out of respect for the prayers of others that are in progress, then how can it possibly be said that a “reasonable dissenter ... could believe that the group exercise signified her own participation or approval”? Quite obviously, it cannot. I may add, moreover, that maintaining respect for the religious observances of others is a fundamental civic virtue that government (including the public schools) can and should cultivate – so that even if it were the case that the displaying of such respect might be mistaken for taking part in the prayer, I would deny that the dissenter’s interest in avoiding even the false appearance of participation constitutionally trumps the 92 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 government’s interest in fostering respect for religion generally. The opinion manifests that the Court itself has not given careful consideration to its test of psychological coercion. For if it had, how could it observe, with no hint of concern or disapproval, that students stood for the Pledge of Allegiance, which immediately preceded Rabbi Gutterman’s invocation? The government can, of course, no more coerce political orthodoxy than religious orthodoxy. Moreover, since the Pledge of Allegiance has been revised since Barnette to include the phrase “under God,” recital of the Pledge would appear to raise the same Establishment Clause issue as the invocation and benediction. If students were psychologically coerced to remain standing during the invocation, they must also have been psychologically coerced, moments before, to stand for (and thereby, in the Court’s view, take part in or appear to take part in) the Pledge. Must the Pledge therefore be barred from the public schools (both from graduation ceremonies and from the classroom)? In Barnette we held that a public school student could not be compelled to recite the Pledge; we did not even hint that she could not be compelled to observe respectful silence – indeed, even to stand in respectful silence – when those who wished to recite it did so. Logically, that ought to be the next project for the Court’s bulldozer. I also find it odd that the Court concludes that high school graduates may not be subjected to this supposed psychological coercion, yet refrains from addressing whether “mature adults” may. I had thought that the reason graduation from high school is regarded as so significant an event is that it is generally associated with transition from adolescence to young adulthood. Many graduating seniors, of course, are old 93 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 enough to vote. Why, then, does the Court treat them as though they were first-graders? Will we soon have a jurisprudence that distinguishes between mature and immature adults? B The other “dominant fac[t]” identified by the Court is that “[s]tate officials direct the performance of a formal religious exercise” at school graduation ceremonies. “Direct[ing] the performance of a formal religious exercise” has a sound of liturgy to it, summoning up images of the principal directing acolytes where to carry the cross, or showing the rabbi where to unroll the Torah. A Court professing to be engaged in a “delicate and fact-sensitive” line-drawing, . . . . would better describe what it means as “prescribing the content of an invocation and benediction.” But even that would be false. All the record shows is that principals of the Providence public schools, acting within their delegated authority, have invited clergy to deliver invocations and benedictions at graduations; and that Principal Lee invited Rabbi Gutterman, provided him a two-page pamphlet, prepared by the National Conference of Christians and Jews, giving general advice on inclusive prayer for civic occasions, and advised him that his prayers at graduation should be nonsectarian. . . . . The Court identifies nothing in the record remotely suggesting that school officials have ever drafted, edited, screened, or censored graduation prayers, or that Rabbi Gutterman was a mouthpiece of the school officials. . . . . 94 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 III The deeper flaw in the Court’s opinion does not lie in its wrong answer to the question whether there was stateinduced “peer-pressure” coercion; it lies, rather, in the Court’s making violation of the Establishment Clause hinge on such a precious question. The coercion that was a hallmark of historical establishments of religion was coercion of religious orthodoxy and of financial support by force of law and threat of penalty. Typically, attendance at the state church was required; only clergy of the official church could lawfully perform sacraments; and dissenters, if tolerated, faced an array of civil disabilities. Thus, for example, in the Colony of Virginia, where the Church of England had been established, ministers were required by law to conform to the doctrine and rites of the Church of England; and all persons were required to attend church and observe the Sabbath, were tithed for the public support of Anglican ministers, and were taxed for the costs of building and repairing churches. The Establishment Clause was adopted to prohibit such an establishment of religion at the federal level (and to protect state establishments of religion from federal interference). I will further acknowledge for the sake of argument that, as some scholars have argued, by 1790 the term “establishment” had acquired an additional meaning – “financial support of religion generally, by public taxation” – that reflected the development of “general or multiple” establishments, not limited to a single church. But that would still be an establishment coerced by force of law. And I will further concede that our constitutional tradition, from the Declaration of Independence and the first inaugural address of Washington, quoted earlier, down to the present day, has, 95 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 with a few aberrations . . . . ruled out of order governmentsponsored endorsement of religion – even when no legal coercion is present, and indeed even when no ersatz, “peerpressure” psycho-coercion is present – where the endorsement is sectarian, in the sense of specifying details upon which men and women who believe in a benevolent, omnipotent Creator and Ruler of the world are known to differ (for example, the divinity of Christ). But there is simply no support for the proposition that the officially sponsored nondenominational invocation and benediction read by Rabbi Gutterman – with no one legally coerced to recite them – violated the Constitution of the United States. To the contrary, they are so characteristically American they could have come from the pen of George Washington or Abraham Lincoln himself. Thus, while I have no quarrel with the Court’s general proposition that the Establishment Clause “guarantees that government may not coerce anyone to support or participate in religion or its exercise,” I see no warrant for expanding the concept of coercion beyond acts backed by threat of penalty – a brand of coercion that, happily, is readily discernible to those of us who have made a career of reading the disciples of Blackstone rather than of Freud. The Framers were indeed opposed to coercion of religious worship by the National Government; but, as their own sponsorship of nonsectarian prayer in public events demonstrates, they understood that "[s]peech is not coercive; the listener may do as he likes." This historical discussion places in revealing perspective the Court’s extravagant claim that the State has “for all practical purposes” and “in every practical sense” compelled students 96 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 to participate in prayers at graduation. Beyond the fact, stipulated to by the parties, that attendance at graduation is voluntary, there is nothing in the record to indicate that failure of attending students to take part in the invocation or benediction was subject to any penalty or discipline. Contrast this with, for example, the facts of Barnette: Schoolchildren were required by law to recite the Pledge of Allegiance; failure to do so resulted in expulsion, threatened the expelled child with the prospect of being sent to a reformatory for criminally inclined juveniles, and subjected his parents to prosecution (and incarceration) for causing delinquency. To characterize the “subtle coercive pressures,” . . . . allegedly present here as the “practical” equivalent of the legal sanctions in Barnette is ... well, let me just say it is not a “delicate and fact-sensitive” analysis. The Court relies on our “school prayer” cases, Engel v. Vitale and School Dist. Of Abington v. Schempp. But whatever the merit of those cases, they do not support, much less compel, the Court’s psycho-journey. In the first place, Engel and Schempp do not constitute an exception to the rule, distilled from historical practice, that public ceremonies may include prayer; rather, they simply do not fall within the scope of the rule (for the obvious reason that school instruction is not a public ceremony). Second, we have made clear our understanding that school prayer occurs within a framework in which legal coercion to attend school (i.e., coercion under threat of penalty) provides the ultimate backdrop. In Schempp, for example, we emphasized that the prayers were "prescribed as part of the curricular activities of students who are required by law to attend school." Engel’s suggestion that the school prayer program at issue there – which permitted students "to 97 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 remain silent or be excused from the room – involved "indirect coercive pressure," should be understood against this backdrop of legal coercion. The question whether the opt-out procedure in Engel sufficed to dispel the coercion resulting from the mandatory attendance requirement is quite different from the question whether forbidden coercion exists in an environment utterly devoid of legal compulsion. And finally, our school prayer cases turn in part on the fact that the classroom is inherently an instructional setting, and daily prayer there – where parents are not present to counter "the students’ emulation of teachers as role models and the children’s susceptibility to peer pressure," – might be thought to raise special concerns regarding state interference with the liberty of parents to direct the religious upbringing of their children: "Families entrust public schools with the education of their children, but condition their trust on the understanding that the classroom will not purposely be used to advance religious views that may conflict with the private beliefs of the student and his or her family." Voluntary prayer at graduation – a one-time ceremony at which parents, friends, and relatives are present – can hardly be thought to raise the same concerns. IV Our Religion Clause jurisprudence has become bedeviled (so to speak) by reliance on formulaic abstractions that are not derived from, but positively conflict with, our long-accepted constitutional traditions. Foremost among these has been the so-called Lemon test, which has received well-earned criticism from many Members of this Court. The Court today 98 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 demonstrates the irrelevance of Lemon by essentially ignoring it, and the interment of that case may the only happy byproduct of the Court’s otherwise lamentable decision. Unfortunately, however, the Court has replaced Lemon with its psycho-coercion test, which suffers the double disability of having no roots whatever in our people’s historic practice, and being as infinitely expandable as the reasons for psychotherapy itself. Another happy aspect of the case is that it is only a jurisprudential disaster and not a practical one. Given the odd basis for the Court’s decision, invocations and benedictions will be able to be given at public school graduations next June, as they have for the past century and a half, so long as school authorities make clear that anyone who abstains from screaming in protest does not necessarily participate in the prayers. All that is seemingly needed is an announcement, or perhaps a written insertion at the beginning of the graduation program, to the effect that, while all are asked to rise for the invocation and benediction, none is compelled to join in them, nor will be assumed, by rising, to have done so. That obvious fact recited, the graduates and their parents may proceed to thank God, as Americans have always done, for the blessings He has generously bestowed on them and on their country. *** The reader has been told much in this case about the personal interest of Mr. Weisman and his daughter, and very little about the personal interests on the other side. They are not inconsequential. Church and state would not be such a difficult subject if religion were, as the Court apparently thinks it to be, some purely personal avocation that can be indulged entirely in secret, like pornography, in the privacy of 99 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 one’s room. For most believers it is not that, and has never been. Religious men and women of almost all denominations have felt it necessary to acknowledge and beseech the blessing of God as a people, and not just as individuals, because they believe in the “protection of divine Providence,” as the Declaration of Independence put it, not just for individuals but for societies; because they believe God to be, as Washington’s first Thanksgiving Proclamation put it, the “Great Lord and Ruler of Nations.” One can believe in the effectiveness of such public worship, or one can deprecate and deride it. But the longstanding American tradition of prayer at official ceremonies displays with unmistakable clarity that the Establishment Clause does not forbid the government to accommodate it. . . . . I must add one final observation: The Founders of our Republic knew the fearsome potential of sectarian religious belief to generate civil dissension and civil strife. And they also knew that nothing, absolutely nothing, is so inclined to foster among religious believers of various faiths a toleration – no, an affection – for one another than voluntarily joining in prayer together, to the God whom they all worship and seek. Needless to say, no one should be compelled to do that, but it is a shame to deprive our public culture of the opportunity, and indeed the encouragement, for people to do it voluntarily. The Baptist or Catholic who heard and joined in the simple and inspiring prayers of Rabbi Gutterman on this official and patriotic occasion was inoculated from religious bigotry and prejudice in a manner that cannot be replicated. To deprive our society of that important unifying mechanism, in order to spare the nonbeliever what seems to me the minimal inconvenience of standing or even sitting in respectful 100 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 nonparticipation, is as senseless in policy as it is unsupported in law. For the foregoing reasons, I dissent. 101 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 Meeting 3: What Is Good? What Is Good? The substantive reading for this class consists of the following three articles by Lawrence Solum on utilitarianism, deontology, and virtue ethics. – http://lsolum.typepad.com/legal_theory_lexicon/ 2003/11/legal_theory_le_4.html – http://lsolum.typepad.com/legal_theory_lexicon/ 2003/11/legal_theory_le_2.html – http://lsolum.typepad.com/legal_theory_lexicon/ 2003/11/legal_theory_le.html After reading the next case, Furman, try to make a utilitarian argument for and a utilitarian argument against the death penalty. Then see whether you can make a deontological Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 argument for and a deontological argument against the death penalty. Observe how these arguments differ and what sort of evidence is relevant to one set of arguments but not to another. Furman v. Georgia, 408 U.S. 238 (1972) PER CURIAM. Petitioner in No. 69-5003 was convicted of murder in Georgia and was sentenced to death pursuant to [Georgia law]. Petitioner in No. 69-5030 was convicted of rape in Georgia and was sentenced to death pursuant to [Georgia law]. Petitioner in No. 69-5031 was convicted of rape in Texas and was sentenced to death pursuant to [Texas law]. Certiorari was granted limited to the following question: ‘Does the imposition and carrying out of the death penalty in (these cases) constitute cruel and unusual punishment in violation of the Eighth and Fourteenth Amendments?’ The Court holds that the imposition and carrying out of the death penalty in these cases constitute cruel and unusual punishment in violation of the Eighth and Fourteenth Amendments. The judgment in each case is therefore reversed insofar as it leaves undisturbed the death sentence imposed, and the cases are remanded for further proceedings. So ordered. 103 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 Mr. Justice BRENNAN, concurring. The question presented in these cases is whether death is today a punishment for crime that is ‘cruel and unusual’ and consequently, by virtue of the Eighth and Fourteenth Amendments, beyond the power of the State to inflict. Almost a century ago, this Court observed that ‘(d)ifficulty would attend the effort to define with exactness the extent of the constitutional provision which provides that cruel and unusual punishments shall not be inflicted.’ Less than 15 years ago, it was again noted that ‘(t)he exact scope of the constitutional phrase ‘cruel and unusual’ has not been detailed by this Court.’ Those statements remain true today. The Cruel and Unusual Punishments Clause, like the other great clauses of the Constitution, is not susceptible of precise definition. Yet we know that the values and ideals it embodies are basic to our scheme of government. And we know also that the Clause imposes upon this Court the duty, when the issue is properly presented, to determine the constitutional validity of a challenged punishment, whatever that punishment may be. In these cases, ‘(t)hat issue confronts us, and the task of resolving it is inescapably ours.’ I We have very little evidence of the Framers’ intent in including the Cruel and Unusual Punishments Clause among those restraints upon the new Government enumerated in the Bill of Rights. [Brennan goes on to to give a history of the 8th Amendment.] 104 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 Several conclusions thus emerge from the history of the adoption of the Clause. We know that the Framers’ concern was directed specifically at the exercise of legislative power. They included in the Bill of Rights a prohibition upon ‘cruel and unusual punishments’ precisely because the legislature would otherwise have had the unfettered power to prescribe punishments for crimes. Yet we cannot now know exactly what the Framers thought ‘cruel and unusual punishments’ were. Certainly they intended to ban torturous punishments, but the available evidence does not support the further conclusion that only torturous punishments were to be outlawed. As Livermore’s comments demonstrate, the Framers were well aware that the reach of the Clause was not limited to the proscription of unspeakable atrocities. Nor did they intend simply to forbid punishments considered ‘cruel and unusual’ at the time. The ‘import’ of the Clause is, indeed, ‘indefinite,’ and for good reason. A constitutional provision ‘is enacted, it is true, from an experience of evils, but its general language should not, therefore, be necessarily confined to the form that evil had theretofore taken. Time works changes, brings into existence new conditions and purposes. Therefore a principle, to be vital, must be capable of wider application than the mischief which gave it birth.’ [Brennan discusses how the Court has interpreted the Cruel and Unusual Clause over time, ultimately concluding that the Court has rejected an interpretation that is limited by history or the desires of the legislature. The historical approach was rejected because it unnecessarily limited the scope of the Clause, and the Court has been unwilling to allow the representative branch—which may be swayed by concerns that would undermine the effectiveness of the 105 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 Clause—to dictate what constitutes cruel and unusual punishment.] Judicial enforcement of the Clause, then, cannot be evaded by invoking the obvious truth that legislatures have the power to prescribe punishments for crimes. That is precisely the reason the Clause appears in the Bill of Rights. The difficulty arises, rather, in formulating the ‘legal principles to be applied by the courts’ when a legislatively prescribed punishment is challenged as ‘cruel and unusual.’ In formulating those constitutional principles, we must avoid the insertion of ‘judicial conception(s) of . . . wisdom or propriety,’ . . . yet we must not, in the guise of ‘judicial restraint,’ abdicate our fundamental responsibility to enforce the Bill of Rights. Were we to do so, the ‘constitution would indeed be as easy of application as it would be deficient in efficacy and power. Its general principles would have little value and be converted by precedent into impotent and lifeless formulas. Rights declared in words might be lost in reality.’ The Cruel and Unusual Punishments Clause would become, in short, ‘little more than good advice.’ II Ours would indeed be a simple task were we required merely to measure a challenged punishment against those that history has long condemned. That narrow and unwarranted view of the Clause, however, was left behind with the 19th century. Our task today is more complex. We know ‘that the words of the (Clause) are not precise, and that their scope is not static.’ We know, therefore, that the Clause ‘must draw its meaning from the evolving standards of decency that mark the 106 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 progress of a maturing society.’ That knowledge, of course, is but the beginning of the inquiry. In Trop v. Dulles . . . it was said that ‘(t)he question is whether (a) penalty subjects the individual to a fate forbidden by the principle of civilized treatment guaranteed by the (Clause).’ It was also said that a challenged punishment must be examined ‘in light of the basic prohibition against inhuman treatment’ embodied in the Clause. It was said, finally, that: ‘The basic concept underlying the (Clause) is nothing less than the dignity of man. While the State has the power to punish, the (Clause) stands to assure that this power be exercised within the limits of civilized standards.’ At bottom, then, the Cruel and Unusual Punishments Clause prohibits the infliction of uncivilized and inhuman punishments. The State, even as it punishes, must treat its members with respect for their intrinsic worth as human beings. A punishment is ‘cruel and unusual,’ therefore, if it does not comport with human dignity. This formulation, of course, does not of itself yield principles for assessing the constitutional validity of particular punishments. Nevertheless, even though ‘(t)his Court has had little occasion to give precise content to the (Clause),’ . . . there are principles recognized in our cases and inherent in the Clause sufficient to permit a judicial determination whether a challenged punishment comports with human dignity. The primary principle is that a punishment must not be so severe as to be degrading to the dignity of human beings. 107 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 Pain, certainly, may be a factor in the judgment. The infliction of an extremely severe punishment will often entail physical suffering. Yet the Framers also knew ‘that there could be exercises of cruelty by laws other than those which inflicted bodily pain or mutilation.’ Even though ‘(t)here may be involved no physical mistreatment, no primitive torture,’ . . . severe mental pain may be inherent in the infliction of a particular punishment. . . . . More than the presence of pain, however, is comprehended in the judgment that the extreme severity of a punishment makes it degrading to the dignity of human beings. The barbaric punishments condemned by history, ‘punishments which inflict torture, such as the rack, the thumb-screw, the iron boot, the stretching of limbs, and the like,’ are, of course, ‘attended with acute pain and suffering.’ When we consider why they have been condemned, however, we realize that the pain involved is not the only reason. The true significance of these punishments is that they treat members of the human race as nonhumans, as objects to be toyed with and discarded. They are thus inconsistent with the fundamental premise of the Clause that even the vilest criminal remains a human being possessed of common human dignity. The infliction of an extremely severe punishment, then, like the one before the Court in Weems v. United States, from which ‘(n)o circumstance of degradation (was) omitted,’ . . . may reflect the attitude that the person punished is not entitled to recognition as a fellow human being. That attitude may be apparent apart from the severity of the punishment itself. In Louisiana ex rel. Francis v. Resweber . . . for example, the unsuccessful electrocution, although it caused ‘mental anguish and physical pain,’ was the result of ‘an unforeseeable 108 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 accident.’ Had the failure been intentional, however, the punishment would have been, like torture, so degrading and indecent as to amount to a refusal to accord the criminal human status. Indeed, a punishment may be degrading to human dignity solely because it is a punishment. A State may not punish a person for being ‘mentally ill, or a leper, or . . . afflicted with a veneral disease,’ or for being addicted to narcotics. To inflict punishment for having a disease is to treat the individual as a diseased thing rather than as a sick human being. That the punishment is not severe, ‘in the abstract,’ is irrelevant; ‘(e)ven one day in prison would be a cruel and unusual punishment for the ‘crime’ of having a common cold.’ Finally, of course, a punishment may be degrading simply by reason of its enormity. A prime example is expatriation, a ‘punishment more primitive than torture,’ . . . for it necessarily involves a denial by society of the individual’s existence as a member of the human community. In determining whether a punishment comports with human dignity, we are aided also by a second principle inherent in the Clause—that the State must not arbitrarily inflict a severe punishment. This principle derives from the notion that the State does not respect human dignity when, without reason, it inflicts upon some people a severe punishment that it does not inflict upon others. Indeed, the very words ‘cruel and unusual punishments’ imply condemnation of the arbitrary infliction of severe punishments. And, as we now know, the English history of the Clause reveals a particular concern with the establishment of a safeguard against arbitrary punishments. This principle has been recognized in our cases. In Wilkerson v. Utah . . . the Court reviewed various treatises on 109 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 military law in order to demonstrate that under ‘the custom of war’ shooting was a common method of inflicting the punishment of death. . . . . As Wilkerson suggests, when a severe punishment is inflicted ‘in the great majority of cases’ in which it is legally available, there is little likelihood that the State is inflicting it arbitrarily. If, however, the infliction of a severe punishment is ‘something different from that which is generally done’ in such cases, . . . there is a substantial likelihood that the State, contrary to the requirements of regularity and fairness embodied in the Clause, is inflicting the punishment arbitrarily. This principle is especially important today. There is scant danger, given the political processes ‘in an enlightened democracy such as ours,’ . . . that extremely severe punishments will be widely applied. The more significant function of the Clause, therefore, is to protect against the danger of their arbitrary infliction. A third principle inherent in the Clause is that a severe punishment must not be unacceptable to contemporary society. Rejection by society, of course, is a strong indication that a severe punishment does not comport with human dignity. In applying this principle, however, we must make certain that the judicial determination is as objective as possible. Thus, for example, Weems . . . and Trop suggest that one factor that may be considered is the existence of the punishment in jurisdictions other than those before the Court. Wilkerson suggests that another factor to be considered is the historic usage of the punishment. Trop . . . combined present acceptance with past usage by observing that ‘the death penalty has been employed throughout our history, and, in a day when it is still widely accepted, it cannot be said to violate the constitutional concept of cruelty.’ In Robinson v. 110 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 California . . . which involved the infliction of punishment for narcotics addiction, the Court went a step further, concluding simply that ‘in the light of contemporary human knowledge, a law which made a criminal offense of such disease would doubtless be universally thought to be an infliction of cruel and unusual punishment.’ The question under this principle, then, is whether there are objective indicators from which a court can conclude that contemporary society considers a severe punishment unacceptable. Accordingly, the judicial task is to review the history of a challenged punishment and to examine society’s present practices with respect to its use. Legislative authorization, of course, does not establish acceptance. The acceptability of a severe punishment is measured, not by its availability, for it might become so offensive to society as never to be inflicted, but by its use. The final principle inherent in the Clause is that a severe punishment must not be excessive. A punishment is excessive under this principle if it is unnecessary: The infliction of a severe punishment by the State cannot comport with human dignity when it is nothing more than the pointless infliction of suffering. If there is a significantly less severe punishment adequate to achieve the purposes for which the punishment is inflicted, . . . the punishment inflicted is unnecessary and therefore excessive. This principle appeared in our cases in Mr. Justice Field’s dissent in O’Neil v. Vermont . . .. He there took the position that: ‘(The Clause) is directed, not only against punishments of the character mentioned (torturous punishments), but against all punishments which by their excessive length 111 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 or severity are greatly disproportioned to the offenses charged. The whole inhibition is against that which is excessive either in the bail required, or fine imposed, or punishment inflicted.’ Although the determination that a severe punishment is excessive may be grounded in a judgment that it is disproportionate to the crime, the more significant basis is that the punishment serves no penal purpose more effectively than a less severe punishment. This view of the principle was explicitly recognized by the Court in Weems. There the Court, reviewing a severe punishment inflicted for the falsification of an official record, found that ‘the highest punishment possible for a crime which may cause the loss of many thousand(s) of dollars, and to prevent which the duty of the state should be as eager as to prevent the perversion of truth in a public document, is not greater than that which may be imposed for falsifying a single item of a public account.’ Stating that ‘this contrast shows more than different exercises of legislative judgment,’ the Court concluded that the punishment was unnecessarily severe in view of the purposes for which it was imposed. There are, then, four principles by which we may determine whether a particular punishment is ‘cruel and unusual.’ The primary principle, which I believe supplies the essential predicate for the application of the others, is that a punishment must not by its severity be degrading to human dignity. The paradigm violation of this principle would be the infliction of a torturous punishment of the type that the Clause has always prohibited. Yet ‘(i)t is unlikely that any State at this moment in history(,)’ . . . would pass a law 112 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 providing for the infliction of such a punishment. Indeed, no such punishment has ever been before this Court. The same may be said of the other principles. It is unlikely that this Court will confront a severe punishment that is obviously inflicted in wholly arbitrary fashion; no State would engage in a reign of blind terror. Nor is it likely that this Court will be called upon to review a severe punishment that is clearly and totally rejected throughout society; no legislature would be able even to authorize the infliction of such a punishment. Nor, finally, is it likely that this Court will have to consider a severe punishment that is patently unnecessary; no State today would inflict a severe punishment knowing that there was no reason whatever for doing so. In short, we are unlikely to have occasion to determine that a punishment is fatally offensive under any one principle. Since the Bill of Rights was adopted, this Court has adjudged only three punishments to be within the prohibition of the Clause. Each punishment, of course, was degrading to human dignity, but of none could it be said conclusively that it was fatally offensive under one or the other of the principles. Rather, these ‘cruel and unusual punishments’ seriously implicated several of the principles, and it was the application of the principles in combination that supported the judgment. That, indeed, is not surprising. The function of these principles, after all, is simply to provide means by which a court can determine whether a challenged punishment comports with human dignity. They are, therefore, interrelated, and in most cases it will be their convergence that will justify the conclusion that a punishment is ‘cruel and unusual.’ The test, then, will ordinarily be a cumulative one: If a punishment is unusually severe, if there is a strong 113 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 probability that it is inflicted arbitrarily, if it is substantially rejected by contemporary society, and if there is no reason to believe that it serves any penal purpose more effectively than some less severe punishment, then the continued infliction of that punishment violates the command of the Clause that the State may not inflict inhuman and uncivilized punishments upon those convicted of crimes. III The punishment challenged in these cases is death. Death, of course, is a ‘traditional’ punishment, . . . one that ‘has been employed throughout our history,’ . . . and its constitutional background is accordingly an appropriate subject of inquiry. There is, first, a textual consideration raised by the Bill of Rights itself. The Fifth Amendment declares that if a particular crime is punishable by death, a person charged with that crime is entitled to certain procedural protections. We can thus infer that the Framers recognized the existence of what was then a common punishment. We cannot, however, make the further inference that they intended to exempt this particular punishment from the express prohibition of the Cruel and Unusual Punishments Clause. Nor is there any indication in the debates on the Clause that a special exception was to be made for death. If anything, the indication is to the contrary, for Livermore specifically mentioned death as a candidate for future proscription under the Clause. Finally, it does not advance analysis to insist that the Framers did not believe that adoption of the Bill of Rights would immediately prevent the infliction of the punishment of death; neither did they believe that it would immediately 114 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 prevent the infliction of other corporal punishments that, although common at the time, . . . are now acknowledged to be impermissible. There is also the consideration that this Court has decided three cases involving constitutional challenges to particular methods of inflicting this punishment. . . . These three decisions thus reveal that the Court, while ruling upon various methods of inflicting death, has assumed in the past that death was a constitutionally permissible punishment. Past assumptions, however, are not sufficient to limit the scope of our examination of this punishment today. The constitutionality of death itself under the Cruel and Unusual Punishments Clause is before this Court for the first time; we cannot avoid the question by recalling past cases that never directly considered it. The question, then, is whether the deliberate infliction of death is today consistent with the command of the Clause that the State may not inflict punishments that do not comport with human dignity. I will analyze the punishment of death in terms of the principles set out above and the cumulative test to which they lead: It is a denial of human dignity for the State arbitrarily to subject a person to an unusually severe punishment that society has indicated it does not regard as acceptable, and that cannot be shown to serve any penal purpose more effectively than a significantly less drastic punishment. Under these principles and this test, death is today a ‘cruel and unusual’ punishment. Death is a unique punishment in the United States. In a society that so strongly affirms the sanctity of life, not surprisingly the common view is that death is the ultimate sanction. This natural human feeling appears all about us. 115 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 There has been no national debate about punishment, in general or by imprisonment, comparable to the debate about the punishment of death. No other punishment has been so continuously restricted, . . . nor has any State yet abolished prisons, as some have abolished this punishment. And those States that still inflict death reserve it for the most heinous crimes. Juries, of course, have always treated death cases differently, as have governors exercising their commutation powers. Criminal defendants are of the same view. ‘As all practicing lawyers know, who have defended persons charged with capital offenses, often the only goal possible is to avoid the death penalty.’ Some legislatures have required particular procedures, such as two-stage trials and automatic appeals, applicable only in death cases. ‘It is the universal experience in the administration of criminal justice that those charged with capital offenses are granted special considerations.’ This Court, too, almost always treats death cases as a class apart. And the unfortunate effect of this punishment upon the functioning of the judicial process is well known; no other punishment has a similar effect. The only explanation for the uniqueness of death is its extreme severity. Death is today an unusually severe punishment, unusual in its pain, in its finality, and in its enormity. No other existing punishment is comparable to death in terms of physical and mental suffering. Although our information is not conclusive, it appears that there is no method available that guarantees an immediate and painless death. Since the discontinuance of flogging as a constitutionally permissible punishment, . . . death remains as the only punishment that may involve the conscious infliction of physical pain. In addition, we know that mental pain is an 116 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 inseparable part of our practice of punishing criminals by death, for the prospect of pending execution exacts a frightful toll during the inevitable long wait between the imposition of sentence and the actual infliction of death. As the California Supreme Court pointed out, ‘the process of carrying out a verdict of death is often so degrading and brutalizing to the human spirit as to constitute psychological torture.’ Indeed, as Mr. Justice Frankfurther noted, ‘the onset of insanity while awaiting execution of a death sentence is not a rare phenomenon.’ The ‘fate of ever-increasing fear and distress’ to which the expatriate is subjected . . . can only exist to a greater degree for a person confined in prison awaiting death. The unusual severity of death is manifested most clearly in its finality and enormity. Death, in these respects, is in a class by itself. Expatriation, for example, is a punishment that ‘destroys for the individual the political existence that was centuries in the development(,)’ that ‘strips the citizen of his status in the national and international political community (,)’ and that puts ‘(h)is very existence’ in jeopardy. Expatriation thus inherently entails ‘the total destruction of the individual’s status in organized society. ‘In short, the expatriate has lost the right to have rights.’ Yet, demonstrably, expatriation is not ‘a fate worse than death.’ Although death, like expatriation, destroys the individual’s ‘political existence’ and his ‘status in organized society,’ it does more, for, unlike expatriation, death also destroys ‘(h)is very existence.’ There is, too, at least the possibility that the expatriate will in the future regain ‘the right to have rights.’ Death forecloses even that possibility. Death is truly an awesome punishment. The calculated killing of a human being by the State involves, by its very 117 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 nature, a denial of the executed person’s humanity. The contrast with the plight of a person punished by imprisonment is evident. An individual in prison does not lose ‘the right to have rights.’ A prisoner retains, for example, the constitutional rights to the free exercise of religion, to be free of cruel and unusual punishments, and to treatment as a ‘person’ for purposes of due process of law and the equal protection of the laws. A prisoner remains a member of the human family. Moreover, he retains the right of access to the courts. His punishment is not irrevocable. Apart from the common charge, grounded upon the recognition of human fallibility, that the punishment of death must inevitably be inflicted upon innocent men, we know that death has been the lot of men whose convictions were unconstitutionally secured in view of later, retroactively applied, holdings of this Court. The punishment itself may have been unconstitutionally inflicted, . . . yet the finality of death precludes relief. An executed person has indeed ‘lost the right to have rights.’ As one 19th century proponent of punishing criminals by death declared, ‘When a man is hung, there is an end of our relations with him. His execution is a way of saying, ‘You are not fit for this world, take your chance elsewhere.“ In comparison to all other punishments today, then, the deliberate extinguishment of human life by the State is uniquely degrading to human dignity. I would not hesitate to hold, on that ground alone, that death is today a ‘cruel and unusual’ punishment, were it not that death is a punishment of longstanding usage and acceptance in this country. I therefore turn to the second principle-that the State may not arbitrarily inflict an unusually severe punishment. 118 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 The outstanding characteristic of our present practice of punishing criminals by death is the infrequency with which we resort to it. The evidence is conclusive that death is not the ordinary punishment for any crime. There has been a steady decline in the infliction of this punishment in every decade since the 1930’s, the earliest period for which accurate statistics are available. In the 1930’s, executions averaged 167 per year; in the 1940’s, the average was 128; in the 1950’s, it was 72; and in the years 1960-1962, it was 48. There have been a total of 46 executions since then, 36 of them in 1963-1964. Yet our population and the number of capital crimes committed have increased greatly over the past four decades. The contemporary rarity of the infliction of this punishment is thus the end result of a long-continued decline. . . . . When a country of over 200 million people inflicts an unusually severe punishment no more than 50 times a year, the inference is strong that the punishment is not being regularly and fairly applied. To dispel it would indeed require a clear showing of nonarbitrary infliction. Although there are no exact figures available, we know that thousands of murders and rapes are committed annually in States where death is an authorized punishment for those crimes. However the rate of infliction is characterized–as ‘freakishly’ or ‘spectacularly’ rare, or simply as rare–it would take the purest sophistry to deny that death is inflicted in only a minute fraction of these cases. How much rarer, after all, could the infliction of death be? When the punishment of death is inflicted in a trivial number of the cases in which it is legally available, the conclusion is virtually inescapable that it is being inflicted 119 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 arbitrarily. Indeed, it smacks of little more than a lottery system. . . . . When there is a strong probability that an unusually severe and degrading punishment is being inflicted arbitrarily, we may well expect that society will disapprove of its infliction. I turn, therefore, to the third principle. An examination of the history and present operation of the American practice of punishing criminals by death reveals that this punishment has been almost totally rejected by contemporary society. . . . . From the beginning of our Nation, the punishment of death has stirred acute public controversy. Although pragmatic arguments for and against the punishment have been frequently advanced, this longstanding and heated controversy cannot be explained solely as the result of differences over the practical wisdom of a particular government policy. At bottom, the battle has been waged on moral grounds. The country has debated whether a society for which the dignity of the individual is the supreme value can, without a fundamental inconsistency, follow the practice of deliberately putting some of its members to death. In the United States, as in other nations of the western world, ‘the struggle about this punishment has been one between ancient and deeply rooted beliefs in retribution, atonement or vengeance on the one hand, and, on the other, beliefs in the personal value and dignity of the common man that were born of the democratic movement of the eighteenth century, as well as beliefs in the scientific approach to an understanding of the motive forces of human conduct, which are the result of the growth of the sciences of behavior during the nineteenth and twentieth centuries.’ It is this essentially moral conflict that forms the backdrop for the past changes in and the present 120 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 operation of our system of imposing death as a punishment for crime. Our practice of punishing criminals by death has changed greatly over the years. One significant change has been in our methods of inflicting death. Although this country never embraced the more violent and repulsive methods employed in England, we did for a long time rely almost exclusively upon the gallows and the firing squad. Since the development of the supposedly more humane methods of electrocution late in the 19th century and lethal gas in the 20th, however, hanging and shooting have virtually ceased. Our concern for decency however, hanging and shooting have virtually changes in the circumstances surrounding the execution itself. No longer does our society countenance the spectacle of public executions, once thought desirable as a deterrent to criminal behavior by others. Today we reject public executions as debasing and brutalizing to us all. Also significant is the drastic decrease in the crimes for which the punishment of death is actually inflicted. While esoteric capital crimes remain on the books, since 1930 murder and rape have accounted for nearly 99% of the total executions, and murder alone for about 87%. In addition, the crime of capital murder has itself been limited. As the Court noted in McGautha v. California, . . . there was in this country a ‘rebellion against the common-law rule imposing a mandatory death sentence on all convicted murderers.’ Initially, that rebellion resulted in legislative definitions that distinguished between degrees of murder, retaining the mandatory death sentence only for murder in the first degree. Yet ‘(t)his new legislative criterion for isolating crimes appropriately punishable by death soon proved as unsuccessful as the 121 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 concept of ‘malice aforethought(,)“ the common-law means of separating murder from manslaughter. Not only was the distinction between degrees of murder confusing and uncertain in practice, but even in clear cases of first-degree murder juries continued to take the law into their own hands: if they felt that death was an inappropriate punishment, ‘they simply refused to convict of the capital offense.’ The phenomenon of jury nullification thus remained to counteract the rigors of mandatory death sentences. Bowing to reality, ‘legislatures did not try, as before, to refine further the definition of capital homicides. Instead they adopted the method of forthrightly granting juries the discretion which they had been exercising in fact.’ Ibid. In consequence, virtually all death sentences today are discretionarily imposed. Finally, it is significant that nine States no longer inflict the punishment of death under any circumstances, and five others have restricted it to extremely rare crimes. Thus, although ‘the death penalty has been employed throughout our history,’ . . . in fact the history of this punishment is one of successive restriction. What was once a common punishment has become, in the context of a continuing moral debate, increasingly rare. The evolution of this punishment evidences, not that it is an inevitable part of the American scene, but that it has proved progressively more troublesome to the national conscience. The result of this movement is our current system of administering the punishment, under which death sentences are rarely imposed and death is even more rarely inflicted. It is, of course, ‘We, the People’ who are responsible for the rarity both of the imposition and the carrying out of this punishment. Juries, ‘express(ing) the conscience of the community on the ultimate 122 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 question of life or death,’ . . . have been able to bring themselves to vote for death in a mere 100 or so cases among the thousands tried each year where the punishment is available. Governors, elected by and acting for us, have regularly commuted a substantial number of those sentences. And it is our society that insists upon due process of law to the end that no person will be unjustly put to death, thus ensuring that many more of those sentences will not be carried out. In sum, we have made death a rare punishment today. The progressive decline in, and the current rarity of, the infliction of death demonstrate that our society seriously questions the appropriateness of this punishment today. The States point out that many legislatures authorize death as the punishment for certain crimes and that substantial segments of the public, as reflected in opinion polls and referendum votes, continue to support it. Yet the availability of this punishment through statutory authorization, as well as the polls and referenda, which amount simply to approval of that authorization, simply underscores the extent to which our society has in fact rejected this punishment. When an unusually severe punishment is authorized for wide-scale application but not, because of society’s refusal, inflicted save in a few instances, the inference is compelling that there is a deep-seated reluctance to inflict it. Indeed, the likelihood is great that the punishment is tolerated only because of its disuse. The objective indicator of society’s view of an unusually severe punishment is what society does with it, and today society will inflict death upon only a small sample of the eligible criminals. Rejection could hardly be more complete without becoming absolute. At the very least, I must conclude 123 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 that contemporary society views this punishment with substantial doubt. The final principle to be considered is that an unusually severe and degrading punishment may not be excessive in view of the purposes for which it is inflicted. This principle, too, is related to the others. When there is a strong probability that the State is arbitrarily inflicting an unusually severe punishment that is subject to grave societal doubts, it is likely also that the punishment cannot be shown to be serving any penal purpose that could not be served equally well by some less severe punishment. The States’ primary claim is that death is a necessary punishment because it prevents the commission of capital crimes more effectively than any less severe punishment. The first part of this claim is that the infliction of death is necessary to stop the individuals executed from committing further crimes. The sufficient answer to this is that if a criminal convicted of a capital crime poses a danger to society, effective administration of the State’s pardon and parole laws can delay or deny his release from prison, and techniques of isolation can eliminate or minimize the danger while he remains confined. The more significant argument is that the threat of death prevents the commission of capital crimes because it deters potential criminals who would not be deterred by the threat of imprisonment. The argument is not based upon evidence that the threat of death is a superior deterrent. Indeed, as my Brother MARSHALL establishes, the available evidence uniformly indicates, although it does not conclusively prove, that the threat of death has no greater deterrent effect than the threat of imprisonment. The States argue, however, that 124 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 they are entitled to rely upon common human experience, and that experience, they say, supports the conclusion that death must be a more effective deterrent than any less severe punishment. Because people fear death the most, the argument runs, the threat of death must be the greatest deterrent. It is important to focus upon the precise import of this argument. It is not denied that many, and probably most, capital crimes cannot be deterred by the threat of punishment. Thus the argument can apply only to those who think rationally about the commission of capital crimes. Particularly is that true when the potential criminal, under this argument, must not only consider the risk of punishment, but also distinguish between two possible punishments. The concern, then, is with a particular type of potential criminal, the rational person who will commit a capital crime knowing that the punishment is long-term imprisonment, which may well be for the rest of his life, but will not commit the crime knowing that the punishment is death. On the face of it, the assumption that such persons exist is implausible. In any event, this argument cannot be appraised in the abstract. We are not presented with the theoretical question whether under any imaginable circumstances the threat of death might be a greater deterrent to the commission of capital crimes than the threat of imprisonment. We are concerned with the practice of punishing criminals by death as it exists in the United States today. Proponents of this argument necessarily admit that its validity depends upon the existence of a system in which the punishment of death is invariably and swiftly imposed. Our system, of course, satisfies neither condition. A rational person contemplating a 125 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 murder or rape is confronted, not with the certainty of a speedy death, but with the slightest possibility that he will be executed in the distant future. The risk of death is remote and improbable; in contrast, the risk of long-term imprisonment is near and great. In short, whatever the speculative validity of the assumption that the threat of death is a superior deterrent, there is no reason to believe that as currently administered the punishment of death is necessary to deter the commission of capital crimes. Whatever might be the case were all or substantially all eligible criminals quickly put to death, unverifiable possibilities are an insufficient basis upon which to conclude that the threat of death today has any greater deterrent efficacy than the threat of imprisonment. There is, however, another aspect to the argument that the punishment of death is necessary for the protection of society. The infliction of death, the States urge, serves to manifest the community’s outrage at the commission of the crime. It is, they say, a concrete public expression of moral indignation that inculcates respect for the law and helps assure a more peaceful community. Moreover, we are told, not only does the punishment of death exert this widespread moralizing influence upon community values, it also satisfies the popular demand for grievous condemnation of abhorrent crimes and thus prevents disorder, lynching, and attempts by private citizens to take the law into their own hands. The question, however, is not whether death serves these supposed purposes of punishment, but whether death serves them more effectively than imprisonment. There is no evidence whatever that utilization of imprisonment rather than death encourages private blood feuds and other disorders. Surely if there were such a danger, the execution of 126 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 a handful of criminals each year would not prevent it. The assertion that death alone is a sufficiently emphatic denunciation for capital crimes suffers from the same defect. If capital crimes require the punishment of death in order to provide moral reinforcement for the basic values of the community, those values can only be undermined when death is so rarely inflicted upon the criminals who commit the crimes. Furthermore, it is certainly doubtful that the infliction of death by the State does in fact strengthen the community’s moral code; if the deliberate extinguishment of human life has any effect at all, it more likely tends to lower our respect for life and brutalize our values. That, after all, is why we no longer carry out public executions. In any event, this claim simply means that one purpose of punishment is to indicate social disapproval of crime. To serve that purpose our laws distribute punishments according to the gravity of crimes and punish more severely the crimes society regards as more serious. That purpose cannot justify any particular punishment as the upper limit of severity. There is, then, no substantial reason to believe that the punishment of death, as currently administered, is necessary for the protection of society. The only other purpose suggested, one that is independent of protection for society, is retribution. Shortly stated, retribution in this context means that criminals are put to death because they deserve it. Although it is difficult to believe that any State today wishes to proclaim adherence to ‘naked vengeance,’ . . . the States claim, in reliance upon its statutory authorization, that death is the only fit punishment for capital crimes and that this retributive purpose justifies its infliction. In the past, judged by its statutory authorization, death was considered 127 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 the only fit punishment for the crime of forgery, for the first federal criminal statute provided a mandatory death penalty for that crime. Obviously, concepts of justice change; no immutable moral order requires death for murderers and rapists. The claim that death is a just punishment necessarily refers to the existence of certain public beliefs. The claim must be that for capital crimes death alone comports with society’s notion of proper punishment. As administered today, however, the punishment of death cannot be justified as a necessary means of exacting retribution from criminals. When the overwhelming number of criminals who commit capital crimes go to prison, it cannot be concluded that death serves the purpose of retribution more effectively than imprisonment. The asserted public belief that murderers and rapists deserve to die is flatly inconsistent with the execution of a random few. As the history of the punishment of death in this country shows, our society wishes to prevent crime; we have no desire to kill criminals simply to get even with them. In sum, the punishment of death is inconsistent with all four principles: Death is an unusually severe and degrading punishment; there is a strong probability that it is inflicted arbitrarily; its rejection by contemporary society is virtually total; and there is no reason to believe that it serves any penal purpose more effectively than the less severe punishment of imprisonment. The function of these principles is to enable a court to determine whether a punishment comports with human dignity. Death, quite simply, does not. 128 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 IV When this country was founded, memories of the Stuart horrors were fresh and severe corporal punishments were common. Death was not then a unique punishment. The practice of punishing criminals by death, moreover, was widespread and by and large acceptable to society. Indeed, without developed prison systems, there was frequently no workable alternative. Since that time successive restrictions, imposed against the background of a continuing moral controversy, have drastically curtailed the use of this punishment. Today death is a uniquely and unusually severe punishment. When examined by the principles applicable under the Cruel and Unusual Punishments Clause, death stands condemned as fatally offensive to human dignity. The punishment of death is therefore ‘cruel and unusual,’ and the States may no longer inflict it as a punishment for crimes. Rather than kill an arbitrary handful of criminals each year, the States will confine them in prison. ‘The state thereby suffers nothing and loses no power. The purpose of punishment is fulfilled, crime is repressed by penalties of just, not tormenting, severity, its repetition is prevented, and hope is given for the reformation of the criminal.’ I concur in the judgments of the Court. [The concurrence of Justice STEWART is omitted.] [The concurrence of Justice WHITE is omitted.] Mr. Justice MARSHALL, concurring. .... 129 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 III Perhaps the most important principle in analyzing ‘cruel and unusual’ punishment questions is one that is reiterated again and again in the prior opinions of the Court: i.e., the cruel and unusual language ‘must draw its meaning from the evolving standards of decency that mark the progress of a maturing society.’ Thus, a penalty that was permissible at one time in our Nation’s history is not necessarily permissible today. The fact, therefore, that the Court, or individual Justices, may have in the past expressed an opinion that the death penalty is constitutional is not now binding on us. . . . There is no holding directly in point, and the very nature of the Eighth Amendment would dictate that unless a very recent decision existed, stare decisis would bow to changing values, and the question of the constitutionality of capital punishment at a given moment in history would remain open. Faced with an open question, we must establish our standards for decision. The decisions discussed in the previous section imply that a punishment may be deemed cruel and unusual for any one of four distinct reasons. First, there are certain punishments that inherently involve so much physical pain and suffering that civilized people cannot tolerate them-e.g., use of the rack, the thumbscrew, or other mont, . . .. Regardless of public sentiment with respect to imposition of one of these punishments in a particular case or at any one moment in history, the Constitution prohibits it. These are punishments that have been barred since the adoption of the Bill of Rights. Second, there are punishments that are unusual, signifying that they were previously unknown as penalties for a given 130 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 offense. If these punishments are intended to serve a humane purpose, they may be constitutionally permissible. [. . .] Third, a penalty may be cruel and unusual because it is excessive and serves no valid legislative purpose. The decisions previously discussed are replete with assertions that one of the primary functions of the cruel and unusual punishments clause is to prevent excessive or unnecessary penalties, . . . these punishments are unconstitutional even though popular sentiment may favor them. [. . .] [T]his Court has steadfastly maintained that a penalty is unconstitutional whenever it is unnecessarily harsh or cruel. This is what the Founders of this country intended; this is what their fellow citizens believed the Eighth Amendment provided; and this was the basis for our decision in Robinson v. California, supra, for the plurality opinion by Chief Justice Warren in Trop v. Dulles, supra, and for the Court’s decision in Weems v. United States, supra. It should also be noted that the ‘cruel and unusual’ language of the Eighth Amendment immediately follows language that prohibits excessive bail and excessive fines. The entire thrust of the Eighth Amendment is, in short, against ‘that which is excessive.’ Fourth, where a punishment is not excessive and serves a valid legislative purpose, it still may be invalid if popular sentiment abhors it. For example, if the evidence clearly demonstrated that capital punishment served valid legislative purposes, such punishment would, nevertheless, be unconstitutional if citizens found it to be morally unacceptable. A general abhorrence on the part of the public would, in effect, equate a modern punishment with those barred since the adoption of the Eighth Amendment. There are no prior cases in this Court striking down a penalty on 131 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 this ground, but the very notion of changing values requires that we recognize its existence. It is immediately obvious, then, that since capital punishment is not a recent phenomenon, if it violates the Constitution, it does so because it is excessive or unnecessary, or because it is abhorrent to currently existing moral values. We must proceed to the history of capital punishment in the United States. IV Capital punishment has been used to penalize various forms of conduct by members of society since the beginnings of civilization. Its precise origins are difficult to perceive, but there is some evidence that its roots lie in violent retaliation by members of a tribe or group, or by the tribe or group itself, against persons committing hostile acts toward group members. Thus, infliction of death as a penalty or objectionable conduct appears to have its beginnings in private vengeance. As individuals gradually ceded their personal prerogatives to a sovereign power, the sovereign accepted the authority to punish wrongdoing as part of its ‘divine right’ to rule. Individual vengeance gave way to the vengeance of the state, and capital punishment became a public function. Capital punishment worked its way into the laws of various countries, and was inflicted in a variety of macabre and horrific ways. It was during the reign of Henry II (1154-1189) that English law first recognized that crime was more than a personal affair between the victim and the perpetrator. 132 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 [Justice Marshall provides a brief history of the expansion of capital crimes in England from the 16th to 19th centuries. He then turns to the history of capital crimes in the United States, noting that while there were generally far fewer capital offenses than in England, executions were still commonplace. Justice Marshall also highlights how opposition to capital punishment is as old as the United States itself. Abolitionists were largely successful in eliminating mandatory capital punishment, with some states abolishing the practice outright by the early 1900s. However, the abolitionist movement was set back by World War I and never fully recovered the momentum they had coming into the 1900s.] At the present time, 41 States, the District of Columbia, and other federal jurisdictions authorize the death penalty for at least one crime. It would be fruitless to attempt here to categorize the approach to capital punishment taken by the various States. It is sufficient to note that murder is the crime most often punished by death, followed by kidnapping and treason. Rape is a capital offense in 16 States and the federal system. The foregoing history demonstrates that capital punishment was carried from Europe to America but, once here, was tempered considerably. At times in our history, strong abolitionist movements have existed. But, they have never been completely successful, as no more than one-quarter of the States of the Union have, at any one time, abolished the death penalty. They have had partial success, however, especially in reducing the number of capital crimes, replacing mandatory death sentences with jury discretion, and developing more humane methods of conducting executions. 133 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 This is where our historical foray leads. The question now to be faced is whether American society has reached a point where abolition is not dependent on a successful grass roots movement in particular jurisdictions, but is demanded by the Eighth Amendment. To answer this question, we must first examine whether or not the death penalty is today tantamount to excessive punishment. V In order to assess whether or not death is an excessive or unnecessary penalty, it is necessary to consider the reasons why a legislature might select it as punishment for one or more offenses, and examine whether less severe penalties would satisfy the legitimate legislative wants as well as capital punishment. If they would, then the death penalty is unnecessary cruelty, and, therefore, unconstitutional. There are six purposes conceivably served by capital punishment: retribution, deterrence, prevention of repetitive criminal acts, encouragement of guilty pleas and confessions, eugenics, and economy. These are considered seriatim below. A. The concept of retribution is one of the most misunderstood in all of our criminal jurisprudence. The principal source of confusion derives from the fact that, in dealing with the concept, most people confuse the question ‘why do men in fact punish?’ with the question ‘what justifies men in punishing?’ Men may punish for any number of reasons, but the one reason that punishment is morally good or morally justifiable is that someone has broken the law. Thus, it can correctly be said that breaking the law is the sine qua non of punishment, or, in other words, that we only 134 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 tolerate punishment as it is imposed on one who deviates from the norm established by the criminal law. The fact that the State may seek retribution against those who have broken its laws does not mean that retribution may then become the State’s sole end in punishing. Our jurisprudence has always accepted deterrence in general, deterrence of individual recidivism, isolation of dangerous persons, and rehabilitation as proper goals of punishment. Retaliation, vengeance, and retribution have been roundly condemned as intolerable aspirations for a government in a free society. Punishment as retribution has been condemned by scholars for centuries, and the Eighth Amendment itself was adopted to prevent punishment from becoming synonymous with vengeance. . . . . It is plain that the view of the Weems Court was that punishment for the sake of retribution was not permissible under the Eighth Amendment. This is the only view that the Court could have taken if the ‘cruel and unusual’ language were to be given any meaning. Retribution surely underlies the imposition of some punishment on one who commits a criminal act. But, the fact that some punishment may be imposed does not mean that any punishment is permissible. If retribution alone could serve as a justification for any particular penalty, then all penalties selected by the legislature would be definition be acceptable means for designating society’s moral approbation of a particular act. The ‘cruel and unusual’ language would thus be read out of the Constitution and the fears of Patrick Henry and the other Founding Fathers would become realities. 135 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 To preserve the integrity of the Eighth Amendment, the Court has consistently denigrated retribution as a permissible goal of punishment. It is undoubtedly correct that there is a demand for vengeance on the part of many persons in a community against one who is convicted of a particularly offensive act. At times a cry is heard that morality requires vengeance to evidence society’s abhorrence of the act. But the Eighth Amendment is our insulation from our baser selves. The ‘cruel and unusual’ language limits the avenues through which vengeance can be channeled. Were this not so, the language would be empty and a return to the rack and other tortures would be possible in a given case. Mr. Justice Story wrote that the Eighth Amendment’s limitation on punishment ‘would seem to be wholly unnecessary in a free government, since it is scarcely possible that any department of such a government should authorize or justify such atrocious conduct. I would reach an opposite conclusion—that only in a free society would men recognize their inherent weaknesses and seek to compensate for them by means of a Constitution. The history of the Eighth Amendment supports only the conclusion that retribution for its own sake is improper. B. The most hotly contested issue regarding capital punishment is whether it is better than life imprisonment as a deterrent to crime. While the contrary position has been argued, it is my firm opinion that the death penalty is a more severe sanction than life imprisonment. Admittedly, there are some persons who would rather die than languish in prison for a lifetime. But, whether or not they should be able to choose death as an alternative is a far different question from that presented here 136 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 —i.e., whether the State can impose death as a punishment. Death is irrevocable; life imprisonment is not. Death, of course, makes rehabilitation impossible; life imprisonment does not. In short, death has always been viewed as the ultimate sanction, and it seems perfectly reasonable to continue to view it as such. It must be kept in mind, then, that the question to be considered is not simply whether capital punishment is a deterrent, but whether it is a better deterrent than life imprisonment. There is no more complex problem than determining the deterrent efficacy of the death penalty. ‘Capital punishment has obviously failed as a deterrent when a murder is committed. We can number its failures. But we cannot number its successes. No one can ever know how many people have refrained from murder because of the fear of being hanged.’ This is the nub of the problem and it is exacerbated by the paucity of useful data. The United States is more fortunate than most countries, however, in that it has what are generally considered to be the world’s most reliable statistics. [Marshall reviews the obvious hypotheses about deterrence and reviews the state of the empirical evidence.] In sum, the only support for the theory that capital punishment is an effective deterrent is found in the hypotheses with which we began and the occasional stories about a specific individual being deterred from doing a contemplated criminal act. These claims of specific deterrence are often spurious, however, and may be more than counterbalanced by the tendency of capital punishment to incite certain crimes. 137 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 .... Despite the fact that abolitionists have not proved nondeterrence beyond a reasonable doubt, they have succeeded in showing by clear and convincing evidence that capital punishment is not necessary as a deterrent to crime in our society. This is all that they must do. We would shirk our judicial responsibilities if we failed to accept the presently existing statistics and demanded more proof. It may be that we now possess all the proof that anyone could ever hope to assemble on the subject. But, even if further proof were to be forthcoming, I believe there is more than enough evidence presently available for a decision in this case. .... In light of the massive amount of evidence before us, I see no alternative but to conclude that capital punishment cannot be justified on the basis of its deterrent effect. C. Much of what must be said about the death penalty as a device to prevent recidivism is obvious—if a murderer is executed, he cannot possibly commit another offense. The fact is, however, that murderers are extremely unlikely to commit other crimes either in prison or upon their release. For the most part, they are first offenders, and when released from prison they are known to become model citizens. Furthermore, most persons who commit capital crimes are not executed. With respect to those who are sentenced to die, it is critical to note that the jury is never asked to determine whether they are likely to be recidivists. In light of these facts, if capital punishment were justified purely on the basis of preventing recidivism, it would have to be considered to be excessive; no general need to obliterate all capital offenders 138 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 could have been demonstrated, nor any specific need in individual cases. D. The three final purposes which may underlie utilization of a capital sanction-encouraging guilty pleas and confessions, eugenics, and reducing state expenditures—may be dealt with quickly. If the death penalty is used to encourage guilty pleas and thus to deter suspects from exercising their rights under the Sixth Amendment to jury trials, it is unconstitutional. Its elimination would do little to impair the State’s bargaining position in criminal cases, since life imprisonment remains a severe sanction which can be used as leverage for bargaining for pleas or confessions in exchange either for charges of lesser offenses or recommendations of leniency. Moreover, to the extent that capital punishment is used to encourage confessions and guilty pleas, it is not being used for punishment purposes. A State that justifies capital punishment on its utility as part of the conviction process could not profess to rely on capital punishment as a deterrent. Such a State’s system would be structured with twin goals only: obtaining guilty pleas and confessions and imposing imprisonment as the maximum sanction. Since life imprisonment is sufficient for bargaining purposes, the death penalty is excessive if used for the same purposes. In light of the previous discussion on deterrence, any suggestions concerning the eugenic benefits of capital punishment are obviously meritless. As I pointed out above, there is not even any attempt made to discover which capital offenders are likely to be recidivists, let alone which are positively incurable. No test or procedure presently exists by which incurables can be screened from those who would benefit from treatment. On the one hand, due process would 139 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 seem to require that we have some procedure to demonstrate incurability before execution; and, on the other hand, equal protection would then seemingly require that all incurables be executed. . .. In addition, the ‘cruel and unusual’ language would require that life imprisonment, treatment and sterilization be inadequate for eugenic purposes. More importantly, this Nation has never formally professed eugenic goals, and the history of the world does not look kindly on them. If eugenics is one of our purposes, then the legislatures should say so forthrightly and design procedures to serve this goal. Until such time, I can only conclude, as has virtually everyone else who has looked at the problem,130 that capital punishment cannot be defended on the basis of any eugenic purposes. As for the argument that it is cheaper to execute a capital offender than to imprison him for life, even assuming that such an argument, if true, would support a capital sanction, it is simply incorrect. A disproportionate amount of money spent on prisons is attributable to death row. Condemned men are not productive members of the prison community, although they could be, and executions are expensive. Appeals are often automatic, and courts admittedly spend more time with death cases. At trial, the selection of jurors is likely to become a costly, time-consuming problem in a capital case, and defense counsel will reasonably exhaust every possible means to save his client from execution, no matter how long the trial takes. During the period between conviction and execution, there are an inordinate number of collateral attacks on the conviction and attempts to obtain executive clemency, all of which exhaust the time, money, and effort of the State. There 140 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 are also continual assertions that the condemned prisoner has gone insane. Because there is a formally established policy of not executing insane persons, great sums of money may be spent on detecting and curing mental illness in order to perform the execution. Since no one wants the responsibility for the execution, the condemned man is likely to be passed back and forth from doctors to custodial officials to courts like a ping-pong ball. The entire process is very costly. When all is said and done, there can be no doubt that it costs more to execute a man than to keep him in prison for life. E. There is but one conclusion that can be drawn from all of this-i.e., the death penalty is an excessive and unnecessary punishment that violates the Eighth Amendment. The statistical evidence is not convincing beyond all doubt, but it is persuasive. It is not improper at this point to take judicial notice of the fact that for more than 200 years men have labored to demonstrate that capital punishment serves no purpose that life imprisonment could not serve equally well. And they have done so with great success. Little, if any, evidence has been adduced to prove the contrary. The point has now been reached at which deference to the legislatures is tantamount to abdication of our judicial roles as factfinders, judges, and ultimate arbiters of the Constitution. We know that at some point the presumption of constitutionality accorded legislative acts gives way to a realistic assessment of those acts. This point comes when there is sufficient evidence available so that judges can determine, not whether the legislature acted wisely, but whether it had any rational basis whatsoever for acting. We have this evidence before us now. There is no rational basis for concluding that capital 141 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 punishment is not excessive. It therefore violates the Eighth Amendment. VI In addition, even if capital punishment is not excessive, it nonetheless violates the Eighth Amendment because it is morally unacceptable to the people of the United States at this time in their history. In judging whether or not a given penalty is morally acceptable, most courts have said that the punishment is valid unless ‘it shocks the conscience and sense of justice of the people.’ [Justice Marshall explains that the details of the death penalty are generally unknown to the public. It particular, he focuses on how its discriminatory application against minorities and the poor would likely shock the conscience of the general public if it was well known.] Assuming knowledge of all the facts presently available regarding capital punishment, the average citizen would, in my opinion, find it shocking to his conscience and sense of justice. For this reason alone capital punishment cannot stand. VII [. . .] In striking down capital punishment, this Court does not malign our system of government. On the contrary, it pays homage to it. Only in a free society could right triumph in difficult times, and could civilization record its magnificent 142 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 advancement. In recognizing the humanity of our fellow beings, we pay ourselves the highest tribute. We achieve ‘a major milestone in the long road up from barbarism’ and join the approximately 70 other jurisdictions in the world which celebrate their regard for civilization and humanity by shunning capital punishment. I concur in the judgments of the Court. Mr. Chief Justice BURGER, with whom Mr. Justice BLACKMUN, Mr. Justice POWELL, and Mr. Justice REHNQUIST join, dissenting. [NOTE: only Part IV of Chief Justice Burger’s dissent is provided here.] IV Capital punishment has also been attacked as violative of the Eighth Amendment on the ground that it is not needed to achieve legitimate penal aims and is thus ‘unnecessarily cruel.’ As a pure policy matter, this approach has much to recommend it, but it seeks to give a dimension to the Eighth Amendment that it was never intended to have and promotes a line of inquiry that this Court has never before pursued. The Eighth Amendment, as I have noted, was included in the Bill of Rights to guard against the use of torturous and inhuman punishments, not those of limited efficacy. One of the few to speak out against the adoption of the Eighth Amendment asserted that it is often necessary to use cruel punishments to deter crimes. But among those favoring the Amendment, no sentiment was expressed that a punishment 143 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 of extreme cruelty could ever be justified by expediency. The dominant theme of the Eighth Amendment debates was that the ends of the criminal laws cannot justify the use of measures of extreme cruelty to achieve them. The apparent seed of the ‘unnecessary cruelty’ argument is the following language, quoted earlier, found in Wilkerson v. Utah, supra: ‘Difficulty would attend the effort to define with exactness the extent of the constitutional provision which provides that cruel and unusual punishments shall not be inflicted; but it is safe to affirm that punishments of torture . . . and all others in the same line of unnecessary cruelty, are forbidden by that amendment to the Constitution.’ To lift the italicized phrase from the context of the Wilkerson opinion and now view it as a mandate for assessing the value of punishments in achieving the aims of penology is a gross distortion; nowhere are such aims even mentioned in the Wilkerson opinion. The only fair reading of this phrase is that punishments similar to torture in their extreme cruelty are prohibited by the Eighth Amendment. In Louisiana ex rel. Francis v. Resweber . . . the Court made reference to the Eighth Amendment’s prohibition against the infliction of ‘unnecessary pain’ in carrying out an execution. The context makes abundantly clear that the Court was disapproving the wanton infliction of physical pain, and once again not advising pragmatic analysis of punishments approved by legislatures. 144 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 Apart from these isolated uses of the word ‘unnecessary,’ nothing in the cases suggests that it is for the courts to make a determination of the efficacy of punishments. The decision in Weems v. United States, supra, is not to the contrary. In Weems the Court held that for the crime of falsifying public documents, the punishment imposed under the Philippine Code of 15 years’ imprisonment at hard labor under shackles, followed by perpetual surveillance, loss of voting rights, loss of the right to hold public office, and loss of right to change domicile freely, was violative of the Eighth Amendment. The case is generally regarded as holding that a punishment may be excessively cruel within the meaning of the Eighth Amendment because it is grossly out of proportion to the severity of the crime; some view the decision of the Court primarily as a reaction to the mode of the punishment itself. Under any characterization of the holding, it is readily apparent that the decision grew out of the Court’s overwhelming abhorrence of the imposition of the particular penalty for the particular crime; it was making an essentially moral judgment, not a dispassionate assessment of the need for the penalty. The Court specifically disclaimed ‘the right to assert a judgment against that of the legislature of the expediency of the laws . . ..’ Thus, apart from the fact that the Court in Weems concerned itself with the crime committed as well as the punishment imposed, the case marks no departure from the largely unarticulable standard of extreme cruelty. However intractable that standard may be, that is what the Eighth Amendment is all about. The constitutional provision is not addressed to social utility and does not command that enlightened principles of penology always be followed. 145 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 By pursuing the necessity approach, it becomes even more apparent that it involves matters outside the purview of the Eighth Amendment. Two of the several aims of punishment are generally associated with capital punishment-retribution and deterrence. It is argued that retribution can be discounted because that, after all, is what the Eighth Amendment seeks to eliminate. There is no authority suggesting that the Eighth Amendment was intended to purge the law of its retributive elements, and the Court has consistently assumed that retribution is a legitimate dimension of the punishment of crimes. Furthermore, responsible legal thinkers of widely varying persuasions have debated the sociological and philosophical aspects of the retribution question for generations, neither side being able to convince the other. It would be reading a great deal into the Eighth Amendment to hold that the punishments authorized by legislatures cannot constitutionally reflect a retributive purpose. The less esoteric but no less controversial question is whether the death penalty acts as a superior deterrent. Those favoring abolition find no evidence that it does. Those favoring retention start from the intuitive notion that capital punishment should act as the most effective deterrent and note that there is no convincing evidence that it does not. Escape from this empirical stalemate is sought by placing the burden of proof on the States and concluding that they have failed to demonstrate that capital punishment is a more effective deterrent than life imprisonment. Numerous justifications have been advanced for shifting the burden, and they are not without their rhetorical appeal. However, these arguments are not descended from established constitutional principles, but are born of the urge to bypass an unresolved 146 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 factual question. Comparative deterrence is not a matter that lends itself to precise measurement; to shift the burden to the States is to provide an illusory solution to an enormously complex problem. If it were proper to put the States to the test of demonstrating the deterrent value of capital punishment, we could just as well ask them to prove the need for life imprisonment or any other punishment. Yet I know of no convincing evidence that life imprisonment is a more effective deterrent than 20 years’ imprisonment, or even that a $10 parking ticket is a more effective deterrent than a $5 parking ticket. In fact, there are some who go so far as to challenge the notion that any punishments deter crime. If the States are unable to adduce convincing proof rebutting such assertions, does it then follow that all punishments are suspect as being ‘cruel and unusual’ within the meaning of the Constitution? On the contrary, I submit that the questions raised by the necessity approach are beyond the pale of judicial inquiry under the Eighth Amendment. [. . .] [The dissent of Justice Blackmun is omitted.] Mr. Justice POWELL, with whom THE CHIEF JUSTICE, Mr. Justice BLACKMUN, and Mr. Justice REHNQUIST join, dissenting. [NOTE: Only Part VI of the dissent is provided here.] 147 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 VI Petitioner in Branch v. Texas, and to a lesser extent the petitioners in the other cases before us today, urge that capital punishment is cruel and unusual because it no longer serves any rational legislative interests. Before turning to consider whether any of the traditional aims of punishment justify the death penalty, I should make clear the context in which I approach this aspect of the cases. First, I find no support-in the language of the Constitution, in its history, or in the cases arising under it-for the view that this Court may invalidate a category of penalties because we deem less severe penalties adequate to serve the ends of penology. While the cases affirm our authority to prohibit punishments that are cruelly inhumane . . . and punishments that are cruelly excessive in that they are disproportionate to particular crimes . . . the precedents of this Court afford no basis for striking down a particular form of punishment because we may be persuaded that means less stringent would be equally efficacious. Secondly, if we were free to question the justifications for the use of capital punishment, a heavy burden would rest on those who attack the legislatures’ judgments to prove the lack of rational justifications. This Court has long held that legislative decisions in this area, which lie within the special competency of that branch, are entitled to a presumption of validity. I come now to consider, subject to the reservations above expressed, the two justifications most often cited for the retention of capital punishment. The concept of retributionthough popular for centuries-is now criticized as unworthy of a civilized people. Yet this Court has acknowledged the 148 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 existence of a retributive element in criminal sanctions and has never heretofore found it impermissible. In Williams v. New York . . . Mr. Justice Black stated that, ‘Retribution is no longer the dominant objective of the criminal law. Reformation and rehabilitation of offenders have become important goals of criminal jurisprudence.’ It is clear, however, that the Court did not reject retribution altogether. The record in that case indicated that one of the reasons why the trial judge imposed the death penalty was his sense of revulsion at the ‘shocking details of the crime.’ Although his motivation was clearly retributive, the Court upheld the trial judge’s sentence. Similarly, Mr. Justice Marshall noted in his plurality opinion in Powell v. Texas . . . that this Court ‘has never held that anything in the Constitution requires that penal sanctions be designed solely to achieve therapeutic or rehabilitative effects.’ While retribution alone may seem an unworthy justification in a moral sense, its utility in a system of criminal justice requiring public support has long been recognized. Lord Justice Denning, now Master of the Rolls of the Court of Appeal in England, testified on this subject before the British Royal Commission on Capital Punishment: ‘Many are inclined to test the efficacy of punishment solely by its value as a deterrent: but this is too narrow a view. Punishment is the way in which society expresses its denunciation of wrong doing; and, in order to maintain respect for law, it is essential that the punishment inflicted for grave crimes should adequately reflect the revulsion felt by the great majority of citizens for them. It is a mistake to consider the objects of 149 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 punishment as being deterrent or reformative or preventive and nothing else. If this were so, we should not send to prison a man who was guilty of motor manslaughter, but only disqualify him from driving; but would public opinion be content with this? The truth is that some crimes are so outrageous that society insists on adequate punishment, because the wrong-doer deserves it, irrespective of whether it is a deterrent or not.’ The view expressed by Lord Denning was cited approvingly in the Royal Commission’s Report, recognizing ‘a strong and widespread demand for retribution.’ Mr. Justice STEWART makes much the same point in his opinion today when he concludes that expression of man’s retributive instincts in the sentencing process ‘serves an important purpose in promoting the stability of a society governed by law.’ The view, moreover, is not without respectable support in the jurisprudential literature in this country, despite a substantial body of opinion to the contrary. And it is conceded on all sides that, not infrequently, cases arise that are so shocking or offensive that the public demands the ultimate penalty for the transgressor. Deterrence is a more appealing justification, although opinions again differ widely. Indeed, the deterrence issue lies at the heart of much of the debate between the abolitionists and retentionists. Statistical studies based primarily on trends in States that have abolished the penalty, tend to support the view that the death penalty has not been proved to be a superior deterrent. Some dispute the validity of this conclusion, pointing out that the studies do not show that the death penalty has no deterrent effect on any categories of 150 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 crimes. On the basis of available, I find myself in agreement available, I find myself in a agreement with the conclusions drawn by the Royal Commission following its exhaustive study of this issue: ‘The general conclusion which we reach, after careful review of all the evidence we have been able to obtain as to the deterrent effect of capital punishment, may be stated as follows. Prima facie the penalty of death is likely to have a stronger effect as a deterrent to normal human beings than any other form of punishment, and there is some evidence (though no convincing statistical evidence) that this is in fact so. But this effect does not operate universally or uniformly, not operate universally or uniformly, and there are many offenders on whom it is limited and may often be negligible. It is accordingly important to view this question in a just perspective and not base a penal policy in relation to murder on exaggerated estimates of the uniquely deterrent force of the death penalty.’ Only recently this Court was called on to consider the deterrence argument in relation to punishment by fines for public drunkenness. The Court was unwilling to strike down the Texas statute on grounds that it lacked a rational foundation. What Mr. Justice Marshall said there would seem to have equal applicability in this case: ‘The long-standing and still raging debate over the validity of the deterrence justification for penal sanctions has not reached any sufficiently clear conclusions to 151 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 permit it to be said that such sanctions are ineffective in any particular context or for any particular group of people who are able to appreciate the consequences of their acts. . . .’ As I noted at the outset of this section, legislative judgments as to the efficacy of particular punishments are presumptively rational and may not be struck down under the Eighth Amendment because this Court may think that some alternative sanction would be more appropriate. Even if such judgments were within the judicial prerogative, petitioners have failed to show that there exist no justifications for the legislative enactments challenged in these cases. While the evidence and arguments advanced by petitioners might have proved profoundly persuasive if addressed to a legislative body, they do not approach the showing traditionally required before a court declares that the legislature has acted irrationally. [The dissent of Justice REHNQUIST, with whom THE CHIEF JUSTICE, Justice BLACKMUN, and Justice POWELL join, is omitted.] 152 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 Meeting 4: Law and Economics Suppose that we adopt the utilitarian model and decide that, generally, we want to create laws that produce “the greatest good for the greatest number” or that produce the best result considering costs and benefits. Once we are committed to evaluating the consequences of our legal regime, we are in the business of predicting the future. Economics is, in part, about predicting the behavior of masses of people in response to incentives. It seems natural, then, that we might turn to this field for help in crafting law. If we are to predict how society will unfold, we will need a model of human behavior. We want to know how a change in some social condition will cause human beings in our society to respond. Modeling human behavior is, to put it mildly, a hard problem. But for certain domains of human interaction and with large enough groups in the right context, a very simple model might produce useful, if incomplete, answers. The Rational Actor Model and Rational Choice Theory The Rational Actor Model models humans as preferencebearing entities who (a) seek to maximize the satisfaction of Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 those preferences and (b) do so coherently. We can add more to this definition, assuming, for example, that the preferences are self-interested. But further elaboration is unnecessary at this point. A rational actor presented with two flavors of ice cream each worth more to her than the money in her pocket will trade the money for a cone of the flavor she values most. We further assume that she can compare any two options, whether ice cream flavors, movies, or anything else. This means that her preferences are complete. Another assumption of the theory is that if our rational actor prefers chocolate over strawberry and strawberry over vanilla, then she must also prefer chocolate over vanilla. In other words, her preferences are transitive. Rational choice theory identifies larger scale social and economic effects with the sum of individual actions taken by rational actors. That’s our model. What will happen if we pass a law taxing high residential rental prices? Just figure out how a rational cost-benefit balancer would respond to the tax and extrapolate those effects to the larger economy. Such modeling can vary from back-of-the-envelope guesswork (general talk about incentives and rationality that can often appear in legal arguments) to sophisticated modeling based on exhaustively gathered data. The effect of the rational actor assumptions is that we can, to some degree, predict the actor’s response to incentives without actually being the actor. We know she will perform a rational cost-benefit calculation when deciding how to act. And so if we make the costs of something higher, she is more likely to avoid it. If we increase the benefits of a choice, she is more likely to make it. The deterrence theory of punishment 154 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 in criminal law is based on the idea that we can make interpersonal predictions in this way: Almost everyone prefers freedom to imprisonment, and so making imprisonment more likely and lengthier decreases the net benefit of a behavior we wish to criminalize. So too would increasing the enforcement effort, making imprisonment more likely. If we were committed to a pure deterrence theory, we would need to gather data to determine the structure of costs people in our society assign to various lengths of imprisonment in order to calibrate sentences. The last example added something: deterrence as a theory of what we wanted to accomplish together. Applying the rational actor model and rational choice theory to make predictions about consequences is just a methodology not a theory of the good. It is not inherently normative. A theory is normative if it purports to tell us what we should do. In contrast, a descriptive theory purports to tell us how things are, not what judgments we should make them. If we are to use the rational actor concept to say something normative, such as whether a law is desirable, we need to develop some criteria for good and bad. All such criteria start as bare definitions and become normative when we attach judgment to them. So let’s start with some definitions. Efficiency Suppose we experience a change in the state of the world from state A to state B. Perhaps that change is only that someone sold his car to another person. We say this change is efficient if it improves the satisfaction of preferences within the group we are studying. This notion of “improves” is vague. So let’s be a little more specific. 155 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 A change is Pareto efficient if someone in the group is made better off by the change and no one is made worse off. That is, there must be people who prefer the change and no one who prefers the older state. Let’s take our car example. Suppose we have a voluntary sale of a car. The buyer prefers the car to the money he must pay to get it. The seller prefers the money the buyer will give her over the car. As between the two of them, this transaction is Pareto efficient. Both are made better off in the sense that their preferences are better satisfied after the transaction has occurred. Neither is made worse off. If we look more broadly at the society of which our buyer and seller are members, this transaction still might be Pareto efficient. If no one else is affected by the transaction, then no one else is made worse off by the decision. And so we have two members of the society who are better off and no one who is worse off. That’s Pareto efficiency. If one of the two did not prefer the transaction, it would not be Pareto efficient. Just think of the cartoon example below. Even though there’s a big heart, symbolizing a lot of love for the change on the part of one person, there’s a thumbs down from the other. We can’t have any thumbs down in a Pareto efficient transaction. 156 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 Contract, in general, requires voluntary offers and acceptances. If we assume uncoerced, rational actors, then valid contracts would appear to be Pareto efficient as between the parties. Contracts that have effects on people not parties to them (consider a murder for hire contract) may well not be. We will take that situation up a bit later. Pareto efficiency is far too demanding a criterion for legal regulation. All rules will create winners and losers. That is, they will have distributive consequences. If we required that all laws be Pareto efficient, it is difficult to imagine we could have any laws. There is another notion of efficiency, however, that may fit the bill. A change in the state of the world is Kaldor-Hicks efficient if those who are made better off by the change could compensate those who are made worse off and still come out ahead. If such compensation actually occurred, the change would be Pareto efficient, because no one would wind up worse off. But Kaldor-Hicks efficiency does not demand that compensation occur, only that if it did we’d have no losers. Another way of thinking of this criterion is in terms of cost-benefit analysis. If we add up all the benefits (in terms of satisfied preferences) and subtracted all the costs (in terms of disappointed preferences), we’d have a positive number. All we require is 157 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 that the benefits of a Kaldor-Hicks efficient change outweigh the costs. In our car sale example, imagine now that there is a thirdparty, say the seller’s parents who had originally given the car to the seller as a sentimental gift. They are disappointed that the seller will part with the car. The sale, therefore, is no longer a Pareto efficient change. But if the benefits to the buyer and seller outweigh the parents’ disappointment, then it is a Kaldor-Hicks efficient change. The buyer and seller could take some of their utility and transfer it to offset the parents’ emotional loss (perhaps just by paying them) and remain happy that the sale occurred. If they cannot, if their happiness is in fact outweighed by the parents’ disappointment, then the exchange would not be Kaldor-Hicks efficient. This is ridiculously depicted below, where that thumbs down is much bigger than the two hearts combined. The costs outweigh the benefits. A less contrived example is that of a polluting factory. In the absence of statutes preventing it, a factory wishes to operate in way that will generate pollution that is unwelcome in a 158 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 neighboring town. The decision to operate is, therefore, not Pareto efficient. Is it Kaldor-Hicks efficient? Only if the benefits of operation outweigh the costs to those affected by the pollution. Notice that if we were to make a normative judgment that a Kaldor-Hicks efficient change should occur, then we are approving net gains despite their distributive impact on the losers. All cost-benefit analyses are efforts to quantify the efficiency of a proposal (whether law, regulation, contract, or business venture), but sometimes, either in the course of analyzing efficiency or for this very purpose, they identify the proposal’s distributive consequences. We may wish to trade some efficiency gains for more distributive fairness. Notions of distributive justice will be covered in a later reading. Externalities You may have noticed something that seemed especially unfair about the polluting factory example. The entity making the decision was not the entity that would bear some of the major costs of that decision. The factory’s decision to operate and pollute imposed costs on neighbors that the factory would not itself bear. These costs are external to the factory. Because it does not have to pay these costs, we can refer to them as unpriced externalities. A rational actor, under the model we are assuming, will make decisions based on the costs and benefits to her, performing an internal cost-benefit calculation. That could lead to wildly inefficient decisionmaking! Suppose the benefits to the factory of operating are, net of its own costs, about $1 million annually. Now suppose that the costs on neighbors, even if we only consider the reduction in property values, is $4 million per year. Here we have a thumbs-down that is four times bigger than the factory’s 159 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 heart. Deciding to operate in this condition would be Pareto inefficient, because there is a loser. But, further and more importantly, it would be Kaldor-Hicks inefficient, because the factory could not compensate the neighbors for their losses and still come out ahead. Under this efficiency criterion, operating the factory would be bad for the world. It’s a change we don’t want. But unless the law forbids the pollution or requires the factory to compensate the neighbors, the factory will decide to operate. The $4 million loss to the neighbors is an unpriced externality that the factory does not include in its private costbenefit calculation. Our social cost-benefit calculation does include it, and we see easily that the factory is making a socially inefficient decision. One solution to the problem of unpriced externalities is associated with early 20th century economist Arthur Pigou. Use taxes or liability to internalize the externality. Suppose we are unsure whether the factory’s profitability would exceed the harm to the neighbors. If the factory has to compensate the neighbors, then it will include the neighbors’ cost in its private cost-benefit calculation and therefore make a socially efficient decision. Pigouvian internalization suggests that law should intervene in otherwise free markets, though taxes, liability, or regulation, when markets would fail to deliver efficiency on account of unpriced externalities. Our job, as legal engineers, would be to ferret out such externalities. Can you see why this might be a hard job? Ronald Coase, Part 1 In a groundbreaking article, The Problem of Social Cost, economist Ronald Coase laid waste to this simple idea of externalities. Coase’s insight was that all “harms” are 160 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 reciprocal in nature. What may look like a problem of one member in a society harming another is, in truth, the desires of the two coming into conflict. They cannot both realize their preferences at the same time. It may be that we prefer one or the other on moral grounds, but that would owe to a particular moral theory - not to a neutral accounting of preferences. For example, return to our car transaction that would impose an external cost on the non-decisionmaking and disappointed parents. The problem here is that the parents and the transactors have conflicting preferences that cannot all be satisfied. If the transaction occurs, a cost is imposed on the parents. If the parents succeeded in blocking the transaction, a cost would be imposed on the transactors. Our polluting factory seemed like such an obvious example of a market actor imposing externalities. But that’s because we have an intuitive idea about which harms are “unnatural” or “unfair,” not because of preference impacts. If the factory operates, it harms the preference satisfaction of the neighbors. If the neighbors can stop the factory, then the factory’s owners preferences are disrupted. The harms are reciprocal, and the real problem is that the factory owners’ desires and the neighbor’s desires conflict. If we knew for sure whether it would be more efficient to realize the preferences of one side or the other (as in the numerical examples I gave in the last section), then we could on efficiency grounds give that side the power to realize their preferences (e.g., allowing the factory to operate or blocking the operation of the factory). Either side we entitle would be in a position to impose an externality on the other. And we would still have to decide whether to make that side pay the 161 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 other its costs (e.g., the neighbors paying the factory not to operate or the factory’s owners paying the neighbors for damages), but such payments would only move costs around, not alter the net social gains. We are often unsure, however, whose preferences in such conflicts are weightier. In other words, we are unsure whether entitling one side or the other would be more efficient in a Kaldor-Hicks sense. Perhaps we could let one side make the decision on condition that it pay the other side. In other words, we could make the side we empower liable for damages to the other side. Which side should we empower? Coase demonstrated that, again without a separate moral theory of harm, we cannot just say that the harm-causer should have to pay the victim. In our factory example, we could either (a) allow the factory to pollute if it pays damages to the neighbors or (b) bar the factory if the neighbors pay damages to the owners. If we knew how to assess such damages, either result would be efficient. Can you see why? This approach suggests that if efficiency is our goal, if we are unsure what use is most efficient, and we are confident in our ability to calculate damages on one side but not the other, we should put liability on that side. For example, suppose we can confidently assess the damages to the neighbors but that the costs of not operating the factory would be very difficult to calculate. We could make the factory liable to the neighbors but allow it to pollute if it pays damages. Because we are confident in the damages to neighbors, we are now confident that when the factory balances the costs and benefits to it, it will do so accurately. If it decides that, even having to pay damages, operation is cost-justified, then the factory’s operation is efficient. If, however, we lacked 162 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 confidence in the amount of damages to the neighbors, we would, correspondingly, lack confidence in the factory’s costbenefit calculation and thus in the efficiency of the action it chooses. Ronald Coase, Part 2 In The Problem of Social Cost, Coase stated an even more provocative principle than that of the reciprocal nature of harm. We have thus far been ignoring the fact that parties can always bargain among themselves. Under our rational actor assumption, if a party identifies an opportunity it values more than the cost of taking the opportunity, it will take the opportunity. If the rational actor values a car more than it values the $1000 in his pocket, he will be willing to trade the money for the car. Let’s examine the implication of this. Suppose the factory wishes to operate but knows that it would be found liable to the neighbors in a tort suit for nuisance - and subject to an injunction forbidding it from operating. If the factory owners stand to earn from operations enough to induce the neighbors not to bring suit (or to enter a settlement agreement), then they should be able to offer this sum to the neighbors who should accept this offer. Indeed, if being free of pollution is worth $1 million to the neighbors and operating the factory is worth $4 million to the owners, then the factory owner should be able to pay the neighbors to settle any claims. End result: the factory operates, which is the efficient solution given our assumptions. If there is no law that would bar the factory from operating, then, under the same assumptions above, the factory will operate. The neighbors would not offer more than $1 million, which would not be enough to induce the factory owners to forego the $4 million they would earn from operating. 163 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 The upshot is that no matter what the law is the factory will operate. If we reverse the numbers above, $4 million in damage to the neighbors and $1 million in factory profits, then we see, similarly, that no matter what the legal rule, the factory will not operate. If they aren’t entitled by law to operate, they won’t be able to induce the neighbors to settle. If they are entitled to operate, the neighbors should be willing to pay more than the $1 million they’d earn to induce them not to operate. The general lesson here is that no matter the legal rule, the parties will bargain to achieve an efficient result. This is rather stunning, because it implies that, perhaps, law does not matter. Ok, before accepting that claim, which is often called the Coase Theorem, let us look at some provisos and necessary assumptions. First, even if the parties will bargain to reach the efficient result, the legal rule has a distributive effect. It will dictate who must pay whom to change an entitlement under law. One party will be made richer and one poorer by this choice. Second, the result above depended on all parties’ being rational actors. Real people, as we will discuss in the next section, depart from this model. Third, for the above sort of Coasean bargaining to occur, the initial entitlement must be clear. If the parties are unsure whether the factory will be found to be a nuisance, then they will be unsure who must pay whom to acquire the entitlement. This uncertainty reduces the likelihood of reaching an agreement. Fourth, we assumed that the parties could bargain without cost. This is not so. In the real world, any bargaining comes 164 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 with transaction costs. Transaction costs are all the costs, conceived broadly, that are required to complete a transaction. They include the cost of finding the person with whom you’ll transact, meeting them, bargaining with them, and closing the deal. In our factory example, reaching a deal with all the neighbors would present steep transaction costs. Although it wouldn’t take much in time or resources to locate them, each neighbor has the power to derail the whole deal by refusing to settle. Each is a potential holdout. Just imagine the likelihood of building a large metropolitan airport if it required purchasing 2,000 residential homes to create the space to build. It wouldn’t be good enough to buy most of the homes. You can’t build a runway that is mostly free of two-story homes. Each of those 2,000 residents now has a great incentive to hold out for as much money as they think the airport is willing to pay — shifting the price of transaction closer to a portion of the value of the airport than to the value the home would have gone for on the market without the airport. If the factory in our example were free under the law to operate but the neighbors valued non-operation far in excess of the value to the owners of operation, then an efficient bargain should take place. But that would require the neighbors each to contribute to raising the amount of money it would take to induce the factory not to operate. Anyone familiar with public radio pledge drives or other efforts to get people to kick in for services they enjoy will appreciate the problem: free riders. Why should you pay unless you can be sure others will pay their fair share? And, even then, why not let other carry the load? Overcoming the free rider and 165 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 holdout problems requires mass organization, a transaction cost that can be immense. These last two are examples of collective action problems, instances in which even rational actors have difficulty acting as a group which itself is rational. Such problems often justify governmental intervention in markets or government provision of a good (like national defense or critical infrastructure). Transaction Cost Economics We now have all the tools to appreciate efficiency-driven analysis of policies, deals, and events. It amounts to predicting what rational actors will do in response to opportunities that present different levels of gain, loss, and transaction cost. Generally, when transaction costs are low, parties will rearrange entitlements to achieve efficient outcomes, absent law barring it. When transaction costs are high, they will be unable to do so. We are on the look-out for high transaction cost scenarios, where our assumptions about the optimizing power of private transactions are likely to fail. So collective action problems, where there are many parties on one side of a transaction, presenting many possible holdouts or free-riders, or bilateral monopolies (situations in which there is only one possible buyer and one possible seller and that thus raise the specter of wasteful, strategic bargaining) – these are areas of likely market failure in which liability or regulation might produce efficiency gains. The Cases The cases you will read next illustrate some of these issues. The first, Lake City is a contracts case. Normally, when you enter an agreement, through offer and acceptance, you are 166 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 bound to perform the terms of the agreement. If you agree to sell your car in exchange for money, you have undertaken a duty to hand over the car, and the buyer has undertaken a duty to hand over the money. When someone fails to perform the duties required under a contract, we say the contract has been breached. Someone who breaches a contract can be sued for doing so, but what should a court order? Only rarely will a court order a party to perform the specific actions required by a contract. Such an injunction is called an order for specific performance. Rather, courts almost always award money damages for breach. But how much? Almost always the answer is expectation damages, meaning the value the plaintiff would have received under the contract if the breaching defendant had fully performed. This raises the possibility that (a) someone might breach a contract to take advantage of a better opportunity, preferring just to pay damages, and (b) that parties might try to write contracts that prevent such instances of “efficient breach.” When you read the case, ask yourself whether you believe “efficient breach” is justifiable and what sorts of considerations would support it or, alternatively, support remedies or contract provisions that deter it. Second, is Carroll Towing, a torts case in which the question is whether a defendant should have taken more precautions to prevent the sinking of a boat. The very general question here is when to make someone liable for injuries to another. Can you see how the court’s explanation of when to hold someone liable for not taking precautions is driven by efficiency concerns? Third is Boomer v. Atlantic Cement Co., another tort case, this one involving neighbors of a factor suing that factory for 167 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 nuisance. The tort of nuisance requires a landowner to prove that the defendant substantially and unreasonably interfered with the private use of land. This ordinarily involves a balancing of the utility of the nuisance-generating conduct and the gravity of the harm to the landowner plaintiff. In this case, there was no question that the air pollution was a nuisance so-defined. The issue is whether the neighbors could get an injunction, an order requiring the factory to stop the pollution (thus likely shutting down). Why does the court’s solution make sense on efficiency grounds? Wouldn’t Coase’s theorem suggest that an injunction would result in efficiency anyway? Review Topics and Questions – Be able to recognize and apply in arguments the basic tools of law and economics methodology: – the rational actor model (its assumptions and dynamics) – efficiency (Pareto and Kaldo-Hicks) – distributive effects – externalities – transaction costs (including hold-outs, free riders, search costs, and strategic bargaining) – Coasean bargaining and the Coase Theorem 168 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 – Make an argument for and against permitting efficient breach of contract. – What is a penalty clause and why does it conflict with permitting efficient breach? – What is the “Learned Hand formula” in tort law, and what is its relation to efficiency? – Why would an injunction for the residents likely be inefficient in Boomer? – Explain why a voluntarily negotiated contract is likely to be Pareto efficient. – What facts about a contract would cause you to doubt the contract's efficiency? (In other words, what facts you might learn as a judge being asked to enforce a contract would cause you to doubt that the contract being litigated is Pareto efficient?) – Identify an externality in your decision to drive your car to school. Explain why it is an externality. Lake River Corp. v. Carborundum Co., 769 F. 2d 1284 Posner, Circuit Judge. This diversity suit between Lake River Corporation and Carborundum Company requires us to consider questions of Illinois commercial law, and in particular to explore the fuzzy line between penalty clauses and liquidated-damages clauses. 169 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 Carborundum manufactures “Ferro Carbo,” an abrasive powder used in making steel. To serve its midwestern customers better, Carborundum made a contract with Lake River by which the latter agreed to provide distribution services in its warehouse in Illinois. Lake River would receive Ferro Carbo in bulk from Carborundum, “bag” it, and ship the bagged product to Carborundum’s customers. The Ferro Carbo would remain Carborundum’s property until delivered to the customers. Carborundum insisted that Lake River install a new bagging system to handle the contract. In order to be sure of being able to recover the cost of the new system ($89,000) and make a profit of 20 percent of the contract price, Lake River insisted on the following minimum-quantity guarantee: In consideration of the special equipment [i.e., the new bagging system] to be acquired and furnished by LAKERIVER for handling the product, CARBORUNDUM shall, during the initial three-year term of this Agreement, ship to LAKE-RIVER for bagging a minimum quantity of [22,500 tons]. If, at the end of the three-year term, this minimum quantity shall not have been shipped, LAKE-RIVER shall invoice CARBORUNDUM at the then prevailing rates for the difference between the quantity bagged and the minimum guaranteed. If Carborundum had shipped the full minimum quantity that it guaranteed, it would have owed Lake River roughly $533,000 under the contract. 170 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 After the contract was signed in 1979, the demand for domestic steel, and with it the demand for Ferro Carbo, plummeted, and Carborundum failed to ship the guaranteed amount. When the contract expired late in 1982, Carborundum had shipped only 12,000 of the 22,500 tons it had guaranteed. Lake River had bagged the 12,000 tons and had billed Carborundum for this bagging, and Carborundum had paid, but by virtue of the formula in the minimumguarantee clause Carborundum still owed Lake River $241,000 — the contract price of $533,000 if the full amount of Ferro Carbo had been shipped, minus what Carborundum had paid for the bagging of the quantity it had shipped. When Lake River demanded payment of this amount, Carborundum refused, on the ground that the formula imposed a penalty. At the time, Lake River had in its warehouse 500 tons of bagged Ferro Carbo, having a market value of $269,000, which it refused to release unless Carborundum paid the $241,000 due under the formula. Lake River did offer to sell the bagged product and place the proceeds in escrow until its dispute with Carborundum over the enforceability of the formula was resolved, but Carborundum rejected the offer and trucked in bagged Ferro Carbo from the East to serve its customers in Illinois, at an additional cost of $31,000. Lake River brought this suit for $241,000, which it claims as liquidated damages. Carborundum counterclaimed for the value of the bagged Ferro Carbo when Lake River impounded it and the additional cost of serving the customers affected by the impounding. The theory of the counterclaim is that the impounding was a conversion, and not as Lake River contends the assertion of a lien. The district judge, after a 171 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 bench trial, gave judgment for both parties. Carborundum ended up roughly $42,000 to the good: $269,000 + $31,000$241,000-$17,000, the last figure representing prejudgment interest on Lake River’s damages. (We have rounded off all dollar figures to the nearest thousand.) Both parties have appealed. .... The hardest issue in the case is whether the formula in the minimum-guarantee clause imposes a penalty for breach of contract or is merely an effort to liquidate damages. Deep as the hostility to penalty clauses runs in the common law, see Loyd, Penalties and Forfeitures, 29 Harv. L. Rev. 117 (1915), we still might be inclined to question, if we thought ourselves free to do so, whether a modern court should refuse to enforce a penalty clause where the signator is a substantial corporation, well able to avoid improvident commitments. Penalty clauses provide an earnest of performance. The clause here enhanced Carborundum’s credibility in promising to ship the minimum amount guaranteed by showing that it was willing to pay the full contract price even if it failed to ship anything. On the other side it can be pointed out that by raising the cost of a breach of contract to the contract breaker, a penalty clause increases the risk to his other creditors; increases (what is the same thing and more, because bankruptcy imposes “deadweight” social costs) the risk of bankruptcy; and could amplify the business cycle by increasing the number of bankruptcies in bad times, which is when contracts are most likely to be broken. But since little effort is made to prevent businessmen from assuming risks, these reasons are no better than makeweights. 172 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 A better argument is that a penalty clause may discourage efficient as well as inefficient breaches of contract. Suppose a breach would cost the promisee $12,000 in actual damages but would yield the promisor $20,000 in additional profits. Then there would be a net social gain from breach. After being fully compensated for his loss the promisee would be no worse off than if the contract had been performed, while the promisor would be better off by $8,000. But now suppose the contract contains a penalty clause under which the promisor if he breaks his promise must pay the promisee $25,000. The promisor will be discouraged from breaking the contract, since $25,000, the penalty, is greater than $20,000, the profits of the breach; and a transaction that would have increased value will be forgone. On this view, since compensatory damages should be sufficient to deter inefficient breaches (that is, breaches that cost the victim more than the gain to the contract breaker), penal damages could have no effect other than to deter some efficient breaches. But this overlooks the earlier point that the willingness to agree to a penalty clause is a way of making the promisor and his promise credible and may therefore be essential to inducing some value-maximizing contracts to be made. It also overlooks the more important point that the parties (always assuming they are fully competent) will, in deciding whether to include a penalty clause in their contract, weigh the gains against the costs — costs that include the possibility of discouraging an efficient breach somewhere down the road — and will include the clause only if the benefits exceed those costs as well as all other costs. On this view the refusal to enforce penalty clauses is (at best) paternalistic — and it seems odd that courts should 173 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 display parental solicitude for large corporations. But however this may be, we must be on guard to avoid importing our own ideas of sound public policy into an area where our proper judicial role is more than usually deferential. The responsibility for making innovations in the common law of Illinois rests with the courts of Illinois, and not with the federal courts in Illinois. And like every other state, Illinois, untroubled by academic skepticism of the wisdom of refusing to enforce penalty clauses against sophisticated promisors, see, e.g., Goetz & Scott, Liquidated Damages, Penalties and the Just Compensation Principle, 77 Colum. L. Rev. 554 (1977), continues steadfastly to insist on the distinction between penalties and liquidated damages. See, e.g., [many Illinois cases]. To be valid under Illinois law a liquidation of damages must be a reasonable estimate at the time of contracting of the likely damages from breach, and the need for estimation at that time must be shown by reference to the likely difficulty of measuring the actual damages from a breach of contract after the breach occurs. If damages would be easy to determine then, or if the estimate greatly exceeds a reasonable upper estimate of what the damages are likely to be, it is a penalty. See, e.g., M.I.G. Investments, Inc. v. Marsala, 92 Ill. App. 3d 400, 405-06 (1981). The distinction between a penalty and liquidated damages is not an easy one to draw in practice but we are required to draw it and can give only limited weight to the district court’s determination. . . . . [W]e conclude that the damage formula in this case is a penalty and not a liquidation of damages, because it is designed always to assure Lake River more than its actual damages. The formula — full contract price minus the amount 174 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 already invoiced to Carborundum — is invariant to the gravity of the breach. When a contract specifies a single sum in damages for any and all breaches even though it is apparent that all are not of the same gravity, the specification is not a reasonable effort to estimate damages; and when in addition the fixed sum greatly exceeds the actual damages likely to be inflicted by a minor breach, its character as a penalty becomes unmistakable. See M.I.G. Investments, Inc., supra [and other cases]. This case is within the gravitational field of these principles even though the minimum-guarantee clause does not fix a single sum as damages. Suppose to begin with that the breach occurs the day after Lake River buys its new bagging system for $89,000 and before Carborundum ships any Ferro Carbo. Carborundum would owe Lake River $533,000. Since Lake River would have incurred at that point a total cost of only $89,000, its net gain from the breach would be $444,000. This is more than four times the profit of $107,000 (20 percent of the contract price of $533,000) that Lake River expected to make from the contract if it had been performed: a huge windfall. Next suppose (as actually happened here) that breach occurs when 55 percent of the Ferro Carbo has been shipped. Lake River would already have received $293,000 from Carborundum. To see what its costs then would have been (as estimated at the time of contracting), first subtract Lake River’s anticipated profit on the contract of $107,000 from the total contract price of $533,000. The difference — Lake River’s total cost of performance — is $426,000. Of this, $89,000 is the cost of the new bagging system, a fixed cost. The rest ($426,000-$89,000 = $337,000) presumably consists of variable costs that are roughly proportional to the amount 175 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 of Ferro Carbo bagged; there is no indication of any other fixed costs. Assume, therefore, that if Lake River bagged 55 percent of the contractually agreed quantity, it incurred in doing so 55 percent of its variable costs, or $185,000. When this is added to the cost of the new bagging system, assumed for the moment to be worthless except in connection with the contract, the total cost of performance to Lake River is $274,000. Hence a breach that occurred after 55 percent of contractual performance was complete would be expected to yield Lake River a modest profit of $19,000 ($293,000$274,000). But now add the “liquidated damages” of $241,000 that Lake River claims, and the result is a total gain from the breach of $260,000, which is almost two and a half times the profit that Lake River expected to gain if there was no breach. And this ignores any use value or salvage value of the new bagging system, which is the property of Lake River — though admittedly it also ignores the time value of money; Lake River paid $89,000 for that system before receiving any revenue from the contract. To complete the picture, assume that the breach had not occurred till performance was 90 percent complete. Then the “liquidated damages” clause would not be so one-sided, but it would be one-sided. Carborundum would have paid $480,000 for bagging. Against this, Lake River would have incurred its fixed cost of $89,000 plus 90 percent of its variable costs of $337,000, or $303,000. Its total costs would thus be $392,000, and its net profit $88,000. But on top of this it would be entitled to “liquidated damages” of $53,000, for a total profit of $141,000 — more than 30 percent more than its expected profit of $107,000 if there was no breach. 176 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 The reason for these results is that most of the costs to Lake River of performing the contract are saved if the contract is broken, and this saving is not reflected in the damage formula. As a result, at whatever point in the life of the contract a breach occurs, the damage formula gives Lake River more than its lost profits from the breach — dramatically more if the breach occurs at the beginning of the contract; tapering off at the end, it is true. Still, over the interval between the beginning of Lake River’s performance and nearly the end, the clause could be expected to generate profits ranging from 400 percent of the expected contract profits to 130 percent of those profits. And this is on the assumption that the bagging system has no value apart from the contract. If it were worth only $20,000 to Lake River, the range would be 434 percent to 150 percent. .... The fact that the damage formula is invalid does not deprive Lake River of a remedy. The parties did not contract explicitly with reference to the measure of damages if the agreed-on damage formula was invalidated, but all this means is that the victim of the breach is entitled to his common law damages. See, e.g., Restatement, Second, Contracts § 356, comment a (1981). In this case that would be the unpaid contract price of $241,000 minus the costs that Lake River saved by not having to complete the contract (the variable costs on the other 45 percent of the Ferro Carbo that it never had to bag). The case must be remanded to the district judge to fix these damages. . . . . 177 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 United States. v. Carroll Towing Co., 159 F.2d 169 (1947) L. HAND, Circuit Judge. [In a busy New York harbor, the Anna C., a barge owned by the Conners Company and chartered by another party, was moored alongside many other barges to a pier. It bore a cargo of flour owned by the United States. A tugboat owned by Carroll Towing and chartered by another company was sent to move one of the barges to allow access to the pier. It collided with a tanker, the propellor of which then made a hole in the Anna C. The Anna C. then took on water and sank, losing its cargo of flour. This spawned many lawsuits and countersuits. The district court found Carroll Towing Co. was liable to the United States and, for half of its loss, to the Conners Company. Among other arguments on appeal, Carrol Towing argued that Conners Company was partially responsible for the loss, because if it had an employee aboard the Anna C. (A “bargee”), the employee would have noticed the damage once struck, called for help, and prevented the sinking.] It appears from the foregoing review that there is no general rule to determine when the absence of a bargee or other attendant will make the owner of the barge liable for injuries to other vessels if she breaks away from her moorings. However, in any cases where he would be so liable for injuries to others obviously he must reduce his damages proportionately, if the injury is to his own barge. It becomes apparent why there can be no such general rule, when we consider the grounds for such a liability. Since there are 178 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 occasions when every vessel will break from her moorings, and since, if she does, she becomes a menace to those about her; the owner’s duty, as in other similar situations, to provide against resulting injuries is a function of three variables: (1) The probability that she will break away; (2) the gravity of the resulting injury, if she does; (3) the burden of adequate precautions. Possibly it serves to bring this notion into relief to state it in algebraic terms: if the probability be called P; the injury, L; and the burden, B; liability depends upon whether B is less than L multiplied by P: i.e., whether B < PL. Applied to the situation at bar, the likelihood that a barge will break from her fasts and the damage she will do, vary with the place and time; for example, if a storm threatens, the danger is greater; so it is, if she is in a crowded harbor where moored barges are constantly being shifted about. On the other hand, the barge must not be the bargee’s prison, even though he lives aboard; he must go ashore at times. We need not say whether, even in such crowded waters as New York Harbor a bargee must be aboard at night at all; it may be that the custom is otherwise, as Ward, J., supposed in ‘The Kathryn B. Guinan,’ . . . ; and that, if so, the situation is one where custom should control. We leave that question open; but we hold that it is not in all cases a sufficient answer to a bargee’s absence without excuse, during working hours, that he has properly made fast his barge to a pier, when he leaves her. In the case at bar the bargee left at five o’clock in the afternoon of January 3rd, and the flotilla broke away at about two o’clock in the afternoon of the following day, twenty-one hours afterwards. The bargee had been away all the time, and we hold that his fabricated story was affirmative evidence that he had no excuse for his absence. At the locus in quo- especially 179 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 during the short January days and in the full tide of war activity- barges were being constantly ‘drilled’ in and out. Certainly it was not beyond reasonable expectation that, with the inevitable haste and bustle, the work might not be done with adequate care. In such circumstances we hold- and it is all that we do hold- that it was a fair requirement that the Conners Company should have a bargee aboard (unless he had some excuse for his absence), during the working hours of daylight. .... Boomer v. Atlantic Cement Co., 26 N.Y.2d 219 (1970) Bergan, J. Defendant operates a large cement plant near Albany. These are actions for injunction and damages by neighboring land owners alleging injury to property from dirt, smoke and vibration emanating from the plant. A nuisance has been found after trial, temporary damages have been allowed; but an injunction has been denied. The public concern with air pollution arising from many sources in industry and in transportation is currently accorded ever wider recognition accompanied by a growing sense of responsibility in State and Federal Governments to control it. Cement plants are obvious sources of air pollution in the neighborhoods where they operate. 180 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 But there is now before the court private litigation in which individual property owners have sought specific relief from a single plant operation. The threshold question raised by the division of view on this appeal is whether the court should resolve the litigation between the parties now before it as equitably as seems possible; or whether, seeking promotion of the general public welfare, it should channel private litigation into broad public objectives. A court performs its essential function when it decides the rights of parties before it. Its decision of private controversies may sometimes greatly affect public issues. Large questions of law are often resolved by the manner in which private litigation is decided. But this is normally an incident to the court's main function to settle controversy. It is a rare exercise of judicial power to use a decision in private litigation as a purposeful mechanism to achieve direct public objectives greatly beyond the rights and interests before the court. Effective control of air pollution is a problem presently far from solution even with the full public and financial powers of government. In large measure adequate technical procedures are yet to be developed and some that appear possible may be economically impracticable. It seems apparent that the amelioration of air pollution will depend on technical research in great depth; on a carefully balanced consideration of the economic impact of close regulation; and of the actual effect on public health. It is likely to require massive public expenditure and to demand more than any local community can accomplish and to depend on regional and interstate controls. A court should not try to do this on its own as a by-product of private litigation and it seems manifest that the judicial 181 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 establishment is neither equipped in the limited nature of any judgment it can pronounce nor prepared to lay down and implement an effective policy for the elimination of air pollution. This is an area beyond the circumference of one private lawsuit. It is a direct responsibility for government and should not thus be undertaken as an incident to solving a dispute between property owners and a single cement plant -one of many -- in the Hudson River valley. The cement making operations of defendant have been found by the court at Special Term to have damaged the nearby properties of plaintiffs in these two actions. That court, as it has been noted, accordingly found defendant maintained a nuisance and this has been affirmed at the Appellate Division. The total damage to plaintiffs' properties is, however, relatively small in comparison with the value of defendant's operation and with the consequences of the injunction which plaintiffs seek. The ground for the denial of injunction, notwithstanding the finding both that there is a nuisance and that plaintiffs have been damaged substantially, is the large disparity in economic consequences of the nuisance and of the injunction. This theory cannot, however, be sustained without overruling a doctrine which has been consistently reaffirmed in several leading cases in this court and which has never been disavowed here, namely that where a nuisance has been found and where there has been any substantial damage shown by the party complaining an injunction will be granted. The rule in New York has been that such a nuisance will be enjoined although marked disparity be shown in economic consequence between the effect of the injunction and the effect of the nuisance. 182 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 The problem of disparity in economic consequence was sharply in focus in Whalen v. Union Bag & Paper Co. (208 N. Y. 1). A pulp mill entailing an investment of more than a million dollars polluted a stream in which plaintiff, who owned a farm, was “a lower riparian owner”. The economic loss to plaintiff from this pollution was small. This court, reversing the Appellate Division, reinstated the injunction granted by the Special Term against the argument of the mill owner that in view of “the slight advantage to plaintiff and the great loss that will be inflicted on defendant” an injunction should not be granted (p. 2). “Such a balancing of injuries cannot be justified by the circumstances of this case”, Judge Werner noted (p. 4). He continued: “Although the damage to the plaintiff may be slight as compared with the defendant's expense of abating the condition, that is not a good reason for refusing an injunction” (p. 5). Thus the unconditional injunction granted at Special Term was reinstated. The rule laid down in that case, then, is that whenever the damage resulting from a nuisance is found not “unsubstantial”, viz., $100 a year, injunction would follow. This states a rule that had been followed in this court with marked consistency (McCarty v. Natural Carbonic Gas Co., 189 N. Y. 40; Strobel v. Kerr Salt Co., 164 N. Y. 303; Campbell v. Seaman, 63 N. Y. 568). .... Although the court at Special Term and the Appellate Division held that injunction should be denied, it was found that plaintiffs had been damaged in various specific amounts up to the time of the trial and damages to the respective plaintiffs were awarded for those amounts. The effect of this was, injunction having been denied, plaintiffs could maintain 183 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 successive actions at law for damages thereafter as further damage was incurred. The court at Special Term also found the amount of permanent damage attributable to each plaintiff, for the guidance of the parties in the event both sides stipulated to the payment and acceptance of such permanent damage as a settlement of all the controversies among the parties. The total of permanent damages to all plaintiffs thus found was $185,000. This basis of adjustment has not resulted in any stipulation by the parties. This result at Special Term and at the Appellate Division is a departure from a rule that has become settled; but to follow the rule literally in these cases would be to close down the plant at once. This court is fully agreed to avoid that immediately drastic remedy; the difference in view is how best to avoid it.1 One alternative is to grant the injunction but postpone its effect to a specified future date to give opportunity for technical advances to permit defendant to eliminate the nuisance; another is to grant the injunction conditioned on the payment of permanent damages to plaintiffs which would compensate them for the total economic loss to their property present and future caused by defendant's operations. For reasons which will be developed the court chooses the latter alternative. If the injunction were to be granted unless within a short period – e.g., 18 months – the nuisance be abated by 1 Respondent's investment in the plant is in excess of $45,000,000. There are over 300 people employed there. 184 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 improved methods, there would be no assurance that any significant technical improvement would occur. The parties could settle this private litigation at any time if defendant paid enough money and the imminent threat of closing the plant would build up the pressure on defendant. If there were no improved techniques found, there would inevitably be applications to the court at Special Term for extensions of time to perform on showing of good faith efforts to find such techniques. Moreover, techniques to eliminate dust and other annoying by-products of cement making are unlikely to be developed by any research the defendant can undertake within any short period, but will depend on the total resources of the cement industry Nationwide and throughout the world. The problem is universal wherever cement is made. For obvious reasons the rate of the research is beyond control of defendant. If at the end of 18 months the whole industry has not found a technical solution a court would be hard put to close down this one cement plant if due regard be given to equitable principles. On the other hand, to grant the injunction unless defendant pays plaintiffs such permanent damages as may be fixed by the court seems to do justice between the contending parties. All of the attributions of economic loss to the properties on which plaintiffs' complaints are based will have been redressed. The nuisance complained of by these plaintiffs may have other public or private consequences, but these particular parties are the only ones who have sought remedies and the judgment proposed will fully redress them. The limitation of relief granted is a limitation only within the four corners of 185 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 these actions and does not foreclose public health or other public agencies from seeking proper relief in a proper court. It seems reasonable to think that the risk of being required to pay permanent damages to injured property owners by cement plant owners would itself be a reasonable effective spur to research for improved techniques to minimize nuisance. The power of the court to condition on equitable grounds the continuance of an injunction on the payment of permanent damages seems undoubted. (See, e.g., the alternatives considered in McCarty v. Natural Carbonic Gas Co., supra.;, as well as Strobel v. Kerr Salt Co., supra.;.) The damage base here suggested is consistent with the general rule in those nuisance cases where damages are allowed. “Where a nuisance is of such a permanent and unabatable character that a single recovery can be had, including the whole damage past and future resulting therefrom, there can be but one recovery” (66 C. J. S., Nuisances, s 140, p. 947). It has been said that permanent damages are allowed where the loss recoverable would obviously be small as compared with the cost of removal of the nuisance (Kentucky-Ohio Gas Co. v. Bowling, 264 Ky. 470, 477). .... Thus it seems fair to both sides to grant permanent damages to plaintiffs which will terminate this private litigation. The theory of damage is the “servitude on land” of plaintiffs imposed by defendant's nuisance. (See United States v. Causby, 328 U. S. 256, 261, 262, 267, where the term “servitude” addressed to the land was used by Justice 186 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 Douglas relating to the effect of airplane noise on property near an airport.) The judgment, by allowance of permanent damages imposing a servitude on land, which is the basis of the actions, would preclude future recovery by plaintiffs or their grantees (see Northern Indiana Public Serv. Co. v. Vesey, supra.;, p. 351). This should be placed beyond debate by a provision of the judgment that the payment by defendant and the acceptance by plaintiffs of permanent damages found by the court shall be in compensation for a servitude on the land. Although the Trial Term has found permanent damages as a possible basis of settlement of the litigation, on remission the court should be entirely free to re-examine this subject. It may again find the permanent damage already found; or make new findings. The orders should be reversed, without costs, and the cases remitted to Supreme Court, Albany County to grant an injunction which shall be vacated upon payment by defendant of such amounts of permanent damage to the respective plaintiffs as shall for this purpose be determined by the court. Jasen, J., Dissenting. I agree with the majority that a reversal is required here, but I do not subscribe to the newly enunciated doctrine of assessment of permanent damages, in lieu of an injunction, where substantial property rights have been impaired by the creation of a nuisance. It has long been the rule in this State, as the majority acknowledges, that a nuisance which results in substantial 187 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 continuing damage to neighbors must be enjoined. (Whalen v. Union Bag & Paper Co., 208 N. Y. 1; Campbell v. Seaman, 63 N. Y. 568; see, also, Kennedy v. Moog Servocontrols, 21 N Y 2d 966.) To now change the rule to permit the cement company to continue polluting the air indefinitely upon the payment of permanent damages is, in my opinion, compounding the magnitude of a very serious problem in our State and Nation today. .... I see grave dangers in overruling our long-established rule of granting an injunction where a nuisance results in substantial continuing damage. In permitting the injunction to become inoperative upon the payment of permanent damages, the majority is, in effect, licensing a continuing wrong. It is the same as saying to the cement company, you may continue to do harm to your neighbors so long as you pay a fee for it. Furthermore, once such permanent damages are assessed and paid, the incentive to alleviate the wrong would be eliminated, thereby continuing air pollution of an area without abatement. It is true that some courts have sanctioned the remedy here proposed by the majority in a number of cases,^104-6 but none of the authorities relied upon by the majority are analogous to the situation before us. In those cases, the courts, in denying an injunction and awarding money damages, grounded their decision on a showing that the use to which the property was intended to be put was primarily for the public benefit. Here, on the other hand, it is clearly established that the cement company is creating a continuing air pollution nuisance primarily for its own private interest with no public benefit. 188 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 This kind of inverse condemnation (Ferguson v. Village of Hamburg, 272 N. Y. 234 may not be invoked by a private person or corporation for private gain or advantage. Inverse condemnation should only be permitted when the public is primarily served in the taking or impairment of property. (Matter of New York City Housing Auth. v. Muller, 270 N. Y. 333, 343; Pocantico Water Works Co. v. Bird, 130 N. Y. 249, 258.) The promotion of the interests of the polluting cement company has, in my opinion, no public use or benefit. Nor is it constitutionally permissible to impose servitude on land, without consent of the owner, by payment of permanent damages where the continuing impairment of the land is for a private use. (See Fifth Ave. Coach Lines v. City of New York, 11 N Y 2d 342, 347; Walker v. City of Hutchinson, 352 U. S. 112.) This is made clear by the State Constitution (art. I, s 7, subd. [a]) which provides that “[p]rivate property shall not be taken for public use without just compensation” (emphasis added). It is, of course, significant that the section makes no mention of taking for a private use. In sum, then, by constitutional mandate as well as by judicial pronouncement, the permanent impairment of private property for private purposes is not authorized in the absence of clearly demonstrated public benefit and use. I would enjoin the defendant cement company from continuing the discharge of dust particles upon its neighbors' properties unless, within 18 months, the cement company abated this nuisance.2 2 The issuance of an injunction to become effective in the future is not an entirely new concept. For instance, in Schwarzenbach v. 189 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 It is not my intention to cause the removal of the cement plant from the Albany area, but to recognize the urgency of the problem stemming from this stationary source of air pollution, and to allow the company a specified period of time to develop a means to alleviate this nuisance. I am aware that the trial court found that the most modern dust control devices available have been installed in defendant's plant, but, I submit, this does not mean that better and more effective dust control devices could not be developed within the time allowed to abate the pollution. Moreover, I believe it is incumbent upon the defendant to develop such devices, since the cement company, at the time the plant commenced production (1962), was well aware of the plaintiffs' presence in the area, as well as the probable consequences of its contemplated operation. Yet, it still chose to build and operate the plant at this site. In a day when there is a growing concern for clean air, highly developed industry should not expect acquiescence by the courts, but should, instead, plan its operations to eliminate contamination of our air and damage to its neighbors. Accordingly, the orders of the Appellate Division, insofar as they denied the injunction, should be reversed, and the actions remitted to Supreme Court, Albany County to grant an injunction to take effect 18 months hence, unless the nuisance is abated by improved techniques prior to said date. Oneonta Light & Power Co. (207 N. Y. 671), an injunction against the maintenance of a dam spilling water on plaintiff's property was issued to become effective one year hence. 190 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 Meeting 5: Collective Action and Human Behavior For this class, first read Garrett Hardin’s famous article in S c i e n c e , T h e Tr a g e d y o f t h e C o m m o n s a t [ h t t p : / / science.sciencemag.org/content/162/3859/1243.full]. Then read pages 1476-1479 and 1510-1516 of Christine Jolls, Cass R. Sunstein, and Richard Thaler, A Behavioral Approach to Law and Economics, 50 Stan. L. Rev. 1471 (1998), at http:// chicagounbound.uchicago.edu/law_and_economics/4/. The latter selection introduces the concept of behavioral law and economics and the ways in which real humans depart from the rational actor model. Note that these two readings present two different challenges to law and economics. The tragedy of the commons (and equivalent problems like the prisoners’ dilemma and public goods, as we’ll discuss in class) demonstrates a market failure arising precisely because of the rationality of the participants. Whereas the following excerpt demonstrates the potential for market failure arising from irrationality. Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 As I will discuss with you in class, the tragedy of the commons, a downward spiral of collective inefficiency, arises when all four of the following elements are present: – There is a destructible resource (or a resource with a limited carrying capacity, such as rangeland or fish in fishery). – Access to this resource is open to more than one person. – The self-interest of the resource users predominates. – The users are unable to enforce cooperation and restraint. Realizing that these are the key elements of Hardin’s tragedy, we can then identify these in various markets and respond in law by attempting to knock out one of these elements. Can you think of other examples of the tragedy of the commons even ones in everyday life? There is one article suggesting that the emergence of such tragedies is what causes a society to adopt property regimes. And, as a case in this section hints, a version of this problem lies behind the entire field of intellectual property law. So this is a pretty important concept! Review Topics and Questions – Can you describe the prisoners’ dilemma and the tragedy of the commons? 192 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 – Why are the pathologies of these two stories a consequence of rational action, rather than a demonstration that the rational actor model doesn’t apply? – Can you recognize whether a particular situation will likely lead to a tragedy of the commons? – How should we respond to a tragedy of the commons? – What are the behavioral law and economics main critiques of the rational actor model, and what are the consequences for law and economics if they are correct? – What is a “reference transaction”? How does the behavioral theory explain the demand for bans on what otherwise seem like efficient transactions? – What exactly does Judge Traynor (in the Supreme Court of California) advocate in Escola v. Coca Cola Bottling Co.? Why? – What is the rational actor theory of plea bargaining? How might the behavioral theory affect our view of plea bargaining? Are there other ways to see plea bargaining in light of our earlier studies of ethical theories? 193 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 Escola v. Coca Cola Bottling Co. of Fresno, 150 P.2d 436 (1944) GIBSON, Chief Justice. Plaintiff, a waitress in a restaurant, was injured when a bottle of Coca Cola broke in her hand. She alleged that defendant company, which had bottled and delivered the alleged defective bottle to her employer, was negligent in selling ‘bottles containing said beverage which on account of excessive pressure of gas or by reason of some defect in the bottle was dangerous * * * and likely to explode.’ This appeal is from a judgment upon a jury verdict in favor of plaintiff. Defendant’s driver delivered several cases of Coca Cola to the restaurant, placing them on the floor, one on top of the other, under and behind the counter, where they remained at least thirty-six hours. Immediately before the accident, plaintiff picked up the top case and set it upon a near-by ice cream cabinet in front of and about three feet from the refrigerator. She then proceeded to take the bottles from the case with her right hand, one at a time, and put them into the refrigerator. Plaintiff testified that after she had placed three bottles in the refrigerator and had moved the fourth bottle about 18 inches from the case ‘it exploded in my hand.’ The bottle broke into two jagged pieces and inflicted a deep fiveinch cut, severing blood vessels, nerves and muscles of the thumb and palm of the hand. Plaintiff further testified that when the bottle exploded, ‘It made a sound similar to an electric light bulb that would have dropped. It made a loud 194 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 pop.’ Plaintiff’s employer testified, ‘I was about twenty feet from where it actually happened and I heard the explosion.’ A fellow employee, on the opposite side of the counter, testified that plaintiff ‘had the bottle, I should judge, waist high, and I know that it didn’t bang either the case or the door or another bottle * * * when it popped. It sounded just like a fruit jar would blow up * * *.’ The witness further testified that the contents of the bottle ‘flew all over herself and myself and the walls and one thing and another.’ The top portion of the bottle, with the cap, remained in plaintiff’s hand, and the lower portion fell to the floor but did not break. The broken bottle was not produced at the trial, the pieces having been thrown away by an employee of the restaurant shortly after the accident. Plaintiff, however, described the broken pieces, and a diagram of the bottle was made showing the location of the ‘fracture line’ where the bottle broke in two. One of defendant’s drivers, called as a witness by plaintiff, testified that he had seen other bottles of Coca Cola in the past explode and had found broken bottles in the warehouse when he took the cases out, but that he did not know what made them blow up. [The majority then upheld the judgment for the plaintiff on grounds that the negligence of bottling company could be inferred, even though no specific negligent acts could be identified. Importantly, for the concurrence that follows, its holding rested on the idea that the plaintiff succeeded in establishing negligence.] TRAYNOR, Justice. 195 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 [I] believe the manufacturer’s negligence should no longer be singled out as the basis of a plaintiff’s right to recover in cases like the present one. In my opinion it should now be recognized that a manufacturer incurs an absolute liability when an article that he has placed on the market, knowing that it is to be used without inspection, proves to have a defect that causes injury to human beings. MacPherson v. Buick Motor Co. ... established the principle, recognized by this court, that irrespective of privity of contract, the manufacturer is responsible for an injury caused by such an article to any person who comes in lawful contact with it. In these cases the source of the manufacturer’s liability was his negligence in the manufacturing process or in the inspection of component parts supplied by others. Even if there is no negligence, however, public policy demands that responsibility be fixed wherever it will most effectively reduce the hazards to life and health inherent in defective products that reach the market. It is evident that the manufacturer can anticipate some hazards and guard against the recurrence of others, as the public cannot. Those who suffer injury from defective products are unprepared to meet its consequences. The cost of an injury and the loss of time or health may be an overwhelming misfortune to the person injured, and a needless one, for the risk of injury can be insured by the manufacturer and distributed among the public as a cost of doing business. It is to the public interest to discourage the marketing of products having defects that are a menace to the public. If such products nevertheless find their way into the market it is to the public interest to place the responsibility for whatever injury they may cause upon the manufacturer, who, even if he is not negligent in the manufacture of the product, is 196 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 responsible for its reaching the market. However intermittently such injuries may occur and however haphazardly they may strike, the risk of their occurrence is a constant risk and a general one. Against such a risk there should be general and constant protection and the manufacturer is best situated to afford such protection. The injury from a defective product does not become a matter of indifference because the defect arises from causes other than the negligence of the manufacturer, such as negligence of a submanufacturer of a component part whose defects could not be revealed by inspection ..., or unknown causes that even by the device of res ipsa loquitur cannot be classified as negligence of the manufacturer. The inference of negligence may be dispelled by an affirmative showing of proper care. If the evidence against the fact inferred is ‘clear, positive, uncontradicted, and of such a nature that it can not rationally be disbelieved, the court must instruct the jury that the nonexistence of the fact has been established as a matter of law.’ An injured person, however, is not ordinarily in a position to refute such evidence or identify the cause of the defect, for he can hardly be familiar with the manufacturing process as the manufacturer himself is. In leaving it to the jury to decide whether the inference has been dispelled, regardless of the evidence against it, the negligence rule approaches the rule of strict liability. It is needlessly circuitous to make negligence the basis of recovery and impose what is in reality liability without negligence. If public policy demands that a manufacturer of goods be responsible for their quality regardless of negligence there is no reason not to fix that responsibility openly. .... 197 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 As handicrafts have been replaced by mass production with its great markets and transportation facilities, the close relationship between the producer and consumer of a product has been altered. Manufacturing processes, frequently valuable secrets, are ordinarily either inaccessible to or beyond the ken of the general public. The consumer no longer has means or skill enough to investigate for himself the soundness of a product, even when it is not contained in a sealed package, and his erstwhile vigilance has been lulled by the steady efforts of manufacturers to build up confidence by advertising and marketing devices such as trade-marks. Consumers no longer approach products warily but accept them on faith, relying on the reputation of the manufacturer or the trade mark. Manufacturers have sought to justify that faith by increasingly high standards of inspection and a readiness to make good on defective products by way of replacements and refunds. The manufacturer’s obligation to the consumer must keep pace with the changing relationship between them; it cannot be escaped because the marketing of a product has become so complicated as to require one or more intermediaries. Certainly there is greater reason to impose liability on the manufacturer than on the retailer who is but a conduit of a product that he is not himself able to test. The manufacturer’s liability should, of course, be defined in terms of the safety of the product in normal and proper use, and should not extend to injuries that cannot be traced to the product as it reached the market. 198 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 Brady v. U.S., 397 U.S. 742 (1970) Mr. Justice WHITE delivered the opinion of the Court. In 1959, petitioner was charged with kidnaping in violation of 18 U.S.C. § 1201(a). Since the indictment charged that the victim of the kidnaping was not liberated unharmed, petitioner faced a maximum penalty of death if the verdict of the jury should so recommend. Petitioner, represented by competent counsel throughout, first elected to plead not guilty. Apparently because the trial judge was unwilling to try the case without a jury, petitioner made no serious attempt to reduce the possibility of a death penalty by waiving a jury trial. Upon learning that his codefendant, who had confessed to the authorities, would plead guilty and be available to testify against him, petitioner changed his plea to guilty. His plea was accepted after the trial judge twice questioned him as to the voluntariness of his plea. Petitioner was sentenced to 50 years’ imprisonment, later reduced to 30. In 1967, petitioner sought relief under 28 U.S.C. § 2255, claiming that his plea of guilty was not voluntarily given because § 1201(a) operated to coerce his plea, because his counsel exerted impermissible pressure upon him, and because his plea was induced by representations with respect to reduction of sentence and clemency. It was also alleged that the trial judge had not fully complied with Rule 11 of the Federal Rules of Criminal Procedure. 199 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 After a hearing, the District Court for the District of New Mexico denied relief. According to the District Court’s findings, petitioner’s counsel did not put impermissible pressure on petitioner to plead guilty and no representations were made with respect to a reduced sentence or clemency. The court held that § 1201(a) was constitutional and found that petitioner decided to plead guilty when he learned that his codefendant was going to plead guilty: petitioner pleaded guilty ‘by reason of other matters and not by reason of the statute’ or because of any acts of the trial judge. The court concluded that ‘the plea was voluntarily and knowingly made.’ The Court of Appeals for the Tenth Circuit affirmed, determining that the District Court’s findings were supported by substantial evidence and specifically approving the finding that petitioner’s plea of guilty was voluntary. We granted certiorari . . . to consider the claim that the Court of Appeals was in error in not reaching a contrary result on the authority of this Court’s decision in United States v. Jackson. We affirm. I In United States v. Jackson, . . . the defendants were indicted under § 1201(a). The District Court dismissed the § 1201(a) count of the indictment, holding the statute unconstitutional because it permitted imposition of the death sentence only upon a jury’s recommendation and thereby made the risk of death the price of a jury trial. This Court held the statute valid, except for the death penalty provision; with respect to the latter, the Court agreed with the trial court ‘that the death penalty provision * * * imposes an impermissible burden 200 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 upon the exercise of a constitutional right * * *.’ The problem was to determine ‘whether the Constitution permits the establishment of such a death penalty, applicable only to those defendants who assert the right to contest their guilt before a jury.’ The inevitable effect of the provision was said to be to discourage assertion of the Fifth Amendment right not to plead guilty and to deter exercise of the Sixth Amendment right to demand a jury trial. Because the legitimate goal of limiting the death penalty to cases in which a jury recommends it could be achieved without penalizing those defendants who plead not guilty and elect a jury trial, the death penalty provision ‘needlessly penalize(d) the assertion of a constitutional right,’ . . . and was therefore unconstitutional. Since the ‘inevitable effect’ of the death penalty provision of § 1201(a) was said by the Court to be the needless encouragement of pleas of guilty and waivers of jury trial, Brady contends that Jackson requires the invalidation of every plea of guilty entered under that section, at least when the fear of death is shown to have been a factor in the plea. Petitioner, however, has read far too much into the Jackson opinion. The Court made it clear in Jackson that it was not holding § 1201(a) inherently coercive of guilty pleas: ‘the fact that the Federal Kidnaping Act tends to discourage defendants from insisting upon their innocence and demanding trial by jury hardly implies that every defendant who enters a guilty plea to a charge under the Act does so involuntarily.’ Cited in support of this statement . . . was Laboy v. New Jersey . . . where a plea of guilty (non vult) under a similar statute was sustained as voluntary in spite of the fact, as found by the 201 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 District Court, that the defendant was greatly upset by the possibility of receiving the death penalty. Moreover, the Court in Jackson rejected a suggestion that the death penalty provision of § 1201(a) be saved by prohibiting in capital kidnaping cases all guilty pleas and jury waivers, ‘however clear (the defendants’) guilt and however strong their desire to acknowledge it in order to spare themselves and their families the spectacle and expense of protracted courtroom proceedings.’ ‘(T)hat jury waivers and guilty pleas may occasionally be rejected’ was no ground for automatically rejecting all guilty pleas under the statute, for such a rule ‘would rob the criminal process of much of its flexibility.’ Plainly, it seems to us, Jackson ruled neither that all pleas of guilty encouraged by the fear of a possible death sentence are involuntary pleas nor that such encouraged pleas are invalid whether—involuntary or not. Jackson prohibits the imposition of the death penalty under § 1201(a), but that decision neither fashioned a new standard for judging the validity of guilty pleas nor mandated a new application of the test theretofore fashioned by courts and since reiterated that guilty pleas are valid if both ‘voluntary’ and ‘intelligent.’ That a guilty plea is a grave and solemn act to be accepted only with care and discernment has long been recognized. Central to the plea and the foundation for entering judgment against the defendant is the defendant’s admission in open court that he committed the acts charged in the indictment. He thus stands as a witness against himself and he is shielded by the Fifth Amendment from being compelled to do so— hence the minimum requirement that his plea be the voluntary expression of his own choice. But the plea is more 202 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 than an admission of past conduct; it is the defendant’s consent that judgment of conviction may be entered without a trial—a waiver of his right to trial before a jury or a judge. Waivers of constitutional rights not only must be voluntary but must be knowing, intelligent acts done with sufficient awareness of the relevant circumstances and likely consequences. On neither score was Brady’s plea of guilty invalid. II The trial judge in 1959 found the plea voluntary before accepting it; the District Court in 1968, after an evidentiary hearing, found that the plea was voluntarily made; the Court of Appeals specifically approved the finding of voluntariness. We see no reason on this record to disturb the judgment of those courts. Petitioner, advised by competent counsel, tendered his plea after his codefendant, who had already given a confession, determined to plead guilty and became available to testify against petitioner. It was this development that the District Court found to have triggered Brady’s guilty plea. The voluntariness of Brady’s plea can be determined only by considering all of the relevant circumstances surrounding it. One of these circumstances was the possibility of a heavier sentence following a guilty verdict after a trial. It may be that Brady, faced with a strong case against him and recognizing that his chances for acquittal were slight, preferred to plead guilty and thus limit the penalty to life imprisonment rather than to elect a jury trial which could result in a death penalty. But even if we assume that Brady would not have pleaded 203 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 guilty except for the death penalty provision of § 1201(a), this assumption merely identifies the penalty provision as a ‘but for’ cause of his plea. That the statute caused the plea in this sense does not necessarily prove that the plea was coerced and invalid as an involuntary act. The State to some degree encourages pleas of guilty at every important step in the criminal process. For some people, their breach of a State’s law is alone sufficient reason for surrendering themselves and accepting punishment. For others, apprehension and charge, both threatening acts by the Government, jar them into admitting their guilt. In still other cases, the post-indictment accumulation of evidence may convince the defendant and his counsel that a trial is not worth the agony and expense to the defendant and his family. All these pleas of guilty are valid in spite of the State’s responsibility for some of the factors motivating the pleas; the pleas are no more improperly compelled than is the decision by a defendant at the close of the State’s evidence at trial that he must take the stand or face certain conviction. Of course, the agents of the State may not produce a plea by actual or threatened physical harm or by mental coercion overbearing the will of the defendant. But nothing of the sort is claimed in this case; nor is there evidence that Brady was so gripped by fear of the death penalty or hope of leniency that he did not or could not, with the help of counsel, rationally weigh the advantages of going to trial against the advantages of pleading guilty. Brady’s claim is of a different sort: that it violates the Fifth Amendment to influence or encourage a guilty plea by opportunity or promise of leniency and that a guilty plea is coerced and invalid if influenced by the fear of a 204 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 possibly higher penalty for the crime charged if a conviction is obtained after the State is put to its proof. Insofar as the voluntariness of his plea is concerned, there is little to differentiate Brady from (1) the defendant, in a jurisdiction where the judge and jury have the same range of sentencing power, who pleads guilty because his lawyer advises him that the judge will very probably be more lenient than the jury; (2) the defendant, in a jurisdiction where the judge alone has sentencing power, who is advised by counsel that the judge is normally more lenient with defendants who plead guilty than with those who go to trial; (3) the defendant who is permitted by prosecutor and judge to plead guilty to a lesser offense included in the offense charged; and (4) the defendant who pleads guilty to certain counts with the understanding that other charges will be dropped. In each of these situations, as in Brady’s case, the defendant might never plead guilty absent the possibility or certainty that the plea will result in a lesser penalty than the sentence that could be imposed after a trial and a verdict of guilty. We decline to hold, however, that a guilty plea is compelled and invalid under the Fifth Amendment whenever motivated by the defendant’s desire to accept the certainty or probability of a lesser penalty rather than face a wider range of possibilities extending from acquittal to conviction and a higher penalty authorized by law for the crime charged. The issue we deal with is inherent in the criminal law and its administration because guilty pleas are not constitutionally forbidden, because the criminal law characteristically extends to judge or jury a range of choice in setting the sentence in individual cases, and because both the State and the defendant often find it advantageous to preclude the 205 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 possibility of the maximum penalty authorized by law. For a defendant who sees slight possibility of acquittal, the advantages of pleading guilty and limiting the probable penalty are obvious—his exposure is reduced, the correctional processes can begin immediately, and the practical burdens of a trial are eliminated. For the State there are also advantages—the more promptly imposed punishment after an admission of guilt may more effectively attain the objectives of punishment; and with the avoidance of trial, scarce judicial and prosecutorial resources are conserved for those cases in which there is a substantial issue of the defendant’s guilt or in which there is substantial doubt that the State can sustain its burden of proof. It is this mutuality of advantage that perhaps explains the fact that at present well over three-fourths of the criminal convictions in this country rest on pleas of guilty, a great many of them no doubt motivated at least in part by the hope or assurance of a lesser penalty than might be imposed if there were a guilty verdict after a trial to judge or jury. Of course, that the prevalence of guilty pleas is explainable does not necessarily validate those pleas or the system which produces them. But we cannot hold that it is unconstitutional for the State to extend a benefit to a defendant who in turn extends a substantial benefit to the State and who demonstrates by his plea that he is ready and willing to admit his crime and to enter the correctional system in a frame of mind that affords hope for success in rehabilitation over a shorter period of time than might otherwise be necessary. A contrary holding would require the States and Federal Government to forbid guilty pleas altogether, to provide a single invariable penalty for each crime defined by the 206 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 statutes, or to place the sentencing function in a separate authority having no knowledge of the manner in which the conviction in each case was obtained. In any event, it would be necessary to forbid prosecutors and judges to accept guilty pleas to selected counts, to lesser included offenses, or to reduced charges. The Fifth Amendment does not reach so far. Bram v. United States . . . held that the admissibility of a confession depended upon whether it was compelled within the meaning of the Fifth Amendment. To be admissible, a confession must be “free and voluntary: that is, must not be extracted by any sort of threats or violence, nor obtained by any direct or implied promises, however slight, nor by the exertion of any improper influence.” More recently, Malloy v. Hogan . . . carried forward the Bram definition of compulsion in the course of holding applicable to the States the Fifth Amendment privilege against compelled self-incrimination. Bram is not inconsistent with our holding that Brady’s plea was not compelled even though the law promised him a lesser maximum penalty if he did not go to trial. Bram dealt with a confession given by a defendant in custody, alone and unrepresented by counsel. In such circumstances, even a mild promise of leniency was deemed sufficient to bar the confession, not because the promise was an illegal act as such, but because defendants at such times are too sensitive to inducement and the possible impact on them too great to ignore and too difficult to assess. But Bram and its progeny did not hold that the possibly coercive impact of a promise of leniency could not be dissipated by the presence and advice of counsel, any more than Miranda v. Arizona . . . held that the possibly coercive atmosphere of the police station could not 207 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 be counteracted by the presence of counsel or other safeguards. Brady’s situation bears no resemblance to Bram’s. Brady first pleaded not guilty; prior to changing his plea to guilty he was subjected to no threats or promises in face-to-face encounters with the authorities. He had competent counsel and full opportunity to assess the advantages and disadvantages of a trial as compared with those attending a plea of guilty; there was no hazard of an impulsive and improvident response to a seeming but unreal advantage. His plea of guilty was entered in open court and before a judge obviously sensitive to the requirements of the law with respect to guilty pleas. Brady’s plea, unlike Bram’s confession, was voluntary. The standard as to the voluntariness of guilty pleas must be essentially that defined by Judge Tuttle of the Court of Appeals for the Fifth Circuit: “(A) plea of guilty entered by one fully aware of the direct consequences, including the actual value of any commitments made to him by the court, prosecutor, or his own counsel, must stand unless induced by threats (or promises to discontinue improper harassment), misrepresentation (including unfulfilled or unfulfillable promises), or perhaps by promises that are by their nature improper as having no proper relationship to the prosecutor’s business (e.g. bribes).’ Under this standard, a plea of guilty is not invalid merely because entered to avoid the possibility of a death penalty. 208 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 III The record before us also supports the conclusion that Brady’s plea was intelligently made. He was advised by competent counsel, he was made aware of the nature of the charge against him, and there was nothing to indicate that he was incompetent or otherwise not in control of his mental faculties; once his confederate had pleaded guilty and became available to testify, he chose to plead guilty, perhaps to ensure that he would face no more than life imprisonment or a term of years. Brady was aware of precisely what he was doing when he admitted that he had kidnaped the victim and had not released her unharmed. It is true that Brady’s counsel advised him that § 1201(a) empowered the jury to impose the death penalty and that nine years later in United States v. Jackson, . . . the Court held that the jury had no such power as long as the judge could impose only a lesser penalty if trial was to the court or there was a plea of guilty. But these facts do not require us to set aside Brady’s conviction. Often the decision to plead guilty is heavily influenced by the defendant’s appraisal of the prosecution’s case against him and by the apparent likelihood of securing leniency should a guilty plea be offered and accepted. Considerations like these frequently present imponderable questions for which there are no certain answers; judgments may be made that in the light of later events seem improvident, although they were perfectly sensible at the time. The rule that a plea must be intelligently made to be valid does not require that a plea be vulnerable to later attack if the defendant did not correctly assess every relevant factor entering into his decision. A defendant is not entitled to withdraw his plea merely because 209 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 he discovers long after the plea has been accepted that his calculus misapprehended the quality of the State’s case or the likely penalties attached to alternative courses of action. More particularly, absent misrepresentation or other impermissible conduct by state agents, . . . a voluntary plea of guilty intelligently made in the light of the then applicable law does not become vulnerable because later judicial decisions indicate that the plea rested on a faulty premise. A plea of guilty triggered by the expectations of a competently counseled defendant that the State will have a strong case against him is not subject to later attack because the defendant’s lawyer correctly advised him with respect to the then existing law as to possible penalties but later pronouncements of the courts, as in this case, hold that the maximum penalty for the crime in question was less than was reasonably assumed at the time the plea was entered. The fact that Brady did not anticipate United States v. Jackson, . . . does not impugn the truth or reliability of his plea. We find no requirement in the Constitution that a defendant must be permitted to disown his solemn admissions in open court that he committed the act with which he is charged simply because it later develops that the State would have had a weaker case than the defendant had thought or that the maximum penalty then assumed applicable has been held inapplicable in subsequent judicial decisions. This is not to say that guilty plea convictions hold no hazards for the innocent or that the methods of taking guilty pleas presently employed in this country are necessarily valid in all respects. This mode of conviction is no more foolproof than full trials to the court or to the jury. Accordingly, we take great precautions against unsound results, and we should 210 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 continue to do so, whether conviction is by plea or by trial. We would have serious doubts about this case if the encouragement of guilty pleas by offers of leniency substantially increased the likelihood that defendants, advised by competent counsel, would falsely condemn themselves. But our view is to the contrary and is based on our expectations that courts will satisfy themselves that pleas of guilty are voluntarily and intelligently made by competent defendants with adequate advice of counsel and that there is nothing to question the accuracy and reliability of the defendants’ admissions that they committed the crimes with which they are charged. In the case before us, nothing in the record impeaches Brady’s plea or suggests that his admissions in open court were anything but the truth. Although Brady’s plea of guilty may well have been motivated in part by a desire to avoid a possible death penalty, we are convinced that his plea was voluntarily and intelligently made and we have no reason to doubt that his solemn admission of guilt was truthful. Affirmed. 211 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 Reading 6: Fairness and Distributive Justice For this section, please read Julian Lamont and Christi Favor’s entry on Distributive Justice in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: https://plato.stanford.edu/ entries/justice-distributive/. Review Topics and Questions – What does strict egalitarianism require? What are some easy arguments to make against it, and how might you rebut them? – How does Rawls Difference Principle embrace aspects of strict egalitarianism while avoiding some of the obvious problems? Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 – What are the two orders of goods in Rawls’ theory and how are they prioritized? – What is the veil of ignorance, and how does this thought experiment work? What did Rawls believe it implied? Does it? – Explain “luck egalitarianism” and the distinction between ambitions (or choice) and endowments (or brute luck). – What are some possible utilitarian or welfare-based arguments regarding distributive justice? – Understand Nozick’s Entitlement Theory. – Why is Holmes’ opinion in Pennsylvania Coal based on distributive justice rather than efficiency? – What constitutional text justifies the regulatory takings doctrine, and how is a regulatory taking different from eminent domain? – Can you summarize the dispute between Holmes and Brandeis? – Why are taxes and regulations potential substitutes, and why does Scalia argue the City of San Jose should have proceeded by taxation? 213 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 Pennsylvania Coal Co. v. Mahon, 260 U.S. 393 (1922) Holmes, J. This is a bill in equity brought by the defendants in error to prevent the Pennsylvania Coal Company from mining under their property in such way as to remove the supports and cause a subsidence of the surface and of their house. The bill sets out a deed executed by the Coal Company in 1878, under which the plaintiffs claim. The deed conveys the surface, but in express terms reserves the right to remove all the coal under the same, and the grantee takes the premises with the risk, and waives all claim for damages that may arise from mining out the coal. But the plaintiffs say that whatever may have been the Coal Company's rights, they were taken away by an Act of Pennsylvania, . . . commonly known there as the Kohler Act. The Court of Common Pleas found that if not restrained the defendant would cause the damage to prevent which the bill was brought, but denied an injunction, holding that the statute if applied to this case would be unconstitutional. On appeal the Supreme Court of the State agreed that the defendant had contract and property rights protected by the Constitution of the United States, but held that the statute was a legitimate exercise of the police power and directed a decree for the plaintiffs. A writ of error was granted bringing the case to this Court. The statute forbids the mining of anthracite coal in such way as to cause the subsidence of, among other things, any 214 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 structure used as a human habitation, with certain exceptions, including among them land where the surface is owned by the owner of the underlying coal and is distant more than one hundred and fifty feet from any improved property belonging to any other person. As applied to this case the statute is admitted to destroy previously existing rights of property and contract. The question is whether the police power can be stretched so far. Government hardly could go on if to some extent values incident to property could not be diminished without paying for every such change in the general law. As long recognized, some values are enjoyed under an implied limitation and must yield to the police power. But obviously the implied limitation must have its limits, or the contract and due process clauses are gone. One fact for consideration in determining such limits is the extent of the diminution. When it reaches a certain magnitude, in most if not in all cases there must be an exercise of eminent domain and compensation to sustain the act. So the question depends upon the particular facts. The greatest weight is given to the judgment of the legislature, but it always is open to interested parties to contend that the legislature has gone beyond its constitutional power. This is the case of a single private house. No doubt there is a public interest even in this, as there is in every purchase and sale and in all that happens within the commonwealth. Some existing rights may be modified even in such a case. But usually in ordinary private affairs the public interest does not warrant much of this kind of interference. A source of damage to such a house is not a public nuisance even if similar damage is inflicted on others in different places. The damage is not common or public. The extent of the public interest is shown 215 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 by the statute to be limited, since the statute ordinarily does not apply to land when the surface is owned by the owner of the coal. Furthermore, it is not justified as a protection of personal safety. That could be provided for by notice. Indeed the very foundation of this bill is that the defendant gave timely notice of its intent to mine under the house. On the other hand the extent of the taking is great. It purports to abolish what is recognized in Pennsylvania as an estate in land — a very valuable estate — and what is declared by the Court below to be a contract hitherto binding the plaintiffs. If we were called upon to deal with the plaintiffs' position alone, we should think it clear that the statute does not disclose a public interest sufficient to warrant so extensive a destruction of the defendant's constitutionally protected rights. But the case has been treated as one in which the general validity of the act should be discussed. The Attorney General of the State, the City of Scranton, and the representatives of other extensive interests were allowed to take part in the argument below and have submitted their contentions here. It seems, therefore, to be our duty to go farther in the statement of our opinion, in order that it may be known at once, and that further suits should not be brought in vain. It is our opinion that the act cannot be sustained as an exercise of the police power, so far as it affects the mining of coal under streets or cities in places where the right to mine such coal has been reserved. As said in a Pennsylvania case, "For practical purposes, the right to coal consists in the right to mine it." What makes the right to mine coal valuable is that it can be exercised with profit. To make it commercially impracticable to mine certain coal has very nearly the same effect for constitutional purposes as appropriating or 216 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 destroying it. This we think that we are warranted in assuming that the statute does. It is true that in Plymouth Coal Co. v. Pennsylvania . . . it was held competent for the legislature to require a pillar of coal to be left along the line of adjoining property, that, with the pillar on the other side of the line, would be a barrier sufficient for the safety of the employees of either mine in case the other should be abandoned and allowed to fill with water. But that was a requirement for the safety of employees invited into the mine, and secured an average reciprocity of advantage that has been recognized as a justification of various laws. The rights of the public in a street purchased or laid out by eminent domain are those that it has paid for. If in any case its representatives have been so short sighted as to acquire only surface rights without the right of support, we see no more authority for supplying the latter without compensation than there was for taking the right of way in the first place and refusing to pay for it because the public wanted it very much. The protection of private property in the Fifth Amendment presupposes that it is wanted for public use, but provides that it shall not be taken for such use without compensation. A similar assumption is made in the decisions upon the Fourteenth Amendment. When this seemingly absolute protection is found to be qualified by the police power, the natural tendency of human nature is to extend the qualification more and more until at last private property disappears. But that cannot be accomplished in this way under the Constitution of the United States. The general rule at least is, that while property may be regulated to a certain extent, if regulation goes too far it will 217 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 be recognized as a taking. It may be doubted how far exceptional cases, like the blowing up of a house to stop a conflagration, go — and if they go beyond the general rule, whether they do not stand as much upon tradition as upon principle. In general it is not plain that a man's misfortunes or necessities will justify his shifting the damages to his neighbor's shoulders. We are in danger of forgetting that a strong public desire to improve the public condition is not enough to warrant achieving the desire by a shorter cut than the constitutional way of paying for the change. As we already have said, this is a question of degree — and therefore cannot be disposed of by general propositions. But we regard this as going beyond any of the cases decided by this Court. The late decisions upon laws dealing with the congestion of Washington and New York, caused by the war, dealt with laws intended to meet a temporary emergency and providing for compensation determined to be reasonable by an impartial board. They went to the verge of the law but fell far short of the present act. We assume, of course, that the statute was passed upon the conviction that an exigency existed that would warrant it, and we assume that an exigency exists that would warrant the exercise of eminent domain. But the question at bottom is upon whom the loss of the changes desired should fall. So far as private persons or communities have seen fit to take the risk of acquiring only surface rights, we cannot see that the fact that their risk has become a danger warrants the giving to them greater rights than they bought. Decree reversed. 218 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 MR. JUSTICE BRANDEIS, dissenting. The Kohler Act prohibits, under certain conditions, the mining of anthracite coal within the limits of a city in such a manner or to such an extent "as to cause the . . . subsidence of any dwelling or other structure used as a human habitation, or any factory, store, or other industrial or mercantile establishment in which human labor is employed." Coal in place is land; and the right of the owner to use his land is not absolute. He may not so use it as to create a public nuisance; and uses, once harmless, may, owing to changed conditions, seriously threaten the public welfare. Whenever they do, the legislature has power to prohibit such uses without paying compensation; and the power to prohibit extends alike to the manner, the character and the purpose of the use. Are we justified in declaring that the Legislature of Pennsylvania has, in restricting the right to mine anthracite, exercised this power so arbitrarily as to violate the Fourteenth Amendment? Every restriction upon the use of property imposed in the exercise of the police power deprives the owner of some right theretofore enjoyed, and is, in that sense, an abridgment by the State of rights in property without making compensation. But restriction imposed to protect the public health, safety or morals from dangers threatened is not a taking. The restriction here in question is merely the prohibition of a noxious use. The property so restricted remains in the possession of its owner. The State does not appropriate it or make any use of it. The State merely prevents the owner from making a use which interferes with paramount rights of the public. Whenever the use prohibited ceases to be noxious — as it may because of further change in local or social 219 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 conditions, — the restriction will have to be removed and the owner will again be free to enjoy his property as heretofore. The restriction upon the use of this property can not, of course, be lawfully imposed, unless its purpose is to protect the public. But the purpose of a restriction does not cease to be public, because incidentally some private persons may thereby receive gratuitously valuable special benefits. Thus, owners of low buildings may obtain, through statutory restrictions upon the height of neighboring structures, benefits equivalent to an easement of light and air. Furthermore, a restriction, though imposed for a public purpose, will not be lawful, unless the restriction is an appropriate means to the public end. But to keep coal in place is surely an appropriate means of preventing subsidence of the surface; and ordinarily it is the only available means. Restriction upon use does not become inappropriate as a means, merely because it deprives the owner of the only use to which the property can then be profitably put. The liquor and the oleomargarine cases settled that. Nor is a restriction imposed through exercise of the police power inappropriate as a means, merely because the same end might be affected through exercise of the power of eminent domain, or otherwise at public expense. Every restriction upon the height of buildings might be secured through acquiring by eminent domain the right of each owner to build above the limiting height; but it is settled that the State need not resort to that power. If by mining anthracite coal the owner would necessarily unloose poisonous gasses, I suppose no one would doubt the power of the State to prevent the mining, without buying his coal fields. And why may not the State, likewise, without paying compensation, prohibit one from digging so 220 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 deep or excavating so near the surface, as to expose the community to like dangers? In the latter case, as in the former, carrying on the business would be a public nuisance. It is said that one fact for consideration in determining whether the limits of the police power have been exceeded is the extent of the resulting diminution in value; and that here the restriction destroys existing rights of property and contract. But values are relative. If we are to consider the value of the coal kept in place by the restriction, we should compare it with the value of all other parts of the land. That is, with the value not of the coal alone, but with the value of the whole property. The rights of an owner as against the public are not increased by dividing the interests in his property into surface and subsoil. The sum of the rights in the parts can not be greater than the rights in the whole. The estate of an owner in land is grandiloquently described as extending ab orco usque ad coelum. But I suppose no one would contend that by selling his interest above one hundred feet from the surface he could prevent the State from limiting, by the police power, the height of structures in a city. And why should a sale of underground rights bar the State's power? For aught that appears the value of the coal kept in place by the restriction may be negligible as compared with the value of the whole property, or even as compared with that part of it which is represented by the coal remaining in place and which may be extracted despite the statute. Ordinarily a police regulation, general in operation, will not be held void as to a particular property, although proof is offered that owing to conditions peculiar to it the restriction could not reasonably be applied. But even if the particular facts are to govern, the statute should, in my opinion, be upheld in this case. For the 221 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 defendant has failed to adduce any evidence from which it appears that to restrict its mining operations was an unreasonable exercise of the police power. Where the surface and the coal belong to the same person, self-interest would ordinarily prevent mining to such an extent as to cause a subsidence. It was, doubtless, for this reason that the legislature, estimating the degrees of danger, deemed statutory restriction unnecessary for the public safety under such conditions. It is said that this is a case of a single dwelling house; that the restriction upon mining abolishes a valuable estate hitherto secured by a contract with the plaintiffs; and that the restriction upon mining cannot be justified as a protection of personal safety, since that could be provided for by notice. The propriety of deferring a good deal to tribunals on the spot has been repeatedly recognized. May we say that notice would afford adequate protection of the public safety where the legislature and the highest court of the State, with greater knowledge of local conditions, have declared, in effect, that it would not? If public safety is imperiled, surely neither grant, nor contract, can prevail against the exercise of the police power. The rule that the State's power to take appropriate measures to guard the safety of all who may be within its jurisdiction may not he bargained away was applied to compel carriers to establish grade crossings at their own expense, despite contracts to the contrary; . . . and, likewise, to supersede, by an employers' liability act, the provision of a charter exempting a railroad from liability for death of employees, since the civil liability was deemed a matter of public concern, and not a mere private right. Nor can existing contracts between private individuals preclude exercise of the 222 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 police power. "One whose rights, such as they are, are subject to state restriction, cannot remove them from the power of the State by making a contract about them." The fact that this suit is brought by a private person is, of course, immaterial to protect the community through invoking the aid, as litigant, of interested private citizens is not a novelty in our law. That it may be done in Pennsylvania was decided by its Supreme Court in this case. And it is for a State to say how its public policy shall be enforced. This case involves only mining which causes subsidence of a dwelling house. But the Kohler Act contains provisions in addition to that quoted above; and as to these, also, an opinion is expressed. These provisions deal with mining under cities to such an extent as to cause subsidence of — (a) Any public building or any structure customarily used by the public as a place of resort, assemblage, or amusement, including, but not being limited to, churches, schools, hospitals, theatres, hotels, and railroad stations. (b) Any street, road, bridge, or other public passageway, dedicated to public use or habitually used by the public. (c) Any track, roadbed, right of way, pipe, conduct, wire, or other facility, used in the service of the public by any municipal corporation or public service company as defined by the Public Service Company Law. A prohibition of mining which causes subsidence of such structures and facilities is obviously enacted for a public purpose; and it seems, likewise, clear that mere notice of intention to mine would not in this connection secure the public safety. Yet it is said that these provisions of the act cannot be sustained as an exercise of the police power where the right to mine such coal has been reserved. The conclusion 223 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 seems to rest upon the assumption that in order to justify such exercise of the police power there must be "an average reciprocity of advantage" as between the owner of the property restricted and the rest of the community; and that here such reciprocity is absent. Reciprocity of advantage is an important consideration, and may even be an essential, where the State's power is exercised for the purpose of conferring benefits upon the property of a neighborhood, as in drainage projects . . . or upon adjoining owners, as by party wall provisions. . . . But where the police power is exercised, not to confer benefits upon property owners, but to protect the public from detriment and danger, there is, in my opinion, no room for considering reciprocity of advantage. There was no reciprocal advantage to the owner prohibited from using his oil tanks . . . his brickyard . . . his livery stable . . . his billiard hall . . . his oleomargarine factory . . . his brewery . . . unless it be the advantage of living and doing business in a civilized community. That reciprocal advantage is given by the act to the coal operators. Pennell v. City of San Jose, 485 U.S. 1 (1998) Chief Justice REHNQUIST delivered the opinion of the Court. This case involves a challenge to a rent control ordinance enacted by the city of San Jose, California, that allows a 224 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 hearing officer to consider, among other factors, the “hardship to a tenant” when determining whether to approve a rent increase proposed by a landlord. Appellants Richard Pennell and the Tri–County Apartment House Owners Association sued in the Superior Court of Santa Clara County seeking a declaration that the ordinance, in particular the “tenant hardship” provisions, are “facially unconstitutional and therefore . . . illegal and void.” The Superior Court entered judgment on the pleadings in favor of appellants, sustaining their claim that the tenant hardship provisions violated the Takings Clause of the Fifth Amendment, as made applicable to the States by the Fourteenth Amendment. The California Court of Appeal affirmed this judgment, . . . but the Supreme Court of California reversed, . . . each by a divided vote. The majority of the Supreme Court rejected appellants’ arguments under the Takings Clause and the Equal Protection and Due Process Clauses of the Fourteenth Amendment; the dissenters in that court thought that the tenant hardship provisions were a “forced subsidy imposed on the landlord” in violation of the Takings Clause. On appellants’ appeal to this Court we postponed consideration of the question of jurisdiction, . . . and now having heard oral argument we affirm the judgment of the Supreme Court of California. The city of San Jose enacted its rent control ordinance (Ordinance) in 1979 with the stated purpose of “alleviat[ing] some of the more immediate needs created by San Jose’s housing situation. These needs include but are not limited to the prevention of excessive and unreasonable rent increases, the alleviation of undue hardships upon individual tenants, and the assurance to 225 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 landlords of a fair and reasonable return on the value of their property.” At the heart of the Ordinance is a mechanism for determining the amount by which landlords subject to its provisions may increase the annual rent which they charge their tenants. A landlord is automatically entitled to raise the rent of a tenant in possession by as much as eight percent; if a tenant objects to an increase greater than eight percent, a hearing is required before a “Mediation Hearing Officer” to determine whether the landlord’s proposed increase is “reasonable under the circumstances.” The Ordinance sets forth a number of factors to be considered by the hearing officer in making this determination, including “the hardship to a tenant.” Because appellants concentrate their attack on the consideration of this factor, we set forth the relevant provision of the Ordinance in full: “5703.29. Hardship to Tenants. In the case of a rent increase or any portion thereof which exceeds the standard set in Section 5703.28(a) or (b), then with respect to such excess and whether or not to allow same to be part of the increase allowed under this Chapter, the Hearing Officer shall consider the economic and financial hardship imposed on the present tenant or tenants of the unit or units to which such increases apply. If, on balance, the Hearing Officer determines that the proposed increase constitutes an unreasonably severe financial or economic hardship on a particular tenant, he may order that the excess of the increase which is subject to consideration under subparagraph (c) of 226 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 Section 5703.28, or any portion thereof, be disallowed. Any tenant whose household income and monthly housing expense meets [certain income requirements] shall be deemed to be suffering under financial and economic hardship which must be weighed in the Hearing Officer’s determination. The burden of proof in establishing any other economic hardship shall be on the tenant.” If either a tenant or a landlord is dissatisfied with the decision of the hearing officer, the Ordinance provides for binding arbitration. A landlord who attempts to charge or who receives rent in excess of the maximum rent established as provided in the Ordinance is subject to criminal and civil penalties. [The Court’s discussion concerning whether the appellants lacked standing to challenge the Ordinance is omitted.] Turning now to the merits, we first address appellants’ contention that application of the Ordinance’s tenant hardship provisions violates the Fifth and Fourteenth Amendments’ prohibition against taking of private property for public use without just compensation. In essence, appellants’ claim is as follows: § 5703.28 of the Ordinance establishes the seven factors that a hearing officer is to take into account in determining the reasonable rent increase. The first six of these factors are all objective, and are related either to the landlord’s costs of providing an adequate rental unit, or to the condition of the rental market. Application of these six standards results in a rent that is “reasonable” by reference to what appellants contend is the only legitimate purpose of rent control: the elimination of “excessive” rents caused by San 227 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 Jose’s housing shortage. When the hearing officer then takes into account “hardship to a tenant” pursuant to § 5703.28(c) (7) and reduces the rent below the objectively “reasonable” amount established by the first six factors, this additional reduction in the rent increase constitutes a “taking.” This taking is impermissible because it does not serve the purpose of eliminating excessive rents—that objective has already been accomplished by considering the first six factors— instead, it serves only the purpose of providing assistance to “hardship tenants.” In short, appellants contend, the additional reduction of rent on grounds of hardship accomplishes a transfer of the landlord’s property to individual hardship tenants; the Ordinance forces private individuals to shoulder the “public” burden of subsidizing their poor tenants’ housing. As appellants point out, “[i]t is axiomatic that the Fifth Amendment’s just compensation provision is ‘designed to bar Government from forcing some people alone to bear public burdens which, in all fairness and justice, should be borne by the public as a whole.’ ” We think it would be premature to consider this contention on the present record. As things stand, there simply is no evidence that the “tenant hardship clause” has in fact ever been relied upon by a hearing officer to reduce a rent below the figure it would have been set at on the basis of the other factors set forth in the Ordinance. In addition, there is nothing in the Ordinance requiring that a hearing officer in fact reduce a proposed rent increase on grounds of tenant hardship. Section 5703.29 does make it mandatory that hardship be considered—it states that “the Hearing Officer shall consider the economic hardship imposed on the present tenant”—but it then goes on to state that if “the proposed 228 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 increase constitutes an unreasonably severe financial or economic hardship . . . he may order that the excess of the increase” be disallowed. (emphasis added). Given the “essentially ad hoc, factual inquir[y]” involved in the takings analysis, . . . we have found it particularly important in takings cases to adhere to our admonition that “the constitutionality of statutes ought not be decided except in an actual factual setting that makes such a decision necessary.” In Virginia Surface Mining, for example, we found that a challenge to the Surface Mining Control and Reclamation Act of 1977, . . . was “premature,” . . . and “not ripe for judicial resolution,” . . . because the property owners in that case had not identified any property that had allegedly been taken by the Act, nor had they sought administrative relief from the Act’s restrictions on surface mining. Similarly, in this case we find that the mere fact that a hearing officer is enjoined to consider hardship to the tenant in fixing a landlord’s rent, without any showing in a particular case as to the consequences of that injunction in the ultimate determination of the rent, does not present a sufficiently concrete factual setting for the adjudication of the takings claim appellants raise here. Appellants also urge that the mere provision in the Ordinance that a hearing officer may consider the hardship of the tenant in finally fixing a reasonable rent renders the Ordinance “facially invalid” under the Due Process and Equal Protection Clauses, even though no landlord ever has its rent diminished by as much as one dollar because of the application of this provision. The standard for determining whether a state price-control regulation is constitutional under the Due Process Clause is well established: “Price 229 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 control is ‘unconstitutional . . . if arbitrary, discriminatory, or demonstrably irrelevant to the policy the legislature is free to adopt. . . .’ ” In other contexts we have recognized that the government may intervene in the marketplace to regulate rates or prices that are artificially inflated as a result of the existence of a monopoly or near monopoly, . . . or a discrepancy between supply and demand in the market for a certain product…. Accordingly, appellants do not dispute that the Ordinance’s asserted purpose of “prevent[ing] excessive and unreasonable rent increases” caused by the “growing shortage of and increasing demand for housing in the City of San Jose,” § 5701.2, is a legitimate exercise of appellees’ police powers. They do argue, however, that it is “arbitrary, discriminatory, or demonstrably irrelevant,” . . . for appellees to attempt to accomplish the additional goal of reducing the burden of housing costs on low-income tenants by requiring that “hardship to a tenant” be considered in determining the amount of excess rent increase that is “reasonable under the circumstances” pursuant to § 5703.28. As appellants put it, “[t]he objective of alleviating individual tenant hardship is . . . not a ‘policy the legislature is free to adopt’ in a rent control ordinance.” We reject this contention, however, because we have long recognized that a legitimate and rational goal of price or rate regulation is the protection of consumer welfare. Indeed, a primary purpose of rent control is the protection of tenants. Here, the Ordinance establishes a scheme in which a hearing officer considers a number of factors in determining the reasonableness of a proposed rent increase which exceeds eight percent and which exceeds the amount deemed reasonable under either § 5703.28(a) or § 5703.28(b). The 230 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 first six factors of § 5703.28(c) focus on the individual landlord—the hearing officer examines the history of the premises, the landlord’s costs, and the market for comparable housing. Section 5703.28(c)(5) also allows the landlord to bring forth any other financial evidence—including presumably evidence regarding his own financial status—to be taken into account by the hearing officer. It is in only this context that the Ordinance allows tenant hardship to be considered and, under § 5703.29, “balance[d]” with the other factors set out in § 5703.28(c). Within this scheme, § 5703.28(c) represents a rational attempt to accommodate the conflicting interests of protecting tenants from burdensome rent increases while at the same time ensuring that landlords are guaranteed a fair return on their investment. We accordingly find that the Ordinance, which so carefully considers both the individual circumstances of the landlord and the tenant before determining whether to allow an additional increase in rent over and above certain amounts that are deemed reasonable, does not on its face violate the Fourteenth Amendment’s Due Process Clause. We also find that the Ordinance does not violate the Amendment’s Equal Protection Clause. Here again, the standard is deferential; appellees need only show that the classification scheme embodied in the Ordinance is “rationally related to a legitimate state interest.” As we stated in Vance v. Bradley, . . . “we will not overturn [a statute that does not burden a suspect class or a fundamental interest] unless the varying treatment of different groups or persons is so unrelated to the achievement of any combination of legitimate purposes that we can only conclude that the legislature’s actions were irrational.” In light of our conclusion above that 231 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 the Ordinance’s tenant hardship provisions are designed to serve the legitimate purpose of protecting tenants, we can hardly conclude that it is irrational for the Ordinance to treat certain landlords differently on the basis of whether or not they have hardship tenants. The Ordinance distinguishes between landlords because doing so furthers the purpose of ensuring that individual tenants do not suffer “unreasonable” hardship; it would be inconsistent to state that hardship is a legitimate factor to be considered but then hold that appellees could not tailor the Ordinance so that only legitimate hardship cases are redressed. We recognize, as appellants point out, that in general it is difficult to say that the landlord “causes” the tenant’s hardship. But this is beside the point—if a landlord does have a hardship tenant, regardless of the reason why, it is rational for appellees to take that fact into consideration under § 5703.28 of the Ordinance when establishing a rent that is “reasonable under the circumstances.” For the foregoing reasons, we hold that it is premature to consider appellants’ claim under the Takings Clause and we reject their facial challenge to the Ordinance under the Due Process and Equal Protection Clauses of the Fourteenth Amendment. The judgment of the Supreme Court of California is accordingly Affirmed. Justice KENNEDY took no part in the consideration or decision of this case. Justice SCALIA, with whom Justice O’CONNOR joins, concurring in part and dissenting in part. 232 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 I agree that the tenant hardship provision of the Ordinance does not, on its face, violate either the Due Process Clause or the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment. I disagree, however, with the Court’s conclusion that appellants’ takings claim is premature. I would decide that claim on the merits, and would hold that the tenant hardship provision of the Ordinance effects a taking of private property without just compensation in violation of the Fifth and Fourteenth Amendments. I [Justice Scalia argues that the Takings Clause challenge is not premature, and as such should be adjudicated on the merits.] II The Fifth Amendment of the United States Constitution, made applicable to the States through the Fourteenth Amendment, . . . provides that “private property [shall not] be taken for public use, without just compensation.” We have repeatedly observed that the purpose of this provision is “to bar Government from forcing some people alone to bear public burdens which, in all fairness and justice, should be borne by the public as a whole.” Traditional land-use regulation (short of that which totally destroys the economic value of property) does not violate this principle because there is a cause-and-effect relationship between the property use restricted by the regulation and the social evil that the regulation seeks to remedy. Since the 233 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 owner’s use of the property is (or, but for the regulation, would be) the source of the social problem, it cannot be said that he has been singled out unfairly. Thus, the common zoning regulations requiring subdividers to observe lot-size and set-back restrictions, and to dedicate certain areas to public streets, are in accord with our constitutional traditions because the proposed property use would otherwise be the cause of excessive congestion. The same cause-and-effect relationship is popularly thought to justify emergency price regulation: When commodities have been priced at a level that produces exorbitant returns, the owners of those commodities can be viewed as responsible for the economic hardship that occurs. Whether or not that is an accurate perception of the way a free-market economy operates, it is at least true that the owners reap unique benefits from the situation that produces the economic hardship, and in that respect singling them out to relieve it may not be regarded as “unfair.” That justification might apply to the rent regulation in the present case, apart from the single feature under attack here. Appellants do not contest the validity of rent regulation in general. They acknowledge that the city may constitutionally set a “reasonable rent” according to the statutory minimum and the six other factors that must be considered by the hearing officer (cost of debt servicing, rental history of the unit, physical condition of the unit, changes in housing services, other financial information provided by the landlord, and market value rents for similar units). Appellants’ only claim is that a reduction of a rent increase below what would otherwise be a “reasonable rent” under this scheme may not, consistently with the Constitution, be based on consideration 234 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 of the seventh factor—the hardship to the tenant as defined in § 5703.29. I think they are right. Once the other six factors of the Ordinance have been applied to a landlord’s property, so that he is receiving only a reasonable return, he can no longer be regarded as a “cause” of exorbitantly priced housing; nor is he any longer reaping distinctively high profits from the housing shortage. The seventh factor, the “hardship” provision, is invoked to meet a quite different social problem: the existence of some renters who are too poor to afford even reasonably priced housing. But that problem is no more caused or exploited by landlords than it is by the grocers who sell needy renters their food, or the department stores that sell them their clothes, or the employers who pay them their wages, or the citizens of San Jose holding the higher paying jobs from which they are excluded. And even if the neediness of renters could be regarded as a problem distinctively attributable to landlords in general, it is not remotely attributable to the particular landlords that the Ordinance singles out—namely, those who happen to have a “hardship” tenant at the present time, or who may happen to rent to a “hardship” tenant in the future, or whose current or future affluent tenants may happen to decline into the “hardship” category. The traditional manner in which American government has met the problem of those who cannot pay reasonable prices for privately sold necessities—a problem caused by the society at large—has been the distribution to such persons of funds raised from the public at large through taxes, either in cash (welfare payments) or in goods (public housing, publicly subsidized housing, and food stamps). Unless we are to abandon the guiding principle of the Takings Clause that 235 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 “public burdens . . . should be borne by the public as a whole,” . . . this is the only manner that our Constitution permits. The fact that government acts through the landlordtenant relationship does not magically transform general public welfare, which must be supported by all the public, into mere “economic regulation,” which can disproportionately burden particular individuals. Here the city is not “regulating” rents in the relevant sense of preventing rents that are excessive; rather, it is using the occasion of rent regulation (accomplished by the rest of the Ordinance) to establish a welfare program privately funded by those landlords who happen to have “hardship” tenants. Of course all economic regulation effects wealth transfer. When excessive rents are forbidden, for example, landlords as a class become poorer and tenants as a class (or at least incumbent tenants as a class) become richer. Singling out landlords to be the transferors may be within our traditional constitutional notions of fairness, because they can plausibly be regarded as the source or the beneficiary of the high-rent problem. Once such a connection is no longer required, however, there is no end to the social transformations that can be accomplished by so-called “regulation,” at great expense to the democratic process. The politically attractive feature of regulation is not that it permits wealth transfers to be achieved that could not be achieved otherwise; but rather that it permits them to be achieved “off budget,” with relative invisibility and thus relative immunity from normal democratic processes. San Jose might, for example, have accomplished something like the result here by simply raising the real estate tax upon rental properties and using the additional revenues thus 236 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 acquired to pay part of the rents of “hardship” tenants. It seems to me doubtful, however, whether the citizens of San Jose would allow funds in the municipal treasury, from wherever derived, to be distributed to a family of four with income as high as $32,400 a year—the generous maximum necessary to qualify automatically as a “hardship” tenant under the rental Ordinance. The voters might well see other, more pressing, social priorities. And of course what $32,400– a-year renters can acquire through spurious “regulation,” other groups can acquire as well. Once the door is opened it is not unreasonable to expect price regulations requiring private businesses to give special discounts to senior citizens (no matter how affluent), or to students, the handicapped, or war veterans. Subsidies for these groups may well be a good idea, but because of the operation of the Takings Clause our governmental system has required them to be applied, in general, through the process of taxing and spending, where both economic effects and competing priorities are more evident. That fostering of an intelligent democratic process is one of the happy effects of the constitutional prescription—perhaps accidental, perhaps not. Its essence, however, is simply the unfairness of making one citizen pay, in some fashion other than taxes, to remedy a social problem that is none of his creation. As the Supreme Court of New Jersey said in finding unconstitutional a scheme displaying, among other defects, the same vice I find dispositive here: “A legislative category of economically needy senior citizens is sound, proper and sustainable as a rational classification. But compelled subsidization by landlords or by tenants who happen to live in an apartment building with senior citizens is 237 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 an improper and unconstitutional method of solving the problem.” I would hold that the seventh factor in § 5703.28(c) of the San Jose Ordinance effects a taking of property without just compensation. 238 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 Meeting 7: Review and Midterm Test Below are some practice problems covering the material we have read and discussed thus far. In formulating your response, read each question carefully and remember to make an argument: giving reasons for your answer. 1. In your own words, explain why Marbury v. Madison is such an important case and what would be different had it come out the other way. 2. In Atkins v. Virginia in 1986, the Supreme Court outlawed the execution of people with intellectual disabilities, vaguely referring to defendants with IQs below 70, as against the Eighth Amendment ban on cruel and unusual punishments. The Court found that many states had prohibited such executions and that executing the disabled failed to serve the goals of either deterrence or retribution. It concluded that execution of the mentally disabled was therefore Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 inconsistent with our “evolving standards of decency” and was therefore unconstitutionally excessive. (a) Why might such executions not provide deterrence? Is that a utilitarian or deontological reason to oppose them? (b) Why might such executions not be consistent with principles of retribution? Is that a utilitarian or deontological reason to oppose them? 3. Suppose in a federal criminal trial the state seeks to introduce evidence in the form of grisly crime scene photographs. Federal Rule of Evidence 403 states: “The court may exclude relevant evidence if its probative value is substantially outweighed by a danger of . . . unfair prejudice . . . .” The judge decides to allow the evidence to go to the jury, and the defendant is convicted. On appeal to a federal circuit court of appeals, the defendant’s lawyer wants to argue that admission of this evidence was contrary to the rule. (a) Is Rule 403 a rule or a standard? Why? (b)What is meant by the “standard of review”? (c) What standard of review do you believe the appellate court should apply and why? 4. Make an argument that a prayer at a law school graduation would be constitutional, even after Lee v. Weisman. 5. Suppose you have plans today to purchase a car. Answer the following two questions: (a) What does it mean to say that a transaction 240 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 between you and a car dealer would be Pareto efficient? (b) What are two transaction costs you will likely incur in your effort to purchase a car? 6. Suppose a state is considering passing a statute requiring car dealers to include limited warranties that would make the dealer responsible for replacing or repairing parts that malfunction within three years of purchase or 30,000 miles driven. (a) Make an argument that it would be more efficient if a state permits car dealers to sell cars as-is rather than requiring car dealers to provide warranties. (The state, in this hypothetical, would not require cars to be sold as-is. Rather, it would permit dealers to choose whether to offer warranties or sell as-is.) (b) Make an argument that it could be more efficient if the state required car dealers to provide the limited warranties. 7. Identify, in each fact pattern below, whether the cause of action is based in contract, tort, or criminal law. (a) A slips on B’s sidewalk and sues B to recover medical expenses and lost wages. (b) C’s family sues B for its emotional injuries and lost wages after B intentionally killed C. (c) The local district attorney brings changes against B for intentionally killing C. 8. In tort law, when a suit for injury arises from the alleged negligence of the defendant, courts often use something like the Learned Hand formula (from 241 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 Carroll Towing) to determine whether the defendant was in fact negligent and therefore liable. In contract law, however, the defendant is liable for damages if he or she failed to comply with the terms of a contract. We don’t care, in contract law, whether it was reasonable or negligent to breach the contract. Why are both approaches, despite this key difference, generally consistent with a goal of efficiency? 9. Suppose a town makes parking free in its commercial district. There are not enough spaces for everyone who would prefer, if parking were available, to shop or dine there. Is this a tragedy of the commons? If yes, why and how would you solve it? If no or maybe, give additional facts that would cause you to conclude that this was a tragedy of the commons and then offer how you might solve the tragedy. 10. Make a Rawlsian veil argument (but not necessarily adopting Rawls’ conclusion) for or against the result in Pennsylvania Coal v. Mahon, the regulatory takings case. In other words, if you conducted Rawls’ thought experiment, would you conclude that the Kohler Act, prohibiting coal companies from causing subsidence, is or is not consistent with distributive justice? (Note, as with so many questions of law, there is no particular right answer here, just good and bad arguments.) Which theory of distributive justice most supports the result in Pennsylvania Coal and why? 11. In 1999, the federal Independent Counsel Act expired. The Act required the Attorney General, head 242 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 of the Department of Justice, to convene a panel of federal judges to appoint a special prosecutor to investigate substantial allegations that high-ranking executive officials have committed federal crimes. The special prosecutor could only be removed by impeachment and conviction in Congress or by the Attorney General (but only for particular reasons related to mental or professional competence). Make an argument that this Act was inconsistent with the unitary executive theory of the United States government. How would you change the Act to make it more consistent with that theory? Would that change have downsides? 12. Suppose that you had contracted with a company to provide tortillas for your taqueria business. The company agreed to provide you with a certain quantity of fresh tortillas weekly, and you promised to pay them a fixed amount of money monthly. One week, you receive fewer than the agreed-upon number of tortillas, and the ones you did receive were repackaged tortillas that were obviously purchased at the grocery store. After trying to contact the company all week and failing, you and your lawyer draft a letter (a) demanding compliance with the contract and compensation for the bad and insufficient tortillas and (b) outlining your legal claim. Provide the outline of your legal claim, including the duty, breach, causation, and damages that establish that legal claim. 13. Assume you are still the taqueria business described in the previous question. You are now negotiating 243 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 with another tortilla supplier. In drawing up a contract, you must decide how to formulate your desire to receive a sufficient number of tortillas weekly and of sufficient quality. Given an example of how you might draft these requirements in rule-like terms and example of how you might draft them in standard-like terms. What are some advantages and disadvantages of each approach? 14. The Kohler Act that was challenged in Pennsylvania Coal v. Mahon prohibited “the mining of anthracite coal in such way as to cause the subsidence of, among other things, any structure used as a human habitation.” (a) Argue that this statute was consistent with utilitarianism but indicate what additional facts you would like to have to bolster this argument. (b) Argue both for and against the proposition that the statute is consistent with Kant's categorical imperative. 15. Suppose a family has installed solar panels on its house. Some time later a new neighbor proposes to build a house compliant with all applicable building and zoning ordinances but which would block the light reaching the solar panels. Family would consider suing for nuisance, as in Boomer v. Atlantic Cement, to stop this particular building plan. (a) Would this suit be in tort, contract, or criminal law, or something else? Why? (b)If the assumptions of the Coase Theorem apply, what should a court decide if a nuisance suit is 244 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 brought? Why? (c) Why might those assumptions not apply? (d) What would you decide if you were the judge, and are your reasons grounded in terms of efficiency or distributive justice? 16. Suppose the manufacturer of a carnival ride called “The Shaker” is sued by the plaintiff after she was injured on the ride. The Shaker did not malfunction, but, as its name suggests, the Shaker shakes riders with considerable force and is popular for that reason. Plaintiff, though not suffering from any known ailment, suffered a painful bone fracture on the ride and has required medical care and physical therapy. She alleges her physical injuries were due to the negligence of the manufacturer because the manufacturer should have foreseen the potential for injury. (a) Explain how you would apply the Learned Hand formula to determine whether the defendant manufacturer was negligent, including what facts you would want to know and how you would use them. (b) Discuss how the Escola majority and concurrence each might approach the question of liability in this case. 17. In the Gulf of Mexico, there is an active fishery for Red Snapper. Decades ago, it was lightly regulated, and over time more and more fish were caught annually. Eventually, with better methods and more boats, the catch began to decline as the breeding stock 245 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 was depleted by an increasing number of sport and commercial fishermen. Policymaker and scientists call the the maximum quantity of fish that can be harvested on an ongoing basis (without costly declines in the stock of fish) the optimal sustainable yield. (a) Explain why this situation presents a tragedy of the commons. (b) For years, federal regulators constrained the per day catch limit, shortened fishing seasons, and regulated the types of equipment that could be used. What element of the tragedy of the commons are such regulations aimed at averting? (c) The above measures proved ineffective. It got so bad that at one point the “season” for red snapper lasted only a day or two. The regulators instead introduced “individual transferable quotas,” which are rights to catch a fixed number of tons of fish. Each year, the regulators set the total tonnage of fish available for catch to be consistent with the optimal sustainable yield. Then quotas are granted that represent a portion of the total. These quotas could be bought and sold, but the fish you catch are assessed against your quota. What element of the tragedy of the commons is this scheme aimed at averting? Do you think it will successfully do so? Why or why not? 246 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 Meeting 8: Courts and Precedent Review Questions – What is the source of the right the Court adjudicates in Casey? – What theory of justice most comports with the reasoning in the opinion? – What is the doctrine of stare decisis? Why is adherence to precedent important? – What criteria does the Court identify to guide its decision whether to depart from precedent? – What is the Court’s rule and to what does it apply? How do they apply it to the state laws at issue? Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 – What are the main dissenting arguments and on what theories of interpretation do they rely? Planned Parenthood of Southeastern Pennsylvania v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833 (1992) Justice O’CONNOR, Justice KENNEDY, and Justice SOUTER announced the judgment of the Court and delivered the opinion of the Court with respect to Parts I, II, III, V–A, V–C, and VI, an opinion with respect to Part V–E, in which Justice STEVENS joins, and an opinion with respect to Parts IV, V–B, and V–D. I Liberty finds no refuge in a jurisprudence of doubt. Yet 19 years after our holding that the Constitution protects a woman’s right to terminate her pregnancy in its early stages, Roe v. Wade . . . that definition of liberty is still questioned. Joining the respondents as amicus curiae, the United States, as it has done in five other cases in the last decade, again asks us to overrule Roe. At issue in these cases are five provisions of the Pennsylvania Abortion Control Act of 1982, as amended in 1988 and 1989. Relevant portions of the Act are set forth in the Appendix. The Act requires that a woman seeking an 248 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 abortion give her informed consent prior to the abortion procedure, and specifies that she be provided with certain information at least 24 hours before the abortion is performed. For a minor to obtain an abortion, the Act requires the informed consent of one of her parents, but provides for a judicial bypass option if the minor does not wish to or cannot obtain a parent’s consent. Another provision of the Act requires that, unless certain exceptions apply, a married woman seeking an abortion must sign a statement indicating that she has notified her husband of her intended abortion. The Act exempts compliance with these three requirements in the event of a “medical emergency”. In addition to the above provisions regulating the performance of abortions, the Act imposes certain reporting requirements on facilities that provide abortion services. Before any of these provisions took effect, the petitioners, who are five abortion clinics and one physician representing himself as well as a class of physicians who provide abortion services, brought this suit seeking declaratory and injunctive relief. Each provision was challenged as unconstitutional on its face. The District Court entered a preliminary injunction against the enforcement of the regulations, and, after a 3–day bench trial, held all the provisions at issue here unconstitutional, entering a permanent injunction against Pennsylvania’s enforcement of them. The Court of Appeals for the Third Circuit affirmed in part and reversed in part, upholding all of the regulations except for the husband notification requirement. We granted certiorari. [Justice O’Connor highlights the need for clarification in light of the Court’s disagreement with the Court of Appeals’ reasoning.] [We] find it imperative to review once more the 249 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 principles that define the rights of the woman and the legitimate authority of the State respecting the termination of pregnancies by abortion procedures. After considering the fundamental constitutional questions resolved by Roe, principles of institutional integrity, and the rule of stare decisis, we are led to conclude this: the essential holding of Roe v. Wade should be retained and once again reaffirmed. It must be stated at the outset and with clarity that Roe’s essential holding, the holding we reaffirm, has three parts. First is a recognition of the right of the woman to choose to have an abortion before viability and to obtain it without undue interference from the State. Before viability, the State’s interests are not strong enough to support a prohibition of abortion or the imposition of a substantial obstacle to the woman’s effective right to elect the procedure. Second is a confirmation of the State’s power to restrict abortions after fetal viability, if the law contains exceptions for pregnancies which endanger the woman’s life or health. And third is the principle that the State has legitimate interests from the outset of the pregnancy in protecting the health of the woman and the life of the fetus that may become a child. These principles do not contradict one another; and we adhere to each. II Constitutional protection of the woman’s decision to terminate her pregnancy derives from the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment. It declares that no State shall “deprive any person of life, liberty, or property, without due process of law.” The controlling word in the cases before us is 250 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 “liberty.” Although a literal reading of the Clause might suggest that it governs only the procedures by which a State may deprive persons of liberty, for at least 105 years . . . the Clause has been understood to contain a substantive component as well, one “barring certain government actions regardless of the fairness of the procedures used to implement them.” As Justice Brandeis (joined by Justice Holmes) observed, “[d]espite arguments to the contrary which had seemed to me persuasive, it is settled that the due process clause of the Fourteenth Amendment applies to matters of substantive law as well as to matters of procedure. Thus all fundamental rights comprised within the term liberty are protected by the Federal Constitution from invasion by the States.” “[T]he guaranties of due process, though having their roots in Magna Carta’s ‘per legem terrae’ and considered as procedural safeguards ‘against executive usurpation and tyranny,’ have in this country ‘become bulwarks also against arbitrary legislation.’ ” The most familiar of the substantive liberties protected by the Fourteenth Amendment are those recognized by the Bill of Rights. We have held that the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment incorporates most of the Bill of Rights against the States. It is tempting, as a means of curbing the discretion of federal judges, to suppose that liberty encompasses no more than those rights already guaranteed to the individual against federal interference by the express provisions of the first eight Amendments to the Constitution. But of course this Court has never accepted that view. It is also tempting, for the same reason, to suppose that the Due Process Clause protects only those practices, defined at the most specific level, that were protected against 251 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 government interference by other rules of law when the Fourteenth Amendment was ratified. But such a view would be inconsistent with our law. It is a promise of the Constitution that there is a realm of personal liberty which the government may not enter. We have vindicated this principle before. Marriage is mentioned nowhere in the Bill of Rights and interracial marriage was illegal in most States in the 19th century, but the Court was no doubt correct in finding it to be an aspect of liberty protected against state interference by the substantive component of the Due Process Clause in Loving v. Virginia . . . . Neither the Bill of Rights nor the specific practices of States at the time of the adoption of the Fourteenth Amendment marks the outer limits of the substantive sphere of liberty which the Fourteenth Amendment protects. As the second Justice Harlan recognized: “[T]he full scope of the liberty guaranteed by the Due Process Clause cannot be found in or limited by the precise terms of the specific guarantees elsewhere provided in the Constitution. This ‘liberty’ is not a series of isolated points pricked out in terms of the taking of property; the freedom of speech, press, and religion; the right to keep and bear arms; the freedom from unreasonable searches and seizures; and so on. It is a rational continuum which, broadly speaking, includes a freedom from all substantial arbitrary impositions and purposeless restraints, . . . and which also recognizes, what a reasonable and sensitive judgment must, that certain interests require particularly careful scrutiny of the state needs asserted to justify their abridgment.” Justice Harlan wrote these words in addressing an issue the full Court did not reach in Poe v. Ullman, but the Court 252 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 adopted his position four Terms later in Griswold v. Connecticut . . . . In Griswold, we held that the Constitution does not permit a State to forbid a married couple to use contraceptives. That same freedom was later guaranteed, under the Equal Protection Clause, for unmarried couples. Constitutional protection was extended to the sale and distribution of contraceptives in Carey v. Population Services International . . . . It is settled now, as it was when the Court heard arguments in Roe v. Wade, that the Constitution places limits on a State’s right to interfere with a person’s most basic decisions about family and parenthood . . . . The inescapable fact is that adjudication of substantive due process claims may call upon the Court in interpreting the Constitution to exercise that same capacity which by tradition courts always have exercised: reasoned judgment. Its boundaries are not susceptible of expression as a simple rule. That does not mean we are free to invalidate state policy choices with which we disagree; yet neither does it permit us to shrink from the duties of our office. As Justice Harlan observed: “Due process has not been reduced to any formula; its content cannot be determined by reference to any code. The best that can be said is that through the course of this Court’s decisions it has represented the balance which our Nation, built upon postulates of respect for the liberty of the individual, has struck between that liberty and the demands of organized society. If the supplying of content to this Constitutional concept has of necessity been a rational process, it certainly has not been one where judges have felt free to roam where unguided speculation might take them. The balance of which I speak is the balance struck by this 253 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 country, having regard to what history teaches are the traditions from which it developed as well as the traditions from which it broke. That tradition is a living thing. A decision of this Court which radically departs from it could not long survive, while a decision which builds on what has survived is likely to be sound. No formula could serve as a substitute, in this area, for judgment and restraint.” [. . .] Men and women of good conscience can disagree, and we suppose some always shall disagree, about the profound moral and spiritual implications of terminating a pregnancy, even in its earliest stage. Some of us as individuals find abortion offensive to our most basic principles of morality, but that cannot control our decision. Our obligation is to define the liberty of all, not to mandate our own moral code. The underlying constitutional issue is whether the State can resolve these philosophic questions in such a definitive way that a woman lacks all choice in the matter, except perhaps in those rare circumstances in which the pregnancy is itself a danger to her own life or health, or is the result of rape or incest. It is conventional constitutional doctrine that where reasonable people disagree the government can adopt one position or the other. That theorem, however, assumes a state of affairs in which the choice does not intrude upon a protected liberty. Thus, while some people might disagree about whether or not the flag should be saluted, or disagree about the proposition that it may not be defiled, we have ruled that a State may not compel or enforce one view or the other.. Our law affords constitutional protection to personal decisions relating to marriage, procreation, contraception, 254 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 family relationships, child rearing, and education. Our cases recognize “the right of the individual, married or single, to be free from unwarranted governmental intrusion into matters so fundamentally affecting a person as the decision whether to bear or beget a child.” Our precedents “have respected the private realm of family life which the state cannot enter.” These matters, involving the most intimate and personal choices a person may make in a lifetime, choices central to personal dignity and autonomy, are central to the liberty protected by the Fourteenth Amendment. At the heart of liberty is the right to define one’s own concept of existence, of meaning, of the universe, and of the mystery of human life. Beliefs about these matters could not define the attributes of personhood were they formed under compulsion of the State. These considerations begin our analysis of the woman’s interest in terminating her pregnancy but cannot end it, for this reason: though the abortion decision may originate within the zone of conscience and belief, it is more than a philosophic exercise. Abortion is a unique act. It is an act fraught with consequences for others: for the woman who must live with the implications of her decision; for the persons who perform and assist in the procedure; for the spouse, family, and society which must confront the knowledge that these procedures exist, procedures some deem nothing short of an act of violence against innocent human life; and, depending on one’s beliefs, for the life or potential life that is aborted. Though abortion is conduct, it does not follow that the State is entitled to proscribe it in all instances. That is because the liberty of the woman is at stake in a sense unique to the human condition and so unique to the law. The mother who carries a child to full term is subject to anxieties, to physical 255 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 constraints, to pain that only she must bear. That these sacrifices have from the beginning of the human race been endured by woman with a pride that ennobles her in the eyes of others and gives to the infant a bond of love cannot alone be grounds for the State to insist she make the sacrifice. Her suffering is too intimate and personal for the State to insist, without more, upon its own vision of the woman’s role, however dominant that vision has been in the course of our history and our culture. The destiny of the woman must be shaped to a large extent on her own conception of her spiritual imperatives and her place in society. It should be recognized, moreover, that in some critical respects the abortion decision is of the same character as the decision to use contraception, to which Griswold v. Connecticut, Eisenstadt v. Baird, and Carey v. Population Services International afford constitutional protection. We have no doubt as to the correctness of those decisions. They support the reasoning in Roe relating to the woman’s liberty because they involve personal decisions concerning not only the meaning of procreation but also human responsibility and respect for it. As with abortion, reasonable people will have differences of opinion about these matters. One view is based on such reverence for the wonder of creation that any pregnancy ought to be welcomed and carried to full term no matter how difficult it will be to provide for the child and ensure its wellbeing. Another is that the inability to provide for the nurture and care of the infant is a cruelty to the child and an anguish to the parent. These are intimate views with infinite variations, and their deep, personal character underlay our decisions in Griswold, Eisenstadt, and Carey. The same concerns are present when the woman confronts the reality that, 256 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 perhaps despite her attempts to avoid it, she has become pregnant. It was this dimension of personal liberty that Roe sought to protect, and its holding invoked the reasoning and the tradition of the precedents we have discussed, granting protection to substantive liberties of the person. Roe was, of course, an extension of those cases and, as the decision itself indicated, the separate States could act in some degree to further their own legitimate interests in protecting prenatal life. The extent to which the legislatures of the States might act to outweigh the interests of the woman in choosing to terminate her pregnancy was a subject of debate both in Roe itself and in decisions following it. While we appreciate the weight of the arguments made on behalf of the State in the cases before us, arguments which in their ultimate formulation conclude that Roe should be overruled, the reservations any of us may have in reaffirming the central holding of Roe are outweighed by the explication of individual liberty we have given combined with the force of stare decisis. We turn now to that doctrine. III A The obligation to follow precedent begins with necessity, and a contrary necessity marks its outer limit. With Cardozo, we recognize that no judicial system could do society’s work if it eyed each issue afresh in every case that raised it. See B. Cardozo, The Nature of the Judicial Process 149 (1921). Indeed, the very concept of the rule of law underlying our own 257 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 Constitution requires such continuity over time that a respect for precedent is, by definition, indispensable. See Powell, stare decisis and Judicial Restraint, 1991 Journal of Supreme Court History 13, 16. At the other extreme, a different necessity would make itself felt if a prior judicial ruling should come to be seen so clearly as error that its enforcement was for that very reason doomed. Even when the decision to overrule a prior case is not, as in the rare, latter instance, virtually foreordained, it is common wisdom that the rule of stare decisis is not an “inexorable command,” and certainly it is not such in every constitutional case…. Rather, when this Court reexamines a prior holding, its judgment is customarily informed by a series of prudential and pragmatic considerations designed to test the consistency of overruling a prior decision with the ideal of the rule of law, and to gauge the respective costs of reaffirming and overruling a prior case. Thus, for example, we may ask whether the rule has proven to be intolerable simply in defying practical workability…; whether the rule is subject to a kind of reliance that would lend a special hardship to the consequences of overruling and add inequity to the cost of repudiation…; whether related principles of law have so far developed as to have left the old rule no more than a remnant of abandoned doctrine…; or whether facts have so changed, or come to be seen so differently, as to have robbed the old rule of significant application or justification…. So in this case we may enquire whether Roe’s central rule has been found unworkable; whether the rule’s limitation on state power could be removed without serious inequity to those who have relied upon it or significant damage to the stability of the society governed by it; whether the law’s 258 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 growth in the intervening years has left Roe’s central rule a doctrinal anachronism discounted by society; and whether Roe’s premises of fact have so far changed in the ensuing two decades as to render its central holding somehow irrelevant or unjustifiable in dealing with the issue it addressed. 1 Although Roe has engendered opposition, it has in no sense proven “unworkable,” . . . representing as it does a simple limitation beyond which a state law is unenforceable. While Roe has, of course, required judicial assessment of state laws affecting the exercise of the choice guaranteed against government infringement, and although the need for such review will remain as a consequence of today’s decision, the required determinations fall within judicial competence. 2 The inquiry into reliance counts the cost of a rule’s repudiation as it would fall on those who have relied reasonably on the rule’s continued application. Since the classic case for weighing reliance heavily in favor of following the earlier rule occurs in the commercial context . . . where advance planning of great precision is most obviously a necessity, it is no cause for surprise that some would find no reliance worthy of consideration in support of Roe. While neither respondents nor their amici in so many words deny that the abortion right invites some reliance prior to its actual exercise, one can readily imagine an argument stressing the dissimilarity of this case to one involving property or contract. Abortion is customarily chosen as an unplanned response to the consequence of unplanned activity or to the 259 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 failure of conventional birth control, and except on the assumption that no intercourse would have occurred but for Roe‘s holding, such behavior may appear to justify no reliance claim. Even if reliance could be claimed on that unrealistic assumption, the argument might run, any reliance interest would be de minimis. This argument would be premised on the hypothesis that reproductive planning could take virtually immediate account of any sudden restoration of state authority to ban abortions. To eliminate the issue of reliance that easily, however, one would need to limit cognizable reliance to specific instances of sexual activity. But to do this would be simply to refuse to face the fact that for two decades of economic and social developments, people have organized intimate relationships and made choices that define their views of themselves and their places in society, in reliance on the availability of abortion in the event that contraception should fail. The ability of women to participate equally in the economic and social life of the Nation has been facilitated by their ability to control their reproductive lives. The Constitution serves human values, and while the effect of reliance on Roe cannot be exactly measured, neither can the certain cost of overruling Roe for people who have ordered their thinking and living around that case be dismissed. 3 [Justice O’Connor discusses how the “liberty” prong of the Roe analysis allows for the debate to be tailored over time based on the evolution of the States’ interests over time.] 260 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 4 [Justice O’Connor discusses how, despite some changes in the factual assumption in Roe, those changed assumptions do not affect the legal reasoning and validity of the Roe holding.] 5 The sum of the precedential enquiry to this point shows Roe’s underpinnings unweakened in any way affecting its central holding. While it has engendered disapproval, it has not been unworkable. An entire generation has come of age free to assume Roe‘s concept of liberty in defining the capacity of women to act in society, and to make reproductive decisions; no erosion of principle going to liberty or personal autonomy has left Roe’s central holding a doctrinal remnant; Roe portends no developments at odds with other precedent for the analysis of personal liberty; and no changes of fact have rendered viability more or less appropriate as the point at which the balance of interests tips. Within the bounds of normal stare decisis analysis, then, and subject to the considerations on which it customarily turns, the stronger argument is for affirming Roe‘s central holding, with whatever degree of personal reluctance any of us may have, not for overruling it. B [. . .] . . . Because neither the factual underpinnings of Roe‘s central holding nor our understanding of it has changed (and because no other indication of weakened precedent has been shown), the Court could not pretend to be reexamining the prior law with any justification beyond a present doctrinal 261 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 disposition to come out differently from the Court of 1973. To overrule prior law for no other reason than that would run counter to the view repeated in our cases, that a decision to overrule should rest on some special reason over and above the belief that a prior case was wrongly decided. C [Justice O’Connor discusses the problem of unnecessarily reexamining and overturning controlling precedent—in this case, Roe—without sufficient legal justification for doing so.] The Court’s duty in the present cases is clear. In 1973, it confronted the already-divisive issue of governmental power to limit personal choice to undergo abortion, for which it provided a new resolution based on the due process guaranteed by the Fourteenth Amendment. Whether or not a new social consensus is developing on that issue, its divisiveness is no less today than in 1973, and pressure to overrule the decision, like pressure to retain it, has grown only more intense. A decision to overrule Roe’s essential holding under the existing circumstances would address error, if error there was, at the cost of both profound and unnecessary damage to the Court’s legitimacy, and to the Nation’s commitment to the rule of law. It is therefore imperative to adhere to the essence of Roe’s original decision, and we do so today. IV From what we have said so far it follows that it is a constitutional liberty of the woman to have some freedom to terminate her pregnancy. We conclude that the basic decision 262 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 in Roe was based on a constitutional analysis which we cannot now repudiate. The woman’s liberty is not so unlimited, however, that from the outset the State cannot show its concern for the life of the unborn, and at a later point in fetal development the State’s interest in life has sufficient force so that the right of the woman to terminate the pregnancy can be restricted. That brings us, of course, to the point where much criticism has been directed at Roe, a criticism that always inheres when the Court draws a specific rule from what in the Constitution is but a general standard. We conclude, however, that the urgent claims of the woman to retain the ultimate control over her destiny and her body, claims implicit in the meaning of liberty, require us to perform that function. Liberty must not be extinguished for want of a line that is clear. And it falls to us to give some real substance to the woman’s liberty to determine whether to carry her pregnancy to full term. We conclude the line should be drawn at viability, so that before that time the woman has a right to choose to terminate her pregnancy. We adhere to this principle for two reasons. First, as we have said, is the doctrine of stare decisis. Any judicial act of line-drawing may seem somewhat arbitrary, but Roe was a reasoned statement, elaborated with great care. We have twice reaffirmed it in the face of great opposition. . . . It is that premise which we reaffirm today. The second reason is that the concept of viability, as we noted in Roe, is the time at which there is a realistic possibility of maintaining and nourishing a life outside the womb, so that the independent existence of the second life can in reason and all fairness be the object of state protection that now overrides the rights of the woman. Consistent with other constitutional 263 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 norms, legislatures may draw lines which appear arbitrary without the necessity of offering a justification. But courts may not. We must justify the lines we draw. And there is no line other than viability which is more workable. To be sure, as we have said, there may be some medical developments that affect the precise point of viability [..], but this is an imprecision within tolerable limits given that the medical community and all those who must apply its discoveries will continue to explore the matter. The viability line also has, as a practical matter, an element of fairness. In some broad sense it might be said that a woman who fails to act before viability has consented to the State’s intervention on behalf of the developing child. The woman’s right to terminate her pregnancy before viability is the most central principle of Roe v. Wade. It is a rule of law and a component of liberty we cannot renounce. On the other side of the equation is the interest of the State in the protection of potential life. The Roe Court recognized the State’s “important and legitimate interest in protecting the potentiality of human life.” The weight to be given this state interest, not the strength of the woman’s interest, was the difficult question faced in Roe. We do not need to say whether each of us, had we been Members of the Court when the valuation of the state interest came before it as an original matter, would have concluded, as the Roe Court did, that its weight is insufficient to justify a ban on abortions prior to viability even when it is subject to certain exceptions. The matter is not before us in the first instance, and coming as it does after nearly 20 years of litigation in Roe’s wake we are satisfied that the immediate question is not the soundness of Roe’s resolution of the issue, but the precedential force that 264 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 must be accorded to its holding. And we have concluded that the essential holding of Roe should be reaffirmed. Yet it must be remembered that Roe v. Wade speaks with clarity in establishing not only the woman’s liberty but also the State’s “important and legitimate interest in potential life.” That portion of the decision in Roe has been given too little acknowledgment and implementation by the Court in its subsequent cases. Those cases decided that any regulation touching upon the abortion decision must survive strict scrutiny, to be sustained only if drawn in narrow terms to further a compelling state interest. Not all of the cases decided under that formulation can be reconciled with the holding in Roe itself that the State has legitimate interests in the health of the woman and in protecting the potential life within her. In resolving this tension, we choose to rely upon Roe, as against the later cases. Roe established a trimester framework to govern abortion regulations. Under this elaborate but rigid construct, almost no regulation at all is permitted during the first trimester of pregnancy; regulations designed to protect the woman’s health, but not to further the State’s interest in potential life, are permitted during the second trimester; and during the third trimester, when the fetus is viable, prohibitions are permitted provided the life or health of the mother is not at stake. . . . The trimester framework no doubt was erected to ensure that the woman’s right to choose not become so subordinate to the State’s interest in promoting fetal life that her choice exists in theory but not in fact. We do not agree, however, that the trimester approach is necessary to accomplish this objective. A framework of this rigidity was unnecessary and 265 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 in its later interpretation sometimes contradicted the State’s permissible exercise of its powers. Though the woman has a right to choose to terminate or continue her pregnancy before viability, it does not at all follow that the State is prohibited from taking steps to ensure that this choice is thoughtful and informed. Even in the earliest stages of pregnancy, the State may enact rules and regulations designed to encourage her to know that there are philosophic and social arguments of great weight that can be brought to bear in favor of continuing the pregnancy to full term and that there are procedures and institutions to allow adoption of unwanted children as well as a certain degree of state assistance if the mother chooses to raise the child herself. “ ‘[T]he Constitution does not forbid a State or city, pursuant to democratic processes, from expressing a preference for normal childbirth.’ ” It follows that States are free to enact laws to provide a reasonable framework for a woman to make a decision that has such profound and lasting meaning. This, too, we find consistent with Roe’ s central premises, and indeed the inevitable consequence of our holding that the State has an interest in protecting the life of the unborn. [Justice O’Connor discusses why the trimester framework should be abandoned. She focuses on the fact that its rigid application is anathema to the sliding scale on which the States’ legitimate interest in pre-viable life is balanced against the liberty interests of the mother.] [. . .] . . . Numerous forms of state regulation might have the incidental effect of increasing the cost or decreasing the availability of medical care, whether for abortion or any other medical procedure. The fact that a law which serves a valid 266 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 purpose, one not designed to strike at the right itself, has the incidental effect of making it more difficult or more expensive to procure an abortion cannot be enough to invalidate it. Only where state regulation imposes an undue burden on a woman’s ability to make this decision does the power of the State reach into the heart of the liberty protected by the Due Process Clause. [. . .] These considerations of the nature of the abortion right illustrate that it is an overstatement to describe it as a right to decide whether to have an abortion “without interference from the State.” All abortion regulations interfere to some degree with a woman’s ability to decide whether to terminate her pregnancy. It is, as a consequence, not surprising that despite the protestations contained in the original Roe opinion to the effect that the Court was not recognizing an absolute right, . . . the Court’s experience applying the trimester framework has led to the striking down of some abortion regulations which in no real sense deprived women of the ultimate decision. Those decisions went too far because the right recognized by Roe is a right “to be free from unwarranted governmental intrusion into matters so fundamentally affecting a person as the decision whether to bear or beget a child.” Not all governmental intrusion is of necessity unwarranted; and that brings us to the other basic flaw in the trimester framework: even in Roe’s terms, in practice it undervalues the State’s interest in the potential life within the woman. [. . .] The very notion that the State has a substantial interest in potential life leads to the conclusion that not all regulations 267 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 must be deemed unwarranted. Not all burdens on the right to decide whether to terminate a pregnancy will be undue. In our view, the undue burden standard is the appropriate means of reconciling the State’s interest with the woman’s constitutionally protected liberty. [. . .] A finding of an undue burden is a shorthand for the conclusion that a state regulation has the purpose or effect of placing a substantial obstacle in the path of a woman seeking an abortion of a nonviable fetus. A statute with this purpose is invalid because the means chosen by the State to further the interest in potential life must be calculated to inform the woman’s free choice, not hinder it. And a statute which, while furthering the interest in potential life or some other valid state interest, has the effect of placing a substantial obstacle in the path of a woman’s choice cannot be considered a permissible means of serving its legitimate ends. To the extent that the opinions of the Court or of individual Justices use the undue burden standard in a manner that is inconsistent with this analysis, we set out what in our view should be the controlling standard. In our considered judgment, an undue burden is an unconstitutional burden. Understood another way, we answer the question, left open in previous opinions discussing the undue burden formulation, whether a law designed to further the State’s interest in fetal life which imposes an undue burden on the woman’s decision before fetal viability could be constitutional. The answer is no. Some guiding principles should emerge. What is at stake is the woman’s right to make the ultimate decision, not a right to be insulated from all others in doing so. Regulations which do no more than create a structural mechanism by which the 268 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 State, or the parent or guardian of a minor, may express profound respect for the life of the unborn are permitted, if they are not a substantial obstacle to the woman’s exercise of the right to choose. Unless it has that effect on her right of choice, a state measure designed to persuade her to choose childbirth over abortion will be upheld if reasonably related to that goal. Regulations designed to foster the health of a woman seeking an abortion are valid if they do not constitute an undue burden. Even when jurists reason from shared premises, some disagreement is inevitable. That is to be expected in the application of any legal standard which must accommodate life’s complexity. We do not expect it to be otherwise with respect to the undue burden standard. We give this summary: (a) To protect the central right recognized by Roe v. Wade while at the same time accommodating the State’s profound interest in potential life, we will employ the undue burden analysis as explained in this opinion. An undue burden exists, and therefore a provision of law is invalid, if its purpose or effect is to place a substantial obstacle in the path of a woman seeking an abortion before the fetus attains viability. (b) We reject the rigid trimester framework of Roe v. Wade. To promote the State’s profound interest in potential life, throughout pregnancy the State may take measures to ensure that the woman’s choice is informed, and measures designed to advance this interest will not be invalidated as long as their purpose is to persuade the woman to choose childbirth over abortion. These measures must not be an undue burden on the right. (c) As with any medical procedure, the State may enact regulations to further the health or safety of a woman seeking 269 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 an abortion. Unnecessary health regulations that have the purpose or effect of presenting a substantial obstacle to a woman seeking an abortion impose an undue burden on the right. (d) Our adoption of the undue burden analysis does not disturb the central holding of Roe v. Wade, and we reaffirm that holding. Regardless of whether exceptions are made for particular circumstances, a State may not prohibit any woman from making the ultimate decision to terminate her pregnancy before viability. (e) We also reaffirm Roe’s holding that “subsequent to viability, the State in promoting its interest in the potentiality of human life may, if it chooses, regulate, and even proscribe, abortion except where it is necessary, in appropriate medical judgment, for the preservation of the life or health of the mother.” These principles control our assessment of the Pennsylvania statute, and we now turn to the issue of the validity of its challenged provisions. V The Court of Appeals applied what it believed to be the undue burden standard and upheld each of the provisions except for the husband notification requirement. We agree generally with this conclusion, but refine the undue burden analysis in accordance with the principles articulated above. We now consider the separate statutory sections at issue. 270 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 A [Justice O’Connor analyzes the “medical emergency” provision, which petitioner’s challenged as too narrow. Because there are three exceptions in the case of extreme medical emergencies, O’Connor states that the burden is not undue, even if situations involving significant complications are not encompassed.] B We next consider the informed consent requirement. [. . .] To the extent [that prior cases] find a constitutional violation when the government requires, as it does here, the giving of truthful, nonmisleading information about the nature of the procedure, the attendant health risks and those of childbirth, and the “probable gestational age” of the fetus, those cases go too far, are inconsistent with Roe’s acknowledgment of an important interest in potential life, and are overruled. [Prior decisions] recognize a substantial government interest justifying a requirement that a woman be apprised of the health risks of abortion and childbirth. It cannot be questioned that psychological well-being is a facet of health. Nor can it be doubted that most women considering an abortion would deem the impact on the fetus relevant, if not dispositive, to the decision. In attempting to ensure that a woman apprehend the full consequences of her decision, the State furthers the legitimate purpose of reducing the risk that a woman may elect an abortion, only to discover later, with devastating psychological consequences, that her decision was not fully informed. If the information the State requires to be 271 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 made available to the woman is truthful and not misleading, the requirement may be permissible. We also see no reason why the State may not require doctors to inform a woman seeking an abortion of the availability of materials relating to the consequences to the fetus, even when those consequences have no direct relation to her health. An example illustrates the point. We would think it constitutional for the State to require that in order for there to be informed consent to a kidney transplant operation the recipient must be supplied with information about risks to the donor as well as risks to himself or herself. A requirement that the physician make available information similar to that mandated by the statute here was described in Thornburgh as “an outright attempt to wedge the Commonwealth’s message discouraging abortion into the privacy of the informedconsent dialogue between the woman and her physician.” We conclude, however, that informed choice need not be defined in such narrow terms that all considerations of the effect on the fetus are made irrelevant. As we have made clear, we depart from the holdings [of prior cases] to the extent that we permit a State to further its legitimate goal of protecting the life of the unborn by enacting legislation aimed at ensuring a decision that is mature and informed, even when in so doing the State expresses a preference for childbirth over abortion. In short, requiring that the woman be informed of the availability of information relating to fetal development and the assistance available should she decide to carry the pregnancy to full term is a reasonable measure to ensure an informed choice, one which might cause the woman to choose childbirth over abortion. This requirement cannot be 272 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 considered a substantial obstacle to obtaining an abortion, and, it follows, there is no undue burden. [The Court dismisses the argument that the “informed consent” provisions act as a “straightjacket” by intruding into the doctor-patient relationship. That the doctor must give information to a women seeking an abortion is no different than any other medical procedure, and the law allows exceptions where the doctor can demonstrate that it is in the patient’s medical (mental and physical) interests not to disclose such information.] All that is left of petitioners’ argument is an asserted First Amendment right of a physician not to provide information about the risks of abortion, and childbirth, in a manner mandated by the State. To be sure, the physician’s First Amendment rights not to speak are implicated . . . but only as part of the practice of medicine, subject to reasonable licensing and regulation by the State . . . .We see no constitutional infirmity in the requirement that the physician provide the information mandated by the State here. [Justice O’Connor examines the remaining “informed consent” arguments and finds that none of them amount to undue burdens.] C Section 3209 of Pennsylvania’s abortion law provides, except in cases of medical emergency, that no physician shall perform an abortion on a married woman without receiving a signed statement from the woman that she has notified her spouse that she is about to undergo an abortion. The woman has the 273 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 option of providing an alternative signed statement certifying that her husband is not the man who impregnated her; that her husband could not be located; that the pregnancy is the result of spousal sexual assault which she has reported; or that the woman believes that notifying her husband will cause him or someone else to inflict bodily injury upon her. A physician who performs an abortion on a married woman without receiving the appropriate signed statement will have his or her license revoked, and is liable to the husband for damages. [. . .] This information and the District Court’s findings reinforce what common sense would suggest. In well-functioning marriages, spouses discuss important intimate decisions such as whether to bear a child. But there are millions of women in this country who are the victims of regular physical and psychological abuse at the hands of their husbands. Should these women become pregnant, they may have very good reasons for not wishing to inform their husbands of their decision to obtain an abortion. Many may have justifiable fears of physical abuse, but may be no less fearful of the consequences of reporting prior abuse to the Commonwealth of Pennsylvania. Many may have a reasonable fear that notifying their husbands will provoke further instances of child abuse; these women are not exempt from § 3209’s notification requirement. Many may fear devastating forms of psychological abuse from their husbands, including verbal harassment, threats of future violence, the destruction of possessions, physical confinement to the home, the withdrawal of financial support, or the disclosure of the abortion to family and friends. These methods of 274 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 psychological abuse may act as even more of a deterrent to notification than the possibility of physical violence, but women who are the victims of the abuse are not exempt from § 3209’s notification requirement. And many women who are pregnant as a result of sexual assaults by their husbands will be unable to avail themselves of the exception for spousal sexual assault, § 3209(b)(3), because the exception requires that the woman have notified law enforcement authorities within 90 days of the assault, and her husband will be notified of her report once an investigation begins, § 3128(c). If anything in this field is certain, it is that victims of spousal sexual assault are extremely reluctant to report the abuse to the government; hence, a great many spousal rape victims will not be exempt from the notification requirement imposed by § 3209. The spousal notification requirement is thus likely to prevent a significant number of women from obtaining an abortion. It does not merely make abortions a little more difficult or expensive to obtain; for many women, it will impose a substantial obstacle. We must not blind ourselves to the fact that the significant number of women who fear for their safety and the safety of their children are likely to be deterred from procuring an abortion as surely as if the Commonwealth had outlawed abortion in all cases. [. . .] We recognize that a husband has a “deep and proper concern and interest . . . in his wife’s pregnancy and in the growth and development of the fetus she is carrying.” With regard to the children he has fathered and raised, the Court has recognized his “cognizable and substantial” interest in their custody. If these cases concerned a State’s ability to 275 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 require the mother to notify the father before taking some action with respect to a living child raised by both, therefore, it would be reasonable to conclude as a general matter that the father’s interest in the welfare of the child and the mother’s interest are equal. Before birth, however, the issue takes on a very different cast. It is an inescapable biological fact that state regulation with respect to the child a woman is carrying will have a far greater impact on the mother’s liberty than on the father’s. The effect of state regulation on a woman’s protected liberty is doubly deserving of scrutiny in such a case, as the State has touched not only upon the private sphere of the family but upon the very bodily integrity of the pregnant woman. The Court has held that “when the wife and the husband disagree on this decision, the view of only one of the two marriage partners can prevail. Inasmuch as it is the woman who physically bears the child and who is the more directly and immediately affected by the pregnancy, as between the two, the balance weighs in her favor.” This conclusion rests upon the basic nature of marriage and the nature of our Constitution: “[T]he marital couple is not an independent entity with a mind and heart of its own, but an association of two individuals each with a separate intellectual and emotional makeup. If the right of privacy means anything, it is the right of the individual, married or single, to be free from unwarranted governmental intrusion into matters so fundamentally affecting a person as the decision whether to bear or beget a child.” The Constitution protects individuals, men and women alike, from unjustified state interference, even when that interference is enacted into law for the benefit of their spouses. 276 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 [. . .] The husband’s interest in the life of the child his wife is carrying does not permit the State to empower him with this troubling degree of authority over his wife. The contrary view leads to consequences reminiscent of the common law. A husband has no enforceable right to require a wife to advise him before she exercises her personal choices. If a husband’s interest in the potential life of the child outweighs a wife’s liberty, the State could require a married woman to notify her husband before she uses a postfertilization contraceptive. Perhaps next in line would be a statute requiring pregnant married women to notify their husbands before engaging in conduct causing risks to the fetus. After all, if the husband’s interest in the fetus’ safety is a sufficient predicate for state regulation, the State could reasonably conclude that pregnant wives should notify their husbands before drinking alcohol or smoking. Perhaps married women should notify their husbands before using contraceptives or before undergoing any type of surgery that may have complications affecting the husband’s interest in his wife’s reproductive organs. And if a husband’s interest justifies notice in any of these cases, one might reasonably argue that it justifies exactly what the Danforth Court held it did not justify—a requirement of the husband’s consent as well. A State may not give to a man the kind of dominion over his wife that parents exercise over their children. Section 3209 embodies a view of marriage consonant with the common-law status of married women but repugnant to our present understanding of marriage and of the nature of the rights secured by the Constitution. Women do not lose their constitutionally protected liberty when they marry. The 277 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 Constitution protects all individuals, male or female, married or unmarried, from the abuse of governmental power, even where that power is employed for the supposed benefit of a member of the individual’s family. These considerations confirm our conclusion that § 3209 is invalid. D [The reporting requirement for minors is upheld.] E [While reporting requirements to the state can be constitutional, the subsection of the statute that requires an explanation relating to the notification of the husband is struck down as imposing an undue burden for the reasons discussed in Part C.] VI Our Constitution is a covenant running from the first generation of Americans to us and then to future generations. It is a coherent succession. Each generation must learn anew that the Constitution’s written terms embody ideas and aspirations that must survive more ages than one. We accept our responsibility not to retreat from interpreting the full meaning of the covenant in light of all of our precedents. We invoke it once again to define the freedom guaranteed by the Constitution’s own promise, the promise of liberty. *** The judgment in No. 91–902 is affirmed. The judgment in No. 91–744 is affirmed in part and reversed in part, and the 278 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 case is remanded for proceedings consistent with this opinion, including consideration of the question of severability. It is so ordered. Justice STEVENS, concurring in part and dissenting in part. The portions of the Court’s opinion that I have joined are more important than those with which I disagree. I shall therefore first comment on significant areas of agreement, and then explain the limited character of my disagreement. I The Court is unquestionably correct in concluding that the doctrine of stare decisis has controlling significance in a case of this kind, notwithstanding an individual Justice’s concerns about the merits.1 The central holding of Roe v. Wade . . . has been a “part of our law” for almost two decades. It was a natural sequel to the protection of individual liberty established in Griswold v. Connecticut . . . .The societal costs of overruling Roe at this late date would be enormous. Roe is an integral part of a correct understanding of both the concept of liberty and the basic equality of men and women. Stare decisis also provides a sufficient basis for my agreement with the joint opinion’s reaffirmation of Roe’s postviability analysis. Specifically, I accept the proposition that “[i]f the State is interested in protecting fetal life after viability, it may go so far as to proscribe abortion during that period, except 279 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 when it is necessary to preserve the life or health of the mother.” I also accept what is implicit in the Court’s analysis, namely, a reaffirmation of Roe’s explanation of why the State’s obligation to protect the life or health of the mother must take precedence over any duty to the unborn. The Court in Roe carefully considered, and rejected, the State’s argument “that the fetus is a ‘person’ within the language and meaning of the Fourteenth Amendment.” After analyzing the usage of “person” in the Constitution, the Court concluded that that word “has application only postnatally.” Commenting on the contingent property interests of the unborn that are generally represented by guardians ad litem, the Court noted: “Perfection of the interests involved, again, has generally been contingent upon live birth. In short, the unborn have never been recognized in the law as persons in the whole sense.” Accordingly, an abortion is not “the termination of life entitled to Fourteenth Amendment protection.” From this holding, there was no dissent . . .; indeed, no Member of the Court has ever questioned this fundamental proposition. Thus, as a matter of federal constitutional law, a developing organism that is not yet a “person” does not have what is sometimes described as a “right to life.” This has been and, by the Court’s holding today, remains a fundamental premise of our constitutional law governing reproductive autonomy. II My disagreement with the joint opinion begins with its understanding of the trimester framework established in Roe. Contrary to the suggestion of the joint opinion, . . . it is not a 280 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 “contradiction” to recognize that the State may have a legitimate interest in potential human life and, at the same time, to conclude that that interest does not justify the regulation of abortion before viability (although other interests, such as maternal health, may). The fact that the State’s interest is legitimate does not tell us when, if ever, that interest outweighs the pregnant woman’s interest in personal liberty. It is appropriate, therefore, to consider more carefully the nature of the interests at stake. First, it is clear that, in order to be legitimate, the State’s interest must be secular; consistent with the First Amendment the State may not promote a theological or sectarian interest. Moreover, as discussed above, the state interest in potential human life is not an interest in loco parentis, for the fetus is not a person. Identifying the State’s interests—which the States rarely articulate with any precision—makes clear that the interest in protecting potential life is not grounded in the Constitution. It is, instead, an indirect interest supported by both humanitarian and pragmatic concerns. Many of our citizens believe that any abortion reflects an unacceptable disrespect for potential human life and that the performance of more than a million abortions each year is intolerable; many find third-trimester abortions performed when the fetus is approaching personhood particularly offensive. The State has a legitimate interest in minimizing such offense. The State may also have a broader interest in expanding the population, 3 believing society would benefit from the services of additional productive citizens—or that the potential human lives might include the occasional Mozart or Curie. These are 281 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 the kinds of concerns that comprise the State’s interest in potential human life. In counterpoise is the woman’s constitutional interest in liberty. One aspect of this liberty is a right to bodily integrity, a right to control one’s person. This right is neutral on the question of abortion: The Constitution would be equally offended by an absolute requirement that all women undergo abortions as by an absolute prohibition on abortions. “Our whole constitutional heritage rebels at the thought of giving government the power to control men’s minds.” The same holds true for the power to control women’s bodies. The woman’s constitutional liberty interest also involves her freedom to decide matters of the highest privacy and the most personal nature. A woman considering abortion faces “a difficult choice having serious and personal consequences of major importance to her own future—perhaps to the salvation of her own immortal soul.” The authority to make such traumatic and yet empowering decisions is an element of basic human dignity. As the joint opinion so eloquently demonstrates, a woman’s decision to terminate her pregnancy is nothing less than a matter of conscience. Weighing the State’s interest in potential life and the woman’s liberty interest, I agree with the joint opinion that the State may “ ‘ “expres[s] a preference for normal childbirth,” ’ ” that the State may take steps to ensure that a woman’s choice “is thoughtful and informed,” and that “States are free to enact laws to provide a reasonable framework for a woman to make a decision that has such profound and lasting meaning.” . . . Serious questions arise, however, when a State attempts to “persuade the woman to choose childbirth over abortion.” . . . Decisional autonomy must limit the State’s 282 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 power to inject into a woman’s most personal deliberations its own views of what is best. The State may promote its preferences by funding childbirth, by creating and maintaining alternatives to abortion, and by espousing the virtues of family; but it must respect the individual’s freedom to make such judgments. This theme runs throughout our decisions concerning reproductive freedom. In general, Roe’s requirement that restrictions on abortions before viability be justified by the State’s interest in maternal health has prevented States from interjecting regulations designed to influence a woman’s decision. Thus, we have upheld regulations of abortion that are not efforts to sway or direct a woman’s choice, but rather are efforts to enhance the deliberative quality of that decision or are neutral regulations on the health aspects of her decision. We have, for example, upheld regulations requiring written informed consent . . .; limited recordkeeping and reporting, . . .; and pathology reports . . .; as well as various licensing and qualification provisions,. . . . Conversely, we have consistently rejected state efforts to prejudice a woman’s choice, either by limiting the information available to her . . . or by “requir[ing] the delivery of information designed ‘to influence the woman’s informed choice between abortion or childbirth.’ ” In my opinion, the principles established in this long line of cases and the wisdom reflected in Justice Powell’s opinion for the Court in Akron (and followed by the Court just six years ago in Thornburgh) should govern our decision today. Under these principles, Pa.Cons.Stat. §§ 3205(a)(2)(i)–(iii) (1990) of the Pennsylvania statute are unconstitutional. Those sections require a physician or counselor to provide the 283 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 woman with a range of materials clearly designed to persuade her to choose not to undergo the abortion. While the Commonwealth is free, pursuant to § 3208 of the Pennsylvania law, to produce and disseminate such material, the Commonwealth may not inject such information into the woman’s deliberations just as she is weighing such an important choice. Under this same analysis, §§ 3205(a)(1)(i) and (iii) of the Pennsylvania statute are constitutional. Those sections, which require the physician to inform a woman of the nature and risks of the abortion procedure and the medical risks of carrying to term, are neutral requirements comparable to those imposed in other medical procedures. Those sections indicate no effort by the Commonwealth to influence the woman’s choice in any way. If anything, such requirements enhance, rather than skew, the woman’s decisionmaking. III The 24–hour waiting period required by §§ 3205(a)(1)–(2) of the Pennsylvania statute raises even more serious concerns. Such a requirement arguably furthers the Commonwealth’s interests in two ways, neither of which is constitutionally permissible. First, it may be argued that the 24–hour delay is justified by the mere fact that it is likely to reduce the number of abortions, thus furthering the Commonwealth’s interest in potential life. But such an argument would justify any form of coercion that placed an obstacle in the woman’s path. The Commonwealth cannot further its interests by simply wearing 284 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 down the ability of the pregnant woman to exercise her constitutional right. Second, it can more reasonably be argued that the 24–hour delay furthers the Commonwealth’s interest in ensuring that the woman’s decision is informed and thoughtful. But there is no evidence that the mandated delay benefits women or that it is necessary to enable the physician to convey any relevant information to the patient. The mandatory delay thus appears to rest on outmoded and unacceptable assumptions about the decisionmaking capacity of women. While there are wellestablished and consistently maintained reasons for the Commonwealth to view with skepticism the ability of minors to make decisions, . . . none of those reasons applies to an adult woman’s decisionmaking ability. Just as we have left behind the belief that a woman must consult her husband before undertaking serious matters, . . . so we must reject the notion that a woman is less capable of deciding matters of gravity. In the alternative, the delay requirement may be premised on the belief that the decision to terminate a pregnancy is presumptively wrong. This premise is illegitimate. Those who disagree vehemently about the legality and morality of abortion agree about one thing: The decision to terminate a pregnancy is profound and difficult. No person undertakes such a decision lightly—and States may not presume that a woman has failed to reflect adequately merely because her conclusion differs from the State’s preference. A woman who has, in the privacy of her thoughts and conscience, weighed the options and made her decision cannot be forced to reconsider all, simply because the State believes she has come to the wrong conclusion. 285 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 Part of the constitutional liberty to choose is the equal dignity to which each of us is entitled. A woman who decides to terminate her pregnancy is entitled to the same respect as a woman who decides to carry the fetus to term. The mandatory waiting period denies women that equal respect. IV In my opinion, a correct application of the “undue burden” standard leads to the same conclusion concerning the constitutionality of these requirements. A state-imposed burden on the exercise of a constitutional right is measured both by its effects and by its character: A burden may be “undue” either because the burden is too severe or because it lacks a legitimate, rational justification.6 The 24–hour delay requirement fails both parts of this test. The findings of the District Court establish the severity of the burden that the 24–hour delay imposes on many pregnant women. Yet even in those cases in which the delay is not especially onerous, it is, in my opinion, “undue” because there is no evidence that such a delay serves a useful and legitimate purpose. As indicated above, there is no legitimate reason to require a woman who has agonized over her decision to leave the clinic or hospital and return again another day. While a general requirement that a physician notify her patients about the risks of a proposed medical procedure is appropriate, a rigid requirement that all patients wait 24 hours or (what is true in practice) much longer to evaluate the significance of information that is either common knowledge or irrelevant is an irrational and, therefore, “undue” burden. 286 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 The counseling provisions are similarly infirm. Whenever government commands private citizens to speak or to listen, careful review of the justification for that command is particularly appropriate. In these cases, the Pennsylvania statute directs that counselors provide women seeking abortions with information concerning alternatives to abortion, the availability of medical assistance benefits, and the possibility of child-support payments. §§ 3205(a)(2)(i)– (iii). The statute requires that this information be given to all women seeking abortions, including those for whom such information is clearly useless, such as those who are married, those who have undergone the procedure in the past and are fully aware of the options, and those who are fully convinced that abortion is their only reasonable option. Moreover, the statute requires physicians to inform all of their patients of “[t]he probable gestational age of the unborn child.” § 3205(a)(1)(ii). This information is of little decisional value in most cases, because 90% of all abortions are performed during the first trimester when fetal age has less relevance than when the fetus nears viability. Nor can the information required by the statute be justified as relevant to any “philosophic” or “social” argument . . . either favoring or disfavoring the abortion decision in a particular case. In light of all of these facts, I conclude that the information requirements in § 3205(a)(1)(ii) and §§ 3205(a)(2)(i)–(iii) do not serve a useful purpose and thus constitute an unnecessary —and therefore undue—burden on the woman’s constitutional liberty to decide to terminate her pregnancy. Accordingly, while I disagree with Parts IV, V–B, and V–D of the joint opinion, I join the remainder of the Court’s opinion. 287 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 [Justice Blackmun’s concurrence in part and dissent in part is omitted.] Chief Justice Rehnquist, concurring in part and dissenting in part. .... We have held that a liberty interest protected under the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment will be deemed fundamental if it is “implicit in the concept of ordered liberty.” Palko v. Connecticut, 302 U. S. 319, 325 (1937). Three years earlier, in Snyder v. Massachusetts, 291 U. S. 97 (1934), we referred to a “principle of justice so rooted in the traditions and conscience of our people as to be ranked as fundamental.” Id., at 105. These expressions are admittedly not precise, but our decisions implementing this notion of “fundamental” rights do not afford any more elaborate basis on which to base such a classification. In construing the phrase “liberty” incorporated in the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment, we have recognized that its meaning extends beyond freedom from physical restraint. In Pierce v. Society of Sisters, 268 U. S. 510 (1925), we held that it included a parent’s right to send a child to private school; in Meyer v. Nebraska, 262 U. S. 390 (1923), we held that it included a right to teach a foreign language in a parochial school. Building on these cases, we have held that the term “liberty” includes a right to marry, Loving v. Virginia, 388 U. S. 1 (1967); a right to procreate, Skinner v. Oklahoma ex 288 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 rel. Williamson, 316 U. S. 535 (1942); and a right to use contraceptives, Griswold v. Connecticut, 381 U. S. 479 (1965); Eisenstadt v. Baird, 405 U. S. 438 (1972). But a reading of these opinions makes clear that they do not endorse any allencompassing “right of privacy.” In Roe v. Wade, the Court recognized a “guarantee of personal privacy” which “is broad enough to encompass a woman’s decision whether or not to terminate her pregnancy.” 410 U. S., at 152-153. We are now of the view that, in terming this right fundamental, the Court in Roe read the earlier opinions upon which it based its decision much too broadly. Unlike marriage, procreation, and contraception, abortion involves the purposeful termination of a potential life. The abortion decision must therefore “be recognized as sui generis, different in kind from the others that the Court has protected under the rubric of personal or family privacy and autonomy.” Thornburgh v. American College of Obstetricians and Gynecologists, supra, at 792 (White, J., dissenting). One cannot ignore the fact that a woman is not isolated in her pregnancy, and that the decision to abort necessarily involves the destruction of a fetus. See Michael H. v. Gerald D., supra, at 124, n. 4 (To look “at the act which is assertedly the subject of a liberty interest in isolation from its effect upon other people [is] like inquiring whether there is a liberty interest in firing a gun where the case at hand happens to involve its discharge into another person’s body”). Nor do the historical traditions of the American people support the view that the right to terminate one’s pregnancy is “fundamental.” The common law which we inherited from England made abortion after “quickening” an offense. At the time of the adoption of the Fourteenth Amendment, statutory 289 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 prohibitions or restrictions on abortion were commonplace; in 1868, at least 28 of the then-37 States and 8 Territories had statutes banning or limiting abortion. J. Mohr, Abortion in America 200 (1978). By the turn of the century virtually every State had a law prohibiting or restricting abortion on its books. By the middle of the present century, a liberalization trend had set in. But 21 of the restrictive abortion laws in effect in 1868 were still in effect in 1973 when Roe was decided, and an overwhelming majority of the States prohibited abortion unless necessary to preserve the life or health of the mother. On this record, it can scarcely be said that any deeply rooted tradition of relatively unrestricted abortion in our history supported the classification of the right to abortion as “fundamental” under the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment. We think, therefore, both in view of this history and of our decided cases dealing with substantive liberty under the Due Process Clause, that the Court was mistaken in Roe when it classified a woman’s decision to terminate her pregnancy as a “fundamental right” that could be abridged only in a manner which withstood “strict scrutiny.” In so concluding, we repeat the observation made in Bowers v. Hardwick, 478 U. S. 186 (1986): Nor are we inclined to take a more expansive view of our authority to discover new fundamental rights imbedded in the Due Process Clause. The Court is most vulnerable and comes nearest to illegitimacy when it deals with judge-made constitutional law having little or no 290 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 cognizable roots in the language or design of the Constitution. Id., at 194. We believe that the sort of constitutionally imposed abortion code of the type illustrated by our decisions following Roe is inconsistent “with the notion of a Constitution cast in general terms, as ours is, and usually speaking in general principles, as ours does.” Webster v. Reproductive Health Services, 492 U. S., at 518 (plurality opinion). The Court in Roe reached too far when it analogized the right to abort a fetus to the rights involved in Pierce, Meyer, Loving, and Griswold, and thereby deemed the right to abortion fundamental. .... Justice SCALIA, with whom THE CHIEF JUSTICE, Justice WHITE, and Justice THOMAS join, concurring in the judgment in part and dissenting in part. The States may, if they wish, permit abortion on demand, but the Constitution does not require them to do so. The permissibility of abortion, and the limitations upon it, are to be resolved like most important questions in our democracy: by citizens trying to persuade one another and then voting. As the Court acknowledges, “where reasonable people disagree the government can adopt one position or the other.” The Court is correct in adding the qualification that this “assumes a state of affairs in which the choice does not intrude upon a protected liberty,” —but the crucial part of that qualification is the penultimate word. A State’s choice between two 291 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 positions on which reasonable people can disagree is constitutional even when (as is often the case) it intrudes upon a “liberty” in the absolute sense. Laws against bigamy, for example—with which entire societies of reasonable people disagree—intrude upon men and women’s liberty to marry and live with one another. But bigamy happens not to be a liberty specially “protected” by the Constitution. That is, quite simply, the issue in these cases: not whether the power of a woman to abort her unborn child is a “liberty” in the absolute sense; or even whether it is a liberty of great importance to many women. Of course it is both. The issue is whether it is a liberty protected by the Constitution of the United States. I am sure it is not. I reach that conclusion not because of anything so exalted as my views concerning the “concept of existence, of meaning, of the universe, and of the mystery of human life.” Rather, I reach it for the same reason I reach the conclusion that bigamy is not constitutionally protected—because of two simple facts: (1) the Constitution says absolutely nothing about it, and (2) the longstanding traditions of American society have permitted it to be legally proscribed. .... The joint opinion frankly concedes that the amorphous concept of “undue burden” has been inconsistently applied by the Members of this Court in the few brief years since that “test” was first explicitly propounded by Justice O'Connor in her dissent in Akron I, 462 U. S. 416 (1983). . . . . Any regulation of abortion that is intended to advance what the joint opinion concedes is the State's “substantial” interest in protecting unborn life will be “calculated [to] hinder” a decision to have an abortion. It thus seems more accurate to 292 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 say that the joint opinion would uphold abortion regulations only if they do not unduly hinder the woman's decision. That, of course, brings us right back to square one: Defining an “undue burden” as an “undue hindrance” (or a “substantial obstacle”) hardly “clarifies” the test. Consciously or not, the joint opinion’s verbal shell game will conceal raw judicial policy choices concerning what is “appropriate” abortion legislation. . . . . Because the portion of the joint opinion adopting and describing the undue burden test provides no more useful guidance than the empty phrases discussed above, one must turn to the 23 pages applying that standard to the present facts for further guidance. . . . . [W]hat is remarkable about the joint opinion’s factintensive analysis is that it does not result in any measurable clarification of the “undue burden” standard. Rather, the approach of the joint opinion is, for the most part, simply to highlight certain facts in the record that apparently strike the three Justices as particularly significant in establishing (or refuting) the existence of an undue burden; after describing these facts, the opinion then simply announces that the provision either does or does not impose a “substantial obstacle” or an “undue burden.” . . . . . . . . Reason finds no refuge in this jurisprudence of confusion. .... [As] THE CHIEF JUSTICE points out, we have been subjected to what the Court calls “ ‘political pressure’ ” by both sides of this issue. Maybe today’s decision not to overrule Roe will be seen as buckling to pressure from that direction. Instead of engaging in the hopeless task of predicting public 293 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 perception—a job not for lawyers but for political campaign managers—the Justices should do what is legally right by asking two questions: (1) Was Roe correctly decided? (2) Has Roe succeeded in producing a settled body of law? If the answer to both questions is no, Roe should undoubtedly be overruled. In truth, I am as distressed as the Court is—and expressed my distress several years ago . . .—about the “political pressure” directed to the Court: the marches, the mail, the protests aimed at inducing us to change our opinions. How upsetting it is, that so many of our citizens (good people, not lawless ones, on both sides of this abortion issue, and on various sides of other issues as well) think that we Justices should properly take into account their views, as though we were engaged not in ascertaining an objective law but in determining some kind of social consensus. The Court would profit, I think, from giving less attention to the fact of this distressing phenomenon, and more attention to the cause of it. That cause permeates today’s opinion: a new mode of constitutional adjudication that relies not upon text and traditional practice to determine the law, but upon what the Court calls “reasoned judgment,” . . . which turns out to be nothing but philosophical predilection and moral intuition. All manner of “liberties,” the Court tells us, inhere in the Constitution and are enforceable by this Court—not just those mentioned in the text or established in the traditions of our society. . . . Why even the Ninth Amendment—which says only that “[t]he enumeration in the Constitution, of certain rights, shall not be construed to deny or disparage others retained by the people”—is, despite our contrary understanding for almost 200 years, a literally boundless 294 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 source of additional, unnamed, unhinted—at “rights,” definable and enforceable by us, through “reasoned judgment.” What makes all this relevant to the bothersome application of “political pressure” against the Court are the twin facts that the American people love democracy and the American people are not fools. As long as this Court thought (and the people thought) that we Justices were doing essentially lawyers’ work up here—reading text and discerning our society’s traditional understanding of that text—the public pretty much left us alone. Texts and traditions are facts to study, not convictions to demonstrate about. But if in reality our process of constitutional adjudication consists primarily of making value judgments; if we can ignore a long and clear tradition clarifying an ambiguous text, as we did, for example, five days ago in declaring unconstitutional invocations and benedictions at public high school graduation ceremonies . . .; if, as I say, our pronouncement of constitutional law rests primarily on value judgments, then a free and intelligent people’s attitude towards us can be expected to be (ought to be) quite different. The people know that their value judgments are quite as good as those taught in any law school —maybe better. If, indeed, the “liberties” protected by the Constitution are, as the Court says, undefined and unbounded, then the people should demonstrate, to protest that we do not implement their values instead of ours. Not only that, but confirmation hearings for new Justices should deteriorate into question-and-answer sessions in which Senators go through a list of their constituents’ most favored and most disfavored alleged constitutional rights, and seek the nominee’s commitment to support or oppose them. Value 295 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 judgments, after all, should be voted on, not dictated; and if our Constitution has somehow accidently committed them to the Supreme Court, at least we can have a sort of plebiscite each time a new nominee to that body is put forward. Justice BLACKMUN not only regards this prospect with equanimity, he solicits it. *** There is a poignant aspect to today’s opinion. Its length, and what might be called its epic tone, suggest that its authors believe they are bringing to an end a troublesome era in the history of our Nation and of our Court. “It is the dimension” of authority, they say, to “cal[l] the contending sides of national controversy to end their national division by accepting a common mandate rooted in the Constitution.” There comes vividly to mind a portrait by Emanuel Leutze that hangs in the Harvard Law School: Roger Brooke Taney, painted in 1859, the 82d year of his life, the 24th of his Chief Justiceship, the second after his opinion in Dred Scott. He is all in black, sitting in a shadowed red armchair, left hand resting upon a pad of paper in his lap, right hand hanging limply, almost lifelessly, beside the inner arm of the chair. He sits facing the viewer and staring straight out. There seems to be on his face, and in his deep-set eyes, an expression of profound sadness and disillusionment. Perhaps he always looked that way, even when dwelling upon the happiest of thoughts. But those of us who know how the lustre of his great Chief Justiceship came to be eclipsed by Dred Scott cannot help believing that he had that case—its already apparent consequences for the Court and its soon-to-beplayed-out consequences for the Nation—burning on his mind. I expect that two years earlier he, too, had thought 296 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 himself “call[ing] the contending sides of national controversy to end their national division by accepting a common mandate rooted in the Constitution.” It is no more realistic for us in this litigation, than it was for him in that, to think that an issue of the sort they both involved—an issue involving life and death, freedom and subjugation—can be “speedily and finally settled” by the Supreme Court, as President James Buchanan in his inaugural address said the issue of slavery in the territories would be. Quite to the contrary, by foreclosing all democratic outlet for the deep passions this issue arouses, by banishing the issue from the political forum that gives all participants, even the losers, the satisfaction of a fair hearing and an honest fight, by continuing the imposition of a rigid national rule instead of allowing for regional differences, the Court merely prolongs and intensifies the anguish. We should get out of this area, where we have no right to be, and where we do neither ourselves nor the country any good by remaining. 297 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 Meeting 9: The Administrative State Review Topics and Questions – Distinguish the elements of the “administrative state,” that is, be able to define what an administrative agency is and how it differs (in form, agenda, and methods) from the President himself, the legislature, and courts. – What is informal rulemaking? What gives agencies the power to make rules? What is the process (at a general level)? – Do the analyses undertaken by agencies tend to accord with any of the theories of justice we studied? Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 – Review and think again about the “controversies” I summarize on pages 7 and 8. – Chevron deference is the phrase for the federal courts’ practice of deferring to an agency’s interpretation of a statute it administers. What does it mean to defer? – Understand the analysis a court performs in a Chevron deference case — what does it do in step 1, and what does it do in step 2? – What is the outline of the Gorsuch critique of Chevron, and what are some counter-arguments? The Administrative State We have so far studied the decisionmaking principles and structure of courts and learned a little about legislative dynamics. Indeed, the basic, grade-school civics model depicts the familiar interplay of the legislative, executive, and judicial branches of government we learned about at the beginning of the course. But this simple picture is not enough to understand, even at a broad level, how the federal government works – or how state governments work. While Congress indeed passes statutes that the Executive Branch is charged with enforcing, the Executive acts through a large number of agencies, offices, and commissions employing about two million people. (Note that this includes the military and postal service.) Within the White House, the president has assistants and advisors, but there are also a 299 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 number of agencies or White House offices. Some of these advisors and agency heads are Senate-confirmed positions. They all generally report to the president’s chief of staff and work in the West Wing, the adjacent Eisenhower Executive Office Building, or in nearby offices.1 The vast majority of federal employees, obviously, do not work within the White House. There are fifteen executive branch departments (the heads of which are members of the president’s cabinet).2 Often these will be called federal agencies. But there are other Executive Branch agencies that are not “executive departments” or White House offices. Some of these “independent agencies” function just like the executive departments (and heads of some, like the Environmental Protection Agency and Central Intelligence Agency, even attend presidential cabinet meetings). Others, like the Social Security Administration, are “independent” in the sense that their top officials can only be removed by the president for cause, providing both policy independence and some potential disunity within the “unitary executive.” Some 1 Among the agencies within the White House are the National Security Council, the Council on Environmental Quality, the Office of Management and Budget, and the Office of the Vice President. Other White House offices include the Office of the First Lady, the Office of Legislative Affairs, the White House Counsel, and others. 2 They are: the Departments of Agriculture, Commerce, Defense, Education, Energy, Health and Human Services, Homeland Security, Housing and Urban Development, the Interior, Justice, Labor, State, Transportation, Treasury, and Veterans Affairs. 300 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 such agencies, like the Federal Communications Commission and the Federal Labor Relations Administration, are headed by commissions of several people who are appointed on a staggered basis. Some of these are even required to maintain a partisan balance, further insulating them from presidential control. While the Department of Justice has primary authority to represent the United States in litigation, some agencies have independent authority to bring suit. Importantly, ”there is no single feature–not even a for– cause removal provision-that every agency commonly thought of as independent shares.”3 Instead, we have a large federal bureaucracy, composed of agencies created by very different statutes, with different missions, structures, and authority. This heterogeneity reflects a staggered history of federal power, crises, and opportunities. For an overview, the chart available here (http://www.bu.edu/lawlibrary/graphics/ gov_chart.png) is very helpful. Agencies as Institutions Agencies are a distinctive type of governmental institution not only in structure and mission but also in function. Consider for a moment some observations we have made about legislatures and courts. On the positive side of the ledger, legislatures tend to be representative, democratically accountable, able to conduct hearings and to engage in wide-ranging fact-finding, and are 3 Kirti Datla and Richard L. Revesz, Deconstructing Independent Agencies, 98 Cornell L. Rev. 769, 772 (2013). 301 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 likely to be perceived as legitimate sources of law. On the negative side, they can be vehicles of majoritarian oppression, can be captured by interest groups, have very limited time to address ongoing social problems, and may operate in ways that conceal the effects of their actions (through, for example, conference committee negotiations and ambiguous and voluminous legislation). Courts tend to be far more independent of political influence, able to engage in deep (but narrow) fact-finding, have agendas that are constrained by the need for concrete disputes, have expertise in fit and justification (and treating like cases alike), may be more likely to protect minority interests, and are able to take a longer view than typical election cycles. Some of these very advantages are also the sources of disadvantage. Courts are often democratically unaccountable, can use rhetorical subterfuge to hide raw policy preferences in legal reasoning, lack agenda control, and possess only blunt remedies (like injunctions and damages, rather than the more fine-tuned machinery of regulatory institutions). Administrative agencies share some of these advantages and disadvantages. But they are in many ways unlike typical courts and unlike typical legislators. For one, they tend to pair personnel with particular social issues: review of the safety of particular classes of drugs, the measurement and analysis of certain types of air pollution, the evaluation of the safety of consumer products intended for use by infants, for example. Courts and legislators both tend to be generalist institutions, and legislators and judges are expected to address themselves to the full range of issues. Agencies, with their narrow range of responsibilities, can be 302 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 loci of true expertise and experience and may be staffed by scientists, economists, or otherwise by workers who repeatedly deal with a narrow set of issues. Consistent with narrow focus, agencies may devote attention to the details of social problems and policy that legislators have no time for – let alone the expertise to appreciate. Congress will not spend time studying and separately legislating the permissible concentrations of all the potentially harmful chemicals and microorganisms in drinking water. But it can direct the EPA to develop regulations that establish maximum contaminant levels for contaminants that “have an adverse effect on [human] health” and where the regulations would “present[] a meaningful opportunity for health risk reduction.” The Safe Drinking Water Act does just this. It is a lengthy act (see https://www.epw.senate.gov/ sdwa.pdf), but it gives general directions and sets policy goals, while leaving many technical and scientific details to the employees at EPA who have the time, expertise, and mandate to do such work. Agencies also possess flexibility, at least to the extent statutes give it to them, to address problems with finely crafted solutions: whether through informal discussions, fines, labeling, provision of information to Congress, or otherwise. Finally, agencies are distinguished by the kind of public participation they usually provide. It is true that the only formal electoral accountability over agencies the public has is through presidential election. But the opportunity directly to comment, to receive notice of proposed rules, and to challenge agency actions both within the agency and in court, all these combine in an alternative form of democratic legitimacy. 303 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 Whether it is enough – or perhaps even a greater measure of real accountability than Congress is subject to – is debatable. How they work Federal agencies administer statutes passed by Congress. But administration necessarily involves interpreting statutes and elaborating their meaning. In doing so, agencies are subject to reporting to and perhaps taking direction from the White House, to the budgetary authority of Congress and the regular review by Congress of agency actions (both through documents and in hearings), to the comments of interested parties, and to judicial review in litigation brought by private citizens or other governmental units. The general blueprint for agencies, in a way the constitution of the regulatory state, is contained in the Administrative Procedure Act. Enacted in 1946, the APA sets out the standards by which courts will review agency actions, these standards depending on which of four kinds of agency action is challenged. Agency actions subject to judicial review are either adjudication or rulemaking. And each of those comes in formal or informal varieties. Formal actions of either type involve trial-like procedures, with a hearing at which evidence is presented and those subject to the action are afforded an opportunity to appear and be heard. An agency is required to resort to formal rule making or adjudication only when Congress requires it, usually through the use of language stating that the agency must reach a decision on the record after an opportunity for a hearing. All of these types of action can be important, but we will focus on the most common type of federal agency action you 304 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 might already be familiar with: informal rulemaking. Spoiler: it’s not all that informal. Informal rulemaking Informal rulemaking is the primary method through which administrative agencies make the rules that are the functional equivalent of laws. The process is detailed but not very complicated in concept once the general process is understood. To appreciate this detail, take a look at this chart of the regulatory process (https://www.reginfo.gov/public/ reginfo/Regmap/index.jsp) provided by the White House. Informal rulemaking proceeds according to the requirements of section 533 of the Administrative Procedure Act. Here it is: (a) This section applies, according to the provisions thereof, except to the extent that there is involved– (1) a military or foreign affairs function of the United States; or (2) a matter relating to agency management or personnel or to public property, loans, grants, benefits, or contracts. (b) General notice of proposed rule making shall be published in the Federal Register, unless persons subject thereto are named and either personally served or otherwise have actual notice thereof in accordance with law. The notice shall include– 305 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 (1) a statement of the time, place, and nature of public rule making proceedings; (2) reference to the legal authority under which the rule is proposed; and (3) either the terms or substance of the proposed rule or a description of the subjects and issues involved. Except when notice or hearing is required by statute, this subsection does not apply– (A) to interpretative rules, general statements of policy, or rules of agency organization, procedure, or practice; or (B) when the agency for good cause finds (and incorporates the finding and a brief statement of reasons therefor in the rules issued) that notice and public procedure thereon are impracticable, unnecessary, or contrary to the public interest. (c) After notice required by this section, the agency shall give interested persons an opportunity to participate in the rule making through submission of written data, views, or arguments with or without opportunity for oral presentation. After consideration of the relevant matter 306 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 presented, the agency shall incorporate in the rules adopted a concise general statement of their basis and purpose. When rules are required by statute to be made on the record after opportunity for an agency hearing, sections 556 and 557 of this title [governing formal rulemaking] apply instead of this subsection. (d) The required publication or service of a substantive rule shall be made not less than 30 days before its effective date, except– (1) a substantive rule which grants or recognizes an exemption or relieves a restriction; (2) interpretative rules and statements of policy; or (3) as otherwise provided by the agency for good cause found and published with the rule. (e) Each agency shall give an interested person the right to petition for the issuance, amendment, or repeal of a rule. The procedure here is also sometimes called “notice and comment rulemaking.” The upshot is that the agency, acting under statutory authority, publishes a notice of proposed rule making, in which it discusses the proposed rule and solicits comments from the public. It analyzes those comments and ultimately, if it chooses to proceed, publishes a final rule. As you will see in the notice of proposed rulemaking included below, agencies not only publish a proposed rule’s 307 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 text, they also engage in analysis of costs of benefits and of other effects. Some of these analyses are statutorily mandated, including, for example, those of environmental impacts, paperwork that will be required, impacts on small businesses, and effects on federalism. Presidents have issued executive orders telling the agencies what steps to take before publishing a notice of proposed rulemaking and under what conditions it should do so. Executive Order 12,866 still provides the general framework. Agencies other than truly independent agencies may be required to get White House approval before issuing an NPR. If a proposed rule is “significant,” then it must be submitted to the Office of Information and Regulatory Affairs (OIRA), a White House office within the Office of Management and Budget, along with an analysis of costs, benefits, and, usually, the other statutorily required analyses. OIRA reviews and may approve or “return” the regulation to the agency for further work. Disputes between an agency and OIRA are ultimately resolved by the president or vicepresident. If approved or exempt from review, the notice of proposed rulemaking is published in the Federal Register and on the web, and a sixty day comment period begins. Comments may be submitted in writing or electronically. After this period, a final rule is drafted. Again, if the rule is significant, OIRA reviews it. If approved, the final rule is published. Rules are usually required to be sent to Congress and the General Accounting Office before taking effect, with a sixty-day period for economically significant regulations. Under the Congressional Review Act, Congress may, during this period, vote to disapprove the rule by simple majority of both houses and signature of the president. 308 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 Together, Executive Orders 12,866 and 13,563, the Obama administration modification to 12,866, also require agencies to prepare semi-annual agendas containing all planned regulations expected to have significant economic effects and requires the periodic audit of regulations. The order generally requires agencies to endeavor to minimize regulatory burden and to engage in evidence-based cost-benefit analyses, consider alternatives to regulation, and maximize net benefits, including distributive benefits. These are some of the nuts and bolts of executive regulation. But the disagreements about how regulation should occur and what it should it include can be quite fundamental. Let us consider some of the typical arguments about the administrative state now. Controversies The administrative state is fundamentally the result of two structural transformations of federal power. The first was in response to the Civil War, and the second, most relevant to the growth and power of regulatory agencies, arose from the New Deal’s response to the Great Depression. We will discuss some of the points of controversy that have raged since the New Deal in class. But here is a list of some of these topics: – What is the proper scope of federal legislative authority under the clause of the Constitution giving Congress the power to regulate interstate commerce and the clause giving it the power to pass laws “necessary and proper” to accomplish such regulation? The New Deal ushered 309 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 in a dramatic expansion of this power, with the Supreme Court’s concluding that this power includes the ability to regulate purely intrastate activities that, in the aggregate, have an effect on interstate commerce. In any increasingly connected and complex economy, just about everything has an effect on everything else. In the past two decades, the Supreme Court has begun to enforce some limits on this power, but it is unclear whether these are effective or warranted. The upshot is that the power of the regulatory state is derivative of the power of Congress to regulate the economy. – To what extent can Congress delegate policymaking authority to agencies? The so-called non-delegation doctrine requires Congress to provide agencies with an “intelligible principle” to guide their decisionmaking. But this constraint is not very meaningful in practice. Congress often grants broad policymaking authority to agencies. – To what extent must agencies be under the ultimate decisionmaking authority of the president? That is, to what extent must we adhere to the unitary executive theory? Congress has created numerous agencies that are insulated from direct control by the president, and these have generally been upheld as consistent with Article II and the separation of powers. – Are the accountability problems of agencies unconstitutionally multiplied by their simultaneous exercise of policymaking, adjudication, and enforcement authorities? 310 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 – To what degree is agency capture by regulated entities a problem, and how insulated from politics and lobbying should agencies be while at the same time responsive to public comment? – And, finally, the topic of the cases that follow: When agencies implement statutes, they must interpret them. Should those interpretations be granted deference by courts, or should courts always be the ones who declare what the law is and thus what statutes mean? Next Up Before we turn to Chevron, the most famous case in administrative law, take a look at this Notice of Proposed Rulemaking (at https://www.federalregister.gov/documents/ 2016/03/02/2016-04609/removal-of-mandatory-country-oforigin-labeling-requirements-for-beef-and-pork-muscle-cutsground). You shouldn’t read this to master the details of this particular rule. Rather, I want you to skim it and to observe its structure and features. Note its summary, solicitation of comments, explanation of the rule being proposed, and the checklist of analyses it discusses, including its cost-benefit analysis, its evaluation of the impact on small businesses, and other reviews, and the actual rule language on the last couple of pages. Note in particular that the agency finds the benefits of consumer labeling in this context difficult to quantify. Think about the value you might personally place on labelling like this. The costs of labeling, though, are relatively easier to quantify, but doing so requires some estimation, including 311 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 identifying the costs of keeping data about country of origin, making new labels either in packing plants or at retail, thinking about whether this would be a cost that sellers would incur eventually anyway as packaging is redesigned, etc. As you can see, it’s a tough job that requires statistical and modeling expertise and familiarity with the industry. Welcome to the world of administrative law. Chevron, U.S.A. v. Natural Resource Defense Council, Inc., 467 U.S. 837 Justice STEVENS delivered the opinion of the Court. In the Clean Air Act Amendments of 1977, Congress enacted certain requirements applicable to States that had not achieved the national air quality standards established by the Environmental Protection Agency (EPA) pursuant to earlier legislation. The amended Clean Air Act required these “nonattainment” States to establish a permit program regulating “new or modified major stationary sources” of air pollution. Generally, a permit may not be issued for a new or modified major stationary source unless several stringent conditions are met. The EPA regulation promulgated to implement this permit requirement allows a State to adopt a plantwide definition of the term “stationary source.” Under 312 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 this definition, an existing plant that contains several pollution-emitting devices may install or modify one piece of equipment without meeting the permit conditions if the alteration will not increase the total emissions from the plant. The question presented by these cases is whether EPA’s decision to allow States to treat all of the pollution-emitting devices within the same industrial grouping as though they were encased within a single “bubble” is based on a reasonable construction of the statutory term “stationary source.” I The EPA regulations containing the plantwide definition of the term stationary source were promulgated on October 14, 1981. Respondents filed a timely petition for review in the United States Court of Appeals for the District of Columbia Circuit pursuant to 42 U. S. C. § 7607(b)(1). The Court of Appeals set aside the regulations. The court observed that the relevant part of the amended Clean Air Act “does not explicitly define what Congress envisioned as a ‘stationary source, to which the permit program. . . should apply,” and further stated that the precise issue was not “squarely addressed in the legislative history.” In light of its conclusion that the legislative history bearing on the question was “at best contradictory,” it reasoned that “the purposes of the nonattainment program should guide our decision here.” Based on two of its precedents concerning the applicability of the bubble concept to certain Clean Air Act programs, the court stated that the bubble concept was 313 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 “mandatory” in programs designed merely to maintain existing air quality, but held that it was “inappropriate” in programs enacted to improve air quality. Since the purpose of the permit program – its “raison d’etre,” in the court’s view – was to improve air quality, the court held that the bubble concept was inapplicable in these cases under its prior precedents. It therefore set aside the regulations embodying the bubble concept as contrary to law. We granted certiorari to review that judgment, . . . and we now reverse. The basic legal error of the Court of Appeals was to adopt a static judicial definition of the term “stationary source” when it had decided that Congress itself had not commanded that definition. Respondents do not defend the legal reasoning of the Court of Appeals. Nevertheless, since this Court reviews judgments, not opinions, we must determine whether the Court of Appeals’ legal error resulted in an erroneous judgment on the validity of the regulations. II When a court reviews an agency’s construction of the statute which it administers, it is confronted with two questions. First, always, is the question whether Congress has directly spoken to the precise question at issue. If the intent of Congress is clear, that is the end of the matter; for the court, as well as the agency, must give effect to the unambiguously expressed intent of Congress. If, however, the court determines Congress has not directly addressed the precise question at issue, the court does not simply impose its own construction on the statute, as would be necessary in the absence of an administrative interpretation. Rather, if the 314 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 statute is silent or ambiguous with respect to the specific issue, the question for the court is whether the agency’s answer is based on a permissible construction of the statute. “The power of an administrative agency to administer a congressionally created . . . program necessarily requires the formulation of policy and the making of rules to fill any gap left, implicitly or explicitly, by Congress.” If Congress has explicitly left a gap for the agency to fill, there is an express delegation of authority to the agency to elucidate a specific provision of the statute by regulation. Such legislative regulations are given controlling weight unless they are arbitrary, capricious, or manifestly contrary to the statute. Sometimes the legislative delegation to an agency on a particular question is implicit rather than explicit. In such a case, a court may not substitute its own construction of a statutory provision for a reasonable interpretation made by the administrator of an agency. We have long recognized that considerable weight should be accorded to an executive department’s construction of a statutory scheme it is entrusted to administer, and the principle of deference to administrative interpretations "has been consistently followed by this Court whenever decision as to the meaning or reach of a statute has involved reconciling conflicting policies, and a full understanding of the force of the statutory policy in the given situation has depended upon more than ordinary knowledge respecting the matters subjected to agency regulations. 315 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 ". . . If this choice represents a reasonable accommodation of conflicting policies that were committed to the agency’s care by the statute, we should not disturb it unless it appears from the statute or its legislative history that the accommodation is not one that Congress would have sanctioned." In light of these well-settled principles it is clear that the Court of Appeals misconceived the nature of its role in reviewing the regulations at issue. Once it determined, after its own examination of the legislation, that Congress did not actually have an intent regarding the applicability of the bubble concept to the permit program, the question before it was not whether in its view the concept is “inappropriate” in the general context of a program designed to improve air quality, but whether the Administrator’s view that it is appropriate in the context of this particular program is a reasonable one. Based on the examination of the legislation and its history which follows, we agree with the Court of Appeals that Congress did not have a specific intention on the applicability of the bubble concept in these cases, and conclude that the EPA’s use of that concept here is a reasonable policy choice for the agency to make. .... VII In this Court respondents expressly reject the basic rationale of the Court of Appeals’ decision. That court viewed the statutory definition of the term “source” as sufficiently flexible to cover either a plantwide definition, a narrower definition 316 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 covering each unit within a plant, or a dual definition that could apply to both the entire “bubble” and its components. It interpreted the policies of the statute, however, to mandate the plantwide definition in programs designed to maintain clean air and to forbid it in programs designed to improve air quality. Respondents place a fundamentally different construction on the statute. They contend that the text of the Act requires the EPA to use a dual definition – if either a component of a plant, or the plant as a whole, emits over 100 tons of pollutant, it is a major stationary source. They thus contend that the EPA rules adopted in 1980, insofar as they apply to the maintenance of the quality of clean air, as well as the 1981 rules which apply to nonattainment areas, violate the statute. Statutory Language The definition of the term “stationary source” in § 111(a)(3) refers to “any building, structure, facility, or installation” which emits air pollution. This definition is applicable only to the NSPS program by the express terms of the statute; the text of the statute does not make this definition applicable to the permit program. Petitioners therefore maintain that there is no statutory language even relevant to ascertaining the meaning of stationary source in the permit program aside from § 302(j), which defines the term “major stationary source.” We disagree with petitioners on this point. The definition in § 302(j) tells us what the word “major” means – a source must emit at least 100 tons of pollution to qualify – but it sheds virtually no light on the meaning of the term “stationary source.” It does equate a source with a 317 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 facility – a “major emitting facility” and a “major stationary source” are synonymous under § 302(j). The ordinary meaning of the term “facility” is some collection of integrated elements which has been designed and constructed to achieve some purpose. Moreover, it is certainly no affront to common English usage to take a reference to a major facility or a major source to connote an entire plant as opposed to its constituent parts. Basically, however, the language of § 302(j) simply does not compel any given interpretation of the term “source.” Respondents recognize that, and hence point to § 111(a) (3). Although the definition in that section is not literally applicable to the permit program, it sheds as much light on the meaning of the word “source” as anything in the statute. As respondents point out, use of the words “building, structure, facility, or installation,” as the definition of source, could be read to impose the permit conditions on an individual building that is a part of a plant. A “word may have a character of its own not to be submerged by its association.” On the other hand, the meaning of a word must be ascertained in the context of achieving particular objectives, and the words associated with it may indicate that the true meaning of the series is to convey a common idea. The language may reasonably be interpreted to impose the requirement on any discrete, but integrated, operation which pollutes. This gives meaning to all of the terms – a single building, not part of a larger operation, would be covered if it emits more than 100 tons of pollution, as would any facility, structure, or installation. Indeed, the language itself implies a “bubble concept” of sorts: each enumerated item would seem to be treated as if it were encased in a bubble. While respondents insist that each of these terms must be given a 318 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 discrete meaning, they also argue that § 111(a)(3) defines “source” as that term is used in § 302(j). The latter section, however, equates a source with a facility, whereas the former defines “source” as a facility, among other items. We are not persuaded that parsing of general terms in the text of the statute will reveal an actual intent of Congress. We know full well that this language is not dispositive; the terms are overlapping and the language is not precisely directed to the question of the applicability of a given term in the context of a larger operation. To the extent any congressional “intent” can be discerned from this language, it would appear that the listing of overlapping, illustrative terms was intended to enlarge, rather than to confine, the scope of the agency’s power to regulate particular sources in order to effectuate the policies of the Act. Legislative History In addition, respondents argue that the legislative history and policies of the Act foreclose the plantwide definition, and that the EPA’s interpretation is not entitled to deference because it represents a sharp break with prior interpretations of the Act. Based on our examination of the legislative history, we agree with the Court of Appeals that it is unilluminating. The general remarks pointed to by respondents “were obviously not made with this narrow issue in mind and they cannot be said to demonstrate a Congressional desire . . . .” Respondents’ argument based on the legislative history relies heavily on Senator Muskie’s observation that a new source is subject to the LAER requirement. But the full statement is 319 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 ambiguous and like the text of § 173 itself, this comment does not tell us what a new source is, much less that it is to have an inflexible definition. We find that the legislative history as a whole is silent on the precise issue before us. It is, however, consistent with the view that the EPA should have broad discretion in implementing the policies of the 1977 Amendments. More importantly, that history plainly identifies the policy concerns that motivated the enactment; the plantwide definition is fully consistent with one of those concerns – the allowance of reasonable economic growth – and, whether or not we believe it most effectively implements the other, we must recognize that the EPA has advanced a reasonable explanation for its conclusion that the regulations serve the environmental objectives as well. Indeed, its reasoning is supported by the public record developed in the rulemaking process, private studies. Our review of the EPA’s varying interpretations of the word “source” – both before and after the 1977 Amendments – convinces us that the agency primarily responsible for administering this important legislation has consistently interpreted it flexibly – not in a sterile textual vacuum, but in the context of implementing policy decisions in a technical and complex arena. The fact that the agency has from time to time changed its interpretation of the term “source” does not, as respondents argue, lead us to conclude that no deference should be accorded the agency’s interpretation of the statute. An initial agency interpretation is not instantly carved in stone. On the contrary, the agency, to engage in informed rulemaking, must consider varying interpretations and the wisdom of its policy on a continuing basis. Moreover, the fact 320 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 that the agency has adopted different definitions in different contexts adds force to the argument that the definition itself is flexible, particularly since Congress has never indicated any disapproval of a flexible reading of the statute. Significantly, it was not the agency in 1980, but rather the Court of Appeals that read the statute inflexibly to command a plantwide definition for programs designed to maintain clean air and to forbid such a definition for programs designed to improve air quality. The distinction the court drew may well be a sensible one, but our labored review of the problem has surely disclosed that it is not a distinction that Congress ever articulated itself, or one that the EPA found in the statute before the courts began to review the legislative work product. We conclude that it was the Court of Appeals, rather than Congress or any of the decisionmakers who are authorized by Congress to administer this legislation, that was primarily responsible for the 1980 position taken by the agency. Policy The arguments over policy that are advanced in the parties’ briefs create the impression that respondents are now waging in a judicial forum a specific policy battle which they ultimately lost in the agency and in the 32 jurisdictions opting for the “bubble concept,” but one which was never waged in the Congress. Such policy arguments are more properly addressed to legislators or administrators, not to judges. In these cases the Administrator’s interpretation represents a reasonable accommodation of manifestly competing interests and is entitled to deference: the regulatory scheme is 321 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 technical and complex, the agency considered the matter in a detailed and reasoned fashion, and the decision involves reconciling conflicting policies. Congress intended to accommodate both interests, but did not do so itself on the level of specificity presented by these cases. Perhaps that body consciously desired the Administrator to strike the balance at this level, thinking that those with great expertise and charged with responsibility for administering the provision would be in a better position to do so; perhaps it simply did not consider the question at this level; and perhaps Congress was unable to forge a coalition on either side of the question, and those on each side decided to take their chances with the scheme devised by the agency. For judicial purposes, it matters not which of these things occurred. Judges are not experts in the field, and are not part of either political branch of the Government. Courts must, in some cases, reconcile competing political interests, but not on the basis of the judges’ personal policy preferences. In contrast, an agency to which Congress has delegated policymaking responsibilities may, within the limits of that delegation, properly rely upon the incumbent administration’s views of wise policy to inform its judgments. While agencies are not directly accountable to the people, the Chief Executive is, and it is entirely appropriate for this political branch of the Government to make such policy choices – resolving the competing interests which Congress itself either inadvertently did not resolve, or intentionally left to be resolved by the agency charged with the administration of the statute in light of everyday realities. When a challenge to an agency construction of a statutory provision, fairly conceptualized, really centers on the wisdom 322 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 of the agency’s policy, rather than whether it is a reasonable choice within a gap left open by Congress, the challenge must fail. In such a case, federal judges – who have no constituency – have a duty to respect legitimate policy choices made by those who do. The responsibilities for assessing the wisdom of such policy choices and resolving the struggle between competing views of the public interest are not judicial ones: “Our Constitution vests such responsibilities in the political branches.” We hold that the EPA’s definition of the term “source” is a permissible construction of the statute which seeks to accommodate progress in reducing air pollution with economic growth. “The Regulations which the Administrator has adopted provide what the agency could allowably view as . . . [an] effective reconciliation of these twofold ends . . . .” The judgment of the Court of Appeals is reversed. Gutierrez-Brizuela v. Lynch, 834 F.3d 1142 GORSUCH, Circuit Judge. We recently confronted the thorny problem what to do when an executive agency, exercising delegated legislative authority, seeks to overrule a judicial precedent interpreting a congressional statute. In our constitutional history, after all, judicial declarations of what the law is haven’t often been thought subject to revision by the executive, let alone by an 323 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 executive endowed with delegated legislative authority. Still, in recent years the Supreme Court has instructed us that, when a statute is ambiguous and an executive agency’s interpretation is reasonable, the agency may indeed exercise delegated legislative authority to overrule a judicial precedent in favor of the agency’s preferred interpretation. And that development required us to confront this question: accepting that an agency may overrule a court, may it do so not only prospectively but also retroactively, applying its new rule to completed conduct that transpired at a time when the contrary judicial precedent appeared to control? Now that curious question has returned, this time with a twist. [As you just read, the Supreme Court held in Chevron that an agency’s interpretation of a statute should control in a case where the language of the statute is ambiguous and the agency’s interpretation is reasonable. In National Cable and Telecommunications Ass’n v. Brand X Internet Services, the Supreme Court held that an agency’s interpretation should trump a court’s previous, incompatible interpretation, when the agency’s interpretation has satisfied the two-step Chevron analysis. Here, the question before the Tenth Circuit Court of Appeal is whether an agency’s interpretation only trumps a court’s interpretation when applied to cases challenging agency actions that occurred after the agency interpretation, or whether the agency’s interpretation can be applied to actions that took place when the court’s interpretation was the governing interpretation. That is, should the agency’s rejection of the court’s interpretation be given retroactive effect? Writing for the Tenth Circuit, then-Judge, now Justice Gorsuch concluded that nothing in Brand X or Chevron necessitates the conclusion that an agency’s interpretation 324 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 should be presumed to apply retroactively “to conduct completed before [the agency’s interpretations] take legal effect.” The case was then remanded back to the agency, here the Board of Immigration Appeals, for further proceedings. In a somewhat surprising turn, Judge Gorsuch then wrote the following concurrence to his own majority opinion and raised a much broader and more consequential issue.] GORSUCH, Circuit Judge, concurring. There’s an elephant in the room with us today. We have studiously attempted to work our way around it and even left it unremarked. But the fact is Chevron and Brand X permit executive bureaucracies to swallow huge amounts of core judicial and legislative power and concentrate federal power in a way that seems more than a little difficult to square with the Constitution of the framers’ design. Maybe the time has come to face the behemoth. In enlightenment theory and hard won experience under a tyrannical king the founders found proof of the wisdom of a government of separated powers. In the avowedly political legislature, the framers endowed the people’s representatives with the authority to prescribe new rules of general applicability prospectively. In the executive, they placed the task of ensuring the legislature’s rules are faithfully executed in the hands of a single person also responsive to the people. And in the judiciary, they charged individuals insulated from political pressures with the job of interpreting the law and applying it retroactively to resolve past disputes. This allocation of different sorts of power to different sorts of 325 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 decisionmakers was no accident. To adapt the law to changing circumstances, the founders thought, the collective wisdom of the people’s representatives is needed. To faithfully execute the laws often demands the sort of vigor hard to find in management-by-committee. And to resolve cases and controversies over past events calls for neutral decisionmakers who will apply the law as it is, not as they wish it to be. Even more importantly, the founders considered the separation of powers a vital guard against governmental encroachment on the people’s liberties, including all those later enumerated in the Bill of Rights. What would happen, for example, if the political majorities who run the legislative and executive branches could decide cases and controversies over past facts? They might be tempted to bend existing laws, to reinterpret and apply them retroactively in novel ways and without advance notice. Effectively leaving parties who cannot alter their past conduct to the mercy of majoritarian politics and risking the possibility that unpopular groups might be singled out for this sort of mistreatment — and raising along the way, too, grave due process (fair notice) and equal protection problems. Conversely, what would happen if politically unresponsive and life-tenured judges were permitted to decide policy questions for the future or try to execute those policies? The very idea of self-government would soon be at risk of withering to the point of pointlessness. It was to avoid dangers like these, dangers the founders had studied and seen realized in their own time, that they pursued the separation of powers. A government of diffused powers, they knew, is a government less capable of invading the liberties of the people. 326 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 Founders meet Brand X. Precisely to avoid the possibility of allowing politicized decisionmakers to decide cases and controversies about the meaning of existing laws, the framers sought to ensure that judicial judgments “may not lawfully be revised, overturned or refused faith and credit by” the elected branches of government. Yet this deliberate design, this separation of functions aimed to ensure a neutral decisionmaker for the people’s disputes, faces more than a little pressure from Brand X. Under Brand X’s terms, after all, courts are required to overrule their own declarations about the meaning of existing law in favor of interpretations dictated by executive agencies. By Brand X’s own telling, this means a judicial declaration of the law’s meaning in a case or controversy before it is not “authoritative,” . . . but is instead subject to revision by a politically accountable branch of government. That’s exactly what happened to Mr. Padilla-Caldera. First this court read the relevant immigration statutes to permit an alien who has entered the country illegally to seek a discretionary adjustment of status from the Attorney General. Then we remanded the case to allow the Attorney General to make that discretionary decision in Mr. Padilla-Caldera’s case. But instead of undertaking that task, the BIA interpreted the statutory scheme to reach the opposite conclusion we had, applied its new statutory interpretation to Mr. Padilla-Caldera, and held him categorically forbidden from receiving a discretionary adjustment of status. When the case returned to this court, we conceded that the relevant statutes were indeed ambiguous and acknowledged that Brand X required us to defer to the BIA’s new interpretation, in the end holding that Mr. Padilla-Caldera was, as the agency said, 327 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 categorically prohibited from applying for a discretionary adjustment of status. Quite literally then, after this court declared the statutes’ meaning and issued a final decision, an executive agency was permitted to (and did) tell us to reverse our decision like some sort of super court of appeals. If that doesn’t qualify as an unconstitutional revision of a judicial declaration of the law by a political branch, I confess I begin to wonder whether we’ve forgotten what might. Of course, since Padilla–Caldera we have reentered the field and sought to tame some of Brand X’s more exuberant consequences. So, for example, in De Niz Robles and now again today we have held that an agency’s revision of a judicial decision of what the law is may bear only prospective effect, governing only future cases and controversies. As a result, an executive agency may no longer revise a judicial decision about the law’s meaning with retroactive effect, like the BIA managed to do in the case of Mr. Padilla-Caldera. No doubt that addresses some of the due process and equal protection problems that follow from allowing politicized decisionmakers to decide cases and controversies about the meaning of existing law. But even this doesn’t fully resolve the problem. When the political branches disagree with a judicial interpretation of existing law, the Constitution prescribes the appropriate remedial process. It’s called legislation. Admittedly, the legislative process can be an arduous one. But that’s no bug in the constitutional design: it is the very point of the design. The framers sought to ensure that the people may rely on judicial precedent about the meaning of existing law until and unless that precedent is overruled or the purposefully painful process of bicameralism and presentment can be cleared. 328 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 Indeed, the principle of stare decisis was one “entrenched and revered by the framers” precisely because they knew its importance “as a weapon against . . . tyranny.” Yet even as now semi-tamed (at least in this circuit), Brand X still risks trampling the constitutional design by affording executive agencies license to overrule a judicial declaration of the law’s meaning prospectively, just as legislation might — and all without the inconvenience of having to engage the legislative processes the Constitution prescribes. A form of Lawmaking Made Easy, one that permits all too easy intrusions on the liberty of the people. Of course, Brand X asserts that its rule about judicial deference to executive revisions follows logically “from Chevron itself.” And that assessment seems fair enough as far as it goes. If you accept Chevron’s claim that legislative ambiguity represents a license to executive agencies to render authoritative judgments about what a statute means, Brand X’s rule requiring courts to overturn their own contrary judgments does seem to follow pretty naturally. But acknowledging this much only brings the colossus now fully into view. In the Administrative Procedure Act (APA), Congress vested the courts with the power to “interpret . . . statutory provisions” and overturn agency action inconsistent with those interpretations. Congress assigned the courts much the same job in the immigration field where we happen to find ourselves today. And there’s good reason to think that legislative assignments like these are often constitutionally compelled. After all, the question whether Congress has or hasn’t vested a private legal right in an individual “is, in its nature, judicial, and must be tried by the judicial authority.” Yet, rather than completing the task expressly assigned to us, 329 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 rather than “interpret[ing] . . . statutory provisions,” declaring what the law is, and overturning inconsistent agency action, Chevron step two tells us we must allow an executive agency to resolve the meaning of any ambiguous statutory provision. In this way, Chevron seems no less than a judge-made doctrine for the abdication of the judicial duty. Of course, some role remains for judges even under Chevron. At Chevron step one, judges decide whether the statute is “ambiguous,” and at step two they decide whether the agency’s view is “reasonable.” But where in all this does a court interpret the law and say what it is? When does a court independently decide what the statute means and whether it has or has not vested a legal right in a person? Where Chevron applies that job seems to have gone extinct. Transferring the job of saying what the law is from the judiciary to the executive unsurprisingly invites the very sort of due process (fair notice) and equal protection concerns the framers knew would arise if the political branches intruded on judicial functions. Under Chevron the people aren’t just charged with awareness of and the duty to conform their conduct to the fairest reading of the law that a detached magistrate can muster. Instead, they are charged with an awareness of Chevron; required to guess whether the statute will be declared “ambiguous” (courts often disagree on what qualifies); and required to guess (again) whether an agency’s interpretation will be deemed “reasonable.” Who can even attempt all that, at least without an army of perfumed lawyers and lobbyists? And, of course, that’s not the end of it. Even if the people somehow manage to make it through this far unscathed, they must always remain alert to the possibility that the agency will reverse its current view 180 degrees 330 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 anytime based merely on the shift of political winds and still prevail. Neither, too, will agencies always deign to announce their views in advance; often enough they seek to impose their “reasonable” new interpretations only retroactively in administrative adjudications. Perhaps allowing agencies rather than courts to declare the law’s meaning bears some advantages, but it also bears its costs. And the founders were wary of those costs, knowing that, when unchecked by independent courts exercising the job of declaring the law’s meaning, executives throughout history had sought to exploit ambiguous laws as license for their own prerogative. Some claim to see a way out of our apparent predicament. They suggest that Chevron isn’t so much about permitting agencies to assume the judicial function of interpreting the law as it is about permitting agencies to make the law, to effect their own preferences about optimal public policy when a statute is ambiguous. On this account, Chevron’s rule of deference isn’t about trying to make judges out of agencies or letting them usurp the judicial function. Rather, it’s about letting agencies fill legislative voids. When Congress passes ambiguous legislation, Chevron means we should read that as signaling a legislative “intention” to “delegate” to the executive the job of making any reasonable “legislative” policy choices it thinks wise. And, to be sure, Chevron itself espouses just this view. In both De Niz Robles and again today we expressly acknowledge as much. But however that may be, none of it rescues us from our riddle. For whatever the agency may be doing under Chevron, the problem remains that courts are not fulfilling their duty to interpret the law and declare invalid agency actions inconsistent with those interpretations in the cases and 331 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 controversies that come before them. A duty expressly assigned to them by the APA and one often likely compelled by the Constitution itself. That’s a problem for the judiciary. And it is a problem for the people whose liberties may now be impaired not by an independent decisionmaker seeking to declare the law’s meaning as fairly as possible — the decisionmaker promised to them by law — but by an avowedly politicized administrative agent seeking to pursue whatever policy whim may rule the day. Those problems remain uncured by this line of reply. Maybe as troubling, this line of reply invites a nest of questions even taken on its own terms. Chevron says that we should infer from any statutory ambiguity Congress’s “intent” to “delegate” its “legislative authority” to the executive to make “reasonable” policy choices. But where exactly has Congress expressed this intent? Trying to infer the intentions of an institution composed of 535 members is a notoriously doubtful business under the best of circumstances. And these are not exactly the best of circumstances. Chevron suggests we should infer an intent to delegate not because Congress has anywhere expressed any such wish, not because anyone anywhere in any legislative history even hinted at that possibility, but because the legislation in question is silent (ambiguous) on the subject. Usually we’re told that “an agency literally has no power to act . . . unless and until Congress confers power upon it.” Yet Chevron seems to stand this ancient and venerable principle nearly on its head. Maybe worse still, Chevron’s inference about hidden congressional intentions seems belied by the intentions Congress has made textually manifest. After all and again, in the APA Congress expressly vested the courts with the 332 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 responsibility to “interpret . . . statutory provisions” and overturn agency action inconsistent with those interpretations. Meanwhile not a word can be found here about delegating legislative authority to agencies. On this record, how can anyone fairly say that Congress “intended” for courts to abdicate their statutory duty under § 706 and instead “intended” to delegate away its legislative power to executive agencies? The fact is, Chevron’s claim about legislative intentions is no more than a fiction — and one that requires a pretty hefty suspension of disbelief at that. Even supposing, too, that we could overlook this problem — even supposing we somehow had something resembling an authentic congressional delegation of legislative authority — you still might wonder: can Congress really delegate its legislative authority — its power to write new rules of general applicability — to executive agencies? The Supreme Court has long recognized that under the Constitution “congress cannot delegate legislative power to the president” and that this “principle [is] universally recognized as vital to the integrity and maintenance of the system of government ordained by the constitution.” Yet on this account of Chevron we’re examining, its whole point and purpose seems to be exactly that—to delegate legislative power to the executive branch. Not only is Chevron’s purpose seemingly at odds with the separation of legislative and executive functions, its effect appears to be as well. While the line between legislative and executive functions may sometimes be murky, history does teach us a couple of things about that line. First, we know that, consistent with the separation of powers, Congress may condition the application of a new rule of general applicability 333 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 on factual findings to be made by the executive (so, for example, forfeiture of assets might be required if the executive finds a foreign country behaved in a specified manner). Second, we know Congress may allow the executive to resolve “details” (like, say, the design of an appropriate tax stamp). Yet Chevron pretty clearly involves neither of these kinds of executive functions and, in this way and as a historical matter, appears instead to qualify as a violation of the separation of powers. Of course, in relatively recent times the Court has relaxed its approach to claims of unlawful legislative delegation. It has suggested (at least in the civil arena) that Congress may allow the executive to make new rules of general applicability that look a great deal like legislation, so long as the controlling legislation contains an “intelligible principle” that “clearly delineates the general policy” the agency is to apply and “the boundaries of [its] delegated authority.” This means Congress must at least “provide substantial guidance on setting . . . standards that affect the entire national economy.” Some thoughtful judges and scholars have questioned whether standards like these serve as much as a protection against the delegation of legislative authority as a license for it, undermining the separation between the legislative and executive powers that the founders thought essential. But even taking the forgiving intelligible principle test as a given, it’s no small question whether Chevron can clear it. For if an agency can enact a new rule of general applicability affecting huge swaths of the national economy one day and reverse itself the next (and that is exactly what Chevron permits, . . . you might be forgiven for asking: where’s the “substantial guidance” in that? And if an agency can interpret 334 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 the scope of its statutory jurisdiction one way one day and reverse itself the next . . . , you might well wonder: where are the promised “clearly delineated boundaries” of agency authority? The Supreme Court once unanimously declared that a statute affording the executive the power to write an industrial code of competition for the poultry industry violated the separation of powers. And if that’s the case, you might ask how is it that Chevron — a rule that invests agencies with pretty unfettered power to regulate a lot more than chicken — can evade the chopping block. Even under the most relaxed or functionalist view of our separated powers some concern has to arise, too, when so much power is concentrated in the hands of a single branch of government. After all, Chevron invests the power to decide the meaning of the law, and to do so with legislative policy goals in mind, in the very entity charged with enforcing the law. Under its terms, an administrative agency may set and revise policy (legislative), override adverse judicial determinations (judicial), and exercise enforcement discretion (executive). Add to this the fact that today many administrative agencies “wield[] vast power” and are overseen by political appointees (but often receive little effective oversight from the chief executive to whom they nominally report), and you have a pretty potent mix. Under any conception of our separation of powers, I would have thought powerful and centralized authorities like today’s administrative agencies would have warranted less deference from other branches, not more. None of this is to suggest that Chevron is “the very definition of tyranny.” But on any account it certainly seems to have added prodigious new powers to an already titanic administrative state — and spawned along the way more than a few due 335 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 process and equal protection problems of the sort documented in the court’s opinion today and in De Niz Robles. It’s an arrangement, too, that seems pretty hard to square with the Constitution of the founders’ design and, as Justice Frankfurter once observed, “[t]he accretion of dangerous power does not come in a day. It does come, however slowly, from the generative force of unchecked disregard of the restrictions” imposed by the Constitution. What I suspect about Chevron’s compatibility with the separation of powers finds confirmation in what I know. The Supreme Court has expressly instructed us not to apply Chevron deference when an agency seeks to interpret a criminal statute. Why? Because, we are seemingly told, doing so would violate the Constitution by forcing the judiciary to abdicate the job of saying what the law is and preventing courts from exercising independent judgment in the interpretation of statutes. An admirable colleague has noted that the same rationale would appear to preclude affording Chevron deference to agency interpretations of statutes that bear both civil and criminal applications. A category that covers a great many (most?) federal statutes today. And try as I might, I have a hard time identifying a principled reason why the same rationale doesn’t also apply to statutes with purely civil application. After all, the APA doesn’t distinguish between purely civil and other kinds of statutes when describing the interpretive duties of courts. Neither did the founders reserve their concerns about political decisionmakers deciding the meaning of existing law to criminal cases; Article III doesn’t say judges should say what the law is or decide whether legal rights have or haven’t vested and been violated only when a crime is alleged. And 336 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 certainly Marbury did not speak so meekly: it affirmed the judiciary’s duty to say what the law is in a case that involved the interpretation of, yes, a civil statute affecting individual rights. Some have suggested that criminal statutes should be treated differently when it comes to Chevron because they are not “administered” by an agency. I take this as a roundabout way of suggesting that Congress hasn’t “delegated” its legislative authority in the criminal context like it has in the civil. But as we’ve seen, the claim that Congress has delegated legislative authority even in the civil context is no more than a fiction. And for that matter it’s hard to see why the Justice Department doesn’t “administer” criminal statutes in much the same way other agencies “administer” various civil statutes. Of course, criminal law enforcement takes place in the courts, not before administrative agencies. But often enough civil administrative actions also depend on court approval for their effectiveness, and as we’ve seen this may be a matter not merely of statutory but sometimes constitutional imperative. Other arguments for rejecting Chevron deference (only) in criminal matters seem equally shaky. Some suggest that principles of due process and equal protection demand that the criminal law be clear and clearly given by judges. Others suggest that prosecutorial agencies have too many incentives to interpret criminal statutes expansively. But while concerns about due process and fair notice surely reach their apex in the criminal context, I am uncertain why we would view that as a license to neglect attending to them in the civil context. Especially given the power our modern administrative state already enjoys, even without Chevron, to penalize persons in 337 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 ways that can destroy their livelihoods and intrude on their liberty even when exercising only purely civil powers. And given that the line between “criminal” and “civil” statutes has often proven tricky enough to administer. Neither, too, are prosecutorial agencies known to be alone in their capacity and willingness to interpret statutes aggressively. Beyond all that, Chevron has presented its fair share of practical problems in its administration. By way of illustration, consider just two examples. First, we once thought Chevron’s presumption of delegation for ambiguous statutes applied uniformly to Congress’s work. Then we learned it doesn’t apply to criminal statutes. Now we know it doesn’t always apply even when it comes to purely civil statutes. In United States v. Mead Corp., . . . the Court added a “step zero” to the Chevron sequence, one that requires courts to employ a multi-factor balancing test to decide whether to proceed to apply Chevron to a civil statute. So today courts will only sometimes apply Chevron deference to ambiguous civil statutes. Neither, respectfully, does looking to the Supreme Court’s case law supply a great deal of guidance on how to apply Mead’s balancing test. In recent years, the Court has declined to apply Chevron deference to arguably ambiguous civil statutes but it has only sometimes cited the Mead balancing test as the reason, leaving more than a few litigants and lower courts to wonder how they are supposed to proceed. Second, long lingering questions linger still about just how rigorous Chevron step one is supposed to be. In deciding whether Congress has “directly spoken” to a question or left it “ambiguous,” what materials are we to consult? The narrow language of the statute alone? Its structure and history? 338 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 Canons of interpretation? Committee reports? Every scrap of legislative history we can dig up? Some claim to have identified at least three potential variants of Chevron jurisprudence governing the line between step one and step two in the Supreme Court’s case law. Of course, we often retain even mistaken judicial decisions because reliance interests have arisen around them. But Chevron is a procedural rule, and procedural rules generally receive little precedential consideration when experience proves them problematic in their administration. No doubt this is because parties form reliance interests primarily around substantive rules of law that allocate property and define the limits of permitted behavior, while procedural rules merely govern how courts will go about their own business when deciding disputes many years later that parties often cannot foresee when arranging their affairs. And it is particularly hard to see how Chevron might have engendered serious reliance interests by individuals (if not agencies). Not only because of the uncertainties associated with its administration. But because even when clearly and properly implemented, Chevron’s very point is to permit agencies to upset the settled expectations of the people by changing policy direction depending on the agency’s mood at the moment. So if reliance interests count, they would seem to count against retaining Chevron. All of which raises this question: what would happen in a world without Chevron? If this goliath of modern administrative law were to fall? Surely Congress could and would continue to pass statutes for executive agencies to enforce. And just as surely agencies could and would continue to offer guidance on how they intend to enforce those 339 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 statutes. The only difference would be that courts would then fulfill their duty to exercise their independent judgment about what the law is. Of course, courts could and would consult agency views and apply the agency’s interpretation when it accords with the best reading of a statute. But de novo judicial review of the law’s meaning would limit the ability of an agency to alter and amend existing law. It would avoid the due process and equal protection problems of the kind documented in our decisions. It would promote reliance interests by allowing citizens to organize their affairs with some assurance that the rug will not be pulled from under them tomorrow, the next day, or after the next election. And an agency’s recourse for a judicial declaration of the law’s meaning that it dislikes would be precisely the recourse the Constitution prescribes — an appeal to higher judicial authority or a new law enacted consistent with bicameralism and presentment. We managed to live with the administrative state before Chevron. We could do it again. Put simply, it seems to me that in a world without Chevron very little would change — except perhaps the most important things. 340 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 Meeting 10: Interpretation For this class, read Justice Scalia’s defense of textualism and of a certain kind of originalism and then a series of exchanges between Judge Posner and Bryan Garner: – Antonin Scalia, Common-Law Courts in a Civil-Law System: The Role of United States Federal Courts in Interpreting the Constitutionand Laws, at http:// tannerlectures.utah.edu/_documents/a-to-z/s/ scalia97.pdf (pages 79-100), – Richard Posner, The Incoherence of Antonin Scalia, at https://newrepublic.com/article/106441/scalia-garnerreading-the-law-textual-originalism, – Bryan Garner and Richard Posner, How Nuanced is Justice Scalia’s Judicial Philosophy? An Exchange, at https:// newrepublic.com/article/107001/how-nuanced-justicescalias-judicial-philosophy-exchange. Then read Cass Sunstein, There Is Nothing that Interpretation Just Is, at https://conservancy.umn.edu/bitstream/handle/ Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 11299/183132/1%20-%20Sunstein.pdf? sequence=1&isAllowed=y. Review Questions – Can you identify whether an interpretive argument (whether statutory or constitutional) is textualist, intentionalist, and purposivist? What do those terms mean, and can you make an argument of each type? (Think of our “no vehicles in the park” example.) – What is Scalia’s justification for objective interpretation of text rather than attempting to interpret what was meant or to attempt to serve a legislature’s broader purposes? – Do you understand Posner’s main critiques of “textualism”: Conservative bias, bad results, judicial incompetence as historians, break with tradition, impossibility? Can you argue in support and against him? – There’s a lot going on in Sunstein’s article, but the main idea is that all methods of interpretation have problems. And none seems compelled by any authoritative document. Do you have a preferred method of interpretation? Is it the same for constitutions, statutes, and contracts - or is it different for each of these kinds of legal texts? Is your method susceptible to any of Sunstein’s critiques? 342 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 – Generally, be able to identify weaknesses in any particular interpretive method. (Originalists have to grapple with what original thing should be privileged and with potentially unsavory results in important cases. Textualists have to deal with ambiguity. Pragmatists and other non-originalists may have to deal with allegations of political manipulation or lack of legitimacy. Intentionalists have to deal with the lack of complete intentions in any human action. Think of the shopping list examples.) – Is a burrito a sandwich? 343 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 Meeting 11: Deference and Scrutiny Review Questions – Why is Lochner criticized as judicial overreach? What kind of analysis does the majority engage in, and what does Justice Holmes say about it? – Can you distinguish rational basis and strict scrutiny? What are they, and why and when must we choose between them? – According to Carolene Products what should trigger strict scrutiny, and when should courts engage only in rational basis review? How does this differ from Lochner? Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 – Do you see how these cases — and Obergefell — are about (a) the standard of review a court should apply to the judgment made by another institution and (b) what policymaking should be left for legislatures and what areas of policymaking should be governed by courts? – How does Obergefell suggest we should identify the rights that are fundamental and therefore protected by strict scrutiny? – What is C.J. Roberts’ argument that the majority has engaged in Lochner-ism? Deference and Scrutiny The cases that follow illustrate how courts have understood their interpretive and regulatory role in legal systems – how they have debated and continue to debate the “which institution should decide what” question. Lochner v. New York, 198 U.S. 45 (1905) MR. JUSTICE PECKHAM. 345 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 The indictment, it will be seen, charges that the plaintiff in error violated the one hundred and tenth section of article 8, chapter 415, of the Laws of 1897, known as the labor law of the State of New York, in that he wrongfully and unlawfully required and permitted an employe working for him to work more than sixty hours in one week. . . . . The mandate of the statute that “no employe shall be required or permitted to work,” is the substantial equivalent of an enactment that “no employe shall contract or agree to work,” more than ten hours per day, and as there is no provision for special emergencies the statute is mandatory in all cases. . . . . The statute necessarily interferes with the right of contract between the employer and employes, concerning the number of hours in which the latter may labor in the bakery of the employer. The general right to make a contract in relation to his business is part of the liberty of the individual protected by the Fourteenth Amendment of the Federal Constitution. Under that provision no State can deprive any person of life, liberty or property without due process of law. The right to purchase or to sell labor is part of the liberty protected by this amendment, unless there are circumstances which exclude the right. There are, however, certain powers, existing in the sovereignty of each State in the Union, somewhat vaguely termed police powers, the exact description and limitation of which have not been attempted by the courts. Those powers . . . relate to the safety, health, morals and general welfare of the public. Both property and liberty are held on such reasonable conditions as may be imposed by the governing power of the State in the exercise of those powers, and with such conditions the Fourteenth Amendment was not designed to interfere. 346 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 The State, therefore, has power to prevent the individual from making certain kinds of contracts, and in regard to them the Federal Constitution offers no protection. If the contract be one which the State, in the legitimate exercise of its police power, has the right to prohibit, it is not prevented from prohibiting it by the Fourteenth Amendment. . . . . Therefore, when the State, by its legislature, in the assumed exercise of its police powers, has passed an act which seriously limits the right to labor or the right of contract . . . , it becomes of great importance to determine which shall prevail — the right of the individual to labor for such time as he may choose, or the right of the State to prevent the individual from laboring or from entering into any contract to labor, beyond a certain time prescribed by the State. This court has recognized the existence and upheld the exercise of the police powers of the States in many cases which might fairly be considered as border ones . . . . [A Utah statute was upheld that] limit[ed] the employment of workmen in all underground mines or workings, to eight hours per day, “except in cases of emergency, where life or property is in imminent danger.” It also limited the hours of labor in smelting and other institutions for the reduction or refining of ores or metals to eight hours per day, except in like cases of emergency. . . . . It was held that the kind of employment, mining, smelting, etc., and the character of the employes in such kinds of labor, were such as to make it reasonable and proper for the State to interfere to prevent the employes from being constrained by the rules laid down by the proprietors in regard to labor. . . . . . . . . The latest case decided by this court, involving the police power, is that of Jacobson v. Massachusetts. It related to 347 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 compulsory vaccination, and the law was held valid as a proper exercise of the police powers with reference to the public health. It was stated in the opinion that it was a case “of an adult who, for aught that appears, was himself in perfect health and a fit subject for vaccination, and yet, while remaining in the community, refused to obey the statute and the regulation adopted in execution of its provisions for the protection of the public health and the public safety, confessedly endangered by the presence of a dangerous disease.” That case is also far from covering the one now before the court. Petit v. Minnesota , was upheld as a proper exercise of the police power relating to the observance of Sunday, and the case held that the legislature had the right to declare that, as matter of law, keeping barber shops open on Sunday was not a work of necessity or charity. It must, of course, be conceded that there is a limit to the valid exercise of the police power by the State. There is no dispute concerning this general proposition. Otherwise the Fourteenth Amendment would have no efficacy and the legislatures of the States would have unbounded power, and it would be enough to say that any piece of legislation was enacted to conserve the morals, the health or the safety of the people; such legislation would be valid, no matter how absolutely without foundation the claim might be. The claim of the police power would be a mere pretext — become another and delusive name for the supreme sovereignty of the State to be exercised free from constitutional restraint. This is not contended for. In every case that comes before this court, therefore, where legislation of this character is concerned and where the protection of the Federal Constitution is sought, 348 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 the question necessarily arises: Is this a fair, reasonable and appropriate exercise of the police power of the State, or is it an unreasonable, unnecessary and arbitrary interference with the right of the individual to his personal liberty or to enter into those contracts in relation to labor which may seem to him appropriate or necessary for the support of himself and his family? Of course the liberty of contract relating to labor includes both parties to it. The one has as much right to purchase as the other to sell labor. This is not a question of substituting the judgment of the court for that of the legislature. If the act be within the power of the State it is valid, although the judgment of the court might be totally opposed to the enactment of such a law. But the question would still remain: Is it within the police power of the State? and that question must be answered by the court. The question whether this act is valid as a labor law, pure and simple, may be dismissed in a few words. There is no reasonable ground for interfering with the liberty of person or the right of free contract, by determining the hours of labor, in the occupation of a baker. There is no contention that bakers as a class are not equal in intelligence and capacity to men in other trades or manual occupations, or that they are not able to assert their rights and care for themselves without the protecting arm of the State, interfering with their independence of judgment and of action. They are in no sense wards of the State. Viewed in the light of a purely labor law, with no reference whatever to the question of health, we think that a law like the one before us involves neither the safety, the morals nor the welfare of the public, and that the interest 349 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 of the public is not in the slightest degree affected by such an act. . . . . . . . . The mere assertion that the subject relates though but in a remote degree to the public health does not necessarily render the enactment valid. The act must have a more direct relation, as a means to an end, and the end itself must be appropriate and legitimate, before an act can be held to be valid which interferes with the general right of an individual to be free in his person and in his power to contract in relation to his own labor. .... We think that there can be no fair doubt that the trade of a baker, in and of itself, is not an unhealthy one to that degree which would authorize the legislature to interfere with the right to labor, and with the right of free contract on the part of the individual, either as employer or employe. In looking through statistics regarding all trades and occupations, it may be true that the trade of a baker does not appear to be as healthy as some other trades, and is also vastly more healthy than still others. . . . . It is unfortunately true that labor, even in any department, may possibly carry with it the seeds of unhealthiness. But are we all, on that account, at the mercy of legislative majorities? A printer, a tinsmith, a locksmith, a carpenter, a cabinetmaker, a dry goods clerk, a bank’s, a lawyer’s or a physician’s clerk, or a clerk in almost any kind of business, would all come under the power of the legislature, on this assumption. No trade, no occupation, no mode of earning one’s living, could escape this all-pervading power, and the acts of the legislature in limiting the hours of labor in all employments would be valid, although such limitation might seriously cripple the ability of the laborer to support 350 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 himself and his family. In our large cities there are many buildings into which the sun penetrates for but a short time in each day, and these buildings are occupied by people carrying on the business of bankers, brokers, lawyers, real estate, and many other kinds of business, aided by many clerks, messengers, and other employes. Upon the assumption of the validity of this act under review, it is not possible to say that an act, prohibiting lawyers’ or bank clerks, or others, from contracting to labor for their employers more than eight hours a day, would be invalid. It might be said that it is unhealthy to work more than that number of hours in an apartment lighted by artificial light during the working hours of the day; that the occupation of the bank clerk, the lawyer’s clerk, the real estate clerk, or the broker’s clerk in such offices is therefore unhealthy, and the legislature in its paternal wisdom must, therefore, have the right to legislate on the subject of and to limit the hours for such labor, and if it exercises that power and its validity be questioned, it is sufficient to say, it has reference to the public health; it has reference to the health of the employes condemned to labor day after day in buildings where the sun never shines; it is a health law, and therefore it is valid, and cannot be questioned by the courts. It is also urged . . . that it is to the interest of the State that its population should be strong and robust, and therefore any legislation which may be said to tend to make people healthy must be valid as health laws, enacted under the police power. . . . . Scarcely any law but might find shelter under such assumptions, and conduct . . . as well as contract, would come under the restrictive sway of the legislature. Not only the hours of employes, but the hours of employers, could be regulated, and doctors, lawyers, scientists, all professional 351 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 men, as well as athletes and artisans, could be forbidden to fatigue their brains and bodies by prolonged hours of exercise, lest the fighting strength of the State be impaired. We mention these extreme cases because the contention is extreme. We do not believe in the soundness of the views which uphold this law. On the contrary, we think that such a law as this, although passed in the assumed exercise of the police power, and as relating to the public health, or the health of the employes named, is not within that power, and is invalid. The act is not, within any fair meaning of the term, a health law, but is an illegal interference with the rights of individuals, both employers and employes, to make contracts regarding labor upon such terms as they may think best, or which they may agree upon with the other parties to such contracts. Statutes of the nature of that under review, limiting the hours in which grown and intelligent men may labor to earn their living, are mere meddlesome interferences with the rights of the individual, and they are not saved from condemnation by the claim that they are passed in the exercise of the police power and upon the subject of the health of the individual whose rights are interfered with, unless there be some fair ground, reasonable in and of itself, to say that there is material danger to the public health or to the health of the employes, if the hours of labor are not curtailed. If this be not clearly the case the individuals, whose rights are thus made the subject of legislative interference, are under the protection of the Federal Constitution regarding their liberty of contract as well as of person; and the legislature of the State has no power to limit their right as proposed in this statute. . . . . .... 352 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 It is impossible for us to shut our eyes to the fact that many of the laws of this character, while passed under what is claimed to be the police power for the purpose of protecting the public health or welfare, are, in reality, passed from other motives. We are justified in saying so when, from the character of the law and the subject upon which it legislates, it is apparent that the public health or welfare bears but the most remote relation to the law. The purpose of a statute must be determined from the natural and legal effect of the language employed; and whether it is or is not repugnant to the Constitution of the United States must be determined from the natural effect of such statutes when put into operation, and not from their proclaimed purpose. The court looks beyond the mere letter of the law in such cases. It is manifest to us that the limitation of the hours of labor as provided for in this section of the statute under which the indictment was found, and the plaintiff in error convicted, has no such direct relation to and no such substantial effect upon the health of the employe, as to justify us in regarding the section as really a health law. It seems to us that the real object and purpose were simply to regulate the hours of labor between the master and his employes (all being men, sui juris), in a private business, not dangerous in any degree to morals or in any real and substantial degree, to the health of the employes. Under such circumstances the freedom of master and employe to contract with each other in relation to their employment, and in defining the same, cannot be prohibited or interfered with, without violating the Federal Constitution. The judgment of the Court of Appeals of New York as well as that of the Supreme Court and of the County Court of Oneida County must be reversed and the case remanded to 353 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 the County Court for further proceedings not inconsistent with this opinion. MR. JUSTICE HARLAN, with whom MR. JUSTICE WHITE and MR. JUSTICE DAY concurred, dissenting. While this court has not attempted to mark the precise boundaries of what is called the police power of the State, the existence of the power has been uniformly recognized, both by the Federal and state courts. All the cases agree that this power extends at least to the protection of the lives, the health and the safety of the public against the injurious exercise by any citizen of his own rights. .... Granting then that there is a liberty of contract which cannot be violated even under the sanction of direct legislative enactment, but assuming, as according to settled law we may assume, that such liberty of contract is subject to such regulations as the State may reasonably prescribe for the common good and the well-being of society, what are the conditions under which the judiciary may declare such regulations to be in excess of legislative authority and void? Upon this point there is no room for dispute; for, the rule is universal that a legislative enactment, Federal or state, is never to be disregarded or held invalid unless it be, beyond question, plainly and palpably in excess of legislative power. . . . . If there be doubt as to the validity of the statute, that doubt must therefore be resolved in favor of its validity, and the courts must keep their hands off, leaving the legislature to meet the responsibility for unwise legislation. If 354 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 the end which the legislature seeks to accomplish be one to which its power extends, and if the means employed to that end, although not the wisest or best, are yet not plainly and palpably unauthorized by law, then the court cannot interfere. In other words, when the validity of a statute is questioned, the burden of proof, so to speak, is upon those who assert it to be unconstitutional. Let these principles be applied to the present case. [Justice Harlan goes on to emphasize the need for deferring to legislative judgments and to survey the evidence about bakery workers.] I do not stop to consider whether any particular view of this economic question presents the sounder theory. What the precise facts are it may be difficult to say. It is enough for the determination of this case, and it is enough for this court to know, that the question is one about which there is room for debate and for an honest difference of opinion. There are many reasons of a weighty, substantial character, based upon the experience of mankind, in support of the theory that, all things considered, more than ten hours’ steady work each day, from week to week, in a bakery or confectionery establishment, may endanger the health, and shorten the lives of the workmen, thereby diminishing their physical and mental capacity to serve the State, and to provide for those dependent upon them. If such reasons exist that ought to be the end of this case, for the State is not amenable to the judiciary, in respect of its legislative enactments, unless such enactments are plainly, palpably, beyond all question, inconsistent with the Constitution of the United States. We are not to presume that the State of New York has acted in bad faith. . . . . 355 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 When this court had before it the question of the constitutionality of a statute of Kansas making it a criminal offense for a contractor for public work to permit or require his employes to perform labor upon such work in excess of eight hours each day, it was contended that the statute was in derogation of the liberty both of employes and employer. It was further contended that the Kansas statute was mischievous in its tendencies. This court, while disposing of the question only as it affected public work, held that the Kansas statute was not void under the Fourteenth Amendment. But it took occasion to say what may well be here repeated: “The responsibility therefor rests upon legislators, not upon the courts. No evils arising from such legislation could be more farreaching than those that might come to our system of government if the judiciary, abandoning the sphere assigned to it by the fundamental law, should enter the domain of legislation, and upon grounds merely of justice or reason or wisdom annul statutes that had received the sanction of the people’s representatives. We are reminded by counsel that it is the solemn duty of the courts in cases before them to guard the constitutional rights of the citizen against merely arbitrary power. That is unquestionably true. But it is equally true — indeed, the public interests imperatively demand — that legislative enactments should be recognized and enforced by the courts as embodying the will of the people, unless they are plainly and palpably, beyond all question, in violation of the fundamental law of the Constitution.” Atkin v. Kansas. The judgment in my opinion should be affirmed. 356 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 MR. JUSTICE HOLMES dissenting. I regret sincerely that I am unable to agree with the judgment in this case, and that I think it my duty to express my dissent. This case is decided upon an economic theory which a large part of the country does not entertain. If it were a question whether I agreed with that theory, I should desire to study it further and long before making up my mind. But I do not conceive that to be my duty, because I strongly believe that my agreement or disagreement has nothing to do with the right of a majority to embody their opinions in law. It is settled by various decisions of this court that state constitutions and state laws may regulate life in many ways which we as legislators might think as injudicious or if you like as tyrannical as this, and which equally with this interfere with the liberty to contract. Sunday laws and usury laws are ancient examples. A more modern one is the prohibition of lotteries. The liberty of the citizen to do as he likes so long as he does not interfere with the liberty of others to do the same, which has been a shibboleth for some well-known writers, is interfered with by school laws, by the Post Office, by every state or municipal institution which takes his money for purposes thought desirable, whether he likes it or not. The Fourteenth Amendment does not enact Mr. Herbert Spencer’s Social Statics. The other day we sustained the Massachusetts vaccination law. Jacobson v. Massachusetts, 197 U.S. 11. United States and state statutes and decisions cutting down the liberty to contract by way of combination are familiar to this court. Northern Securities Co. v. United States,193 U.S. 197. Two years ago we upheld the prohibition of sales of stock on 357 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 margins or for future delivery in the constitution of California. Otis v. Parker, 187 U.S. 606. The decision sustaining an eight hour law for miners is still recent. Holden v. Hardy, 169 U.S. 366. Some of these laws embody convictions or prejudices which judges are likely to share. Some may not. But a constitution is not intended to embody a particular economic theory, whether of paternalism and the organic relation of the citizen to the State or of laissez faire. It is made for people of fundamentally differing views, and the accident of our finding certain opinions natural and familiar or novel and even shocking ought not to conclude our judgment upon the question whether statutes embodying them conflict with the Constitution of the United States. General propositions do not decide concrete cases. The decision will depend on a judgment or intuition more subtle than any articulate major premise. But I think that the proposition just stated, if it is accepted, will carry us far toward the end. Every opinion tends to become a law. I think that the word liberty in the Fourteenth Amendment is perverted when it is held to prevent the natural outcome of a dominant opinion, unless it can be said that a rational and fair man necessarily would admit that the statute proposed would infringe fundamental principles as they have been understood by the traditions of our people and our law. It does not need research to show that no such sweeping condemnation can be passed upon the statute before us. A reasonable man might think it a proper measure on the score of health. Men whom I certainly could not pronounce unreasonable would uphold it as a first installment of a general regulation of the hours of work. Whether in the latter aspect it would be open to the charge of inequality I think it unnecessary to discuss. 358 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 United States v. Carolene Products Co., 304 U.S. 144 (1938) MR. JUSTICE STONE delivered the opinion of the Court. The question for decision is whether the “Filled Milk Act” of Congress of March 4, 1923 . . . which prohibits the shipment in interstate commerce of skimmed milk compounded with any fat or oil other than milk fat, so as to resemble milk or cream, transcends the power of Congress to regulate interstate commerce or infringes the Fifth Amendment. Appellee was indicted in the district court for southern Illinois for violation of the Act by the shipment in interstate commerce of certain packages of “Milnut,” a compound of condensed skimmed milk and coconut oil made in imitation or semblance of condensed milk or cream. The indictment states, in the words of the statute, that Milnut “is an adulterated article of food, injurious to the public health,” and that it is not a prepared food product of the type excepted from the prohibition of the Act. [Justice Stone describes the procedural history of the case.] Appellee assails the statute as beyond the power of Congress over interstate commerce, and hence an invasion of a field of action said to be reserved to the states by the Tenth Amendment. Appellee also complains that the statute denies to it equal protection of the laws and, in violation of the Fifth 359 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 Amendment, deprives it of its property without due process of law, particularly in that the statute purports to make binding and conclusive upon appellee the legislative declaration that appellee’s product “is an adulterated article of food injurious to the public health and its sale constitutes a fraud on the public.” First. The power to regulate commerce is the power “to prescribe the rule by which commerce is to be governed,” . . . and extends to the prohibition of shipments in such commerce. The power “is complete in itself, may be exercised to its utmost extent and acknowledges no limitations other than are prescribed by the Constitution.” Hence Congress is free to exclude from interstate commerce articles whose use in the states for which they are destined it may reasonably conceive to be injurious to the public health, morals or welfare, . . . or which contravene the policy of the state of their destination. Such regulation is not a forbidden invasion of state power either because its motive or its consequence is to restrict the use of articles of commerce within the states of destination, and is not prohibited unless by the due process clause of the Fifth Amendment. And it is no objection to the exertion of the power to regulate interstate commerce that its exercise is attended by the same incidents which attend the exercise of the police power of the states. The prohibition of the shipment of filled milk in interstate commerce is a permissible regulation of commerce, subject only to the restrictions of the Fifth Amendment. Second. The prohibition of shipment of appellee’s product in interstate commerce does not infringe the Fifth Amendment. Twenty years ago this Court, in Hebe Co. v. Shaw, . . . held that a state law which forbids the manufacture 360 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 and sale of a product assumed to be wholesome and nutritive, made of condensed skimmed milk, compounded with coconut oil, is not forbidden by the Fourteenth Amendment. The power of the legislature to secure a minimum of particular nutritive elements in a widely used article of food and to protect the public from fraudulent substitutions, was not doubted; and the Court thought that there was ample scope for the legislative judgment that prohibition of the offending article was an appropriate means of preventing injury to the public. We see no persuasive reason for departing from that ruling here, where the Fifth Amendment is concerned; and since none is suggested, we might rest decision wholly on the presumption of constitutionality. But affirmative evidence also sustains the statute. In twenty years evidence has steadily accumulated of the danger to the public health from the general consumption of foods which have been stripped of elements essential to the maintenance of health. The Filled Milk Act was adopted by Congress after committee hearings, in the course of which eminent scientists and health experts testified. An extensive investigation was made of the commerce in milk compounds in which vegetable oils have been substituted for natural milk fat, and of the effect upon the public health of the use of such compounds as a food substitute for milk. The conclusions drawn from evidence presented at the hearings were embodied in reports of the House Committee on Agriculture, . . . and the Senate Committee on Agriculture and Forestry . . . . Both committees concluded, as the statute itself declares, that the use of filled milk as a substitute for pure milk is generally injurious to health and facilitates fraud on the public. 361 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 There is nothing in the Constitution which compels a legislature, either national or state, to ignore such evidence, nor need it disregard the other evidence which amply supports the conclusions of the Congressional committees that the danger is greatly enhanced where an inferior product, like appellee’s, is indistinguishable from a valuable food of almost universal use, thus making fraudulent distribution easy and protection of the consumer difficult. Here the prohibition of the statute is inoperative unless the product is “in imitation or semblance of milk, cream, or skimmed milk, whether or not condensed.” Whether in such circumstances the public would be adequately protected by the prohibition of false labels and false branding imposed by the Pure Food and Drugs Act, or whether it was necessary to go farther and prohibit a substitute food product thought to be injurious to health if used as a substitute when the two are not distinguishable, was a matter for the legislative judgment and not that of courts. It was upon this ground that the prohibition of the sale of oleomargarine made in imitation of butter was held not to infringe the Fourteenth Amendment in Powell v. Pennsylvania . . . . Appellee raises no valid objection to the present statute by arguing that its prohibition has not been extended to oleomargarine or other butter substitutes in which vegetable fats or oils are substituted for butter fat. The Fifth Amendment has no equal protection clause, and even that of the Fourteenth, applicable only to the states, does not compel their legislatures to prohibit all like evils, or none. A legislature may hit at an abuse which it has found, even though it has failed to strike at another. 362 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 Third. We may assume for present purposes that no pronouncement of a legislature can forestall attack upon the constitutionality of the prohibition which it enacts by applying opprobrious epithets to the prohibited act, and that a statute would deny due process which precluded the disproof in judicial proceedings of all facts which would show or tend to show that a statute depriving the suitor of life, liberty or property had a rational basis. But such we think is not the purpose or construction of the statutory characterization of filled milk as injurious to health and as a fraud upon the public. There is no need to consider it here as more than a declaration of the legislative findings deemed to support and justify the action taken as a constitutional exertion of the legislative power, aiding informed judicial review, as do the reports of legislative committees, by revealing the rationale of the legislation. Even in the absence of such aids the existence of facts supporting the legislative judgment is to be presumed, for regulatory legislation affecting ordinary commercial transactions is not to be pronounced unconstitutional unless in the light of the facts made known or generally assumed it is of such a character as to preclude the assumption that it rests upon some rational basis within the knowledge and experience of the legislators.1 1 There may be narrower scope for operation of the presumption of constitutionality when legislation appears on its face to be within a specific prohibition of the Constitution, such as those of the first ten amendments, which are deemed equally specific when held to be embraced within the Fourteenth. It is unnecessary to consider now whether legislation which 363 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 The present statutory findings affect appellee no more than the reports of the Congressional committees; and since in the absence of the statutory findings they would be presumed, their incorporation in the statute is no more prejudicial than surplusage. Where the existence of a rational basis for legislation whose constitutionality is attacked depends upon facts beyond the sphere of judicial notice, such facts may properly be made the subject of judicial inquiry, . . . and the constitutionality of a statute predicated upon the existence of a particular state of facts may be challenged by showing to the court that those facts have ceased to exist. Similarly we recognize that the constitutionality of a statute, valid on its face, may be assailed by proof of facts tending to show that the statute as applied to a particular article is without support in reason because the article, although within the prohibited class, is so different from others of the class as to be without the reason for the restricts those political processes which can ordinarily be expected to bring about repeal of undesirable legislation, is to be subjected to more exacting judicial scrutiny under the general prohibitions of the Fourteenth Amendment than are most other types of legislation. [Citations omitted.] Nor need we enquire whether similar considerations enter into the review of statutes directed at particular religious, . . . or national, . . . or racial minorities . . . : whether prejudice against discrete and insular minorities may be a special condition, which tends seriously to curtail the operation of those political processes ordinarily to be relied upon to protect minorities, and which may call for a correspondingly more searching judicial inquiry. 364 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 prohibition, . . . though the effect of such proof depends on the relevant circumstances of each case, as for example the administrative difficulty of excluding the article from the regulated class. But by their very nature such inquiries, where the legislative judgment is drawn in question, must be restricted to the issue whether any state of facts either known or which could reasonably be assumed affords support for it. Here the demurrer challenges the validity of the statute on its face and it is evident from all the considerations presented to Congress, and those of which we may take judicial notice, that the question is at least debatable whether commerce in filled milk should be left unregulated, or in some measure restricted, or wholly prohibited. As that decision was for Congress, neither the finding of a court arrived at by weighing the evidence, nor the verdict of a jury can be substituted for it. The prohibition of shipment in interstate commerce of appellee’s product, as described in the indictment, is a constitutional exercise of the power to regulate interstate commerce. As the statute is not unconstitutional on its face the demurrer should have been overruled and the judgment will be Reversed. 365 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 Obergefell v. Hodges, 135 S.Ct. 2584 (2015) Justice KENNEDY delivered the opinion of the Court. The Constitution promises liberty to all within its reach, a liberty that includes certain specific rights that allow persons, within a lawful realm, to define and express their identity. The petitioners in these cases seek to find that liberty by marrying someone of the same sex and having their marriages deemed lawful on the same terms and conditions as marriages between persons of the opposite sex. I These cases come from Michigan, Kentucky, Ohio, and Tennessee, States that define marriage as a union between one man and one woman. The petitioners are 14 same-sex couples and two men whose same-sex partners are deceased. The respondents are state officials responsible for enforcing the laws in question. The petitioners claim the respondents violate the Fourteenth Amendment by denying them the right to marry or to have their marriages, lawfully performed in another State, given full recognition. .... From their beginning to their most recent page, the annals of human history reveal the transcendent importance of marriage. The lifelong union of a man and a woman always 366 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 has promised nobility and dignity to all persons, without regard to their station in life. Marriage is sacred to those who live by their religions and offers unique fulfillment to those who find meaning in the secular realm. Its dynamic allows two people to find a life that could not be found alone, for a marriage becomes greater than just the two persons. Rising from the most basic human needs, marriage is essential to our most profound hopes and aspirations. The centrality of marriage to the human condition makes it unsurprising that the institution has existed for millennia and across civilizations. Since the dawn of history, marriage has transformed strangers into relatives, binding families and societies together. Confucius taught that marriage lies at the foundation of government. This wisdom was echoed centuries later and half a world away by Cicero, who wrote, “The first bond of society is marriage; next, children; and then the family.” There are untold references to the beauty of marriage in religious and philosophical texts spanning time, cultures, and faiths, as well as in art and literature in all their forms. It is fair and necessary to say these references were based on the understanding that marriage is a union between two persons of the opposite sex. That history is the beginning of these cases. The respondents say it should be the end as well. To them, it would demean a timeless institution if the concept and lawful status of marriage were extended to two persons of the same sex. Marriage, in their view, is by its nature a genderdifferentiated union of man and woman. This view long has been held—and continues to be held—in good faith by reasonable and sincere people here and throughout the world. 367 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 The petitioners acknowledge this history but contend that these cases cannot end there. Were their intent to demean the revered idea and reality of marriage, the petitioners’ claims would be of a different order. But that is neither their purpose nor their submission. To the contrary, it is the enduring importance of marriage that underlies the petitioners’ contentions. This, they say, is their whole point. Far from seeking to devalue marriage, the petitioners seek it for themselves because of their respect—and need—for its privileges and responsibilities. And their immutable nature dictates that same-sex marriage is their only real path to this profound commitment. Recounting the circumstances of three of these cases illustrates the urgency of the petitioners’ cause from their perspective. Petitioner James Obergefell, a plaintiff in the Ohio case, met John Arthur over two decades ago. They fell in love and started a life together, establishing a lasting, committed relation. In 2011, however, Arthur was diagnosed with amyotrophic lateral sclerosis, or ALS. This debilitating disease is progressive, with no known cure. Two years ago, Obergefell and Arthur decided to commit to one another, resolving to marry before Arthur died. To fulfill their mutual promise, they traveled from Ohio to Maryland, where samesex marriage was legal. It was difficult for Arthur to move, and so the couple were wed inside a medical transport plane as it remained on the tarmac in Baltimore. Three months later, Arthur died. Ohio law does not permit Obergefell to be listed as the surviving spouse on Arthur’s death certificate. By statute, they must remain strangers even in death, a stateimposed separation Obergefell deems “hurtful for the rest of 368 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 time.” He brought suit to be shown as the surviving spouse on Arthur’s death certificate. .... The cases now before the Court involve other petitioners as well, each with their own experiences. Their stories reveal that they seek not to denigrate marriage but rather to live their lives, or honor their spouses’ memory, joined by its bond. B The ancient origins of marriage confirm its centrality, but it has not stood in isolation from developments in law and society. The history of marriage is one of both continuity and change. That institution—even as confined to opposite-sex relations—has evolved over time. For example, marriage was once viewed as an arrangement by the couple’s parents based on political, religious, and financial concerns; but by the time of the Nation’s founding it was understood to be a voluntary contract between a man and a woman. As the role and status of women changed, the institution further evolved. Under the centuries-old doctrine of coverture, a married man and woman were treated by the State as a single, male-dominated legal entity. As women gained legal, political, and property rights, and as society began to understand that women have their own equal dignity, the law of coverture was abandoned. These and other developments in the institution of marriage over the past centuries were not mere superficial changes. Rather, they worked deep transformations in its structure, affecting aspects of marriage long viewed by many as essential. 369 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 These new insights have strengthened, not weakened, the institution of marriage. Indeed, changed understandings of marriage are characteristic of a Nation where new dimensions of freedom become apparent to new generations, often through perspectives that begin in pleas or protests and then are considered in the political sphere and the judicial process. This dynamic can be seen in the Nation’s experiences with the rights of gays and lesbians. Until the mid–20th century, same-sex intimacy long had been condemned as immoral by the state itself in most Western nations, a belief often embodied in the criminal law. For this reason, among others, many persons did not deem homosexuals to have dignity in their own distinct identity. A truthful declaration by same-sex couples of what was in their hearts had to remain unspoken. Even when a greater awareness of the humanity and integrity of homosexual persons came in the period after World War II, the argument that gays and lesbians had a just claim to dignity was in conflict with both law and widespread social conventions. Same-sex intimacy remained a crime in many States. Gays and lesbians were prohibited from most government employment, barred from military service, excluded under immigration laws, targeted by police, and burdened in their rights to associate. See Brief for Organization of American Historians as Amicus Curiae 5–28. For much of the 20th century, moreover, homosexuality was treated as an illness. When the American Psychiatric Association published the first Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders in 1952, homosexuality was classified as a mental disorder, a position adhered to until 1973. Only in more recent years have psychiatrists and others 370 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 recognized that sexual orientation is both a normal expression of human sexuality and immutable. In the late 20th century, following substantial cultural and political developments, same-sex couples began to lead more open and public lives and to establish families. This development was followed by a quite extensive discussion of the issue in both governmental and private sectors and by a shift in public attitudes toward greater tolerance. As a result, questions about the rights of gays and lesbians soon reached the courts, where the issue could be discussed in the formal discourse of the law. This Court first gave detailed consideration to the legal status of homosexuals in Bowers v. Hardwick . . . . There it upheld the constitutionality of a Georgia law deemed to criminalize certain homosexual acts. Ten years later, in Romer v. Evans, . . . the Court invalidated an amendment to Colorado’s Constitution that sought to foreclose any branch or political subdivision of the State from protecting persons against discrimination based on sexual orientation. Then, in 2003, the Court overruled Bowers, holding that laws making same-sex intimacy a crime “demea [n] the lives of homosexual persons.” .... III Under the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment, no State shall “deprive any person of life, liberty, or property, without due process of law.” The fundamental liberties protected by this Clause include most of the rights enumerated in the Bill of Rights. In addition these liberties 371 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 extend to certain personal choices central to individual dignity and autonomy, including intimate choices that define personal identity and beliefs. The identification and protection of fundamental rights is an enduring part of the judicial duty to interpret the Constitution. That responsibility, however, “has not been reduced to any formula.” Rather, it requires courts to exercise reasoned judgment in identifying interests of the person so fundamental that the State must accord them its respect. See ibid. That process is guided by many of the same considerations relevant to analysis of other constitutional provisions that set forth broad principles rather than specific requirements. History and tradition guide and discipline this inquiry but do not set its outer boundaries. That method respects our history and learns from it without allowing the past alone to rule the present. The nature of injustice is that we may not always see it in our own times. The generations that wrote and ratified the Bill of Rights and the Fourteenth Amendment did not presume to know the extent of freedom in all of its dimensions, and so they entrusted to future generations a charter protecting the right of all persons to enjoy liberty as we learn its meaning. When new insight reveals discord between the Constitution’s central protections and a received legal stricture, a claim to liberty must be addressed. Applying these established tenets, the Court has long held the right to marry is protected by the Constitution. In Loving v. Virginia, . . . which invalidated bans on interracial unions, a unanimous Court held marriage is “one of the vital personal rights essential to the orderly pursuit of happiness by free men.” The Court reaffirmed that holding in Zablocki v. 372 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 Redhail, . . . which held the right to marry was burdened by a law prohibiting fathers who were behind on child support from marrying. The Court again applied this principle in Turner v. Safley, . . . which held the right to marry was abridged by regulations limiting the privilege of prison inmates to marry. Over time and in other contexts, the Court has reiterated that the right to marry is fundamental under the Due Process Clause. It cannot be denied that this Court’s cases describing the right to marry presumed a relationship involving opposite-sex partners. The Court, like many institutions, has made assumptions defined by the world and time of which it is a part. This was evident in Baker v. Nelson, . . . a one-line summary decision issued in 1972, holding the exclusion of same-sex couples from marriage did not present a substantial federal question. Still, there are other, more instructive precedents. This Court’s cases have expressed constitutional principles of broader reach. In defining the right to marry these cases have identified essential attributes of that right based in history, tradition, and other constitutional liberties inherent in this intimate bond. And in assessing whether the force and rationale of its cases apply to same-sex couples, the Court must respect the basic reasons why the right to marry has been long protected. This analysis compels the conclusion that same-sex couples may exercise the right to marry. The four principles and traditions to be discussed demonstrate that the reasons marriage is fundamental under the Constitution apply with equal force to same-sex couples. 373 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 A first premise of the Court’s relevant precedents is that the right to personal choice regarding marriage is inherent in the concept of individual autonomy. This abiding connection between marriage and liberty is why Loving invalidated interracial marriage bans under the Due Process Clause. Like choices concerning contraception, family relationships, procreation, and childrearing, all of which are protected by the Constitution, decisions concerning marriage are among the most intimate that an individual can make. Indeed, the Court has noted it would be contradictory “to recognize a right of privacy with respect to other matters of family life and not with respect to the decision to enter the relationship that is the foundation of the family in our society.” Choices about marriage shape an individual’s destiny. As the Supreme Judicial Court of Massachusetts has explained, because “it fulfils yearnings for security, safe haven, and connection that express our common humanity, civil marriage is an esteemed institution, and the decision whether and whom to marry is among life’s momentous acts of selfdefinition.” The nature of marriage is that, through its enduring bond, two persons together can find other freedoms, such as expression, intimacy, and spirituality. This is true for all persons, whatever their sexual orientation. There is dignity in the bond between two men or two women who seek to marry and in their autonomy to make such profound choices. A second principle in this Court’s jurisprudence is that the right to marry is fundamental because it supports a twoperson union unlike any other in its importance to the committed individuals. This point was central to Griswold v. Connecticut, which held the Constitution protects the right of 374 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 married couples to use contraception. Suggesting that marriage is a right “older than the Bill of Rights,” Griswold described marriage this way: Marriage is a coming together for better or for worse, hopefully enduring, and intimate to the degree of being sacred. It is an association that promotes a way of life, not causes; a harmony in living, not political faiths; a bilateral loyalty, not commercial or social projects. Yet it is an association for as noble a purpose as any involved in our prior decisions. And in Turner, the Court again acknowledged the intimate association protected by this right, holding prisoners could not be denied the right to marry because their committed relationships satisfied the basic reasons why marriage is a fundamental right. The right to marry thus dignifies couples who “wish to define themselves by their commitment to each other.” Marriage responds to the universal fear that a lonely person might call out only to find no one there. It offers the hope of companionship and understanding and assurance that while both still live there will be someone to care for the other. As this Court held in Lawrence, same-sex couples have the same right as opposite-sex couples to enjoy intimate association. Lawrence invalidated laws that made same-sex intimacy a criminal act. And it acknowledged that “[w]hen sexuality finds overt expression in intimate conduct with another person, the conduct can be but one element in a personal bond that is more enduring.” But while Lawrence confirmed a dimension of freedom that allows individuals to engage in intimate association without criminal liability, it 375 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 does not follow that freedom stops there. Outlaw to outcast may be a step forward, but it does not achieve the full promise of liberty. A third basis for protecting the right to marry is that it safeguards children and families and thus draws meaning from related rights of childrearing, procreation, and education. The Court has recognized these connections by describing the varied rights as a unified whole: “[T]he right to ‘marry, establish a home and bring up children’ is a central part of the liberty protected by the Due Process Clause.” Under the laws of the several States, some of marriage’s protections for children and families are material. But marriage also confers more profound benefits. By giving recognition and legal structure to their parents’ relationship, marriage allows children “to understand the integrity and closeness of their own family and its concord with other families in their community and in their daily lives.” Marriage also affords the permanency and stability important to children’s best interests. As all parties agree, many same-sex couples provide loving and nurturing homes to their children, whether biological or adopted. And hundreds of thousands of children are presently being raised by such couples. Most States have allowed gays and lesbians to adopt, either as individuals or as couples, and many adopted and foster children have same-sex parents . . . . This provides powerful confirmation from the law itself that gays and lesbians can create loving, supportive families. Excluding same-sex couples from marriage thus conflicts with a central premise of the right to marry. Without the recognition, stability, and predictability marriage offers, their children suffer the stigma of knowing their families are 376 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 somehow lesser. They also suffer the significant material costs of being raised by unmarried parents, relegated through no fault of their own to a more difficult and uncertain family life. The marriage laws at issue here thus harm and humiliate the children of same-sex couples. That is not to say the right to marry is less meaningful for those who do not or cannot have children. An ability, desire, or promise to procreate is not and has not been a prerequisite for a valid marriage in any State. In light of precedent protecting the right of a married couple not to procreate, it cannot be said the Court or the States have conditioned the right to marry on the capacity or commitment to procreate. The constitutional marriage right has many aspects, of which childbearing is only one. Fourth and finally, this Court’s cases and the Nation’s traditions make clear that marriage is a keystone of our social order. Alexis de Tocqueville recognized this truth on his travels through the United States almost two centuries ago: There is certainly no country in the world where the tie of marriage is so much respected as in America ... [W]hen the American retires from the turmoil of public life to the bosom of his family, he finds in it the image of order and of peace.... [H]e afterwards carries [that image] with him into public affairs. In Maynard v. Hill, . . . the Court echoed de Tocqueville, explaining that marriage is “the foundation of the family and of society, without which there would be neither civilization nor progress.” Marriage, the Maynard Court said, has long been “ ‘a great public institution, giving character to our 377 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 whole civil polity.’ ” This idea has been reiterated even as the institution has evolved in substantial ways over time, superseding rules related to parental consent, gender, and race once thought by many to be essential. Marriage remains a building block of our national community. For that reason, just as a couple vows to support each other, so does society pledge to support the couple, offering symbolic recognition and material benefits to protect and nourish the union. Indeed, while the States are in general free to vary the benefits they confer on all married couples, they have throughout our history made marriage the basis for an expanding list of governmental rights, benefits, and responsibilities. These aspects of marital status include: taxation; inheritance and property rights; rules of intestate succession; spousal privilege in the law of evidence; hospital access; medical decisionmaking authority; adoption rights; the rights and benefits of survivors; birth and death certificates; professional ethics rules; campaign finance restrictions; workers’ compensation benefits; health insurance; and child custody, support, and visitation rules. Valid marriage under state law is also a significant status for over a thousand provisions of federal law. The States have contributed to the fundamental character of the marriage right by placing that institution at the center of so many facets of the legal and social order. There is no difference between same- and opposite-sex couples with respect to this principle. Yet by virtue of their exclusion from that institution, same-sex couples are denied the constellation of benefits that the States have linked to marriage. This harm results in more than just material burdens. Same-sex couples are consigned to an instability 378 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 many opposite-sex couples would deem intolerable in their own lives. As the State itself makes marriage all the more precious by the significance it attaches to it, exclusion from that status has the effect of teaching that gays and lesbians are unequal in important respects. It demeans gays and lesbians for the State to lock them out of a central institution of the Nation’s society. Same-sex couples, too, may aspire to the transcendent purposes of marriage and seek fulfillment in its highest meaning. The limitation of marriage to opposite-sex couples may long have seemed natural and just, but its inconsistency with the central meaning of the fundamental right to marry is now manifest. With that knowledge must come the recognition that laws excluding same-sex couples from the marriage right impose stigma and injury of the kind prohibited by our basic charter. Objecting that this does not reflect an appropriate framing of the issue, the respondents refer to Washington v. Glucksberg, . . . which called for a “careful description” of fundamental rights. They assert the petitioners do not seek to exercise the right to marry but rather a new and nonexistent “right to same-sex marriage.” Glucksberg did insist that liberty under the Due Process Clause must be defined in a most circumscribed manner, with central reference to specific historical practices. Yet while that approach may have been appropriate for the asserted right there involved (physicianassisted suicide), it is inconsistent with the approach this Court has used in discussing other fundamental rights, including marriage and intimacy. Loving did not ask about a “right to interracial marriage”; Turner did not ask about a “right of inmates to marry”; and Zablocki did not ask about a 379 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 “right of fathers with unpaid child support duties to marry.” Rather, each case inquired about the right to marry in its comprehensive sense, asking if there was a sufficient justification for excluding the relevant class from the right. That principle applies here. If rights were defined by who exercised them in the past, then received practices could serve as their own continued justification and new groups could not invoke rights once denied. This Court has rejected that approach, both with respect to the right to marry and the rights of gays and lesbians. The right to marry is fundamental as a matter of history and tradition, but rights come not from ancient sources alone. They rise, too, from a better informed understanding of how constitutional imperatives define a liberty that remains urgent in our own era. Many who deem same-sex marriage to be wrong reach that conclusion based on decent and honorable religious or philosophical premises, and neither they nor their beliefs are disparaged here. But when that sincere, personal opposition becomes enacted law and public policy, the necessary consequence is to put the imprimatur of the State itself on an exclusion that soon demeans or stigmatizes those whose own liberty is then denied. Under the Constitution, same-sex couples seek in marriage the same legal treatment as opposite-sex couples, and it would disparage their choices and diminish their personhood to deny them this right. The right of same-sex couples to marry that is part of the liberty promised by the Fourteenth Amendment is derived, too, from that Amendment’s guarantee of the equal protection of the laws. The Due Process Clause and the Equal Protection Clause are connected in a profound way, though they set forth independent principles. Rights implicit in 380 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 liberty and rights secured by equal protection may rest on different precepts and are not always co-extensive, yet in some instances each may be instructive as to the meaning and reach of the other. In any particular case one Clause may be thought to capture the essence of the right in a more accurate and comprehensive way, even as the two Clauses may converge in the identification and definition of the right. This interrelation of the two principles furthers our understanding of what freedom is and must become. The Court’s cases touching upon the right to marry reflect this dynamic. In Loving the Court invalidated a prohibition on interracial marriage under both the Equal Protection Clause and the Due Process Clause. The Court first declared the prohibition invalid because of its unequal treatment of interracial couples. It stated: “There can be no doubt that restricting the freedom to marry solely because of racial classifications violates the central meaning of the Equal Protection Clause.” With this link to equal protection the Court proceeded to hold the prohibition offended central precepts of liberty: “To deny this fundamental freedom on so unsupportable a basis as the racial classifications embodied in these statutes, classifications so directly subversive of the principle of equality at the heart of the Fourteenth Amendment, is surely to deprive all the State’s citizens of liberty without due process of law.” The reasons why marriage is a fundamental right became more clear and compelling from a full awareness and understanding of the hurt that resulted from laws barring interracial unions. The synergy between the two protections is illustrated further in Zablocki. There the Court invoked the Equal Protection Clause as its basis for invalidating the challenged 381 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 law, which, as already noted, barred fathers who were behind on child-support payments from marrying without judicial approval. The equal protection analysis depended in central part on the Court’s holding that the law burdened a right “of fundamental importance.” It was the essential nature of the marriage right, discussed at length in Zablocki, . . . that made apparent the law’s incompatibility with requirements of equality. Each concept—liberty and equal protection—leads to a stronger understanding of the other. .... In Lawrence the Court acknowledged the interlocking nature of these constitutional safeguards in the context of the legal treatment of gays and lesbians. Although Lawrence elaborated its holding under the Due Process Clause, it acknowledged, and sought to remedy, the continuing inequality that resulted from laws making intimacy in the lives of gays and lesbians a crime against the State. Lawrence therefore drew upon principles of liberty and equality to define and protect the rights of gays and lesbians, holding the State “cannot demean their existence or control their destiny by making their private sexual conduct a crime.” This dynamic also applies to same-sex marriage. It is now clear that the challenged laws burden the liberty of same-sex couples, and it must be further acknowledged that they abridge central precepts of equality. Here the marriage laws enforced by the respondents are in essence unequal: same-sex couples are denied all the benefits afforded to opposite-sex couples and are barred from exercising a fundamental right. Especially against a long history of disapproval of their relationships, this denial to same-sex couples of the right to marry works a grave and continuing harm. The imposition of 382 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 this disability on gays and lesbians serves to disrespect and subordinate them. And the Equal Protection Clause, like the Due Process Clause, prohibits this unjustified infringement of the fundamental right to marry. These considerations lead to the conclusion that the right to marry is a fundamental right inherent in the liberty of the person, and under the Due Process and Equal Protection Clauses of the Fourteenth Amendment couples of the samesex may not be deprived of that right and that liberty. The Court now holds that same-sex couples may exercise the fundamental right to marry. No longer may this liberty be denied to them. Baker v. Nelson must be and now is overruled, and the State laws challenged by Petitioners in these cases are now held invalid to the extent they exclude same-sex couples from civil marriage on the same terms and conditions as opposite-sex couples. .... *** No union is more profound than marriage, for it embodies the highest ideals of love, fidelity, devotion, sacrifice, and family. In forming a marital union, two people become something greater than once they were. As some of the petitioners in these cases demonstrate, marriage embodies a love that may endure even past death. It would misunderstand these men and women to say they disrespect the idea of marriage. Their plea is that they do respect it, respect it so deeply that they seek to find its fulfillment for themselves. Their hope is not to be condemned to live in loneliness, excluded from one of civilization’s oldest institutions. They ask for equal dignity in the eyes of the law. The Constitution grants them that right. 383 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 The judgment of the Court of Appeals for the Sixth Circuit is reversed. Chief Justice ROBERTS, dissenting.** Petitioners make strong arguments rooted in social policy and considerations of fairness. They contend that same-sex couples should be allowed to affirm their love and commitment through marriage, just like opposite-sex couples. That position has undeniable appeal; over the past six years, voters and legislators in eleven States and the District of Columbia have revised their laws to allow marriage between two people of the same sex. But this Court is not a legislature. Whether same-sex marriage is a good idea should be of no concern to us. Under the Constitution, judges have power to say what the law is, not what it should be. The people who ratified the Constitution authorized courts to exercise “neither force nor will but merely judgment.” The Federalist No. 78, p. 465 (C. Rossiter ed. 1961) (A. Hamilton) (capitalization altered). Today, however, the Court takes the extraordinary step of ordering every State to license and recognize same-sex marriage. Many people will rejoice at this decision, and I begrudge none their celebration. But for those who believe in a government of laws, not of men, the majority’s approach is deeply disheartening. Supporters of same-sex marriage have achieved considerable success persuading their fellow citizens —through the democratic process—to adopt their view. That ends today. Five lawyers have closed the debate and enacted their own vision of marriage as a matter of constitutional law. Stealing this issue from the people will for many cast a cloud 384 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 over same-sex marriage, making a dramatic social change that much more difficult to accept. The majority’s decision is an act of will, not legal judgment. The right it announces has no basis in the Constitution or this Court’s precedent. The majority expressly disclaims judicial “caution” and omits even a pretense of humility, openly relying on its desire to remake society according to its own “new insight” into the “nature of injustice.” Ante, at 11, 23. As a result, the Court invalidates the marriage laws of more than half the States and orders the transformation of a social institution that has formed the basis of human society for millennia, for the Kalahari Bushmen and the Han Chinese, the Carthaginians and the Aztecs. Just who do we think we are? It can be tempting for judges to confuse our own preferences with the requirements of the law. But as this Court has been reminded throughout our history, the Constitution “is made for people of fundamentally differing views.” Lochner v. New York, 198 U. S. 45, 76 (1905) (Holmes, J., dissenting). Accordingly, “courts are not concerned with the wisdom or policy of legislation.” Id., at 69 (Harlan, J., dissenting). The majority today neglects that restrained conception of the judicial role. It seizes for itself a question the Constitution leaves to the people, at a time when the people are engaged in a vibrant debate on that question. And it answers that question based not on neutral principles of constitutional law, but on its own “understanding of what freedom is and must become.” Ante, at 19. I have no choice but to dissent. .... 385 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 The need for restraint in administering the strong medicine of substantive due process is a lesson this Court has learned the hard way. The Court first applied substantive due process to strike down a statute in Dred Scott v. Sandford, 19 How. 393 (1857). There the Court invalidated the Missouri Compromise on the ground that legislation restricting the institution of slavery violated the implied rights of slaveholders. The Court relied on its own conception of liberty and property in doing so. It asserted that “an act of Congress which deprives a citizen of the United States of his liberty or property, merely because he came himself or brought his property into a particular Territory of the United States . . . could hardly be dignified with the name of due process of law.” Id., at 450. In a dissent that has outlasted the majority opinion, Justice Curtis explained that when the “fixed rules which govern the interpretation of laws [are] abandoned, and the theoretical opinions of individuals are allowed to control” the Constitution’s meaning, “we have no longer a Constitution; we are under the government of individual men, who for the time being have power to declare what the Constitution is, according to their own views of what it ought to mean.” Id., at 621. Dred Scott’s holding was overruled on the battlefields of the Civil War and by constitutional amendment after Appomattox, but its approach to the Due Process Clause reappeared. In a series of early 20th-century cases, most prominently Lochner v. New York, this Court invalidated state statutes that presented “meddlesome interferences with the rights of the individual,” and “undue interference with liberty of person and freedom of contract.” 198 U. S., at 60, 61. In Lochner itself, the Court struck down a New York law setting 386 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 maximum hours for bakery employees, because there was “in our judgment, no reasonable foundation for holding this to be necessary or appropriate as a health law.” Id., at 58. The dissenting Justices in Lochner explained that the New York law could be viewed as a reasonable response to legislative concern about the health of bakery employees, an issue on which there was at least “room for debate and for an honest difference of opinion.” Id., at 72 (opinion of Harlan, J.). The majority’s contrary conclusion required adopting as constitutional law “an economic theory which a large part of the country does not entertain.” Id., at 75 (opinion of Holmes, J.). As Justice Holmes memorably put it, “The Fourteenth Amendment does not enact Mr. Herbert Spencer’s Social Statics,” a leading work on the philosophy of Social Darwinism. The Constitution “is not intended to embody a particular economic theory . . . . It is made for people of fundamentally differing views, and the accident of our finding certain opinions natural and familiar or novel and even shocking ought not to conclude our judgment upon the question whether statutes embodying them conflict with the Constitution.” Id., at 75–76. In the decades after Lochner, the Court struck down nearly 200 laws as violations of individual liberty, often over strong dissents contending that “[t]he criterion of constitutionality is not whether we believe the law to be for the public good.” Adkins v. Children’s Hospital of D. C., 261 U. S. 525, 570 (1923) (opinion of Holmes, J.). By empowering judges to elevate their own policy judgments to the status of constitutionally protected “liberty,” the Lochner line of cases left “no alternative to regarding the court as a . . . legislative chamber.” L. Hand, The Bill of Rights 42 (1958). 387 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 Eventually, the Court recognized its error and vowed not to repeat it. “The doctrine that . . . due process authorizes courts to hold laws unconstitutional when they believe the legislature has acted unwisely,” we later explained, “has long since been discarded. We have returned to the original constitutional proposition that courts do not substitute their social and economic beliefs for the judgment of legislative bodies, who are elected to pass laws.” Ferguson v. Skrupa, 372 U. S. 726, 730 (1963) ; see Day-Brite Lighting, Inc. v. Missouri, 342 U. S. 421, 423 (1952) (“we do not sit as a super-legislature to weigh the wisdom of legislation”). Thus, it has become an accepted rule that the Court will not hold laws unconstitutional simply because we find them “unwise, improvident, or out of harmony with a particular school of thought.” Williamson v. Lee Optical of Okla., Inc., 348 U. S. 483, 488 (1955). Rejecting Lochner does not require disavowing the doctrine of implied fundamental rights, and this Court has not done so. But to avoid repeating Lochner’s error of converting personal preferences into constitutional mandates, our modern substantive due process cases have stressed the need for judicial self-restraint. Our precedents have required that implied fundamental rights be “objectively, deeply rooted in this Nation’s history and tradition,” and “implicit in the concept of ordered liberty, such that neither liberty nor justice would exist if they were sacrificed.” Glucksberg, 521 U. S., at 720–721 (internal quotation marks omitted). .... . . . . Expanding a right suddenly and dramatically is likely to require tearing it up from its roots. Even a sincere profession of “discipline” in identifying fundamental rights, ante, at 10–11, does not provide a meaningful constraint on a 388 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 judge, for “what he is really likely to be ‘discovering,’ whether or not he is fully aware of it, are his own values,” J. Ely, Democracy and Distrust 44 (1980). The only way to ensure restraint in this delicate enterprise is “continual insistence upon respect for the teachings of history, solid recognition of the basic values that underlie our society, and wise appreciation of the great roles [of] the doctrines of federalism and separation of powers.” Griswold v. Connecticut, 381 U. S. 479, 501 (1965) (Harlan, J., concurring in judgment). Justice SCALIA, with whom Justice THOMAS joins, dissenting. [...] The substance of today’s decree is not of immense personal importance to me. The law can recognize as marriage whatever sexual attachments and living arrangements it wishes, and can accord them favorable civil consequences, from tax treatment to rights of inheritance. Those civil consequences — and the public approval that conferring the name of marriage evidences — can perhaps have adverse social effects, but no more adverse than the effects of many other controversial laws. So it is not of special importance to me what the law says about marriage. It is of overwhelming importance, however, who it is that rules me. Today’s decree says that my Ruler, and the Ruler of 320 million Americans coast-to-coast, is a majority of the nine lawyers on the Supreme Court. The opinion in these cases is the furthest extension in fact — and the furthest extension one can even imagine — of the Court’s claimed power to create “liberties” that the Constitution and its Amendments neglect to mention. 389 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 This practice of constitutional revision by an unelected committee of nine, always accompanied (as it is today) by extravagant praise of liberty, robs the People of the most important liberty they asserted in the Declaration of Independence and won in the Revolution of 1776: the freedom to govern themselves. I Until the courts put a stop to it, public debate over same-sex marriage displayed American democracy at its best. Individuals on both sides of the issue passionately, but respectfully, attempted to persuade their fellow citizens to accept their views. Americans considered the arguments and put the question to a vote. The electorates of 11 States, either directly or through their representatives, chose to expand the traditional definition of marriage. Many more decided not to. Win or lose, advocates for both sides continued pressing their cases, secure in the knowledge that an electoral loss can be negated by a later electoral win. That is exactly how our system of government is supposed to work. The Constitution places some constraints on self-rule— constraints adopted by the People themselves when they ratified the Constitution and its Amendments. Forbidden are laws “impairing the Obligation of Contracts,” denying “Full Faith and Credit” to the “public Acts” of other States, prohibiting the free exercise of religion, abridging the freedom of speech, infringing the right to keep and bear arms, authorizing unreasonable searches and seizures, and so forth. Aside from these limitations, those powers “reserved to the States respectively, or to the people” can be exercised as the 390 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 States or the People desire. These cases ask us to decide whether the Fourteenth Amendment contains a limitation that requires the States to license and recognize marriages between two people of the same sex. Does it remove that issue from the political process? Of course not. It would be surprising to find a prescription regarding marriage in the Federal Constitution since, as the author of today’s opinion reminded us only two years ago (in an opinion joined by the same Justices who join him today): “[R]egulation of domestic relations is an area that has long been regarded as a virtually exclusive province of the States.” “[T]he Federal Government, through our history, has deferred to state-law policy decisions with respect to domestic relations.” But we need not speculate. When the Fourteenth Amendment was ratified in 1868, every State limited marriage to one man and one woman, and no one doubted the constitutionality of doing so. That resolves these cases. When it comes to determining the meaning of a vague constitutional provision — such as “due process of law” or “equal protection of the laws” — it is unquestionable that the People who ratified that provision did not understand it to prohibit a practice that remained both universal and uncontroversial in the years after ratification. We have no basis for striking down a practice that is not expressly prohibited by the Fourteenth Amendment’s text, and that bears the endorsement of a long tradition of open, widespread, and unchallenged use dating back to the Amendment’s ratification. Since there is no doubt 391 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 whatever that the People never decided to prohibit the limitation of marriage to opposite-sex couples, the public debate over same-sex marriage must be allowed to continue. But the Court ends this debate, in an opinion lacking even a thin veneer of law. Buried beneath the mummeries and straining-to-be-memorable passages of the opinion is a candid and startling assertion: No matter what it was the People ratified, the Fourteenth Amendment protects those rights that the Judiciary, in its “reasoned judgment,” thinks the Fourteenth Amendment ought to protect. That is so because “[t]he generations that wrote and ratified the Bill of Rights and the Fourteenth Amendment did not presume to know the extent of freedom in all of its dimensions....” One would think that sentence would continue: “... and therefore they provided for a means by which the People could amend the Constitution,” or perhaps “... and therefore they left the creation of additional liberties, such as the freedom to marry someone of the same sex, to the People, through the neverending process of legislation.” But no. What logically follows, in the majority’s judge-empowering estimation, is: “and so they entrusted to future generations a charter protecting the right of all persons to enjoy liberty as we learn its meaning.” The “we,” needless to say, is the nine of us. “History and tradition guide and discipline [our] inquiry but do not set its outer boundaries.” Thus, rather than focusing on the People’s understanding of “liberty” — at the time of ratification or even today — the majority focuses on four “principles and traditions” that, in the majority’s view, prohibit States from defining marriage as an institution consisting of one man and one woman. 392 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 This is a naked judicial claim to legislative — indeed, superlegislative — power; a claim fundamentally at odds with our system of government. Except as limited by a constitutional prohibition agreed to by the People, the States are free to adopt whatever laws they like, even those that offend the esteemed Justices’ “reasoned judgment.” A system of government that makes the People subordinate to a committee of nine unelected lawyers does not deserve to be called a democracy. Judges are selected precisely for their skill as lawyers; whether they reflect the policy views of a particular constituency is not (or should not be) relevant. Not surprisingly then, the Federal Judiciary is hardly a crosssection of America. Take, for example, this Court, which consists of only nine men and women, all of them successful lawyers who studied at Harvard or Yale Law School. Four of the nine are natives of New York City. Eight of them grew up in east- and west-coast States. Only one hails from the vast expanse in-between. Not a single Southwesterner or even, to tell the truth, a genuine Westerner (California does not count). Not a single evangelical Christian (a group that comprises about one quarter of Americans), or even a Protestant of any denomination. The strikingly unrepresentative character of the body voting on today’s social upheaval would be irrelevant if they were functioning as judges, answering the legal question whether the American people had ever ratified a constitutional provision that was understood to proscribe the traditional definition of marriage. But of course the Justices in today’s majority are not voting on that basis; they say they are not. And to allow the policy question of same-sex marriage to be considered and resolved 393 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 by a select, patrician, highly unrepresentative panel of nine is to violate a principle even more fundamental than no taxation without representation: no social transformation without representation. II But what really astounds is the hubris reflected in today’s judicial Putsch. The five Justices who compose today’s majority are entirely comfortable concluding that every State violated the Constitution for all of the 135 years between the Fourteenth Amendment’s ratification and Massachusetts’ permitting of same-sex marriages in 2003. They have discovered in the Fourteenth Amendment a “fundamental right” overlooked by every person alive at the time of ratification, and almost everyone else in the time since. They see what lesser legal minds — minds like Thomas Cooley, John Marshall Harlan, Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr., Learned Hand, Louis Brandeis, William Howard Taft, Benjamin Cardozo, Hugo Black, Felix Frankfurter, Robert Jackson, and Henry Friendly — could not. They are certain that the People ratified the Fourteenth Amendment to bestow on them the power to remove questions from the democratic process when that is called for by their “reasoned judgment.” These Justices know that limiting marriage to one man and one woman is contrary to reason; they know that an institution as old as government itself, and accepted by every nation in history until 15 years ago, cannot possibly be supported by anything other than ignorance or bigotry. And they are willing to say that any citizen who does not agree with that, who adheres to what was, until 15 years ago, the unanimous 394 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 judgment of all generations and all societies, stands against the Constitution. The opinion is couched in a style that is as pretentious as its content is egotistic. It is one thing for separate concurring or dissenting opinions to contain extravagances, even silly extravagances, of thought and expression; it is something else for the official opinion of the Court to do so.2 Of course the opinion’s showy profundities are often profoundly incoherent. “The nature of marriage is that, through its enduring bond, two persons together can find other freedoms, such as expression, intimacy, and spirituality.” (Really? Who ever thought that intimacy and spirituality [whatever that means] were freedoms? And if intimacy is, one would think Freedom of Intimacy is abridged rather than expanded by marriage. Ask the nearest hippie. Expression, sure enough, is a freedom, but anyone in a long-lasting marriage will attest that that happy state constricts, rather than expands, what one can prudently say.) Rights, we are told, can “rise ... from a better informed understanding of how constitutional imperatives define a liberty that remains urgent in our own era.” (Huh? How can a better informed understanding of how constitutional imperatives [whatever that means] define 2 If, even as the price to be paid for a fifth vote, I ever joined an opinion for the Court that began: “The Constitution promises liberty to all within its reach, a liberty that includes certain specific rights that allow persons, within a lawful realm, to define and express their identity,” I would hide my head in a bag. The Supreme Court of the United States has descended from the disciplined legal reasoning of John Marshall and Joseph Story to the mystical aphorisms of the fortune cookie. 395 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 [whatever that means] an urgent liberty [never mind], give birth to a right?) And we are told that, “[i]n any particular case,” either the Equal Protection or Due Process Clause “may be thought to capture the essence of [a] right in a more accurate and comprehensive way,” than the other, “even as the two Clauses may converge in the identification and definition of the right.” (What say? What possible “essence” does substantive due process “capture” in an “accurate and comprehensive way”? It stands for nothing whatever, except those freedoms and entitlements that this Court really likes. And the Equal Protection Clause, as employed today, identifies nothing except a difference in treatment that this Court really dislikes. Hardly a distillation of essence. If the opinion is correct that the two clauses “converge in the identification and definition of [a] right,” that is only because the majority’s likes and dislikes are predictably compatible.) I could go on. The world does not expect logic and precision in poetry or inspirational pop-philosophy; it demands them in the law. The stuff contained in today’s opinion has to diminish this Court’s reputation for clear thinking and sober analysis. Hubris is sometimes defined as o’erweening pride; and pride, we know, goeth before a fall. The Judiciary is the “least dangerous” of the federal branches because it has “neither Force nor Will, but merely judgment; and must ultimately depend upon the aid of the executive arm” and the States, “even for the efficacy of its judgments.” With each decision of ours that takes from the People a question properly left to them — with each decision that is unabashedly based not on law, but on the “reasoned judgment” of a bare majority of this Court — we move one step closer to being reminded of our impotence. 396 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 Meeting 14: Review and Final Test Below are some problems representative of those that could appear on the final test. 1. In Marbury v. Madison, how did Marbury’s case come before the Supreme Court? Supposing you are the lawyer for Marbury and that this case had arisen today, what could you do after losing the case (could you still sue and would you likely be successful?), and how could your case come before the Supreme Court again? 2. A state passes a law providing: “The official language of the State is English. The English language is the language to be used by all public agencies in all government functions and actions. The English language shall be used in the preparation of all official public documents and records, including all documents officially compiled, published or recorded by the government. Nothing in this section shall be construed to prevent any private citizen from using an Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 interpreter to communicate with state officials.” (a) Make a textualist argument that this statute permits a state agency to accept employment applications completed in Spanish from private citizens. (b) How would an intentionalist analyze the question in (a)? 3. The law in the above problem is challenged as violating the Constitution’s guarantee of Equal Protection. (a) Argue that the statute in the above problem should, under Carolene Products, receive only rational basis review. Why would this be a desirable result even if you oppose the law on substance? Would it survive rational basis review? (b) Argue that the law should be subjected to strict scrutiny. Why would this be a desirable result? Would the law survive strict scrutiny? 4. Consider the following issue in tort law concerning the liability of accountants. Assume that an accountant supplied performed an audit on a financial company’s balance sheet for a client but that the accountant’s audit opinion was wrong and was performed negligently (below the level of competency and care at which accountants are expected to operate). Consider four categories of potential plaintiffs, all of whom lost money because of the audit: (1) the accountant’s client, (2) non-clients whom the auditor knew would rely on the accountant’s work (banks known to the auditor to have been considering loans to the audited 398 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 company, e.g.), (3) non-clients whom the accountant should have known (but may not have known) would rely on the audit, and (4) any entity that ultimately relied on the negligently performed audit. The question of which of these classes of people can sue is a question of duty: to whom does the accountant owe a duty of care. Using the rational actor model and law and economics methodology, make an argument concerning how far this duty should extend. (And assume that these plaintiffs could otherwise show that reliance on the audit caused them to lose money and that the accountant has no other defenses.) 5. We discussed the doctrine of stare decisis (adhering to precedent) in the context of Planned Parenthood v. Casey. Legislatures, in contrast, will repeal laws if a new majority disagrees with the decisions of past legislatures. And new presidents routinely pursue policies opposite those of past administrations. Why are courts different, and how do the criteria for departing from precedent given in Casey take account of those differences? 6. Suppose a federal statute provides for penalties for “the interstate distribution of any food product containing food coloring additives that may have negative impacts on human health.” The Food and Drug Administration, the agency charged with administering the statute, issues a Notice of Proposed Regulations that, among other things, proposes to require that any food coloring additive in a food shipped in interstate commerce have been proved safe 399 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 in a double-blind, longitudinal study of at least twenty years’ duration. The upshot is that they’re requiring the additive to have been studied over a very long period in an expensive way. If you’re the lawyer for a company that produces such additives, how would you explain to your client what its options are for stopping this - not only, ultimately, in court, but before that point as well. 7. A libertarian group had fought the food-coloring statute just discussed. They argued that it was a big government move to deprive citizens a chance to decide for themselves what foods they wanted to eat a most basic liberty. (a) Would the law likely improve efficiency? (Think about whether individual transactions without the law are efficient, as we usually assume contracts are. What could be going wrong?) (b) Do you think Nozick’s theory would condemn this law? What about other theories of distributive justice? 8. William Eskridge has argued that courts can be part of the solution to the imbalance of interest groups in the legislative process that leads to rent-seeking legislation and not enough legislation in the broader public interest. Courts, he argues, do not have similar problems and can correct this imbalanced by interpreting public interest provisions in statutes broadly to protect the public and interpreting more narrowly those provisions that advantage narrow interests. Why aren’t courts subject to the same public 400 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994 choice dynamics as legislatures? (Think about interest group formation and the judicial process.) 401 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3066994