Republic of the Philippines ACLC COLLEGE OF ORMOC CITY, INC. Science, Technology, Engineering, and Mathematics Lilia Ave., Cogon, Ormoc City In Partial Fulfillment of the requirements for the subject PHILOSOPHY HUMAN FREEDOM ACCORDING TO ARISTOTLE Submitted by: Edrianne G. Rivera STEM 12-Copper Submitted to: Jose Emannuel Calag Instructor 1ST Semester | S.Y. 2022-202 TABLE OF CONTENTS Title Page………………………………………………………………………….………. 1 Table of Contents …………………………………………………………………………. 2 Introduction to Aristotle …………………………………………………………………... 3 Writings …………………………………………………………………………… 4 Lost Works ………………………………………………………………………… 4 Extant Works ……………………………………………………………………… 4 Aristotle’s Conception of Freedom ………………………………………………………. 5 Freedom and Slavery ……………………………………………………………… 6 Freedom as a Rational Self-Direction …………………………………………….. 7 Conclusion ………………………………………………………………………………… 8 References ………………………………………………………………………………… 8 HUMAN FREEDOM ACCORDING TO ARISTOTLE Introduction to Aristotle Aristotle, 322, Chalcis, Greek Aristoteles, Euboea), ancient (born Greek 384 BCE, Stagira, Chalcidice, philosopher and scientist, Greece—died one of the greatest intellectual figures of Western history. He was the author of a philosophical and scientific system that became the framework and vehicle for both Christian Scholasticism and medieval Islamic philosophy. Even after the intellectual revolutions of the Renaissance, the Reformation, and the Enlightenment, Aristotelian concepts remained embedded in Western thinking. Aristotle’s intellectual range was vast, covering most of the sciences and many of the arts, including biology, botany, chemistry, ethics, history, logic, metaphysics, rhetoric, philosophy of mind, philosophy of science, physics, poetics, political theory, psychology, and zoology. He was the founder of formal logic, devising for it a finished system that for centuries was regarded as the sum of the discipline; and he pioneered the study of zoology, both observational and theoretical, in which some of his work remained unsurpassed until the 19th century. But he is, of course, most outstanding as a philosopher. His writings in ethics and political theory as well as in metaphysics and the philosophy of science continue to be studied, and his work remains a powerful current in contemporary philosophical debate. This paper deals with Aristotle’s life and thought. For the later development of Aristotelian philosophy, see Aristotelianism. For treatment full context of Western philosophy, see philosophy, Western. of Aristotelianism in the Writings Aristotle’s writings fall into two groups: those that were published by him but are now almost entirely lost, and those that were not intended for publication but were collected and preserved by others. The first group consists mainly of popular works; the second group comprises treatises that Aristotle used in his teaching. Lost works The lost works include poetry, letters, and essays as well as dialogues in the Platonic manner. To judge by surviving fragments, their content often differed widely from the doctrines of the surviving treatises. The commentator Alexander of Aphrodisias suggested that Aristotle’s works may express two truths: an “exoteric” truth for public consumption and an “esoteric” truth reserved for students in the Lyceum. Most contemporary scholars, however, believe that the popular writings reflect not Aristotle’s public views but rather an early stage of his intellectual development. Extant works The works that have been preserved derive from manuscripts left by Aristotle on his death. According to ancient tradition passed on by Plutarch and Strabo, the writings of Aristotle and Theophrastus were bequeathed to Neleus of Scepsis, whose heirs hid them in a cellar to prevent their being confiscated for the library of the kings of Pergamum (in present-day Turkey). Later, according to this tradition, the books were purchased by a collector and taken to Athens, where they were commandeered by the Roman commander Sulla when he conquered the city in 86 BCE. Taken to Rome, they were edited and published there about 60 BCE by Andronicus of Rhodes, the last head of the Lyceum. Although many elements of this story are implausible, it is still widely accepted that Andronicus edited Aristotle’s texts and published them with the titles and in the form and order that are familiar today. Aristotle’s Conception of Freedom There is no place in the Nicomachean Ethics, or the Politics, where Aristotle provides us with an explicit definition of freedom. Nevertheless, it is possible to glean Aristotle’s notion of freedom from a series of passages in the Politics, in which Aristotle discusses such matters as the existence of the natural slave, and the understanding of freedom underlying certain forms of democracy. This effort is useful insofar as it not only helps us to understand Aristotle, but also presents us with a conception of freedom interestingly different from many contemporary versions and perhaps worth our consideration. I will focus in this paper on Aristotle’s use of the term eleutheria, and its cognates. Eleutheria, usually translated as ‘liberty’ or ‘freedom,’ is conceived by Aristotle in terms more moral and political than metaphysical, i.e., he considers tyranny and slavery, rather than determinism, to be its principal contraries. Self-direction, rather than bare spontaneity, is the crucial characteristic of the free person. In this respect, Aristotle is similar to many political philosophers of our time. As we will see, however, there is an important difference: while many contemporary theorists think of freedom as simply the capacity to guide one’s own actions, without reference to the object or objects sought through action, Aristotle conceives of freedom as the capacity to direct oneself to those ends which one’s reason rightly recognizes as choiceworthy. This concept of freedom as rational self-direction can be found underlying Aristotle’s discussions of natural slavery and democracy. Freedom and Slavery Book I of the Politics contains an analysis of the relationships among the individual, the household, and the polis. In Chapters 2 and 5 of this book, Aristotle presents an interpretation of one of the relations within the household, namely, that of master and slave. He there makes a distinction between the political status of slavery, and the naturally slavish condition which alone can make this political status legitimate. Aristotle’s discussion of the difference between the man who is naturally suited for slavery and the man naturally suited for freedom gives us a basis upon which we may build a definition of freedom as a condition of soul, rather than as a conventionally granted civil status. Our first clue is found in Chapter 2, in which the masterslave relationship is first discussed: “For that which can foresee with the mind is the naturally ruling and naturally mastering element, while that which can do these things with the body is the naturally ruled and slave”. The naturally ruling man has a certain intellectual capacity that the natural slave lacks: he is able to “foresee with the mind.” Aristotle does not tell us precisely what it is that he is able to foresee. Perhaps he is able to predict the results of certain actions and events, for this would give him the knowledge of what tasks he must command in order to achieve his purposes. This capacity, the capacity to see which means will lead to given ends, is part of the excellence of the deliberative faculty. Aristotle claims that the slave is “wholly lacking the deliberative element”, which would seem to make him incapable of cleverness as well as that form of deliberation particular to phronesis. Alternatively, and, given that Aristotle seems to admit that there can be clever slaves, perhaps more plausibly, it could be that the naturally free man is able to foresee with the mind which ends he objectively ought to pursue; this is the feature that differentiates the deliberation of cleverness from that of phronesis. In either case, from these texts we have already learned something about the free man: he has foresight and a capacity for deliberation. He is capable of attaining cleverness, i.e., skill in choosing means to given ends. Once we consider the fact that deliberation is one of the characteristic tasks of the free man or eleutheros, we can better understand Aristotle’s remark that a people without any deliberative responsibilities in the polis would be “enslaved and an enemy to the constitution” Freedom as Rational Self-Direction As we have seen, Aristotle’s notion of freedom is intimately connected with his notion of rationality. Indeed, it is difficult to find a significant difference between his conceptions of what it is to be an eleutheros and what it is to be a rational animal. Rationality in the system of Aristotle is not merely the instrumental deliberative capacity of discovering means to ends, but also is the capacity to apprehend ends, including both intermediate ends and the final end of human happiness, where the ends in question are demanded by one’s own essential nature and accidental circumstances. Freedom, in turn, is not just the capacity to move oneself towards whatever ends one wishes, but the capacity to order one’s life by right reason, i.e., to move oneself towards the telos that one’s reason has discovered. The human being who has achieved the fullest expression of his rational and free human nature is the one who has the most developed capacity to apprehend reality, including the reality of his own inherent telos, and of the particular circumstances of his situation affecting the range of actions which may be seen as means to the fulfillment of this telos. The free man’s rational apprehension of reality must be confirmed and made effective in his practice, through his developed habit of bringing his passions and desires to embrace that which his reason apprehends as good. His freedom is thus not the democratic freedom of doing whatever he likes, but rather of living his life in accordance with his accurate apprehension of the highest good, or rather in some way from this apprehension. Freedom requires the intellectual virtues needed for seeing what the good life demands, and the moral virtues that lead one to desire and to act in accordance with this vision. In its most perfect state, this will include activity on behalf of the polis as a whole. It remains only to state an obvious fact: this sort of freedom is something that we can possess in greater or lesser degrees, according to the level of development of our rational faculties, the strength of the habit of bringing our passions and desires into cooperation with our reason, and the richness of our experience. Conclusion Freedom is something that I feel differs from person to person. Freedom in my own opinion is being able to live the life that you want and be happy. I feel that in my own life I express my freedom through my free speech and also through my decisions. I consider myself to be an open minded person and I feel that I am able to express my opinions freely, although sometimes there is backlash involved with this. Freedom means to just be able to grow into your own person and not have to worry about the societal constraints and social norms that impose pressure on individuality in today’s society, because according to Aristotle “freedom requires the intellectual virtues needed for seeing what the good life demands, and the moral virtues that lead one to desire and to act in accordance with this vision”. References https://philotech119334246.wordpress.com/2018/10/08/aristotles-conception-of-freedom/